A General Decision-Tree Approach To Real Option Valuation: Myers 1977
A General Decision-Tree Approach To Real Option Valuation: Myers 1977
> T. We do not equate the investment horizon with the maturity of the investment,
i.e. cash ows from the investment may continue beyond T
, (1)
1
As in Kasanen and Trigeorgis (1995), the market price could be related to the utility of a representative decision
maker, being the break-even price at which the representative decision maker is indierent between investing or
not.
2
This rate depends on the business risk of the investment as perceived by the nancer, not as perceived by the
decision maker. It may also depend on the decision-makers credit rating but this assumption is not common in the
real options literature.
3
To avoid additional complexity we do not consider that investments could be nanced from wealth, even though
this would be rational if wealth is liquid and r is greater than the return on wealth, r.
5
where and are the decision-makers subjective drift and volatility associated with p
t
and W
t
is a Wiener process. Then p
t
has a lognormal distribution, p
t
log N
_
( r) t,
2
t
_
.
It is convenient to use a binomial tree discretisation of (1) in which the price can move up or
down by factors u and d, so that p
t+1
= p
t
u with probability and otherwise p
t+1
= p
t
d. No
less than eleven dierent binomial parameterisations for GBM are reviewed by Chance (2008).
Smith (2005), Brand ao and Dyer (2005), Brand ao et al. (2005, 2008), Smit and Ankum (1993) and
others employ the CRR parameterisation of Cox et al. (1979). However, the Jarrow and Rudd
(1982) parameterisation, which is commonly used by option traders, is more stable for low levels
of volatility and when there are only a few steps in the tree. Thus we set
m =
_
r 0.5
2
t, u = e
m+
t
, d = e
m
t
and = 0.5. (2)
We also consider a modication of (1) that represents a regime-dependent process, which trends
upward with a low volatility for a sustained period and downward with a high volatility for another
sustained period, replicating booms and busts in the market price. Thus we set:
dp
t
p
t
=
_
_
_
(
1
r)dt +
1
dW
t
, for 0 < t T
1
,
(
2
r)dt +
2
dW
t
, for T
1
< t T
.
(3)
Alternatively, the decision maker may believe the market price will mean-revert over a relatively
short time horizon, and to replicate this we suppose the expected return decreases following a price
increase but increases following a price fall, as in the Ornstein-Uhlenbeck process:
d ln p
t
= ln
_
p
t
p
_
dt +dW
t
(4)
where denotes the rate of mean reversion to a long-term price level p. Following Nelson and Ra-
maswamy (1990) (NR) we employ the following binomial tree parameterisation for the discretised
Ornstein-Uhlenbeck process:
u = e
t
, d = u
1
(5a)
s(t)
=
_
_
1, 0.5 +
s(t)
t/2 > 1
0.5 +
s(t)
t/2, 0 0.5 +
s(t)
t/2 1
0, 0.5 +
s(t)
t/2 < 0
(5b)
where
s(t)
= ln
_
p
s(t)u
p
_
(5c)
is the local drift of the log price process, which decreases as increases. The corresponding price
process thus has local drift:
s(t)
= ln
_
p
s(t)u
p
_
+ 0.5
2
+r (5d)
6
Note that when = 0 there is a constant transition probability of 0.5 and the NR parameterisation
is equivalent to the parameterisation (2) with m = 0.
The cash ows, if any, may depend on the market price of the asset as, for instance, in rents
from a property. Let s(t) denote the state of the market price at time t, i.e. a path of the market
price from time 0 to time t. In the binomial tree framework s(t) may be written as a string of us
and ds with t elements, e.g. uud for t = 3. Now CF
s(t)
denotes the cash ow when the market
price is in state s(t) at time t. Regarding cash ows as dividends we call the price excluding all
cash ows before and at time t the ex-dividend price, denoted p
s(t)
. At the time of a cash ow
CF
s(t)
the market price follows a path which jumps from p
+
s(t)
= p
s(t)
+CF
s(t)
to p
s(t)
. We suppose
that he receives the cash ow at time t if he divests in the project at time t but does not receive
it if he invests in the project at time t. The alternative assumption that he receives the cash ow
at time t only when he invests is also possible.
4
The dividend yield, also called dividend pay-out
ratio, is dened as
s(t)
=
p
+
s(t)
p
s(t)
p
+
s(t)
. (6)
We assume that dividend yields are deterministic and time but not state dependent, using the
simpler notation
t
. Then the cash ows are both time and state dependent.
5
3.2 Costs and Benets of Investment and Divestment
The investment cost at time t, in time 0 terms, is:
K
t
= K + (1 ) g(p
t
), 0 1, (7)
where K is a constant in time 0 terms and g : R R is some real-valued function linking the
investment cost to the market price, so that cost is perfectly correlated with price only when g
is linear. When = 1 we have a standard real option with a predetermined strike K, such as
might be employed for oil exploration decisions. When = 0 we have a variable cost linked to the
market price p
t
, such as might be employed for real estate or merger and acquisition options. The
intermediate case, with 0 < < 1 has an investment cost with both xed and variable components.
We assume that initial wealth w
0
earns a constant, risk-free lending rate r, as do any cash ows
paid out that are not re-invested. Any cash paid into the investment (e.g. development cost) is
nanced at the borrowing rate r. The nancial benet to the decision-maker on investing at time
t is the sum of any cash ows paid out and not re-invested plus the terminal market price of the
investment. Thus the wealth of the investor at T
uud
are the left and right limits of a realisation of pt when t = 3. From henceforth we only use the subscript
s(t) when it is necessary to specify the state of the market otherwise we simplify notation using the subscript t.
Also, assuming cash ow is not received when divesting at time t, p
t
is a limit of pt from the right, not a limit from
the left.
5
If the cash ow is not state dependent, then the dividend yield must be state dependent. The state dependence of
cash ows induces an autocorrelation in them because the market price is autocorrelated. For this reason, dening an
additively separable multivariate utility over future cash ows as in Smith and Nau (1995) and Smith and McCardle
(1998) may be problematic.
7
is
w
I
t,T
= e
( rr)T
w
0
+
T
s=t+1
e
( rr)(T
s)
CF
s
+p
K
t
. (8)
Some investments pay no cash ows, or any cash ows paid out are re-invested in the project.
Then the nancial benet of investing at time t, in time 0 terms, is simply the cum-dividend
price p
t,T
of the investment accruing from time t. If a decision to invest is made at time t, with
0 t T, then p
t,t
= p
t
but the evolution of p
t,s
for t < s T
diers to that of p
s
because
p
t,s
will gradually accumulate all future cash ows from time t onwards. In this case, when the
decision maker chooses to invest at time t his wealth at time T
in time 0 terms is
w
I
t,T
= e
( rr)T
w
0
+ p
t,T
K
t
. (9)
Note that if r = r then also
s=t+1
e
( rr)(T
s)
CF
s
+p
= p
t,T
in (8).
Similarly, if the decision maker already owns the investment at time 0 and chooses to sell it at
time t, the time 0 value of his wealth at time T
is
w
S
t,T
= e
( rr)T
w
0
+
t1
s=1
e
( rr)(T
s)
CF
s
+p
+
t
p
0
. (10)
Note that p
0
is subtracted here because we assume the investor has borrowed funds to invest in
the property. Alternatively, if there are no cash ows, or they are re-invested,
w
S
t,T
= e
( rr)T
w
0
+ p
0,t
p
0
. (11)
The wealth w
D
t,T
= U
_
w
I
t,T
_
, but
since w
I
t,T
is random so is U
I
t,T
_
= E
_
U
_
w
I
s(t),T
__
,
as a point estimate. Then, given a specic decision node at time t, say when the market is in state
s(t), the potential investor chooses to invest if and only if
E
_
U
I
s(t),T
_
> E
_
U
D
s(t),T
_
,
8
and we set
E
_
U
s(t),T
= max
_
E
_
U
I
s(t),T
_
, E
_
U
D
s(t),T
__
. (12)
Since there are no further decisions following a decision to invest, E
_
U
I
s(t),T
_
can be evaluated
directly, using the utility of the terminal wealth values obtainable from state s(t) and their associ-
ated probabilities. However, E
_
U
D
s(t),T
_
depends on whether it is optimal to invest or defer at the
decision nodes at time t +1. Thus, the expected utilities at each decision node must be computed
via backward induction.
First we evaluate (12) at the last decision nodes in the tree, which are at the time T that
option expires. These nodes are available only if the investor has deferred at every node up to
this point. We associate each ultimate decision node with the maximum value (12) and select the
corresponding optimal action, I or D. Now select a penultimate decision node; say it is at time
T kt. If we use a recombining binomial tree to model the market price evolution, it has 2
k
successor decision nodes at time T.
6
Each market state s(T kt) has an associated decision node.
Each one of its successor nodes is at a market state s
(T)
determined by the state transition probability of 0.5,
given that we employ the parameterisation (2).
7
Using the expected utility associated with each
attainable successor node, and their associated probabilities, we compute the expected utility of
the decision to defer at time T kt. More generally, assuming decision nodes occur at regular
time intervals, the backward induction step is:
E
_
U
D
s(tkt),T
_
=
(t)
(t)
E
_
U
s
(t),T
_
, (14)
6
The recombining assumption simplies the computation of expected utilities at the backward induction step.
However, we do not require that the binomial tree is recombining so the number of decision nodes could proliferate
as we advance through the tree. Note that the state price tree will recombine if cash ows are determined by a
time-varying but not state-varying dividend yield.
7
So if the tree recombines these probabilities are 0.5
k
, k0.5
k
, k!/(2!(k 2)!)0.5
k
, ...., k0.5
k
, 0.5
k
under the JR
parameterization (2). If the CRR parameterisation is employed instead the transition probabilities for a recombining
tree would be more general binomial probabilities.
9
where w denotes the terminal (time T
E[U(w)]
_
. (15)
This function is frequently employed because it has special properties that make it particularly
tractable (see Davis et al., 2006, Chapter 6).
1. The exponential function (14) is the only utility with a CE that is independent of the decision-
makers initial wealth, w
0
.
2. The Arrow-Pratt coecient of risk aversion is constant, as U
(w)/U
(w) = . Thus,
the exponential utility (14) represents decision makers with constant absolute risk aversion
(CARA) and in (14) is the absolute risk tolerance.
3. The CE of an exponential utility is additive over independent risks. When x
t
NID(,
2
)
and w
T
= x
1
+. . . +x
T
then CE(w
T
) = T (2)
1
2
T.
Properties 1 and 2 are very restricting. CARA implies that decision makers leave unchanged
the dollar amount allocated to a risky investment when their initial wealth changes, indeed the
investors wealth has no inuence on his valuation of the option. Property 3 implies that when
cash ows are normally and independently distributed (NID) the decision-makers risk premium
for the sum of cash ows at time t is (2)
1
2
t, so it scales with time at rate (2)
1
2
. This could
be used to derive the risk-adjustment term that is commonly applied to DCF models and in the
inuential book by Copeland et al. (1990).
8
Exponential utilities also have an important time-homogeneity property which, unlike the prop-
erties above, is shared by other utility functions in the HARA class: Suppose U
t
: R R on
t = 0, 1, ...., T
w
t
t
_
= e
rt
exp
_
w
0
t
_
= e
rt
U(w
0
t
), (16)
where U : R R is a time-invariant exponential utility function as in (14) dened on any future
value of wealth discounted to time 0. This property makes any HARA utility particularly easy to
employ in decision-tree analysis. In particular, on assuming the risk tolerance is time-varying and
grows exponentially at the same rate as the discount rate, we can value any future uncertainty using
the constant utility function (14) applied to time 0 values. This is much easier than discounting
the expected values of time-varying utility functions applied to time t values at every step in
the backward induction. Our framework is not constrained to exponential preferences over NID
uncertainties; indeed, this would lead to a solution where the same decision (to invest, or to defer)
8
Setting exp[r
a
] = (2)
1
2
gives r
a
= log[1 (2)
1
2
], so r
a
(2)
1
2
.
10
would be reached at every node in the tree, because the uncertainties faced are just a scaled version
of uncertainties at any other node.
The CARA property of the exponential utility is often criticised because it does not apply to
investors that change the dollar amount allocated to risky investments as their wealth changes.
For this reason we allow other utility functions from the HARA class, where both absolute and
relative risk aversion can increase with wealth.
9
HARA utility functions have a local relative risk
tolerance that increases linearly with wealth at the rate , and are dened as:
U(w) = [1 +
w
0
(w w
0
)]
1
1
(1 )
1
, for w > (1
1
)w
0
. (17)
We consider four special cases: when = 0 we have the exponential utility; = 1 corresponds to
the displaced logarithmic utility; = 0.5 gives the hyperbolic utility; and = gives the power
utility. Note that an investors risk tolerance and its sensitivity to wealth may be dened fairly
accurately using the techniques introduced by Keeney and Reia (1993).
4 Properties under GBM
Our real option value represents the net present value that, if received with certainty, would give a
risk-averse investor the same utility value as the expected utility of the uncertain investment. Such
values enable the investor to rank alternative investment opportunities and the solution species
an optimal time to exercise. The minimum value of zero applies when the investment would never
be attractive whatever its future market price. The special case of RNV, while most commonly
employed in the literature, only applies to a real option that is tradable on a secondary market.
A separate appendix presents a simple example, with full illustration of the decision tree and
Matlab code, to help readers x ideas. The decision maker has an exponential utility and the
transacted price is the market price of the asset. Thus, the investment decision provides a concrete
example of the zero-correlation case considered by Grasselli (2011), where the opportunity to invest
still carries a positive value. A second example shows that the equivalent divest decision also has
a positive value.
Properties of the general model are now described under the GBM assumption (1) for market
prices. Unlike risk-neutral prices, general real option values may reect: (i) the cost of the in-
vestment relative to the companies net asset value/initial wealth; (ii) the scheduling of decision
opportunities; and (iii) the sensitivity of risk tolerance to wealth.
10
4.1 Investment Costs and the RNV Approach
Great care should be taken when making assumptions about investment costs. In some applications
for instance, when a licence to drill for oil has been purchased and the decision concerns whether
the market price of oil is sucient to warrant exploration a xed-strike or predetermined cost
9
Relative risk tolerance is expressed as a percentage of wealth, not in dollar terms. So if, say, = 0.4 the decision
maker is willing to take a gamble with approximately equal probability of winning 40% or losing 20% of his wealth,
but he would not bet on a 50:50 chance (approximately) of winning x% or losing x%/2 for any x > 0.4.
10
From henceforth, unless otherwise stated, we set r = r; no additional insights to the model properties are
provided by using dierent lending and borrowing rates.
11
assumption could be valid. However, in many cases the investment cost is linked to the market
price. The assumption (7) about the investment cost has a crucial inuence not only on the value
of a real option and its optimal exercise strategy, but also on their sensitivity to changes in the
input parameters.
A xed cost, where = 1 in (7), may be regarded as the strike of an American call option,
and the value is derived from the expected utility of a call option pay-o for which the upper
part of the terminal wealth distribution above the strike matters. The opposite extreme ( = 0)
focuses on the lower part of the terminal wealth distribution below the current price p
0
, where the
investment costs are lowest. Although log returns are similar across the whole spectrum under
the GBM assumption (1), P&L is in absolute terms and it is greater in the upper part of the
distribution than in the lower part. For this reason an at-the-money xed-strike assumption yields
a greater real option value than the invest-at-market-price assumption.
11
Real option values for
risk-averse investors always increase with risk tolerance, and can be greater than or less than the
RNV option price depending on the investors expected return and risk tolerance.
We illustrate these properties with a typical example of an option to purchase an asset that has
no associated cash ows. The current price of the asset is $1m and the investor believes this will
evolve according to (1) with and as specied in Table 1. The risk-free lending and borrowing
rates are both 5%. The investment horizon is T
t
if p
t
> $1m
(p
t
< $1m).
Table 1 reports the real option values under each cost assumption, for = 0.1, 0.5 and 1, the
real option value corresponding to the linear utility of a risk-neutral investor ( = ), and the
RNV price. Under the option value we report the year and any market state that the optimal
investment strategy is conditional upon. For instance, 1/d denotes invest at time 1 provided the
market price moved down between time 0 and 1, and 4/uu denotes invest at time 4 provided the
market price moved up between time 0 and 1, and again between time 1 and 2, irrespective of
later market price moves. Investment at time 0 has no market state, 4/ denotes invest in year 4
irrespective of the price state, and never invest is marked simply .
The risk-averse option value always increases with , in accordance with results of Henderson
(2007). Clearly, the more risk tolerant the investor, the lower the risk premium required to invest.
11
However, this property only holds under GBM views for market prices, see Section 5.1 for a counter example
under dierent price processes.
12
Similar properties are evident using other real option parameters, with results available on request.
12
Table 1: Exponential utility option values for dierent risk tolerance and dierent invest-
ment costs of the form (7). Risk-neutral values (linear utility, i.e. = ) and RNV prices
(linear utility, = r). Real option parameters: T
= 5 years, t = k = 1, K = p
0
= $1m,
r = r = 5%, with and specied above.
= 10% g(x) - x
x x/2
= 20% 1 0.5 0 0.5 0 0.5 0
0.1
Value 47,387 29,349 0 36,260 32,222 115,185 390,296
Year/State 3/uu 4/uuu - 4/uuu 4/uuu 4/u 4/-
0.5
Value 199,103 117,936 43,008 166,906 129,091 323,672 561,529
Year/State 2/uu 4/uu 0 4/uu 4/uu 4/u 2/dd
1
Value 261,839 157,221 141,249 218,048 170,077 393,401 641,249
Year/State 3/uuu 3/uud 0 4/uu 4/uu 2/ud 0
0.1
Value 37,277 5,374 0 34,229 6,454 36,865 148,551
Year/State 3/uuu 4/uuuu - 4/uuu 4/uuuu 4/uuu 4/-
0.5
Value 151,743 36,014 3,023 125,942 82,806 181,581 341,763
Year/State 3/uuu 4/uuu 3/ddd 4/uuu 4/uuu 4/uu 3/ddd
1
Value 254,963 112,602 17,221 216,766 166,120 312,741 461,455
Year/State 4/uuu 4/uuu 2/dd 4/uuu 4/uuu 4/uu 2/dd
= 5yrs, t = 1/12, T = T
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
=0
Exponential Hyperbolic Power Logarithmic
0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1
0
100
200
300
400
500
=1
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
For typical risk tolerance (0 < < 1) the exponential and logarithmic utility values provide
lower and upper bounds for the real option values derived from other HARA utilities. For very high
risk tolerance, i.e. > 1, hyperbolic utility values still lie between the exponential and logarithmic
values, but the power utility values exceed the logarithmic values, and as increases further the
power values can become very large indeed because the risk tolerance increases extremely rapidly
with wealth.
Because of the boundary in (17) HARA utilities are not always well-behaved,unlike exponential
15
utilities that even yield analytic solutions in some cases. But exponential utility values will be too
low if the decision makers risk tolerance increases with wealth (generally regarded as a better
assumption than CARA). In that case, power utilities produce the most reliable real option values
for typical values of risk tolerance, but with very high risk tolerance logarithmic or hyperbolic
utility representations would be more appropriate, the former giving real option values that are
greater than the latter.
4.4 Eect of Asset Price on Option Value
The higher the underlying asset price at time 0 the more variable the terminal P&L. Its eect on
the option value depends on risk tolerance (and how it changes with wealth). To investigate this
we compute both exponential and logarithmic real option values, supposing the time 0 asset price
is either $0.1m, $1m or 10$m, xing the investors initial wealth at $1m and keeping all other real
option characteristics xed, as in (18).
Figure 2: Real option values under exponential and logarithmic utilities as a function of risk
tolerance , T
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
=0
10
1
10
0
10
1
10
2
10
3
10
3
10
2
10
1
10
0
10
1
=1
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
Exponential (p
0
=0.1)
Logarithmic (p
0
=0.1)
RNV (p
0
=0.1)
Exponential (p
0
=1)
Logarithmic (p
0
=1)
RNV (p
0
=1)
Exponential (p
0
=10)
Logarithmic (p
0
=10)
RNV (p
0
=10)
Figure 2 displays the results for dierent values of with both option value and represented
on a base 10 log scale. We depict option values for = 0 (invest at market price) and = 1 (xed
ATM strike at p
0
). The values for the high-priced asset, represented by red lines, are most sensitive
to and the values for the low-priced asset, represented by black lines, are least sensitive to .
Usually, the smaller (greater) the risk tolerance of the investor, the higher he ranks the option to
invest in the relatively low-priced (high-priced) asset, given that the asset-price dynamics follow the
same GBM process. In each case the option value converges to the value obtained for a risk-neutral
investor as , and this value increases with p
0
. As 0 the option value decreases with p
0
,
except for an investor in a xed-strike option with an exponential utility. For intermediate values
of lambda there is no general rule for ranking, especially when invest cost is linked to market price.
Hence, risk-neutral investors rank investments according to the underlying price, ceteris paribus,
but this need not be the case risk-averse investors.
16
The RNV option price is is zero when K
t
= p
t
( = 0) and when K
t
is xed at $1m ( = 1)
it is marked by the dotted horizontal lines in Figure 2. In this case it is less than the risk-neutral
subjective value because > r, but would exceed that value if < r. The exponential option
values (solid lines) never exceed the logarithmic utility values (dashed lines) for the same initial
risk tolerance, and they are much lower for the xed-strike option to invest in a high-priced asset
by a highly risk-averse investor.
4.5 Sensitivity to and
When the decision maker has low condence in his views about the price process his subjective
values for and may be highly uncertain. We describe the sensitivity of real option values
to the expected returns and risks of the investment. The RNV principle yield option prices that
increase with volatility under the xed time 0 cost assumption, yet the DCF approach implies the
opposite. In our approach option values can decrease or increase with volatility depending on the
cost structure and the utility.
Figure 3: Value of an investment option under exponential and logarithmic utilities as a
function of the investors subjective views on expected return and volatility , for = 0.2.
CE value in $m for p
0
= $1m, w
0
= $10m, r = 5%, T
= 5, t = 1/12, k = 3.
5%
10%
15%
20%
25%
10%
20%
30%
40%
50%
0
0.5
1
1.5
=1
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
5%
10%
15%
20%
25%
10%
20%
30%
40%
50%
0
0.5
1
1.5
=0
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
Exponential Logarithmic
Figure 3 depicts the values of a real option to invest as a function of these expected return and
volatility of the GBM price process, with other parameters xed as stated in the legend. When
= 0 the option value always decreases as uncertainty increases, for any given expected return, due
to the risk aversion of the decision maker. When there is high uncertainty ( greater than about
30%) the exponential utility values are zero, i.e. the investment opportunity is valueless as the
price would never fall far enough (in the decision makers opinion) for investment to be protable.
By contrast, the logarithmic utility always yields a positive value provided the expected return is
greater than about 10%, but again the investor becomes more likely to defer investment as the
volatility increases. Indeed, the option values are monotonically decreasing as for every , and
monotonically increasing with for every . Volatility sensitivity can be dierent for the xed-
strike option, = 1. For instance, with the logarithmic utility the option values can decrease as
17
increases, when the expected return is low. In particular, when = r the logarithmic option
values increase monotonically with volatility, as they also do in the RNV case.
The sensitivity of the option value to and also decreases as risk tolerance increases. To
illustrate this we give a simple numerical example, for the case = 0 and an exponential utility.
Suppose = 20%. If = 0.2 the option value is $1, 148 when = 40% and $241, 868 (almost 211
times larger) when = 20%. When = 0.8 the option value is $167, 716 when = 40%; but now
when = 20% it only increases by a multiple of about 4, to $713, 812. Similarly, xing = 20%
but now decreasing from 20% to 10% the value changes from $241, 867 to $109 (2, 210 times
smaller) for = 0.2, but from $713, 812 to $113, 959 (only about 6 times smaller) when = 0.8.
Hence, the option values sensitivities to and are much greater for low levels of risk tolerance.
Similar eects are present with the logarithmic utility but they are much less pronounced.
5 Cash Flows and non-GBM Price Processes
Given the generality and exibility of our approach it has applications to a wide range of invest-
ment or divestment decisions. Here we use examples of decision problems commonly encountered
by private real-estate companies or housing trusts, from large-scale land development to individual
residential property transactions. Many real estate real options have been considered in the litera-
ture, including: the option to abandon, e.g. Smith (2005), the option to defer a land development,
e.g. Brand ao and Dyer (2005) and Brand ao et al. (2005), and the option to divest, e.g. Brand ao
et al. (2008) and Smith (2005). But all these papers employ the RNV approach.
Our model permits risk-averse private companies, publicly-funded entities, or individuals to
compute a real option value that is tailored to the decision maker, and which could be very
dierent from the risk-neutral price obtained under the standard but (typically) invalid assumption
of perfectly-hedgeable risk and xed costs. This is signicant because such decisions can have
profound implications for the decision makers economic welfare. For instance, an individuals
investment in housing may represent a major component of his wealth and should not be viewed
simply in expected net present value terms, nor should all uncertainties be based on systematic risk
because they are largely unhedgeable. Private companies typically generate returns and risks that
have a utility value that is specic to the owners outlook. Similarly, charitable and publicly-funded
entities may have objectives that are far removed from wealth maximisation under risk-neutrality.
First we consider an option to purchase a residential property when the investors views are
captured by a process (3) where a long period of property price momentum could be followed by
a crash. Then we analyse real options for investors that believe in a mean-reverting price process
(4). After this we focus on the inclusion of cash ows, considering both positive cash ows for
modelling buy-to-let real options and negative cash ows for modelling construction costs in an
on-going development.
5.1 Property Price Recessions and Booms
Many property markets are subject to booms and recessions. For example, the average annualised
return computed from monthly data on the Vanguard REIT exchanged traded fund (VQN) from
18
January 2005 to December 2006 was 21% with a volatility of 15%. However, from January 2007 to
December 2009 the property market crashed, and the VQN had an average annualised return of
13% with a volatility of 58%. But from January 2010 to June 2011 its average annualised return
was 22% with volatility 24%. Clearly, when the investment horizon is several years a property
investor may wish to take account of both booms and busts in his views about expected returns.
We now give a numerical example of an option to purchase a residential property, i.e. with zero
cash ows, under such scenarios.
Consider a simple boom-bust scenario over a 10 year horizon. The expected return is negative,
1
< 0 for the rst n years and positive,
2
> 0 for the remaining 10n years. Following the above
observations about VQN we set
1
= 10%,
1
= 50% and
2
= 10%,
2
= 30%. We suppose
decisions are taken every quarter with t = 0.25 and set r = 5% in the price evolution tree. The
real option values given in Table 3 are for investors having exponential utility, with varying levels
of risk tolerance between 0.2 and 1. The property price recession is believed to last n = 0, 2, 4, 6, 8
or 10 years.
15
Table 3: Eect of a time-varying drift for the market price, with downward trending price for
rst n years followed by upward trending price for remaining 10 n years. Exponential utility
with dierent levels of risk tolerance, with = corresponding to the risk-neutral (linear
utility) value. Real option values in bold are the maximum values, for given . p
0
= $1 million,
w
0
= $1 million, T
= 10, t = 0.25, T = T
t, r = 5%,
1
= 10%,
2
= 10%,
1
= 50% and
2
= 20%.
= 0
n 0 2 4 6 8 10
= 10, t = 1/4, K = p
0
= $1m, T = T
t,
= 40%. Characteristic time to mean-revert = t/ in years, e.g. with t = 1/4 then
= 0.02 = 12.5yrs, = 0.1 = 2.5yrs.
0 0.02 0.04 0.06 0.08 0.1
0.5
1
1.5
2
2.5
3
3.5
4
4.5
5
x 10
5
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
=1
0 0.02 0.04 0.06 0.08 0.1
0.5
1
1.5
2
2.5
3
3.5
4
4.5
5
5.5
6
x 10
4
O
p
t
i
o
n
V
a
l
u
e
=0
Exponential Hyperbolic Power Logarithmic
Increasing the speed of mean-reversion has a similar eect to decreasing volatility. Hence, xed-
cost option values can decrease with , as they do on the right graph of Figure 4 ( = 1) especially
when the investor has logarithmic utility. By contrast, the invest-at-market-price ( = 0) option
displays values that increase with . Note that for xed these values could increase with , due
to the positive eect of in the local drift (5d).
17
16
Lower values for have slower mean-reversion, e.g. = 0.02 corresponds to a characteristic time to mean revert
of = 0.02
1
/4 = 12.5 years if time-steps are quarterly.
17
This eect is only evident for values of below a certain bound, depending on the utility function and other real
option parameters. For the parameter choice of Figure 4 the invest-at-market-price option values have their usual
20
Now consider a risk-neutral investor who wishes to rank two property investment opportunities,
A and B. Both have mean-reverting price processes but dierent and : property A has a
relatively rapid mean-reversion in its price ( = 1/10, = 2.5 years) with a low volatility ( = 20%)
and property B has a relatively slow mean-reversion in its price ( = 1/40, = 10 years) with a
higher volatility ( = 40%). Such an investor would have a great preference for property B since
he is indierent to the high price risk and has regard only for the local drift. Given the slow rate of
mean-reversion, he sees only the possibility of a sharp fall in price at which point he would invest
followed by a long upward trend in its price. Indeed, assuming p
0
= p = $1m the risk-neutral
value of option B is $797,486, but the corresponding value for option A is only $98,077.
However, once we relax the risk-neutral assumption the ranking of these two investment oppor-
tunities may change, depending on the utility of the investor. The real option values for risk-averse
investors with high risk tolerance ( = 0.8) or low risk tolerance ( = 0.4) are shown in Table
4. In each case the greater option value is depicted in bold. This shows that an investor with a
logarithmic utility would also prefer property B, as would an investor with a relatively high risk
tolerance ( = 0.8) and a hyperbolic or a power utility. In all other cases the investor would prefer
property A.
Table 4: Comparison of invest option values for property A ( = 1/10, = 20%) and proporty
B ( = 1/40, = 40%) with = 0.4 or 0.8 . All other parameter values are the same as in Figure
4. For each utility we highlight the preferred property in bold.
0.4 0.8
A B A B A B
Exponential 30,421 12,952 52,732 43,947
98,077 797,486
Hyperbolic 33,526 17,563 55,230 58,909
Power 33,045 16,651 56,365 68,051
Logarithmic 19,890 21,260 56,986 73,131
5.3 Positive Cash Flows: Buy-to-Let Options
Short-horizon decision trees for the invest and divest options on an investment that yields positive
cash ows are depicted in Figures 5 and 6. A typical real-esate investment with regular positive
cash ows is a buy-to-let residential property or oce block, or a property such as a car park
where fees accrue to its owner for its usage. Rents, denoted x
s(t)
in the trees, are captured using
a positive dividend yield dened by (6) that may vary over time. Even a constant dividend yield
would capture rents that increase/decrease in line with the market price. We suppose cash ows
not re-invested, otherwise we could employ the cum-dividend price approach that has previously
been considered. Instead, cash ows are assumed to earn the risk-free rate, as to suppose they
are invested in another risky project would introduce an additional source of uncertainty which is
beyond the scope of this paper.
Each time a cash ow is paid the market price jumps down from p
+
t
to p
t
= p
+
t
x
t
. Between
negative sensitivity to once exceeds approximately 2, where the characteristic time to mean revert is 1/8th of a
year or less. Detailed results are not reported for lack of space, but are available from the authors on request.
21
payments the decision maker expects the discounted market price to grow at rate r, and based
on the discretisation (2) we have p
+
t+1
= up
t
or p
+
t+1
= dp
t
with equal probability. The terminal
nodes of the tree are associated with the increment in wealth w w
0
where the nal wealth w is
given (8) for the option to invest in Figure 5, and by (10) for the option to divest in Figure 6, now
setting CF= x.
The decision tree in Figure 5 is now used to rank the options to buy two dierent buy-to-let
properties. Both properties have current market value p
0
= 1, the initial wealth of the investor is
w
0
= 1 and the risk-free rate r = 5%. In each case rents are paid every six months, and are set
at a constant percentage of the market price at the time the rent is paid. But the investor has
dierent views about the future market price and rents on each property, as specied in the rst
pair of columns in Table 5. Similarly, Figure 6 is used to rank the options to sell two dierent buy-
to-let properties, with views on market prices and rents as specied in the second pair of columns
in Table 5. Note that the CE values given for the divest option include the expected utility value
of capital gains on the property itself, as well as the expected utility value of the opportunity to
divest. In each case the value of the preferred property is marked in bold.
Table 5: Columns 2 and 3 compare the values of 2 real options, each to purchase a buy-to-let
property based on the decision tree shown in Figure 5. Columns 4 and 5 compare the values
of 2 real options, each for buy-to-let property with the option to sell, based on the decision
tree in Figure 6. For the decision maker, in each case = 0.4, r = 5%, w
0
= $1 million and for
each property p
0
= $1 million. The decision makers beliefs about , and depend on the
propertys location. For each utility we highlight in bold the preferred location for buying (or
selling) the property.
Invest Divest
40% 25% 30% 20%
15% 10% 15% 10%
10% 10% 20% 10%
Exponential 289 316 6,775 6,052
Hyperbolic 348 339 6,610 6,103
Power 340 336 7,283 6,296
Logarithmic 358 345 4,286 5,330
Again the form assumed for the utility function investor has material consequences for decision
making. An investor with exponential (CARA) utility would prefer the option to buy the second
property, whilst investors with any of the other HARA utilities having the same risk tolerance at
time 0 would prefer the option to buy the rst property. Similarly, regarding the divest real option
values of two other properties, both currently owned by the decision maker, all investors except
those with a logarithmic utility would favour selling the rst property.
5.4 Negative Cash Flows: Buy-to-Develop Options
Setting a negative dividend yield is a straightforward way to capture cash that is paid into the
land or property to cover development costs. But there are other important dierences between
the buy-to-develop and buy-to-rent option above. In the buy-to-develop case there are no cash
22
ows until the land or property is purchased, and thereafter these cash ows are included in the
market price. Hence, the market price following an invest decision is cum-dividend and prior to
this the market price evolves as in the zero cash ow case. Also, now the investment horizon T
is
path dependent because it depends on the time of the investment (e.g. it takes 2 years to develop
the property after purchasing the land).
A simple decision tree for the buy-to-develop option is depicted in Figure 7, in which the
development cost is y
s(t)
> 0 and p
t
is the (cum-dividend) market price. The option maturity T
is 2 periods, and so is the development time, so T
=
3, T = 2, k = 1. Terminal nodes labelled with P&L (w w
0
), given by (10) with CF = x if the
owner remains invested (R), or if the owner sells the property (S) by the dierence between
the selling price and initial price.
29
Figure 7: Decision tree depicting the option to invest in land for development. If the land
is acquired (I) the development takes 2 periods and development costs occur only after the
rst period. Terminal nodes are associated with the P&L, ww
0
resulting from the decision.
30