John Locke's Natural Law and Natural Rights: Summary of A Part of Case Reading (Locke's View)
John Locke's Natural Law and Natural Rights: Summary of A Part of Case Reading (Locke's View)
CAHUYA JD-1A
Locke’s theory showed the necessity of civil society and government yet it was careful to
assert and protect the individual’s rights against governmental invasion, thus implying a theory of
limited government that both restricted the role of the state to protect the rights to life, liberty and
property and prohibited the same, on moral grounds, from violating those rights. Undoubtedly, this
Locke’s ideas influenced Thomas Jefferson who espoused his theory that man is free in the state
of nature. While Locked limited the authority of the state by the doctrine of natural rights,
Jefferson, on the other hand, used the doctrine of natural rights as a basis for a fundamental law or
constitution established by the people. Therefore, two (2) ideas are fundamental in the constitution:
one is the regulation of the form of government and the other, the securing of the liberties of the
people. But while the constitution guarantees and protects fundamental rights of the people, it
should be stressed that it does not create them. Thus, natural law is to not to be understood as the
residual source of constitutional rights but instead, as the reasoning that implied the necessity to
sacrifice natural liberty to government in a written constitution. Natural law and natural rights were
concepts that explained and justified written constitutions.
With the establishment of civil government and constitution, there arises a distinction
between civil rights and natural rights. Civil rights are rights secured by the Constitution to all its
citizens or inhabitants not connected with the organization or administration of government which
belong to the domain of political rights. Civil rights may vary in different states or countries. Civil
rights are those natural rights – particularly rights to security and protection – which by themselves,
individuals could not safeguard, rather requiring the collective support of civil society and
government. Thus, they are rights appertain to man for him being a member of the society. On the
other hand, Natural rights, according to Black, may be used to describe those rights which belong
to man by virtue of his nature and depend upon his personality. Natural rights were often
categorized as the rights to life, liberty and property; or life, liberty and pursuit of happiness. These
were also fundamental rights endowed by God upon human beings which are not injurious to the
natural rights of others. Thus, they are rights which appertain to man in right of his existence.
2. State of Nature
Locke’s concept of the state of nature has been interpreted by commentators in a variety of
ways. At first glance it seems quite simple. Locke writes “want [lack] of a common judge, with
authority, puts all persons in a state of nature” and again, “Men living according to reason, without
a common superior on earth, to judge between them, is properly the state of nature.” (Two Treatises
2.19) Many commentators have taken this as Locke’s definition, concluding that the state of nature
exists wherever there is no legitimate political authority able to judge disputes and where people
live according to the law of reason. On this account the state of nature is distinct from political
society, where a legitimate government exists, and from a state of war where men fail to abide by
the law of reason.
Simmons presents an important challenge to this view. Simmons points out that the above
statement is worded as a sufficient rather than necessary condition. Two individuals might be able,
in the state of nature, to authorize a third to settle disputes between them without leaving the state
of nature, since the third party would not have, for example, the power to legislate for the public
good. Simmons also claims that other interpretations often fail to account for the fact that there are
some people who live in states with legitimate governments who are nonetheless in the state of
nature: visiting aliens (2.9), children below the age of majority (2.15, 118), and those with a
“defect” of reason (2.60). He claims that the state of nature is a relational concept describing a
particular set of moral relations that exist between particular people, rather than a description of a
particular geographical territory. The state of nature is just the way of describing the moral rights
and responsibilities that exist between people who have not consented to the adjudication of their
disputes by the same legitimate government. The groups just mentioned either have not or cannot
give consent, so they remain in the state of nature. Thus A may be in the state of nature with respect
to B, but not with C.
Simmons’ account stands in sharp contrast to that of Strauss. According to Strauss, Locke
presents the state of nature as a factual description of what the earliest society is like, an account
that when read closely reveals Locke’s departure from Christian teachings. State of nature theories,
he and his followers argue, are contrary to the Biblical account in Genesis and evidence that
Locke’s teaching is similar to that of Hobbes. As noted above, on the Straussian account Locke’s
apparently Christian statements are only a façade designed to conceal his essentially anti-Christian
views. According to Simmons, since the state of nature is a moral account, it is compatible with a
wide variety of social accounts without contradiction. If we know only that a group of people are
in a state of nature, we know only the rights and responsibilities they have toward one another; we
know nothing about whether they are rich or poor, peaceful or warlike.
A complementary interpretation is made by John Dunn with respect to the relationship
between Locke’s state of nature and his Christian beliefs. Dunn claimed that Locke’s state of nature
is less an exercise in historical anthropology than a theological reflection on the condition of man.
On Dunn’s interpretation, Locke’s state of nature thinking is an expression of his theological
position that man exists in a world created by God for God’s purposes but that governments are
created by men in order to further those purposes.
Locke’s theory of the state of nature will thus be tied closely to his theory of natural law,
since the latter defines the rights of persons and their status as free and equal persons. The stronger
the grounds for accepting Locke’s characterization of people as free, equal, and independent, the
more helpful the state of nature becomes as a device for representing people. Still, it is important
to remember that none of these interpretations claims that Locke’s state of nature is only a thought
experiment, in the way Kant and Rawls are normally thought to use the concept. Locke did not
respond to the argument “where have there ever been people in such a state” by saying it did not
matter since it was only a thought experiment. Instead, he argued that there are and have been
people in the state of nature. (Two Treatises 2.14) It seems important to him that at least some
governments have actually been formed in the way he suggests. How much it matters whether they
have been or not will be discussed below under the topic of consent, since the central question is
whether a good government can be legitimate even if it does not have the actual consent of the
people who live under it; hypothetical contract and actual contract theories will tend to answer this
question differently.
3. Property
Locke’s treatment of property is generally thought to be among his most important
contributions in political thought, but it is also one of the aspects of his thought that has been most
heavily criticized. There are important debates over what exactly Locke was trying to accomplish
with his theory. One interpretation, advanced by C.B. Macpherson, sees Locke as a defender of
unrestricted capitalist accumulation. On Macpherson’s interpretation, Locke is thought to have set
three restrictions on the accumulation of property in the state of nature: 1) one may only
appropriate as much as one can use before it spoils (Two Treatises 2.31), 2) one must leave
“enough and as good” for others (the sufficiency restriction) (2.27), and 3) one may (supposedly)
only appropriate property through one’s own labor (2.27). Macpherson claims that as the argument
progresses, each of these restrictions is transcended. The spoilage restriction ceases to be a
meaningful restriction with the invention of money because value can be stored in a medium that
does not decay (2.46–47). The sufficiency restriction is transcended because the creation of private
property so increases productivity that even those who no longer have the opportunity to acquire
land will have more opportunity to acquire what is necessary for life (2.37). According to
Macpherson’s view, the “enough and as good” requirement is itself merely a derivative of a prior
principle guaranteeing the opportunity to acquire, through labor, the necessities of life. The third
restriction, Macpherson argues, was not one Locke actually held at all. Though Locke appears to
suggest that one can only have property in what one has personally labored on when he makes
labor the source of property rights, Locke clearly recognized that even in the state of nature, “the
Turfs my Servant has cut” (2.28) can become my property. Locke, according to Macpherson, thus
clearly recognized that labor can be alienated. As one would guess, Macpherson is critical of the
“possessive individualism” that Locke’s theory of property represents. He argues that its coherence
depends upon the assumption of differential rationality between capitalists and wage-laborers and
on the division of society into distinct classes. Because Locke was bound by these constraints, we
are to understand him as including only property owners as voting members of society.
Macpherson’s understanding of Locke has been criticized from several different directions.
Alan Ryan argued that since property for Locke includes life and liberty as well as estate (Two
Treatises 2.87), even those without land could still be members of political society. The dispute
between the two would then turn on whether Locke was using property in the more expansive
sense in some of the crucial passages. James Tully attacked Macpherson’s interpretation by
pointing out that the First Treatise specifically includes a duty of charity toward those who have
no other means of subsistence (1.42). While this duty is consistent with requiring the poor to work
for low wages, it does undermine the claim that those who have wealth have no social duties to
others.
Tully also argued for a fundamental reinterpretation of Locke’s theory. Previous accounts
had focused on the claim that since persons own their own labor, when they mix their labor with
that which is unowned it becomes their property. Robert Nozick criticized this argument with his
famous example of mixing tomato juice one rightfully owns with the sea. When we mix what we
own with what we do not, why should we think we gain property instead of losing it? On Tully’s
account, focus on the mixing metaphor misses Locke’s emphasis on what he calls the
“workmanship model.” Locke believed that makers have property rights with respect to what they
make just as God has property rights with respect to human beings because he is their maker.
Human beings are created in the image of God and share with God, though to a much lesser extent,
the ability to shape and mold the physical environment in accordance with a rational pattern or
plan. Waldron has criticized this interpretation on the grounds that it would make the rights of
human makers absolute in the same way that God’s right over his creation is absolute. Sreenivasan
has defended Tully’s argument against Waldron’s response by claiming a distinction between
creating and making. Only creating generates an absolute property right, and only God can create,
but making is analogous to creating and creates an analogous, though weaker, right.
Another controversial aspect of Tully’s interpretation of Locke is his interpretation of the
sufficiency condition and its implications. On his analysis, the sufficiency argument is crucial for
Locke’s argument to be plausible. Since Locke begins with the assumption that the world is owned
by all, individual property is only justified if it can be shown that no one is made worse off by the
appropriation. In conditions where the good taken is not scarce, where there is much water or land
available, an individual’s taking some portion of it does no harm to others. Where this condition
is not met, those who are denied access to the good do have a legitimate objection to appropriation.
According to Tully, Locke realized that as soon as land became scarce, previous rights acquired
by labor no longer held since “enough and as good” was no longer available for others. Once land
became scarce, property could only be legitimated by the creation of political society.
Waldron claims that, contrary to Macpherson, Tully, and others, Locke did not recognize
a sufficiency condition at all. He notes that, strictly speaking, Locke makes sufficiency a sufficient
rather than necessary condition when he says that labor generates a title to property “at least where
there is enough, and as good left in common for others” (Two Treatises 2.27). Waldron takes
Locke to be making a descriptive statement, not a normative one, about the condition that happens
to have initially existed. Waldron also argues that in the text “enough and as good” is not presented
as a restriction and is not grouped with other restrictions. Waldron thinks that the condition would
lead Locke to the absurd conclusion that in circumstances of scarcity everyone must starve to death
since no one would be able to obtain universal consent and any appropriation would make others
worse off.
One of the strongest defenses of Tully’s position is presented by Sreenivasan. He argues
that Locke’s repetitious use of “enough and as good” indicates that the phrase is doing some real
work in the argument. In particular, it is the only way Locke can be thought to have provided some
solution to the fact that the consent of all is needed to justify appropriation in the state of nature.
If others are not harmed, they have no grounds to object and can be thought to consent, whereas if
they are harmed, it is implausible to think of them as consenting. Sreenivasan does depart from
Tully in some important respects. He takes “enough and as good” to mean “enough and as good
opportunity for securing one’s preservation,” not “enough and as good of the same commodity
(such as land).” This has the advantage of making Locke’s account of property less radical since
it does not claim that Locke thought the point of his theory was to show that all original property
rights were invalid at the point where political communities were created. The disadvantage of this
interpretation, as Sreenivasan admits, is that it saddles Locke with a flawed argument. Those who
merely have the opportunity to labor for others at subsistence wages no longer have the liberty that
individuals had before scarcity to benefit from the full surplus of value they create. Moreover poor
laborers no longer enjoy equality of access to the materials from which products can be made.
Sreenivasan thinks that Locke’s theory is thus unable to solve the problem of how individuals can
obtain individual property rights in what is initially owned by all people without consent.
Simmons presents a still different synthesis. He sides with Waldron and against Tully and
Sreenivasan in rejecting the workmanship model. He claims that the references to “making” in
chapter five of the Two Treatises are not making in the right sense of the word for the workmanship
model to be correct. Locke thinks we have property in our own persons even though we do not
make or create ourselves. Simmons claims that while Locke did believe that God had rights as
creator, human beings have a different limited right as trustees, not as makers. Simmons bases this
in part on his reading of two distinct arguments he takes Locke to make: the first justifies property
based on God’s will and basic human needs, the second based on “mixing” labor. According to
the former argument, at least some property rights can be justified by showing that a scheme
allowing appropriation of property without consent has beneficial consequences for the
preservation of mankind. This argument is overdetermined, according to Simmons, in that it can
be interpreted either theologically or as a simple rule-consequentialist argument. With respect to
the latter argument, Simmons takes labor not to be a substance that is literally “mixed” but rather
as a purposive activity aimed at satisfying needs and conveniences of life. Like Sreenivasan,
Simmons sees this as flowing from a prior right of people to secure their subsistence, but Simmons
also adds a prior right to self-government. Labor can generate claims to private property because
private property makes individuals more independent and able to direct their own actions.
Simmons thinks Locke’s argument is ultimately flawed because he underestimated the extent to
which wage labor would make the poor dependent on the rich, undermining self-government. He
also joins the chorus of those who find Locke’s appeal to consent to the introduction of money
inadequate to justify the very unequal property holdings that now exist.
Some authors have suggested that Locke may have had an additional concern in mind in
writing the chapter on property. Tully (1993) and Barbara Arneil point out that Locke was
interested in and involved in the affairs of the American colonies and that Locke’s theory of labor
led to the convenient conclusion that the labor of Native Americans generated property rights only
over the animals they caught, not the land on which they hunted which Locke regarded as vacant
and available for the taking. Armitage even argues that there is evidence that Locke was actively
involved in revising the Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina at the same time he was drafting
the chapter on property for the Second Treatise. Mark Goldie, however, cautions that we should
not miss the fact that political events in England were still Locke’s primary focus in writing the
the Second Treatise.
A final question concerns the status of those property rights acquired in the state of nature
after civil society has come into being. It seems clear that at the very least Locke allows taxation
to take place by the consent of the majority rather than requiring unanimous consent (2.140).
Nozick takes Locke to be a libertarian, with the government having no right to take property to use
for the common good without the consent of the property owner. On his interpretation, the majority
may only tax at the rate needed to allow the government to successfully protect property rights. At
the other extreme, Tully thinks that, by the time government is formed, land is already scarce and
so the initial holdings of the state of nature are no longer valid and thus are no constraint on
governmental action. Waldron’s view is in between these, acknowledging that property rights are
among the rights from the state of nature that continue to constrain the government, but seeing the
legislature as having the power to interpret what natural law requires in this matter in a fairly
substantial way.
7. Toleration
In Locke’s Letter Concerning Toleration, he develops several lines of arguments that are
intended to establish the proper spheres for religion and politics. His central claims are that
government should not use force to try to bring people to the true religion and that religious
societies are voluntary organizations that have no right to use coercive power over their own
members or those outside their group. One recurring line of argument that Locke uses is explicitly
religious. Locke argues that neither the example of Jesus nor the teaching of the New Testament
gives any indication that force is a proper way to bring people to salvation. He also frequently
points out what he takes to be clear evidence of hypocrisy, namely that those who are so quick to
persecute others for small differences in worship or doctrine are relatively unconcerned with much
more obvious moral sins that pose an even greater threat to their eternal state.
In addition to these and similar religious arguments, Locke gives three reasons that are
more philosophical in nature for barring governments from using force to encourage people to
adopt religious beliefs (Works 6:10–12). First, he argues that the care of men’s souls has not been
committed to the magistrate by either God or the consent of men. This argument resonates with
the structure of argument used so often in the Two Treatises to establish the natural freedom and
equality of mankind. There is no command in the Bible telling magistrates to bring people to the
true faith and people could not consent to such a goal for government because it is not possible for
people, at will, to believe what the magistrate tells them to believe. Their beliefs are a function of
what they think is true, not what they will. Locke’s second argument is that since the power of the
government is only force, while true religion consists of genuine inward persuasion of the mind,
force is incapable of bringing people to the true religion. Locke’s third argument is that even if the
magistrate could change people’s minds, a situation where everyone accepted the magistrate’s
religion would not bring more people to the true religion. Many of the magistrates of the world
believe religions that are false.
Locke’s contemporary, Jonas Proast, responded by saying that Locke’s three arguments
really amount to just two, that true faith cannot be forced and that we have no more reason to think
that we are right than anyone else has. Proast argued that force can be helpful in bringing people
to the truth “indirectly, and at a distance.” His idea was that although force cannot directly bring
about a change of mind or heart, it can cause people to consider arguments that they would
otherwise ignore or prevent them from hearing or reading things that would lead them astray. If
force is indirectly useful in bringing people to the true faith, then Locke has not provided a
persuasive argument. As for Locke’s argument about the harm of a magistrate whose religion is
false using force to promote it, Proast claimed that this was irrelevant since there is a morally
relevant difference between affirming that the magistrate may promote the religion he thinks true
and affirming that he may promote the religion that actually is true. Proast thought that unless one
was a complete skeptic, one must believe that the reasons for one’s own position are objectively
better than those for other positions.
Jeremy Waldron, in an influential article, restated the substance of Proast’s objection for a
contemporary audience. He argued that, leaving aside Locke’s Christian arguments, his main
position was that it was instrumentally irrational, from the perspective of the persecutor, to use
force in matters of religion because force acts only on the will and belief is not something that we
change at will. Waldron pointed out that this argument blocks only one particular reason for
persecution, not all reasons. Thus it would not stop someone who used religious persecution for
some end other than religious conversion, such as preserving the peace. Even in cases where
persecution does have a religious goal, Waldron agrees with Proast that force may be indirectly
effective in changing people’s beliefs. Much of the current discussion about Locke’s contribution
to contemporary political philosophy in the area of toleration centers on whether Locke has a good
reply to these objections from Proast and Waldron.
Some contemporary commentators try to rescue Locke’s argument by redefining the
religious goal that the magistrate is presumed to seek. Susan Mendus, for example, notes that
successful brainwashing might cause a person to sincerely utter a set of beliefs, but that those
beliefs might still not count as genuine. Beliefs induced by coercion might be similarly
problematic. Paul Bou Habib argues that what Locke is really after is sincere inquiry and that
Locke thinks inquiry undertaken only because of duress is necessarily insincere. These approaches
thus try to save Locke’s argument by showing that force really is incapable of bringing about the
desired religious goal.
Other commentators focus on Locke’s first argument about proper authority, and
particularly on the idea that authorization must be by consent. David Wootton argues that even if
force occasionally works at changing a person’s belief, it does not work often enough to make it
rational for persons to consent to the government exercising that power. A person who has good
reason to think he will not change his beliefs even when persecuted has good reason to prevent the
persecution scenario from ever happening. Richard Vernon argues that we want not only to hold
right beliefs, but also to hold them for the right reasons. Since the balance of reasons rather than
the balance of force should determine our beliefs, we would not consent to a system in which
irrelevant reasons for belief might influence us.
Other commentators focus on the third argument, that the magistrate might be wrong. Here
the question is whether Locke’s argument is question begging or not. The two most promising
lines of argument are the following. Wootton argues that there are very good reasons, from the
standpoint of a given individual, for thinking that governments will be wrong about which religion
is true. Governments are motivated by the quest for power, not truth, and are unlikely to be good
guides in religious matters. Since there are so many different religions held by rulers, if only one
is true then likely my own ruler’s views are not true. Wootton thus takes Locke to be showing that
it is irrational, from the perspective of the individual, to consent to government promotion of
religion. A different interpretation of the third argument is presented by Tuckness. He argues that
the likelihood that the magistrate may be wrong generates a principle of toleration based on what
is rational from the perspective of a legislator, not the perspective of an individual citizen. Drawing
on Locke’s later writings on toleration, he argues that Locke’s theory of natural law assumes that
God, as author of natural law, takes into account the fallibility of those magistrates who will carry
out the commands of natural law. If “use force to promote the true religion” were a command of
natural law addressed to all magistrates, it would not promote the true religion in practice because
so many magistrates wrongly believe that their religion is the true one. Tuckness claims that in
Locke’s later writings on toleration he moved away from arguments based on what it is
instrumentally rational for an individual to consent to. Instead, he emphasized testing proposed
principles based on whether they would still fulfill their goal if universally applied by fallible
human beings.
Sources:
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke-political/#LawNat
https://fee.org/articles/john-locke-natural-rights-to-life-liberty-and-property/