2018 Voting From Prison Against The Demo
2018 Voting From Prison Against The Demo
Pablo Marshall
To cite this article: Pablo Marshall (2018) Voting from prison: against the democratic case for
disenfranchisement, Ethics & Global Politics, 11:1, 1498696
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
Introduction
Many convicted offenders around the world do not vote in elections; they have been
legally deprived of their voting rights as a consequence of their criminal convictions.
Most countries restrict this measure to those serving prison sentences. That is why this
practice is usually referred to as prisoner disenfranchisement. Theoretically, this prac-
tice embodies a tension between the idea of universal democratic participation and the
exclusion experienced by those who break the most serious rules prescribed by a
community. This article addresses this tension, which has been mainly articulated in
legal terms as a conflict between the fundamental right to vote and the public’s interest
in excluding prisoners from the exercise of said right. The traditional legal claim that
disenfranchisement is a legitimate practice has been based on the notion that the
CONTACT Pablo Marshall pmarshall@uach.cl School of Law, Universidad Austral de Chile, Campus Isla Teja s/
n, Valdivia, Chile
© 2018 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group.
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial License (http://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/), which permits unrestricted non-commercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any
medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
2 P. MARSHALL
electorate has to hold a minimum degree of civic virtue (and that prisoners are not
virtuous) (see e.g. Manfredi, 2009) or on the idea that disfranchisement is an expression
of a legitimate additional punishment or civil sanction for serious offenders (see e.g.
Hampton, 1998). This article departs from the analysis of framing the problem of
disenfranchisement in a legal and constitutional perspective, and adopts the more
flexible theoretical approach. It also departs from the premise that disenfranchisement
must be justified in terms of electoral capacity or additional punishment.
Ramsay and López-Guerra argue that the conditions of limited or non-existent
freedom in which prisoners live are not compatible with the claim that prisoners are
members of an authentic self-governed community. Thus, persons living under such
conditions must be excluded from the franchise to protect the purity of the electoral
process. This argument is referred to as the democratic case for disenfranchisement or
democratic disenfranchisement because, unlike arguments based on punishment and
capacity, it is based on the premise of the value of prisoners’ democratic participation
and embraces democracy, not virtue or desert, as the value that is served by
disenfranchisement.1 The main implication of this difference is that democratic disen-
franchisement, due to its commitment with democracy, seems less vulnerable to criti-
cism which indicates that disenfranchisement embodies punitive forms of degradation
and political exclusion (see e.g. Pettus, 2013).
The arguments of Ramsay and López-Guerra are presented in the first section. They
are then critically examined in the following sections, where two serious problems that
affect the premises and consequences of their arguments are brought forth. The second
section introduces the need for democratic conditions of imprisonment, and the third
section argues that electoral coercion and manipulation are limited threats to electoral
integrity. Finally, the last section of the article argues that there is no strong case for
disenfranchisement in the context of a community with an inclusionary democratic
commitment; this is because democratic disenfranchisement is affected by the exclu-
sionary and degrading consequences resulting from justifications of disenfranchisement
based on punishment or capacity.
1
A different case for democratic disenfranchisement has been offered by Altman (2005) and Büllow (2016). They have
focused on the justification of a community’s collective right to disenfranchise convicted criminals, instead of on
certain goals that are pursued by disenfranchisement as an institutional practice. They have recently been under
criticism by Matt S. Whitt (2017).
ETHICS & GLOBAL POLITICS 3
This democratic model contrasts with what Ramsay calls post-democracy. Post-
democracy can be described as an alternative political regime that differs from democ-
racy in two main elements that mirror the elements of democracy as self-government.
First, under post-democracy, ‘a minimalist conception of representative democracy has
[…] entirely marginalised the connection between political representation and the self-
government of the people’ (2013b, 13). Democracy is minimized because there is no
political competition (rather only a ‘contest over technical competency’), and, therefore,
the critical dialogue between representatives and their constituency cannot take place
beyond the margins of political alienation (2013c, 230–1). This, in turn, has an impact
on the second element. In post-democracy, ‘people can be imprisoned when they have
not violated the ‘social contract’ and civil liberty is not regarded as absolutely essential
to political citizenship’ (2013a, 424, 433–4).
but only at the cost of eradicating every possibility for the political autonomy of
prisoners to be expressed. The principle of political equality is protected at the expense
of the prisoners’ political freedom. However, as Beckman (2009, 129) suggests, if it is
acknowledged that it is not the prisoners’ right to vote that causes the problem but the
fraudulent conduct of the authorities, the solution must involve acting against the fraud
rather than against the victims of the fraud. His suggestion is that ‘to a large extent, the
lack of opportunities for political participation can be mitigated by organising the penal
system in the right way’ (124).
López-Guerra (2014) offers a contextual objection to Beckman’s conclusion by arguing
that ‘with the exception of some developed countries, the conditions in many prisons
around the world are such that the risk of coerced voting is very high’ (128). The
possibility of avoiding the electoral abuse, therefore, would depend on the conditions
of the particular prison system and should be decided on a case-by-case basis. In some
cases, electoral fraud may be committed directly by prison authorities under the control
of the government; in other cases, a lack of control over conditions inside the prison may
allow criminal organizations operating inside to sell prisoners’ votes to the highest bidder.
No prison reform can be expected to fully eliminate the factual basis of López-Guerra’s
contextual objection or fully improve prison conditions. Thus, there is a case for disen-
franchisement in those contexts in which prison conditions are likely to lead to voting
fraud and are unlikely to change. However, López-Guerra emphasizes that this is not a
justification for excluding prisoners from the franchise but simply a justification for not
adopting a device to allow voting from prison. Excluding prisoners from the franchise, he
maintains, would send the message that prisoners deserve political exclusion, whereas
the second ‘is an indicator of unacceptable life conditions […which] does not speak
negatively of inmates, but of the society where they live’ (129).
The main difference between the proposals of López-Guerra and Ramsay can be
summarized as follows. López-Guerra considers that the reason to exclude prisoners
from voting is the particular conditions of prisons. Therefore, disenfranchisement must
be evaluated empirically and will depend on the probabilities of electoral coercion in
each prison. On the other hand, Ramsay’s proposal has universal application and points
to the conditions of a lack of independence vis-à-vis the government that affect all those
who are in an institution with the characteristics of a prison. His proposal does not
require an empirical evaluation and would affect even those inmates in prisons with
high standards of respect for human rights.
as a consequence of the needs of prison administration and only for those purposes.
Justificación de este principio. This distinction implies that the offender’s liberty ought
to be considered divisible and that it should be accepted that imprisonment only
affects the offender’s liberty in some regards and not in its entirety (Lazarus 2016).
Framed in other terms, a democratic conception of imprisonment demands that
prisoners be considered rights holders and therefore excludes the radical scenario in
which the prisoners’ status is reduced by depriving them of their entire liberty and
abandoning them to the discretion of authorities. This conception of imprisonment as
the suspension of some aspects of the right to liberty opposes Ramsay’s conception of
imprisonment as a total suspension of the right to liberty and consequential suspen-
sion of other liberties. Designing legal mechanisms to guarantee the prisoners’ enjoy-
ment of liberties and to defend them from arbitrary state interference may throw a
punch to Ramsay’s argument. For example, an independent judicial review system
that oversees whether prisoners’ liberties are being respected could also have the
potential to guide the prison system towards the creation of internal policies which
are more respectful of those liberties. There is no space here to more accurately
develop the functioning and effectiveness of the aforementioned mechanisms that
could be carried out by an independent judicial review, but it can be imagined how
they may improve the conditions of freedom and independence within prison.
A second step in building a democratic prison is the recognition of prisoners as
citizens. In a democratic prison regime, which takes the need of civil liberties seriously,
prisoners should be guaranteed all civil liberties and political rights compatible with the
needs of the prison administration (see e.g. van Zyl Smit and Snacken, 2009, 65–9).
Freedom of information, expression, reunion, and association cannot be limited with-
out clear reasons concerning the administration’s objectives (Foster 2002). For example,
freedom of reunion in a protest against the prison authorities might be reasonably
limited based on arguments of security, but when prisoners organize a meeting to listen
to and speak with their democratic representatives there seem to be no good reasons to
apply such limits (Lippke, 2007). In sum, prisons can be organized in such a way to
respect certain key aspects of prisoners’ civil liberties, generating spaces for meaningful
political participation. Enfranchisement completes the recognition of prisoners as
citizens whose voice and interest must count equally.
and individual interests. For example, the right to freedom of expression is limited by
national security laws and libel and hate speech regulation. The right to assembly, in
turn, is limited by the need for administrative permits and for restricting demonstra-
tions to a certain size or certain zones. In the case of prisoners, such regulation might be
more intrusive, thus restricting their liberties considerably. However, civil liberties
outside prison walls can also be similarly affected by arguments of security or other
deliberations of public interest. This demonstrates that people’s liberty can be restricted
in several forms and in varying degrees, thereby affecting the possibilities for its
exercise. It is simply wrong to sustain that prisoners lack all liberty and that free
citizens enjoy full liberty. Civil liberties have never been absolute, and sustaining this
claim does not mean we must endorse a post-democratic society as described by
Ramsay. Based on the previous observations, one must be critical of the claim that
imprisonment necessarily involves the loss of civil liberties or that the liberties which
prisoners enjoy would only constitute an executive licence. That assertion can indeed be
correct and accurate regarding a concrete prison regime, but as a general claim it must
be regarded as false.
Secondly, even if it is accepted that the degree of freedom enjoyed by prisoners will
never be comparable to the degree of freedom experienced by citizens outside prison,
this difference does not need to lead to disenfranchisement based on a lack of political
equality. Political equality, in Ramsay’s terms, requires that ‘citizens have the formal
status of rulers’ and that ‘equal influence over policy and the making of the laws’ is
granted to every citizen (2015, 7–8). However, even with these two core elements of
political equality, this equality can be understood in two different ways: as a point of
departure or as a point of arrival for democratic citizenship. If it is understood as a
precondition for enfranchisement (departure), it is essential to ask whether the degree
of freedom enjoyed by prisoners is sufficiently similar to other enfranchised citizens.
The answer would be that within the premises of a democratic prison prisoners would
not be in conditions of political participation that are qualitatively different from other
citizens. On the other hand, political equality can also be understood as the regulative
ideal, a point of arrival, that demands the creation of democratic prisons and the
enfranchisement of prisoners on the same grounds, under which the latter does not
depend on the former. Prisoners must be treated as citizens and should be granted the
means to act in equal terms regardless of whether or not they actually enjoy equal
political influence; this is because political equality recognizes all persons as members of
a democratic society. Although this second conception of political equality (as a point
of arrival) is more favourable to enfranchisement, it can be argued that no conception
of political equality is an obstacle to enfranchising prisoners.
Disenfranchisement as punishment
The second objection to democratic disenfranchisement is partially related to the first.
Ramsay might argue that, despite the respect for civil liberties that a democratic prison
guarantees, prisoners will always be in a position of dependence on the authorities
because imprisonment coincides with a formal denial of civil liberties, which in turn
coincides with the formal denial of political equality. Here the word ‘formal’ is very
important as it implies that the denial of civil liberties, and therefore the denial of
10 P. MARSHALL
political equality and citizenship, is deliberate and intended, and not a secondary and
unintended consequence of imprisonment. In this argument, therefore, disenfranchise-
ment is ultimately disconnected from the fact of prisoners’ lack of liberty. Instead, it is
clearly connected to the status produced by the formal act of criminal conviction;
therefore, all the exclusionary and degrading problems affecting punitive conceptions
of disenfranchisement must be duly considered.
This idea that disenfranchisement follows the formal denial of liberties has a
systematic position in Ramsay’s account of imprisonment and account of the relation-
ship between citizenship and the commission of a criminal offence, in which he sees the
punishment of imprisonment to be a formal denial of liberty. The justification for
imprisonment as punishment, he sustains, is founded on the suspension of citizenship
experienced by the inmates. The radical deprivation of liberty implied by imprisonment
is not compatible with the idea of democratic citizenship. This is an argument for a
more lenient use of imprisonment, but it also implies a radical conclusion regarding
those who are imprisoned. The radical consequence of exclusion from citizenship is
justified by Ramsay when he argues that the commission of a criminal offence is
considered a self-exclusion from citizenship. Only on these grounds can Ramsay envi-
sage the justification of the convict’s deprivation of liberty: ‘[i]mprisonment does not
violate the citizenship of those who deny the rights of citizenship [, it is only]
symbolically and practically implementing the offenders’ own negation of citizenship’
(Ramsay, 2013a, 428). This idea regarding the (temporary) loss of citizenship due to a
criminal conviction posits serious questions as to the relevance of the democratic
explanation based on the relationship between civil liberties and the right to vote. If
those correctly imprisoned are non-citizens during their sentence, then one might
sincerely question why disenfranchisement should be explained in relation to the lack
of civil liberties. The right to vote is, on the same grounds as civil liberties, a right of
democratic citizenship. Under this model, the justification of disenfranchisement as an
expression of the demands of self-government seems redundant: if the consequence of a
criminal conviction is the suspension of citizenship, this is the fact that authorizes both
imprisonment and disenfranchisement.
Ramsay seems committed to the understanding of disenfranchisement as the nor-
mative consequence of the act committed by the offender. Ultimately, he sees disen-
franchisement as a part of the punishment. It was mentioned in the introduction that
one of the distinctive features of democratic disenfranchisement is that disenfranchising
prisoners is meant to protect democracy rather than further punish offenders by
excluding them from the franchise. Ramsay’s proposal of democratic disenfranchise-
ment thus lacks an important part of its democratic appeal as he argues in favour of
disenfranchisement not to protect democracy but rather to punish offenders.
electoral preferences but at the ‘circumstances in which these preferences are formed’
(Ramsay, 2013a, 425). The elector has been influenced and persuaded to prefer an
electoral option that without manipulation he would not prefer. The line between the
two forms of intervention can, of course, be fine in some cases; however, it is important
to distinguish between these forms because they require different responses. I argue that
the solution to the first kind of intervention is not disenfranchisement but electoral
reform. Concerning the second case, I support the view that prisoners who are under
some form of manipulation are not in a fundamentally different position from other
persons living outside of prison.
ballot boxes inside (because doing so would jeopardize some of the previous objectives),
then special arrangements must be made so that prisoners are taken out at random to
cast their votes somewhere within the premises or in an area surrounding the prison.
Finally, it is important for prisoners to be aware of the impact of the aforementioned
measures (that is, they are bringing about electoral integrity) and for the prisoners to be
plausibly persuaded of the integrity of elections within prison. Otherwise, it is possible
that prisoners would have no stable grounds to trust the integrity of electoral process
and that those who run the prison could credibly threaten sanctions if prisoners do not
vote in a certain way.
These directions have the potential to limit the problems of coercion or to eliminate
it altogether in certain cases. However, they do not constitute an all-things-considered
case against electoral coercion, and certain extreme cases could still be problematic. In
contexts in which prison conditions are severely corrupt and deteriorated, even the
correct implementation of the directions is not enough to impede electoral coercion.
Under such conditions, there may be a case for disenfranchisement.
military and civil servants are also affected by this kind of relationship, in which rights
have a legitimate source of restriction in other values such as security or discipline. This
list can be extended to include all those people under the massive disciplinary influence
of private powers that, as already admitted by Franz Neumann in (1953), ‘can be even
more dangerous to liberty than public power’ (919). In a society with high indexes of
inequality, the incapacity to exercise fundamental political rights is common amongst
the unprivileged, and the social and economic power of non-state actors frequently
renders this group irrelevant. More broadly, the influence of the state, and in particular
of the administrative power, as a product of social welfare and the consequential
consumerization of certain sectors of the population stands as a major threat to the
independence of citizens in general (Habermas, 1993, 406–10). It is not clear under
which conditions prisoners’ subjection to executive powers and the subjection of the
underprivileged to political, economic and cultural powers must be codified differently
in relation to enfranchisement. To be coherent with a demand for an electorate free of
influence and manipulation, all those classes of persons should be disenfranchised.
Concluding remarks
The cases for prisoner disenfranchisement argued by Ramsay and López-Guerra are
probably the strongest democratic arguments available to normatively justify this practice.
These cases, however, are not without great fault. Their arguments are based on a diagnostic
of the conditions of imprisonment being the element that causes prisoners’ electoral
participation to be problematic for democracy as their participation endangers electoral
integrity. This article argued against their position and suggested that for prisoners to be
treated as democratic citizens they must be enfranchised and given the opportunity to vote.
Firstly, I argued that prisoners cannot be made responsible for the conditions of their
imprisonment and that, instead of an argument for disenfranchisement, undemocratic
prisons must be interpreted as the need to protect the democratic premises of prisoner
participation. It was also affirmed that the conditions of those imprisoned are not
sufficiently different, in relevant aspects, from the conditions of other enfranchised
people. Some objections to my case against democratic disenfranchisement were con-
sidered and discarded. Secondly, I also claimed that Ramsay’s and López-Guerra’s
arguments underestimate the possibilities of prison reform and electoral regulation to
overcome the democratic problems of electoral coercion and electoral manipulation.
There are several issues that must be discussed concerning prison reform advocating
a more democratic model of imprisonment, with the recognition of prisoners as citizens
constituting an urgent affair. In contrast with other rights of participation, the right to
vote is particularly propitious to expressing democratic recognition for those impri-
soned. This is mainly because the right to vote does not depend on a demanding notion
of participation. Even prisoners in conditions of serious deprivations of liberty can be
included as members of the democratic community via enfranchisement. If a compen-
satory relation between the mechanisms of participation and forms of recognizing
citizenship can be imagined, then granting prisoners the right to vote is certainly an
essential formula for such a relation. Subjecting prisoners to a legal regime in which
other rights of participation are massively affected puts in danger the continuation of
their recognition as citizens. Their right to vote might constitute an adequate response
ETHICS & GLOBAL POLITICS 15
to this serious problem and perhaps the starting point of a constructive solution. This
diagnosis could lead to a conclusion in opposition with Ramsay’s: the less liberty
prisoners enjoy, the more important their enfranchisement becomes.3 It is interesting
to note that this seems to be the logic of the German model of disenfranchisement. In
Germany, disenfranchisement does not affect prisoners, but only ex-prisoners.
According to section 45a of the Criminal Code (1975) ‘[t]he duration of the loss of
ability or of a right shall be calculated from the day the term of imprisonment has been
served’ (see Demleitner, 2000).
To conclude, we have seen that democratic disenfranchisement is not such a promising
alternative to justify the electoral exclusion of prisoners. In actuality, commitment with
democratic participation, respect for political equality and the democratic dignity of our
fellow citizens speak in favour of the inclusion, rather than exclusion, of those who are
imprisoned into the electoral franchise. To justify general disenfranchisement in a way that
is consistent with democracy requires more robust arguments. While waiting for those
arguments, the transition towards a more democratic prison system should be the main
concern. The enfranchisement of all prisoners is a question that cannot be ignored in
bringing about the advancement of the fundamental aim of more democratic prisons.
Acknowledgments
This paper has benefitted from comments provided by Claudio López-Guerra, Su Bian, Marco
Goldoni, and two anonymous reviewers.
The author would like to thank Peter Ramsay, Fernando Muñoz, William Bullow and Su
Bian for their comment to earlier drafts
Disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.
Funding
This work was supported by Fondo de Fomento al Desarrollo Científico y Tecnológico (Conicyt-
Chile) [grant number 11150299].
ORCID
Pablo Marshall http://orcid.org/0000-0001-8347-4620
References
Altman, A. 2005. “Democratic Self-Determination and the Disenfranchisement of Felons.”
Journal of Applied Philosophy 22: 263–273. doi:10.1111/japp.2005.22.issue-3.
Beckman, L. 2009. The Frontiers of Democracy. The Right to Vote and Its Limits. London:
Palgrave Macmillan.
3
This reasoning might lead to conclude that the disenfranchisement of prisoners is more problematic than the
disenfranchisement of people who are not in prison because the latter group can in fact exercise other rights of
participation. However, in such a case, the aim of disenfranchisement would be evidently punitive and not regulative.
16 P. MARSHALL
Behan, C. 2014. Citizen Convicts: Prisoners, Politics and the Vote. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Brettschneider, C. 2007. “The Rights of the Guilty: Punishment and Political Legitimacy.”
Political Theory 35 (2): 175–199. doi:10.1177/0090591706297714.
Brettschneider, C. 2010. Democratic Rights: The Substance of Self-Government. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Büllow, W. 2016. “Felon Disenfranchisement and the Argument for Democratic
Self-Determination.” Philosophia 44: 759–774. doi:10.1007/s11406-016-9722-y.
Demleitner, N. 2000. “Continuing Payment on One’s Debt to Society: The German Model of
Felon Disenfranchisement as an Alternative.” Minnesota Law Review 84: 753–804.
Duff, A. 2001. Punishment, Communication and Community. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Easton, S. 2009. “The Prisoner’s Right to Vote and Civic Responsibility: Reaffirming the Social
Contract?” Probation Journal 56: 231. doi:10.1177/0264550509337455.
Foster, S. 2002. “Prisoners’ Rights, Freedom of Expression and the Human Rights Act 1998.”
Journal of Civil Liberties 7: 53–82.
Foucault, M. 1995. Discipline and Punishment. London: Penguin.
Garland, D. 1990. Punishment and Modern Society. New York: Oxford University Press.
Habermas, J. 1993. Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Hampton, J. 1998. “Punishment, Feminism, and Political Identity: A Case Study in the
Expressive Nature of Law.” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 11: 23–45.
doi:10.1017/S0841820900001673.
Lazarus, L. 2006. “Conceptions of Liberty Deprivation.” Modern Law Review 69: 738–744.
doi:10.1111/j.1468-2230.2006.00608.x.
Lippke, R. 2002. “Toward a Theory of Prisoners’ Rights.” Ratio Juris 15: 122–145. doi:10.1111/
raju.2002.15.issue-2.
Lippke, R. 2007. Rethinking Imprisonment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
López-Guerra, C. 2014. Democracy and Disenfranchisement: The Morality of Electoral Exclusions.
New York: OUP.
Manfredi, C. 2009. “In Defence of Prisoner Disenfranchisement.” In Criminal
Disenfranchisement in an International Perspective, edited by A. Ewald and B. Rottinghaus.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Neumann, F. 1953. “The Concept of Political Freedom.” Columbia Law Review 53: 901–935.
doi:10.2307/1119178.
Pettus, I. 2013. Felony Disenfranchisement in America: Historical Origins, Institutional Racism,
and Modern Consequences. New York: SUNY Press.
Ramsay, P. 2013a. “Voters Should Not Be in Prison! the Rights of Prisoners in a Democracy.”
Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 16: 421–438. doi:10.1080/
13698230.2013.795706.
Ramsay, P. 2013b. “Faking Democracy with Prisoners’ Voting Rights”. LSE Law, Society and
Economy Working Papers 7/2013.
Ramsay, P. 2013c. “Democratic Limits to Preventive Criminal Law.” In Prevention and the Limits
of the Criminal Law, edited by A. Ashworth, L. Zedner, and P. Tomlin. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Ramsay, P. 2015. “Imprisonment and Political Equality”. LSE Law, Society and Economy
Working Papers 8/2015.
van Zyl Smit, D., and S. Snacken. 2009. Principles of European Prison Law and Policy. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Whitt, M. S. 2017. “Felon Disenfranchisement and Democratic Legitimacy.” Forthcoming in
Social Theory and Practice 43.