100% found this document useful (1 vote)
331 views11 pages

History of The Idea of Progress PDF

This document provides a brief history of the idea of progress. It discusses how the idea of linear, directed progress emerged from Christianity's conception of history but was later secularized during the Enlightenment. Key aspects of the modern theory of progress include: (1) the view of time as linear and history as having meaning and direction towards the future, (2) the idea of fundamental human unity and shared progress, and (3) the view that humanity can transform the world through science and technology. The document traces how these ideas developed from ancient Greek thought to Christian theology to the scientific revolution and Enlightenment.

Uploaded by

alanmoore2000
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
331 views11 pages

History of The Idea of Progress PDF

This document provides a brief history of the idea of progress. It discusses how the idea of linear, directed progress emerged from Christianity's conception of history but was later secularized during the Enlightenment. Key aspects of the modern theory of progress include: (1) the view of time as linear and history as having meaning and direction towards the future, (2) the idea of fundamental human unity and shared progress, and (3) the view that humanity can transform the world through science and technology. The document traces how these ideas developed from ancient Greek thought to Christian theology to the scientific revolution and Enlightenment.

Uploaded by

alanmoore2000
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 11

A B RIEF H ISTORY OF


THE IDEA OF P ROGRESS

ALAIN DE BENOIST
_____________________

TRANSLATED BY G REG JOHNSON

The idea of progr e s s se e m s on e of theor eti cal pres u p p o si -


tions of mod er ni ty. One can ev en regar d it, not withou t rea -
son, as the real “religion of West er n civilizatio n.” Historically,
this idea was form ul at e d earlier than it is gen e r ally thoug ht ,
aroun d 1680, during the quarr el of Ancient s and th e Moder n s,
in which Terr as s o n, Charles Perrault, the Abbé of Saint- Pierre,
and Fonte n ell e participat e d . It was then dev elo p e d on the ini-
tiative of a secon d gene r a t ion, including princip ally Turgot,
Condorc et , and Louis Seba s ti e n Mercier.
Progr es s can be defined as a cum ul a tiv e proce s s in which
the most rece nt st ag e is always con sider e d prefer a b l e an d
bet t er, i.e., qualitatively sup erior, to what prec e d e d it. This
definition cont ain s a descrip tive elem e n t (ch an g e takes place
in a given direction) and an axiological elem e n t (this progr e s -
sion is interpr et e d as an improv e m e n t ) . Thus it refer s to
chang e th at is orient e d (towar d th e best), nece s s a r y (one
do es not stop progr e s s) , and irreversible (no overall retur n to
the past is possibl e). Improv e m e n t being inesca p a bl e, it fol-
lows that tom orro w will be always bett er than tod a y.

***
The theorist s of progr es s differ on the directio n of
progr e s s , the rat e and the nat ur e of the chan g e s th at acco m -
pany it, ev en its principal ag e nt s . Never t h el e s s , all adh er e to
thre e key idea s: (1) a linear conce p tion of time an d th e idea
that history has a m e a ni ng, orien t e d towar ds the futur e; (2)


Alain de Benoist, “Un brève histoire de l’idé e de progr è s,” in his Cri-
tique s —Th é ori que s (Laus a n n e , Switzerla n d: L’Age d’Hom m e , 2002), 55–
62. The tran sl a tor wishe s to tha nk Alain de Benoist for per mi ssion to
tran sl at e and publish this ess a y, Micha el O’Meara for checking the trans -
lation, and Arjuna for help with Frenc h idiom s.
8 The Occiden t al Quarterly , vol. 8, no. 1, Spring 2008

the idea of the funda m e n t a l unity of hum a ni t y, all called to


evolve in the sam e direction toget h e r; and (3) the idea that
the world can and must be tran sfor m e d , which implies that
the m an affirm s him s elf as sover ei g n ma st e r of nat u r e.
Thes e thr e e ideas originat e d from Christianity. But with th e
rise of scien c e and technolog y in th e sev e n t e e n t h cent ur y,
they were reform ul at e d in secul ar ter m s.
For th e Greeks, et ernit y alone is real. Authen ti c being is im -
mut a bl e: circular motion, which en su r e s the et er n al retur n of
sam e in a series of succe s siv e cycles, is the mo st perfec t ex -
pression of the divine. If ther e ar e rises and falls, progr e s s
and decline, it is within a cycle inevita bly followed by ano th er
(Hesiod’s th eor y of the succe s sio n of the ag es , Virgil’s retur n
of the golden ag e). In ad dition, the m ajor det er m i ning factor
com e s from the past , not the future: the ter m arche refers
abo ve all to an origin (“archaic”) as an aut h ority (“ archon t e ,”
“mon ar c h ”).
With the Bible, history beco m e s an objectiv ely knowabl e
phe no m e n o n , a dyna mi c of pro gr e s s that aims, from the Mes -
sianic point of view, towar d the adv en t of a bet t er world. Gen -
esis assi gn s man the mission of “domi n a tin g the Earth.” Tem -
porality is the vect or in ter m s of which the bet t e r mu st pro -
gressiv ely rev e al itself in the world. As a result, a historical
eve nt can have a savin g role: God ap pe a r s historically. Tem -
porality, mor eo v e r , is direct e d towar d s th e futur e, from Cre -
ation to the Second Coming , the Gard e n of Eden to th e Last
Judgm e n t . The golden age no long er lies in the past, but at
the end of tim es: history will en d, and it will end well, at least
for the choo s e n ones.
This linear tem por ality exclu de s any eter n al retur n , any
cyclic conce p tion of history bas e d on the succe s si o n of age s
and sea s o n s . Since Adam and Eve, the history of salvatio n
proce e d s accor di n g to a nec e s sit y fixed for all et ernity, com -
m en ci ng with the old Covena nt an d, in Christi anity, culmin at -
ing in an Incarna ti on that cann o t be repe a t e d . Saint Augus -
tine was th e first to derive from this conc e pti o n a philoso p hy
of univers al history applicabl e to all hu m a ni t y, which is called
to progr e s s from ag e to age towar ds the bet t e r.
The the ory of prog re s s seculariz es this linear conc e pti o n of
history, from which all mod er n historicism s arise. The m ajor
differenc e is that the her e aft e r is reco n c ei v e d as th e futur e,
and happi n e s s replac e s salvati on . Inde e d, in Christi anity,
Benoist, “A Brief History of the Idea of Progre s s” 9

progr e s s rem ain s more esch a t ol ogical tha n historical in the


prope r sens e. Man mus t seek salv atio n here below, but with a
view to th e other world. For he has no control over the divine.
Christia nity also cond e m n s insati abl e desire an d, like Sto -
icism, holds that moral wisdom lies more in the limitation
than the multiplica tion of desire s. Only the millen nialist cur -
ren t in Christianity, inspired by the Apocalyp s e , envis ag e s a
terr es t ri al reign of a thous a n d year s prece di ng the Last Judg -
m en t . Secul arizing Augustin e’s vision, millennialis m inspire d
Joachi m of Flora and his spiritu al desc e n d a n t s . But the theor y
of prog re s s need e d addition al elem e n t s to arriv e at its mo d -
ern form. These elem e n t s first ap pe ar e d in the Renaiss a n c e
and cam e to fruition in the sev e n t e e n t h cent ur y.
The rise of scienc e and techn olo g y, as well as the discov -
ery of the New World, nourish ed opti mis m while ap pe a ri n g to
op en a field for infinite possibl e improv e m e n t . Francis Baco n,
who was the first to use the word “progre ss ” in a te m p o r al
rath er th an a spati al sens e, affirm e d that man’s role is to
control nat ur e by knowing its laws. Ren é Descar t e s , in similar
fashio n, propo s e d that ma n make hims elf mas t e r and poss e s -
sor of nat u r e. Nat ur e, conceive d in the “m at h e m a t i c al lan -
gua g e” of Galileo, the n beco m e s mut e and inani m a t e . The
cos m o s no longer has any m ea nin g in itself. It is nothing
more tha n a machi ne that mu st be disas s e m b l e d to be known
and m anipul at e d . The world beco m e s a pur e object to the hu -
m an subject . Thanks to his reas on , man feels that he can rely
on hims elf alone.
The cos m o s of the Ancient s thu s gives way to a new world:
geo m e t ri cal, hom o g e n e o u s , and (proba b ly) infinite, gover n e d
by laws of caus e and effect . The mod el of this world is the
m achi n e , specifically the clock. Time itself beco m e s ho m o g e -
neo u s, m ea s ur a bl e: “m er ch a n t tim e” replace s “p ea s a n t time”
(Jacq ue s Le Goff). The techn olo gic al m en t ality em er g e s from
this new scientific spirit. The princip al purp os e of tech n olog y
is m axi mizing utility, i.e., helpin g to prod uc e useful thin gs.
There was an obvious conver g e n c e betw e e n this scientific
optimis m and the aspir ation s of a bourgeois class taking com -
man d of natio nal m arket s , which were creat e d in tand e m with
territorial kingdo m s. The bourge oi s men t ality tend s to regar d
only calculabl e quan tities, i.e., com m er ci al values, as valuable,
indeed as real. Georges Sorel later saw the theory of progres s
as a “bourge ois doctrine.”
10 The Occiden t al Quarterly , vol. 8, no. 1, Spring 2008

In the eight e e n t h cent ur y, the classical eco no mi s t s (Adam


Smith, Bernar d Mande ville, David Hum e) reh a bilit at e d insa -
tiable desire: According to the m , ma n’s nee d s can alway s be
increa s e d . Thus by his very nat u r e, m an always want s more
and act s accordin gly, con st a n t ly seekin g to m aximize his best
inter es t . Along with the regna n t optimis m , this line of arg u -
m en t ten ds to relativize or effac e the the m e of original sin.
The cum ul ative char ac t e r of scien tific knowledg e was
stre ss e d with particular insist e n c e. Progre s s, it was conclu d -
ed, is nece s s a r y : one will alway s know more, thu s ev eryt hi ng
will always get bett er . Given th at a good mind is “for m e d by
all that prec e d e s it,” the Moder n s are obviou sly sup erio r: “We
are dwarfs perch e d on the should er s of giant s,” said
Font en elle, quoting Bern ar d of Clairvau x. Thus the Ancien t s
are dives t e d of au tho rity. Traditio n, in fact, is see n as inher -
ently an obst a cl e in reaso n’s path. The com p a ri so n of pres e n t
and past—always to th e form er’s adv a n t a g e— al s o allows on e
to glimp s e the cours e of the futur e. Com p a ris o n thu s be -
com e s prediction: progr es s, initially posit e d as the effect of
evolutio n, is hencefort h taken as its cau s e .
A relat e d conce p ti o n, alre ad y form ul at e d by Saint Augu s -
tine, is of hum a ni ty as a unitary org anis m th at grad u ally
leave s the childh oo d of the “first age s” to ent e r “adultho o d .”
Thus according to Turgot, “m ankin d, consider e d from its in -
ception . . . app e a r s to the eyes of the philoso ph e r as an im -
m en s e whole that has, like ever y individu al, a childho od and
a dev el o p m e n t . ” The mech a ni c al met a p h or yields her e to an
orga nic one, but this organici sm is par ad oxical, since it envis -
age s neith er old age nor de at h . This idea of a collectiv e or -
ganis m becom in g perp et u a lly “more adult” gav e rise to the
cont e m p o r a r y idea of “develop m e n t ” under s t o o d as ind efi -
nite growt h. In the eight e e n t h cent ury , a cert ain con t e m p t for
childhoo d took hold, which wen t han d in han d with cont e m p t
for origins and beginni ng s, which are always reg ar d e d as in -
ferior.
The conc ep t of progr e s s implies an idolatry of the novu m :
every innov ation is a priori bet t e r simply beca u s e it is new.
This thirst for novelty—sys t e m a t i c ally eq ua t e d with the bett er
—quickly beca m e one of mod er ni ty’s obse s si o ns . In art, it led
to the conc e pt of the “avan t- garde ” (which also has its coun -
terp ar t s in politics).
From then on, the theory of progr e s s poss e s s e d all its com -
Benoist, “A Brief History of the Idea of Progre s s” 11

pone n t s . Turgot, in 1750, then Cond orce t , form ul at e d it sim -


ply, as th e conviction th at: “Mankind as a whole is always be -
comin g mor e perfect .” Thus the history of hu m a n it y was see n
as definitively unit ary . This pres er v e d the Christian idea of a
futur e perfe ctio n of hum a ni ty an d the certitu d e that hum a n i -
ty is moving toward s a single end . But Provid en c e was aba n -
done d and repl ac e d by hum a n reas o n. From then on, univer -
salis m was bas e d on reaso n conceive d as “on e and entir e in
each individu al,” regar dl e s s of cont ext and particul arity.
Man was likewise conceive d not just as a bein g of unce a s -
ingly ren ew e d desire s and need s , but also as an infinitely per -
fectible being. A new ant hr o p olo gy mak e s ma n a tabula rasa ,
a blank slat e at birth, or allott s him an abs tr a c t “nat u r e” en -
tirely dissociat e d from his concr e t e exist en c e . Hum an diversi -
ty, whet h er individual or collectiv e, is regar d e d as contin ge n t
and com pl et ely m allea bl e by edu c at io n an d “enviro nm e n t .”
The conce p t of artifice beco m e s centr al to and syno ny m o u s
with refine d culture. Man realizes his hum a n it y—“civilizes”
hims elf—only by opposi ng nat ur e and freeing hims elf from it.
Thus hum a nit y has to be free d from every t hi n g that can
block the irresistibl e forwar d march of prog re s s : “prejudic es ,”
“sup er s ti tions, ” the “weight of the past.” This touche s, indi -
rectly, on the justification of the Terror during th e French
Revolutio n : if progre s s is hum a ni t y’s nec e s s a r y aim, who ev er
oppo s e s progr e s s can justifiably be killed; whoev er is op -
pos ed to hu m a ni t y’s progr e s s can justifiably be place d out -
sid e hum a nit y and declar e d an “ene m y of m an ki nd” (hen c e
the difficulty in reconciling the two Kantian ass er tio ns of
equ al dignity and hum a n prog r es s). Modern totalitaria nis m s
(Soviet Com m u ni s m , National Socialism ) gen er alize d this idea
that ther e are “exc es s m en” whos e very exist e n c e preve n t s
the adve n t of a bett e r world.
This rejection of “nat ur e” and the “past ” is freq ue n tl y rep -
res en t e d as syno ny m o u s with liber ati on from all det er mi ni s m .
But in fact, det er mi n a ti on by the pas t is repl ace d by det e r mi -
natio n by the futur e: it is the “point of history.” 1
The opti mis m inher en t in the theo ry of progre s s is prom p t -
ly ext e n d e d to all dom ain s: to society and to m an. The reign
1
I hav e transl a t e d “sens ” here as “point” to pres e rv e wha t appe a r s to
be a felicitous am biguity of the Frenc h: “Sens ” m ay be transla t e d both as
“direc tion” and as “m e a ni ng.” “Point” can have both sens e s as well (e.g.,
“end point,” “the point of the story”).—GJ.
12 The Occiden t al Quarterly , vol. 8, no. 1, Spring 2008

of reas o n is supp o s e d to lead to a societ y that is bot h tran s -


par en t and peac ef ul. Suppos e dl y adv a nt a g e o u s for all par -
ties, Mont es q ui eu’s “gen tl e com m e r c e ” is sup po s e d grad u ally
to elimin at e the “irration al” caus e s of conflict and repl ace it
with com m e r ci al exch a n g e . Hence th e abbo t of Saint- Pierre
anno u n c e d , well before Kant, a “projec t of per p e t u al peac e ,”
which Rouss e a u criticized hars hly. Condorc e t propos e d to ra -
tionally improve lang u a g e and spelling. Morality itself was
supp os e d to display th e char a ct eri stics of a scien c e. Educa -
tion aim e d at accus t o mi n g childr en to rid the m s e lv e s of “prej -
udices,” the source of all social evil, an d use their own rea -
son.
Thus hum a ni ty’s march towar d s hap pi n e s s was inter pr e t e d
as th e culmina tion of mor al happi n e s s . The men of the En -
light en m e n t believe d that, since m an in the futur e will act in
an alway s more “enlight e n e d ” m an n er , rea so n will continu al -
ly improv e, and hu m a n i ty will beco m e mor ally bet t e r. Thus
progr e s s , far from affecting only the ext ern al fram ew o rk of
exist e n c e, will transfor m man hims elf. Progr es s in one do -
m ain is nece s s a rily reflect e d in all oth er s. Materi al progr e s s
leads to mor al progr es s.
On the political plan e, the theo ry of progr e s s was very
quickly asso cia t e d with an anti- political ani m us. Nev ert h el es s ,
the th eorist s of progre s s have an am bi g uo us view of th e
stat e . On the one hand , the stat e limits th e auton o m y of th e
econ o m y, regar d e d as the sph er e of “freed o m ” and ration al
action par exc ellenc e : William Godwin say s th at gover n m e n t s
by their nat ur e creat e obst a cl e s to the nat ur al prop e n si t y of
m an to go forwar d. On th e other han d , in the contr act a ri a n
tradition inaugur a t e d by Hobbe s , the stat e allows man to es -
cap e the const r ai nt s sp ecific to th e “stat e of nat ur e .” Thus
the st at e is simult a n e o u sl y an obst acl e and an engin e of
progr e s s .
The mo st com m o n view is that politics itself mu st beco m e
ration al. Political actio n must ceas e being an art, gover n e d by
the principle of pru de n c e, and beco m e a scienc e , gov ern e d
by the principle of rea so n. As with th e univ ers e, soci et y can
be viewed as a machi ne , in which individ uals are th e cogs.
Hence it must be man a g e d ratio n ally, accor di ng to principles
as regul ar as those obse rv e d in physics. The sover eign mu st
be a mech a ni c overs e ei n g the evolution of “social phy sics”
towar d s “the great e s t public utility.” This conce p tion inspired
Benoist, “A Brief History of the Idea of Progre s s” 13

tech no c r a cy an d the administr a tiv e and m an a g e ri al conce p -


tion of politics of a Saint- Simon or a Com t e.
A particularly import a n t ques tio n is whet h e r progr es s is in -
definit e or leads to a final st ag e. This ter mi n u s would either
be an abs olut e innovation or a mor e “perf ec t” restitutio n of
an original or form er stat e: Heg elian synt h e sis , the resto r a -
tion of primitive Com m u nis m by classl es s society (Marx), th e
end of history (Franci s Fukuy a m a ) , etc. One mu st also ask if
the final goal—as su m i n g ther e is only one—ca n be known in
adv a n c e . To what end do es progr e s s lead, insofar as it lead s
to so m e t hi n g other tha n itself?
Liberal s tend to believ e in an indefinit e progr e s s, an un en d -
ing improv e m e n t of the hum a n con dition, wher e a s socialist s
assign man a well- defined happy end . The latter attitud e mix -
es progr e s sivis m and utopi anis m : perp e t u al ch an g e lead s to
a st atio na ry st at e; historical mov e m e n t is posit ed only as a
m e a n s to envisa g e its end. The liberal attitu d e is not, howev -
er, more realistic. For, on th e one han d, if ma n is moving to -
wards perfe ctio n, then, to the ext en t th at he achiev e s it, he
must stop perfecting hims elf. If, on the oth er han d, ther e is
no recog niz abl e goal of pro gr es s, how can one spe ak of
progr e s s at all? Only by recog nizin g a given goal can we say
that a new stat e repr es e n t s an adv an c e over an earlier one.
Another equally import a nt ques tion : Is progr e s s an uncon -
trolled force that acts on its own, or mus t m en interv e n e to
accel er a t e it or rem ov e impedi m e n t s ? Is progr e s s , moreov e r ,
reg ul ar and continu ou s, or does it imply abr up t qualit ativ e
jump s and ruptur e s ? Can one accel er a t e progr e s s while inter -
vening in its cour se , or, in doing so, does on e risk delayin g its
com pl e ti on ? Here agai n liber als, believin g in the “invisible
han d” and “laisse z- faire ,” differ from socialists, who are more
volunt a ris t, if not revolution ar y.

***
In the ninet e e n t h cent ury, th e th eory of progr e s s reach e d
its apo ge e in the West. It was, howev e r, reform ul at e d in a dif -
ferent climat e, m arke d by industri al mod e r niza tion , scien ti s -
tic positivis m, evolutionis m , an d the appe a r a n c e of th e grea t
historicist theori es.
The stres s was hencefor th put more on science than on rea -
son, in the philosophic al sens e of the term. The hope for a
14 The Occiden t al Quarterly , vol. 8, no. 1, Spring 2008

“scientific” organization of hum a ni ty and the scientific control


of all social pheno m e n a bec a m e wides pr e a d. This the m e was
tireles sly revisit ed by Fourier, with his Phalan st er y ; by Saint- Si-
mon, with his technocr atic principles; by August e Comt e, with
his Positivist Catechis m and his “religion of progre ss .”
At the sa m e time, the term s “progr es s” an d “civilization”
tend e d to beco m e synony m o u s . The idea of progr e s s was
used to legitim a t e colonizatio n, sup po s e d ly to spr ea d th e
ben efits of “civilization” everywh er e in the world
The conc e p t of progr e s s was also refor m ul a t e d in light of
Darwinian evolutionis m . The evolution of life itself was rein -
terpr e t e d in term s of progr e s s , particul arly by Herb ert
Spen c er , who defin ed progr e s s as the evolution from simple
to com ple x, hom o g e n e o u s to het er o g e n e o u s . Indee d , th e
char ac t e r of progr es s appr e ci a bly chan g e d . Henc efo rt h, the
Enlight e n m e n t’ s mech a ni c al mo d el was co m bi n e d with a bio -
logical orga nicis m , as its vaunt e d pacifism gav e way to a de -
fens e of the “strug gl e for life.” Progre s s result e d from the se -
lection of the “fittes t ” (“th e best”), in a gen er alized vision of
com p et i tion. This reint er pr e t a t i on reinforce d West er n imperi -
alism: beca u s e it was “mo st evolve d,” the civilizatio n of the
West was also nece s s a rily the best .
Thus West er n civilization was the high point of social evolu -
tion. The history of hum a ni t y was divided into succe s si v e
“sta g e s ,” marking the various ste p s of its “progr e s s .” The dis -
persion of various cultur es in spac e was tran s p o s e d into tim e:
“primitiv e” societie s gave West er n e r s an imag e of their own
past (they were “con t e m p or a r y anc e s t or s”), while the West
would give the m an image of their futur e. Condorce t had al -
ready clai m ed hu m a nit y had pass e d thro u gh ten succe s siv e
stag e s . Hegel, Comt e, Marx, Freud, etc., propos ed analog ou s
sche m e s , going from “supers titiou s faith” to “science,” the
“theological” era to the “scien tific” one, the “primitive” or
“m agic al” men t ality to the “civilized” men t ality and the uni -
versal reign of reason.
Combine d with scientistic positivism , which com pl et ely per -
vad e d ant h ro pology and nourish e d the illusion that one can
m e a s u r e the value of cultur es with precision , this theor y gave
rise to racis m , which perc eive d tradition al civilizations as ei -
ther per m a n e n tl y inferior to or tem p o r a rily behind the West
(th e “civilizing mission ” of the colonial power s consist e d in
m aking the m catch up), and post ul at e d a univers al criterion,
Benoist, “A Brief History of the Idea of Progre s s” 15

an overar chi n g para dig m , th at m ade it possibl e to rank cul -


tures an d peopl es in a hierar ch y. Racis m was thu s directly
linked to the univer s alis m of progr e s s , which alre ad y con -
ceale d an uncon sciou s or mask e d et hn o c e n t ri s m .
I will not deal her e with th e criticis m of the idea of
progr e s s , which, in moder n time s, begins with Rouss e a u , or
with the innum e r a bl e theori es of declin e or deca d e n c e that
on e could oppos e to it. I shall not e only that th e latt er often
(but not always) repr e s e n t the nega tiv e dou bl e, the mirror
imag e, of the theory of progr e s s . The idea of a nec es s a r y
mov e m e n t of history is pres er v e d , but from the rever s e d
point of view: history is inter pr e t e d not as const a n t progr e s -
sion but as inevit a bl e regre s sio n (spe cific or gene r alize d). In
fact, a tend e n c y toward s declin e or deca d e n c e ap pe a r s as
unverifiabl e as one toward s progr e s s .

***
For at leas t twenty year s, books on the disillusions of
progr e s s have proliferat e d . Cert ain aut h or s hav e gon e so far
as to say progr e s s is nothing mor e than a “de ad idea”
(William Pfaff). Reality is undo u b t e dl y more nuan c e d. The the -
ory of progr e s s is seriously que sti o ne d today, but th er e is no
doub t that it lives on in variou s form s.
The tot alit aria nis m s of the twenti e t h cent ury an d the two
World Wars have obviously sapp e d the optimis m of th e two
previous cent u ri e s. The very disillusio ns that das h e d revolu -
tionary hopes have foster e d th e idea that cont e m p o r a r y soci -
ety— spiritually poor and m ea ni n gl e s s thoug h it m ay be—is
none t h el e s s the only one possibl e: social life is incre a si n gly
infus ed with fat alism . The futur e, which now see m s unfor e -
see a b l e, inspire s more fears than hop e s . A dee p e n i n g crisis
see m s mor e likely than a “bett er tom orr ow.”
The idea of unitary progr e s s is bat t e r e d and brok en. No
on e believes any longer that mat e ri al progr e s s make s m an
bet t er, or that progr e s s regist e r e d in one dom ain is au to m a t i -
cally reflect e d in th e rest . In th e “risk societ y” (Ulrich Beck),
m at erial progr es s itself see m s am biv al e nt . It is gran t e d that ,
alon g with its adva n t a g e s , ther e are cost s. It is quite evid e n t
that unplann e d urba niz ation multiplies social pat h ologi es and
that indust ri al mod e r niza tio n res ults in an unpr ec e d e n t e d
degr a d a t io n of the nat u r al fram ew o rk of life. The m as sive de -
16 The Occiden t al Quarterly , vol. 8, no. 1, Spring 2008

struction of the environ m e n t gav e rise to ecolo gical move -


m en t s, which were am on g the first to deno un c e the “illusions
of progr e s s .” The develo p m e n t of tech n o s ci en c e also forceful -
ly rais es th e ques tion of purpos e . The devel op m e n t of scien c e
is no longer percei ve d as nece s s a rily contribu tin g to the hap -
pines s of hum a n it y: knowled g e itself, as one sees in th e de -
bat e on biotec hn ol ogie s, is reg ar d e d as pot en ti ally thre a t e n -
ing. Increa singl y large sections of the pop ulation now under -
stan d that “mor e” is not synony m o u s with “bet t e r.” We distin -
guish betw e e n having and being, mat eri al hap pin e s s and
hap pin es s in gen er al.
The the m e of progr e s s never t h el e s s rem ai n s preg n a n t , if
only as a sym bol. The political class contin ue s to mus t e r the
“forces of progre s s” ag ains t the “m en of the past ” an d to
thu nd e r ag ai nst “m edi ev al obscur a n t i s m ” (or the “ma nn e r s
of anot h e r age”). In public discour s e , th e word “progr e s s ” still
ret ains a larg ely positive reson a n c e .
The orient a tion towar ds the futur e also rem ai ns domi na nt .
Even if one ad mit s that the future is filled with me n a ci n g un -
cert ai nti e s, we still exp e ct that, logically, thin gs should im -
prove overall. Swept along by the rise of cutting edg e tech -
nologies and medi a m anipul at e d fashion s, the cult of nov elty
rem ai ns strong e r tha n ever. Peopl e also contin ue to believe
that m an’s “freedo m ” increa s e s to the ext en t that he is up -
root e d fro m organic ties and inherit ed traditions. The reignin g
individualism , alon g with a West e r n et hn o c e n t ri s m— which le -
gitim a t e s itself with th e ideology of hum a n rights—d e s t r u c -
tures the family, dissolve s social bon d s, and discre dit s tradi -
tional Third World societi es, wher e econ o m y is still em b e d d e d
in soci et y and wher e individuals and com m u ni tie s are still in -
terd e p e n d e n t .
But ab ov e all, the theory of progr es s persist s in its produ c -
tivist versio n. It nourish e s the idea that indefinit e growt h is
both norm al and desira bl e, and that a bet t er futur e dep e n d s
upon an ev er- incre a sin g volu m e of produc e d good s , an idea
that favors the globalizatio n of trade . This idea also inspires
the ideology of “dev elop m e n t , ” which still views Third World
societi es as (econ o mi c ally) lagging behind the West and ex -
alts th e Weste r n mod el of pro duc ti o n an d con su m p ti o n th e
desti ny of all hum a nit y. This ideolo gy of dev el o p m e n t was
form ula t e d perfectly in 1960 by Walt Rostow, who enu m e r a t -
ed the “stag e s ” that every society on the planet must travers e
Benoist, “A Brief History of the Idea of Progre s s” 17

to reach the age of consu m e ris m and com m er cial capitalis m.


As Serge Latouch e, Gilbert Rist, and others show, the theory of
dev elop m e n t is ultimat ely just a faith. As long as this faith per -
sists, so too will the ideology of progre s s.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy