Matter, Mathematics, and God: John Byl
Matter, Mathematics, and God: John Byl
1, 2007
JOHN BYL
Abstract This paper contrasts materialism and theism in their ability to give a plausible account of
mathematics. The ideal, abstract entities of mathematics do not fit readily within a materialist world.
Truth, logic, and mathematics require the existence of universal norms. However, materialism has no
place for abstract entities or universal norms. How can such ideal norms, inert in themselves,
influence our minds? The indispensability of mathematics to physics is a strong argument for
realism. Theism posits that God upholds mathematical truths, which reside in the divine
mind. Classical mathematics presumes the existence of an Ideal Mathematicianan all-powerful,
all-knowing and infinite God. Since theism holds that man is created in Gods image and that God
can communicate truth to us, humans may be expected to have access to mathematical knowledge.
Since God has created the world according to a rational plan, the world may be expected to have a
mathematical structure.
Key words: Mathematics; Materialism; Theism; Realism; Platonism; Universals; Norms;
Constructivism
Introduction
The aim of this paper is to examine and contrast the abilities of materialism and
theism to account for mathematics. A key question is whether mathematics is a
mere human invention or an exploration of an already existent realm.
Historically, most mathematicians believe that mathematical truths (e.g. 2 5
7) exist independently of human minds, being universally and eternally true. Most
mathematicians believe they are discovering properties of, say, prime numbers,
rather than merely inventing them. This view of mathematics dates back to
Pythagoras (ca 569 475 BC) and Plato (427 347 BC). It is often called Platonism
or mathematical realism.
Mathematics has led to some profound philosophical speculation. Bertrand
Russell, certainly no friend of theism, concluded from his study of the history of
Greek philosophy that Mathematics is . . . the chief source of the belief in eternal
and exact truth, as well as in a supersensible intelligible world.1 This is so,
Russell argues, because of the abstract nature of mathematical concepts. For
example, geometry deals with exact circles, but no physical object is exactly
ISSN 1474-6700 print/ISSN 1474-6719 online/07/010073-14
2007 Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences
DOI: 10.1080/14746700601159598
74
circular. This suggests that exact reasoning applies to ideal, rather than physical,
objects. Furthermore, numbers appear to be time-independent. Hence, mathematics seems to deal with an ideal, eternal world of pure thought.
However, where and how do such mathematical entities exist? The existence of
eternal, ideal mathematical thoughts seems to require the existence of something
actual in which they exist.
The early theistic philosophers Philo (ca 20 BC 50 AD) and Augustine (354
430) placed the ideal world of eternal truths in the mind of God. Augustine argued
that mathematics implied the existence of an eternal, necessary, infinite Mind in
which all necessary truths exist. He asserted that we all know time-independent
truths about logic (e.g. A A) and mathematics (e.g. 2 2 4). However,
changing, material things cannot cause fixed, eternal truths. Nor can finite human
minds, since our thinking does not make them true but rather, it is judged by
them. Thus, truth must derive from something non-material that is superior to the
human mind. Mathematical truths must depend on a universal and unchanging
source that embraces all truth in its unity. Such a Truth, Augustine argued, must
exist and is by definition God.2
Thus arose the classical Christian view that mathematics exists in the mind of
God, that God created the universe according to a rational plan (Proverbs 8), and
that mans creation in the image of God (Genesis 1:26) entailed that man could
discern mathematical patterns in creation. Mathematics was held to be true
because of its supposed divine origin. The notion of a rational Creator was
vigorously espoused by Kepler, Galileo, Newton, and many other early scientists.
It was a major factor in motivating the scientific revolution.
75
76
results from false ones. Nor can they yield any explanation for correctness, a basic
issue in mathematics. Indeed, if all knowledge is based on neural connections, so
is the idea that all knowledge is based on neural connections. Hence, if true, we
have no basis for believing it to be true.
David Ray Griffin notes that, according to materialism, all causation is efficient
causation, meaning that each event is completely caused by previous events.8
Rational thought, however, is guided by goals and norms, such as the rules of
logic. As such, rational activity reflects final causationcausation in terms of a
norm or goalwhich is quite different from efficient causation. Since materialism
equates the mind with the brain, whose activities are presumed to be completely
determined by the physical activities of its parts (e.g. brain neurons), materialism
has no room for final causation.
This raises the question: If everything can be explained in terms of physics,
where do logical norms enter into our thinking? Note that it is possible for a
physical mechanism to do logical operations. In a computer, for example, there is an
exact correlation between the flow of physical states of the computer and the
corresponding flow of logical operations. Here the correspondence is specifically
designed by an intelligent agent. However, if the origin of the brain is attributed
to a purposeless process then we have no grounds for believing in a perfect
correspondence between the brains physical flow and the minds logical thinking.
Further, in the case of the computer, the output is meaningless unless it is
interpreted by an intelligent observer. In a purely material brain, where is there
room for an intelligent interpreter?
77
Logical laws are neither hypothetical nor inductive but, rather, necessary and
universal. They remain valid, regardless of the state of the physical world.
Hence, they cannot be proven from any physical laws or state of affairs.
Logical laws, like truth, are abstractions. As such, they belong to the realm of
ideas, not matter. J. P. Moreland contends that consistent materialistic
naturalism must reject abstract objects of any kind (including sets, numbers,
propositions, and properties), if we take these in the traditional sense of being
non-physical.10
These considerations raise particular problems for a materialist view of
mathematics. Most mathematicians believe that numbers, equations, perfect
circles, and so on, exist in some ideal, abstract sense. Such non-physical objects
must be rejected by consistent materialists. However, if ideal entities do not exist,
this means that any propositions concerning them cannot be true in the sense of
corresponding to anything. As Griffin points out, one is then forced either to
reduce mathematics to a mere game with meaningless symbols or to think of
mathematical objects as part of the physical world, which is clearly not the case.11
Consequently, few mathematicians are materialists.
78
dubious than the idea of there being a truth or falsity to any claim that
something ought to be believed.14 Hence, Mackies argumentation can just as
well be applied to rational norms. Mackie must then conclude that objective
rational norms, too, are inconsistent with naturalism. This destroys the very idea
of rationality.
Larmore asserts that, whereas natural facts are found by observation and
experiment, normative facts involve reasons, which are found by reflection. He
writes:
The inadequacy of naturalism is in the end its inability to account for normative
truth in general. Thus, the minute we suppose it is true that we ought to believe
something, we have broken with the naturalistic perspective. Acknowledging that
there are indeed reasons for belief and action is enough to dispel the mystery. . .. By
leaving no room for there being reasons for belief, naturalism contradicts itself. Or it
does if it presents itself as the truth regarding what we ought to believe about the
world . . .15
In sum, materialism has no place for non-physical, universal norms. There can
be no absolute standards of right or wrong mathematics. Even if there were,
empiricism denies that we can acquire knowledge of such norms. After all, we can
only observe what is, not what ought to be. Hence, naturalism, must postulate that
all normswhether rational, mathematical, or moralare purely human
inventions. Truth and falsity, right and wrong, and good and evil are thus
reduced to mere human opinion or convention.
Thus, for example, Michael Ruse argues that human rationality is determined
solely by genetic traits developed via the evolutionary struggle for survival.16
However, such a claim undermines any claim of Ruse that his thinking is rational.
As Hilary Putnam notes, if rationality were measured by survival value, then the
proto-beliefs of the cockroach . . . would have a far higher claim to rationality than
the sum total of human knowledge.17 Putnam, who had earlier denied the
existence of any ideal truths, concedes that the law of non-contradiction, at least, is
an absolutely unrevisable ideal truth.
Constructivism
The rejection of theism, with the consequent concerns for the soundness of
mathematics, had implications also for the actual content of mathematics. Classical
mathematics was based on the concept of an Ideal Mathematician. It assumed the
existence of an all-knowing, all-powerful, and infinite God. The operations and
proofs allowed in classical mathematics were those that could in principle be
performed by such a God.
Some naturalist mathematicians, considering mathematics to be no more than
the free creation of the human mind, felt that the methods of mathematics should
be adjusted accordingly. Only those mathematical concepts and proofs were to be
considered valid that could be (mentally) constructed in a finite number of explicit
steps. The there exists of classical mathematics was to be replaced by we can
79
80
81
82
How, then, they ask, can mathematics be responsible for the worlds being the
way it is? Further, if mathematical entities are inert, how do they influence our
minds? Paul Benacerraf contends true beliefs may be considered genuine
knowledge only if their truth is causally responsible for our belief.30 Since
mathematical entities are causally inert, they cannot give rise to our mathematical
knowledge.
It is clear that realism requires an active agent. In the theistic worldview this
poses no problem, for mathematical objects can be causally effective in the world,
and in our minds, by virtue of being in the mind of God. God can always cause the
required connections to be made. Those who reject theism, however, are faced
with a daunting problem. Griffin comments:
The implication of Benacerrafs insight . . . is that atheism renders unintelligible the
idea that we can have knowledge of a Platonic realm of numbers. Several
philosophers of mathematics, including Hersch himself, use Benacerrafs insight as
the basis for rejecting a Platonic realm. As Quine points out, however, such a realm
is presupposed by physics. Benacerrafs insight, plus Quines observation, implies
that atheism makes an adequate philosophy of mathematics impossible.31
83
Since God has created the physical world according to a rational plan, the world
may be expected to exhibit mathematical structure. Since God has created man in
Gods image, humans may be expected to discern this mathematical structure.
This accounts for the applicability of human mathematics to the physical world.
As we noted earlier, classical mathematics is based on the notion of an infinite,
omniscient, and omnipotent God. Thus, theism provides a basis for classical
mathematics. Georg Cantor (1845 1918), the founder of modern set theory,
justified his belief in infinite sets by his belief in an infinite God.40 He thought of
sets in terms of what God could do with them. An infinite God would have no
difficulty forming the power set of any given infinite set. Even today, almost every
attempt to motivate the principles of combinatorial set theory relies on some
notion of idealized manipulative capacities of the Omnipotent Mathematician.
Constructionists, however, reject Cantors transfinite cardinal numbers since these
cannot be constructed by finite methods.
Alvin Plantinga notes that theists have a distinct advantage when it comes to
explaining sets and their properties. The existence of sets depends upon a certain
84
Conclusions
In summary, mathematics is not plausibly explained by materialism. A materialist
view of origins does not account for the ability of the human mind to do advanced
mathematics. If mathematics is generated by a brain operating purely by physical
causes, then there is no reason why such mathematics should be true. Indeed, the
very notions of truth and logic do not fit well with materialism, which has no
place for universals norms.
Classical mathematics is based on the notion of an infinite, omnipotent, and
omniscient God. The rejection of such a being leads to constructivism. However,
constructivism fails to support the sophisticated mathematics needed for physics.
The indispensability of mathematics for physics is a strong argument for realism. The
universality of mathematics, as well as its applicability to the physical universe, are
further evidence that mathematics cannot be reduced to a mere human invention.
Realism is faced with the problems of where to place ideal mathematical entities
and how humans can access such an ideal realm. These problems are difficult to
solve without theism. Theism posits that God upholds mathematical truths, which
reside in the divine mind. Classical mathematics presumes the existence of an Ideal
Mathematicianan all-powerful, all-knowing and infinite God. Theism holds that
man is created in Gods image and that God can communicate truth to us. Hence,
humans may be expected to have access to mathematical knowledge. Since God is a
rational Creator, the physical universe may be expected to have a physical structure.
Finally, theism provides the resources to justify the soundness of mathematics.
Endnotes
1 Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster,
1945), 37.
2 Norman Geisler and Winfred Corduan, Philosophy of Religion, 2nd ed. (Grand Rapids,
Mich.: Baker, 1988), 154.
85
3 Cf. Jean-Pierre Changeux and Alain Connes, Conversations on Mind, Matter, and
Mathematics (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995), 13.
4 Stanislas Dehaene, The Number Sense: How the Mind Creates Mathematics (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1997).
5 George Lakoff and Rafael Nunez, Where Mathematics Comes From (New York: Basic
Books, 2000).
6 Penelope Maddy, Realism in Mathematics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).
7 Paul Davies, Are We Alone? (New York: Basic Books, 1995), 85 86.
8 David R. Griffin, Naturalism: Scientific and Religious, Zygon, vol. 37, no. 2 (2002): 372.
9 Dallas Willard, Knowledge and Naturalism, in Naturalism: A Critical Analysis, eds.
William L. Craig and James P. Moreland (London: Routledge, 2000), 39.
10 James P. Moreland, Naturalism and the Ontological Status of Properties, in
Naturalism, eds. Craig and Moreland, 67.
11 Griffin, Naturalism: Scientific and Religious, 369.
12 John L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1979), 38 41.
13 John L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), 115.
14 Charles Larmore, The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1996), 99.
15 Ibid., 115 116.
16 Michael Ruse, Taking Darwin Seriously (Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1998), 206.
17 Hilary Putnam, Realism and Reason (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 232.
18 Errett Bishop, Schizophrenia in Contemporary Mathematics, in Errett Bishop:
Reflections on Him and His Research, ed. Murray Rosenblatt (Providence, R.I.: American
Mathematical Society, 1985), 9.
19 Errett Bishop, Foundations of Constructive Analysis (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967), 2.
20 Geoffrey Hellman, Constructive Mathematics and Quantum Mechanics: Unbounded
Operators and the Spectral Theorem, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23 (1993): 221 228;
idem, Quantum Mechanical Unbounded Operators and Constructive MathematicsA
Rejoinder to Bridges, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 26 (1997): 121 127.
21 Willard V. O. Quine, Theories and Things (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1982), 14 15.
22 Mark Colyvan, The Indispensability of Mathematics (New York: Oxford University Press,
2001).
23 Hartry Field, Science Without Numbers (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980).
24 Eugene Wigner, The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics, Communications on
Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13 (1960): 8.
25 Ibid., 14.
26 Mark Steiner, The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998).
27 Roger Penrose, The Emperors New Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 95, 112.
28 G. H. Hardy, A Mathematicians Apology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967),
123 124.
29 Colin Cheyen and Charles R. Pigden, Pythagorean Powers or a Challenge to
Platonism, Australian Journal of Philosophy, 74 (1996): 639 645.
30 Paul Benacerraf, Mathematical Truth, in Philosophy of Mathematics, 2nd ed., eds. Paul
Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 412.
31 Griffin, Naturalism: Scientific and Religious, 373.
32 Reuben Hersch, What Is Mathematics, Really? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997),
122.
33 Ibid., 135.
34 Ibid., 42.
35 Yehuda Rav, Philosophical problems in the light of Evolutionary Epistemology,
in Math Worlds, ed. Sal Restivo (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press,
1993), 81.
86
36 Ibid., 100.
37 R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics (Lanham, Md.: University Press of America,
1984), 250 257.
38 C. F. von Weizsacker, The Relevance of Science (New York: Harper & Row, 1964), 163.
39 Alvin Plantinga, Warrant and Proper Function (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993),
201.
40 See Joseph W. Dauben, Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite
(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979), 229.
41 Alvin Plantinga, Prologue: Advice to Christian Philosophers, in Christian Theism and
the Problems of Philosophy, ed. Michael D. Beaty (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1990), 35.
42 Christopher Menzel, An Activist Model of the Metaphysics of Mathematics, in A Sixth
Conference On Mathematics From A Christian Perspective, ed. Robert L. Brabenec
(Wheaton, Ill.: Wheaton College Mathematics Department, 1987), 55 72; idem,
Theism, Platonism, and the Metaphysics of Mathematics, in Christian Theism and the
Problems of Philosophy, ed. Michael D. Beaty (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1990).
Biographical Notes
John Byl is Professor of Mathematics and Chair of the Department of
Mathematical Sciences at Trinity Western University (Langley, BC, Canada). He
has authored numerous publications, including the book The Divine Challenge: On
Matter, Mind, Math & Meaning (Banner of Truth, 2004).