0% found this document useful (0 votes)
740 views21 pages

Meinong, Theory of Objects

The document discusses Alexius Meinong's theory of objects, which proposes a science of objects as such, beyond just the objects of cognition. It notes that while cognition takes objects, many objects like similarities, differences, and mathematical objects do not actually exist in reality. It argues a science of objects is needed to study these "ideal" objects, which do not exist but are still part of cognition, ideas, assumptions, and judgments. Such a science would complement existing sciences by studying objects beyond just realities.

Uploaded by

bec61974
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
740 views21 pages

Meinong, Theory of Objects

The document discusses Alexius Meinong's theory of objects, which proposes a science of objects as such, beyond just the objects of cognition. It notes that while cognition takes objects, many objects like similarities, differences, and mathematical objects do not actually exist in reality. It argues a science of objects is needed to study these "ideal" objects, which do not exist but are still part of cognition, ideas, assumptions, and judgments. Such a science would complement existing sciences by studying objects beyond just realities.

Uploaded by

bec61974
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 21

The Theory of Obiects

uv ALEXIUS MEINONG (rneNsrerrD By IsAAcLEvI, D. B. TERRELL, AND


RODERICK M. CHISHOLM

l. Tne Pnosr.BM

,^^2. see my -Psychologisch-ethischen tlntersuchungen 1894), pp. 34 f. AIso H1flet, Psychologie, p. 389,

zur

v[/erttheorie

(Graz,

fneort ol Obiects Lt t J fne "hesitatingly concedethat we are happy about something,interested in something,and, at least in the majority of cases,do not wish or intend without wishing fpr or intending something.To put it briefly, eventsso very commonly no one fails to recogniz-d psychological that have this distinctive "character of being directedto something" (auf etwas Gerichtetsein) to suggestvery strongly (at least) that we \as should take it to be I characteristicaspect of the psychologicalas opposedto the non-psychological. not to The purpose of the following remarks is, nevertheless, explain why I hold this way of looking at the matter to be firmly established,despite the many difficulties confronting it. There are so many casesin which reference,indeed explicit directedness(Garichtetsein), to that "something," or (as we say quite naturally) to an object, unquestionablyforces itself upon our attention that, even if they alone were to be considered,the question would soon be answered for anyone who investigatedthese matters scientifically. and needstheoreticalconThe partitioning of whateverdeserves siderationinto difterent scientificrealms,and the careful delimitation of these realms, may often be of little practical importance in advancing the researchconnectedwith it. What matters in the final analysisis the work that is accomplished, and not the banner under which it is done. However, obscuritiesas to the boundariesof the diverse areas of sciencecan become significant in two contrasting encroachupon ways: either the areaswhich are actually investigated one another, or they are separatedfrom each other, and consequently leave an intermediate area untouched./The significanceof such obscurities, within the sphere of our theoretical interest, is exactly the opposite of their significancewithin the sphere of practical affairs. In the latter, the "ieutral zone" is a guarantee(always desired but rarely capableof being reahzed) of amicableneighborly relations, while the overlapping of territorial claims presents the typical case of conflict of interests.But in the realm of theoretical activity, where such conflicts, at least, have no justification, it is a gain, objectively considered,if the frontier districts coincide, for as a result they are investigatedfrom different sides.A separation,on of the the other hand, is always a disadvantage, seriousness which dependson the size and significanceof the intermediate territory. The intent of the problem raised here is to call attention to just such an area of knowledge,T which is sometimesoverlooked, sometimes not sufficiently appreciatedin its distinctive character. The questionconcernsthe proper place for the scientific investigationof

ltel

ALEXIUS MEINONG [78] the Object (Gegenstand)taken as such and in general-we wish to know whether, among the sciencesthat are accreditedby scientific tradition, there is one within which we could attempt a theoretical consideration the Object as such, or from which we could at least of demandthis.

The Theory ol Objects

uel

2. Tnu Pnr.ruprcp rN FAvoR oF THBAcruar, It was no accidentthat the foregoing account took cognition as its startingpoint in order to arrive at the Object. To be sure,cognition is not unique in "having" an Object. It has it in such a distinctive manner, however, that whenever we are speaking of Objects, we are influenced to think first of all of the Object of cognition. For, to be precise,the psychologicalevent we call cognition does not constitute the cognitive situation in and of itself: knowledgeis, so to speak, a double fact (Doppehatsache) in which what is known confronts the act of knowing as somethingrelatively independent. The act of knowing is not merely directed toward what is known, in the way in which a false judgment may be directed toward its Object. In knowing, on the contrary, it is as though what is known werg seized or grasped by the psychologicalact, or however else one might attemptto describe, an unavoidablypictorial way, somein thing which is indescribable.If one concentrates exclusivelyon the Object of knowledge, the problem about the science of Objects which was raised above is initially placed in a rather unfavorable light. A scienceof the Objects of cognition: does this mean anything more than the demand that what is already known as the Object of cognition be now made the Object of a science,and thus the Object of cognition for a secondtime? In other words, are we not asking for a sciencewhich either is made up of the sum-totalof the sciences taken together,or one which would have to accomplish jointly accomplishanyall over again what the recognizedsciences. way? We should guard ourselvesagainst concluding from these considerationsthat the idea of a universal science,in addition to the special sciences, abstrd. This understandingof the nature of the is world in its entirety and of its ulrimate foundations,which the best minds have always consideredto be the final and most estimable goal of their pursuit of knowledge, can only be the subject of a comprehensive science addition lo the specialsciences. in Indeed,the

discipline which goes under the name of metaphysicshas been thought to be exactly such a science.No matter how many disappointmentshave been associated with this name, and are associated with it, the responsibilityfor them lies with our intellectual capacities, and not with the idea of such a science.May one go so far, therefore, as to take metaphysics be the sciencewhose legitimate to function is to deal with Objects as such-or Objectsin their totality? If we rememberhow metaphysics has always been conceivedas I includingtn its subjectmatter the farthest and the nearest,the greatest and the smallestalike, we may be surprisedto be told that metaphysics cannot take on such a task. It may sound strangeto hear that metaphysics not universalenoughfor a scienceof Objects, is and hence cannot take on the task just formulated. For the intentions of metaphysics have been universal (a fact which has so often been disastrousto its success).Without doubt, metaphysicshas to do with everything that exists.However, the totality of what exists, including what has existed and will exist, is infinitely small in comparison with the totality of the Objects of knowledge. This fact easily goesunnoticed, probably becausethe lively interest in reality which is part of our nature tends to favor that exaggerationwhich finds the non-real a mere nothing--or, more precisely, which finds the non-real to be somethingfor which sciencehas no application at all or at least no application of any worth. How little truth there is in such a view is most easily shown by (bestehen), but which do not ideal Objectss which do indeedsubSist by any means exist (existieren), and consequentlycannot in any of sensebe rcal (wirklicft). Similarity and differenceare examples objects of this type: perhaps,under certain circumstances, they sub sist betweenrealities; but they are not a part of replity themselves. That ideas, as well as assumptions and judgments, are nevertheless concerned with such Objects (and often have reason to be very intimately concerned with them) is, of course, beyond question. Similarly, number does not exist in addition to what is numbered, supposingthe latter does exist; this we clearly know from the fact that we can also count what doesnot exist. Again, a connectiondoes not exist in addition\to what is connected,supposingthe latter does exist: That their existenceis not indispensableis proven by the
3. Concerning the sense in which I intend to\mploy the expression "ideal," which unfortunately is ambiguous in ordinary language, see my essay, "Uber Gegenst6nde h6herer Ordnung, ete.," Zeitschrilt lilr Psychologie, XXl, 198. lThis essay appears in Volume II of Meinong's -collected works; see Selected Bibliography.l
t

I
AIE)(IUS MEINONG [80] connection between the equilaterality and equiangularity of a triangle. Moreover, where existing objects are concerned, such as atmosphericand thermometric or barometric conditions, the connectedness does not unite these realities themselvesso much as it doestheir being or even their non-being.In knowing such a connection, we are already dealing with that special type of Object (mit jenem eigentumlichenGegenstandartigen), which, as I hope-I have shown,ais related to judgment and assumptions(Urteilen und Annahmen) in the rvay in which the Object, in a strict sense, (der eigentlicheGegenstand)is related to presentations(Vorstellungen). I haye recommendedthe name "Objective" (Obietkiv) for this type of Object, and I have shown that the Objective itself can assumethe functions of an Object in the strict sense.In particular, it can become the Object (Gegenstand) of a new judgment, or of some other intellectual operation, which is related to it as to an ordinary object (Obiekt). If I say, "It is true that the antipodes exist," truth is ascribednot to the antipodes,but to the Objective, "that the antipodesexist." But this existenceof the antipodesis a fact (Tatsache) which, as everyoneseesimmediately,can very well have a subsistentstatus, but cannot be still another existent entity in its own tufn, as it were.* This holds, likewise, for all other objectives, so that every cognitive act which has an Objective as its Object represents thereby a caseof knowing somethingwhich does not exist. What has been stated here only in terms of isolated examples is supportedby the testimony of a very highly developedscienceindeed the most highly developed one: mathematics.We would surely not want to speak of mathematics as alien to reality, as though it had nothing to do with what exists.Indeed,we cannot fail to recognizethat mathematicsis assuredof an extensivesphere of application in practical life no less than in the theoreticaltreatment of reality. However,pure mathematicalknowledgeis never concerned with anything which must, in the nature of the cage,be actual. The form of being (^Seiru) with which mathematicsas such is occupied is never existence (Existenz). In this respect, mathematicsnever (Bestand): a straight line has no more existtranscends subsistence ence than a right anglg a regular polygon, no more tlan a circle. It can be regarded only as a peculiarity of the mathematicaluse

[ 81 ] of languagethat this usage rnakes quite explicit existence-claims.E Even though the mathematicianmay use the term "existence," he cannot but concedethat what we would otherwisecall "possibility" is, in the final analysis, all that he requires of the objects of his theoretical consideration; it is very noteworthy, however, that a positive turn is being given to this ordinarily merely negativeconcept. Togetherwith the prejudicein favor of our knowledgeof reality, from of alluded to previously, the basic independence nnathematics existenceenables us to understand a fact which would be fair$ Attempts to system-surprising if these points were not considened. in atizn the sciences parts of a whole usually find themselves an as embarragsingposition in connection with mathematics, and they by must be extricated,with varying degreesof success, more or less artificial expedients.This is in striking contrast to the recognitionone might straightaway say popularity-which mathematics has But the acquired for itself even in lay circles by its achievements. organization of all knowledge into the science of nature and the appearingto be scienceof mind (Natur- und Geisteswissenschaft), an exhaustivedisjunction, realtrytakes into account only the sort of knowledge which has to do with reality (Wirklichkeit). Consequently,when we look at the rnatter more closely,we should not be at all surprised to find that this organization does not do full justice to mathematics"
The Theory of Objects

3. Sosew ANDNrcHTsErN There is thus not the slightestdoubt that what-is supposed be to the Object of knowledgeneed not exist at all. But our account up to now may seem to leave room for the conjecture that wherever existenceis absent, it not only can be but must be replaced by subsistence. even this restriction is inadmissable, may bp seen But as by contrastingthe characteristicfunctions of judging and assuming, a distinction I have attemptedto maintain by contrastingthe "thetic and synthetic function" of thought.In the former case,the act of thought graspsa Sein,in the latter a "Sosein."In eachcase,natnrally, it is an Objective that is grasped;it is reasonableto speak of a
5. Cf. K. Zindler: "BeitrZige zur Theorie der mathematischen Erkenntnis," Sitangsberichte der l<ais, Akademie der Wissenschalten in Wien, phil, hbt. KI., CXVIII (1889), p. 33 and 53 f. .6. Uber Annahmen, pp. 142-ff.

4. Uber Annahmen, chap. vii. * ld,ass zwar sehr wohl bestehen, sie aber nicht ihrerseitssozusagen noch einmal existierenkann.'l

\ { [82]
ALEXIUS MEINONG

houseor the land doesexist, has existed,or will exist. However,the

[83] The Theory ol Obiects in the first casewhether the necessitystemsfrom nor does it matter of the essence the object or whether it stems from aspectswhich are external to the Obiect in question.In order to know that there is no round square,I must make a If physics,physiology,and psychol ideal character of sense-qualities, about color as well as about soun more than the other. Those who l sion could very well say: "There i there are no such objects." The fa is meant by this statementthrows of objects to reality, or their relation to being, genglaly: that a somewhatcloser eximination of the matter, which is of fundamental importancein its own right, is entirely in place in our present study' 4. Tnr AussrnselN oF THE Pune Oslncr ilself A recourse to certain psychologicalexperiencessuggestsp natural way of resolvingttre paradox which seemsto lie betore as us.I have attemptedto preJent the most essentialpoints pertaining to this problem in anotherwork.8 But, accordingt9 my-a:count here, subjectivity of senseif we were now to maintain the aforementioned of qualities,we could speakof the object of a Presentation blue only in ttre senseof somethingwhich is a capacity of that presentation, from which reality withholds, as it were, the opportunity. for its realization. considered from the standpoint of the presentation,this still seemsto me to touch on something of essentialsignificance. However, I cannot concealfrom myself at presentthe fact that it is to no more necessary an object that it be presentedin order not to exist than it is in order for it to exist. Further, even if there were a referenceto it, the most that could result from its being presented would be a sori of existence-"s;d5fsngs by way of idea (in der To Vorstellung)"-21d 5s, more precisely, "pseudo-existence"'1 . exactly: If I sayf "Blue doesnot exist," I am thinkexpressit more and the capacities ing just of blue, and not at all of a pr,esentation -may have. It is as if the blue musi have place, it $ing_ in .the first the question of its being (sein) or non-being before we can raise (Nichtsein). But in ordef not to fall into new paradoxesor actual
8. t)ber Annahmen, PP. 98 ff' 9. See "Uber Gegensiinde hijherer Ordnung," loc. cit', pp. 186 f'

light might be shedon domainswhich are especially important for us to know. But such things may be alien to our natural way of thinking; it is even more instructive to recall this trivial fact, which does not yjt go beyond the realm of the Seinsobjektiv.' Any particular thing that isn't real (Nichtseiendes)must at least be c-apiUteof serving as the Object for tlose judgmentswhich grasp its Nichtsein It does not matter whether this Nichtseln is neces$ary merely factual; or
--Jllil-ro*i.nate. translations of the German terms in the text are the following. The sein of an object is its existing, or its being real; its Nichtseln is its not exisring' or its being unreal; its ,sosein is its having characteristics. A seinsobJektiv is an objective consisting of sopething existing, or of something being reai; anarogously for Soseinsobjektiv and Nichtseinsobiektiv.l 7, This principlt was first enunciated by E. Mally in his treatise which was honored by the Wartinger prize in 1903, and which appears in completely revised form as No. III of tlese papers; see chap. i, $ 3, of Mally's paper. [Meinbng here refers to thc volume in which his own essay originally appeared. Mally's paper is entitled "Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie des Messens."l

[84] ALEXIUS MBINONO absurdities,_perhaps following turn of expressionmay be ap_ the propriate: Blue, or any-other Oblect whatsoevlr, is somehLwgiven prior to our determination--ofits -beingor non-biing, io ; way"that does not Trry any prejudice to its ion-being. we"'co-urduiJo a"scnoetne srtuationfrom its psychological sidein this way: if I should be able to judge that.a certain Otieit is not, then I upi.u, to have had.to gra-spthe ObjecJin some way befoieh*A, i"'iiJ"r-to ,uy anything about its non-being,or morl precisely,ii orao io or to deny the ascriptionof non-beingto^the Object "mrThis fact, despite its commonplice charactlr, is seen to be of re to do justice toit with somewhat rs of the following considerations. I a certain thing, A, is not-more st as much an Objective as is the tainty with which I am iustified in degreeof certainty that the Objective, f -i: u seinsobiektiv or Nichiseinsobiiictiv, standsin relation to its (Obiekt), albe-it cum grano salis,as the *n.f" t it, p".tr. 9Uj"."l But if the whole has being, so must its parts. This seemsto iean, when it is extendedto theiase of the objective: if the objectivi has being (rsl), so, in some senseor other, must the object *rri.n u"longs to it, even whel th9 Objective is an objective of non_being (Nichtseiwobiektiv). Furthermore, since the otjective rtri"tly pr"vents us from assumingthat A has being, (being, as we have si"n, can sometimes understood existence; be as sometimes subsistence), as it appearsthat the requirementthat the object have beinj r*rri"n was inferred from the being of the Nichtseinsobiektiv)o,u[", ,ror" only insofar as the being in question is neither existencenor subsistbnce-only ihsofar as a third order of t"in!, it oo" t"1, ip""t this way, is adjoined to existenceand subsistence. This rort of ueing must belong, therefore,to every Object as such. A Nichtseinof the sametype cannot be set in opposition to it, for a Nichtsein evenin this new-sense urculd have !g immediatelyproducedifrculties analogous to those which arise fibm Nichtsein in its ordinary sense,and which the new conceptwas to have eliminated.The teri "euasisein, seemedto me for a while to be a completelysuitableexpression for this rather oddly constituted typey'f being.
--tU UUu ennahmen, chap. vii. /

The Theory ol Objects

[8s ]

however,like others that were approvedearlier This designation, 1r) (for instance, "Pseudoexistenz"and "Quasitranszendenz," runs

above,thatithassubsistencef &:,::itfffl#l",i3li;"ti"li#i',",ffi1

for such a postulate.Must we not take thought to avoid it in our case also wherever it is possible?The considerationwhich seems to force us to such a postulateis, to be sure, an experiencewhich is easilyobserved. we have seen,A must be "given" to me in some As way or other if I am to grasp its non-being.This produces,however, as f have already shown elsewhere,l2an assumption (Annahme) possessing affirmativequality: in order to deny A, I must first assume the being of A. What I refer to, so far as the being of A is con' cerned,is thus somethingwhich is to a certain extent only a claimant Sein des ,4 ). But it is of to being (ein gewissermassen vorgegebenes tfte essence assumptionthat it direct itself upon a being which of itself does not need to be. Without a doubt, it would be comforting to be able to say that the strange kind of being which belongs to that which does not have being (Sedndes Nichtseiendes)is just as absurd as it sounds' Such a view could recommenditself to us were it not for the fact that the to Objective,which has being, alwaysseems require in turn an Object which has being. For the present, this requirementis based solely on the analogy to the part-whole relation: an Objective is thereby treated as a complex of some kind and the Object belonging to it this may be in accordance as a kind of component.In many:respects with our insight into the nature of an Objective,which is as yet still exceedinglydefective.However, no one will deny that this analogy and that there is only an initial expedient in our embarrassment grounds for following this analogy rigorously even for would be no part of the way. Thus, insteadof derivingthe being of an Object from analory the being of an Objective,even on tle basisof a questionable where the Objective is an Objective of non-being,it would be better to conclude from the facts with which we are concernedthat this analogl! does not apply to the Objective of non-being-i.e., that the being of the Objective is not by any means universally dependent upon the being of its Object.
ll. Uher Anruhmen, p.95. L2. Loc. cir., pp, 105 ff.

ALEXIUS MEINONG [86] This is a position which speaksfor itself without any further ado. If the oppositionof being and non-beingis primarily a matter of the Objective and not of the Object, then it is, after all, clearly understandablethat neither being nor non-being can belong essentially to the Object in itself. This is not to say, of course,that an Object can neither be nor not be. Nor is it to say that the question,whether or not the Object has being, is purely accidentalto the nature of every Object. An absurd Object such as a round square carries in 'of itself the guarantee its own non-being in every sense;an ideal Object, such as diversity, carries in itset the guarantee of its own non-existence. Anyone who seeksto associatehimself with models which have become famous could formulate what has been shown above by saying that the Object as such (without consideringthe occasionalpeculiaritiesor the' accompanyingObjectire-clausewhich is always present) stands"beyond being and non-being." This may also be expressed the following less engagingand also less prein tenticlusway, which is in my opinion, however, a more appropriate one: The Object is by nature indifferent to being (aussersetend), although at least one of its two Objectives of being, the Object's being or non-being, subsists. What one could thus call with propriety the principle of the indifferenceof pure Objects to being (den Satz vom Ausserseindes reinen Gegenstandes) finally eliminatesthe appearance a paradox of which was the immediateoccasionfor the assertionof this principle. As soon as it is recognized that, apart from specialcases, both being and non-being are equally external to an Object, it is then understandablethat nothing more, so to speak,is involved in comprehending the non'being of the Object than there is in comprehending its being. The above-mentioned principle of the hdependenceof Sosein from Sein now presentsa welcome supplementto this view. It tells us that that which is not in any way external to the Object, but .constitutes its proper essence,subsists in its Sosein-the Sosein attachingto the Object whether the object has being or not. We are finally in a position to see with sufficient clarity what confronted us above as the prejudice in favor of the existence,or at least the being, of afl possible Objects of knowledge.Being is not the presupposition under whi& knowledge finds, as it were, its point of attack; it is itself such a point of attack. Non-being is equally as good a point of attack. Furthermore, in the Soseinof each Object, knowledge already finds a field of activity to which it may have access without fust answeringthe questionconcerningbeing or nonbeing, or without answering-tfiilquestion afErmatively.

The Theory ol Objects

[87]

5. TnB Tnsonv or Onrncrs ns Psvcnotocv We now know that those Objects which exist, and even those which have being, run fan short of the sum-totalof Objectsof knowledge,and we can seethereforehow inaccurateit would be to regard a scienceof the actual, or a scienceof being in general,no matter how comprehensive scope,as a scienceof Objects of knowledge its taken simply as such.Moreover, in the prwious paragraphs,we have consideredonly the Objects of cognition. But the question raised at the very outset of this exposition had to take into consideration the fact that not only cognition but every case of judgment and presentationhas its Object-not to mention the Objectivity (Gegenstiindlichkeir)* of extra-intellectualexperiences. This all-embracing importance of Objectivity for the psychical side of life-it may indeed be preciselyits distinguishingcharacteristic,as I have briefly mentioned already-may now suggestto us that (owing to our exclusive attention to cognition) we permitted ourselves to be led down a detour that might easily have been avoided.For tlrc science which most naturally would have to do with Objects as such would be the very one whose businessit is to deal with this Objectivity. This task, in view of what I have just touchedon once again, seems to belong to psychology. In any event, it must be concededthat the current direction of psychologyis not entirely opposedto such a conceptionof its task. There is, for example,a psychologyof sound as well as a psychology of color, within which by no rneans the least important tasks are taken to be the ordering of the diverse Objects belonging to the sensorydomain concerned,and the investigationof their distinctive nature.13It is also natural that the scienceof psychologicalfacts draws into its range of investigationthe distinctive activities of the psychologicalsphere-in particular, intellectual activities. Xt would be an odd psychologyof judgrnent that took no notice of that capacitf which (under sufficientlyfavorable circumstances)reachesout beyond itself to take possession reality in sorne way. There is of
* [By "Objectivity" is meant here merely the characteristic of referring to some Object, It has no direct connection with the usual philosophlcal sense of "objectivity" in English, where objectivity is opposed to subjectivity.l 13. For more detarls, see my "Bemerkungen iiber den Farbenkdrper und das Mischungsgesetz," Zeitschrilt lilr Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, )OOGIL p. 3 ff, tThis paper is included in Volume I of Meinong's collected works.l

[88]

ALE)SUS MEINONG

The Theory ol Oblects

somethingbesidesreality which can be known, and it is sometlfng which wg are in a position to know with the aid of certain intellectual therefore,certainly cannot refrain from conoperations.Psychology, sideringboth this capacity to know and also that somethingoutside of reality (Ausserwirkliche) toward which these characteristicactivities are directed. To this extent, therefore, the Objects of judging, assuming,and presenting,as well as the Objects of feeling and desiring, undoubtedly gain entry into psychology.But everyone will notice at once that this sciencedoes not take these Objects into considerationfor their own sakes. In practice, both inside and outside of scientific pursuits, it is, frequently enough, quite an incidenql matter as to what result is a primary-goal, and what is just acceptedas an accidental by-product. For example,it is certainly useful to archaeology merely for textual interthat what philologistsoften find necessary pretation pbints to the "real things," yet is no proper part of classical philology, Otherwise, the latter sciencecould easily lay claims to being the most basic discipline, since work on 4ncient languages has provided the starting point for all sorts of scientific activity. Similarly, psychologicalinquiry can bear fruit for related areas as which are either less developedthan long as they belong to sciences psychology or have not yet been formally recognizedas sePar,ate Cciences all. Nothing more clearly demonstratesthat this has at of happenedin the caseof theoreticalconsideration Objectsthan the eximple of colors mentioned above, where investigation of the psychologicalfacts first led to the investigationof facts concerning Objects; an exampleis the investigationof the relationshipsamong colors conceivedin spatial terms (der Farbenkdrper auf den Farbenraum).raThe referenceto linguistic science,already introduced, shows in another respect how little psychologYcan qualify as the true scienceof Objects. In dealing with the meaning of words and also concernedwith Obsentences,l6 linguistic scienceis necessarily jects, and grammar has done the spadeworkfor a theoretical grasp of Objectsin a very basic way. Thus, in point of fact, the viewpoint from which psychologywas to have been concededany prerogative in this matter is not apparent; rather, it is clearty seenthat neither of of thesetko disciplingscan be that science Objectswe are seeking. of After it'had beeir shown that the sciences being in general, including the one which has to do generallywith whateveris actual, are inadequateto the task of the scienceof Objects, it would be
---t+ Ct- tor. cir., pp. 11 ff. ) pp,2{ft. 15, Cf..Uber Annahmen,

[8e]

16. "ub* Gegenstiinde h<iherer Ordnung,,, loc. cit., pp. 186 f. 17. Cf' E. Mally, in the third of these studies, chap. i, Sec. 15; chap. iii, Sec. 20; chap. iv, Sec. 25. [See footnote 7.]

Ie0]

ALB)CUS MEINONO

which, strangeto say, has not yet entirely been forgotten. This argument statesthat if "esse" need not be precisely"percipii' it must at any rate be "cogitari"; for no one can think of an "essd' withoutmay be thinking of it. In any case,the effect of such considerations more opposedto, than in accord with, their intent. If, for example, the ultrawhite mentionedabove is brought into the domain of theojust by meansof a conceptiondirected towards retical consideration it, then the novel psychologicalevents which come to ltfe could engendernew work for psychology.To be sure, this is by no means necessary. the caseof the examplewe are consideringhere, such In work is scarcelyto be expected,since an abundanceof similar conceptions is already available. However, the possibilty must certainly be kept in mind, and if it is once actually rcaliz.ed,then how little the conceptionof ultrawhite is a part of psychologywill become quite clear. By viitue of this conception, the work of the theory of Objects is to a certain extent already completed, btrt that of psychologyhas yet to be done. It would be odd do consider the accomplished task a psychologicalone just becauseof the task that is still to be done. 6. Tns TnBonv or OsrBcrs ls e Tneony or tnB Os.recrs oF KNowrepcn What psychology cannot provide us might better be sought, therefore, in those areaswhere the very nature of what we investigate is constituted,in part, by Objects.On the basis of our previous discussion, can hardly be doubtedthat in cog3itionwe have before it us facts of this type. Cognition is not merely a jirdgrnentthat happens to be true; it is true by its own n4fiug-frus from within, as it were. A judgment is true, however, not insofar as it has an Object that exists, or even one that has being, but only insofar as it graspsan Objective that has being. That there are black swans,but that there is no perpetuummobile, are both true judgments;but the first concerns an exfuent object, the seconda non-existentobject. In the one case,the being of the Object in question subsists; the other case, in its non-beingsubsistsri Truth is always bound up with the being of Objectives and is therefore partially constituted out of it. The judgment would not be true if therp were no Objective to which it referred. Nor would the judgmerrte true if it were constituteddifferently than it is and therefore did not agree with the facts. The

The Theoryof Obiects Ie1] coincidence the one subjectiveand the other objectiverequirement of can thus be entirely accidental: as when one draws a true conclusion from false premises. Now such an accidentalor external character is surely foreigrr to the relation between knowing and what is known. In the case of knowing, it belongs to the nature of the judgrnent that it does not miss its aim at what is to be known. This distinctive feature of cognitionachieves place in the forum of psychologicalinvestigation a through what we know as evidence(Evidenz). However, the evident judgment itself does not constitutethe fact of cognition. It is essential to grasp the Object with respectto the Objective, and for this the being of the latter is indispensable. this respect,the cognition In entirely resemblesthe judgment which is true per accidens, as it were. For this reason,it was possibleeven at the beginning of the present essay to call knowledge a double fact (Doppeltatsache). Anyone who wishesa scientificallycloserview of this compoundfact must not restrict himself to the psychologicalaspect of it; he must also take into consideration, quite expresslya part of the problem as set before him, the other side, i.e., the Objective which has being and the Object which is implicated in the Objective. With regardto our major problem, we have in somemeasurereturned to a standpoint which we abandonedin the previous paragraphs, for we have appealed to the fact that objects belong not only to cognition, but also to false judgment, to presentation,and to psychologicalactivities which are totally non-intellectual.trf we conclude that the theory of Objectsfalls most naturally within the scientific treatment of cognition, we are confronted with this question: By restricting ourselvesto cognition and thus excluding other psychologicalevents,do we not.cut ourselvesoff from certain Objects and give up that universality which is required in dealing with Objects as such? The doubt is unfounded. trn order to see this, one must, above all, rememberthe characteristicdifferencebetweenpsychology and the scienceof knowledge.It is obvious that psychologyis concerned only with real psychologicaleventsand not with the merely possible. A scienceof knowledgecannot set similar limitations on itself, becauseknowledgeas such has value, and therefore somethingwhich is not but could be may draw attention to itself as a desideratum for knowledge.Accordingly, not only are pseudo-objects general, in and hence all objects which are actually judged or presented,to be included as Objects of our scientiflcknowledge (Wissens), but also

lez1

ALE)CUS MBINONG

The Theory ol Objects

all Objects which are Objects of our cognition only in possibility. However, there is no Object which could not at least in possibility be an Object of cognition; at any rate, we may say this if we adopt the instructivefiction that the capacityfor knowledgeis not impaired by limitations, such as stimulusthresholdsand thresholdsof discriminations, which are laid down by the constitution of the subject and are never entirely absent. Assuming an intelligence of unlimited capacities, there is nothing unknowable; and what is knowable, is. Ilowever, since the preferred usage is generally to apply "it is" (es gibt) to things which have being, and particularly to existingthings, it would perhapsbe clearerto say: All that is knowable is given-narnely, given to cognition. To this extent, all objects are knowable.Given-ness a most generalproperty can be ascribed as to Objects without exception,whether they are or are not. The consequence these considerations the relation of the of for activities Objects of cognition to the Objects of other psycho{ogical of scarcelyneedsto be drawn more explicitly. Regardless the other types of experience one might have of Objects,all Objects are, without exception, Objects of knowledge. Consequently,anyone who undertakesa scientific treatment of Objects from the standpoint of cognition need not fear that he rnight thus excludeany areafrom the totality of Objects.

Ie3j

,7.

T'Jin Tnronv or Osrncrs As "PURELoclc"

It is in accord with long-established trad$on to think of logic first, when consideringa scientific treatment of cognition. Actually, it is only very recently that problems have been set for one of the which agree main parts of logic, the so-calledpure or formal logic,18 unmistak4blywith what must properly be demandedof a theoretical elsewhere treatmenC Objects as such.lo I have already expressed of my basic agreement with E. Husserl'sattack against"psychologism" prevented in logic.2o did this at a time when external circumstances I me from obtaining r,norethan a preliminary and very incomplete acquaintance with thb extensivework of this author. Today, when I trust that through penetrating study I have done justice in some
18. S.. E" Husserl, LogischeUntrry*lr,ngrr, tnro volumes, (Leipzig and Halle, 1900and 1901), "Pure" and "Formal" Eogic are explicitly identifiedin Vol. I, p, 252. 19. In particular, Vol. I, pp. 241 ff,; also Vol. II, pp. 92 fr., p, 20. Uber Annahmen, l9P

measureto the merits of the publication in question, I can completely support my previous expressionof agreementand extend it still further to many another of those "problems." trt is, then, perhaps a dissentof relatively rninor importancethat I wotrld not rifer theseproblems precisely to "pure logic." I am influencedabove all by this fact: it is only with great difficulty that the notion of logic can be separatedfrom that of a technology devotedto the advancement our intellectual powers. Conof sequently,logic always remains a "practical discipline."zl We may say at most that a transition can be made from the work of this practical discipline to what tr have occasionally chancterized as a "theoretico-practicaldiscipline."z When logic is thus called "pure Iogic,"28 would prefer to say that the result is not logic at all. And I I would refer tle probiems set for "pure logic" to that theoretical discipline,or to one of those theoretical disciplines,to which logic, like all other practical disciplines,must fina-llybe traced. I am in complete agreementwith the author of the Logische Untersuchungen, I have just mentioned,in insisting that recourse as is not to be made exclusively to psychology.Indeed, when I consider the guiding idea to which our author returns again and again in his polemic against "psychologism" in order to characterizethis extra-psychological domain of knowledge, it is difficult for rne to avoid the impression that he was not entirely able to free himself from what he had opposedwith as much zeal as truth. "Pure" logic has to do with "concepts," "propositions," "arguments," and the like.* But are not concepts, after all, presentationswhich may be used for theoretical purposes,but which are nevertheless presentations? If one disregardsthe. obtrusive grammatical meaning of the word "proposition" (Satz), bs is explicitly demanded, a.8., by Bolzano, will one then be able to disregard the psychologicalprocess (assumptionor judgment) expressedby the grammatical proposi,1. I h"* tried to present this in greater detail in my work, tlber philosophische llissenschaJt und ihre Proprideutik (Vienna, 1885). See particularly pp. 96 t. 22. Loc. cit., p. 98. 23. I find the equivalent term, "formal logic," objectionable in that it brings to mind what used to be taught under tlis name and what has properly been opposed and apparently overcome. Is this objection based merely on a personal idiosyncrasy? We must also give some weight to the fact that the term "form" cannot provido a clear picture of what it is supposed to mean. * [It is impossible to reproduce in English the full significance of Meinong's remarks here and below. There is no English word or expression which duplicates the ambiguities of the German "Satz." The word "Satz" is here translated as "proposition," but obviou$ly "proposition of contradiction" is to be avoided,l

l e4l

ALEXIUS

MBINONO

The Theory ol Objects

Ies]

tion? More precisely: If we do this, what will be retained that can in some measurelay claim to the name "proposition"? Still, there is an extralogicalsensehere in which one can talk of a "law (Satz) of contradiction," or the "Carnot law (Satz)" and so on,% although, to be sure, this has the feel of a rather extendedusageof words. As far as I can see, such an extralogical senseis completely lacking in the case of the word "inference" (Schluss). Even il one speaks quite naturally of "the" syllogismin modus Darapti, of "the" hypothetical syllogism, and the like, one means an intellectual event or the possible results of such an event, just as one means a physiological event when one speaksof "the' circulation of the blood. To contrast "objective" inferencesand proofs with thory that are subjective26 might thus seem to obscure rather than to clarify the facts of the matter. But the entire tenor of the Logische Untersuchungen, well as many of the particular statements as that are contained in it, convincesone that, despitecertain differencesin detail (at presentunavoidable),the author'sgoal is thesame as our own. It is a goal to which he has beenforced by mathematico-philosophical studies20 by certain distinctionswhich are in part genuinely,and and in part only supposedly,psychological;I refer to the distinction between content (Inhalt) and Objectu and, what is even more to the point, to that between Object and Objective.2s Under such circumstances, common causewill be better servedif I ceasedwellthe ing on these considerations(which may be largely terminological anyway) and, instead, try to show briefly how, in my opinion, we may deal more adequatelywith the danger of "psychologism"-2 danger which, in spite of the attention devoted to it, may not yet \ have been entirely avoided. 8. TUB Tnronv or Os.recrs es Eprstsnolocy Before we-do this, however, we may draw an obvious practical consequence from the criticisms we have directed against the expression "pure logic." There is no need to invent a name for a (Wissen) which setsitself no practical theory of scientifickq5rwledge
24, What is involved here is, of course, the Objective; see Uber Annahmen, p . 1 9 7. ' IIy.p..26;-ilso pp. 94 and 101. i5. Losische(Jntersuchungez, 26. Seeop. cit., Prefacsto Vol. I, p. v. hcibererOrdnung," Io?tit,, pp. 185 ff. 27. "Uber Gegenstiinde 28. Uber Annahmen,pp. 150&

goals and accordingly represents a theoretical science. One could not wish for a more natural name than the designation,"Theorie

remote. "Psychologism,"as the name of a natural or consideredtendency to solve problerns with predorninantly psychological rneans, involves no blame in itself.2gHowever, within a certain sphere of

who neglectsthe second side of this fact and so proceedsin the theory of knowledge as if there were only a psychologicalside of cognition, or one who would foist the viewpoint of psychological events on this second side, is not to be spared the reproach of psychologism. Can we make clear to ourselveswhy there is this danger of falling into such a psychologism,a danger from which scarcely matters has anyonewho has concernedhimself with epistemological withheld his tribute? The double aspect (Doppelseitigkeit) of. cognition is so striking that hardly anyone could overlook it even if only existing things were to be known. However, as we have seen, all of mathematics,and particulad geometry,deals with the nonreal. Thus, the prejudice in favor of reality that I have repeatedly called to attention leads here to a dilemma which seemsto be quite illuminating and which is, nevertheless, basically very singular. To be sure, we may not become explicitly consciousof it easily, but
29. The proven objectivity of Uberweg-Heinze's presentation of facts assures me of this in my own case. They place my own scientific activity under the general title of "Psychologism," (Grundriss der Geschichte det Philosophie, 9th ed., Part IV, pp. 312 ff.) Ths sense in which I myself might agree with this characterization may be seen in Uber Annahmen, p, 196,

Ie6]

ALE)CUS MBINONO

The Theory ol Obiects

it may be formulated approximatelyin the following manner: either the Object to which cognition is directed exists in reality or it exists perhaps solely "in my idea" (more briefly, it "pseudo-exists',). nothing bearsmore eloquenttestimonyto the naturalness this disof junction than the use of the word itdeal.', According to modern usage,without regard for its historical meaning, the word .,ideal,' means the same as "thought of" or ',merely presented"; hence it pertains, apparently, to all of those objects which do not exist or which could not exist. What does not exist outside of us, so one automatically thinks, must at least exist in us. Such an belongsbefore the forum of psychology;one Qbject, it is supposed, then makes room for the thought that the knowledge of eiisting things (and along with this knowledgereality itself) cin perhapsbe treated "psychologically." And perhap5 this prejudice in favor of what is actqal can be traced one step farther back by exhibiting the truth from which it could have originated.It would certainly be mi$takento believethat every instance of hnowledgemust concern existenceor something existent. But is it not correct to say that all cognition as such ul-being timately has to do with something which has (mit einem Seienden)2That which has being, the "fact,', without which no cognition could count as cognition, is the Objective.It is the Objective which is graspedby the relevant cognitive act and to which being (Sein) or, more precisely, subsistence (Bestand) belongs,whether it is positive or negative,whether it is an Objective of being (Sein) or of.Sosein Would it be too risky to suppgsethat the faciuality of its Objective, which is unfailingty associatedwith any instance of cognition, has undergonea sort of transference the Object (which to is almost the only thing consideredby theory) and that it is then exaggeratedinto the tacit demand that everything that confronts knowing be real? The question may remain undecidedhere. Our problem is not the psychology of psychologism.This much, however, stands beyond all doubt: psychologism the theory of knowledgeis invariin ably based on the neglect or misunderstanding the Object side \ of of(the word "Object,' being here taken in its cognitive state,u -the widest sense,in which it includes the Objective). One falls into psychologism one fails to grasp the significance if and the distinctive character of the Objective agd aEcordingly,looks to the Object -In for the being which belongsto all cognfion. such a caseone does not, sufficiently appreciatgJhe possibility of Nichtsein and Sosein, and one says that ss6sthing actual must be involved in anything

l e1l

that has being. And surely, whoever wishes to free himself from this misconceptionneed not make it his task to keep psycholory at a distance from the theory of knowledge. The psychology of cognition must always constitute an integral part of the theory of knowledge.The only thing against which he rnust guard himself is taking for psychology that part of the theory of knowledge which is and must remain the theory of Objects. If the theory of the Objects of knowledgeor, more briefly, the theoryof Objects,is presented us as an integral part of the theory to of knowledge,so answerto the initial questionof our presentdisthe cussioncan easily be found. The proper place for investigatingObjects as such, we could then say, is the theory of knowledge.And, in fact, this result could be left standing without rnuch damageto the theory of Objects. The more clearly the theory of knowledge becomes aware of its tasks, the more certainly it will become and remain,by virtue of one of its fundamentalparts, a theory of that which is to be known, of the "given" in the sensein which the word of was employedabove, and consequently the sum-total of Objects generally. interestswill quite naturally Often enough,epistemological preparethe way for an interest in the theory of Objects. Nevertheless,if I seerightly, we must go one step further if we are really to do justice to the claims which a theory of Objects is competentto make in virtue of its distinctive nature. ScrcNce e 9. TUB Tusonv or Osrrcrs .4,s SppaRAre The position of psychology, which along with the theory of Objectsmust be given a fundamentalshare in the theory of knowlthat edge, points to this fact. We havealreadyseenit to be self-evident there can be no theory of knowledgewhich does not concern itself with the act of knowing and which is not to this extent also a psychology of cognition. However, no one would consider the significanceof psychologyfor the theory of knowledgeto be an adequate characterization the position of psychologyin the systemof sciof ences.No one would wish to regard psychology as nothing more than a piece of episternology. Shall we be satisfiedwith a wholly analogouscharccteization of the theory of Objects? Is it necessary
30. Agreement i$ expressed most recently by A. Hiifler, "Zur gegenw2irtigen Naturphilosophie," in Vol. II oL Abhandlungen zur Didoktik und Philosophie der Naturwissenschalt, ed. F. Poske, A, E{<ifler, and E. Grimsehl (tserlin, 1904), p. 151 (p. 91 of the separate edition).

Ie8]

ALE)CUS MEINONG

The Theory ol Obiects

Ie e]

for our interest in the theory of Objects to proceed, as it were, by way of our interest in cognition? It seemsthat anyone who has involved himself closely with the problems of the theory of Objects has plenty of direct experience to the effect that this is not the case. We may acknowledgethat epistemologymay utilize every detail which competent inquiry in the theory of Objectshas producedand will produce,to afford some further information, perhaps less directly, but no less clearly. We can fully appreciate the basic significance of what the theory of Objects has to show us concerningpsychologism epistemology, in as we have just done, and at the same time admit that the theory of Objects raises problems whose solutions are interesting for their own sakes. This becomesparticularly clear when qe make an ,assumption which may still involve much that is obscure,but concerningwhose essentialsI have no fear of making any mistake. I have referred before to the fact that a suitable place for mathematicscould never be found in the systemof sciences. I am not mistaken,the anomaIf lous position of mathematicshad its basis in the fact that the concept of a theory of Objects had not yet been formed. Mathematics is, in its essential features,a part of the theory of Objects.I say "in its essential features" in order to explicitly leave open the possibility of a specificdifferentiationof mathematical interests(which I believe is one of the unexplainedmatters mentioned above).81Apart from that, it seemsquite obvious to me that both internal and external factors have securedfor mathematicsan advantagewithin its own domain, while the theory of Objects must set the entire domain of objects before itself as its task or hold this domain before its eyes as an unattainableideal. If.this considerationis justified, then, as soon as some account is taken of the more specific aspectsof the theory of Objects we cannot fail to see how little our interests in it are epistemological interests. From what has been said, I draw the conclusionthat the theory of Objectshas a claim to the statusof a disciplineindependent even ^\ of the theory of knowledge, and, accordingly, to that of an independent science.Thh claim cannot be elevatedto the level of an accomplishedfact, but, on the contrary, is scarcely beginning to be fulfilled, for the theory as a whqle is somethingto be developed, and not somethingready to'be exhibited. The high stageof development of one of its parts constlutes an external obstacleto the
-J-t. E- tl" beginningsof #relevant work, see E. Mally, in No. uI ot these studies: Intro., Sec. 2; chap. vii, Secs,40 ff. [See footnote 7.]

recognition of its claims, which can hardly be overestimated.A mathematicianmight well be disturbed by the suggestionthat he is "really" a theorist of Objects (Gegerutandstheoretiker).F{owever, no one will demand that a physicist or chernistconsider hirnself to be a metaphysician.This is so becausea sciencewhich already exists cannot be either charactenzed even named in terms or of a sciencewhich is still merely an object of aspiration. Moreover, a relatively general science as such can and must set itself goals which are foreign to the relatively specializedsciences.This secondpoint is somewhatobscured,in the case of the relation of mathematicsto the theory of Objects, by the fact that in the domain of the theory of Objects mathematics represents not one (of several) but, at least for the time being, the only special science of its type which is known and recognized.A twofold task, perhaps quite dissimilar in its two aspecls, is, accordingly, to be ascribedto the theory of Objects. On the one hand, the theory of Objectshas the problems of a scienceof the highest degreeof generality and comprehensiveness. the other, it has, as if standOn ing in the place of a whole group of specializedsciences,those problemswhich so far have not received any special consideration. Becauseof the necessityfor descendinginto relatively specialized domains which arises from this situation, its nature as a general scienceis unavoidably again obscured.Consequently,the subsumption of mathematicsunder the theory of Objects can easily appear to threatenthe distinctive characterand specialclaim of the former. However, such external and accidental matters ought not to hamper insight into the essentialconnection between mathematics and the theory of Objects tg the extent that that connectionexists. This not entirely simple situation can, perhaps, best be given its due by saying: Mathematicsis certainly not the theory of Objects, but is now as before a sciencein its own right. However, its Objects are includedin the domain which the Theory of Objects,also having its own justification, must deal with as a whole. 10. TnB TnBonv oF OBJEcrs ,c,I.ro OrHen ScrsNrcrs; GeNeRAr, ANDSpncrArrzeo TueoRy oF Osrncrs The theory of sciencecan adopt two approachesto its subject matter-that is to say, the various sciences themselves-with which it deals. In the natural approach, it can proceed with assurance if it obeys the principle of all the factual sciences:first the facts and

[1oo]

ALEXIUS MEINONG

The Theory of Obiects

[ 101 ]

then the theory. The severalsciences rnust first be given. T'hen the necessityfor examining more closely their nature and mutual relationship may become justified. However, science is also, at least partially, the result of premeditatedactivity. In employingsuch forewhich sightedness, theory of sciencecan also deal with sciences the do not yet exist but should exist. It can find itself directed toward as renderingthe idea and the tasks of such sciences preciseas possible in anticipation of them. In the preceding discussionwe found ourselvescompelled by our interest in Objects to. considerations which belong to the theory of science.In this connettion, it is incumben?upon the theory of scienceto function in the secondof the two ways mentionedabove. The theory of Objects, which we must claim to be a proper science,is, in the main, a science that for the time'beinghardly exists at altr-especially as a separatediibipline explicitly recognizedin its have been carried out in own right. But, although no investigations that this the name of the theory of Objects, we must not suPpose sciencehas been wholly neglected. trf we were to trace out in detail the numerousand intimate relations which the sciencewe have just proposed bears to ways of thinking that have been followed in the past, we would see that it justifies itself by what it has to offer. This is not the proper time to trace theseconnections; in nevertheless, introducing this new science it is appropriateto make somemention of them, Thus, some notice can be taken of necessities which have been felt for a long time and which have already found expressionin the r,nostdiverseways, necessities which have arisen in consciouslyworking out interests that are very widespread,but which have often been unconscious of their real goal. In fact, I believethht no specialhistorical investigation actually is required to establishthat, although the theory of Objects may not have been pursued "explicitly" heretofore, it has all the rnore frequently been pqrsued "implicitly." To this I must add that, at least in practice, the implicit status has degreeswhich smooth,fransition to the explicit status. Anyone who wishes to pay attention to such transitions and their orsets should bear in mind that we have met with interests of two different types pertaining to the theory o\ Objects: those in regard to questiofisabout certain specialdomains of Objects,and those in regaqd'to questionswhich concern the domain of Objects as a whole. We can in this sense,even if it be only for momentary undqetdnding, separatea specializedand a generaltheory of Objects.

(in We have referred above to the faat that speciatrized a certain sensethe most specialized) ttreory of Objec'r.s has found in mathematics most splendid representation the that could be desired. This luster has long led to efforts to make the procedure, more mathematico,accessible other sciences-I might say, other doto mains of Objects. We shall scarcelybe tripped unr by any significant error if we add: wheneversuch atternptshave been undertaken, then to that extent an effort has been naadealso to do the task of specialized theory of Objects in areas outside of rnathernatics.Of course,not every application of mat"hernatical proceduresneed thus be taken into considera{.ion. When the merchant or the engineercatrculates,he has as little to do with the theory of Objects as with any other theory. Flowever, certain presuppositionshaving to do with Objects lie naturally at the base of such practicanapplications; it is not otherwisewhen the application results in a theoretical interest. In contrast with the technique of calculation which dernands complete attention, the nature of these presuppositions can rernain fully in the background"This is ilinrstrated most clearly by the theory of probability and the theory of probable error, which even now are still not recognizedby everyone as naturatrlybelonging to Logicand psychology.The nature of these assulroptions possibly put the can calculationsin question at the serviceof the theory of Objects (as we can see in the case of the theory of combinations). Meanwhile, geometry seernsbetter prepared than arithrnetic to extend a hand beyond its narrow borders to discoveriesin the theory of Objects. trf one observesthat the domain of spatiatrquantities belongs to arithmetic, then what is offered as the translation (so familiar to everyone) of the geornetricalview from space to tirne is already extramathematical and, moreover,pertains to the theory of Objects. It pertains to the theory of Objects becauseit is in no way tied up with the so-calledreality, or more precisely,real existenceof tirne. It is obvious that the analogy is valid for phoronorrnyto a rnuoh greaterrneasure; if-what seemsto me to need no proof-,A. Fliifler is correct in contending that tension is the "third fundamental phenomenonof rnechanics" along with space and time,82then an additional direction is indicated in which this science,without prejudice to its naturaXly ernpirical character,engages iraterests the the of
32. A. Eltjfler, "Zur gegenwiirtigen Naturphilosophie," p. 84 (p. 24 in the separate edition), note 23; also p. 164 (104). In any case, "the theory of dimensions" mentioned on p. 147 {87), ibid., deserves to be mentioned in connection with the point before us.

ALE)SUS MEINONG [102] a priori treatment theory of Objectsthrough the most thoroughgoing

The Theory of Obiects

[1031

chology to order the "perceptual Objects" ("Empfindungsgegens' tiinde')ts belonging to t}te difterent sensesand, where possible,to understandtheir multifarious aspectsin tep.s of spatial representation are particular$ instructive. Even if, in regard to visual sensation, where these effortl have brought forth the most tangible results,sa the name "color-geometry" implies far more praise than is actually deserved,it still becomesundeniably aPparentthat the character of the pertinent investi$tions belongsmuch more to the theory of Objectsthan to psychology.I trust that it is not excessively personal for me to report at this time that much of the essential nature of the way in which the theory of Objects frames its questions originally occurred to me while I was engagedin supposedly labors toward clarification of thesematters. exclusivelypsychological What I have called the encroachmentof the mathematicalapproach beyond its strictest limits has an instinctive and unconscious iharacter in comparison with the completely explicit attempts to expand that domain and to generalizeto the fullest extent possible that way of framing a problem.Thesehaveprobably alreadyachieved someimportanceunder the name of the generaltheory of functions; one cannot fail to see this in such designationsas "the theory of extension" and "the theory of manifolds," and even under the frequently misunderstoodcatchword, "meta-mathematics."From the point of view we have addptedhere, thesestrikingly significantinvesiigations representthe transition from the specializedto the general theory of objects.A similar statusmay be ascribedto the endeavors and results customarily grouped under the generalname of "mathematical logic," even though those endeavorsare in many respects intended for an'entirely different purpose. On the o$er hand, it is and suglestions,which likely that the treasureof valuable assertions from Aris(non-mathematical)logi,q,epistemology, and metaphysics totle to the presenthave contributed to the area with which we are
33. A t** introduced by Witasek, o,h?"h ,""-. to me very useful. (Cf' his der allgemeinen Gr.unillagen Asthetik [Ireitrzig, 1904], pp. 36 ff.) psychologischen Farbenkiirper," Ioc. cit., fp":,i"f 34. Cf. my "Bermerkungen pp. 5 ff.

tences.86 Huwever different the two casesmay be on the whole, one to is 0empted say that the generaltheory of Objects must learn from grammarjust ai the specializedtheory of Objects must learn from mathematics. As this quick survey showsdespiteits somewhatcursory nature, the theory of Objects is by no means completely dependentupon work which is yet to be performed. Indeed, one might ask whether the attempt to introduce a "theory of Objects" lneans any more than a new name for an old concern. One could easily go on to find that it is indifferent to the investigationitself whether it is undertaken by a mathematician,physicist, logician, ot a student of the would lurk in a theory of Objects. Nevertheless, misunderstanding which was countered explicitly this last move-a misunderstanding at the beginning of this exposition. It is certainly immaterial who solvestheoretical problems and under which name he solvesthem. obtained If recognitionas a special discipline should be successfully for the theory of Objects, one would, now as before, always have physicists,linguists, and the repreto be thankful to nnathematicians, for their energeticfurthering of the insentatives other sciences of terestsof the theory of Objects, even when they do not mean to But, havedepartedfrom the legitimateterritory of their own science. for many, recognition of this science would clarify the nature of the problems to be solved-especially where (as is commonly the case) the most relevant works are not of the greatestimportance. A natural consequence this is that old problemsare renderedprecise of and new ones introduced. From the point of view of the theory of Objects, the problems and concernswhich we have just grouped together-and which at first glancewould seemso diverse-present themselves belonging together; the value of such a point of view as is thus confirmed.
35. Ct, Uber Annahmen,esp, pp. 19 ff., 175 ff.

[104]

AIEXIUS

MEINONO

[105] his claim may pursuedonly in the name of the theory of knowledge,
The Theory ol Obiects

11. Pnnosopr{y AND rnr Tlrsony on OnlBcrs

one must resolve, particularly if one endeavors to start from tle

-le.

one cannot work in the theory of knowledge without also working in the F.ory of Objects, or at least utilizingl the most important discoveriesof the theory of Objects, seemsto me beyond doubt.s? Therefore, if someofleshould claim that these studiei are properly
riloJoetails on this point u." 3 b, found in rpy work, uber phirosophische ' Wissenschaltund ihre Propiideutik,. chap. i. Squ,{-*t recently, Utin.., :;Zu, gegenwiirtigen Naturphilosophie,', Ioc. c4, pp. 123 (63) fi. 37, Cf. also H:ilfler, loc, cr'l.,p. l5l (91).

existencetherefore can be inferred from the fact of the appearance. I would certainly not deny that the things that thus appear are of interestto the physicist.But I cannot imagine how the "phenomena"
38. Communicated in SuPplementI of Hiifler's repeatedly cited u'ork, "Zur gegenw?irtigen NaturphilosoPhic." 39. Ibid., pp. 15a (94) ff. ;ii, gegenwtirtigen Naturphilosophie,"esp' pp' 131 (71) ff' +0. Ct.

[ 10 6 J

ALEXIUS

MEINONG

of these (e.g., the "phenomena" that come after the beginning and the end 9f the appearingthing) can be excrudedfrom ihe d6main of metaphysics .{l..gnnronriate evaluation of the importance of what Breuer and Hiifler suggstwould require me to digress too far from the main therneof this study. Fof now, thesefei hints to show why it still seemsto me to be most appropriut","rougt, -"V-U" in the

--.it*

rcarm _or-mvestlgatlon the inorganic as well as the organic and psychological, order to ascettainwhat has validity toi in Eu"rytrring that falls in such diverserealms. of course,the emphasiswniJtr trris definition places on universarityrenders the necess-ity clarifying for the relations betweenmetaphyiics and the tnrory oi o;jr.tr-;'re"cially obvious. This is so because our attentionhas utso ulen-aiu*r, 9{ .th" exceptionalbreadth of the area pertaining to th" tfreoSyot Objects.But- perhaps it is precisely bV th" simultaneous considera_ the theory of Objects that we are led to ,a standpoint from :t??_-ol wnrchwe can perfectour characterization metaphysics thereby of ind silen"", many of the doubts which may previousrynu* u."rr iui*a about it. . - In this way, moreover, I can fan back on what has been said before and, to that extent, cut my discussion ,nort. f, u, *e _ may well believe,everythingthat exisisin the world is either psychological_or physical, then metaphysics,insofar as it is conclrned with the psychologicalas welf ai the physical, is the science of reality in general (von der Gesamtheit des wirktichen). To this extent, then, to cite an example, both the fundamentai thesis of monism, which assertsthe essentialidentity of the physicar tn" psychological,and that of duarism,which assertstneii "oJ difessentiar f:t"l:",. are metaphysical. But any one who knows miog, it U" rdentical or different certainly knows sometflng about thes=e things; yet his knowledge,however, also concerns idintity and/or differT"?, ."ld identity itsel-fis as far from being a thing atrIs difference. Both identity and differencestandgutside oi the disjunctionbetween the physical and the psychologicali sing they stand beyond rtre real
philosophische Ilisserucha!t,d",, p. 7,

[107] (ausserhalbdes Realen). There is atrsoknowledge of what is not (von Nichtwirklichem). No matter how generally the probact:c,al which are even lems of metaphysics construed, there are questions are are not more general;these questions,unlike those of metaphysics, oriented exclusivelytoward reality. The questionsof theory of Objects are of this kind. But one will immediately ask: is it not forced, or at least arbifrom the area of trary, to exclude in principle all ideal objectsa2 metaphysicalinvestigation?f answer that in the first place they are by no means excluded in every sense.Our metaphysicalinterests would certainly be in a sorry plight indeed, as the exarnple of monism and dualism has just shown, if one couLd not speak in of metaphysics identity and difference,nor of cause,purpose, unity, continuity, and many other objects which are either entirely or partially of an ideal nature. However, many Objects of this type are also discussed physics,althoughno one would count them among in the Objects of physical inquiry. In any case, the restriction of the realm of metaphysics reality is intended with a very definite resto ervation. Fresupposingsuch a reservation, however, X believe in fact that this restriction is entirely compatible with the spirit in which metaphysics has been carried on both in ancient and in modof ern times, in accordance with that natural.pre-erninence the real which has been repeatedlytouched upon. "Ontolory," the "theory of categories,"and the other subjectsassignedmore or less unanimouslyto metaphysics have occasionallyallowed a place for interests extendingbeyond the limits of the real; but this is an indication only of the correctness and unavoidability of these interests.Itrowever,as far as I can see,there is no roorn for doubting that the fundarnental intention of all metaphysics[as always been directed toward comprehending the "world" in a strict, natural sense,i.e., the world seemsto show of reality. This is so even when this comprehension that what is to be comprehendedhas no claim at aXl to the title of a real object. But even if our present view of the character of metaphysicsup to this time should not convince everyone,indeed even if it should be shown to be historically incorrect, the error concernsonly the definition "de lege late," as it were, and the defititton "de lege ferenda"4swould remain open for consideration. of On this assumption,the characterizattom rnetaphysicsadvanced above would be a proposal for a definition: the restriction of the
42, "Uber Gegensttinde hdherer Ordnung," pp. 198 ff. 43. Breuer,in Hiifler, Ioc, cit,, p. 189 (129),

The Theory ol Objects

ALE)SUS MEINONO [108] name "metaphysics" to the general science of reality would be just as desirablein the interest of a clear formulation of the problems of metaphysics it would be in the interest of its distinct deliminaas tion in relation to the theory of Objects.

The Theory of Objects

llOel

ist"aa in such a way that, whereas all existing things subsist, it is not true that all subsisting entities (e.g., difference) also exist? Even in this case,the area which the theory of Objectscomprehends, as,we have seen, would not be included in its entirety; the nonsubsistent, absurd,would be excluded.To be sure, the nonsubsisthe tent is of little concernto the natural interest,and it provides an even smallerpoint of purchaseto intellectualunderstanding.aE it does But belong to the "given" (Gegebenen),after all, so that the theory of Objectscan by no meansignoreit.

44. "Uber Gegenstiinde htiherer Ordnung," p. 186. 45. SeeE. Mally, in No. III of thesestudies, i, Spcs.5 f.. ,chap. I

absurd by nature, whether it subsistsor could equally weli existthese are questionswhich are actually of interest to the theory of Objects and which are ultimately questionsabout being. trn brief, therefore: even the restriction to Soseinprobably cannot be brought into harmony with the essentialnature of the theory of Objects. There may be, however, a rather sirnpie source of assistance here. It is a methodologicaldistinction, and one which, so far as it peoptre heretofore have sought concernsthe nature of the sciences, to make with too much, rather than too little, ardor. As is generally known, some casesof knowledgeare justified in terms of the characteristics,the Sosein,of their Objects or Objectives.Again' there are other casesof which this is not so.aoThe first type of knowledge has long been called a priori, and the latter, empirical. Nowadays we occasionallymeet with failure to recognizethis distinction, but such failure no rnore affectsthe validity of the distinction than does the fact of color blindness aftect the distinction between the various colors. (The state of color blindness,however,is psychologically much more interesting.) If we now make use of the distinction betweena priori and empirical, we will have no difficulty, it seems to me, in making a satisfactorydifferentiationbetweenour two disciplines. What can be known about an Object in virtue of its nature, hence a prioiri, belongs to the theory of Objects"This involves, in the first place, the Sosein of the 'ogiven." But it also involves its being (Sedn) insofar as that can be known frorn i.ts Sosein.On the other hand, that which is to be determined about Objects only provided that the knowledgeis a posteriori belongsto rnetaphysics, of a sufficiently general character. That the domain of reality will not be oversteppedas long as the knowledgein question is affirmative in nature is assuredby the a posteriori characterof this knowledge. There are, therefore, precisely two sciencesof highest generality: an a priori sciencewhich concernseverythingwhich is given, and an a posteriori one which includes in its investigationseveryknowledge,i.e,, reality thing which can be consideredby empiricatr the in general"The latter scienceis metaphysics, former is the theory of Objects. The most striking feature of this definition is that metaphysics of appearsas an empiiical science;yet the representatives the separate scienceshave reproached both ancient and modern rnetaphysicsmainly for a lack of sufrcient empiricism. I would not wish
46, Uber Annahmen,pp. 193 f.

[1 1 0 ]

ALEXIUS MEINONG

objects, however,that the word ,,metaphysics" has often . If one_ been used as a name for intellectual endeavorsor -evenfor results

It is imp-robable that all difficulties concerningthe boundary betweenmetaphysics the theory of Objectsare eliminatedby means and

[111] of this division. Eut it would be unfair to demand in this instance what has not been clearly achievedin any instance of contiguous sciences. more important objection emergesspecificallyfrom the A standpoint of the theory of Objects. We have treated this as if it were simply a generalscience,even though we had to make a quite explicit distinction above betweena generaland a specialized theory of Objects. Here is an imperfection which cannot be removed, at least in the present state of knowledgeof nnatterspertaining to the theory of Objects; there are practical reasonsfor this. trt is clear that mathematics,insofar as it is a specializedtheory of Objects, could be accompanied still other specializedtheories of Objects, by their number scarcelyto be determined.However, these areas are at present so incompletelyknown to us that in studying them there is not yet any need to specialize.The specialized theoriesof Objects divide at this time, therefore, into rnathernaticaland non-rnathematical. What can now be said about the second member of this wholly primitive division is so obvious that it easily finds a place within the limits of the general theory of Objects. T'o this extent, there is at present no specialiZedtheory of Objects other than mathematics. course, one cannotpredict how long this will be so. Cf Developmentalong these lines will not be forestalled by the definition proposed above. Jr.lstas specializedempiricatrsciencesare set over against the general empirical science,specializeda priori sciences can accompany the general a priori science.For the tirne being, this possibility is realized only in mathematics;in subsuming rnathematicsunder the standpoint of the theory of Objects, we have placed it alongsideof disciplines which are not now actual, but they are disciplines which at least are possible. fn any event, rnathernaticsneed no trongerfind itself in that odd isolation frorn which earlier theoretical conceptionsof mathematicssuffer.a? I must finally return to placing the theory of Objects among the philosophical sciences,which was accomplishedabove without appealing to a definition. Ou occasion,I have attempted to classify as philosophicalthose sciences which are occupiedonly with psychological mattersor which are occupiedalso with psychological matters. The opinion has been expressedvery recentlt'8 that my work in the theory of relations and complexes may have led me by now to ascribe an essentiallytwofold object to philosophy: firstly, psychological matters and, secondly, relations and complexes. That
47. See above,Secs.2 and 7. Naturphilosophie,"p. L24 (64), 48. By lltjfler in his study, "Zur gegenw?irtigen

The Theory ol Objects

I rr2]

ALEXIUS MEINONG

The Theoryof Obiects

[113]

such a modificationwould destroy completelythe uniiy of the original definition is amply evident. One should be scandalized find to the objects of philosophy turning out to be a hodgepodge leftof oversfrom the natural sciences, unlessone believedthat philosophy should generallybe characterized referenceto whateverthe natby ural sciences happenedto leave over.4o such a view the function On remaining for philosophy could hardly be called worthy. And even if the introduction of a scientific activity intended esientially for pjcking up left-overs could have some practical justification, this should scarcely alter the theoretical facf that in ttremselves these some particular technique contributed by another science. Insofar theory in as mathematics partiiular can be regardedas a specialized of Objects,it would be ungratefulto forget that researchof the type which belongsto the theory of Objectsoften leadsto splendidresults without any thought for otber philosophicalinterests. science.If I may count metaphysicsamong the philosophicaldisciplines becauseit conceivesits problems broadly enouglrthat, along with the physical,the psychologicalis also to be included in it, then 12. CotqcrusroN

must be consideredtoo. The foregoing can be said quite independently of the fact that, in connection with ideal Objects (which by nature are always superordinate Objects lsuperiusf), psychological .as indispensablesubordican sometimesenter into consideration nates (inferiora). Of course,I do not hesitateto admit that the parallelism which has just been shown to holdrQetweenthe theory of Objectp and metaphysics also holds in othei matters which are fundamentdllyof more practical than theoretical significance.From the fact that metaphysics concernedwith the psychological,and not only wlth is the psychologicalbut. dso with the physical, I have 'concluded,on the side of metaphysics, that the repr\sentativeof the psychological +g.-Ef.T sreuer, H6fler, c;r., (trO). in /oc. tp.ttso
50. Concerning the reasons for this change in the terminology I have used heretofore, see No. III of these studies by Mally, chap. i, Secs. 9, 11.

[114]

D\ ALEXIUS MEINONG

The Theory ol Obiects

[115]

siders himself authorized (or under the present circumstances,

of Objects is a young, a very young, science.Anyone who betakes wealth of problems-to-be himself to its domain finds an immeasurable considerand possiblesolutions.trIowever,evenwith the rnost carefutr ation, he cannothope to fiit the correct answereverytime. Instead,he firmly will to must expectthat whai he believes have been established and to the developed oftentimesfall victim to advancedknowtredge techniques the future. trt is also obviousthat in the beginof research ning the individuality of the investigatormust play a more determinatraditions tive role in the results than it does in tirnes of established

vation. some utopia, but as a goal which we may clearly hold before our eyes, and which we have already begun to use our best abilities to achieve. Accordingly,,if the present explanationsare to.function at the same time as a kind of special preface to the p3rt of the present book which has to do with the theory of obiJcts, this is the Lppro-

sequently sometimesto go into ones tr have touched on. This is itself a sign of the primitive stateof the theory of Objects.One might in very well reproachus for not having smoothedout our differences oral converiation in order that we might appear before the public with a firmly unified systemof harrnoniousconceptsand terrns. The ought to be decidedin private rather than demandthai controversies in print is certainly legitimate, but I can rePort that we_are not spahng of discussionin the Graz PhilosoptricalInstitute' Naturally,

[ 116] ALEXIUS MEINONG the principle of the greatestpossiblefreedom of conviction hords at the sametime; had we decided not to allow individual views to be

[117] burdensome(and insofar as they really are, they and be superfluous will certainly not endure). Nor will he take ofiense at the fact that we have decidedto give this or that concept a name different from the one I have used in earlier works. .A.good term is as nnuch as hatrfa discovery;and it is better to replacea bad term when a better one has been found than to continue draggingalong the evil consequences the old for the sake of conservatisrn. of I may now summat'up.\n the foregoing, an attempt has been made to demonstratethe legitimacy of the theory of Objects as a separatesciencein its own right. The two treatises that followin iniidentally and implicitly the other studies assembled this book as well-are intended to make contributions to this science.In this and irrefutability can hardly be respect, to demand completeness reaionable as things now stand. It is enoughif we should have been to able successfully set forth a considerationand critique of ideas that strive to go still further, and by this to show that the path we have taken is worthy of confidence,and one by which anyone who resolvesto take it will be advanced.It is to be hoped that what we have been able to offer here will bring friends and recognition to the new scienceof the theory of Objects.

The Theory ol Obiects

Q * -[ : t*,

'b 8* -\\^-^

" "ttt

u o t' r-' d

L'\ , ed.R"tr ,i= CL"-' *,,


Fro* puor) tq b O

c o.C ?L*,.6\rnr-'{''t o\ "1 5

If I am not mistaken, the reader will take no offense at the great number of new conceptsand terms,.of which many may appeir to -lZ. s.e s.c. to.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy