The document discusses the concepts of valid and invalid arguments. It introduces the idea of an "argument form" which abstracts away the specific statements in an argument to focus on its logical structure. An argument is valid if and only if it has no substitution instances where the premises are true and conclusion is false. The method of refutation by logical analogy can be used to show that two arguments with the same form are both invalid by exhibiting one with true premises and a false conclusion.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
1K views7 pages
Argument Forms and Refutation by Logical Analogy
The document discusses the concepts of valid and invalid arguments. It introduces the idea of an "argument form" which abstracts away the specific statements in an argument to focus on its logical structure. An argument is valid if and only if it has no substitution instances where the premises are true and conclusion is false. The method of refutation by logical analogy can be used to show that two arguments with the same form are both invalid by exhibiting one with true premises and a false conclusion.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 7
ARGUMENT FORMS AND REFUTATION BY LOGICAL ANALOGY
THE PRECISE MEANING OF INVALID AND VALID
ARGUMENT FORMS AND REFUTATION BY LOGICAL ANALOGY
Deductive argument is one whose premises are claimed to provide conclusive grounds for the truth of its conclusion. If that claim is correct, that is, if the premises of the argument really do assure the truth of its conclusion with necessity, that deductive argument is valid. Every deductive argument either does what it claims, or does not; therefore every deductive argument is either valid, or invalid. If it is valid it is impossible for its premises to be true without its conclusion being true also.
The central task of deductive logic is discriminating valid arguments from invalid ones. If the premises of a valid argument are true, its conclusion must be true. If the conclusion of a valid argument is false, at least one of the premises must be false. In short, the premises of a valid argument give incontrovertible proof of the conclusion drawn.
This informal account of validity must be made more precise, thus, the introduction of the concept of an argument form. Suppose we are presented with these arguments:
First argument: If Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare, then Bacon was a great writer Bacon is a great writer. Therefore, Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare.
Second argument: If Washington was assassinated, then Washington is dead. Washington is dead. Therefore, Washington was assassinated.
In the first argument, we may agree with the premises but disagree with the conclusion, judging the argument to be invalid. By logical analogy, seeing that the second argument has the same form as that of the first argument, which is the premises are true but the conclusion is false, we can say that the second argument is invalid.
First argument is invalid. Second argument has the same form as that of the First argument. Therefore, Second argument is also invalid.
Such is a method of Refutation by Logical Analogy. Refutation by Logical Analogy exhibits the fault of an argument by presenting another argument with the same form whose premises are known to be true and whose conclusion is known to be false.
In Refutation by Logical Analogy, to prove the invalidity of an argument, it suffices to formulate another argument that: 1. Has exactly the same form as the first, and 2. Has true premises and a false conclusion.
The method of Refutation by Logical Analogy is based upon the fact that validity and invalidity are purely formal characteristics of arguments, which is to say that any two arguments having exactly the same form are either both valid or both invalid, regardless of any differences in the subject matter with which they are concerned.
A given argument exhibits its form very clearly when the simple statements that appear in it are abbreviated by capital letters. Thus we may abbreviate the arguments as:
First Argument:
If Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare, then Bacon was a great writer B G Bacon is a great writer. G Therefore Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare
B
Second Argument:
If Washington was assassinated, then Washington is dead A D Washington is dead. D Therefore Washington was assassinated
A
Thus the forms, First Argument Second Argument BG G B AD D A
So written, their common form is easily seen.
Statement variable is simply a letter for which, or in place of which, a statement may be substituted. In the preceding section we used capital letters to symbolize particular simple statements, to avoid confusion, we will use lowercase letters from the middle part of the alphabet p,q,r,s, as statement variables.
Argument form refers to an array of symbols containing statement variables but no statements; such that when statements are substituted for the statement variables the same statement being substituted for the same statement variable throughout the result is an argument. For definiteness, the convention that in any argument form p shall be the first statement variable that occurs in it, q shall be the second, r the third, and so on. Thus the expression: p q q p is an argument form, for when the statements B and G are substituted for variables p and q respectively, the result is the first argument and when the statements A and D are substituted for the same variables, the result will be the second argument.
Any argument that results from the substitution of statements for statement variables in an argument form is called a substitution instance of that argument form. It is clear that any substitution instance of an argument form may be said to have that form, and that any argument that has a certain form is a substitution instance of that form.
For any argument there are usually several argument forms that have the given argument as a substitution instance. For example, using the first argument:
BG G B
is a substitution instance of each of the four argument forms Argument 1 Argument 2 Argument 3 Argument 4 p q q p p q r p p q r s p q r
Thus we obtain the given arguments by substituting: Argument 1 Argument 2 Argument 3 Argument 4 B p p p and s p and r G q q and r q and r q
In the four argument forms, Argument 1 corresponds more closely to the structure of the given argument than do the others. It does so because the given argument results from the first argument form by substituting a different simple statement for each different statement variable in it. We call the first argument form the specific form of the given argument. Specific form of that argument refers to that argument form from which the given argument results when a different simple statement is substituted for each different statement variable.
THE PRECISE MEANING OF INVALID AND VALID
Merriam Webster Dictionary defines validity as having such force as to compel serious attention and usually acceptance. It implies being supported by objective truth or generally accepted authority. Words synonymous to valid are sound, which implies a basis of flawless reasoning or of solid grounds, cogent, which stress either weight of sound argument and evidence of lucidity of presentation, and convincing, which suggests a power to overcome doubt, opposition, or reluctance to accept.
Saying that an argument is valid is equivalent to saying that it is logically impossible that the premises of the argument are true and the conclusion false. A less precise but intuitively clear way of putting this is to say that in a valid argument IF the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true.
Arguments of a valid FORM are valid even if they are completely absurd. For example, the following argument is valid: All women are cats. All cats are men. Therefore, All women are men.
This argument has false premises and a false conclusion. This brings out the hypothetical character of validity. What the validity of these arguments amounts to is that it assures us the conclusion must be true IF the premises are true.
Valid argument is truth preserving. Truth in the premises of a valid argument is preserved in the conclusion. Of course, if the premises are not true to begin with, then even a valid argument cannot ensure that the conclusion is true. But ONLY valid arguments are truth preserving.
Relying upon the technique of refutation by logical analogy, the specific form of a given argument has any substitution instance whose premises are true and whose conclusion is false, then the given argument is invalid.
By refutation by logical analogy, an invalid argument form is an invalid argument. Any argument form that is not invalid must be valid. Hence, an argument for is valid if and only if it has no substitution instances with true premises and false conclusion. Since validity is a formal notion, an argument is valid if and only if the specific form of that argument is a valid argument form.
REFERENCES:
Logic: Language, Deduction and Induction. Irving M. Copi and Carl Cohen
Merriam Websters Dictionary
http://www.theology.edu/logic/logic22.htm
ARGUMENT FORMS AND REFUTATION BY LOGICAL ANALOGY
The central task of deductive logic is discriminating valid arguments from invalid ones. If the premises of a valid argument are true, its conclusion must be true. If the conclusion of a valid argument is false, at least one of the premises must be false. In short, the premises of a valid argument give incontrovertible proof of the conclusion drawn.
This informal account of validity must be made more precise, thus, the introduction of the concept of an argument form. Suppose we are presented with these arguments:
First argument: If Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare, then Bacon was a great writer Bacon is a great writer. Therefore, Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare.
Second argument: If Washington was assassinated, then Washington is dead. Washington is dead. Therefore, Washington was assassinated.
In the first argument, we may agree with the premises but disagree with the conclusion, judging the argument to be invalid. By logical analogy, seeing that the second argument has the same form as that of the first argument, which is the premises are true but the conclusion is false, we can say that the second argument is invalid.
First argument is invalid. Second argument has the same form as that of the First argument. Therefore, Second argument is also invalid.
Such is a method of Refutation by Logical Analogy. Refutation by Logical Analogy exhibits the fault of an argument by presenting another argument with the same form whose premises are known to be true and whose conclusion is known to be false.
In Refutation by Logical Analogy, to prove the invalidity of an argument, it suffices to formulate another argument that: 3. Has exactly the same form as the first, and 4. Has true premises and a false conclusion.
The method of Refutation by Logical Analogy is based upon the fact that validity and invalidity are purely formal characteristics of arguments, which is to say that any two arguments having exactly the same form are either both valid or both invalid, regardless of any differences in the subject matter with which they are concerned.
A given argument exhibits its form very clearly when the simple statements that appear in it are abbreviated by capital letters. Thus we may abbreviate the arguments as:
First Argument: If Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare, then Bacon was a great writer B G Bacon is a great writer. G Therefore Bacon wrote the plays attributed to Shakespeare
B
Second Argument: If Washington was assassinated, then Washington is dead A D Washington is dead. D Therefore Washington was assassinated A
Thus the forms, First Argument Second Argument BG G B AD D A
So written, their common form is easily seen.
Statement variable is simply a letter for which, or in place of which, a statement may be substituted. In the preceding section we used capital letters to symbolize particular simple statements, to avoid confusion, we will use lowercase letters from the middle part of the alphabet p,q,r,s, as statement variables.
Argument form refers to an array of symbols containing statement variables but no statements; such that when statements are substituted for the statement variables the same statement being substituted for the same statement variable throughout the result is an argument. For definiteness, the convention that in any argument form p shall be the first statement variable that occurs in it, q shall be the second, r the third, and so on. Thus the expression: p q q p is an argument form, for when the statements B and G are substituted for variables p and q respectively, the result is the first argument and when the statements A and D are substituted for the same variables, the result will be the second argument.
Any argument that results from the substitution of statements for statement variables in an argument form is called a substitution instance of that argument form. It is clear that any substitution instance of an argument form may be said to have that form, and that any argument that has a certain form is a substitution instance of that form.
For any argument there are usually several argument forms that have the given argument as a substitution instance. For example, using the first argument:
BG G B
is a substitution instance of each of the four argument forms Argument 1 Argument 2 Argument 3 Argument 4 p q q p p q r p p q r s p q r
Thus we obtain the given arguments by substituting: Argument 1 Argument 2 Argument 3 Argument 4 B p p p and s p and r G q q and r q and r q
In the four argument forms, Argument 1 corresponds more closely to the structure of the given argument than do the others. It does so because the given argument results from the first argument form by substituting a different simple statement for each different statement variable in it. We call the first argument form the specific form of the given argument. Specific form of that argument refers to that argument form from which the given argument results when a different simple statement is substituted for each different statement variable.
THE PRECISE MEANING OF INVALID AND VALID
Relying upon the technique of refutation by logical analogy, the specific form of a given argument has any substitution instance whose premises are true and whose conclusion is false, then the given argument is invalid.
By refutation by logical analogy, an invalid argument form is an invalid argument. Any argument form that is not invalid must be valid. Hence, an argument for is valid if and only if it has no substitution instances with true premises and false conclusion. Since validity is a formal notion, an argument is valid if and only if the specific form of that argument is a valid argument form.