Non Standard Analysis
Non Standard Analysis
Branden Laske
Department of Mathematics
University of California, Santa Cruz
June 13, 2012
Abstract
Introducing the notion of a new branch in Mathematics, this idea of
Non-Standard analysis was rst introduced in the 1960s by Abraham
Robinson. The concept of his ideas was using this intuitively natural
idea of innitesimals and their appeal to our natural intuition and
understanding of numbers.These innitesimals were rst popularized
by Leibniz in the late 1600s along with the discovery of innitesi-
mal calculus. Our today understanding of these innitesimals exists
in our real number system as vanishing quanities. We were not
able to give a consistent theory in analysis of which included these
innitesimals until Robinson introduced a satisfactory way in doing
so. The simplest way in understand what Robinson did to achieve this
was using a semantic approach. This was basically the study of mod-
els and developing purely set-theoretic objects called superstructures
which construct a mapping from our real numbers to this extension
of the real numbers called the hyperreals. Think of these hyperre-
als as our real number system but include innitely small quanities
called infinitesimals and quantities which are innitely large, or a
largest value of which we will call infinite. To gain a sucient grasp
in understanding our new perspective in Analysis, we will begin by
introducing Leibniz and the innitesimals that greatly inuenced ad-
vancements into Non-standard Analysis.
1
1 Leibniz and the innitesimals
A philosopher, rationalist, and mathematician, Leibniz became an impor-
tant contributer to anything he set his mind to. Much of his mathematical
successes were in the development of innitesimal calculus, his work in me-
chanical calculators with the description of the pinwheel calculator, and the
renement of the binary number system. Leibniz saw through his work that
there was much importance in understanding this notion of innite and he
began relying on a principle called the Law of Continuity. This law states
that what succeeds for the nite numbers must also succeed for the innite
numbers. Although much of his work is relevant to todays mathematics, we
are only concerned with his work within innitesimals.
We want to rst dene what we mean by infinitesimal. We can introduce
our Archimedean property which denes some number x N and x = 0 as
an infinitesimal if it satises the following.
1
x
< 1,
1
x
<
1
1 + 1
,
1
x
<
1
1 + 1 + 1 . . .
, . . .
Again by the Archimedean property we want to give a similar denition
of what we mean by the value innite. Let us dene some number x as
being infinite if it satises the following.
|x| > 1, |x| > 1 + 1, |x| > 1 + 1 + 1, . . .
Innitesimals The reason Leibniz adopted this idea of very small values
was beause of its intuitive value. The idea of an innitely small value doesnt
seem like a very natural idea of thinking as humans. Lets consider a visual
representation of an innitesimally small value.
The basic idea behind this picture is an intuitive example of innitesimal.
We take triangles and plug in a triangle inside of the triangle. We continue
2
to do this innitely many times to construct innitely small triangles down
even smaller than the known existent sub atomic particles. In order to accept
this idea you must think Pseudo-Physically passed what we actual know in
science and see in reality.
Now that we have a good understanding of the innitesimals that inuenced
the work of Non-Standard Analysis we will now begin to study and gain a
grasp in understand the construction of what we call the hyperreals.
2 Robinson and the Hyperreals
First let us dene in words what is meant by a hyperreal. Think of it as
taking our real number line, the collection of all rational numbers, integers,
irrationals, and transcendentals, and extending it to include our two values
dened earlier, infinite and infinitesimal. This term hyper-real was rst
introduced by Edwin Hewitt in 1948 when we pioneered the construction of
the hyperreals. We will denote these hyperreals as
R and we can think of the
reals, R, as a subset of the hyperreals R
P (S
n1
)
S :=
S
n
is a superstructure of S.
From this we dene elements of S as individuals or atoms;
elements of
S are entities.
Putting this denition into words we dene our structure,
S as a nite set
of rules, elements, etc. We dene a superstructure as a powerset of many
sets. So when we speak of values within our superstructure we are speaking
in terms of a union of structures which help construct our superstructure.
To better understand exactly what we mean by an entity, let us examine the
rules and properties which hold within entities.
5
(1) S
o
S
1
S
2
. . .
S and S
o
S
1
S
2
. . .
S. S
n
are entities
including .
(2) Each entity is transitive such that for
S if A is an entity and x A, then
x is either an entity or an atom.
(3) If A is an entity and B A, then B is also an entity.
(4) If A is an entity, then P (A) is an entity.
(5) Let A be a set of entities. If A = , then
A :=
xA
X is an entity. If
A
S, then
A :=
xA
X is an entity.
(6) If x
1
, . . . , x
k
S, then {x
1
, . . . , x
k
} is an entity.
(7) If A
1
, . . . , A
k
are entities, then
j
A
j
= A
1
. . . A
k
is an entity.
(8) If A
1
, . . . , A
k
are entities, then A
1
. . . A
n
is an entity.
(9) All functions acting between entities are themselves entities.
These entities are very fundamental once we approach our construction of
the Transfer Principle and dening our three fundamental principles which
will construct it. But rst we must also dene our formal language which
will be used within our new restricted universe,
S.
Formal Language Our formal language will be very similar to our normal
logic language used within our mathematics. We then must identify what
will be used within
S.
(i) Variables : {a, b, c} and they will be underlined to denote variables.
(ii) Constants : cns(L) which will denote the set of all constants.
(iii) Basic Predicates : and = which denote as an object in some set and
equality.
(iv) Seperation Symbols : ( and )
(v) Connectives : , , , ,
(vi) Quantiers : and
Our language will only be admissible to formulas that are well-formed formu-
las aka ws. Now that we have layed the structure we will be working with
along with the language, we can now begin to dene the Transfer Principle
which allows us to dene our non-standard world as a Totally Ordered Set.
6
5 The Transfer Principle
The idea of the Transfer Principle is to dene the mapping from our standard
world to our non-standard world so that what holds within our real numbers
also holds within our hyper-reals. We denote this mapping as:
Let :
S
S such that ;
S is our standard world so that
S
S. (1)
Basically we dene our standard world
S as being contained within the non-
standard world
S. In order for this denition to be true we must develope
it through three fundamental principles. These principles help us to make
use of a non-surjective interpretation maps to add non-standard elements to
our standard superstructure
S. This should be more clear as we dene some
important properties within this superstructure.
Standard Denition Principle For simplicity of things this principle
implies that the mapping * preserves much of the structure of
S. In other
words, * does not run into any diculties in terms of properties, equivalences,
structure, etc.
Internal Denition Principle We dene this principle as the following:
Denition: An entity A
S is internal i it can be written as
A = {x B : (x)}
Where B
S is an internal entity and is a transitively bounded internal
predicate with x as its only free variable.
In other words, A is considered internal if it contains a predicate , which
contains a free variable within any arbitrary entity, in this case B. This
arbitrary entity must be an entity of our standard world. We can understand
this by saying
Let A
S and A = (x) for some x B. Since B
S
A
S
A is internal since x A B
S
S.
Existence of External Sets We will denote
B as an external set. We
let
S contain an innite entity, is nonstandard i
B =
B some innitely
countable entity B
S. For any entity A
S the following hold.
7
(1) If A is innite, then
A is external.
(2) If A is innite, then P (
A) is external and
P (A)
P (A) P (
A)
(3) If S is innite, then
S\