Post Modern Theory
Post Modern Theory
Postmodern Theory
and Progressive
Politics
TOWA RD A N EW HUMA N IS M
Series Editor
Michael J. Thompson
William Paterson University
New York, NY, USA
This series offers books that seek to explore new perspectives in social and
political criticism. Seeing contemporary academic political theory and
philosophy as largely dominated by hyper-academic and overly-technical
debates, the books in this series seek to connect the politically engaged
traditions of philosophical thought with contemporary social and political
life. The idea of philosophy emphasized here is not as an aloof enterprise,
but rather a publicly-oriented activity that emphasizes rational reflection as
well as informed praxis.
Postmodern Theory
and Progressive
Politics
Toward a New Humanism
Thomas de Zengotita
New York University
New York, NY, USA
This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature
Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
“Philosophy is an age grasped in thought.”
—Hegel
Series Editor’s Foreword
vii
viii SERIES EDITOR’S FOREWORD
a new and more textured humanism and study the human condition with
more nuance, more sensitivity. Perhaps then we will be able to start anew,
as he asks us to, and create a more humane, and more just cultural and
political sensibility. And that, given the nature of our times, will be wel-
come indeed.
Part II Modernism 55
xi
xii CONTENTS
4 Phenomenology 91
References 100
7 Critical Theory 127
7.1 Theodore Adorno (1903–1969) 127
References 135
9 Texts and Bodies 181
9.1 Roland Barthes (1915–1980) 183
9.2 Jacques Derrida (1930–2004) 204
9.3 Gilles Deleuze (1925–1995) 237
9.4 Michel Foucault (1926–1984)282
References 306
CONTENTS
xiii
References 359
Author Index 377
Subject Index 385
List of Figures
xv
CHAPTER 1
This book is for people who care about the humanities and progressive poli-
tics and want to understand the lasting influence upon them of postmod-
ernism as it was expressed in the academic culture wars of the late twentieth
century. What to make now of those furious debates over the canon versus
multiculturalism, relativism, deconstruction, on and on? These are espe-
cially urgent questions for students in humanistic disciplines today, thrown
as they have been into settings shaped by those battles and obliged to
make their way as best they can through the debris left in their wake.
The end of postmodernism has been announced many times—but one
could always wonder if the authors were stating a fact or trying to pull the
plug. In recent years there has been a shift in tone. Looking ahead to the 2012
MLA conference, Stanley Fish reported that “topics that in previous years
dominated the meeting and identified the avant-garde—postmodernism,
deconstruction, post-colonialism, neo-colonialism, racism, racialism, femi-
nism, Queer Theory, theory in general”—were “absent or sparsely repre-
sented” in the schedule (Fish 2011). And Warren Breckman, in an essay about
French theory as an “historical object,” said that, while “there is a widespread
consensus that theory’s expiry date has already arrived,” it seems that “ends
are at least as complicated as beginnings” (Breckman 2010, 346). That com-
plexity reflects the range of influence of “theory.” In some academic settings
its discourses still flourish; in others, they have been displaced, squelched,
mocked. But recent innovations in self-reference through personal gender
pronouns (PGPs), millions of contributions to #MeToo, and continuing
1
I owe much of my understanding of modern intellectual history to Trilling and others in
that cohort. Without them, this book could not have been written. But it is worth noting at
the outset how critics of postmodernism have simply assumed that they represent the tradi-
tion of Western thought, of Western philosophy in particular. If the focus is on method, on
the value of rationality—logic, clarity—that makes sense. But if the focus is on substance,
their claim looks weaker. What did Socrates ultimately care about? His famous method, his
logic—or the meaning of life in the face of death?
INTRODUCTION: PHENOMENOLOGY, IDEAL TYPES, NARRATIVE 3
teachers and topics that happened to catch their interest. Meanwhile the
technology juggernaut assimilates everything and rolls on, offering academ-
ics spectacular solutions to “how” problems and pushing the humanities
ever further to the margins of the curriculum, unable to contend with a
question only the humanities can ask seriously: what next? What next for the
meaning of being human in a world growing more incomprehensible and
vulnerable every day? There presently exists no account of our intellectual
history designed to provide that orientation. This book will supply that lack.
In After Babel (1975), George Steiner chose 1870 to mark the onset of
the radical disruption of artistic intelligibility we know as “modernism.”
That disruption resonated with a crisis in comprehensibility across the cul-
tural spectrum, from the Freudian unconscious to the uncertainty principle
in physics. No surprise, then, to find the term “postmodern” first used in
1870 to describe painting styles more avant-garde than impressionism. In
the twentieth century, historians like Arnold Toynbee used it to mark “the
next age” on their big picture timelines before it was picked up and dissemi-
nated by critics like Susan Sontag, again referencing disorienting innova-
tions in the arts and architecture. But this book focuses on a set of intellectual
strategies and a certain style that shaped academic postmodernism in anglo-
phone universities since the 1960s, also with disruptive consequences.
Postmodernism in this sense is derived largely from a particular group
of French thinkers and the radical artists and German philosophers who
inspired them—though, of course, as Fredric Jameson (1991) and David
Harvey (1990) have demonstrated, shifts in modes of production from
bricks and mortar assembly-line Fordism to instantaneous digital transac-
tions in cyberspace ultimately conditioned the emergence of the postmod-
ern in general, in the academy and in society at large. But this book is not
principally concerned with technological causes. Its focus is on their effects,
on culture, on consciousness—and especially on ethics and conceptions of
politics. It tries to provide a straightforward and balanced account of certain
movements of thought and value, from their origins to the present moment.
In that way, it hopes to exemplify the core values of the humanism it is
calling for. It shows that, while absolute objectivity may be beyond our
finite powers, a good faith effort to be fair is not. We expect no more of
ourselves in our lives and should ask no less of ourselves in our work.
This book tells a familiar (too familiar?) story of modernity. But it does
so in a particular way, to a particular purpose—highlighting those aspects
of thought and culture that conditioned the emergence of “modernism”
and “postmodernism.” The first chapter, for example, aims to show how
and why early modern thinkers were so captivated by the physical sciences.
4 T. DE ZENGOTITA
1.1 Interlude
One of my earliest memories: the front lawn of my Grandfather’s house in
a small Massachusetts town. It is the 4th of July and the parade is under-
way, people gathered along the street to watch—all ages, some on lawn
chairs, some standing, a few little flags waving, a smattering of applause
now and then. It is 1949, maybe 1950. The veterans appear, rounding the
corner, and the applause thickens and lifts as they draw near. The ranks are
ordered in accordance with how recently the veterans served—the still
youthful and most numerous World War II servicemen bringing up the
rear. I was struck at once by a lone figure, an ancient specter, all bone and
8 T. DE ZENGOTITA
parchment skin and blue veins, being pushed along in a wheelchair, alone
at the head of the column. My mother was standing behind me and I
remember her leaning over me, her face next to mine, her hair brushing
my cheek, pointing out in front of us discreetly, as was only proper, whis-
pering: “See him? He was a drummer boy in the Civil War.”
So here I am, in 2017, recalling an encounter with a man who could
have stood at a 4th of July parade in 1856 and seen an aged veteran of the
American Revolution go by, a man who, in his turn, might have met
Thomas Jefferson or known someone—an officer of rank, perhaps—who
sat down with Edmund Burke in London to discuss the latest news from
Paris in 1789. Or 1793. Only two more such passages and we are in the
company of Descartes and Galileo, present at the creation of modern
thought, or so the story goes. And it is the story that most concerns us
here—the myth, if you like, of modernity’s making. And in that mythol-
ogy, the genesis moment was not that long ago.
It seems more distant because so much has happened. More changes
have been wrought on the face of the planet in the last 400 years than in
the 50,000 years preceding. The changes have been so massive and intri-
cate that our sense of the time it took expands in proportion—as if to
make room, as if to fit it all in. But it was not that long ago. We moderns—
just a few generations, really—have been caught up in an explosion of
events and developments we couldn’t possibly comprehend with any
certainty. Today, looking back, one is perhaps most struck by how willing
so many of our intellectual ancestors were to assume that they could.
References
Breckman, Warren. 2010. Times of Theory: On Writing the History of French
Theory. Journal of the History of Ideas 71 (3): 339–361.
Fish, Stanley. 2011. The Old Order Changeth. The New York Times, December 26.
Harvey, David. 1990. The Condition of Postmodernity: An Enquiry into the Origins
of Cultural Change. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hegel, Georg W. F. (1807) 1967. The Phenomenology of Mind. New York: Harper
Torchbooks.
Jameson, Fredric. 1991. Postmodernism, or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism.
Durham: Duke University Press.
Marx, Karl. (1845) 1998. The German Ideology: Including Theses on Feuerbach and
Introduction to the Critique of Political Economy. Amherst: Prometheus Books.
Ryle, Gilbert. (1949) 1984. The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Steiner, George. 1975. After Babel: Aspects of Language and Translation.
New York: Oxford University Press.
PART I
Essential Background
CHAPTER 2
NATURE (the art whereby God hath made and governs the world) is by the
art of man … imitated [so] it can make an artificial animal. (Thomas Hobbes
1651)
things and for people. Falling apples were, in some way, obedient and tyran-
nical monarchs unruly. From a place apart, the early modern mind assigned
itself the task of learning those laws and applying them, technologically,
economically, politically, and personally. Two texts will recall to us the basic
architecture: Descartes’ Discourse on Method ([1637] 1968) and Galileo’s
“Two Kinds of Properties” ([1623b] 1970).
2
For Descartes’ contemporaries, the implicit contrast was with books of traditional phi-
losophy and theology. Derrida will make much of this image in “The End of the Book and
the Beginning of Writing” (see Chap. 9). A world authored as a whole and readable as a
whole is assumed by this metaphor of containment—and poststructuralist “writing” tried to
disrupt both its terms.
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 15
could pass such a test? Descartes will have to find out and his rhetorical
stance summons us to follow him, to take that risk for ourselves—each
reader with the right stuff must take the plunge alone. That is the tease
and the challenge of the fourth part of the Discourse.
As it turned out, one entity survived the massacre: Descartes himself or,
more precisely, his mind. And so it would be for everyone following the
path laid out by this self-help book that secured the essence of
modernity.
For the process of epistemological self-examination soon boils down to
this: how do I know that I am holding this book in my hand right now?
How do I know I’m not dreaming or hallucinating? I’ve had dreams where
I dreamt I woke up and thought I was awake—until later, when I really
woke up. At least, I think I did.3 And we have all seen psychotics on the
street talking to their imaginary friends, hearing voices—it’s at least con-
ceivable that I am one of them right now, hallucinating the book in my
hand (Derrida and Foucault will fall out over Descartes’ view of insanity,
see Chap. 9). So that gives me some reason to doubt the truth of this expe-
rience. And that’s all the method requires.
Now I have to assume that there is no book in my hand and then look
around and see if there’s anything left that I just cannot doubt.
Right away I realize that what applies to the book applies to everything
I experience through my senses. On these grounds, I can doubt every-
thing I see, touch, smell—including my own body, for the same reason I
can doubt the book. Maybe I don’t even have a hand. I might be a brain
in a vat wired up to some supercomputer that puts me in The Matrix.
People with an amputated limb can feel it itching, after all.
But then I suddenly realize that, while I can doubt the physical reality
of all these things I am experiencing, I cannot doubt the experiences per
se. I can doubt that I have a real book in a real hand, but I can’t doubt that
I am having book-in-my-hand sensations of various kinds—tactile, visual.
If I try to doubt that I just add effort-to-doubt sensations to the book-in-
my-hand sensations—and so on, for the entirety of my subjective experi-
ence at any given instant. All my thoughts and feelings, sensations, ideas,
memories, whatever—I can doubt that they correspond to anything real,
but I can’t doubt that I’m having them, the pure experiences themselves,
3
The autumn of 1619 found Descartes, filled with “enthusiasm,” engaged in fervent med-
itations as he conceived his life’s work. On 19 November, he had a dream so vivid and so
weighted with significance that he took it for a supernaturally inspired vision—of which he
had had premonitions before going to sleep. Auguste Comte once lamented that modern
philosophy originated in this “cerebral episode” (Maritain 1944).
18 T. DE ZENGOTITA
4
The Meditations ([1641] 1968) develops the argument in detail—in Latin, for a scholarly
audience. There Descartes argues that not only empirical knowledge but logical/mathemati-
cal knowledge is subject to doubt, thanks to conceivable interventions by an evil demon.
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 19
promise knows no bounds. In the sixth part, Descartes famously called for
“a practical philosophy” which would allow us to know the workings of
nature’s bodies “as distinctly as we know the various crafts of our artisans”
and so “apply them in the same way to all the uses to which they are
adapted and thus render ourselves the lords and possessors of nature.” In
the very last paragraph, he commits the remainder of his life to the study
of medicine and hints at a cure for death.
Shades of Larry Page and Ray Kurzweil.
5
“Consciousness” would be a reference to what Freud exposed as a mere surface and
“convention” to what both Marx and Nietzsche exposed as mere surface.
20 T. DE ZENGOTITA
6
“Suppose I pass my hand, first over a marble statue, then over a living man … the primary
qualities of motion and contact will similarly affect the two objects, and we would use identi-
cal language to describe this in each case. But the living body … will feel itself affected … [for
example] ‘tickling.’ This latter affection is altogether our own, and is not at all a property of
the hand.” (Galileo [1623b] 1970, 8).
7
Said Galileo: “Philosophy [physics] is written in this grand book—I mean the universe—
which stands continually open to our gaze, but it cannot be understood unless one first learns
to comprehend the language and interpret the characters in which it is written. It is written
in the language of mathematics.” ([1623a] 1957, 237–238). Compare Descartes’ “book of
the world.”
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 21
They had no sense of the eons of time it took for the universe to take shape
since the big bang, no idea that billions of years had passed since the for-
mation of our solar system. No fossil record to consult. No dinosaurs to
imagine. No knowledge of genes. No speciation, no natural selection—
above all, no evolution. The great panorama of life, the stunning diversity
of its forms and adaptations, the intricacies of anatomy and physiology—
all this was immediately apparent and deeply appreciated, but the unexam-
ined assumption was that all of it had always been there more or less as it
now appeared, ever since it appeared in the first place.
The (almost) inevitable conclusion was that an intelligent Maker was
responsible for the order of the universe—especially the intricate biologi-
cal machinery. To look at nature, at all the inorganic bodies dancing to
Newtonian measures and all the organic bodies sensing, respirating, loco-
moting, ingesting, digesting, reproducing—to look at all that and not
apprehend design would be like coming across an array of pebbles on a
beach precisely spelling out some message and perceiving it as a random
effect of surf and tide. “Let there be light” was beautiful poetry, but
F = MA was the word of the modern God.
But with organisms a curious difference prevailed: a healthy body was
obviously in conformity with a designer’s intentions. But one also encoun-
tered mortality and disease. Here, for some reason, was a sort of disobedi-
ence, a malfunctioning. Why that should be so was the subject of much
debate, but almost no one doubted the framework of interpretation. Modern
medicine was founded on the metaphor of repairing such malfunctions.
And so, when early moderns looked upon human history—the carnage,
absurd superstitions, institutionalized barbarities—the conclusion was
inevitable. Here was a disease of another order, a malfunctioning of
another kind. Again, there was much debate over why this should be so,
but the framework of interpretation remained. And the question became:
what were the Maker’s designs for His human creatures at the social level,
what were those natural laws, and how could His creatures cure the dis-
eases of history in accordance with them?
Locke went on to claim that human labor gave value to the “almost
worthless” raw materials of nature by transforming them into “useful goods.”
Title belonged, under natural law, to those whose labor gave the value.
At the same time, in the context of the Essay Concerning Human
Understanding ([1689] 1996), with practical politics far from his thoughts,
Locke articulated the first principle of modern empiricism when he com-
pared the human mind to a tabula rasa—a blank slate when it left the
“hand of nature” (I, ii, 15; II, i,2).
Consider those claims together. Locke, in his piety, never saw the impli-
cations, but he was announcing to generations of striving moderns the
discovery of an uncultivated and unimproved piece of raw material of a
new order. And those rational and industrious human analogues of the
Divine Maker were quick to seize the opportunity. The abstracted modern
subject—locus now of all meaning and value—took control of raw mate-
rial, of objects as “they left the hand of nature,” and imposed upon them
the designs of human makers. This massive, intricate process constituted
the modern form of life. Implicit in the whole situation was this question:
whose “workmanship” would humanity be? The project of progress, in its
myriad actuality, would supply the answer.8
The basic plot of modernity’s story has now been outlined. The under-
lying themes—the transformation of nature and society by modern sci-
ence, technology and politics, the displacement of God—figure largely in
many accounts of modernity, of course. But this particular telling brings
out the fact that the Hegelian/Marxist version was continuous with its
predecessor; it took Locke’s labor theory of value and reassigned it from
an individual subject to a social one. The complexities of dialectical mate-
rialism and the passions of politics have obscured that essential commonal-
ity—which marks both Locke and Marx as fundamentally modern and
sheds much light on that “mirroring” of structures of capitalist domina-
tion by Communist institutions that so troubled left intellectuals during
the 1950s and 1960s, especially in France (see Chaps. 8, 9).
8
Jacques Barzun once remarked the fact that “the appliance works” was “the great argu-
ment that has redirected the western mind” (1964, 19). Barzun had technological appliances
in mind, but his point is only deepened when extended to include modern self-made persons
and their social arrangements. And it never applied more aptly than it does today.
26 T. DE ZENGOTITA
of salon life (Elias 1978). Manners were also immediate proof of the
improvability of human nature. Hence, Gay’s remark: “For the spokesman
of the Enlightenment, progress was an experience before it became a pro-
gram” (Gay 1969, 56).
Systematic differences distinguished national modes of Enlightenment
in the eighteenth century and those differences conditioned the various
ways modernity would eventually seek to overcome itself when the post-
modern moment came. Objective conditions of life in different places had
profound effects. But such conditions can be rightly understood only if
this fact is grasped to begin with: for the first time in Western history, a
range of “life-styles” (just the right phrase) was distributed across divisions
of nationality and class. In the eighteenth century, a Scottish burgher of
grave Presbyterian mien might see his son become a dancing school fop
while a French noble of the sword might see his son, clad in cloth, on his
knees in a tenant’s field, taking soil samples.
Historians describe large-scale trends in Western Europe in this period:
a population explosion, an uprooting and emigration of peoples, incipient
industrialization, world trade and colonization, new modes of transport
and communication under the control of a rising bourgeoisie, and a
declining rural order transformed by new agricultural techniques and asso-
ciated political developments. All these forces, which would culminate in
the French and the Industrial revolutions, together shaped the eighteenth
century—but at different paces, differently emphasized, according to
national and local circumstances (Braudel 1982). Eric Hobsbawm’s classic
account of France and Great Britain during the “dual revolutions” of the
nineteenth century is rooted in developments already well under way in
the eighteenth century ([1962] 1996). Great Britain was his exemplar of
modernity’s economic aspect and France of its politics, because “England
had already had both its religious reformation and its bourgeois revolu-
tion… whereas in France the forms and privileges of feudalism and medi-
eval religion had survived almost intact into the heart of the Enlightenment”
(Willey 1950, 120). From this fundamental difference flow several conse-
quences that shaped the Enlightenment in distinctive ways.
In France, sumptuary laws prohibited the bourgeoisie, no matter how
wealthy, from adorning themselves as lavishly as nobles, no matter how
impoverished. Other laws prohibited nobles, no matter how equipped or
inclined, from trade or manufacture. The Catholic Church retained its
power over educational and medical institutions, and essential social rituals
were still at its disposal, even after the revolution. Before the revolution,
28 T. DE ZENGOTITA
9
Not that the radically unorthodox were always welcome in Great Britain. Samuel Johnson
stalked out of a dinner party when David Hume joined the company, and conservative forces
in the Presbyterian Church were able to deny Hume a university chair. But Hume had friends
in that church who prevented his ex-communication and defended his right to his opinions.
In a nutshell, this contrast, known as the “Great Infidel” in Great Britain, was lionized on his
visits to France—but at D’Holbach’s dinners for assorted philosophes, he was cordially chided
for stopping short of atheism. To his hosts, Hume’s principled skepticism was a cop out.
Hume, in turn, was struck by a certain dogmatism in the French radicals—they reminded
him of Churchmen! An irony with a future (Mossner [1954] 1970, 153–163; 475–486).
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 29
The eighteenth century was an age of public fetes, follies, and pastorales
that featured the public as actors and audience, an age of ever-innovating
clubs, salons, and coffee houses, of Richard Sennett’s “public man” before
his fall (1974). It was also an age of zoos and circuses where the sight of
exotic animals made familiar creatures seem less inevitable as the rage for
exotic spices, coffee, chocolate, and tea made familiar tastes seem more
provisional. It was an age of libraries and museums—which were surely also
“public houses” open to consumers of novelty. At the same time, they were
monumental trophy halls that honored public benefactors and the con-
querors of history, geography, and nature whose prizes were there exhib-
ited for those disposed to emulation. It was the age of the gourmet, the
virtuoso, and the dilettante (a term of praise), of the so-called bourgeois
family dramas of Diderot and Lessing, and, of course, the age of the “novel”
itself—forms of art designed to provide the productive classes with reflec-
tions of themselves. Finally, and across the board, it was an age of satire, of
cartoons, of social criticism and self-scrutiny. How else was one to improve?
The Enlightenment’s mission was everywhere evident in European cul-
ture in the eighteenth century. Take, for example, “the most influential
magazine in history,” a “civilizing agent” that spawned imitators across the
world: in Addison’s words, The Spectator would “bring philosophy out of
the closets and libraries, schools and colleges, to dwell in clubs and assem-
blies, at tea tables and in coffeehouses.” It aimed to “polish man’s behavior
and purify his intentions” on the basis of the new natural and moral phi-
losophy. The anonymous voice of the journal (referring to itself as The
Spectator of Mankind representing a Spectator Club) spoke as a “Newton
for the average man,” as a painter of “lyrical portraits” of intricate and
beneficent systems of industry, trade, and technology, as a constant critic of
“frenzy and enthusiasm,” as a satirist of superstition, and as a general arbi-
ter of aesthetic and social taste. And good taste depended above all on the
“agreement of the well-bred” and, according to The Spectator, the well-
bred agreed that the artist should avoid Gothic excess and “take as much
pains in forming his imagination, as a philosopher in cultivating his under-
standing.” The Spectator was dedicated to showing its eager readers, “men
and women with a modicum of learning,” how to form themselves on the
same model (Gay 1969, 27, 52–55, 559–660; Whitney 1965).
The very name of this publication makes the point. The vanguard
had found a public. Self-possession through self-improvement was installed
as a central theme in the modern form of life, although it would take time for
the consequences to emerge on a significant scale. God’s designs were not
30 T. DE ZENGOTITA
replaced overnight. Still, the image of the rude, but improvable, device
had given the idea of progress an irresistible purchase on history. Millions
of people would come to understand and treat themselves and others in
accordance with this theme. Self-possession through self-improvement
was potentially the project of the whole species, already being realized in
the “party of humanity.”10 And as partisans of improvement grew more
numerous, so their visions of it became more various. Out of a sense of
duty, out of satisfaction with their own positions, out of disgust with
unnecessary suffering, out of sheer acquisitive ambition—enlightened
Europeans felt their entitlements extend beyond themselves to embrace
the raw material of the entire globe and all humanity. Upon them
descended the glory, the burden, and the profit of leading it. Economic
and missionary imperialism, abolitionism, public education, and women’s
suffrage were all conceived by the same style of mind.
2.3.2 Romantic Subjectivity
These cultural developments were intricately and ironically related—and
something like a dialectical development is discernible in hindsight. When
Samuel Johnson, for example, traveled to the wastes of Scotland he wanted
to “experience [the] simplicity and wildness” of a “totally different …
system of life.” But he had to content himself with wild landscapes.
Scotland’s ambitious natives received him as civilized hosts, bursting with
civic pride, managers of a booming economy, a united, educated, and
striving people growing daily more enlightened and refined. They refused
to expose the “savage,” “clannish,” “patriarchal family spirit” Johnson
had hoped to see (1958, 92–106). In other contexts, the Scots would find
a residue of virtue in the old ways, but no touring Englishman would be
permitted to judge on so delicate a question.
The French, on the other hand, were inclined to view the English some-
what as the English viewed the Scots. But the French were disposed to a
different kind of tour. The lure was the same, but the means were more
intense and complete psychologically, less strenuous in practice. A “cult of
sensibility,” encouraged by the wave of anglomania that swept through the
salons in the 1750s and 1760s, took shape at the heart of the Enlightenment.
10
Famously represented in Kant’s essay “What is Enlightenment?” ([1784] 1966): “the
few who, after having themselves thrown off the yoke of immaturity, will spread the spirit of
a rational appreciation for both their own worth and for each person’s calling to think for
himself.”
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 31
In his Letters Concerning the English Nation (1734), Voltaire’s praise for
English thought and politics had been hedged by criticism of English taste
and manners. But his old-fashioned Classical standards would soon be
overwhelmed by a fad for all things natural, simple, and sentimental, which
often meant things English (Green 1931, 29–59). But the French were
incubating a more radical Romantic discourse soon to be expressed by the
author of, among other things, the wildly popular novel of natural senti-
ment—La Nouvelle Heloise (by Jean-Jacques Rousseau).
Mme. d’Genlis, who laughs at these affectations, is no less affected than the
rest. Suddenly, someone in the company is heard to say to the young orphan
whom she is exhibiting: “Pamela, show us Heloise,” whereupon Pamela,
loosening her hair, falls on her knees and turns her eyes up to heaven with
an air of inspiration, to the great applause of the assembly. Sensibility became
an institution. (Taine [1867] 1931, 160–162)
The French had been performing for more than a century at the center
of European fashion. They had brought manners to the highest pitch of
refinement. In every social situation, “there was a certain way of walking,
of sitting down, of saluting, of picking up a glove, of holding a fork, of
tendering any article, in fine a complete mimicry, which children had to be
taught at a very early age” (Taine, citing a contemporary memoir, 1931,
158). And, Taine adds, “Not only was the outward factitious, but, again,
the inward; there was a certain prescribed mode of feeling” for every situ-
ation as well. The appeal of nature, emotion, sensibility can only be appre-
ciated against that background. One mistress of the drawing room stage
remarked in her diary: “A genuine sentiment is so rare, that, when I leave
Versailles, I sometimes stand still in the street to see a dog gnaw a bone”
(Taine 1931, 157).
Horace Walpole was a representative English gentleman of the eigh-
teenth century. He resented the idea that English styles were the object of
longings that might also be satisfied by the sight of a dog gnawing a bone.
He would have glowed with pleasure at Rude’s description of him as pos-
sessor, “an unrivaled sense of the social proprieties” (1972, 121). Like
Johnson, Walpole loved to deride Scottish backwardness. At the same
time, he mocked the French fancy for the natural—with their passion for
doing things “A l’Anglaise” in mind, he remarked: “Their next mode will
be ‘A l’Iriquoise” (1972, 152). But fashion was fashion and the French
32 T. DE ZENGOTITA
were still its masters. Walpole built his neo-Gothic estate at Strawberry
Hill under the influence he mocked.
The “cult of sensibility” is itself testimony to the breadth and depth of
proprietorial humanism’s dominion. Rightly associated with an immanent
Romanticism, it was not necessarily opposed to Enlightenment rationality
and pragmatism. The situation of Romanticism at its outset was essentially
similar to its situation in decline a century later—thoroughly domesticated
in ways described by Raymond Williams (1958). It began as one of many
fashions in a fashioned world, hanging together with utilitarian rationality
in the cupboard of the public mind as easily as day and evening dresses in
the cupboard of the boudoir. And that was something hard-core Romantics
would not countenance.
Scholarly efforts to define Romanticism have been legion. History
of ideas distinctions are most familiar. They often come in pairs, to
contrast with the Enlightenment: transcendence versus immanence,
mechanical versus organic, control versus spontaneity, calculation versus
imagination/feeling, society versus community, sincerity versus authen-
ticity, abstract versus concrete, static versus dynamic, and liberty versus
self-determination. Taken together, the traditional polarities point to a
constitutive gesture in the underlying phenomenology. Romantic inten-
tionality is the ongoing effort of the abstracted modern mind to refuse
itself, as abstracted, and so re-fuse itself as embodied in the world. This
dialectic of refusion, an attitude of thought in motion, evokes the gesture
on the wing, as it were—it is more like a pun than a category. Actually,
this pun recalls the Hegelian notion—for what was Hegel’s project if not
the refusion of Absolute Mind? Hegel would repudiate Romanticism’s
sentimental excesses, but he was its ultimate philosopher (Abrams 1971,
67, 173; Taylor 1979, 5–13).
11
Rousseau in particular and Romanticism in general are often rightly associated with soli-
tude, rather than with what I have called “refusion” (see Rousseau’s own Reveries of a
Solitary Walker [1782] 1979). But an alienated spirit, with no authentic social connections,
has no choice but seek solace in that solitude, especially in the company of nature.
34 T. DE ZENGOTITA
That was how Thomas Malthus chose to introduce “An Essay on the
Principle of Population, as it affects the Future Improvement of Society with
remarks on the Speculations of Mr. Godwin, M. Condorcet, and Other
Writers.” In that hugely influential work he argued for the inevitability of
poverty and starvation due to differential reproduction rates in human
populations and food supply. In the paragraph quoted earlier, he framed
his theory with a mocking critique of the Enlightenment faith in human
progress, lampooning its lack of an evidence-based developmental per-
spective and affording a telling glimpse of his own commitment to it.
It is widely known that Darwin’s concept of natural selection was inde-
pendently formulated by Alfred Wallace, but it is not so widely known that
both men were reading Malthus’ essay at the time of their respective
“Ah-hah” moments. A cursory reflection on the concept of natural selec-
tion on the one hand and Malthus’ basic argument on the other makes
that coincidence unsurprising and sets the stage for the great intellectual
12
The “Idea of Progress” has a long history going back to antiquity if the concept is con-
strued broadly enough (Bury 1932; Nisbet 2017)—but the modern idea has been uniquely
ideological, an aspect of popular belief. In the eighteenth century, it took on certain features
that prepared the way for its specifically “evolutionist” form. Robert Turgot, for example,
anticipated the Marquis de Condorcet’s schematic of progress (Manuel 1962). Both posited
a certain direction in history on the grounds that the obvious benefits of rationality (thanks
especially to literacy) would create momentum for human self-cultivation. But, for a trauma-
tized nineteenth century, that just wasn’t enough. A more comprehensive guarantee was
needed and the place of the idea of Providence was open, pre-pared for a secular occupant.
38 T. DE ZENGOTITA
with them. They lived with the consequences of the French and the Industrial
revolutions—and those consequences appeared as a bitter comeuppance to
modernizers who identified with the whole enterprise, now threatened
with disaster. So they felt obligated in a way no traditional authority ever
had. For they were not merely responsible for some time-honored office
they happened to hold. They were responsible for inventing the offices or
radically reforming them—for inventing the social order, the technology,
the economy, the settings of human life. And things were not going well.
The second thing to remember is that this was the last generation of
(more or less) sane moderns who could still hope to comprehend everything.
To Hegel, Comte, and Spencer, it still seemed possible to work through all
the books that mattered, in every department of learning, and master them
all. And then—the crowning achievement—possible also to cast that great
sprawl of material into a systematic whole. No wonder the determination
to face facts, to be empirical, was overwhelmed. The imperatives of such
an aspiration were bound to move these men to reach too far, and hammer
the facts into shapes that would fit their elaborate theoretical receptacles.
When modernists at last decided that there was no telos to be found in
nature, they also gave up on the idea of a comprehensible world. In hindsight
it is obvious: two aspects of the same moment. Without a purposeful narrative
to contain its history, the world was bound to fall apart and lose its meaning.
This section cannot describe the systems of these thinkers in detail. But
the selection of Hegel, Comte, and Spencer permits an overall contrast
between national styles of evolutionist thought while foregrounding what
they had in common. The aim is to highlight elements in those systems
that conditioned the emergence of modernism.
Over the whole scene hovered the mystery of the “forces” of nature in
the absence of a deity—especially life forces and their derivatives on the
social level, including “forces of production” and the like. The challenge
for a contemporary reader is to imagine how compelling this mystery
became for thinkers who could no longer fall back on a general sense, how-
ever vague, that a deity had somehow set the cosmos in motion. What to
make now of gravity, magnetism, electricity? Were they on a continuum
with hunger and lust? With ambition and love?13 What of hysteria, mesmer-
ism, patriotic fervor, aesthetic uplift, ecstasy?14 Most urgently, perhaps, what
13
Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein belongs in this context: a motley of body parts; the light-
ning; “It’s Alive!”
14
Interest in religion actually intensified during the nineteenth century. From Strauss’ Life
of Jesus to James’ Varieties of Religious Experience—here was a force to be reckoned with all
40 T. DE ZENGOTITA
2.4.1 G.W.F. Hegel (1770–1831)
The only thought which Philosophy brings with it to the contemplation of
History, is … that Reason is the Sovereign of the World; that the history of
the world … presents us with a rational process. (Hegel 1837)
All the worth which the human being possesses, all spiritual reality, he pos-
sesses only through the State. … For Truth is the unity of the universal and
subjective will; and the Universal is to be found in the State … in which
Freedom obtains objectivity. (Hegel 1837)
the more seriously as belief in literal validity waned. The philosophes and the men of ’89 had
fatefully underestimated the power of religious emotion.
15
This question in particular haunted the period. The “revolutions” of 1830, 1848, and
1871 were potential reruns of 1793. For all their differences, Hegel, Comte, and Spencer
were united in their opposition to democracy. They feared the “mob.”
16
W.E. Houghton (1957) convincingly interpreted characteristics we associate with the
Victorians—prudishness, hard work, ambition, earnestness, respect for authority, and so
on—as responses to an underlying anxiety. Both Spencer and Comte suffered severe nervous
breakdowns more than once, and Hegel had to cope with depression.
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 41
Hegel delivered the lectures from which these quotes are drawn in the
1820s in Berlin, often to overflowing public audiences. He addressed the
cream of Prussian society under a reactionary Hohenzollern monarchy
that may have been more securely situated than the House of Bourbon in
post-Napoleonic France but, with the Revolution of 1830 a looming pros-
pect, still in need of as much reassurance as its state philosopher could
provide. And that turned out to be a very great deal.
One must picture Hegel—now catching up with his boyhood nick-
name, old in fact as well as demeanor—standing before the audience just
described. He is gravely explaining to the hushed throng why the events
of the French Revolution in 1789 constituted a “splendid dawn” that all
“thinking people greeted with celebration.” And one must imagine
them—given what they had already heard and could rightly anticipate—
nodding their plumed heads in agreement just as grave (Althaus 2000,
186). And they would continue to nod as Hegel plodded methodically on,
showing that even the Terror and Napoleon (who brought down the Holy
Roman Empire of the German Nation in 1806) had a place in the great
scheme of things, the ultimate scheme of things—the story of the self-
realization of Absolute Spirit in World History. There was nothing that did
not have a role to play in that story, as Hegel told it—including Nothing
itself. That was the sovereignty of Reason.
And his audience was willing to accept it all. For, as it turned out, they
were being introduced to themselves, in their very being, as a climactic
step toward some ultimate resolution—as the Absolute Spirit’s chosen
ones. Much could be overlooked, gazing back from such an elevation, if it
could be shown that, like labor pains, those awful historical “moments”
had been necessary tribulations.
From his early teens, Hegel’s mission had been reconciliation. He was
driven, above all, to reconcile his youthful Christianity with Greek phi-
losophy, to synthesize the two determinative Western traditions. Because
the French Revolution had appealed so incessantly to ancient models of
citizenship in its attack on the medieval order, it seemed to Hegel and
many of his peers that the crisis of their time could only be resolved on the
basis of that reconciliation. Hegelian Dialectic developed in service of that
project; it became the means by which Hegel would preserve and trans-
form whatever was essential through aufhebung—sublation.17
17
For example: Jewish monotheism severed the immediate and irrational fusion of the
divine and earthly that was ancient paganism. This separation of God and World was in turn
42 T. DE ZENGOTITA
After his death, Right and Left Hegelians divided over a question that
had dogged Hegel over his whole career—the question of his atheism.
Hegel’s basic claim was that the self-realization of Absolute Spirit in the
World lifted Christianity in its (merely) representational form to the pure
truth of its Idea. That means, for example (as with the incarnated God him-
self), that the doctrine of transubstantiation during communion—the
wafer becomes flesh, the wine becomes blood—was a representational
(imagistic, symbolic) evocation of Absolute Spirit recognizing itself as an
invisible conceptual being “incarnated” in the world as the world’s order.18
Add a dash of tolerance for ordinary folk who need visible representa-
tions of truth, however imperfect, and it became plausible for many
Hegelians (and for Hegel himself) to claim that Hegelianism was the ful-
fillment of Christianity—one that promised reconciliation across the sec-
tarian divisions that image-based dogmas inevitably entail. On the other
hand, it was possible (and dialectically sound) to find in the same claim the
end of Christianity—for what was left of that faith, as it had always been,
faith in the truth of icons and doctrines, if they turned out to be mere
images of abstractions to be found in Hegel’s Logic?19
There is no need to dwell on Hegel’s efforts to bring the Dialectic to
the natural sciences. Even Goethe, otherwise so supportive of him,
thought it a “bad, sophistical joke” to speak of growing plants “negating”
seeds and eating as a “negation” of food and so on (Lowith [1941] 1991,
14). If Hegel was doomed in the long run to more ridicule than any other
major philosopher has suffered, it is in large part because his account of
overcome by Christian incarnation which preserved (in sublated form) that separation in the
paradox of an “embodied God”—and that preserved what had been true in paganism to
begin with. See also the oft-cited Master/Slave dialectic.
18
Hegelianism is usefully described as Platonism historicized. Karl Lowith summed up his
account of Hegel by saying that “As the philosopher of the Christian-Germanic [i.e.
Protestant] world, Hegel understood the Spirit as will and freedom.” His problem was to
reconcile this modern notion with the eternity of ancient Idealism. A narrative account of
Absolute Spirit expounding itself as the world, over time, was his solution (Lowith [1941]
1991, 210–219).
19
Feuerbach rallied left Hegelians around the claim that “Whoever does not surrender
Hegelian philosophy does not surrender theology … the doctrine that reality is determined
by the idea is only the rationalistic expression of the theological doctrine that nature was cre-
ated by God.” Left Hegelians overtly did what Hegel’s orthodox critics had suspected him
of doing covertly.
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 43
nature would one day appear so ludicrous.20 But this much of how he
integrated geist and nature must be grasped if we are to understand, not
only Hegel’s appeal, but Comte’s and Spencer’s as well. For Hegel, Spirit
was not only alive in the usual sense; it was continuous with all activity, it
was force in general, it was motion in the world—and in the mind.21 The
deepest appeal of Dialectic was the sensation it conferred of motion in
thought, in thinking. The actual feeling of reversal that attends the experi-
ence of thinking dialectically was apprehended as the movement of Spirit
in the individual mind. And, as we shall see, the most influential group of
postmodernists, the creators of what would be known as French “theory”
who defined themselves in opposition to a “philosophy of the subject”
that went back to Hegel, were manifestly in his debt when it came to for-
mulations of mentality that depended on its essential motility.
So, if one asks how Hegel’s Berlin audience could have (thought they)
understood a philosopher who strikes us today as so obscure, part of the
answer lies in this: as good (or at least practiced) Lutherans, they were
accustomed to the idea of personal salvation, accustomed to the idea of
the Holy Spirit as something to be experienced.22 It was no great leap for
them to the idea that there was a more modern supreme being, one that
traditional religions had struggled, impossibly, to picture—a World Spirit
that was the true agent of history. And when they felt uplifted and
redeemed by oratory, or moved by a storm or a symphony, it was not dif-
ficult to decide that this was the force of that Spirit, the ultimate will that
20
Karl Kautsky, who presided over the literary legacy of Marx and Engels, decided not to
publish their Dialectics of Nature. It finally saw the light of day in the Soviet Union in 1925.
21
Goethe and Hegel first bonded over their opposition to Newtonian concepts of color
and force. What horrified (that is not too strong a word) them was how mathematics substi-
tuted itself for the phenomenon (see Adorno and Husserl on the same issue). How could a
theory of color or force that did not convey color and force be true in any full sense of that
word? Or consider Chevalier de Lamarck, most notorious of the Romantic failures in science,
best remembered as Darwin’s displaced predecessor. But his biological work came late in
his life’s work, as “an epilogue to an attempt to save the science of chemistry for the world
of organic continuum.” Lamarck “attached primary importance to the element of fire. …
Fire is the principle of activity in nature” and, since “life and activity are ultimately one,”
chemistry would be a life science (Gillispie 1960, 271–276).
22
It is striking that when Hegel refers to the doings of the World Spirit in his personal cor-
respondence, the syntax, the phrasing is eerily familiar. It can seem as if the expression “World
Spirit” was simply substituted for “God” or “God’s will” in the correspondence of an ortho-
dox believer—as if by a search and replace function.
44 T. DE ZENGOTITA
sustained the world through all changes, the being of becoming, that held
the world together—with mind. It was all very empirical.
Here are the words with which Hegel, addressing his students, greeted
the triumphant arrival of Napoleon (Hegel called him the “World Spirit
on horseback”) at Jena in 1806:
“Ideas and concepts” are the very bonds of the world—its forms, in
other words. But they are subject to change, sometimes cataclysmic
change. No wonder Lowith saw Plato historicized in Hegel’s thought.
23
For Karl Lowith, Hegel was the philosopher who tried to make Christianity modern—to
“secularize” it without losing what was spiritually fundamental. Andrew Wernick’s study of
Comte proposes a revealing parallel to Lowith’s account. Hegel’s path to modern secularity
proceeded “inward,” to the realm of spirit, before turning outward, to politics and the
Ethical Life (sittlichkeit); and it was bound to, argued Lowith, because Protestantism pro-
vided its basic orientation. So it makes sense that, in Catholic France, Comte began with
external institutions and practices, with a Positivist Church that would shape the inward life
of the modern citizen.
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 45
The great object which Positivism sets before us individually and socially is
the endeavor to become more perfect. … Towards Humanity, who is for us
the only true Great Being, we, the conscious elements of whom she is com-
posed, shall henceforth direct every aspect of our life. … Thus Positivism
becomes, in the true sense of the word, a Religion. (Comte 1848)
25
It is hard to determine how much exposure Comte had to German thought. He denied
any influence, but there was a lengthy correspondence with a protégé who was studying in
Germany and various other indications of interest and some familiarity.
48 T. DE ZENGOTITA
he who rightly interprets the doctrine contained in this work, will see that
neither of these terms [Spirit and Matter] can be taken as ultimate. He will
see that though the relation of subject and object renders necessary to us
these antithetical conceptions of Spirit and Matter; the one is no less than
the other to be regarded as but a sign of the Unknown Reality which under-
lies both.
26
This reduced image of Spencer is due in large part to W.G. Sumner, the first teacher of
“sociology” in an American university. He edited out the last chapter of Spencer’s Study of
Sociology (1896), a chapter in which Spencer posited a final stage of social equilibrium sus-
tained by refined emotions, much like those Comte proposed to cultivate immediately in his
Positivist polity. Spencer, of course, would not countenance the imposition of any Frenchified
regulations. His science was British—the perfected social life-form had to be an evolutionary
outcome. Spencer’s nature did not just inform rational government, it governed—as
Providence had before.
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 49
When Spencer waxed eloquent about The Unknown and, later in his
career, on the tendency of living things27 toward equilibrium, he almost
invariably remarked as well upon the inexplicable presence of beauty in
the world. The panorama of Life in all its forms was most precious to
Spencer precisely because its beauty lay beyond the reach of his dogged
efforts to explain the myriad adaptations he found in living forms. It was
impossible to explain the beauty of the natural world in terms of
adaptation—and yet beauty there was, and Spencer never tired of singing
its praises. It was authentic appreciation of this gratuitous beauty that
moved Spencer and his cohort to catalogue and depict so reverently. One
has only to peruse the works—especially the sketches—to recognize them
as expressions of devotion.
Spencer’s philosophical meditations are marked, over time, by an
increasing emphasis on the significance of instinct and emotion inspired
first of all by his own personal experience and confirmed by his reading of
the Scottish “common sense” philosophers with their psychological inter-
pretation of Kant. When he exempted beauty in nature and art from sci-
entific explanation (as Kant had noumena), he forgave himself, as it were,
for betraying his Methodist upbringing by providing a vessel into which
he could pour residual religious feelings that were harder to jettison than
doctrine. And in so doing, Spencer—like Hegel and Comte before him—
met deep-seated needs in his followers as well.
Early on, Spencer was involved with a “New Reformation” undertaken
by a group that included Thornton Hunt (son of Leigh) and G.H. Lewes.
They established a journal, The Leader, to promote their cause. Its flyleaf
displayed a quote from Alexander Von Humboldt’s great work of Romantic
science, Kosmos, and carried pieces by Harriet Martineau, J.A. Froude, and
Robert Owen, along with some of Spencer’s most inspirational essays. The
new reformation was an agnostic, yet intensely spiritualized, vitalist move-
ment that was looking for a middle way between Christianity and rational
materialism. Once again, the parallel with Hegel and Comte is obvious, but
the principles Spencer articulated for his readers were British to the core. In
language Locke himself might have approved, Spencer followed the most
influential Scots in asserting that whatever the psycho-physical apparatus of
27
As with Comte and Hegel, life for Spencer was very broadly defined. “Science,” for
example, was classified as a living thing in accordance with a definition Spencer cribbed (he
cribbed so much!) from Cuvier’s “law of organic correspondences.”
50 T. DE ZENGOTITA
human nature supplied by way of perception, belief, and feeling had its
own kind of necessity—and thus provided, without further ado, a basis for
justification and truth. And this principle applied as well to the awe we feel
in contemplation of the absolute and infinite, however unknowable. The
feelings in and of themselves were valid. They were facts.28 Thus were the
materialist reductions of utilitarianism avoided and the irrationalities of reli-
gious orthodoxy given—at long last—a natural place.
The mission of the new reformation supplied Spencer’s essential frame-
work long after the movement itself had disintegrated. No matter how his
formulations varied over the decades—as they did continuously, depend-
ing on what ideas or findings this omnivorous autodidact had most
recently absorbed—Spencer was always looking for ways to endow scien-
tific fact and reason with transcendent value. For Spencer, as for Comte
and Hegel, the idea of the whole, on the one hand, and immediately expe-
rienced life forces, on the other, made this synthesis possible, whatever the
content of their systems. It is above all important to remember that scien-
tists and philosophers were not Spencer’s real audience. He wrote for gen-
erally educated Victorians who had a “desire to see the living universe as
personally significant” (Francis 2007, 184).
And that, of course, is precisely what modernists in the arts and the
academy would not be able to see.
If you believe in improvement you must weep, for the attained perfection
must end in darkness, cold, and silence. In a dispassionate view the ardor for
reform, improvement, for virtue, for knowledge, even for beauty is only a
vain sticking up for appearances as though one were anxious about the cut
of one’s clothes in a community of blind men. Life knows us not and we do
not know life—we don’t know even our own thoughts. Half the words we use
have no meaning whatever and of the other half each man understands each
word after the fashion of his own folly and conceit. Faith is a myth and beliefs
shift like mists on the shore; thoughts vanish; words, once pronounced, die;
and the memory of yesterday is as shadowy as the hope of tomorrow. (Joseph
Conrad 1897 (italics mine))
28
“All reasonings must be from first principles; and for first principles no other reason can
be given but this, that by the constitution of our nature, we are under a necessity of assenting
to them” (Thomas Reid, 1764).
THE SITUATION OF THE MODERN SUBJECT 51
References
Abrams, M.H. 1971. Natural Supernaturalism: Tradition and Revolution in
Romantic Literature. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Althaus, Horst. 2000. Hegel: An Intellectual Biography. Trans. Michael Tarsh.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Barzun, Jacques. 1964. Science: The Glorious Entertainment. New York: Harper &
Row.
Braudel, Fernand. 1982. Civilization and Capitalism, 15th–18th Century.
New York: Harper & Row.
Braver, Lee. 2007. A Thing of This World: A History of Continental Anti-realism.
Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Bury, J.B. (John Bagnell). 1932. The Idea of Progress: An Inquiry into Its Origin
and Growth. New York: The Macmillan Company.
Descartes, Rene. 1968. The Discourse on Method (1637) and the Meditations
(1641). Harmondsworth: Penguin Classics.
Dunn, John. 1969. The Political Thought of John Locke: An Historical Account of
the Argument of the “Two Treatises of Government”. London: Cambridge
University Press.
Elias, Norbert. 1978. The Civilizing Process: The History of Manners. Trans.
Edmund Jephcott. New York: Urizen Books.
Francis, Mark. 2007. Herbert Spencer and the Invention of Modern Life. Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.
Galilei, Galileo. (1623a) 1957. Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo: Including the
Starry Messenger. Trans. Stillman Drake. Garden City: Doubleday Anchor
Books.
———. (1623b) 1970. Two Kinds of Properties. In Philosophy of Science: Readings
Selected, ed. and Introduced by Arthur Danto and Sidney Morganbesser.
New York: Meridian Books.
Gay, Peter. 1969. The Enlightenment, an Interpretation: The Science of Freedom.
New York: Knopf.
Gillispie, Charles Coulston. 1960. The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History
of Scientific Ideas. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Green, F. 1931. 18th Century France, Six Essays. New York: D. Appleton.
Hegel, Georg W. F. (1837) 1996. Hegel’s Lectures on the History of Philosophy.
Amherst: Prometheus Books.
Hobsbawm, Erik J. (1962) 1996. The Age of Revolution: 1789–1848. New York:
Vintage.
Houghton, Walter E. 1957. The Victorian Frame of Mind, 1830–1870. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Johnson, Samuel. 1958. The Yale Edition of the Works of Samuel Johnson. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
52 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Weber, Max. (1905) 2014. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.
Kettering: Angelico Press.
Wernick, Andrew. 2001. Auguste Comte and the Religion of Humanity: The Post-
theistic Program of French Social Theory. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Whitney, Lois. 1965. Primitivism and the Idea of Progress in English Popular
Literature of the Eighteenth Century. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.
Willey, Basil. 1950. The 18th Century Background: Studies on the Idea of Nature in
the Thought of the Period. New York: Columbia University Press.
Williams, Raymond. (1958) 1983. Culture and Society: 1780–1950. New York:
Columbia University Press.
PART II
Modernism
CHAPTER 3
Dada aimed to destroy the reasonable deceptions of man and recover the
natural and unreasonable order. … Dada is senseless like nature. (Jean Arp
(in Karl [1948] 1988, 349))
Of all the modernist schools and movements, Dada can plausibly lay claim
to that coveted encomium, “most radical.” How typically provocative of
Arp to frame the project as an attempt to “recover the natural.” It was
heresy to challenge the self-sufficiency of art, especially its independence
from or dominance over nature. But the first impression is immediately
undermined and an article of faith restored—for Dada was out to “recover”
a modernist nature seething with aimless forces and quantum uncertain-
ties, obedient only to the laws of chance, the nature Nietzsche had
described.
John Locke and Adam Smith had God’s designs to guide and restrain
them when they imagined constituting governments and political econo-
mies based on natural law. Hegel, Spencer, and Comte could no longer
rely on a Deistic or orthodox Creator, but history for them was still
going in some direction, however painfully. They felt supported by a
natural process of social evolution—an essential continuity retained.
Nietzsche’s announcement of God’s death stood apart from a chorus of
nineteenth-century atheistic proclamations because he wasn’t just talk-
ing about religious faith. Nietzsche meant that there was nothing for
1
“Worldhood” is the term Heidegger used to evoke the ultimate “there” of Da-sein, the
environing horizon of all actualities and possibilities that constitute Dasein as
being-in-the-world.
2
This passage focuses on everyday experience but, for the modernist elite, the impact of
relativity theory and quantum mechanics reinforced the basic message. The intuitively acces-
sible Newtonian cosmos, a monument to modern rationality, was no more.
60 T. DE ZENGOTITA
ovements, founded one day, dissolving the next, and then founded once
m
more—always in pursuit of an ineffable something that lingered just over
the horizon of what had already been done. The true artist was bold
enough to reject a world that no longer made sense, to decline to repre-
sent it, first of all—but to repudiate all traditional themes and methods
and attitudes as well. While philistines wallowed in the kitsch of history,
the modernist artist refused to look back, except in search of images and
allusions appropriate to present purposes. The rubble of time, the chaos of
city life—it was all grist for the mill. Hence, above all, the cult of original-
ity, the mad desire to be a genius, to prove oneself a genius through an
authored work that transcended the given.
That is why modernist art was such an elitist undertaking. What else
could be expected of an enterprise that supplied a lack bequeathed by a
departed God?3
An assembly of reminders follows—staples in the voluminous literature
on modernism. They point to a manifestation of a modernist way of being
in the world that sets the stage for the emergence of postmodernism. We
have already heard from Proust: “A book is the product of a different self
from the one we manifest in our habits, in society.”
Consider also these remarks from other writers:
3
William Cronin, speaking of Frank Lloyd Wright, said that “job of the artist (is) to create
a vision of nature more natural than nature itself” (Frank Lloyd Wright, Ken Burns [1997]
2014).
62 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Shapeless emotions such as fear, joy, grief, etc. … will no longer greatly
attract the artist. He will endeavor to awake subtler emotions, as yet
unnamed … his work will give to those observers capable of feeling them
lofty emotions beyond the reach of words. (Wassily Kandinsky Concerning
the Spiritual in Art 1914)
the artist acts like a mediumistic being who, from a labyrinth beyond time
and space, seeks his way out to a clearing. If we give the attributes of a
medium to the artist, we must deny him the state of consciousness on the
esthetic plane about what he is doing or why he is doing it. (Marcel Duchamp
“The Creative Act” 1975)
follows from the nature of intentionality. The more separated, the more
exalted and purified, the more unprecedented—in many cases, the more
literally abstract—the work, the more the creator felt as if the everyday
person who ate and drank and chatted, the person immersed in the natural-
historical flux, the person “fallen” into average everydayness—that person
couldn’t possibly be the author of something so radically unsuited to the
plane of ordinary existence.
Flaubert famously quipped, “Madame Bovary, c’est moi”—which can
seem inconsistent with what he wrote to Mlle de Chantepie, cited earlier.
But Flaubert was speaking of himself as a person with a biography in the
latter case—of himself as creator of a work in the former. Joyce and Eliot
were making essentially the same point. Personal biography provided mate-
rial for the creator’s work, resources like any other—but the works did not
express the accidental wretch the artist happened to be. That view of art
went out with the Romantics, the predecessors modernists most loved to
loathe. Instead, works “expressed” the potentialities of the very media of
the arts with which the creators had somehow managed to merge.
It is worth recalling what “surrealism” literally means. Breton and his
cohort, tapping into the depths of what they took to be the Freudian
unconscious, the other-self from whom their works surged forth, fully
intended the imputation of superiority.4 A sense of privileged access
founded the elitism, the contempt for mass society and sensibility that was
so typical of the great modernists.5 In Search of Lost Time was surreal in
this enlarged sense too; not dogmatically, of course, but just as improba-
bly—and even more strikingly when one considers the characteristic
Proustian effect, the “heightened” experience of experience, the transcen-
dence of experience by itself, as it were—thanks to a rendering more faith-
ful than the original.
And—once again, and at a further degree of removal—modernist cre-
ators were not only producing sur-worldly works from sur-selfly sources,
they were also defining art, defining what sort of thing a poem or a paint-
ing or a building ought to be—creating values, in accordance with
Nietzsche’s challenge to the “midnightly men” of the future for whom he
4
Contemporary usage “it was so surreal” seems not to carry that connotation. High
Culture brought low under the postmodern regime.
5
Said Ezra Pound, writing from Stone Cottage, where he was at work with Yeats: “to
explain a symbol is to destroy its ability to embody the divine or permanent world; knowl-
edge that could be understood by the uninitiated masses would not be knowledge at all” (in
Longenbach 1988, 91).
64 T. DE ZENGOTITA
6
Says Nietzsche’s biographer: “All of the significant currents in the early 20th century,
from symbolism to art nouveau and expressionism, were inspired by Nietzsche. Every self-
respecting member of these circles had a ‘Nietzsche experience’” (Safranski 2002, 323).
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 65
new Moscow Art and Popular Theater was in the nature of a revolution,”
he said, in which “we protested against the customary manner of acting,
against theatricality … we needed a new beginning. We needed new bases
and foundations” (1924, 330, 483). Those foundations were also psycho-
logical and would eventually be represented in a chart known as “The
Stanislavski System.” (This particular chart is too complex for anyone not
driven by obsession to decipher, but the fondness of modernist authorities
for such devices will be considered in some detail later. See especially the
discussion of Structuralism in Chap. 5.)
The upshot is this: a gesture of authorial definition, of completed con-
struction in defiance of senseless surroundings—that is the intentional act
that constituted modernist “foundationalism.” It will become a principal
target of the counter-gesture of deconstruction when it comes, a counter-
gesture that the modernist avant-garde anticipated in various ways.
Because that avant-garde played an essential role in shaping French
theory, Part IV will consider it in some detail. Here, a simple comparison,
to highlight what is at stake:
But the stillness and the brightness of the day were as strange as the chaos
and tumult of the night, with the trees standing there, and the flowers
standing there, looking before them, looking up, yet beholding nothing,
eyeless, and so terrible.”7
Both Marinetti and Woolf felt oppressed by conventions of a dead past
deeply embedded in the general culture. Alienated from that culture and
essentially alone—especially Woolf in her Cartesian envelope—each was
nevertheless sustained by a small group of the like-minded, an elite few
profound enough to understand their absurd situation and brave enough
to produce the works that provided what redemption could be had.
Boundless achievement seemed possible to Marinetti’s gang of proto-
fascist visionaries, or so they proclaimed while the fever lasted. More
ephemeral epiphanies were all that Bloomsbury’s extraordinary souls
could expect, and the fact that they could settle for that testified to their
exalted standing in their own minds. As with Marinetti and Woolf person-
ally, the contrast between the ethos of Bohemian refinement at Bloomsbury
and the hothouse atmosphere of the Futurist school could hardly be more
striking. And yet, at the deepest level, a common form of life is discernible.
Modern subjectivity, in extremis, determined to create. Let Woolf stand in
for a rough-hewn category—call it mainstream high modernism. Marinetti
represents a wing of the avant-garde.
Woolf took note of the experience of self-splitting, of a division in her
psyche corresponding to the production of a work abstracted from every-
day life—though she was not as categorical about it as Flaubert and Joyce.
In “Notes on an Elizabethan Play,” for example, she famously described
the “great artist” as the man who knows “that there is a station, some-
where in mid-air, whence Smith and Liverpool can be seen to the best
advantage” and who knows how to sustain himself in that “place,” nei-
ther too far removed, nor too much involved, with the Smiths and
Liverpools of the real world (1925, 17). No assertion of divine authority,
of absolute separation—no Joycean flourish of pared fingernails, cer-
tainly—but the essential point remains. The truth of Smith and Liverpool,
which was the artist’s special provenance, had to be precipitated in an
alchemy of creation that produced, not reality itself, but an experience of
it—through a work that registered essences and evoked them. It was that
alchemy that T S. Eliot, inclined to the most stringent objectivism, had in
mind when he called for a “depersonalization” so complete that “art may
7
From “Time Passes” in To The Lighthouse ([1927] 1989).
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 67
she scored her canvas with brown running nervous lines which had no
sooner settled there than they enclosed (she felt it looming out at her) a
space … what could be more formidable than that space? Here she was
again, she thought, stepping back to look at it, drawn out of gossip, out of
living, out of community with people into the presence of this formidable
68 T. DE ZENGOTITA
ancient enemy of hers—this other thing, this truth, this reality, which sud-
denly laid hands on her, emerged stark at the back of appearances and com-
manded her attention. She was half unwilling, half reluctant. Why always be
drawn out and haled away? Why not left in peace to talk to Mr. Carmichael
on the lawn. (158)
And later:
as she lost consciousness of outer things, and her name and her personality
and her appearance, and whether Mr. Carmichael was there or not, her mind
kept throwing up from its depths, scenes, and names and sayings, and mem-
ories and ideas like a fountain. (159)
While an artist is labouring at his work of art, nothing prevents it from sur-
passing Dream. As soon as it is finished, the work must be hidden or
destroyed, or better still, thrown as a prey to the brutal crowd which will
magnify it by killing it with its scorn, and thereby intensify its absurd useless-
ness. We thus condemn art as finished work, we conceive of it only in its
movement, in the state of effort and draft. Art is simply a possibility for
absolute conquest. For the artist, to complete is to die. (Marinetti in Ottinger
[1915] 2009, 21; Italics mine)
The loathing Marinetti and his cohort felt for a stifling tradition was so
intense that their expressions of it—the calls for the destruction of libraries
and museums and so on—sometimes feel like a parody of modernist dis-
dain. It was as if Marinetti had appropriated Baudelaire’s classic balance
between the ephemeral and the eternal in art, the necessary descent, as it
were, of the eternal to transitory styles in history that give it expression—
and promoted, by sheer force, the transitory to the level of an absolute in
itself. The doomed logic of that move goes a long way to explain why, at
the limits of the modernist avant-garde, in Vorticism and Dada and early
Surrealism too—wherever manifestos seemed essential!—there was only
so much that could be done. When authorial self-assertion reached the
point where finished works of any kind seemed alien and smacked of con-
formity, art lapsed and dogma produced sects and boredom.
But in the glory days of futurism, in the decade before the Great War,
Marinetti used his inherited wealth to sponsor outrageous public events in
various venues—demanding to be booed, provoking fights and riots.8 When
it took this form—in the name of “action art” under the slogan “art=life”—
Marinetti’s futurism tried to live its creed of opposition to all works, to all
completion—in the name of change, in the name of speed, in the name of
“absolute conquest” by the modernist creator. Mainstream high modern-
ists abstracted finished works from the pointless churn of history in the
8
The pervasive influence of Alfred Jarry’s Ubu Roi (1896) and his nonsense-science of
pataphysics is most apparent in this aspect of Marinetti’s work.
70 T. DE ZENGOTITA
We declare that the splendor of the world has been enriched by a new
beauty: the beauty of speed. A racing automobile with its bonnet adorned
with great tubes like serpents with explosive breath … a roaring motor car
which seems to run on machine-gun fire, is more beautiful than the Victory
of Samothrace. We want to sing the man at the wheel, the ideal axis of which
crosses the earth, itself hurling along its orbit. … Poetry must be a violent
assault on the forces of the unknown, to force them to bow before man. …
We are on the extreme promontory of the centuries! What is the use of look-
ing behind at the moment when we must open the mysterious shutters of
the impossible? Time and Space died yesterday. We are already living in the
absolute, since we have already created eternal, omnipresent speed. (The
Futurist Manifesto 1909)
So—a very large ego, no question about that. But not a transcendental
ego, mysteriously removed from everyday events and its own proper name.
Quite the contrary. One might say that Marinetti took on the role of god/
author openly, without much sublimation, making a personal commitment
to directly confront the senseless mix of entrenched routine and meaningless
accident that was history and, in effect, to try to beat the flux of life itself into
a work, ranting and roaring the while. Hence, the corresponding emphases
at the pole of the object—the stress on incompletion, on creative destruc-
tion—and on the original practice of “Action-Art”—genuine attempts to live
a refusal to separate the work from the world. It was a radical response to
the circumstances, but it too played out in the phenomenological space
structured by the subject/object dialectic of modernism so far described.
Steiner’s “lacking word” can now be situated more comprehensively.
The fact that language was so promiscuous a medium, so irretrievably woven
into the fabric of everyday life in mass society, made it that much harder to
reconceive and renew. There was a near limit to what one could get out of
arranging words in new ways on the page, after the manner of Mallarmé’s
Un Coup de Dés. The same goes for experiments with automatic writing and
neologisms and all the rest. At the end of the day, there were just those 20
odd letters to work with, and just so many words—all of them shamelessly
available to journalists and bureaucrats as well as the literary vanguard. So
it was inevitable that writers, reaching for glimpses of the eternal in the tran-
sitory flux, would feel more frustrated with their depreciated medium than
creators in the plastic arts. Here are two representative expressions:
More and more my language appears to me like a veil which one has to tear
apart in order to get to those things (or the nothingness) lying behind it.
Grammar and style! To me they seem to have become as irrelevant as a
Biedermeier bathing suit or the imperturbability of a gentleman. A mask. It
is to be hoped the time will come, thank God, in some circles it already has,
when language is best used where it is most efficiently abused. (Samuel
Beckett, letter to Axel Kaun 1937)
As the mimetic imperative lost its grip, the possibilities for innovation
in painting, sculpture, the performing arts, and architecture would seem
almost unlimited by comparison with literature. And in those media inno-
vations were evident at first glance. The “shock of the new” depended
upon immediacy—as does any genuine shock—and that was provided by
Picasso’s Les Demoiselles d’Avignon, Duchamp’s Fountain, and Stravinsky’s
Rite of Spring. So modernist painters did not typically complain about the
“lacking color,” nor did sculptors feel betrayed by their material just
because, say, bronze was also used in hackneyed statues of Great Men on
Horseback in the public square. The sheer appearance of Brancusi’s
Princess X overcame the happenstance of “bronze” at a stroke, and with
an immediate and total effect that no amount of wordplay in Finnegans
Wake could match.
So the difference in attitude between writers and artists toward their
media was essentially an accident, a by-product of intrinsic characteristics
and customary social deployments. The common ground shows through
with the realization that all of them were self-consciously concerned with
artistic means per se. And, whatever the medium, that concern tended to
intensify as a function of artistic aspiration—the more ambitious the proj-
ect, the more exalted and transcendent the aim, the more concerned with
the how-of-it creators became.
Beyond that, it seems impossible to generalize much further. The sheer
experimental variety is boundless and accompanying accounts—the trea-
tises and tracts—almost as various. But whether, like Le Corbusier,
Malevich, or Mondrian, a creator had identified (often on psychological
grounds) axiomatic aesthetic elements or, like Kandinsky and de Chirico,
was intent on eternal ineffables (or both), the characteristic rhetorical ges-
ture—the tone, the style—is unmistakable; ultimate matters had been
consigned to one’s care in the absence of God and an aspect of one’s being
had risen to the occasion.
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 73
In this famous speech, Weber was concerned with one of the most
important of modernist abstractions—the one separating “value judg-
ments” from “judgments of fact.” The social scientist, like anyone else,
must live on the level of incorrigibly messy everyday experience where all
factors come into play, including the values and interests of the scientist.
Disciplined study depends upon the abstraction of a well-defined object
from that messy actuality. When the object is society, the most urgent of
74 T. DE ZENGOTITA
all the disciplinary tasks must be to neutralize the “values” that the man
the scientist happens to be cannot help but have. The establishment of the
fact/value distinction enacts a split in the consciousness of founders of the
modernist (human) sciences that parallels the division between the artist
as creator and the artist’s personal biography. The correlations of
Husserlian intentionality are operating here as well.
Weber’s aim, of course, was to cleanse these sciences of bias to the
extent possible and study human beings objectively, as preceding genera-
tions of moderns had somehow failed to do, in spite of all their efforts.
That long record of failure to live up to the example of natural science
accounts for Weber’s tone—alternately steely (toward those committed to
objectivity) and contemptuous (of those who lacked the right stuff). It was
as if he were rehearsing the extremes of personal discipline that the purity
of his academic discipline had required of him. As indeed he was. So
sternly committed was he to his science that the neo-Romantic poet Stefan
George and his circle saw in Weber a prototype of the alienated man of
reason living through what Weber himself called the “disenchantment of
the world.” To them—and to many others—Weber was an impressive but
tragic figure who embodied the almost inhuman resolution it took to
assess the world he lived in without allowing values to cloud his judgment.
Edgar Salin, of the George circle, had a ready explanation: “Weber was
profoundly insensitive to the arts … instead, he created his ‘sociology’ in
order to approach through conceptual means phenomena he could not
reach by way of experience” (in Marianne Weber [1926] 2017, xli). Details
of Weber’s biography cut against that assessment, but there is no doubt
that he made heroic efforts to live the discipline he advocated.
This section will show certain parallels between modernism in the arts
and the way academic disciplines were defined by their “authors” in the
academy during the same period, under the same circumstances. If the
modernist context made the “lacking word” a problem for creators of lit-
erary works, creators of knowledge were hard hit as well. As the credibility
of the master theories of nineteenth century evolutionism eroded, espe-
cially under pressure from developments in the natural sciences, students
of humanity’s ways—of history and society, culture, language, religion,
and psychology—found themselves almost literally picking up the pieces
of those shattered systems. Yet another embarrassment for modern
thought, but this one was even more disruptive than the one that had led
evolutionists to mock their Enlightenment predecessors (see Chap. 2).
That had been a difference over what nature’s plan was like. Now it looked
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 75
pronoun? (see Chap. 2). The confiding tone certainly makes a promise, the
title alludes to the Discourse on Method—and Durkheim’s ambition for his
science would become almost as comprehensive as Descartes’ had been.
But the promise of the modernist is more selectively directed. The reader is
not going to be told, as he was by Descartes, that reason and good sense
are naturally equal in all men, and likewise the ability to judge of truth and
falsity. On the contrary, in the very first paragraph, the “accepted opinions”
of the “ordinary man” are stripped of all authority when it comes to assess-
ing social facts—Ezra Pound could not have asked for a more definitive
exclusion. The reader Durkheim addresses is being invited to join him in an
unprecedented quest for detachment from the “promptings of common
sense” which so implacably “imposes its judgments upon us unawares” that
only a “sustained and special practice can prevent” its corrupting influence
([1895b] 1982, 31–32). But this practice must be undertaken, for the
“state of mind of the physicists, chemists, and biologists,” a state of mind
to which sociologists must aspire, is more difficult for them to attain. That
is because, as Durkheim explains in a later text, “we live our lives in society”
just like everyone else (1982, 37, 246).
Once again, the essential distinction between the personal-historical
subject and the transcendental observer/founder/creator arises in a sys-
tematic practice that abstracts the object/work from the flow of lived
experience.
The problem with common sense notions about society is that, “because
they have been developed unmethodically … they no more exactly express
social things than the ideas the ordinary person has of substances and their
properties (heat, light, sound, etc.)” express the realities of the physical
world (1982, 246). And so, full circle—back to Galileo and his particles
on the other side of the veil of ideas (see Chap. 2). Hence, the built-in
advantage of social facts over psychological facts: they appear to us, they
“display much more naturally and immediately all the characteristics of a
thing” in legal codes, statistics, monuments, manners, fashion, and so on.
Theories about hidden factors, based on such facts, conform to the
Classical model of natural science. Facts of the personal psyche, on the
other hand, are “internal by definition” and cannot be treated as things
“save by doing violence to their nature.” That difference led Durkheim to
expect that “once the principle of sociological method is universally
acknowledged,” it would challenge the imperial claims of that other
human science and “make up the lead of psychology, which it owes solely
to its prior historical place” (1982, 71–72).
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 77
3.2.2 G.E. Moore (1873–1958)
What, then, is good? How is good to be defined? (G. E. Moore [1903]
2005, 6)
But this is not the sort of definition I am asking for. Such a definition can
never be of ultimate importance to any study except lexicography. If I
wanted that kind of definition I should have to consider in the first place
how people generally used the word “good”; but my business is not with its
proper usage, as established by custom. … What I want to discover is the
nature of that object or idea, and about this I am extremely anxious to arrive
at an agreement. (6)
9
Evil, beautiful, and ugly are the other non-natural predicates Moore identifies. They are
also non-physical, invisible, intangible—but intuitively discernible in ways that depend ulti-
mately on “taste.”
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 81
10
Moore skewers Spencer immediately, in his typical way, as he introduces the fallacy: “It
is absolutely useless, so far as Ethics is concerned, to prove, as Mr. Spencer tries to do, that
increase of pleasure coincides with increase of life, unless good means something different
from either life or pleasure. He might as well try to prove that an orange is yellow by shewing
that it is always wrapped up in paper.”
82 T. DE ZENGOTITA
use the naturalistic fallacy in details; but with regard to his fundamental
principles, the following doubts occur: Is he fundamentally a Hedonist?
And, if so, is he a naturalistic hedonist? … Does he hold that a tendency to
increase life is merely a criterion of good conduct? Or does he hold that such
increase in life is marked out by nature as an end at which we ought to aim?
… his language in various places would give color to all these hypotheses,
though some of them are mutually inconsistent. I will try to discuss the
main points. (46)
Poor Spencer. New standards were obviously being set—and none too
soon, it seems, for the old standards had countenanced a way of thinking
so undisciplined that a really qualified commentator, one who had defined
his field and methods with sufficient rigor, could do no more than “try”
to discuss the main points made by its most prominent representative.
After Moore finished with his predecessors, he used his foundational
predicate to identify and define “the good” in itself, not as a means, but as
that which has the quality “good” intrinsically. He offered two kinds of
“complex organic unities” summarily characterized as “personal affec-
tions” and “aesthetic enjoyments”—with a crucial proviso: the affections
and enjoyments must involve people and objects that are actually worthy,
which would boil down to “judgments of taste” (189, 192–193).
In After Virtue (1984), Alasdair MacIntyre was out to update Aristotle’s
socio-biological functionalism in hopes of reviving a battered Marxism in
some form by at least moving beyond bourgeois “emotivism.” His experi-
ence of working-class realities in mid-twentieth-century Great Britain
allowed him to give, by way of contrast, an unforgettable image of Moore
as a darling of the Bloomsbury group—which had received his Principia
Ethica with rapturous enthusiasm. He cited Maynard Keynes, who was pres-
ent as Moore and Woolf, and all their friends persuaded themselves that
their personal tastes in matters of art and love were actually neo-platonic
universals that their supremely cultivated sensibilities enabled them to intuit.
The fact that they were so easy to persuade is what makes this anecdote
relevant here. As MacIntyre puts it, they envisaged “the whole of the past
… as a burden that Moore helped them cast off” in discussions of love and
art in which, “as Keynes tells us … ‘victory was with those who could
speak with the greatest appearance of clear, undoubting conviction and
could best use the accents of infallibility’ and Keynes goes on to describe
the effectiveness of Moore’s gasps of incredulity and head shaking, of
Strachey’s grim silences and Lowes Dickinson’s shrugs” (16–17).
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 83
MacIntyre calls all this “a great silliness … but the great silliness of
highly intelligent and perceptive people,” so it is worth “asking if we can
discern any clues as to why they accepted Moore’s naïve and complacent
apocalypticism (16).” This chapter is providing some of those clues.
It is not until the third chapter of the Course in General Linguistics that
we reach the title “The Object of Linguistics.” The titles of the first two
chapters, however, make this a difference without distinction as compared
to Durkheim and Moore.11 The first chapter (5 pages) is called “A Glance
at the History of Linguistics” (no more than a glance was called for) and
the second (2 pages) is called “Subject Matter and Scope of Linguistics; its
Relations with the Other Sciences.” It amounts to a brisk house-cleaning
operation in which old-fashioned diachronic studies of language evolution
are allowed to retain a place under the broad umbrella of “linguistics”
understood as the study of “all manifestations of human speech.” The
relevance of other sciences—like sociology and physiology—is admitted
under that broad umbrella as well. But it is only when “The Object of
Linguistics” is actually defined that those “other viewpoints” that have had
linguists “going around in circles” for too long can be banished at last—
along with “the superficial notions of the general public (16).” At that
point, a science of language becomes possible and serious work begins.
Langue, the synchronic code, the grammar of a language, makes that sci-
ence possible thanks to the abstraction of this “well-defined object” from
“the heterogeneous mass of speech facts” (14).
Another prototype of academic self-definition and containment, then,
to be discussed in some detail in the section on Structuralism (Chap. 5).
Here, the point is simple, categorical: Saussure’s enormously influential
modernist science of language was founded through the same basic ges-
tures and tropes as the other disciplines considered in this chapter.
11
The fact that this “book” was actually assembled by students from their notes on
Saussure’s lectures may account for this divergence.
84 T. DE ZENGOTITA
3.2.4 I.A. Richards (1893–1979)
The first chapter of Principles of Literary Criticism is called “The Chaos of
Critical Theories”—and I.A. Richards was, if it be possible, even more
aghast at the spectacle of past confusion than were the other founders:
if we now turn to consider what are the results yielded by the best minds
pondering these questions [of artistic value] in the light of the eminently
accessible experiences provided by the Arts, we discover an almost empty
garner. A few conjectures, a supply of admonitions, many acute isolated
observations, some brilliant guesses, much oratory and applied poetry, inex-
haustible confusion, a sufficiency of dogma, no small stock of prejudices,
whimsies and crochets. (6)
Richards concluded that “of such as these, it may be said without exag-
geration, is extant critical theory composed.” To ensure that his readers
are aware of the scope of this archly phrased indictment, he mentions
names. Beginning with Aristotle, Longinus, and Horace and ending with
Coleridge, Carlyle, and Matthew Arnold—he provides a “few specimens
of the most famous utterances of each” to justify the overall assertion.
Another list, another long paragraph—and an impression of historical
chaos is established, over which Richards presides by implication of his
controlling style. Obviously, only a completely fresh start on the soundest
possible foundation could dissipate this fog of doxa. The style is infectious.
Delicious sensations of authority attend it.
Shifting to what he seemed to think was a moment of becoming mod-
esty, Richards allows that “some of these apices of critical theory, indeed
many of them, are profitable starting points for reflection” but (having
relieved us of the suspicion that Aristotle was actually stupid) he moves on
to the real point, which is that “neither together, nor singly, nor in any
combination do they give what is required.” And what is required? By
now we know roughly what to expect. Someone who feels supremely
qualified to give an incontrovertible answer to that portentous question is
about to give it. “Explanations” are required, explanations that answer
“the central question, what is the value of the arts, why are they worth the
keenest hours of the best minds, and what is their place in the system of
human endeavors?” (7).
So there it is again. To build a disciplinary compartment among other
such compartments by appropriate abstraction of criteria that will define
what needs explaining (in this case, the value of art) and provide the
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 85
12
See Mark Micale The Mind of Modernism (2004) for a revealing overview.
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 87
of purity and contamination, and this is what accounts for the ferocious
debates that broke out over the ensuing decades—debates about whether
or not some issue at hand qualified as “philosophy” or “anthropology” or
“history” or whatever. And, of course, the stakes would be that much
higher when the whole idea of—the very institutions of—these modernist
disciplines finally came under attack.14
It will be no surprise then, when we get to Part IV, to find Derrida,
Foucault, Barthes, and all the rest of them taking such delight in figures of
transgression, dispersion, and contamination at the expense of categorical
purities and ab-solutes (not soluble, not mixable) of all kinds. In Anglo-
American contexts, the politics of academic postmodernism will play out
in the same conceptual arena, broadly construed. The rise of “interdisci-
plinary studies” in itself, of course—but the unity and purity of the disci-
plines would be eroded from within as well. The multiplication of
perspectives and “discourses”—women, gays, ethnicities—but also, in the
fabric of “theory” itself as it ramified across the humanities, the reach for
margins, for multiple readings and aporias, for problematics that eschew
solutions. The uncontainable play of Nietzschean forces that drove the
modernists to abstraction was welcomed by postmodernists determined to
participate in it—the only reality.
Writing, writing, writing.
References
Cahoone, Lawrence E., ed. 1996. From Modernism to Postmodernism: An
Anthology. Cambridge: Blackwell.
de Saussure, Ferdinand. (1916) 1966. Course in General Linguistics. Trans. Wade
Baskin. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Duchamp, Marcel. 1975. The Creative Act. In The Essential Writings of Marcel
Duchamp. London: Thames and Hudson.
Durkheim, Emile. (1895a) 1938. The Rules of Sociological Method. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
———. (1895b) 1982. The Rules of Sociological Method. Trans. W. D. Halls.
New York: The Free Press.
14
Margaret Mead was my advisor at Columbia in the 1970s. She was a student of Franz
Boas, a disciplinary founder of American Anthropology at the beginning of the twentieth
century. Only a few decades from modernist founding to postmodern crisis, then—but in the
heat of battle it felt to all concerned as if ancient testaments were at issue.
NEW AUTHORITIES, WORKS, AND DISCIPLINES 89
Eliot, T.S. 1920. Tradition and the Individual Talent. In The Sacred Wood, 47–59.
London: Methuen.
Frank Lloyd Wright. Directed by Ken Burns. [1997] 2014. Public Broadcasting
System (PBS.)
Joyce, James. (1914) 2003. Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man. New York:
Penguin Classics.
Kandinsky, Wassily. (1914) 2010. Concerning the Spiritual in Art. Whitefish:
Kessinger Publishing.
Karl, Frederick Robert. 1988. Modern and Modernism: The Sovereignty of the
Artist, 1885–1925. New York: Atheneum.
Le Corbusier. (1923) 1986. Towards a New Architecture. Trans. Frederick Etchells.
New York: Dover Publications.
Longenbach, James. 1988. Stone Cottage: Pound, Yeats, and Modernism. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1984. After Virtue. Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press.
Marinetti, Filippo Tommaso. (1909) 1996. The Futurist Manifesto. In From
Modernism to Postmodernism: An Anthology, ed. Lawrence E. Cahoone.
Cambridge: Blackwell.
Micale, Mark. 2004. The Mind of Modernism: Medicine, Psychology, and the
Cultural Arts in Europe and America, 1880–1940. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Moore, G.E. (1903) 2005. The Subject Matter of Ethics. In Principia Ethica.
New York: Barnes and Noble.
Ottinger, Didier, ed. (1915) 2009. In Futurism, ed. Didier Ottinger. Paris:
Éditions de Centre Pompidou.
Proust, Marcel. (1913) 1998. Swann’s Way: In Search of Lost Time: Volume 1.
New York: Modern Library.
Richards, Ivor Armstrong. 1924. The Analysis of a Poem. In Principles of Literary
Criticism. London: Routledge.
Safranski, Rüdiger. 2002. Nietzsche: A Philosophical Biography. New York:
W.W. Norton & Company.
Schoenberg, Arnold. 1952. My Evolution. The Musical Quarterly 38 (4): 517–527.
Stanislavski, Constantin. 1924. My Life in Art. Trans. J.J. Robbins. Boston: Little,
Brown & Co.
Steiner, George. 1975. After Babel: Aspects of Language and Translation.
New York: Oxford University Press.
von Hofmannsthal, Hugo. (1902) 2005. The Lord Chandos Letter. In The Lord
Chandos Letter: And Other Writings. Trans. Joel Rotenberg. New York:
New York Review Books/Classics.
Weber, Max. (1918) 1946. Science as a Vocation. In From Max Weber: Essays in
Sociology, Trans. and ed. H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford
University Press.
90 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Weber, Marianne. (1926) 2017. Ancestors. In Max Weber: A Biography, Trans. and
ed. Harry Zohn, 1–30. New York: Routledge.
Wimsatt, William K., Jr., and Monroe Curtis Beardsley. 1946. The Intentional
Fallacy. The Sewanee Review 54 (3): 468–488.
Woolf, Virginia. (1925) 1984. In The Common Reader, ed. Andrew McNeillie. San
Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, A Harvest Book.
———. (1927) 1989. To the Lighthouse. New York: Harvest Books/Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich.
CHAPTER 4
Phenomenology
Notice that the transcendental ego did not merely grasp essences in
philosophic contemplation; it was the source, by way of its “intentional-
ity,” of world-constituting essences. Could there be a more ambitious
expression of the modernist aspiration to author meaning in nature and
history? In the context of this narrative, Husserl looks like the Western
mind’s last desperate lunge toward comprehension of an incomprehensi-
ble world. He feels inevitable.
With the centrality of this distinction for modern phenomenology
established, we will turn to Heidegger for a more accessible (and perti-
nent) account of phenomenology’s pivotal role in this story. Heidegger
was both a principal foil and an enduring, if subterranean, influence on
postmodern theory.
But first, four very general and (once again) organizational and rhetori-
cal elements of Husserl’s work show how this discipline and this disciplin-
ary founder belong to the same moment as Durkheim, Moore, Saussure,
and Richards:
point of view. Or look at it this way: a rock may be in contact with the
ground—but it cannot touch the ground.
If you are thinking “that’s because a rock hasn’t got a central nervous
system,” you have fallen back into the science-inspired mode of objectifi-
cation which phenomenology is out to dismantle. Nervous systems may
indeed be necessary conditions, as a matter of scientific fact, for touch-
ing—but that’s beside the point. The lived experience of “touching” has
nothing to do with facts of neurology, but with the phenomenology of
touching itself.
Do we suppose that premodern people with no knowledge of neurol-
ogy don’t know what “touching” is? It is important to dwell upon this
question. It may help to “carve out,” as it were, the phenomenon of
touching itself—and, by extension, the whole realm of experience that
concerns phenomenology.
Back to the rock, in contact with, but not touching the path. Beyond
the sensation itself, touching is directional—just as paths are. Not only can
a rock not feel, it has no orientation in the world, no directionality in time
or space, no implicit connections to anything else. For a rock, the world
has no significance.
That’s why equipment is such a special kind of thing, a sort of interme-
diary between rocks and people. A screwdriver wouldn’t be a screwdriver
if it didn’t have its orientation, its functional segments all “pointing” to
their purpose. It would not be “ready-to-hand,” as Heidegger put it, but
“present-at-hand”—a sheer thing, like a rock.
To say that we are embodied mind, “being-in-the-world,” does not
imply that screwdrivers are conscious. But it does imply that we are con-
scious only through the totality of oriented things that constitute our
world as a world—screwdrivers, paths, tables, chairs, hands and feet, and,
yes, rocks too can come in handy, or, in the limiting case, prove to be
interesting, even beautiful, strewn across a silent landscape.
Unlike a sheer thing, which exists in an enclosed way, consciousness
exists, not merely in an open way, that’s not radical enough—conscious-
ness literally ex-ists, which means it is outside itself. Hence, “there-being.”
Once that becomes evident across the board, a different way of thinking
becomes possible.
In the case of the screwdriver, for example, you could say, just to get the
idea started, that you exist not just “through,” but as the pointing of the
screwdriver. That idea takes on more force when you begin to realize the
general implication, which is that you exist as all the orientations of all the
PHENOMENOLOGY 95
things that constitute your world—that is, all their interrelated pointings,
some in the foreground, most in the background—and, finally, you exist
as that which weaves all their pointings together as a world.2
Hence, “being-in-the-world.”
Or take time. You ex-ist outside yourself in time constantly. That is,
outside the present. This is easy to see. Just monitor your activity without
interrupting it (as suggested by Husserl’s abstention). Notice how com-
pletely your present moments are infused with past moments that “put”
you in your present context and with future moments that are constantly
in the process of actualizing—or not. If you do that, you will find that you,
as you are now, exist almost entirely in past and future moments. And then
you will notice that those moments merge with the directionalities and
orientations of all the significant things and settings that make up your
world. Your past and future consist of possibilities, implicit in those things
and settings, some irrevocably actualized and others not yet. The future
just is possibility and you ex-ist as possibility. The present moment, as an
instant, can’t actually be experienced at all. If you try to “fix” it with your
attention, you will find that it has not quite arrived or just slipped away.
Even Husserl, for all his emphasis on “presence,” called the present instant
an “ideal”—and Derrida would make much of that, as we shall see.
At first, as an objectifying modern accustomed to thinking of yourself
as a present-at-hand mental entity lodged somehow “in” your body, you
may be tempted to say, “Oh, nonsense, I exist entirely in the present and,
in the present, I have memories of the past and plans for the future that
condition my present activity.”
But that’s just how things look to you when you adopt that objectifying
attitude toward yourself—which, as a modern, you automatically do when-
ever discussions like this get under way. Then you appear before the gaze
of your own mind’s eye as a mental-thing that “has” memories and plans
(and feelings and so on). But when you are actually living your life you are
not really like that at all—you are the way I have been describing you.
Consult Proust for confirmation.
Finally, to complete the inventory of your existence as being-in-the-
world, in addition to the pointings of things and the determinations and
possibilities of time, there are the people with whom you share the world—
2
You might feel like saying that the screwdriver is really a piece of plastic and metal with
such-and-such shape and so-and-so mass and so on. Its functions, you might want to say, are
really knowledge that makers and users of screwdrivers have in their Cartesian mind/brains.
When you talk this way, you use sciencey language (that is true in its own explanatory way)
to cover up how you actually live in the world.
96 T. DE ZENGOTITA
a world that embodies you all, more or less intensively, more or less recip-
rocally, depending on the circumstances.
Heidegger thought of his “existential phenomenology” as radically
opposed to the “transcendental phenomenology” of his teacher, Edmund
Husserl—mainly because he had jettisoned the transcendental ego. On
Heidegger’s account, that remnant of Platonic/Kantian Idealism had to
go if consciousness was to recognize itself as the meaning of Being unfold-
ing temporally, and nothing besides, nothing transcendent. But that does
not mean that Heidegger somehow eluded the modernist moment. The
characteristic sense of self-splitting was displaced in his thought to a sense
of himself as divided between an asocial and authentic “being-toward-
death” and a socialized “they-self” unavoidably “fallen” into “average
everydayness.” In a way, Heidegger’s urgent phrasing makes it a more
cogent and value-laden expression of the special sense of destiny that ani-
mated the modernist creator.
It is also worth noting how much Heidegger’s account of time had in
common with Henri Bergson’s distinction between experienced time
(elastic duration) and measured time as well as the affinities between both
and, as already suggested, Proust’s literary treatment of time. The point is
that, for all these modernists, time was no longer just an objective con-
tainer of unfolding historical and natural events; it was, more primordially,
a dimension of the psyche.
With temporality understood as elastic “stretches” of experience,
sometimes punctual, as with an abrupt interruption, sometimes indefi-
nitely extended, as when we “lose track” of it (meaning clock time), so
immersed are we in duration. Time flies when you’re having fun and
slows to crawl when you are waiting for the test results. It seems likely
that the internalization of time3 was an aspect of the gesture of abstrac-
tion, giving modernist creators the authority, as it were, to simply
stipulate—by fiat, by definition—the eternal instants upon which logic,
grammar, and code depend. As we shall see, many French
poststructuralists—steeped as they were in Classical philosophy, thanks to
the French educational system—may have been too quick to read Plato’s
distinction between Being (the Ideas) and becoming into this. The mod-
ernist moment supplied motives of its own for seeking shelter from the
3
See Husserl’s Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness ([1928] 1964). See also Ann
Banfield “Time Passes: Virginia Woolf, Post-Impressionism, and Cambridge Time” in Poetics
Today Fall, 2003.
PHENOMENOLOGY 97
4
See L. Lawlor “Phenomenology and Metaphysics, and Chaos: on the Fragility of the
Event in Deleuze” (2012, 104–106).
5
Gary Gutting calls Sartre “the perfect whipping boy for the attack on Subjectivity”
(2013, 81–82).
98 T. DE ZENGOTITA
6
For accounts of such mishaps, see Cusset (2008), Derrida (2001), and Mathy (2000).
7
Compare Adorno on the “aura of materiality” that lured adherents of phenomenology
away from history.
8
Says Gary Gutting of the creators of French theory: “for each of these philosophers there
is a Nietzsche who is the primary historical antecedent to his anti-Hegelianism” (2013, 84).
PHENOMENOLOGY 99
9
See Merquior (1987, 52) for the difference, on this crucial point, between Levi-Strauss
and Foucault. This also explains why Levi-Strauss was perfectly comfortable talking about
everyday subjectivity when he wasn’t practicing his “science.” Indeed, several of the most
compelling moments in his work revolve around such anecdotes (see, e.g., the description of
the French peasant custom of wine exchange in The Elementary Structures of Kinship ([1949]
1969) and the account of a Bororo chieftain’s appropriation of writing in Tristes Tropique
([1955] 1992)).
100 T. DE ZENGOTITA
References
Baring, Edward. 2011. The Young Derrida and French Philosophy, 1945–1968.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cusset, Francois. 2008. French Theory: How Foucault, Derrida, Deleuze, & Co.
Transformed the Intellectual Life of the United States. Trans. Jeff Fort with
Josephine Berganza and Marlon Jones. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Derrida, Jacques. (1966) 2001. Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the
Human Sciences. In Writing and Difference. Trans. Alan Bass. London:
Routledge.
Gutting, Gary. 2013. Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Heidegger, Martin. 1969 (1929). Being and Time. New York: Harper and Row.
———. (1954) 1977. The Question Concerning Technology. In Basic Writings
from “Being and Time” (1927) to “The Task of Thinking” (1964), Ed. David
Farrell Krell, and Trans. Frank A. Capuzzi with J. Glenn Gray and David Farrell
Krell. New York: Harper & Row.
Husserl, Edmund. (1928) 1964. Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness.
Ed. M. Heidegger and Trans. James S. Churchill. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
———. (1929) 1977. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology.
The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
———. (1954) 1970. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology. Trans. David Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Lawlor, Leonard. 2012. Phenomenology, and Metaphysics, and Chaos: On the
Fragility of the Event in Deleuze. In The Cambridge Companion to Deleuze, ed.
Daniel W. Smith and Henry Somers-Hall, 103–125. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. (1949) 1969. The Elementary Structures of Kinship. Trans.
James Harle Bell and John Richard von Sturmer. Boston: Beacon Press.
———. (1955) 1992. Tristes Tropique. New York: Penguin Group.
Marx-Scouras, Danielle. 1996. The Cultural Politics of Tel Quel: Literature and the
Left in the Wake of Engagement. University Park: University of Pennsylvania
Press.
Mathy, Jean-Philippe. 2000. French Resistance: The French-American Culture
Wars. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Merquior, José Guilherme. 1987. Foucault. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Ryle, Gilbert. (1949) 1984. The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
CHAPTER 5
This chapter takes its title from a landmark anthology, edited by Richard
Rorty, that contains seminal papers in the analytic tradition dating from
the 1930s to the 1960s. But most attention will be given to the develop-
ment of Structuralism on the continent, from Saussure’s linguistics already
mentioned to the work of Claude Levi-Strauss. It will also focus on certain
themes developed by Wittgenstein. Together, these make up the modern-
ist treatments of language that influenced postmodern theory most
directly. This chapter aims to highlight the importance of this question:
what was it about language, and about “signs” more generally, that under-
mined the modern sense of subjectivity when signification itself became
the object of academic study?1
1
“No doubt that is why Western thought took so long to think the being of language: as
if it had a premonition of the danger that the naked experience of language poses for the self
evidence of I think” (Michel Foucault in “The Thought from Outside” in Foucault/Blanchot
1987, 13).
2
Multiple ironies, and a lot of moral credit, attend a comparison of Bruno Latour’s “Why
Has Critique Run out of Steam?” (2004) with Schlick’s assertion that science, unlike phi-
losophy, is actually about something. In that essay, Latour appeals for a new realism and asks
“Was I wrong to participate in the invention of this field known as science studies?”
THE LINGUISTIC TURN 103
3
He also (this is less often remarked) showed how the world would have to be in order for
such a symbolism to be viable.
104 T. DE ZENGOTITA
So Wittgenstein went back to Cambridge and spent the rest of his life
doing for logic and language what Hume had once done for experience:
rendering it contingent. Now there could be no conclusion to philosophy’s
problems. They arose in specific contexts, consequences of specific confu-
sions. The most accomplished abstractionist of the modernist age was
returned to temporality, to history, to speech and performance—to the
“human form of life” in its myriad actuality. That is why the Philosophical
Investigations (1953) is full of little stories, often absurd and comical, for
they are meant to render how things might go on at the very margins of the
“language games” that human beings could possibly play—or maybe not.
The trajectory just described represents the passage from (Enlightenment)
modernity and modernism to what came to be called postmodernism. It
does so with unique cogency, since Wittgenstein made the journey on his
own, in serious dialogue only with his past self, the author of the Tractatus.
But the Philosophical Investigations conveys a sense of the human form of
life that parallels Heidegger’s “Being-in-the-world” remarkably, especially
with respect to the pivotal place of “equipment” (“tools” and “projects”)
in that form of life—with language itself very much a part of the tool kit
(compare Foucault, Deleuze, and Guattari below). Even more remarkable
is the convergence with Derrida. In particular, Wittgenstein’s critique of
sense data and private language—that is, of the modern subject—is
remarkably similar, even in points of detail, to Derrida’s critique of pres-
ence in Husserl’s foundational notion of purely expressive interior mono-
logue (see Chap. 9).4
The point here is this: if Wittgenstein, on his own, navigated a parallel
path from modern to something like “postmodern” thought, then there
must be something—if not logically or causally “necessary,” at least deeply
revealing—about the way the collapse of abstract synchronic systems (gram-
mars, codes) into temporality leads to dissolution for modern subjectivity
and indeterminacy for its essential concepts. Something very real in language
and mind, in the human condition, is at work here. I find that heartening.
5
“We can understand, too, that natural species are chosen not because they are ‘good to
eat’ but because they are ‘good to think’” (Levi-Strauss, Totemism 1963, 89). This widely
quoted remark elevated La Pensee Sauvage above social science explanations that typically
showed how irrational tribal beliefs had latent adaptive functions and so made a kind of
“sense”—our kind of sense.
108 T. DE ZENGOTITA
6
It was not only Structuralism that deployed these tools, of course. It seemed the obvious
way to define disciplinary compartments and fundamental subject matter—a visual jargon,
emblems of expertise. And it was not just Levi-Strauss who relied upon the iconic kinship
charts in particular; all the schools in modernist social and cultural anthropology were deeply
invested in them and associated formalisms.
THE LINGUISTIC TURN 109
7
Modernist kinship theory in the work of Levi-Strauss was built around the idea of women,
as signs, being exchanged. That idiom—especially!—would not survive postmodern critique
in anthropology.
8
The preceding chapter is called “Fugue of the Five Senses.” Every chapter of the book
makes reference to music. In an earlier analysis, music and myth had showed up as congruent
opposites in the structure of the human mind—the one a chorus of senseless sound, the
other a chorus of soundless sense.
THE LINGUISTIC TURN 111
it is in the last resort immaterial whether in this book the thought processes
of the South American Indians take shape through the medium of my
thought or, whether mine take place through the medium of theirs. What
matters is that the human mind, regardless of the identity of those who hap-
pen to be giving it expression, should display an increasingly intelligible
structure as a result of the doubly reflexive forward movement of two
thought processes acting one upon the other, either of which can in turn
provide the spark or tinder whose conjunction will shed light on both.
(1964, 13)
References
Foucault, Michel. 1987. The Thought from Outside. In Foucault/Blanchot.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Garver, Newton, and Seung-Chong Lee. 1994. Derrida & Wittgenstein.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Greif, Mark. 2015. The Age of the Crisis of Man: Thought and Fiction in America,
1933–1973. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Latour, Bruno. 2004. Why Has Critique Run Out of Steam? From Matters of Fact
to Matters of Concern. Critical Inquiry 30 (2): 225–248.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. (1949) 1969. The Elementary Structures of Kinship. Trans.
James Harle Bell and John Richard von Sturmer. Boston: Beacon Press.
———. 1963. Totemism. Trans. Rodney Needham. Boston: Beacon Press.
———. (1964) 1969. The Raw and the Cooked. In Introduction to the Science of
Mythology. New York: Harper and Row.
———. 1966. The Science of the Concrete. In The Savage Mind. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. (1921) 1961. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans.
D.F. Pears and B.F. McGuinness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
———. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford:
Blackwell.
PART III
Masters of Suspicion
That made for a situation rife with temptations. One could pursue
whatever course seemed most promising, provided only that the results
could be cast in terms that might pass muster as “Marxist” in whatever
sense of the word (as yet to be determined) was emerging. As Part IV will
show, one of the principal motivations for postmodern jargon was to jus-
tify and, at the same time, obscure the fact that Marx was actually being
jettisoned by overlapping generations of twentieth-century intellectuals
who didn’t want to admit they had simply been wrong; wrong about the
workings of history and wrong to excuse the criminality of certain regimes.
Some of the most difficult language in French theory gives an appearance
of solidarity with Marxism when radical moves in very different directions
were actually being made. And if the authors themselves were among
those who had to be fooled, it doesn’t take a Nietzsche to see how cleverly
crafted those rhetorical masks would have to be.
Guattari, for example, and in much feminist critique. And Freud himself
had shown the way out of his own residual evolutionism just insofar as the
actual practice of psychoanalysis, the “talking cure”—the scene of empiri-
cal confirmation—actually did depend on radical innovations in theories of
representation in general and language in particular. Freud himself did not
make the linguistic turn but he pointed prepared minds in that direction.
The key was this: Freud took for granted the psychoanalytic evidence of
unconscious wishes and forces revealed to him by patients committed to
close examination of their dreams and fantasies, symptomatic foibles and
slips of the tongue. And what that scrutiny revealed, with shocking regu-
larity, was the existence of incestuous and murderous Oedipal desires and
conflicts in the nuclear family—and the mechanisms of their repression
and sublimation over the course of a child’s development. Freud grounded
his evolutionist claim in Totem and Taboo on that “clinical” evidence.1 And
that was typical. Freud based all his sweeping cultural and historical specu-
lations (Civilization and its Discontents ([1930] 1961); Moses and
Monotheism ([1939] 1967)) on that immediate evidence. His use of
ancient references was founded on the conviction that universals of human
psychology revealed by psychoanalysis operated in human beings at all
times and places. It was not a question of an unfolding over time—the
deep psychic mechanisms he first described in The Interpretation of Dreams
([1899] 2010) were at work in the production of myths and fairy tales all
over the world, across the ages. The axis of origination was shifting.
What took place in the distant past, after all, could never be empirically
known; even archeology, Freud’s favorite hobby, was necessarily highly
speculative. Psychoanalysis, on the other hand, dealt directly with observed
speech and behavior and with theoretical entities in the unconscious that
could account for those observations. The same essential situation as
Galileo and his heat particles but, alas, without the quantifiable precision
supplied by the “primary properties”—which is why, in hindsight, Freud’s
“science” looks more like hermeneutics than physics. But at the time, in
its reliance on empirical immediacy, Freud’s modernist creation felt like a
science in the making (compare I.A. Richards above) because the psychol-
ogy took priority—no matter how tempting the grand sweep of evolution-
ist speculation remained.
1
“Ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny” was Ernst Haeckel’s way of summing up the general
idea, which was influential throughout the nineteenth century and persisted in one form or
another into the twentieth century, especially in developmental psychology. See, for example,
the work of Jean Piaget.
MARX, FREUD, NIETZSCHE 119
remained for Nietzsche, but all sense of direction was gone. This was very much the Nietzsche
Deleuze would introduce to his Parisian audience in 1962—a turning point for their
thinking.
122 T. DE ZENGOTITA
4
Although Kant seems to have coined the term, Heidegger’s usage and Derrida’s appro-
priation of it are most relevant. A conflation of religious and philosophical notions is implied.
That is what Nietzsche intended when he arraigned Platonism and the Judeo-Christian tradi-
tion on the same charge—disguising decadence as idealism.
MARX, FREUD, NIETZSCHE 123
The only valid tribute to thought such as Nietzsche’s is precisely to use it, to
deform it, to make it groan and protest. And if commentators then say that
I am being faithful or unfaithful to Nietzsche, that is of absolutely no inter-
est. (Foucault, in Schrift 1995, 33)
5
Speaking in the name of “youth,” Nietzsche had called for “redemption from the histori-
cal sickness” of his age and urged those still healthy enough to “make use of the past in the
service of life.” This was “effective history” and the lesson was: take what you need from the
past; don’t follow history, create it. On the Utility and Liability of History for Life (1874).
6
Repelling his followers, Zarathustra demanded “Why then should you not pluck at my
laurels?” More specifically, Nietzsche’s “Effective History” (using the past for life-affirming
present purposes) in Untimely Meditations ([1874] 1997) inspired Foucault as well
(“Nietzsche, Genealogy, History” in Language, Counter-Memory, Practice 1980). Compare
Deleuze on “buggering” his favorite philosophers.
124 T. DE ZENGOTITA
pursued their careers, especially in the USA in the last decades of the twen-
tieth century.7 One could read about the power/knowledge dynamics in
eighteenth- and nineteenth-century institutions as Foucault described
them and immediately apply the notion to contemporary university battles
over resources, tenure, and curriculum. And likewise for all sorts of specific
institutional circumstances—power/knowledge relations shaped contem-
porary families, prisons, workplaces, hospitals as they were understood by
theory-inspired activists “thinking globally and acting locally” in the 1970s
and beyond.
So politics went on. It was in this context also that the terms “discourse”
and “discursive practices” took up their now familiar mission: to weave
texts and talk into the same fabric as offices and deeds. And this could all
still be very radical, in some sense of the term—Queer Theory and Cyborg
Manifestos were hardly mainstream. At the same time, by virtue of its
diverse and situational orientation, it was generously conceived—a practical
advantage. Women who wanted to run global corporations could find
something for themselves in identity discourses as readily as organizers of
women who labored in the sweatshops sustaining those corporations.8
Nietzsche had imposed some condition on his heirs, however—and the
one that proved most fortuitous was his insistence that the Cartesian ego
was an artifact of a grammar that insisted on a “subject” for what was actu-
ally a multifarious flowing. He thus planted the seed that would become
Heidegger’s “fallen into inauthentic everydayness,” first of all, and then
Althusser’s “interpellation” and Lacan’s “symbolic” and all their kindred
notions. As a measure of the importance of this theme for the account of
postmodern theory to be given in Part IV, consider this from Alan Schrift’s
Nietzsche’s French Legacy: he is explaining Deleuze and Guattari’s use of
the notion “desiring machines” in their account of the play of will to
power in the socius. “Deleuze’s goal,” he says, “is to place desire into a
functionalist vocabulary, a machinic index, so as to avoid the personifiction
or subjectivation of desire in a substantive will, ego, unconscious, or self”
(Shrift 1995, 68, 69).
7
This helps explain the persistence of theory in the American academy, long after its
moment had passed in France where educational structure and practice is centrally controlled
(See Schrift 2006; Mathy 2000; Kauppi 1996).
8
I once overheard a young man running a workshop on gender issues in a secondary
school recommending a particular “advocacy camp” to a gay student who approached him
after his presentation. I asked “advocacy of what” and he said “anything.” The camp was
“about skills and methods,” regardless of content.
MARX, FREUD, NIETZSCHE 125
9
Nietzsche has always appealed to radicals on the right, of course—the very idea of a
Nietzsche for the left once seemed bizarre. One need only recall the many fascist intellectuals
and artists in the 1920s and 1930s who were every bit as contemptuous of the bourgeoisie
as demonstrators in the streets of Paris in the late 1960s. Hence, the importance of Foucault’s
permission slip.
126 T. DE ZENGOTITA
References
Deleuze, Gilles. (1962) 1983. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Derrida, Jacques. 1994. Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of
Mourning, and the New International. Trans. Peggy Kamuf. New York:
Routledge.
Foucault, Michel. 1980. Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. In Language, Counter-
Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews. Trans. Donald F. Buchard, and
Sherry Simon, 139–164. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Freud, Sigmund. (1899) 2010. The Interpretation of Dreams. New York: Basic
Books.
———. (1913) 1998. Totem and Taboo: Resemblances Between the Mental Lives of
Savages and Neurotics. Mineola: Dover Thrift Editions.
———. (1930) 1961. Civilization and Its Discontents. Trans. James Strachey.
New York: W.W. Norton.
———. (1939) 1967. Moses and Monotheism. New York: Vintage Books.
Kauppi, Niilo. 1996. French Intellectual Nobility: Institutional and Symbolic
Transformations in the Post-Sartrian Era. Albany: State University of New York
Press.
Mathy, Jean-Philippe. 2000. French Resistance: The French-American Culture
Wars. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. (1872) 1967. The Birth of Tragedy and the Case of
Wagner. New York: Knopf, Doubleday Publishing Group.
———. (1874) 1997. On the Utility and Liability of History for Life. In Untimely
Meditations, ed. D. Breazeale and Trans. R.J. Hollingdale. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Safranski, Rüdiger. 2002. Nietzsche: A Philosophical Biography. New York:
W.W. Norton & Company.
Schrift, Alan. 1995. Nietzsche’s French Legacy: A Genealogy of Poststructuralism.
New York: Routledge.
———. 2006. Twentieth-Century French Philosophy: Key Themes and Thinkers.
Malden: Blackwell.
CHAPTER 7
Critical Theory
this job so that they could earn their bread. Then they get what they deserve,
having to shovel snow, I cried out in rage, bursting uncontrollably into
tears. (Adorno Minima Moralia [1951] 2006, 122)
Lowenthal had not been taken in by some façade. Adorno was haunted
all his life by the (undeserved) happiness he knew as boy; he referred to it
constantly, almost automatically, whenever he wanted to talk about feel-
ings in ways that might otherwise be mistaken for Romantic indulgence.
Adorno persisted in his pessimism (he idolized Beckett for purity of
vision), but he still insisted that an “anticipatory glimpse” of possible uto-
pias was discernible in the meanest products of the culture industry. And
childhood, recollected, was the prototype for him.1
Notice this about the snow shovelers incident: however pampered he
may have been, the precocious “Teddie” Adorno—who would head a
Frankfurt School that did more to keep Marxism viable in the twentieth-
century academy than any other body—had not broken into tears out of
pity, at least not as he recalled it looking back. A closer reading (Minima
Moralia’s aphorisms are not explained) provokes the question: was little
Teddie insisting that their plight must be deserved in an effort to subdue
bourgeois sentimentality, even at that age? Or was it because it was dawn-
ing on him that he would not be able accept a society that tolerated the
contrast between their fate and his own (both equally undeserved)? Such
sentiments would, in any case, become a lifelong target of Adorno’s con-
siderable capacity for contempt, starting with his withering attacks on
“comfort music” in concert reviews he was publishing in major venues
while still in his teens. Yet it was not until the mid-1920s that Adorno
began to look to “historical materialism” in a systematic way for specific
intellectual inspiration.
Marxist ideas had been in the air all along, to be sure, and everyone
who was anyone understood that “commodities” were the corruption of
culture. Adorno was against all things bourgeois as a partisan of revolution
in the arts, first of all, in the same way most of the modernists were, as we
have seen—whatever their politics, which were as likely to be right as left.
After WWI, especially, it was almost inevitable that young intellectuals
would blame that catastrophe of modernity on the ascendant bourgeoisie
1
“in the prohibition of the images of hope, hope has its last dwelling place … and in the
strength to name the forgotten that is concealed in the stuff of experience” (Adorno, in
Muller-Doohm 2005: 395).
CRITICAL THEORY 129
and all its works—in spite of, or perhaps because of, the fact that so many
of them were heirs to that ascendancy. So when the time came for Adorno,
under the influence of Lukacs and Horkheimer, to take up a political posi-
tion, he would frame his commitment this way: “What had to be done to
make the spark leap from the realm of art to that of society?” (Muller-
Doohm 2005, 81).
That itinerary tells us a lot about how Adorno, and many others, could
maintain themselves as “Marxists” without joining Communist parties,
without much faith in the proletariat or even in “history” in the nineteenth-
century sense. And, of course, it was precisely those prescient reservations
that helped preserve the credibility of the Frankfurt School as Stalin rose
to power and the Soviet Union asserted imperial prerogatives in Eastern
Europe. Still, reading descriptions of Adorno’s comfortable living arrange-
ments in Los Angeles during WWII—the jolly parties with Chaplin and
Garbo and all that—it is not hard to understand the reactions of more
orthodox believers:
On the second front, and on the other hand, the enemy was named
“positivism”—or materialism, utilitarianism, scientism. The threat from
that quarter was not so much philosophical as it was economic and social—
above all, technological in the broadest sense. This was Western reason
reduced to an instrument of human enterprises, a generator of formulas
and algorithms that might be tolerable if confined to a chemistry labora-
tory but had long since burst its bounds and assumed the name of Reason
entire. The bureaucracy and the factory were the inevitable consequence.3
Of course, positivism/materialism appeared to be the enemy of idealism—
the whole history of philosophy looked like a series of pitched battles
between these antagonists. But critical theory was not taken in by this ideo-
logical sham. In actual fact, idealism and materialism had been in cahoots
all along.4 While debating philosophers distracted those (few) who were
paying attention, the forces of bourgeois society stepped in to divvy up the
cultural goodies. Natural and social reality were assigned to instrumental
reason, while morals, religion, art, and entertainment—the meaning of life,
if you will—went to the mind, the soul, feelings, the realm of the subjec-
tive, the unquantifiable. There, in a by-definition irrational space apart
from the real world, people were granted their illusory freedoms.
“Traditional theory,” positivist theory, was handmaiden to this arrange-
ment. We have seen how claims to value-free objectivity in the newly
minted social and psychological sciences justified descriptions and explana-
tions of human beings of the kind an entomologist might propose for a
comparative treatment of ant species (see Chap. 3, above)? And that was
trumpeted as a virtue! “Critical theory” would be the very opposite of that.
This refusal of the fact/value distinction in the name of a historical reality
that included the theorist would have been enough all by itself to qualify
critical theory for a place at the table when the postmodern moment came.
Now we are in a position to understand what many find most baffling in
Adorno’s view of art, namely, his counter-intuitive insistence that “aesthetic
experience is not a genuine experience until it becomes philosophy”—that
is, until it becomes rational, discursive. This accounts for Adorno’s turn
3
The parallels between this analysis and Foucault’s are eerily rich, but Foucault swears he
was unacquainted with the Frankfurt School (Macey 1995, 326). More evidence of a late-
breaking compressed climax for modernism in France, one that melted almost immediately
from structuralist abstraction back into history—but, with Sartre dislodged, a Nietzschean
history.
4
Compare Derrida on the idealism at the heart of pure materialism in his interview about
Marxism with his former colleagues at Tel Quel (in Positions, (1972) 1981, 39–91).
132 T. DE ZENGOTITA
5
This account obviously comes uncomfortably close to Husserl’s intentionality endowing
objects with conceptual identity—as Adorno certainly realized. Hence, the relentless insis-
tence on historical context as the necessary partner in the disclosure of truth content. Hence,
the changing truth content of art works over time. Compare Walter Benjamin on
translation.
CRITICAL THEORY 133
In each of these cases, the truth content of the artwork was uncovered
in its relation to a social context. Both terms were essential. Dialectical
conceptuality “negated” the reified, unquestioned object (the music
taken-for-granted) and, released now from habituality, allowed thinking to
be “determined” by actual material elements of the music or the context
(the relations between notes, the position of a king on a throne). A con-
nection was made, the truth content of the art object in its context
134 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Adorno believed that the philosophy of modern music was basically nothing
but “the attempt … to explicate the dialectics of the particular and the gen-
eral in concrete terms.” … This applied with particular force to his central
thesis that the twelve-tone method begins with a rational technique which
then transformed into an irrational system that stifles the constructive
impulses of the composer. (Muller-Doohm 2005, 275)
6
Once again, phenomenology’s proximity looms. People who begin to study it in a serious
way often describe an experience of relinquishing agency to things and situations. See, for
example, Merleau-Ponty’s famous account of our three dimensional perception as dependent
on the “eyes” (perspectives) of objects in the environment (in Kelly 2004).
CRITICAL THEORY 135
References
Adorno, Theodor W. (1951) 2006. Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged
Life. Trans. E.F.N. Jephcott. New York: Verso.
———. (1964) 2003. The Jargon of Authenticity. London: Routledge.
———. 2004. Aesthetic Theory. Trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor. New York:
Continuum.
Aronowitz, Stanley. 2015. Against Orthodoxy: Social Theory and Its Discontents.
New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
7
The reader can tell when a work is to be found guilty of commodity fetishism long before
the gavel comes down. For the partisan, of course, that frequency simply reflects the ubiqui-
tous influence of the commodity function. But it is troubling how repetitive (algorithmic?)
the gesture can seem—especially given Adorno’s heartfelt opposition to any theory that
substitutes itself for thought.
136 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Bernstein, J.M. 2006. Against Voluptuous Bodies: Late Modernism and the Meaning
of Painting. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Buck-Morss, Susan. 1979. The Origin of Negative Dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno,
Walter Benjamin, and the Frankfurt Institute. New York: The Free Press.
Derrida, Jacques. (1972) 1981. Positions. Trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. (1944) 2002. Dialectic of
Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Trans. Edmund Jephcott. Stanford:
Stanford University Press.
Lukács, Georg. 1971. The Theory of the Novel: A Historico-Philosophical Essay on the
Forms of Epic Literature. London: Merlin Press.
Macey, David. 1995. The Lives of Michel Foucault. New York: Vintage.
Muller-Doohm, Stefan. 2005. Adorno: A Biography. Trans. R. Livingstone.
Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Thompson, Michael. 2015. Radical Intellectuals and the Subversion of Progressive
Politics: The Betrayal of Politics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
PART IV
Postmodern Undoings
Introduction
The conceptual understanding of empirical reality is equivalent to a murder.
(Alexandre Kojeve, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel (in Borch-Jacobsen
1991, 192))
Apart from the shock value of Kojeve’s phrasing, the view of concepts he
was propounding in the 1930s reflected what would become conven-
tional wisdom among creators of French theory—a legacy of Heidegger’s
teaching for which they would eventually credit (justifiably) Nietzsche, a
more welcome ancestry for thinkers determined to rid themselves of all
things phenomenological. That transfer of credit for so essential a claim
encapsulates the most proximate intellectual-historical move that shaped
the postmodern moment in France. But really understanding the signifi-
cance of that move means understanding the historical context that
prompted Nietzsche to pursue his deconstructive mission in the first
place. Chapters 2, 3, 4, 5, and 6 described that context. Chapter 7, deal-
ing with essentials of critical theory by way of Adorno, bears directly on
how postmodernism was received in the anglophone academy, but
French theory, in spite of striking convergences, apparently developed
without Frankfurt School influence. We can hope that this is more evi-
dence of an underlying logic at work—some logic that might be brought
to light and evaluated so that we can do a bit better than blunder and
grope toward whatever comes next.
138 Postmodern Undoings
So Part IV, the heart of this book, has been historically situated. It
will succeed in proportion to the validity of these claims: French theo-
ry’s seminal texts are so difficult because (1) they strive for an appear-
ance of continuity with Marx when radical moves in very different
directions were actually being made, and/or (2) they reject the abstrac-
tions of Structuralism and return to temporality, to performance, and to
history—but without the subject, without allowing significant reference
to the intentions and feelings of actual human beings. That profoundly
counterintuitive constraint forced the framers of theory into elaborate
syntactic and lexical contortions in their effort to return to the func-
tioning of language without resorting to subject talk.1 The transcen-
dental ego of Husserl’s phenomenology, like the brain-code grammar
(langue) in Saussure and Levi-Strauss, could never be mistaken for the
living, speaking person. Modernist self-splitting in creator/authors
reflected that fact (see above, Chap. 3). So when those abstractions
were rejected in the name of temporality—history, events—the place of
the subject had to be taken by something equal to the explanatory task
those abstractions had performed. That something would be described
in terms like “field of the mark” (Derrida), “process of signification”
(Kristeva), “event of utterance” (Deleuze), and so on. The result, as we
shall see, was a strange Hegelian knock-off that, in effect, put language
(or, in Deleuze’s case, “expression”) in place of Absolute Mind. But
before that could happen the mind of Man—the existential-phenome-
nological mind—would stake a claim to the position once held by
Hegel’s Absolute, a claim that was bound to be rejected.
Among the Parisian luminaries who attended Alexandre Kojeve’s
groundbreaking lectures on Hegel at the École Pratique des Hautes Études
in the 1930s were Louis Althusser, Raymond Queneau, Georges Bataille,
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, André Breton, Jacques Lacan, Raymond Aron,
and, according to some reports, Jean-Paul Sartre himself. Those lectures
consolidated a turn to Hegel in France before WWII and inspired the
Marxist-existential phenomenology that would dominate the scene until
the rise of Structuralism and the revival of Nietzsche in the late 1950s and
1960s. In Vincent Descombes’ opinion, only the Russian Revolution can
1
Derrida gave the game away when he casually remarked that he used the phrase “func-
tioning of the mark” rather than “understanding the written utterance” merely to accom-
modate the possibility of misunderstanding (1988: 61).
Postmodern Undoings
139
2
Gary Gutting (2013) shows that Kojeve’s influence has actually been exaggerated in
hindsight at the expense of the influence of Jean Hyppolite and Jean Wahl. But it is the
founding myth that concerns us here. See also Alan Schrift in Bourg 2004 for an American
tendency to overlook the influence of philosophy of science during this period.
3
The overarching example, from Hegel’s Logic: think pure “Being” (not the being of any
particular) and you will find you are thinking “Nothing.” Negate the negating relation, but
preserve both terms, and a synthesis emerges: “Becoming.”
4
Said Hegel: “For Spirit, there is nothing whatever that is entirely other” (in Macdonald
and Ziarek (eds), Adorno and Heidegger (2008, 88)).
140 Postmodern Undoings
5
Yet another, apparently historically unrelated, convergence between poststructuralist and
Frankfurt School critique. For discussion of this theme in France in the wake of the 1968, see
Peter Starr The Logics of Failed Revolt (1995).
Postmodern Undoings
141
Of course, one can always conclude that trying to think the impossible
was a wrongheaded way to spend time, whatever (or because of) the
motives. But first the works deserve consideration on their own terms. So,
in keeping with the spirit of the enterprise, this formula—meant to evoke
Lacan’s mysterious algebras:
( ( PH + STR × N / F ) − M = PoMo )
Which says that phenomenology plus Structuralism times a mash-up of
Nietzsche and Freud minus Marx equals Postmodernism.
Where “–Marx” suggests the presence of his absence, of course.
The chapters in this part will discuss some of the most representative
postmodern thinkers and some of their most influential texts. But in order
to clarify what the texts were doing the ban on subject talk (see above) will
frequently be violated so as to bring out what they would have been saying
had that ban not existed in the first place. Chapter 8 begins with a brief
account of Jacques Lacan and Louis Althusser, elders presiding over the
nativity scene—encouraging, scolding, anointing. It then attempts to
evoke something of atmosphere, the mood of the moment when French
theory was born—a moment-of-multiple-moments captured and released
in real time through the pages of the journal Tel Quel and in the deeds and
words of the power couple who were its guiding spirits, Philipe Sollers and
Julia Kristeva. A principal aim of this chapter is to show how closely con-
ditioned the whole process was by politics, especially by the “events” of
1968.6 Chapter 9 focuses on individual thinkers and shows that, in spite of
passionate and sometimes painful differences, they were all pursuing basic
aims they took for granted even as they competed ferociously to produce
the most effective strategies. Chapter 10 will turn to the reception of
French theory in anglophone contexts, and Chap. 11 will offer a post-
postmodern theory of “theory” that expands on the narrative outlined in
Chap. 2 and brings the story to the present moment. Chapter 12 will
“Event” was the term of choice. Labels like “revolution,” “rebellion,” and “revolt,” so
6
embedded in French historical experience, looked almost quaint when applied to what trans-
pired in May of 1968. Whatever this outpouring was—it was something else. It is no coinci-
dence that the idea of “event” carried such heft in subsequent theorizing, especially in the
work of Deleuze, Lyotard, and Baidou (who taught together at the radical experimental
university at Vincennes in 1969).
Postmodern Undoings
143
the problem of language has never been simply one problem among others.
But never as much as at present has it invaded, as such, the global horizon
of the most diverse researches. … This inflation of the sign “language” is the
inflation of the sign itself, absolute inflation … language itself is menaced in
its very life, helpless, adrift in the threat of limitlessness. (Jacques Derrida
[1967] 1974, 92)
References
Borch-Jacobsen, Mikkel. 1991. Lacan: The Absolute Master. Trans. Douglas Brick.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Bourg, Julian. 2004. After the Deluge: New Perspectives on the Intellectual and
Cultural History of Postwar France. Lanham: Lexington Books.
7
The American pragmatists—John Dewey in particular—shared Nietzsche’s view of lan-
guage’s representational inadequacy but, being American (hopeful, practical), they did not
locate the fault in language itself but in the philosophies that made the mistake of thinking
language was representationally adequate in the first place. Like everything else in Darwinian
nature, language was its best self when it worked, however the face of reality might appear to
God’s eyes.
Postmodern Undoings
145
Breton, André. (1924) 1996. The Lost Steps. Trans. Mark Polizzotti. Lincoln:
University of Nebraska Press.
Deleuze, Gilles. (1967) 2004. How Do We Recognize Structuralism? In Desert
Islands and Other Texts: 1953–1974. Trans. Mike Taormina. Los Angeles:
Semiotext(e).
Derrida, Jacques. 1988. Limited Inc. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Gutting, Gary. 2013. Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Kristeva, Julia. 2002. Intimate Revolt: And, the Future of Revolt. Trans. Janine
Herman. New York: Columbia University Press.
Lyotard, Jean-Francois. (1979) 1984. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on
Knowledge. Trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Macdonald, Iain, and Krzysztof Ziarek, eds. 2008. Adorno and Heidegger:
Philosophical Questions. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Starr, Peter. 1995. The Logics of Failed Revolt: French Theory After May 68’.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Turkle, Sherry. 1981. Psychoanalytic Politics: Freud’s French Revolution. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
CHAPTER 8
the peculiar modern French branch of the great western tradition of philo-
sophical thinking … seek[s] immediate translation of all positions of debate
in terms of very contemporary politics. (Alan Montefiore, Foreword to
Modern French Philosophy 1980)
1
For young Americans in revolt in the 1960s, and for decades thereafter, the 1950s played
an analogous role—captured in images of ticky-tacky suburban uniformity, housewives in
high heels cooing over gleaming washing machines, commuter husbands in gray flannel suits.
The poolside party Dustin Hoffman’s parents held for their son (The Graduate (1967)),
featured this iconic scene: an overbearing business man, intending to do his good deed for
the day, drapes a possessive arm over young Dustin’s shoulder and confides: “One word for
you, young man, just one—plastics.”
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 149
assigned an important role to these “ISAs, one which kept him on the cut-
ting edge of theory’s development for years to come.”2 They were princi-
pally responsible for reproducing “relations of production” by imposing
identities defined by a “social unconscious” on society’s members. For a
generation of young radicals, especially party members, as anxious as their
predecessors to identify with revolution against the bourgeois order and,
at the same time, as anxious to keep up with the latest trends in avant-
garde thought, Althusser offered a perfect solution. One could participate
in the cultural turn, the linguistic turn—one could succumb to the lure of
Structuralism and even try to move beyond it—and still claim allegiance to
Marx and historical materialism. Taken-for-granted categories, norms, and
activities invited a new form of “ideology critique.” Thanks to Structural
ism, an aspect of the personal unconscious could now be treated “scientifi-
cally,” as cultural code, as what Lacan had called “the Symbolic” or “the
big Other” in his account of subject formation.
Althusser’s project also converged with the Tel Quel program for cultural
politics, especially in the late 1960s when Philippe Sollers was leading that
collective into open alliance with the French Communist Party (PCF). He
was stressing more and more strongly the materiality of texts, thus main-
taining his anti-idealist bona fides, while, at the same time, providing intel-
lectual ammunition for Party intellectuals committed to de-Stalinization. So
an insistence on a certain autonomy for the arts—for culture generally—was
the message from both these prestigious intellectual sources, the most
potent possible message to send to intellectual opponents of Stalinist ortho-
doxy—appealing, as it did, to their need to feel that the work they did best
and cared about most could also c ontribute directly to the revolutionary
cause by dismantling bourgeois conventions and, by extension, the institu-
tions that sustained them (Marx-Scouras 1996, 146–149).
2
Francois Dosse stresses the importance of a convergence between Althusser and an ascen-
dant Foucault: “After 1968 Althusserians left their ivory towers, where they had limited
themselves to simple exegeses of Marx’s ideas, in order to meet the real world. It was from
this perspective in 1970 that Althusser defined a vast research program with his famous
article on the SIAs: State Ideology and Ideological Apparatuses … his positions were closer
to those of Michel Foucault in 1969, when he argued that the discursive order needed to be
complemented by the study of non-discursive practices. … For both Althusser and Foucault,
ideology had a material existence incarnated by institutional practices. … Althusser’s under-
taking was the most ambitious and totalizing in the gamut of speculative structuralism. …
[It] prepared the way for a historicized structuralism, incarnated by Michel Foucault, among
others” (1977, 167–168, 188).
150 T. DE ZENGOTITA
used concepts that diminished not only its importance but questioned its
very existence in the conventional sense—that critic had returned with his
last words to the sanctity of the confessional in order to “represent” and
“express” his personal experience as if that were, at the end of the day,
what mattered most to him after all. No wonder so many of Althusser’s
students and allies resisted his legal heir’s decision to publish The Future
Lasts a Long Time. Pierre Machery spoke for many of them when he called
it “a tissue of lies and half-truths” (in Fetterer 2006, 113).
Not coincidentally, it seemed, it was also in that last book that Althusser
renounced his hopes for the realization of communism in history. At the
same time, he loosened the explanatory parameters to which he had always
submitted in the name of science and proposed instead an “aleatory mate-
rialism” more in keeping with the Nietzschean conjuncture of the day. But
by that time no one was listening.
Jacques Lacan was a more slippery character—though tormented in his
own way as well, at least in the end. He often spoke “in the Name (pun-
ning ‘nom’ and ‘non’) of the Father”—of the Law, of the Symbolic Order,
and of the Oedipal scene. But that was only because he thought that
unconscious subjection to society and culture was as unavoidable as falling
into inauthentic everydayness had been for Heidegger’s Dasein.3 The con-
stituents of the ego as imago (real desires having been condemned to
reach perpetually for impossible fulfillment) were drawn entirely from the
social symbolic, especially language. There was no other way for a person
to exist. Hence, Lacan’s famous “subject of the signifier.” In accepting this
tragic “lack” at the heart of desire, Lacan was retracing the itinerary Freud
had sketched out in broad strokes in Civilization and its Discontents
(1930) and taking a similar satisfaction in confronting humanity with its
ultimate futility. That tragic posture appealed to many modernist c reators—
and one of the theory’s strategies for overcoming the modern took aim at
this perverse negativity in the name of proliferating jouissance and affirma-
tive desire (see especially Deleuze, Chap. 9).
But if Lacan seemed to enjoy confronting his audiences (and his analy-
sands) with the tragic necessity of prohibition in the economy of the
3
Gary Gutting thinks Heidegger’s main legacy for French philosophy in the 1960s was the
conviction that, whatever the way forward, Classical metaphysics was exhausted (2013, 60).
But Heidegger’s focus on the “average everydayness” of Dasein, thrown into a social and
linguistic setting, seems to me ancestral also—not only to Lacan’s “symbolic” and Althusser’s
“ideological apparatus,” but to Barthes’ “doxa,” Derrida’s “general text,” Foucault’s “dis-
cursive practices,” and Bourdieu’s “habitus.”
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 153
psyche—his followers understood that his heart lay with hopeless desire,
without object, without end, the truth of a nameless subject lost in “the
real” beyond words, beyond the reach of the social symbolic.4 That is why
Lacan’s influence extended beyond the Structuralism he espoused and
played an important role in shaping various manifestations of post-
structuralism’s efforts to think the impossible (see, especially, Kristeva sec-
tion in this chapter and Deleuze and Guattari, Chap. 9). Lacan’s account
of “castration,” for example, made it a perfect “symbol for the loss of an
ideal wholeness analogous to traditional notions of presence and truth”
(Gutting 2013, 105; see Derrida section, Chap. 9). And that was typical of
the way Freud was put to use by theory; he served as a storehouse of imag-
ery that turned out to implicate much more than individual psychology.
Lacan made his modernist allegiance to the real more and more evident
as the 1970s unfolded and he began to devote his time to lecture/perfor-
mances. He turned away from the pedestrian task of therapeutic practice
and committed himself fully to theory, now expressed by his totemic
“mathemes” and Borromean knots by means of which he seriously pro-
posed what he had once consigned to impossibility—namely, penetrating
to the real after all. Or was this a surrealist parody of traditional “para-
noid” theorizing? Or was it both? Did it start as a parody and become
serious? Opinions differ. It is hard to tell. In this instance, as in so many
others, we must accept that obscurity inevitably attends efforts to think
the inconceivable, regardless of how sincere or insincere particular think-
ers may have been in this or that context.
An anecdote to dramatize the perhaps unbridgeable gulf between an
oh-so-French intellectual personality like Jacques Lacan and the solid citi-
zens who set the tone in the anglophone academy: in Psychoanalytic
Politics (1981), Sherry Turkle invites us to a presentation by Jacques (“I
came to speak”) Lacan before an audience of American mathematicians,
linguists, and philosophers at MIT. It is hard to imagine a more illuminat-
ing encounter, at least in hindsight. This hilarious scene was topped off
during Q&A with this response to an earnest American’s inquiry about
the exterior/interior distinction in human studies. Lacan was elaborately
dubious—“he was not at all certain that man even had an interior”:
4
But his language, and the categorical tone—“necessity,” “the real”—no matter how
obscure the referents, suggest that he retained the aspiration of an older generation: he
wanted truth.
154 T. DE ZENGOTITA
The only thing that seems to testify to it is that which we produce as excre-
ment. The characteristic of a human being—and this is very much in con-
trast with other animals—he doesn’t know what to do with his shit. He is
encumbered by his shit. … Of course it is true that we are always coming
across cat shit, but a cat counts as a civilized animal. But if you take ele-
phants, it is striking how little space their leavings take up in nature, whereas
when you think of it, elephant turds could be enormous. The discretion of
the elephant is a curious thing. Civilization means shit, cloaca maximus. (In
Turkle 1981, 238)
This section’s lead quote is taken from a graffiti slogan that went viral
on the walls of Paris in the spring of 1968. Coined by “sexo-leftists” deter-
mined to outrage bourgeois morality, its application can be expanded to
capture the spirit of theory’s paradoxical undertakings more generally.6 An
overview of their unfolding, as experienced month to month by Parisian
intellectuals caught up in the birth of what would become “theory,” is
best provided from the vantage point of the journal/collective Tel Quel. In
a 1996 review of books about that enterprise, Frederic Jameson recalled
that Tel Quel had once “seemed to offer the most prestigious theoretical
synthesis of the age, so that the fate, not just of theory itself—now pro-
nounced dead by some—is at stake here but also some of its components:
Marxism, psychoanalysis, linguistics” (“Apres le Avant Garde,” London
Review of Books 1996). And the first thing anglophone readers need to
understand about the intellectual provenance of those events is this: “If
there was a May ’68 mindset, it was not to be found among the propo-
nents of Structuralism, but rather among its adversaries. … May 1968
exhumed what Structuralism had repressed. History once again became a
subject for discussion, even among linguists” (Dosse 1997, 115–117). No
doubt the word “seemed” in Jameson’s assessment should be stressed—
but, to the extent that we can take his praise at face value, it is because, as
a Marxist, he welcomed any effort to return to history after all that time
spent languishing in The Prison House of Language (Jameson 1972). And
this was the essential postmodern gesture, this rejection of abstraction,
formalism, compartmentalization—and, even though the most vital source
of French theory was certainly Nietzsche, not Marx, enough common
5
See Peter Starr, The Logics of Failed Revolt (1995).
6
Every boundary, every category, was suspected of owing its existence to some prohibi-
tion, some violent exclusion.
156 T. DE ZENGOTITA
7
Les Temps Modernes was in turn conceived in reaction to the fate of the premiere intel-
lectual journal of the first half of the twentieth century, La Nouvelle Revue Française. Its
apolitical commitment to literature and art made the NRF an easy mark for sophisticated
Nazi occupiers and it succumbed with barely a murmur. “Engagement” became a byword at
Les Temps Modernes for good reason (Marx-Scouras 1996, 11–17).
8
For French intellectuals, the “postmodern” begins with the radical artistic and literary
innovators of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. “Modern,” unless qualified
in some way, suggests the Third Republic, bourgeois convention, and so on. In his interview
with Clare Parnet (see “C is for Culture”), Gilles Deleuze waxes nostalgic in very revealing
ways about the Liberation, and the rich years after, discovering and especially rediscovering
things from before the war in philosophy and the arts.
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 157
9
By the end of the 1960s, however, when Tel Quel was insisting on the materiality of the
text and consequently on writing as political action, Sollers turned against the original sur-
realists—especially Breton. They were indicted for an “idealist,” even “spiritualist,” effort to
preserve the autonomy of art and artists and for the popularity of their works with bourgeois
audiences. Tel Quel affiliated itself instead with Bataille and Artaud, “dissident surrealists”
who insisted on the materiality of a subject identified with the body and whose works held
no appeal for bourgeois sensibilities (Marx-Scouras 1996, 159–164).
158 T. DE ZENGOTITA
And it promised these culture warriors that they could be good Marxists
still as they returned to history in this new guise.
That promise was to be justified in theory by an emphasis on the mate-
rial aspects of language—on “writing” and “textuality.” In 1967,
Kristeva’s first paper on textuality was published in Tel Quel, Derrida’s
Writing and Difference appeared under its aegis, and Sollers himself
announced a “Program” which explicitly, as a matter now of doctrine,
linked “a theory of textuality to a critique of society and culture of Marxist
dimensions” (Marx-Scouras 1996, 12). Soon enough, it would be
decided that everything was writing but, at the beginning of the process
of linguistic materialization, special honors went to the so-called limit
texts produced by the likes of de Sade, Lautreamont, Mallarme, and
Artaud and celebrated, with particular effect, by Georges Bataille who
welcomed the forces limit texts released and disseminated. “Writing,” in
other words, aimed above all to distinguish itself from language under-
stood as representation, depiction—which implicates the image of lan-
guage as communication between Cartesian subjects conveying ideas
between minds across divides of physical space and the bodies that popu-
lated it like so many marbles in a jar (see the Saussure diagram, above;
compare Walter Benjamin’s “Task of the Translator”). That was not
enough for ultra-structuralists bent on intervening as Marxists in history
by way of art. The materiality of writing, on the other hand, promised
efficacy on the plane of actual events, and all the more so when compared
(as Derrida did so compellingly) with ephemera of speech, voice, con-
cept. Hence, an emergent article of faith for creators of French theory—
even Deleuze, the metaphysical outlier, was committed to it: language,
now understood as “writing,” was production, not representation. In
perhaps its most influential issue, the Division of the Assembly (Theorie
d’ensemble October, 1968), Tel Quel hailed the advent of that long-sought
alliance between art and action. In all caps, it admonished: “WRITING
IN ITS PRODUCTIVE FUNCTION IS NOT REPRESENTATION”
(in The Tel Quel Reader 1998, 22). Years later, looking back, Sollers iden-
tified “the fundamental aesthetic error—the political economic error” as
“believing that language is a simple i nstrument of representation (Writing
and the Experience of Limits Columbia 1983, 71).”
As these theoretical commitments were being established, Sollers led
the journal’s collective into an ongoing and, for a while at least, mutually
advantageous dialogue with the PCF. Tel Quel got to burnish its creden-
tials as a partisan of the working classes, an increasingly important qualifi-
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 159
was truly History! Almost overnight Tel Quel’s offices were transformed,
festooned with revolutionary Chinese graphics. Mao was quoted in an
epigraph to the next issue of the journal (“A mortal combat has been
declared between the new culture and reactionary cultures”). Statements
like this were issued:
Down with the corrupt Bourgeoisie! Down with filthy revisionism! Down
with the binarism of the super-powers! Long live de la Chine! Long Live
revolutionary China! Long live the thought of Mao Tse-Tung! (In Marx-
Scouras 1996, 169)
With a 1981 Sollers essay called “Why I was Chinese” in focus, Marx-
Scouras goes on to sum up the rationale behind the fateful turn toward
Maoism. She notes an underlying irony—namely, that the Tel Quel pro-
gram for a cultural politics had actually had more in common with the
partisans of May 1968 than with PCF critics of that uprising, whose views
Tel Quel had endorsed:
“Merely repeating the axiom that intertextuality was a materialism did not
make it so” but this “longing to anchor their symbolic revolution in in
materiality” is what “led the Telquelians, after a brief flirtation with the
Communist Party, into an equally flighty dalliance with Maoism” (2011,
2). Cecilia Sjoholm sums it up this way:
12
Sollers once went so far as to call Tel Quel a theoretical organ of Derridean deconstruc-
tion. He singled out Of Grammatology and admonished his readers that no “thinking can
henceforth avoid situating itself with respect to this event.” (“Le reflexe de reduction,” in Tel
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 163
So determined was Sollers to effect this union that he insisted that the
“production and circulation of meaning” in material texts showed that “the
man who is nothing [the ‘dead’ author, see Barthes below, Chap. 9] and the
one who has nothing [the worker] are thus profoundly joined” (1983, 84).
It was a stretch, even then.
Even in 1968, with the soundtrack from Godard’s La Chinoise pounded
out invocations of “Mao! Mao!” through apartment windows thrown
open to the May morning and echoing down the streets of Paris, sum-
moning the faithful to the barricades; even then, it was a stretch; for the
coming alliance of de Gaulle’s government and the Communist labor
unions was already taking shape.
Quel: Theorie d’ensemble, 1968 p. 303). Jacques Derrida’s disingenuously articulated materi-
alism served him as well at Tel Quel as it did at ENS, under Althusser.
13
Francois Mauriac was a renowned Nobel Prize-winning author, one of a cohort of
Catholic intellectuals actively opposed to Fascism. Louis Aragon was a surrealist poet and
journalist, actively affiliated with the PCF, who became something of a gatekeeper for aspir-
ing writers on the Left. Francis Ponge was a poet and an essayist, influenced by surrealism,
active in the resistance, and a PCF member until the end of WWII. It would be hard to
imagine a core of supporters more suited to help Sollers in his ascent to the summit.
164 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Sollers managed the infighting skillfully and, by 1962, with the well-timed
publication of his own “new novel” (Le Parc), he was emerging as a leader
without rival. Robbe-Grillet himself was happy to claim the honor of being
the “father of Philippe Sollers” and Louis Pinto, in 1978, would remember
him in those days as an emerging “intellectual emperor.”
From that position, entirely independent of the university system,
Sollers was able to penetrate the academy and engage “humanities stu-
dents in their continuing search for master thinkers to legitimize symbolic
ruptures” and to decide whom, beside himself, might qualify for that posi-
tion. And certain professors within those institutions (Barthes, Foucault,
Derrida) found it advantageous to appear in the pages of Tel Quel in quest
of precisely that status. Its cachet contributed to their accumulating “social
capital” and, of course, Tel Quel could claim a certain academic credibility
in return. Together, then, the intellectual emperor and the rebellious aca-
demics promoted a “symbolic revolution as a way to integrate avant-
gardism, structuralist linguistics, and radical politics” (Bourg 2011, 2).
The arrangement was typical of the real genius of Philippe Sollers; his
contributions to theory may not stand out in hindsight, especially com-
pared to those of Julia Kristeva (they were married in 1968), but as a cul-
tural entrepreneur in that historical moment he was without peer.
So, with 1968 on the horizon and his track record as an oracle of the
avant-garde established, Sollers found an “echo chamber” within the
institutions he at the same time scorned. His “strategy involved progres-
sive moves announced suddenly; provocations, made largely as a function
of changes in the political climate; games of contradiction; and, most of
all, criticism of all institutions. … For fear of being labeled as a follower,
Sollers constantly rejuvenated himself.” His mission was to deposit a series
of the so-called power-ideas into that echo chamber, ideas that resonated
across “texts, ideas, persons, collectivities, institutions, materiality and his-
tory” (Kauppi 1994, 37). Danielle Marx-Scouras chose well when she
called her book The Cultural Politics of Tel Quel (1996), and if, as I will
argue in conclusion, postmodern politics is distinguished above all by the
energy it devotes to expression, getting voices heard, raising awareness, col-
lecting likes and followers, going viral, creating memes—in short, to get-
ting attention—then that tendency was discernible long before Facebook
and Twitter came along. Now, most of our politics is cultural and so-called
identity politics, with all its intersectional complexity—including recent
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 165
an experience that the ban on subject talk would not allow theory to repre-
sent (that forbidden function), but it was readily accessible anyway to people
playing the language game of theory. The dominating analogy from the lin-
guistic side saw the signifier pursuing (impossible) “fulfillment” in the
signified—where “fulfillment” meant union, completion (Derrida’s “pres-
ence”). Kristeva herself was an enthusiastic contributor to this ubiquitous
trope of the wandering signifier.16 But in her work the oft-obscured source
of the power of this image of the untethered signifier—namely, the ordi-
nary subjective experience of desire—was more transparently proposed: the
experience we have of desire as never quite getting there, and certainly not
staying there. We all know what that feels like.
As with Lacan and Derrida and all the rest of them, so with Kristeva:
she too was out to dismantle what Deleuze would call Saussure’s “des-
potic sign.” Despotic because, in the synchronic realm of the code, sheer
stipulation was sufficient to command the complete presence of signified
to signifier. And it was that formal (invisible, offstage) stipulation that was
disrupted by the return to temporality and performance simply because of
what desire is, what we all know it to be from first-hand experience.
Structured by analogy with desire, the moment of the signifier meaning
something (intending, pointing, naming) precedes the moment of that
which is meant (thing, concept) and the next moment of meaning some-
thing is upon us before we have grasped that which was meant completely.
Where desire propels signification, all encounters between signifier and
signified are glancing. Time was back with a vengeance.
And so we have another example of how violating the ban on subject
talk can help to clarify theory.17 The question in the end will be—how
much of what theory was doing gets lost when the ban gets broken?
Kristeva’s use of the term “semiotic” in her “semanalysis” was idiosyn-
cratic. She used it in opposition to Lacan’s “Symbolic”—to mean the
body and its inarticulate surges and rhythms (tones, gestures) and she
made that body the driving force in signification, as just described. Indeed,
she shared with Deleuze and other Lacan-inspired ultra-structuralists a
16
The proximate source of this notion of fulfillment is Husserl’s distinction between an
intentional relation with some entity that is “fulfilled” because it is actually perceived as
opposed to one that is merely indicated or supposed in thought or speech. Once again we
can’t help but notice the remarkable influence of phenomenology on the thinking of its fierc-
est critics.
17
Again, I am not saying “why did they indulge in obscurity, why didn’t they just come out
and say it thusly if that’s what it comes down to?” In fact, they believed they were transgress-
ing conventional conceivability and were committed to that project.
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 169
8.3.1 Kristeva’s Gadget
But perhaps the most ingenious—and certainly the most influential—of
Kristeva’s innovations reflected her earlier investment in the discourse of
writing and textuality, not psychoanalysis. At the age of 24, having just
arrived in Paris from Communist Bulgaria, she introduced a new line of
thought inspired by the Russian formalists to an influential seminar chaired
by Roland Barthes at the École Pratique des Hautes Études (EPHE) early
in 1966 (for the importance of this seminar, see Kauppi 1996, 118–119).19
The controlling notion was a construct she fashioned on the fly and frankly
called a “gadget.”20 Francois Dosse makes clear how the pressures of intel-
lectual fashion among the textualistes with whom she was working at Tel
Quel and EPHE had as much to do with its creation as did the logic of her
developing theory. He describes the origins “intertextuality” this way:
19
Kristeva herself recalls her arrival on the scene this way: “Having come to France under
the auspice of the Gaullist dream of a ‘Europe from the Atlantic to the Urals,’ I felt I had
found in this territory that stretched from the publishing house of Le Seoul to the … EPHE
… a cosmopolitanism that transcended the socialist and European domains and that consti-
tuted a continent of thought, speculation, and writing corresponding to the high points of
the universalistic legend of Paris” (2002, 6).
20
The term carry the connotation of “gimmick,” to be sure—but it is important to remem-
ber that Deleuze and Foucault especially were responding to deconstruction’s assault on con-
cepts (including the concept of “concept”) by insisting that they were best dealt with as
“tools,” that meaning lay in their use. And this, apparently, without any input from Wittgenstein.
21
Compare, again, Derrida coining the term “field of the mark” so that the possibility of
misunderstanding a bit of “writing” enjoyed the same status as understanding it and the state
of mind of the subject would be rendered moot.
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 171
In this crucial case, we have it from the horse’s mouth: what I intended
metaphorically when I first coined the phrase “ban on subject talk” in
reference to Alan Schrift’s revealing explanation of some Deleuzean jar-
gon was experienced as a literal ban by this brilliant young woman from
Europe’s provinces absorbing the rhetorical customs of her prestigious
hosts in Europe’s intellectual capital. Perhaps only Derrida, catering to
Althusser’s materialism as his assistant at ENS while he wrote Of
Grammatology, was as conscious of creating conceptual “gadgets” to
disguise the subject’s role in the functioning of language (see below, Chap.
9). In any case, he and Barthes were only the most prominent of the
ultra-structuralists to realize the possibilities inherent in Kristeva’s
improvised formulation. Thanks to her contribution, it became much
more plausible to claim, and perhaps even to believe, that ideas, mean-
ings, values—all things cultural, aesthetic, ethical, mental—were actually
material processes operating independently of their ephemeral and
wholly derivative subjective effects. Derrida’s famous paper, “Structure,
Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences,” often credited
for launching anglophone post-structuralism, was presented at Johns
Hopkins in Baltimore in October of 1966 (after Kristeva presented at
EPHE). Derrida was clearly wielding Kristeva’s gadget in that seminal
paper and many of the subject-avoidance techniques he deployed from
then on owed much to it as well. By the time the Tel Quelians were
meeting with Communist party intellectuals at a climactic conference in
April 1968 to realize the paradoxical dream of a “structuralist Marxism,”
Kristeva’s influence was generally recognized. Francois Dosse reports:
“This colloquium at Cluny was extraordinary: Kristeva was the diva, and
others were on bended knee before her. It was even pathetic intellectu-
ally to see the relationship” (1997, 90).
To be able to account for the functioning of language at the level of
material events without referring to the mentalities of individual subjects
was manna from heaven for Marxists in particular and materialists in
general. And, moving away from the 1960s context in France, Kristeva’s
creation found widespread acceptance among anglophone poststructur-
alists because of a striking, apparently accidental, convergence with the
Hypertext craze of the late 1980s and 1990s. There was no denying the
experience of making and using links between online texts: it just was
“intertextuality,” concretely realized, not just conceptually—but the
172 T. DE ZENGOTITA
8.3.2 Kristeva’s Politics
One of the problems with Kristeva’s account of the revolutionary subject is
that it slides over the question of revolutionary agency … her emphasis on
the semiotic as an unconscious force precludes any analysis of the conscious
decision-making processes that must be part of any collective revolutionary
project. The stress on negativity and disruption, rather than on questions of
organization and solidarity, leads Kristeva in effect to an anarchist and sub-
jectivist political position. … Allon White also accuses Kristeva of political
ineffectiveness, claiming that her politics “remain purified anarchism in this
perpetual state of self dispersal.” And Nancy Fraser said that “neither half of
Kristeva’s split subject can be a feminist political agent” issue. (Toril Moi
1985, 170)
French context, she was only one of many ’68ers who felt the impact of
Solzhenitsyn’s Gulag Archipelago (published in France in 1973) and took
part in a “turn to ethics” as the “new philosophers” appeared on the
Parisian scene in the early 1970s. That was a definite moment for what we
have been calling “ultra-structuralism” in France, the moment of its
abrupt decline and imminent demise, leaving its orphan “theory” to sol-
dier on for decades in foreign lands. Of the French thinkers considered in
Part IV, only Deleuze stuck to his guns in that moment, expressing no
regrets and attacking others in his cohort (including his friend, Foucault)
for backsliding. But, as we shall see, Deleuze had always been the outlier
and his politics was as idiosyncratic as his work.
Many years later, looking back on the China trip in My Memory’s
Hyperbole ([1984b] 2002), Kristeva saw the seed of her eventual disillu-
sionment with politics in an earlier alliance of convenience she had once
embraced.22 It seemed, in hindsight, to expose an irreducible problem
with politics as such. Of the actions Tel Quel took in 1968–1969 in alliance
with the PCF, she said:
What were we looking for in the PCF? My hypothesis, I think, far from
exempting us, casts a less violent but more cruel light on the cynicism that
binds the individual to politics, on the perversion that lies at the heart of the
political institution, regardless of its nature …. PCF was the best mouth-
piece for experimental literary or theoretical work. To make this work public
in order to continue it, seemed to us imperative in an era of mass media …
on the whole the idea was to use the Communist Party, not be used by it.
(2002, 16)
22
See Joy, O’Grady, and Poxon eds. French Feminists on Religion: A Reader (2002, 86–88)
for a succinct account of how Kristeva’s experience in Communist Bulgaria, compounded by
the embarrassments of 1968 and 1974, explain why she “spurns the group identification
necessary in both social and radical feminisms.”
176 T. DE ZENGOTITA
experience (“the only one in which the wildness of speaking being, and of
language, can be heard” (2002, 19)), such maneuvers would eventually
become intolerable. But, back in the day, her new surroundings had given
her hope: even though “[It] seemed to me completely unrealistic from the
point of view of the socialism I had experienced [in Bulgaria]. I knew to
what extent a regime born of a Marxist social mutation rejected not merely
all aesthetic formalism … but also all individual stylistic experience that
could question or explore the common code and its stereotypes in which
ideology must seek shelter in order to dominate” (1984, 270). In spite of
that lesson learned, the Parisian scene in general and Tel Quel in particular
had inspired her, allowing her to believe that “in France, it would be differ-
ent.” Her blood was up, the game was on—and she was, all of a sudden, a
rising star: no wonder she thought, during those heady days, that radical art
and revolutionary politics might yet coincide and what Sollers once called
the “great wager” of the twentieth-century avant-garde might still be won.
In Kristeva’s particular case, the retreat from politics was especially
painful for her anglophone admirers because it was more repudiation than
retreat. Its terms were characteristically categorical, adamant. Unlike
Derrida and Foucault, Kristeva left no wiggle room, no rhetorical cover,
no way to say—“well, yes, of course my politics has evolved but I am still
committed to the basic aim of _______.” Fill in the blank.
That refusal to waffle was almost certainly rooted in the added impetus
the trip to China had given her. Perhaps only Barthes had been as dis-
mayed as she at the spectacle of that profanation—yet another dream of
justice realized being sacrificed before their eyes to the gods of power and
the whims of bureaucracy.23 But, in Kristeva’s case, it also reflected the inher-
ently personal orientation of psychoanalysis, to which she now committed
herself professionally, and to her long-standing love of literature, to which
she was devoted as a critic and a novelist—to literature understood as “free
creation,” with no apologies if a bourgeois value seemed to echo in that
phrase. Indeed, her turn took her so far off the course upon which she had
originally embarked, that she ended up expressing a certain affirmation
that would prove more offensive to many than any repudiation, no matter
how complete:
23
“I myself was alarmed by the profound unflagging presence of the Soviet model, the
only sign of the 20th century in this land of peasants, and all the more evident because it was
violently resisted.... I saw nothing that might possibly prevent the cultural revolution from
becoming a national and socialist variation. … It marked my farewell to politics, including
feminism” (From “My Memory’s Hyperbole” in The Portable Kristeva ([1984b] 2002, 19)).
THE MOOD OF THE MOMENT 177
References
Boer, Roland. 2007. Althusser’s Catholic Marxism. Rethinking Marxism 19 (4):
469–486.
Bordo, Susan. 1987. The Cartesian Masculinization of Thought. In The Flight to
Objectivity: Essays on Cartesianism and Culture. Albany: State University of
New York Press.
Bourg, Julian. 2011. Review of Radicalism in French Culture: A Sociology of French
Theory in the 1960s, by Niilo Kauppi. H-France Review 11 (186): 1–4.
Champagne, Roland A. 1996. Philippe Sollers. Amsterdam: Rodopi.
de Zengotita, Thomas. 2006. Mediated. New York: Bloomsbury.
Dosse, Francois. 1997. The History of Structuralism: Volume 2: The Sign Sets, 1967–
Present. Trans. Deborah Glassman. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Ferretter, Luke. 2006. Louis Althusser. New York: Routledge.
Ffrench, Patrick, and Roland-Francois Lack, eds. 1998. The Tel Quel Reader.
London: Routledge.
Foucault, Michel. (1961) 1965. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in
the Age of Reason. Trans. Richard Howard. New York: Random House.
———. 1977. A Preface to Transgression. In Language, Counter-Memory,
Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews. Trans. Donald F. Buchard and Sherry
Simon. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Freud, Sigmund. (1930) 1961. Civilization and Its Discontents. Trans. James
Strachey. New York: W.W. Norton.
Gutting, Gary. 2013. Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
178 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Texts and Bodies
1
The chair that Foucault assumed that day had long been supposed to go to the already
venerable Paul Ricoeur. A sign of the times.
only point is—it bears repeating—to remind us that they all intended and
approved a way of writing that was necessarily obscure because it purpose-
fully violated conventions of language and thought. At the end of the day,
it will be appropriate to pass judgment on the value of this radical experi-
ment. But it will not be, and never was, appropriate to attack the obscurity
of these discourses (as originally practiced by their creators) without
acknowledging their experimental nature.
This chapter will deal in some detail with the French theorists who had
the most impact in anglophone settings and, at the same time, were most
often held responsible for the obscurity of these discourses—Jacques
Derrida and Gilles Deleuze in particular. But a brief account of other
important figures will show how pervasive were the basic aims of the
whole enterprise. Perhaps the most important thing to bear in mind is this:
these people knew each other, often intimately, and they were completely
immersed in a competitive game they had been playing since their school
days, often in the same school—the Lycee Louis-le-Grand, perhaps, or the
Lycee Henri-IV in preparation for the École Normale Supérieure (where
they were paid as civil servants), and from there, hopefully, on to fame as
a master thinker with a following in the popular press and a chair at the
Collège de France.2 I read at least one biography of each of these thinkers
by a French author and was struck by how they focused, with an almost
parental pride, on their subject’s academic performance going back to
grammar school (see, e.g., Didier Eribon’s biography of Foucault (1992,
chap. 1). The significance of the French educational system—the curricu-
lar uniformity, the ruthless rankings—was taken for granted by almost
everyone involved, no matter how programmatically opposed to conven-
tions and institutions they might have been. Members of the Académie
Française (established in 1635, by Cardinal Richelieu), known as “the
forty immortals,” adorn the summit of a system that invests like no other
in “symbolic capital” (Bourdieu [1979] 1984)). Prestige, above all.
So, a comprehensive insight to be stressed at the outset: the intensity and
ingenuity these thinkers brought to this intellectual contest in the 1960s
verged on the manic. Niilo Kauppi aptly called it an “arms race” of “theo-
retical radicalization” (2010, 8). Stylistic pyrotechnics were inevitable.
2
Alan Schrift’s Twentieth Century French Philosophy (2006) is an invaluable resource here
(see especially Appendix 1). He describes the educational institutions and their roles in some
detail. He emphasizes in particular how narrow is the path to the top and how grueling the
competition.
TEXTS AND BODIES 183
person. His innate courtesy helped make him one of the great readers of his
time—and he knew it and took pride in it. So he was more inclined to use
his perch at EPHE to assemble points of agreement among those he dis-
cussed or addressed than he was to admonish them for committing some
theoretical faux pas. This accounts for why he was so open to the influence
of others, particularly to Kristeva and Derrida (Dosse 1997, 56–59). He
liked to accompany wilder spirits on their theoretical flights and then chan-
nel them down to earth, down to cases, down to particular texts or genres.
This may explain why his popularity in the United States extended well
beyond the circle of postmodernism’s true believers to include more inde-
pendent thinkers like Susan Sontag and Philip Roth.
Whatever the case may be in terms of character, one of the sources of
Barthes’ critical flexibility is a simple matter of personal history. For
decades, he had to make a living as a writer and adjusting to trends was for
him a professional necessity. To be sure, there were core convictions to
which he held fast throughout his career—but that career took him from
a Classical modernist stance as a critic, through a structuralist phase and
then a poststructuralist phase, and, finally, to a phase in which he renounced
all systems, theoretical and political, in favor of simple “pleasures of the
text” he had once judged inferior to the “bliss” of a radically unconven-
tional work that forces the reader to become the writer in order to follow
it at all. The career of Roland Barthes tracks the development of dominant
paradigms in French thought from the early 1950s to the late 1970s. Not
coincidently, perhaps, he became acutely aware of the way such trends
worked—experientially aware of their effects in his own mind and life and
work. For these reasons, Chap. 9 begins with an overview of Roland
Barthes’ career. It will not only identify some of his substantive contribu-
tions to the formation of French theory but also serve as ground and
context for a more intensive focus on the works of some of his peers, to be
discussed in the rest of the chapter.
than ever. In a single day, how many really non-signifying fields do we cross?
Very few, sometimes none. Here I am, before the sea; it is true that it bears no
message. But on the beach, what material for semiology! Flags, slogans, sig-
nals, signboards, clothes. (“Myth Today” in Mythologies [1957] 1972, 112;
italics mine)
3
“Doxa” is Greek for “appear” or “seem”—it refers to commonsense beliefs and percep-
tions, implying that they are mistaken. Critique of Doxa was a constant in Barthes’ work,
through all the phases ([1975b] 1977, 44, 59, 85, 130).
4
Years later, looking back on his career, he recalled a subsequent stage: “the Doxa crushes
origin and truth together, in order to make them into a single proof. … In order to thwart
origin, he [meaning Barthes himself] first acculturates nature thoroughly: nothing natural any-
where, nothing but the historical” ([1975b] 1977, 139; italics mine).
186 T. DE ZENGOTITA
obviously fell short. But so did the modernist avant-garde, which was will-
fully refusing to represent the world in favor of attending to form, to writing
itself, an utterly futile gesture of mere rebellion in Sartre’s view.5 An appar-
ently intractable problem for the writers of his time was the consequence of
this stand-off. Though he remained personally committed, no matter what,
Sartre painted a bleak picture of the overall situation. “We have fallen out-
side of history,” he said of writers in general, and we are “speaking in the
desert” ([1948] 2001, 205).
But it was at precisely this juncture that Barthes discerned an alternative.
“Writing,” understood as a form, became an artifact unmoored from con-
vention, something an author could make creative decisions about. It opened
up a path of maximum resistance to Literature with a capital “L” and, by
extension, to conventionality itself. At that time, Barthes believed, the form
of writing that best exemplified that resistance was to be found in the work
of Albert Camus (The Stranger 1942) and, later, in Robbe-Grillet (Jealousy
1957) and other practitioners of the “nouveau roman.” The hallmark?
Impersonal description of objects and actions that eschewed conventions of
character and plot and reached for utter neutrality, a total absence of style and
value, transparent, colorless; in other words, Writing Degree Zero (see Allen
2003, 14–31). A blanket rejection of subjectivity—understood as the per-
sonal, the expressive—was the aim, a rejection that implicated both char-
acters and authors. T.S. Eliot would have approved.
So already, in 1953, “écriture” was a term of art for Barthes and would
remain so, under permutation, throughout his career. And Barthes stressed
another perennial theme in his first book as well. No innovation of form
in the arts could expect its subversive effects to last long, including writing
degree zero ([1953] 1984, 65–75). Inevitably it would congeal into a
convention of its own, into commodified doxa—such was the power of the
system to appropriate novelty. So Barthes’ political vision, like that of
many in his cohort, was darker than Sartre’s, reminiscent in its way of
Adorno’s pessimism (see above, Chap. 6)—and certainly too harsh for
many anglophone practitioners of theory who adopted its tropes and ges-
tures in a more optimistic register (see below, sections on Judith Butler
and Cultural Studies in Chap. 9).
5
“For the engaged writer, language is essentially instrumental. … They are transparent
signs quickly passed over in favor of the represented object or transmitted idea. Style must
pass unnoticed: ‘since words are transparent and since the gaze looks through them, it would
be absurd to slip in among them some panes of rough glass’ (Sartre’s words). In reducing
language to an instrument and discarding style as excess, committed writer fails to take lan-
guage seriously” (Marx-Scouras 1996, 26).
TEXTS AND BODIES 187
6
See above for Kristeva, inspired by Emile Benveniste and Mikhail Bakhtin, making that
expansion programmatic at Barthes seminar at EPHE (spelling?) in 1966 (date?).
188 T. DE ZENGOTITA
7
Barthes was not simply rhapsodizing here. He adds: “I can remember, as a child of ten or
so, during a winter of solitude in a strange town, becoming obsessed with the Encyclopedia
Britannica. And not least among the pleasures of that text were the surprises that attended
the order (anti-order, parody of order, Dada order) the alphabet imposed. The marvelous
semantic shifts” ([1975b] 1977, 147).
TEXTS AND BODIES 189
8
Compare Derrida’s soon abandoned scientific pretensions in Of Grammatology, or the
shameless way Deleuze absconded with the “Structuralism” label. Perhaps even Foucault was
only pretending to believe in the reality of the synchronic code he called an “episteme”?.
190 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Here is one example (there will be others)—but this one bears directly on
his experiments with Structuralism—of the candor he would bring to that
task in his 1975 autobiography RB by RB (see below, 9.1.3):
He has never worked out real algorithms; there was a moment when he fell
back on less arduous formulations … simple equations, schemas, tables …
such figures, in fact, are of no use whatever; they are simple toys. … One
plays at science, one puts it in the picture—like a piece in a collage. ([1975b]
1977, 99–100)
Here is Barthes, as usual, riding high upon the next new thing and, as
so often happened, framing it in terms that everyone who was anyone
would soon adopt. “Death of the Author” was a doubly compelling phrase
because it played upon the enduring aim of all the French thinkers who
took the linguistic turn while introducing the up and coming notion of
“writing.” Barthes read everything and tolerated almost as much and that
allowed him to internalize interesting ideas, methods, and vocabularies
with astonishing facility. And, as we have seen, he was happy to experiment
with them for as long as that seemed desirable. Like Dosse, I see certain
character traits at work here, but Barthes himself, going back to his earliest
work in Writing Degree Zero, understood his own willingness to drop a
style and adopt a new one in a more substantive way: it was rooted in a
conviction that, no matter how radical a provocation a cultural innovation
might provide for a moment, it would inevitably congeal into a c onventional
gesture—that being the nature of what Adorno called the “culture indus-
try,” operating now, in Barthes’ view, at the level of high culture.9
There can be no doubt that Barthes’ commitment to the discourse of
writing and intertextuality was primarily due to the influence of Kristeva
and the gadget she presented at his seminar at EPHE in the winter of
1965–1966. Along with Derrida’s account of writing as opposed to
speech, the idea of intertextuality as a functional substitute for references
to subjectivity eroded what remained of Barthes’ commitment to
Structuralism in particular and the objectifying modernist stance in
general:
9
Compare Thomas Frank’s The Conquest of Cool: Business Culture, Counterculture, and the
Rise of Hip Consumerism (1997).
TEXTS AND BODIES 195
the text he wrote announcing the “death of the author,” which was the liter-
ary equivalent of Foucault’s “death of man” in philosophy, made a consider-
able impact. An author would be nothing more than a recent notion born at
the end of the Middle Ages thanks to capitalist ideology … this mythical
figure was on the verge of dissolving. … Surrealism had begun to jolt the
myth … but linguistics would finish it off. … In its place came the ‘scriptor,’
a sort of being outside of time and space, set within the infinity of the signi-
fier’s unfolding. … Barthes joyfully celebrated the birth of the reader on the
ashes of the still smoldering body of the Author. (Dosse 1997, 85)
attack. For Barthes was refusing, not just the Author of books or the Author
of nature (God), but Law and Science as well. Revolution indeed—and we are
reminded that this essay was written a year before the events of ’68, a period
when Barthes was intensely involved with Tel Quel and determined to show
himself as ready as the next fellow for the destruction revolution would bring.
The image Dosse provides of Barthes celebrating the birth of the reader on
the “ashes of the still smoldering body of the Author” is aptly chosen. It cap-
tures the mood of the moment and it is all too easy to forget the underlying
rage that drove the creators of theory to their conceptual extremes. When
Roland Barthes sided with all writing that shows that “the subject is merely an
effect of language” (1975a, 79), he was not just arguing philosophy in the
mode of, say, Hume or Wittgenstein or even Nietzsche. Barthes saw his cri-
tique of the Author as fulfilling “the intellectual’s (or the writer’s) historical
function today,” which was “to maintain and to emphasize the decomposition
of bourgeois consciousness.” And Barthes characterizes the intellectual’s
function by means of this comparison: “decomposition is here contrary to
destruction: in order to destroy bourgeois consciousness we should have to
absent ourselves from it … and such exteriority is possible only in a revolu-
tionary situation: in China, today, class consciousness is in the process of
destruction, not decomposition” (1975a, 79, 63; italics in the original).
Once again, the same obsession, the same mission. Barthes even man-
aged, in this passage, to sound a bit wistful—as if he were longing to be in
such a situation, actually destroying people. I am inclined to suspect him
of affecting a ferocity he didn’t really feel in order to be part of what was
happening, but, either way, it serves to make the point at hand.10 Because
he and his colleagues at Tel Quel were abandoning Marxist orthodoxy to
practice “cultural politics,” they had not only to convince themselves, by
way of “writing” and “textuality,” that they were still materialists, but they
had to convince themselves that their revolutionary fervor burned as
brightly as the Bolsheviks’ in the fall of 1917.
Barthes’ “death of the author,” which he wrote as he was abandoning
Structuralism in favor of more postmodern positions, can be revealingly
10
On the other hand, I think we can take expressions of alienation cast in less political
terms at face value: “Like many of us, I profoundly reject my civilization, to the point of
nausea. This book [Empire of Signs, about his experience of Japan] expresses my absolute
demand for a total alterity, which is becoming a necessity for me” (Roland Barthes in Dosse
1997, 61).
TEXTS AND BODIES 197
In this way is revealed the whole being of writing: a text consists of multiple
writings, issuing from several cultures and entering into dialogue with each
other … there is one place where this multiplicity is collected, united, and
this place is not the author … but the reader: the reader is the very space in
which are inscribed, without any being lost, all the citations a writing consists
of; the unity of a text is not in its origin, it is in its destination; but this desti-
nation can no longer be personal: the reader is a man without history, without
biography, without psychology; he is only that someone who holds gathered
into a single field all the paths of which the text is constituted. ([1968]
1977, 6; italics mine)
11
And the displacement underway is given political significance, reminiscent of the early
days of the Internet and Blogging when citizen opinion and reporting were cheered on as
the established media platforms lost control of the public conversation.
198 T. DE ZENGOTITA
The Author, when we believe in him, is always conceived as the past of his
own book … he maintains with his work the same relation of antecedents a
father maintains with his child … the modern writer (scriptor) is born simul-
taneously with his text … every text is eternally written here and now. This
is because to write can no longer designate an operation of recording, of
observing, of representing. … The modern writer … can therefore no lon-
ger believe … that his hand is too slow for his thought … for him, on the
contrary, his hand, detached from any voice, borne by a pure gesture of
inscription (and not of expression) traces a field without origin or at least has
no other origin then language itself … we know the text … a tissue of cita-
tions, resulting from the thousand sources of culture. … The writer’s …
only power is to combine the different kinds of writing. ([1968] 1977, 145)
think of the whole historical and natural world as “text” and that will
prove to be an essential first step toward understanding how the creators
of theory could ever have imagined that their “cultural politics” might
actually effect a transformation of modern subjectivity.12
As for Barthes, it remains to be stressed how, in “The Death of the
Author” and other works of this period, he insisted on the act of writing
as a bodily act. Besides the rote rejection of “representation” and “expres-
sion” in literature, there is a particular emphasis on “the hand” of the
scriptor as agent—it does the inscribing, out of nowhere, in the eternal
now. There is an allusion here to the automatic writing of the Surrealists,
but, more immediately, it reflects Barthes’ general determination to treat
subjects as effects, not as agents. The commitment of the Tel Quel team to
materialize everything cultural was also being satisfied by talk of “the body
that writes” (compare Kristeva’s semiotic).
12
“History itself is less and less conceived as a monolithic series of determinations; we
know, more and more, that it is, just as is language, a play of structures, whose respective
interdependence can be pushed far further then one had thought; history is also a writing. …
What is at stake is to increase the rupture of the symbolic system in which the modern West
has lived and will continue to live. … To decenter it, withdraw its thousand-year-old privi-
leges, such that a new writing (and not a new style) can appear, a practice founded in theory
is necessary” (Barthes in “The Division of the Assembly” in The Tel Quel Reader (1998, 22)).
200 T. DE ZENGOTITA
was entitled to count himself out, I believe), only Barthes turned defini-
tively to poststructuralist textualism—before abandoning even that13 in
order to “transgress the transgression” that theory was supposed to be by
indulging in pleasures of the text as an ordinary reader. Graham Allen
describes Barthes’ ultimate move this way:
In order to avoid the Doxa of radical left-wing discourse, Barthes allows into
his writing themes and tones (here, love and sentimentality) which are pre-
cisely barred by the orthodoxies of that discourse. Barthes’ desire, therefore,
is to protect writing (ecriture) from solidifying into Doxa … in his later work
[he] is … taking up apparently unfashionable positions as a writer, in par-
ticular the position of a personalized, individual, pleasure seeking subject.
(Allen 2003, 101).
13
As time goes by, talk of text “tends to degenerate into prattle. Where to go next? That is
where I am now” (71).
14
In fact—I suddenly realize—Barthes chose to “break the ban on subject talk,” just as I
have been doing in this study, but for more personal reasons.
TEXTS AND BODIES 201
The first one fleshes out his notion of the “temptation of the alphabet”.
This little recollection was enough on its own to convince me that Barthes’
taste for a certain anti-order was not an intellectual affectation:
But later on, with more intellectual concerns on the table, in a little
section called “The Abandonment of Origins,” he offers this:
By an abusive interest, the Doxa crushes origin and truth together, in order
to make them into a single proof. … In order to thwart origin, he first accul-
turates nature thoroughly: nothing natural anywhere, nothing but the histori-
cal … then this culture is restored to the infinite movement of various
discourses, set up one against the other (and not engendered) as in hand-
over-hand choosing.
The illusion of the natural is … the alibi paraded by a social majority: the
natural is a legality. … We might see the origin of such a critique in the
minority situation of RB himself … who does not feel how natural it is, in
France, to be Catholic, married, and properly accredited with the right
degrees? … against this natural, I can rebel in two ways: by arguing … or by
wrecking the majority’s law by a transgressive avant-garde action. But he
seems to remain strangely at the intersection of these two rejections … it is
possible to enjoy the codes even while nostalgically imagining that someday
they will be abolished: like an intermittent outsider, I can enter into or
emerge from the burdensome sociality, depending on my mood. (130–131)
In what he writes there are two kinds of important words. Some are …
vague, insistent, they serve to take the place of several signifieds (“determin-
ism,” “history,” “nature”). I feel the limpness of these important words,
limp as Dali’s watches. The others (“writing,” “style”) are remodeled
according to a personal project. … He’s not very good at getting to the
heart of things. … A word, a figure … fastens upon him for several years, he
repeats it, uses it everywhere … but he makes no effort to reflect further as
to what he means … you cannot get to the heart of a refrain; you can only
substitute another one for it. And this, after all is what fashion does. In other
words, he has his internal, his personal fashions. (125–130)
heights (Proust [1913] 1998, 252). Poor Roland was similarly afflicted
with respect to language: “I have a disease: I see language. What I should
simply hear, a strange pulsion—perverse in that in it desire mistakes its
object, reveals it to me as a vision (all allowances made) like the one Scipio
had in his dream of the musical spheres,” and so on.
A little vanity—so easy to forgive; in fact, Roland Barthes did have a
remarkable feel for language in so many various venues, high and low, and
a remarkable talent for evoking in others the experiences that guided his
writing. Of all the creators of French theory, he was the most comprehen-
sible precisely because he regarded the concepts he developed and the
language he used as “personal fashions”—and he never lost touch with the
real RB, the one who finally wrote Roland Barthes by Roland Barthes.
The ultra-structuralist Barthes and his colleagues at Tel Quel, including
Jacques Derrida, represented the best efforts of the so-called textualistes to
undermine the modern subject and camouflage their abandonment of
Marx. But Derrida’s contributions to this end were, if anything, even less
convincingly materialist than Barthes’ and so very much more obscure
that it is possible to suspect Derrida of intentional deception flavored with
mockery. Where Barthes appears to have succumbed to peer pressure, as it
were, and fallen into innocent conformity with the trends of the day, we
suspect sometimes that Derrida might have been playing a more devious,
perhaps more enjoyable game.
For the anglophone reader familiar with the logical positivist rejection
of “nonsense,” watching Jacques Derrida position himself so explicitly in
opposition to Wittgenstein on this pivotal issue ought to be enough in
itself to adjust whatever conventional expectations he or she might bring
to the reading of a “philosophical” text. Michel Foucault undoubtedly
had more influence on actual research anglophone academics did under
the influence of the French theorists, but Derrida was as well known—and
the most controversial. John Searle famously said that he “gave bullshit a
bad name” and, in general, he was the center of attention for critics exco-
riating the jargon of theory. So more extended explicative attention will be
TEXTS AND BODIES 205
15
This discussion relies especially on Peter Gordon’s “Hammer Without a Master” (2007)
and the “Afterword” to Limited Inc. (1988), in which Derrida, guided by carefully con-
structed questions from Gerald Graff, concentrates with unprecedented simplicity on
explaining himself to an anglophone audience.
16
Of special significance, then: Derrida’s lifelong engagement with writers like Mallarme,
Artaud, and Joyce. Francois Dosse claims that Derrida was actually after for a new genre of
“creative writing” (1997, vol 2, 20–21), with Glas as his principal example. Derrida’s biog-
rapher describes a man who spent his whole working life poised, and torn, between philoso-
phy and literature (Peeters 2013, 27–34, 101, 134, 267–270, 309–312).
206 T. DE ZENGOTITA
the concept of the text I propose is limited neither to the graphic, nor to the
book, nor even to discourse. … What I call “text” implies all the structures
called “real,” “economic,” “historical” socio-institutional, in short: all pos-
sible referents. (1988, 148)
Derrida has also used the term “general text” to convey the same
notion (1982, 125–126). The infamous “there is nothing outside the
text” belongs here—and the reading that takes “text” to mean written
texts in the ordinary sense will be treated in what follows as emblematic
of the gulf that separated Derrida’s actual argument from its anglophone
reception.18
What was to be gained from this sweeping re-description? In Derrida’s
milieu, as we have seen, returning the abstract (idealized) “sign” of Struc
turalism (langue) to temporality and performance (parole) without read-
mitting the subject was the order of the day. Derrida’s various formulations
(differAnce, trace, iteration, dissemination, etc.) of “archewriting” gained
the most traction and propelled him to the forefront, at first in France and
later abroad. At ENS in the late 1950s and early 1960s, Derrida had been
close to Althusser when he was at his zenith—his merger of Structuralism
with Marxism was shaping every debate. Derrida felt compelled to mate-
rialize his account of language if he wanted to be heard at all (Peeters
17
The vision: in spite of the evanescence of voice, units of speech (phonemes, words,
phrases, sentences) are cycled and recycled (iterated) through spoken discourse ad infinitum,
in and out of changing contexts in changing combinations, woven together, an ephemeral
textile composed of “chains of signification.”
18
Derrida did not, however, step in as forcefully as he might have to correct them. Most of
his specific deconstructions dealt with literal texts and he had a valuable audience to cultivate,
especially among American literary critics—for whom literal “texts” had an obvious priority.
TEXTS AND BODIES 207
19
Of Grammatology ([1967] 1976, 163).
20
Philosophical Investigations (1953, 400). Wittgenstein used this expression to evoke
Cartesian solipsism. It shows how everything can be transformed, even though nothing actu-
ally changes, at the margin of a language game.
208 T. DE ZENGOTITA
9.2.2 Presence
In his early work, Jacques Derrida took up a position in the phenomeno-
logical tradition. Most immediately, he was inspired by Heidegger, who
was out to undermine Western ontology since Plato, especially Cartesian
dualism, and to rescue “the question of Being” from a “forgetting”
brought about by philosophical systems and associated forms of life in the
western history. In Derrida’s view, Heidegger was still captive to the meta-
physics he sought to overcome because his teacher, Edmund Husserl, had
bequeathed to him a dream, the dream upon which phenomenology, like
all of traditional ontology, was based—the dream of presence.
21
Why is no absolute origin conceivable? Consider a footprint in the sand. It is the trace of
a foot, which is its origin. But the foot only becomes an origin, thanks to the trace. Hence
the chain of signifiers, without beginning or end.
TEXTS AND BODIES 209
22
In Modern French Philosophy (1979), Vincent Descombes—a native of this world, though
not a partisan—states what to him is obvious: Derrida was engaged in “the radicalization of
phenomenology” (136).
23
An advocate of more rigorous public standards for philosophical justification is entitled
to demur at this point, of course. But that demurral will apply as much to William James and
the later Wittgenstein as to early Derrida.
24
Compare Wilfred Sellars’ “Myth of the Given” ([1956] 1997), “What might the Given
be? … Sellars observes, ‘Many things have been said to be ‘Given’: sense contents, material
objects, universals, propositions, real connections, first principles, even Givenness itself.’
Intuitively, it would be something that is self-evident or certain or indubitable” (Maher
2012, 52).
210 T. DE ZENGOTITA
This is not difficult. Anyone can test it. When you gaze at something or
think of something, how much attentional/intentional flickering goes on?
How much of what a thing or a word or a concept is to you actually
includes what it isn’t—it’s context and background, various associations
and contrasts, recollections and projections? Isn’t anything you attend to
constantly disturbed by traces of these absent “others?” Most fundamen-
tally, when you mean something, isn’t your experience of your intention
actually constituted by a reaching-toward and a leaving-behind of the
moment of “touching” what you mean, a moment that never quite occurs?
That is “differAnce,” with an “a,” an amalgam of the French words for
differ (as in Structuralism) and defer—which tells us that the sign has been
activated, that meaning is now an event).
Derrida’s notion of “writing” will develop this theme, offered in this
distilled form now just to give a sense of direction. And, once again, one
could ask—if this describes what Derrida basically means when he decon-
structs presence, why didn’t he just say so? And, once again, the answer is
that I resorted to ordinary subject talk (“you gaze” and “you attend”)
while he was committed to a way of writing that would evoke an anony-
mous process of signification upon which subjects, mere effects of that
process, impose their false clarities.
9.2.2.2 Phonologocentrism
Another reason internal expressions provided that instance for Husserl
involved the phenomenology of the voice as a form of “auto-affection.”
Auto-affection means sensing yourself, touching yourself, looking at your-
self, and so forth. Talking to yourself silently, “hearing” your own voice in
your mind, is auto-affection too, said Derrida, but it has special phenom-
enological characteristics.
Speaking to yourself “in your head” is an entirely internal form of
auto-affection. If you look at or touch yourself you have to go “through”
the outside of yourself to get to yourself. But not when you talk to your-
self—the proximity of stimulator to stimulated is absolute. And not only
that, voice is immaterial and invisible, the most non-physical of sensual
media. So it is the most akin, phenomenologically, to ideal entities—rea-
son, meanings, concepts, the logos. The voice is also transitory and vibrant
and ephemeral—alive, like soul or spirit. In sum, the voice is the medium
25
For Derrida (and Deleuze), this “inhabiting” of a material sound (image) by an immate-
rial concept is immediately attributed to the persistence of Platonic metaphysics. The assimi-
lation of modern subjective idealism to Platonism, if too easily carried out, risks papering
over how radical in their own right the abstractions of modernity actually were.
212 T. DE ZENGOTITA
26
On the face of it, this claim is hard to reconcile with the exalted status of literacy and the
veneration of literature in so much of the Western tradition. That problem, so far as I know,
was never satisfactorily addressed.
TEXTS AND BODIES 213
the idea is before I announce it, surely? Otherwise why would I be sur-
prised or grateful, which I often am? Even more significantly—do I know
what the idea is as I make the announcement? That dawning feeling and
the few images that accompany the announcement aren’t actually the idea,
fully understood, not yet. Isn’t it a lot like when someone else explains a
good idea to me, and it begins to dawn on me, what the other person is
saying? Most compelling: don’t I sometimes get the dawning feeling as I
announce the idea to myself, and then it turns out not to be the idea I felt
it was—not the solution to the problem, not the way back to the hotel
after all. When that happens, this process is almost indistinguishable from
assessing a communication from someone else.
There are many examples that show that talking to yourself is not free
of indication. Wittgenstein has some lovely ones.27 In effect, they all sug-
gest that when you talk to yourself the sender and the receiver are some-
how separate, distinct, different. And that constitutes a fissure in the unity
of the cogito, a disturbance of self-presence, a step toward an exorcism of
the ghost from the machine.
The upshot so far is this: not only is the subject not self-present in the
way Descartes (and Husserl) supposed, it is not unified either—at a mini-
mum, the subject that speaks to itself and the subject that listens to itself
do not coincide. At the same time, the meaning of an expression is not
fixed by the intention of the speaker. Unlike the creator of a formal gram-
mar, a real speaker in real time cannot stipulate the meaning of her utter-
ances even if she is addressing herself in her head. Another meaning is always
possible and frequently occurs. You can, and often do, take what you said
to yourself in your head and interpret it in some way that differs from what
you originally intended. Therefore, there is a gap, a slippage—the pres-
ence of absent possibilities—between signifier and signified. Finally, no
signified can be discerned that is not also a signifier, no concept or object
that does not signify other concepts and objects in the actual play of lan-
guage (parole) as it actually unfolds. That was implicit in Derrida’s denial
of “transcendental signifieds”, and the “inflation of the sign” found its
27
There is remarkable, apparently coincidental, overlap between the early Derrida and the
later Wittgenstein. See especially the critique of private sensations and private language in the
Philosophical Investigations (1953). The common aim was to neutralize the cogito before it
gets off the ground, but convergences of detail are striking. See Preface to Speech and
Phenomena (1973, xiii–xxii). See also H. Rapaport The Theory Mess (2001, 8, 9); N. Garver
and S. Lee Derrida and Wittgenstein (1994); H. Staten Wittgenstein and Derrida (1986).
Richard Rorty makes the same point in “Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the reification of lan-
guage” (1991).
214 T. DE ZENGOTITA
28
Searle declined to engage after Derrida’s reply to his reply (Limited Inc. 1988). He
turned instead (six years later) to a withering review of a book on deconstruction by Jonathan
Culler, a Derrida defender (Searle 1983). His “Reply” to Derrida was not mentioned in that
review. Nor would Searle allow it to be included in Limited Inc. (1988), a book conceived as
a collection of all the documents relevant to the dispute, along with commentary in hind-
sight. Only Derrida would contribute.
216 T. DE ZENGOTITA
eviscerate Sarl’s “Reply”29 got Searle off the hook.30 He was able to take
advantage of Derrida’s outburst, refuse to participate further, and sidestep
the task of explaining his initial misreading. Before a d iscussion of what
might have been had common courtesy prevailed, some essential
background:
These two quotes, juxtaposed, present the basic issue in a nutshell, and
they do it so clearly that the only wonder is that those involved (not only
the principals) in this classic academic tempest in a teapot never managed
to sort out what was really at stake. Obviously, Derrida’s critique of Austin
was only incidentally about Austin. Not fully realizing that, Searle read
into the critique a shocking ignorance of basic rational procedures when
in fact it was those procedures that were its target. A profound difference
in attitude toward abstraction and systemization, entrenched in the tradi-
tions Searle and Derrida represented, shaped their taken-for-granted
assumptions about what it means to do philosophy and was ultimately
responsible for the specific ways they failed to engage.
In Chap. 3, I argued for an expanded concept of modernism, one that
would include founding figures in several academic disciplines as well the
usual suspects in the arts and literature. I tried to show that a certain gesture
29
A footnote appended to the name “Derrida” in the title of Searle’s “Reply” thanked
H. Dreyfus and D. Searle for “discussion of these matters.” In his blistering 85-page response
to that ten-page paper (Limited Inc. 1988), Derrida pretended that a certain “Sarl” (French
acronym for “Society of Limited Responsibility”) was the author of Searle’s “Reply.”
30
Years later, explaining the game he was playing in his reply to Searle’s “Reply,” Derrida
describes it as “dual writing,” an effort to show and say things about speech acts simultane-
ously. He was taunting Searle, saying “try to interpret this text too with your categories and
to you, as well as the reader, I say: enjoy!” For example, with the role of “speaker intentions”
at issue, Derrida’s first words are “I could have pretended to begin with a false beginning.”
TEXTS AND BODIES 217
31
If anything, Searle stepped back from the casual manner Austin adopted, as if to empha-
size the modesty of his program. Searle took a more aggressively formal approach, aiming to
contribute ultimately to a scientific psychology.
218 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Are these three predicates, together with the entire system they entail, lim-
ited … to “written” communication in the narrow sense of this word? Are
they not to be found in all language, in spoken language for instance, and
ultimately in the totality of “experience” insofar as it is inseparable from this
field of the mark [meaning whatever has significance], which is to say, from
the network of effacement and of difference, of units of iterability, which are
separable from their internal and external context and also from themselves,
inasmuch as the very iterability which constituted their identity does not permit
them ever to be a unity that is identical to itself. (1988, 10; italics mine)
32
Quite apart from the value of this claim, it is not hard to understand. It amounts to
conventional Platonism, the kind students encounter in oft-cited passages about why one
should not attribute “Being” to ever-changing sensible/material things.
220 T. DE ZENGOTITA
happens to “go through your head” as you apprehend the necessity of “If
A > B and B > C then A > C.” During the same period, in another discipline,
the text of a poem on a page was taken to say what the language says regard-
less of what the poet happened to be thinking and feeling when he wrote it.
The term “intentional fallacy” excluded from the precincts of the New
Criticism benighted Romantics who still thought poems were “expressing”
poets as opposed to language. The term might apply as well to benighted
philosophers who lapsed into “psychologism,” the bête noir of all who saw
the light shining from within crystalline logic. In general, then, excluding
the subject from modernist formalism was a practical matter, part of the
cleansing gesture (a loaded term for Derrida) of abstraction.
But for French “theory,” successor to phenomenology, the issue of the
subject was central—and charged with political passion as well. French
theorists were determined to abandon abstraction and return to history
and performance but that had to happen, as we have seen, without return-
ing to the subject and its intentions, and not just for methodological rea-
sons. The subject had to be demolished—deconstructed, decentered,
destabilized—for a mix of philosophical and ideological reasons already dis-
cussed. Paradoxes of subjectivity that were (apparently) treated like little
puzzles by Wittgenstein (do you know what you are going to say before
you say it?) were, for the ultra-structuralists, concrete evidence of subjec-
tivity’s inherent otherness that heralded the longed-for end of the autono-
mous Cartesian agent as an actual historical development, as a dismantling
of “bourgeois consciousness” and its Stalinist reflection. To allow that
subject to return to its central place on the stage of meaning would have
been, in effect, to betray a political left already in crisis.
So when Austin, taking procedures of abstraction for granted, found
himself referring to subjective intentions as well as objective circumstantial
factors in his theory of speech acts, it was not anything like the metaphysi-
cal and ethico-political disaster for him that it was for Derrida. He would
have preferred not to do it, to limit himself to public contextual criteria,
but sometimes there seemed to be no other recourse if progress was to be
made at all. As Searle patiently explained, prioritizing “standard cases” of
speech acts like promising rather than “parasitical cases” like promising in
a play or under duress was a methodological decision for Austin.
Exasperated by Derrida’s moralistic attitude, Searle thought he was plead-
ing for the obvious when he said: “Such parasitism is a relation of logical
dependence; it does not imply any moral judgment and certainly not that
the parasite is somehow immorally sponging off the host (Does one really
have to point this out?)” (1977, 205).
222 T. DE ZENGOTITA
One could say that I “went through a form of” naming the vessel [christen-
ing a ship] but that my “action” was “void” or “without effect,” because I
was not a proper person, had not the “capacity,” to perform it: but one
might also and alternatively say that … there is no accepted conventional
procedure; it is a mockery, like a marriage with a monkey. Or again one
could say that part of the procedure is getting oneself appointed. … I do not
think that these uncertainties [the latter two] matter in theory, though it is
pleasant to investigate them and in practice convenient to be ready, as jurists
are, with a terminology to cope with them. (1962, 23–24; italics mine)
34
Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut were underestimating the reach of “style” when they said
“Derrida = Heidegger + le style de Derrida,” but as a sound-bite description of Derrida’s
basic mission, it’s fair enough (in Gutting 2013, 57).
35
If anything like “sponging” was going on, Derrida’s accusatory finger was pointed at the
standard cases, not the parasites. His argument was always that standard cases depend on
marginal ones, as an intrinsic condition of their possibility.
TEXTS AND BODIES 223
To Derrida, this shows that Austin was fully aware of the impossibility of
“capturing” in “theory” the complexity of events as they really are. The
idea that “part of the procedure” (the “convention” that Derrida believes
is what ought to be at issue here) might include “getting oneself appointed”
to the priesthood in order to perform a marriage ceremony successfully is
especially revealing. Imagine asking Austin, as Derrida is in effect doing
when he claims that context is indeterminable, “well, how about the his-
torical process of establishing the priesthood itself—isn’t that also ‘part of
the procedure’?” Austin—a jolly chap, it seems—would, in congenial cir-
cumstances, most likely say, “Well, my dear boy (for only an excitable youth
who had fallen in with some mad German on holiday would ask such a
question), you can draw the line wherever you like, of course, but given my
heavy teaching schedule, I choose to draw it narrowly enough so that I can
actually finish a book on ‘speech act theory’—ha, ha-hah!”36 That’s what
Austin means when he says that these kinds of infelicities don’t matter in
theory—because the latter two infelicities point to eventualities that his
theory was not designed to cover. The whole appeal of theory, for Austin—a
classic modernist—was that it was formally limited. Its elements and rules
were defined by theorists to explain (generate, cover, account for) whatever
domain of idealized facts the theory itself had abstracted from the morass
of ongoing actuality. In the case of speech act theory, that domain con-
sisted of certain speech acts (promising, ordering, apologizing etc.) defined
by the theorist and taking place under normal circumstances, as “seriously
intended” and so forth—that is, “standard cases.” Obviously, only a lunatic
would try to codify actuality in its ongoing open-endedness—which is, of
course, why Derrida was suspicious of codification in the first place.
For Derrida the act of codification, of abstraction, of idealization—of
“theory” in the analytic sense—is itself, at best, a powerfully consequential
practice determined by a certain tradition of rational inquiry we cannot do
without (the sciences) and also, at worst, an act of violence committed
upon actuality in its ongoing open-endedness, sometimes with political
and social consequences (compare the Frankfurt School on Enlightenment
reason). If Derrida had political commitments (as opposed to political
positions he affiliated himself with in order to fit in at various junctures in
his career), they derived directly from his appreciation of the danger of
36
This is intended to be more than amusing. Derrida’s pivotal chapter in Of Grammatology
(1967c) is called “The End of the Book and the Beginning of Writing.” It concerns the
socio-political artificiality, the conventionality of the “book”—illusion of containment and
completion.
224 T. DE ZENGOTITA
And the question to ask of Derrida at the end of the day becomes: to
what extent can one really do that? If the procedure of deconstruction was
meant to haunt the scene of traditional ontology,38 finding ways to “belong
without belonging to the class of concepts of which it must render an
accounting, to the theoretical space that it organizes in a (as I often say)
‘quasi’ transcendental manner” (1988, 127). What value was added by
this ghost?
9.2.4 Derrida’s “Ontology”
For the educated anglophone reader committed to giving Derrida in par-
ticular and French theory in general a fair reading, this passing remark in
a letter Derrida wrote to a friend should be attached like a mezuzah to the
portal that leads to their work; I repeat it here: “I am profoundly con-
vinced, against Wittgenstein ... that, what we cannot speak about we must
(not) pass over in silence” (see, once again, Gutting’s Thinking the
Impossible). That’s why explaining Derrida in conventional prose leads
inevitably to a confetti of scare quotes—beginning with the title of this
section. In fact, his whole enterprise is aptly introduced simply by noticing
that. Making us suspicious of philosophical concepts was his basic aim
and—once again, not for the first or last time—he shared that aim with the
38
Derrida’s term “hauntology” might have been used instead of scare quotes in the title of
the next section—but I decided against it because, for many people, annoying puns are one
of the most off-putting of all the stylistic conceits in his repertoire.
226 T. DE ZENGOTITA
later Wittgenstein.39 Wittgenstein’s strategy and style may have been more
effective than Derrida’s (I think so), but both were coping with the same
moment in the history of philosophy’s linguistic turn as it was realized in
their different traditions—the moment when language confronts its limits.
That is why it would be wrong to speak of a Derridean ontology in the
traditional sense; it cannot “say” anything to describe the unrepresentable.
Instead, it contrives to participate in it, to evoke it. In place of Wittgenstein’s
early silence and his later riddles, Derrida offers a torrent of fluidly related
“semi-concepts” that are supposed to accomplish this feat.
The question of the value of a philosophy that relies on semi-concepts
and their elusive effects remains open, of course—a separate question. The
point here is that Derrida was quite candid about his program. There were
no middle-range issues for him. Every text, every artwork was immediately
revealed as subject to (or disruptive of) classic metaphysical categories and
deconstruction was the way to (partial) emancipation in each case. One by
one, case by case—the metaphysical oppressor was what Derrida always
found and, like Arnold Schwarzenegger’s terminator, gunning for it was
all he did. J.L. Austin’s modest undertaking was but one in a long line of
metaphysically dominated projects he solicited in the name of shaking up
the whole.40
– Derrida’s dream
Deep down, my desire to write is the desire for an exhaustive chronicle …
the thing I’d like to have written is just that: a “total” diary. (Derrida in
Peeters 2013, 290)
39
“A picture held us captive. And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language and
language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably” (Wittgenstein 1953, 115).
40
In the originary essay “DifferAnce” ([1967e] 2001), Derrida invoked the names of
Freud, Nietzsche, and Levinas as representative of an “epoch” determined to make the tra-
ditional ontology of Being and beings “shake all over” (1973, 153).
TEXTS AND BODIES 227
That does not mean that all referents are suspended, denied, or enclosed in
a book, as people have … accused me of believing. But it does mean that
every referent, all reality, has the structure of a differential trace, and that
one cannot refer to this “real” except in an interpretive experience. The lat-
ter neither yields meaning nor assumes it except in a movement of differential
referring. (1988, 148; italics mine)
talk level, it’s like this: the words you are reading are traces of my thoughts
and actions. That’s step one. Now zoom in to your actual experience of
reading them and/or my writing them. Those processes involve, in com-
pressed form, specific motions of their own from trace (trace of the imme-
diately preceding “from,” trace of preceding appearance of “trace,” trace of
the anticipated appearance of “trace”) to trace (trace of the preceding
“trace,” as these parentheses are a trace of the preceding parentheses). And
so on.41
Derrida himself could not stoop to such examples of the “structure of
the differential trace” for reasons already established—he was committed
to construing the subjective aspects (you and me, consciousness) of the
processes just described as “effects” of the materials involved (effects of
“writing,” of the gram, of the mark, of the trace, etc.) and, just as impor-
tant, committed to the literary/philosophical challenge of crafting his
own writing so as to reflect that “ontological” situation. But you can be
sure he did the phenomenology I’ve just recreated and then erased the
subject from his account of it. That is how to read Derrida. Note, by way
of confirmation and a harbinger of our eventual return to the notion “iter-
ability,” that no appearance of the word “trace” in the last two paragraphs
was really (experientially or literally) the same as any other.
Derrida launched his career with a critique of static (present) “ideality”
in Husserl’s Origins of Geometry ([1962] 1989), aiming to undo the atem-
poral abstractionist tendencies of early phenomenology. Heidegger won
him over by showing that time was the meaning of Being and Dasein the
perpetual becoming of that meaning. Heidegger’s basal insight on
Derrida’s reading of him was this: like (or as) consciousness itself—mean-
ing, significance, has to happen. Meaningful distinctions are not mere dif-
ferences, as in an abstract code, as in Saussure’s grammar—they have to
occur. They are events—possibilities made real, realized, and then, with
time or as time, undone and deferred, “effaced” forever, never to be purely
repeated but only iterated in significations to come.42 For Derrida, any
philosophy that will not deal with that eventfulness has turned away from
41
It seems that the French word translated as “trace” carries immediate connotations of
tracking, of spoor.
42
The intensity of the poststructuralist commitment to temporality was, as already noted,
pungently expressed by Julia Kristeva when she described how “writing” targets what she
called the “necrophiliac” stasis of Structuralism’s elements and rules and Structuralism’s
“imperial thinkers” who believe “that by codifying” the “remains of a process” we “can pos-
sess them” (in Kristeva 2002, 27–31).
TEXTS AND BODIES 229
truth and any philosophy that deals authentically with eventfulness will
never arrive at truth.43 This ontology of “writing” was only the latest in a
long line of proposals by continental philosophers out to capture or (for
postmoderns) to evoke ongoing eventfulness. It is Derrida’s dream of the
absolute diary projected onto a level that transcends individual subjects, a
level on which all actual and possible subjects appear as effects, or potential
effects, of the play of a “writing” coextensive with the “entire field of what
philosophy would call experience” (this is a linguistic version of what
Husserl’s eidetic study of the personal-historical ego’s experience pro-
duced on the transcendental level). Searle may be forgiven for not getting
all that out of Derrida’s little critique of Austin, even if he read it care-
fully—but that is its basis.
Now, consider this:
43
“Intentionality [in Husserl’s sense] cannot and should not attain the plenitude toward
which it nonetheless inevitably tends. Plenitude is its telos … [but] if it is attained, it, as well
as intention both disappear, are paralyzed, immobilized, or die” (1988, 129).
44
Compare Heidegger’s account of the possibilities lodged in tools, settings, and projects
in Being and Time (1927). Appropriated by many American pragmatists, that account reso-
nates with Wittgenstein’s emphasis on the use of words in concert with customary activities,
and in the unrealized possibilities implicit in those language games described in the
Philosophical Investigations (1953).
230 T. DE ZENGOTITA
This etymology, of course, has no value qua proof and were it to be false, the
very shift in meaning would confirm the law here indicated: the time and
place of the other time already at work, altering from the start the start itself.
(1988, 62)
45
“Thus we are obliged to think in opposition to the truisms which we believed—which
we still cannot not believe—to be the very ether of our thought and language. … And it is a
question not only of thinking the opposite which is still in complicity with the classical alter-
natives, but of liberating thought and its language for the encounter occurring beyond these
alternatives” (1967f, 118).
TEXTS AND BODIES 231
Had some Sanskrit expert during Q&A put the “iter = other” etymol-
ogy into question and had Derrida given the expert the response he gives
here to himself, it would have seemed slippery indeed. But here he actually
was discussing the many ways in which misunderstandings of an expres-
sion are a constant possibility and a frequent actuality and how they can,
in turn, become understandings of another kind, and so, at worst, we
might suspect him of setting up a justification for future slipperiness or
slipperiness in general, which indeed he was. And so the question becomes:
is this a valid justification and for what slipperiness, exactly?
How many readers of this essay have mourned, as I have, the passing of
that exquisite expression “begging the question”? How many have felt, as
I have, a certain muted despair watching and listening while this subtle
figure is reduced to a synonym for “invites the question” by the talking
heads under the klieg lights? That is, of course, just a particularly piquant
example of a ubiquitous process. Nero Wolfe would not countenance using
“contact” as a verb, but I contact people all the time without even noticing.
On the other hand, I cringe when things “impact” people—and get almost
nauseous when I hear how “impactful” something is. But there is nothing
to be done about all this. anglophone researchers in historical linguistics
call it “semantic drift”—a perfectly intelligible notion. French theorists
called it the “play of the signifier.” It is Derrida’s “writing” over time and,
yes, it happens with speech too. Some people in my Bronx neighborhood
play “pick-a-boo” (not “peek”) with their babies and when I moved as a
very young child from England to New England we went from “ashes,
ashes” to “ahchoo-achoo” before we all fell down. This process is con-
stantly underway at the micro-level of dialect and slang (no one could pos-
sibly “list” instances or formulate rules for the process) and we only notice
the ones that catch on—which means get iterated more generally.
So Derrida’s remark was a justification for his insistence on the slipperi-
ness of language—but, ultimately, it was a claim that this “slipperiness” is
essential to language, as something like its very life. That is to say, events
of meaning, actual significations, occurring out of possibilities given some-
how by “text” and context (and by grammar and intentions as well, to be
sure). Such events and contexts are more and less customary—some
utterly routine, others less so, and yet others (Dada performance art) radi-
cally less so. But all are events of actualization and so must be admitted
first as possibilities. These possibilities in turn must be conceived as some-
how “built into” or at least “allowed by” all the significant entities and
232 T. DE ZENGOTITA
processes that bear upon and constitute the moment when these possibili-
ties are actualized and those are not with (or as) the passing of time in the
actual process of history, with all its specificity and concreteness and, most
especially, all its accidents—source of the new.
Now compare Searle’s idea of possibility. It seemed pretty vast to him
and he seemed to think (at first at least) that it took us to the level of
events:
The performances of actual speech acts … are indeed events, datable singu-
lar events in particular historical contexts. But as events they have some very
peculiar properties. They are capable of communicating from speakers to
hearers an infinite number of different contents. … Furthermore, hearers
are able to understand this infinite number of possible communications …
what is it that gives their speech acts this limitless capacity for communica-
tion? The answer is that the speaker and hearers are masters of the rules of
language, and these rules are recursive. They allow for the repeated applica-
tion of the same rule. … Iterability—both as exemplified by the repeated use
of the same word type and as exemplified by the recursive character of syn-
tactical rules—is not as Derrida seems to think something in conflict with
the intentionality of linguistic acts, spoken or written, it is the necessary
presupposition of the forms which that intentionality takes. (1977, 208)
dred—again, that vast expansion of the “field of the mark” that “every
possible user in general” entailed by the lead quote for this section—the
phrase Searle overlooked. Derrida’s “ontology” of writing and possibility is
Hegel’s Absolute Mind fallen into pieces, into all actual and all possible
significant events individually. Just as the phenomenology of the “trace”
recreated above was typically presented by Derrida in terms that erased the
subject experiencing the traces, so in his “ontology” of writing Derrida
simply erased Hegel’s Absolute Mind—eliminating, as it were, the absolute
author and absolute reader of the general text. What remains of subjectivity
are but ephemeral effects of an infinitely tiny slice of that general text that
happen to be, for the nonce, you and me—sites of events of signification.
To repeat, by way of setting up a conclusion, what was said by way of
introduction to this whole discussion of Derrida—for him, a philosophi-
cally adequate account of “possibility” in language would admit the
achievements of James Joyce in Finnegans Wake (1939) rather than being
bound by the rules, however recursive, and word types of a formal gram-
mar.46 With this fundamental difference in their understanding of the
notion “meaningful event” brought to light, we arrive at the point where
Derrida and Searle could have met, come to clarity, and agreed to dis-
agree. Ironically, the theme of “iterability” would have provided the per-
fect starting point.
However botched his reading of Derrida, when Searle built his “Reply”
around the type-token distinction he describes here, he chose wisely. It
encapsulates the dependence of his (and Austin’s) project on abstraction
and offers a concentrated image of the target of Derrida’s critique at the
same time—a perfect object for some concluding reflections. Presumably,
46
“in The Post Card (1987), referring to Joyce’s influence on the formation of his theories,
he goes further, confessing that he has ‘never imitated anyone so irresistibly’ as he has imi-
tated Joyce; and interestingly, Derrida formally remarks in the 1984 Joyce symposium that
‘without Joyce,’ ‘Deconstruction could not have been possible’” (Zangouei 2012, 31).
234 T. DE ZENGOTITA
when Searle gave Derrida his for-beginners tour of the type/token distinc-
tion, he did not realize that Derrida had to be familiar with it. Husserl had
used it in the Logical Investigations (with which Derrida was thoroughly
familiar) and of course it corresponds closely to Saussure’s broader abstrac-
tion of langue (grammar) from parole (speech), common currency for
French intellectuals of the period. More consequentially, Searle did not
understand as he wrote that “iterability” actually did the same work in
Derrida’s “ontology” of writing that the type/token distinction did for
abstractionist philosophizing—without resorting to codification, without
idealizing. That’s why it was called “post-structuralism.” And “post-
structuralism” was “postmodern” precisely because it was committed to
undoing that gesture of abstraction. A “type” abstracts an ideal singularity
out of “token” instances that, given the way things actually go on in the
world, can never be absolutely identical and so makes it possible for us to
recognize “instances” as instances of the “same thing,” in both theory and
practice. Now this from Derrida, and we have our hands around the issue
between them:
the unique character of this structure of iterability … lies in the fact that,
comprising identity and difference, repetition and alteration, etc., it renders
the project of idealization possible without lending “itself” to any pure, sim-
ple, and idealizable conceptualization. No process or project of idealization
is possible without iterability and yet iterability itself cannot be idealized.
(Derrida 1988, 71)
47
I cannot in this space describe how often I am overwhelmed by the suspicion that
Western thought is driven most deeply by the desire to put things into words in some way.
48
For example, in the “Afterword” to Limited Inc., Gerald Graff asks Derrida if he hasn’t
created something of a straw man for himself by attributing to abstract philosophizing in
general and Austin in particular, an insistence on absolute conceptual purity and complete
containment of facts by theory. Derrida admits that Austin’s personal affect and attitude
don’t reflect that insistence—that he is tentative and provisional and happy to admit excep-
tions and imperfections in his work. But for Derrida, following Heidegger in this, Austin’s
personal intentions (the very topic at issue!) are beside the point. It is the telos of Western
metaphysics he is addressing and that, he believes, is relentlessly at work underneath all spe-
cific manifestations—abstracting, purifying, containing, controlling. That is a topic both
camps might discuss. In a nutshell, it comes down to this: to what extent is abstract reason,
at work in the sciences and philosophy, necessarily complicit with social and economic sys-
tems of domination and exploitation? Noam Chomsky, for example, would not admit any
such necessity—but compare the Frankfurt School.
TEXTS AND BODIES 237
for the reasons Searle supplied. Confronted with the idea that “possibili-
ties” in language are best exemplified by that carnival of free associations
Joyce staged in Finnegans Wake, Searle and Austin would say, “But that’s
no use, you can’t create a formal theory to explain all that!” To which
Derrida would reply, “Exactly! That’s my point!” At bottom, and quite
apart from the personal shortcomings of the parties involved, this con-
frontation never quite took place because these two ways of doing phi-
losophy are so different that arguments over which is the “right way” can
now be seen for what they are: as misguided as an argument over whether
painting or sculpture is the “right way” to make art.49
We have now seen how the most prominent of the textualistes among
creators of French theory went about overcoming the modern, especially by
way of dismantling the modern subject. In the next section, Deleuze will
represent the desirants, those who appealed directly, in the manner of
Nietzsche, to unrepresentable drives and forces to accomplish the same end.
9.3.1 Introduction
Of all the major contributors to la pensée 68, Gilles Deleuze was the most
obvious outlier—a declared opponent of the linguistic/textual emphasis
that persisted in the work of the “poststructuralist” creators of French
theory whom Francois Dosse calls the “ultra-structuralists.”50 That is why,
like his friend Foucault, he survived the decline of all that and continues
to shape ongoing enterprises—in Deleuze’s case, most especially in the
arts and academic departments associated with them. As with Derrida, but
49
Nor can either side claim to better represent Western Reason. The analytics, like the
scientists they emulate, can rightly say they have been true to the rigor of it, to the logic, the
method; they tackle problems they can solve. But Derrida and the tradition that shaped him
could claim to have better served philosophy’s original aim: wisdom, not knowledge—the
wisdom of fallible mortals whom Socrates originally represented and addressed.
50
Deleuze’s engagement with Structuralism/post-structuralism was tactically contrived to
keep him in the conversation—bordering on downright disingenuous, if you attend closely
to his argument in “How Do We Recognize Structuralism” ([1967] 2004). He wasn’t swept
up in the French “linguistic turn”—and he came right out and said so later on, when the
pressures of fashion were dissipating. That is one reason many admirers position him as an
opponent of postmodernism. If you think of postmodernism as an extension of
Structuralism/post-structuralism, however disruptive, and take Derrida as the prototype that
makes perfect sense.
238 T. DE ZENGOTITA
not Foucault, his works are notorious for a particular kind of obscurity
that derives from a certain wildness in his thought, a wildness he was happy
to flaunt to the delight of his acolytes, the bafflement of other readers, and
the annoyance of so many critics. He was the most prominently featured
target of Alan Sokal’s and Jean Bricmont’s widely cited book Fashionable
Nonsense (1998), a favorite source for left-wing opponents of academic
postmodernism. In that book, Deleuze’s “abuse” of scientific terms was
excoriated as if he had been engaged in their explication. But he wasn’t.
He was possessed by a sensuous and intuitive vision for a new metaphysics.
It took the form of an art project on a cosmic scale, one that would evoke
“what it is like to be”—not a mere bat51—but “what is it like to be the
whole of reality,” with modern science serving as inspiration. Said Deleuze:
“I feel myself to be a pure metaphysician. … Bergson says that modern
science hasn’t found its metaphysics, the metaphysics it would need. It is
this metaphysics that interests me” (in Bogue 2007, 42).
I call this metaphysics a “vision” to play upon the word “see,” the way
it blends visual encounter and conceptual understanding—as when “I see”
means “I get it.” I call it sensuous and intuitive because not only sight (of
either kind) was enlisted in this venture. All the senses, all sensations, all
prearticulate feelings were summoned to the cause of escaping from the
prison house of language and the formal theories that codified it. It was an
attempt to ascend to the threshold of new kind of thinking, a thinking that
opened out to the inconceivable, to the real.52
I want this notion (and the term “notion”) available because I want to
show that the works of Gilles Deleuze are best understood as installments
in this philosophical art project that encourages willing participants to
acquire a special kind of sensitivity, one that yields a “sense” of the way
things really are, a sense of perpetual becoming at every level of order and
disorder in the universe, a sense that arises from certain notions when they
are well-deployed and dissipates when those notions are forced into the
confines of a conventional conceptuality that presumes to represent reality
and express subjectivity. Once again, the basic adjustment anglophone
51
“What is it Like to Be a Bat” was a 1974 paper by Thomas Nagle, an analytically oriented
philosopher of mind who argued that consciousness is a reality unto itself, irreducible to
physical processes correlated with it.
52
Frederic Jameson, author of The Prison House of Language (1972) and an influential
critique of Structuralism in particular and formalism more generally, was no fan of most
“theory.” But he was lavish in his praise of Deleuze because he was the one who explicitly
and consistently sought to escape that prison and engage with reality.
TEXTS AND BODIES 239
escape and a validation that would equip him with the self-confidence he
would need to take the lonely philosophical path he chose.
Sartre was Deleuze’s first philosophical hero. Being and Nothingness was
published in 1943, during the darkest days of the German occupation, and
Tournier reports that Deleuze devoured that 722-page book in a week.
Along with most of the cognoscenti in Paris, they attended Sartre’s lecture,
“Existentialism is a Humanism,” at Club Maintenant in Paris, on 29
October 1945. It marked a decisive break.53 Tournier later reported: “We
were floored. So our master had had to dig through the trash to unearth
this worn-out mixture reeking of sweat and the inner life of humanism” (in
Dosse [2007] 2010, 95). Deleuze was already committed to a critique of
the “idea of interiority” and of the various modern humanisms associated
with it. In an early publication, a 1946 article called “From Christ to the
Bourgeoisie” (dedicated to his patroness, Mlle Davy), he described the
“unbroken historical link between Christianity and capitalism, which are
both trapped in the same delusional cult of interiority” (92).
Young Deleuze was not alone in longing for a philosophical “out-
side”—with the “inside” originally understood in terms of the Kantian
“subjective idealism” that still dominated the French academy after the
war. His teacher, Jean Hyppolite, was trying to situate Marx and Marxism
in relation to Hegel (see Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology of
Spirit 1947), a relation of intense interest to many. And, of course, that
project immediately implicated an “outside” of thought, that being the
basic point of Marxist materialism. Even Husserl, in his later work, pursued
a “genetic phenomenology,” seeking access to the social/historical condi-
tions that determined the emergence of thought (Joe Hughes in Deleuze’s
Difference and Repetition: A Reader’s Guide 2009, 6–10, 79) (For an
overview, see John Heckman’s “Hyppolite and the Hegel Revival in
France” in Telos (Summer 1973, 128–145)).
Of course Deleuze had to find his own idiosyncratic route to that “out-
side” so many were seeking. He had only flirted with phenomenology and
his Marxism was more assumed than expounded—an accessory essential
to his station but not of much interest in his work. He boasted of avoiding
the “three H’s” (Hegel, Husserl, Heidegger) who commanded the atten-
53
This lecture elicited from Heidegger the landmark “Letter on Humanism” in 1946
(Heidegger 1977), at the behest of Jean Beaufret. That “letter” marked the onset of decline
for existentialism and humanism, which led to the critique of phenomenology itself that
attended the linguistic turn in France, the rise of Structuralism—with all its consequences for
French theory.
242 T. DE ZENGOTITA
tion of his teachers and peers and turned instead to an H of his own—to
David Hume. And in him, of all people, he discovered what would become
his metaphysics: “transcendental empiricism” (jargon item #1). Hume
had approached this paradoxical construct without realizing it and Deleuze
would always relish wrenching an unintended conundrum from the depths
of an admirable philosophy.
So Deleuze had the gall to pronounce Hume’s empiricism “transcenden-
tal”—an outcome from which Hume would have recoiled in horror or (good-
humored fellow that he was) embraced as a parody of metaphysical reason’s
overreach. Inspired, I suspect, by Nietzsche’s call for “effective history” that
served contemporary life-affirming purposes, Deleuze liked to compare his
method to “buggering,” to taking the man whose work was the object of his
study from behind and, in a species of immaculate conception, engendering a
monster that would serve Deleuze’s purposes (see, e.g., Deleuze and History
2009, 208). Hard to say how Hume would have felt about that image—per-
haps it would depend on whether it was presented to him at home in
Edinburgh or in one of the Parisian salons that made him so welcome.
simply the coherence of human experience once it fell under the sway of
custom and produced that creature of habit, including the habit of saying
“I,” that is the human subject. Said Constantin Boundas, the translator of
Empiricism and Subjectivity:
An account of the birth of the subject from “inside the given,” of the
subject as a contingent effect of other entities and forces—that was Hume’s
most profound contribution to modern philosophy. But Deleuze, from his
perch of procreation as philosophical buggerer, noticed a transcendent
something at the nativity scene that le bon David had missed:
How can the mind become a subject? … Deleuze-Hume’s answer is that the
mind becomes a subject … as the result of the … the principles of associa-
tion contiguity, resemblance and causality [that] form habit, establish belief
and constitute the subject as an entity that anticipates. (Boundas 1991, 15;
my italics)
tery. The “given” is the social and natural environment into which neuro-
psychological flesh packets we call “babies” are born biologically. But, from
the point of view (if there were one) of those little flesh packets, there is
indeed a mystery—for they are not (yet) subjects. From that point of view
the question becomes: “given” to what?
Gilles Deleuze would spend the rest of his working life experimenting
with answers to that question—imagining answers to that question.
In his last essay, “Immanence: a Life” (2001), Deleuze looked back on
the founding gesture from the point of view of subsequent experiments
and imaginings:
Wild and powerful. For Deleuze, no other kinds of ideas had value.
Trying to understand him means reaching for experiences of that “pre-
reflexive impersonal consciousness”—however unlikely the prospect.
Deleuze gave us some sense of what he meant when he referred to delir-
ium as an example of experience without a subject. Think also of certain
moments between sleeping and waking—of multiple overlapping
sensations and image fragments that exist more or less on their own—or
as given to various “larval selves.”
Deleuze ransacked the works of thinkers he admired, looking for the
“tools” he needed to realize this unlikely prospect.
sity of chance—we must not make of the eternal return a return of the same.
(Deleuze [1995] 2001, 86–87; italics mine)
The third moment remains absent. … We know that Nietzsche did not have
time to write this projected part. … Nietzsche gave us only the past condi-
tion and the present metamorphosis, but not the unconditioned which was
to have resulted as the “future.” (1994, 92)
And so on, indefinitely. And that also happens to capture what is meant
by Difference and Repetition. There is no such thing as pure repetition.
There is always difference, no matter what is repeated, no matter how
many times (compare Derrida above, Chap. 9.2.3.1). Pure identity is an
illusion of Idealism—along with other tropes of closure like analogy,
resemblance, and opposition. Deleuze called these relations “the four iron
collars of representation” because, especially in Hegel—but throughout
the history of Western thought—they refused difference the ontological
standing it deserves. Some difference is obviously at work in three of the
relations: “A” can only resemble or be analogous to or oppose “B” if there
is some difference between them—but this is a dependent, subordinate
difference, not the wild motor of change that endows Becoming with its
Nietzschean claim over Being. The case of identity is trickier; it is not so
obvious how difference enters into self-identity. That is why it commands
the nexus of representation. But if identity is conceived as a relation, some
difference is implicated and even eternally self-identical Platonic ideas,
with no physical aspect for change to get a handle on, seem somehow to
be in relation to themselves if they are represented.
Since Deleuze’s conceptual multiplicities are always ready for further
encounters in ever-changing contexts, it fell to me, a finite reader/writer
with promises to keep, to decide when to stop. So I could finish the sec-
tion. So I could finish the book. Of course, with each decision, I fore-
closed on further encounters—which meant, with every decision, I risked
not having some encounter that would have qualified as a genuine “event”
(jargon item #5: everything that happens is, strictly speaking, an “event”
insofar as it is uniquely determined—but the term typically makes honor-
ific reference to especially fruitful happenings, as in the “events of ’68” or
the “events of 9/11”; at the same time, in its a metaphysical aspect, the
“pure event” refers to the “eternal structure” of becoming: just happened,
about to happen, never is55). I could only hope that, in each case, I had
55
This obviously mirrors Husserl on pro- and re-tention and Heidegger on “having been”
and “not yet.” It bears repeating: the debt Deleuze and other creators of “theory” owed to
phenomenology is incalculable. They were as determined to escape the bubbles of its “life-
worlds” as they were to escape the epistemological prison of the cogito. Indeed, for them, it
often came down to the same thing. But inevitably, given their uniform educations and
entrenched habits of thought, that “escape” entailed a reworking of phenomenological
notions—efforts to open them up to some “outside” (compare today’s “speculative
realism”).
248 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Science fiction in yet another sense, one in which the weaknesses become
manifest. How else can one write but of those things which one doesn’t
know, or knows badly? It is precisely there that we imagine having some-
thing to say. … We are therefore well aware, unfortunately, that we have
spoken about science in a manner which was not scientific. (1994, xxi)
The time is coming when it will hardly be possible to write a book of phi-
losophy as it has been done for so long: ‘Ah! the old style …’. The search for
new means of philosophical expression was begun by Nietzsche and must be
pursued today in relation to the renewal of certain other arts. … One imag-
ines a philosophically bearded Hegel, a philosophically clean-shaven Marx, in
the same way as a moustached Mona Lisa. (1994, xxi)
57
I am every bit as serious about critique of theory, of which this is a small example, as I
am about my effort to explicate it fairly. If this book gives less space and time to the task of
critique, it is only because I believe that a really significant critique depends, first and fore-
most, on a fair reading of its object—and that is the principal aim of this book.
TEXTS AND BODIES 251
58
More overlap with Adorno; note that abstraction, usually the villain on the scene, is a
good thing in this case. That is because Deleuze’s idea of thinking (line of flight, affirmative
difference, novelty, open-ended, never “settled”) could be described as “abstract” in its self-
referential orientation compared to representation, the font of all banality and conformity.
59
There is nothing obscure, by the way, about the idea of the “force” of language: think of
your body responding to a sudden cry of pain or the literally uplifting effect of anthems for
the faithful (singing La Marseillaise in Rick’s Café in Casablanca). Passages in Walter Ong’s
study of oral cultures, The Presence of the Word (1967), might also serve to remind the skepti-
cal of what it means to speak of language having force. See also Deleuze on writing “for”
animals.
252 T. DE ZENGOTITA
60
Once again, Heidegger’s influence is apparent: see the discussion of “assertion” in Being
and Time.
61
Spinoza’s univocity is an ontological monism that says that every particular happening/
entity is a mode of the one Sub-stance—so all being “is” in the same way: if a possibility “is”
then it “is” as much as an actuality “is.”
62
Compare George Steiner’s “lacking word” reading of high modernism in Chap. 3. Like
all his confreres, Deleuze was deeply invested in the work of the radical modernists in the arts
and literature—but, once again, even more so. He wrote more books and papers about the
arts than all his colleagues combined. “More” is a word that readily attaches to Deleuze. But
the most significant source of Deleuze’s view of language is Nietzsche’s early essay “On
Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense.” A half hour with that little essay provides a key for
decoding the Deleuzean discourse.
TEXTS AND BODIES 253
pushes “to the limit that separates language from animality, that separates
language from the cry, that separates language from song. … One has to be
on this limit, that’s what I think. Even when one does philosophy. One has
to be on the limit between thought and non-thought” (Deleuze and Parnet
2012: “A is for animal”). Alain Beaulieu nails it when he says: “Deleuze
seems to imply that animals intuitively have this capacity to express an
impersonal life with its network of affects … the task of writers and philoso-
phers consists of tuning into the forces of an impersonal life similar to the
actions and reactions of an animal and its environment” (Beaulieu 2011).63
No surprise to find that, in her introduction to the Deleuze Dictionary
(2010), Claire Colebrook worries that the very idea “might seem a
particularly craven, disrespectful, literal minded and reactive project”
because the Dictionary entailed the risk that “in systematizing Deleuze’s
thought” we “reduce an event and untimely provocation to one more
doxa” (pp. 1–2). Similarly, Joe Hughes, in his invaluable Deleuze’s
Difference and Repetition: A Reader’s Guide (2009) wonders if the “idea
of a reader’s guide which attempts to bring the vibrations, rotations and
whirlings of difference and repetition into the dubious clarity of everyday
language is in fact a fundamental betrayal of Dells aesthetic project” (23).
And, tasked with introducing The Cambridge Companion to Deleuze
(2012), Henry Somers-Hall devoted ten pages to the difficulties involved
in reading him: “Deleuze introduces a certain obscurity into his language,
a stuttering or in his own words a deterritorialization of language that
prevents reliance on ready-made categories of thought” that enable us to
“think that which is outside of the intellect” (5).
“Stuttering” was especially interesting to Deleuze—an everyday
example of the “schizophrenic” poetic creations of Antonin Artaud
with which he was well-nigh obsessed. One needs to reflect upon the
phenomenon as concretely as possible to see why. The near-spastic ten-
sions and suspenses that constitute a severe case of stuttering testifies
to (as Deleuze would put it) collisions of hidden forces in the depths
of bodies that determine experienced actuality. When you watch and
listen to someone stutter, it’s like watching a schizophrenic make
63
Certain feminist critics rightly discerned a boyish “masculinity” in Deleuze’s fascination
with animals—wolf packs in particular seemed to appeal to a lingering Mowgli/Tarzan fan-
tasy at work in his thinking. And later, fully invested a kind of panpsychism, he saw the
“origins” of art in the territorial markings of animals and was as comfortable with that con-
tinuity as any nineteenth-century evolutionist would have been.
254 T. DE ZENGOTITA
create a painting of the priest” (“J is for Joy”; italics mine; see his memory
of first encountering philosophical concepts above, 9.3.2.1). And finally,
just as great painters produce “percepts at the edge of the bearable,” so
philosophers should create “concepts at the edge of the thinkable … and
between the creation of a great character and the creation of a concept, so
many links exist that one can see it as constituting somewhat the same
enterprise” (“L is for literature”).
But, at the end of the day, Deleuze never came right out and said his
metaphysics was a work of art—period. I therefore propose to bugger him
as he buggered philosophers he admired and foist upon him this claim: his
new method to address his new problem was essentially artistic, even by
his own definition.
Yes, Deleuze created concepts (or semi-concepts)—with such abandon,
so profusely—and that super-abundance alone is suggestive. But they were
most effective, most Deleuzean, when they in turn “hurled off” affects
and percepts that caused people who fell under his spell to see and feel
differently, just as Van Gogh and Proust and Bacon did. Perhaps more
devotedly than any other philosopher, Deleuze responded to Nietzsche
when he called upon his followers to make philosophy like art, not math
and science.
Perhaps we should not be surprised to find that the world disclosed to
Deleuze when he assumed the position of Spinoza’s God was already express-
ing itself—as if to welcome him home, to the heart of immanence. Which
makes this the right moment to ask why Spinoza’s God specifically?
Clearly, only a God existing in peculiar intimacy with His creation could
enjoy an empiricism that comprehensive and finely attuned. Such an attun-
ement, cast into a description, would amount to a phenomenology as if
performed by God—by Spinoza’s God in particular—because Spinoza’s
God was coextensive with, indeed identical to, all nature, existence itself.
That was his atheism, for which he suffered sanctions in his day.65
So the cosmic art project is laying a claim of some kind to the point of
view of Spinoza’s God—that is the “point of view” that everything that
exists would have of itself and everything else (debt to Leibniz’ monads
noted) at every level of its organization. Ten pages after mentioning the
danger of pantheism that expressionism brings with it, this time referenc-
ing Spinoza specifically and admiringly, Deleuze spells out the conse-
quences of this awesome affirmation in language that leaves little doubt as
to his inclinations:
65
A quick reminder of how radical a view this was in its context: for the posthumously
published Dutch version of de Spinoza’s Ethics: Including the Improvement of the
Understanding ([1677] 1989), Spinoza’s friends arranged to leave out the clause “or
Nature” as it appears in the Latin version, thusly: “That eternal and infinite being we call
God, or Nature, acts from the same necessity from which he exists” (Part IV, Preface).
258 T. DE ZENGOTITA
66
“readers may recall from A Thousand Plateaus the image of the cosmic egg from the
Dogon mythology, complete with the distribution of intensities running across the surface of
the egg. According to the ancient myth, seven vibrations criss-crossed the egg in spiraling
zig-zag lines, morphing its shape into a helix before it birthed the world” (see Marcel Griaule
and Germaine Dieterlen, “The Dogon” in African Worlds: Studies in the Cosmological Ideas
and Social Values of African Peoples, by Daryll Forde (Oxford University Press 1954: 84–85)).
TEXTS AND BODIES 259
67
In what follows I will be calling rather freely on imagery that dates to Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, the umbrella title for Anti-Oedipus (1972, trans. 1977) and A Thousand
Plateaus (1980, trans. 1987). So credit (or blame) for this phase of the cosmic art project
goes to Felix Guattari as well as Deleuze.
68
“Deleuze invokes Bergson’s theory of pure memory … Bergson believes that pure mem-
ory stores every conscious event in its particularity and detail. The perceptions of actual
existence are duplicated in a virtual existence as images with the potential for becoming
conscious, actual ones. Thus every lived moment is both actual and virtual, with perception
on one side and memory on the other; an ever-growing mass of recollections” (Stagoll
“Memory” in The Deleuze Dictionary; italics mine).
260 T. DE ZENGOTITA
But we are brought up short along this line of speculation by the fact
that genes of organisms don’t really dictate their phenotypical actualiza-
tion in detail due to a host of complex interactions that arise during mor-
phogenesis, during the organism’s development. Analogously, a Deleuzean
“concept” is called a “multiplicity” because it is not a fixed definition; it is
a mobile grouping of thoughts, of thinking and speaking processes, and
associated activities (writing, teaching) that happen among people involved
in a conversation (perhaps a long one, over months and years) and roughly
governed by something like a Kantian “regulative idea” (i.e., a necessary
fiction) and is only to that extent coherent (let alone the same!). In this
case, the concept being released into this conversation can be roughly
stated thusly: suppose we think, not only of the information encoded in
the genes of a given organism at conception, but of all the contingencies
that will affect the morphogenetic process in each and all cases, suppose
we think of all that as the “information” that really and truly conditions
the emergence of life forms in every detail—suppose we think of all that as
a kind of “SuperGenome.”
The actual process of morphogenesis, like all natural processes, is con-
stantly subject to random impingements from internal and external envi-
ronments seething with other entities and forces, from cosmic rays to
maternal diet, from traffic noise to antibodies—there is no “isolating” the
event of actualizing an organism. From overall physiognomy to the tiniest
details of skin lesion or stem striation, what actually eventuates in all
cases—and at each moment—is a product of a vast and various conver-
gence and divergence of entities and forces. The SuperGenome “behind”
every organism.
Since the aim is a metaphysics for the twentieth century’s scientific
age—not the practice of any particular science—what emerges from that
realization is precisely the “meta-” that was sought. But one more step
remains to be taken (brace yourself). The imagination must now move
beyond the issue of morphogenesis in organisms and, in one massive and
propulsive leap, conceive of the entirety of events in the universe—past,
present, and future—as “emerging” from and in that universe, and the
totality of circumstances that specify all possible events in it and, by way of
specific conjunctions of entities and forces in particular circumstances,
produces all actual events. The open-ended totality of those conjunctions
and possible conjunctions just is the “virtuality” that immanently contains
those actualizations and possible actualizations. That is what “plane of
immanence” and “virtuality” came to mean in later works. Call it the
SuperDuperGenome.
TEXTS AND BODIES 261
69
Deleuze refused to talk about virtuality as a set of possibilities—though he doesn’t give
a satisfactory explanation. My guess is that, if he had, a deflating realization would have
followed: his notion of “virtuality” is very close to Heidegger’s “possibility” with Spinoza’s
God in the place of Dasein and the works of nature in the place of “equipment.”
262 T. DE ZENGOTITA
of lightning. Consider it in all its particularity and ask why this bolt of
lightning and not some other, perhaps brighter or sharper or longer-
lasting, bolt of lightning? And the answer is, of course, because a particular
arrangement of entities and relative charges and forces happened to obtain
at the moment of actualization and not some other, slightly different but
possible, such arrangement.
If Spinoza really were the presiding spirit here, that would simply mean
that only the bolt of lightning that actually happened was ever really possi-
ble. Indebted to Nietzsche more than Spinoza, Deleuze could not tolerate
that. An ancient materialist, the imperturbable Lucretius, had provided him
with just what he needed to meet the case. Lucretius described his atoms as
subject to random “swerves”—and, on that basis, Nietzsche’s ever-colliding
wills to power were restored to their commanding positions in this meta-
physics of a modern science that relied, after all, on quantum mechanics.
Chance is king in a Nietzschean cosmos and contention is its métier.
Whatever else one might make of this SuperDuperGenome notion, it
must be admitted that it is what actualities “express.” It is likewise what an
actuality exists in “virtually” (immanently) until the “event” of its “actual-
ization.” So, unlike Platonic Ideas, Deleuzean Virtuality does not exist
apart from actuality—it just is that actuality insofar as that actuality is con-
stantly in the process of producing its own next moment. If the actuality in
question is a bubbling stream, fast moving water over pebbles and rocks
and fallen branches, then (from our point of view) it is easy to see actualiza-
tions emerging from already actual configuration of entities and forces, easy
to see how virtuality exists in the already actual. If the actuality in question
is a mountain range hundreds of millions of year in the making through the
shifts and submersions of tectonic plates the size of continents, then—not
so easy.70 But, for Spinoza’s God, there is no essential difference. All is
becoming and all becoming is actualization of the virtual. By the same
token, each actualization alters the virtual, shifts ever so slightly (or not so
70
At a time when I was immersing myself in Deleuze’s art project while working on this
book, I happened to be hiking on Mt. Katahdin in Maine when it occurred to me to “touch
the mountain.” Not the slab of rock next to me (though that was all I could physically
touch), but the whole mountain. And something happened; I could “feel” the mountain’s
ephemerality as well as its massive solidity (no illicit substances were involved). Or, better, I
got a “sense” of its ephemerality on time scales accessible to Spinoza’s God but not usually
to me (see discussion of “sense,”). That’s all. Not a conversion experience, it didn’t make me
a Deleuzean—but an experience nevertheless. Cezanne’s’ paintings of the mountains of
Provence have a similar effect.
TEXTS AND BODIES 263
slightly: a section of the stream’s bank suddenly gives way) the configura-
tion of entities and forces that will condition subsequent actualizations.
Finally, it is not possible (or necessary) to assign a definite locale to an
actualization.71 How far away in time and space would one have to go to
take note of every condition on the actualization of that lightning bolt?
Perhaps it flashed out just to the east of the Mississippi, just north of
Baton Rouge, but the fast moving mass of air that was its proximate cause
took shape in the Arctic. Spinoza’s God would know and we can’t—but it
doesn’t matter. All we want is to get a sense of the way things happen and
then to allow that sense to condition the way we happen—philosophically,
artistically, personally, politically.
From the point(s) of view of Spinoza’s God, there is no practical need
to organize reality into manageable categories when the whole of what
happened, happens, and will happen is right there. Not even “there.”
Here. For Spinoza’s God is all of it, the virtual and the actual, the molecu-
lar and the molar at every level and space/time location in the Universe.
Spinoza’s God doesn’t have to imagine it. But Deleuzean philosopher/
artists, emulating that imagined God, do have to. They linger perpetually
at the portal between the virtual and the actual, participant/observers in
the ontological event of becoming.72
Let’s look at it from another angle:
71
Expression is “non-local, belonging directly to the dynamic relation between a myriad of
charged particles. The flash of lightning expresses this nonlocal relation. Expression is always
fundamentally of a relation, not a subject. In the expression product and process are one”
(Massumi 2002, 18).
72
I came eventually to understand the never-ending (and never-beginning) quality of the
commentaries by the Deleuzeans—D.W. Smith and Joe Hughes, John Protevi and Brian
Massumi, Leonard Lawlor and Claire Colebrook, and the rest. Over years of lingering at the
virtual/actual portal, after many arrests and lessons learned and paroles undertaken, they
sustained a continuous quest for moments of “getting” the Deleuzean vision, a “sense” of
what only Spinoza’s God could really “know.” They produced an improvisational catechism
that settles around their thought and prose like the aura of a reputation earned, an aura vis-
ible only to those who have attempted the journey themselves—or find themselves immedi-
ately committed to it as if this, yes, and only this deserves the title “life of the mind.” I think
that’s how they feel and the hippie in me applauds them.
264 T. DE ZENGOTITA
a bolt of lightning that will be named Deleuze: a new way of thinking is pos-
sible. … It does not lie in the future. … It is here in Deleuze’s texts, springing
forth, dancing before us, in our midst; genital thought, intensive thought, affir-
mative thought, acategorical thought. (Foucault, reviewing Difference and
Repetition and The Logic of Sense in Critique 1970, 885–908; italics mine)
Foucault was not just hailing his friend with the customary hyperbole
when he called him a bolt of lightning—he was also deploying that favor-
ite example of an “event.” Foucault was also, I think, genuinely excited.
Deleuze had produced a pair of profoundly original Nietzschean books.
The scope and verve of the affirmation they announced moved Foucault
to declare, in the same review, that the twentieth century might one day
be known as the “Deleuzian century”—after the manner of certain histo-
rians who once thought it apt to talk about “The Age of Voltaire.” That
such a possibility even occurred to him speaks volumes, not only about
how high his opinion of Deleuze’s achievement was, but also how high
the high drama of their time had become for Foucault at the beginning of
the 1970s. Gilles Deleuze was accomplishing what they were all aiming
for. He had found a new way to think, a way to “think the impossible”, to
break out of the “iron collar” of representation, the legacy of a linguistic
doxa that had imprisoned philosophy and common sense alike since
TEXTS AND BODIES 265
Sense is both the expressible or the expressed of the proposition, and the
attribute of the state of affairs. It turns one side toward things, and another
side toward propositions. … It is exactly the boundary between propositions
and things. ([1969] 1990, 22; italics mine)
74
Foucault felt entitled to assimilate the event almost entirely to its sense-effect and cele-
brate the event per se as “incorporeal” (“Theatrum Philosophicum” in Critique (1970,
885–908)). He seemed delighted to be able to talk about processes usually consigned to the
mental without renouncing his commitment to materialism; Deleuzean metaphysics had dis-
closed what he took the liberty of calling “incorporeal materiality.” That phrase is typical of
the paradoxical lengths to which interpreters have had to go to cope with The Logic of Sense.
TEXTS AND BODIES 267
75
This account of “surface effects” bears an inescapable similarity to Galileo’s dogmatically
mechanical world-picture described above (see pp. 19–21). And it calls to mind an accidental
connotation—the way “surface effect” seems to echo cinematic “special effects”—and that’s
apt because this is an effort to relegate the subject’s experience to a transient periphery of the
universe where it belongs. Galileo’s decision to call heat (and color and sound) “secondary
properties” as compared to “primary properties” that really exist—also makes it apt to say of
Deleuze and Guattari’s usage: it was immanent in Galileo’s.
TEXTS AND BODIES 269
And that irreverence, which marked Deleuze’s attitude from the begin-
ning of his career, was without question essential to the book’s success—
how could it not be, given the frequency with which Anti-Oedipus is
celebrated or denigrated as the book that captured the spirit of 1968,
when irreverence was the order of the day. And on this point especially,
Felix Guattari was the perfect collaborator. As a student of Lacan’s, he was
prepared to innovate outlandishly in whatever settings he found himself,
clinical or political. But his taste for irreverence extended beyond texts and
lectures, however performative; he was an activist above all. Charismatic,
aggressive, sexually provocative—he dominated their relationship from
the beginning. The force of his example drove Deleuze to extremes of
TEXTS AND BODIES 271
thought and proposals for practice that the shy and sickly author of
Difference and Repetition could not have countenanced.
Lacan was in fact Guattari’s training analyst and before he teamed up
with Deleuze to critique the Oedipal—the lynchpin of Lacanian theory—
he was widely regarded as the chosen heir. But when Lacan caught wind
of the traitorous project, he banished his protégé and replaced him with
his son-in-law, Jacques-Alain Miller. The world of the French Intellectual
Nobility (Kauppi 1996) did indeed resemble a village, but it was a rarified
one, especially given the veneration in which its inhabitants were held.76
Yet another reason why the language of theory was so often obscure: like
teenagers in a clique, sharing an evolving slang, the creators of theory
could take a lot for granted.
When Felix Guattari came to confer with Deleuze in his study about
their book, he brought with him a sensational resonance, residual emana-
tions of the turbulence that had flowed so recently through the streets of
Paris in the schizoid rush of revolution. Both he and Deleuze insisted that
their books were “expressions” or “effects” of the “events” of May 1968,
but only Guattari had actually participated. Deleuze just thought about it.
But his thought had always been Nietzschean—the play of forces and their
consequences had always obsessed him. With Guattari, he was discovering
what he had meant all along and was inspired to go for broke.77
But the original target of the ultra-structuralists remained the focus, in
spite of the mind-boggling reach of the discourse they would concoct. Of
all the ways the major French theorists found to decenter, deconstruct,
and demote the modern subject, in philosophy and action, their approach
was the most transparent. It was a frontal assault. Whether we look at
Guattari’s early efforts, instituted at the Le Borde clinic, to create “social
subjects” that could replace the interpellated subjectivities of the suffering
patients and the professional staff or at Deleuze’s straightforward denials
of the significance of consciousness, that hapless shuttlecock of molecular
determinations, we are struck by the same directness—especially in com-
parison to the tactics employed by other practitioners of theory. For
76
In 1960, when Sartre was in a terrorism-supporting phase of his career, regularly exhort-
ing French troops in Algeria to desert, de Gaulle was asked why he took no action against the
philosopher. He replied, “One does not arrest Voltaire.”
77
Deleuze himself, alluding to Kant, once said that Felix had awakened him from “dog-
matic slumbers.” He called Felix the “diamond miner” and relegated himself to the role of
“polisher.” Others, for example, Slavoj Zizek, saw in that influence the corruption of a great
philosopher (in Zizek 2012).
272 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Deleuze and Guattari, the subject did not have to be seduced into recog-
nition of the “other” in itself or tricked into unraveling in “writing.” One
simply, in accordance with the will to power and the priority of action,
forced the issue, in both senses of the word “issue.”
From a rational point of view, one would expect the pauperized masses of
workers to develop a sharp consciousness of their social situation, to develop
a will to eliminate their social misery … [but] … it was exactly the pauper-
ized masses who carried fascism, the ultimate in political reaction, to power.
(Wilhelm Reich The Mass Psychology of Fascism 1946, 7)
78
The jargon of cognitive gerunds—as in “thinking the limits of the body” or “theorizing
the post-soul aesthetic”—belongs in this environment. The message: fluid, open, unfixable,
not dominating, not dominated—not “about” a separate “object.”
TEXTS AND BODIES 273
79
It is worth remembering that the idea of human beings and groups as “machines” itself
goes back, somewhat ironically, to Descartes (see, e.g., in the Enlightenment, La Mettrie’s
Man the Machine, and a slew of other works leading up to the mechanism still evident in
Comte and even Durkheim). Cartesian dualism had a materialist aspect that many French
thinkers, including Descartes himself, sometimes found irresistible.
274 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Such constructions play a key role in the art project: at every historical
moment, they are treated as the agents of whatever process of becoming is
in focus—up to the point where even speech, in all its manifestations, is
conceived as a product of “collective assemblages of enunciation” (Deleuze
and Guattari 1987, 7). The world of the Anti-Oedipus, like the fantastic
landscape that houses A Thousand Plateaus, is swarming with these newly
discovered creatures (though they’ve been there all along); one creature
alone has passed from the scene. There are no individual people doing and
saying things. Parts of the assemblage that we used to think of as people
moving their limbs in various ways and uttering various noises are admit-
ted, but they are merely parts, like the tents and the canoes. It is “the
assemblage that enunciates”—which means that, if you descended to the
molecular level with Spinoza’s god at the moment that George asks Martha
if she wants mustard on her hot dog you would realize that the sound
waves that really constitute those words are products of the open-ended
molecular totality of the chance-saturated circumstances at that moment
and what George and Martha think is going on is a surface effect of all that.
Why think of the infant’s mouth and the breast as a “desiring machine”?
Because, taken as a unit, it traverses the classic subject-object boundary,
violating the unity of the monadic subject and liberating a nomadic subject
of organs without a body, thus evoking the multiplicity and machinic
implacability of desires, and—once the bottle is substituted for the breast—
tying this dismembered self to a bottle-making factory under the regime
of late capital—the ultimate schizo Deathstar machine now undoing itself
in spite of itself, caught up as it is in a frenetic and fragmented connectivity
that has taken on an unstoppable life of its own.
Anti-Oedipus aimed to merge the “private theater” of the Freudian
psyche with the political reality of “desiring-production,” where Marx
supposedly held sway. But the operations of forces in flux in the book as
written proved to be, in accordance with the schizo imperative itself, too
promiscuous to be contained by any recognizable form of Marxist theory
or action. And action was very much the point. “It is not enough to say
‘Long Live the Multiple!’” proclaimed Deleuze, with Hegel’s Dialectic in
his sights, “you must do and make the multiple” (in Bogue 2007, 84).
Felix Guattari, for his part, was always doing that—always organizing,
always motivating. He was a leader of the “Institutional Therapy” move-
ment in France (see Thomas Szas in the USA and R.D. Laing in Great
Britain for parallels). At the La Borde clinic in particular, he and his cohort
devised various practices designed to dismantle systems of authority and
TEXTS AND BODIES 275
So the pantheism that Deleuze flirted with in his Spinoza studies was
transformed in his work with Guattari into a doctrinal panpsychism that he
81
This helps to explain why identity politics activists in the USA gave so much attention to
regulating language, especially in educational institutions. To shape language was to shape
institutions—that was the conviction behind the forces of “political correctness.”
TEXTS AND BODIES 277
82
See also “Deleuze is in my bones” in an interview with Bruno Latour, where it becomes
clear that the whole “agency of things” trope in “Actor Network Theory” echoes Deleuze’s
metaphysics: http://figureground.org/interview-with-bruno-latour/.
278 T. DE ZENGOTITA
lectures available on YouTube, all of which vividly convey the spirit of the
Deleuzean enterprise.
The key term “singularity” began life with Deleuze as a reference to
something like the sense-certainty moment in Hegel’s Phenomenology, a
moment when the subject, emerging from the given of the transcendental
field, is absorbed in the immediate object/content of an intuition; it was
later expanded to include multiple “sensitive points” in the transcendental
field, a multiplication that seemed somehow to put more “experience”
into the impossible notion of pre-subjective experience. By the time of the
Guattari collaborations, it had taken on a topological, quasi-scientific sig-
nificance—referencing threshold effects and changes of state in dynamic
systems (e.g., water’s boiling point as a function of variable intensities like
pressure and temperature).
The motivating intention at that juncture was the hope that singularities
understood in this way might also apply, at least in principle, to societies as
dynamic systems. Could “revolution points” be identified as singularities
on a Riemann topological graph if the right variables were chosen along the
N-axes—with this all-important amendment: it might be practically impos-
sible to identify the relevant variables, let alone “measure” them for values,
but the metaphysics of univocity (Spinoza’s monism), fusing with a meta-
physics of becoming across all levels of order and disorder in the universe,
would be vividly evoked along with the in-principle possibility of scientific
describability for revolutions in human history that testifies to a completely
naturalist ontology.
I am arguing, in effect, that the idea of that topological graph, with its
many thousands of axes referencing social/economic/political trends, is
essentially an artwork—one of many in a vast installation called Capitalism
and Schizophrenia. It evokes, on the one hand, the uncontainable com-
plexity of human historical circumstances and happenings while at the
same time assimilating human history in principle to the same theoretical
apparatus that applies in fluid dynamics. Feel free to indulge in a love of
science fiction by imagining a day when the Internet-of-Things, measur-
ing actual values for the relevant variables, converges with advances in
network theory and computer modeling to actually produce something
like the graph in question. Such imaginings will be constrained to some
extent by concepts drawn from science and math, with the extent being
determined by how much you happen to know about the science and
math. But ultimately the extent and accuracy of such knowledge is beside the
point. This is art. Deleuze’s whole metaphysical vision, like Delanda’s topo-
logical graph, should be understood as art—philosophy-as-art.
TEXTS AND BODIES 279
Could it be that at the moment the war machine ceases to exist, conquered
by the State, it displays to the utmost its irreducibility, that it scatters into
thinking, loving, dying, or creating machines that have at their disposal vital
or revolutionary powers capable of challenging the conquering State?
(Deleuze and Guattari 1987, 356)
Coda: Becoming-sensation
For Gilles Deleuze, at the end of the day, becoming was what mattered
and becoming-sensation was its purest form, for that led most surely to the
beyond-self.83 Becoming just is life—for people, for the ocean, for the
mountain, for the planet. If there is no discernible political program to be
found in Capitalism and Schizophrenia, it is because the whole idea of a
“program” was antithetical to becoming. That priority, which ultimately
makes it futile to try to found a politics on Deleuzean metaphysics, was
made perfectly clear by the man himself in an interview with Parnet (Deleuze
from A to Z 2012) that took place under the rubric “G is for Gauche
(Left)”: after mocking the new philosophers and various historians who
whine about revolutions not turning out well, he distinguishes between
“becoming-revolutionary” and whatever actually happens as a result. He
said that “’68 was a becoming-revolutionary without a revolutionary future.
People can always make fun of it after the fact, but there were phenomena
of pure becoming that took hold of people” and his face is aglow at the
thought of it all. “Precocious adolescent to the end of his days”—that’s how
I described him at the beginning of this account and I think it holds up well.
There he is in that interview, illness visibly upon him, his every gesture radi-
ating innocence of all responsibility—not “responsibility for this or that”
but responsibility itself, the very idea of it. The future of history is always up
for grabs in a Nietzschean cosmos and its artist/philosopher was not about
to cower under a political program for protection from its elements.
So look to Deleuze, as you would to any artist, for inspiration as a pri-
vate being and look elsewhere for your politics, serious business of another
order (but compare Rorty 1989, chap. 4, 73–95). Politics is like parent-
hood in a lot of ways, not least in this: responsibility cannot be avoided. On
83
It must have seemed to Deleuze that in becoming-sensation he was healing the breach
created by Kant’s self-alienating “I think” (the first “difference” that fascinated him) just
insofar has he managed to be aware of becoming-sensation without really thinking about it.
With this, Deleuze thinks he is getting outside of “representations” through encounters with
“the being of the sensible.” All of which suggests that there is a practice associated with this
art project, just as there is with phenomenology or meditation. This practice doesn’t consist
of habits but of openness to all that isn’t habitual. To Artaud and to Bacon, to surges and
flows of intensities in general—as opposed to the objects we are conditioned to attend to. In
other words, to be a Deleuzean means cultivating a faculty for “thinking the impossible.”
282 T. DE ZENGOTITA
the other hand, as long as we are considering sensible advice from Rorty,
we are also obliged to make a space for experiments in our quest for a
vocabulary that works for our time—so why not this one? Create it and see
if it works. John Dewey welcomed that test. And this much must be said
for Deleuze and Guattari: they felt Nietzsche’s arrow pointing straight at
them and they responded with everything they had. So what if the fruit of
their collaboration turned out to be something more like one of Raymond
Roussel’s novels than a work of serious philosophy or a platform for a new
politics. Surely there is room in the Amazon warehouse for both?
So we turn to another leading light among the desirants, known (unlike
Deleuze) for his political activism; perhaps he can supply what was want-
ing in his friend’s efforts.
This section aims to shed some light on the reasons for his abiding
influence, but the kind of interpretive scrutiny given to Deleuze and
Derrida will not be necessary. Foucault presents no comparable challenge
to our understanding. Instead, this section will try to recover something
of the evocative force of his example, the drama of his life and work. He
serves as an epitome.84
surprise there, when you think about it, for many of them were fortunately
placed in society by birth, yet moved somehow to profound opposition.
And the authors of French theory were no exception, although little
“Jackie” Derrida seems to have been relatively content—plenty of friends,
loved his soccer and cinema, cared deeply for his father, tensions with his
mother eventually resolved (Peeters [2010] 2013, 22–34). And, indeed, it
is notable that the particular flavor of a bitterness rooted in personal pain
is largely missing from his work. But the rest of them did not have an easy
time of it, growing up—although Foucault was in a class all his own,
utterly wretched. He was tormented until near the end by a “self” he spent
his life looking for ways to escape. Like the others, he found consolation
in the exercise of his native intelligence in environments where academic
performance and status were universally respected. But even in those envi-
ronments Foucault suffered terribly.
After describing an “almost insane tension” at the École Normale
Superieure where “everyone felt he was risking his social and intellectual
existence” in the race “to be brilliant, to stand out … to play the part of
the exceptional individual, to strike a pose for future fame,” Didier Eribon
places Foucault specifically:
own life as a young man and was obsessed as well with self-mutilation
(Macey 1995, 27–28). Psychiatric evaluations attributed all this to his com-
pulsive and conflicted sexual behavior—hooking up with strangers in the
gay underground at a time when the social taboo against “homosexuals”
was virulent, plus his indulgence in drugs, and other self-destructive activi-
ties (Macey 1995, 30; Miller 1994, 55–56). For Michel Foucault, there was
nothing abstract about “transgression,” which is why Elisabeth Roudinesco
called him “The philosopher of the pathways of the night” (2010, 93).
9.4.2 Transgression, Salvation
for us, discontinuous beings that we are, death means continuity of being …
reproduction and death … both of these concepts are equally fascinating
and this fascination is the dominant element in eroticism … [as] individuals
who perish in isolation in the midst of an incomprehensible adventure, we
yearn for our lost continuity. … This nostalgia … is responsible for the three
forms of eroticism in man … physical, emotional and religious … with all of
them, the concern is to substitute for the individual isolated discontinuity a
feeling of profound continuity. (Georges Bataille [1962] 1986, 13–15)
85
Bataille was indebted to many for inspiration and he acknowledged them frequently, but
he insisted that Nietzsche had the “decisive” impact upon him (Surya 2002, 52). And his
friend, Pierre Klossowski, also passed on to the creators of French theory a version of
Nietzsche that invited appropriation—especially in Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle (1997).
286 T. DE ZENGOTITA
In 1957, the young Michel Foucault noticed some faded yellow books in José
Corti’s famous Parisian book store and tentatively asked the grand old man
‘who was Raymond Roussel?’ Wearied by Foucault’s ignorance, Corti looked at
him with a ‘generous sort of pity’ and feeling a sense of loss sighed: ‘But after
all, Roussel …’ What Corti told him and what he found in the pages he raced
through mesmerized Foucault into paying for an expensive copy of ‘La Vue’
and (in two months) he wrote the darkly Romantic Death and the Labyrinth on
Roussel’s world. (Foucault cited in Clark’s “A Lovely Curiosity,” 2002)
86
Which appealed to Foucault because “his music … tears apart the knowledge of the
subject by rendering it foreign to itself” (Santini 2002).
TEXTS AND BODIES 287
all this and goes to the heart of the matter when he foregrounds Roussel’s
strangely staged suicide (Hence, “death” in the book’s title) and Foucault’s
fascination with that staging.88 Gutting sums up: “We have no way of
knowing whether this focus on death—which continues throughout
Foucault’s writings—led, as Miller encourages us to speculate, to Foucault
deliberately putting himself and others at risk from AIDS. But there is no
doubt that his work shows a fascination with the loss of self brought both
by death and by its mirror in the linguistic formalism of writing such as
Roussel’s.”
Finally, and—with just that theme in mind—most importantly, there
was Georges Bataille. He is the most proximate and perhaps the most
scandalous representative of the artistic guild known as Poetes Maudits,
and for good reason. In prewar Paris, he had brought to life the legendary
violations of Lautreamont, Verlaine, and Rimbaud. In the 1950s, he still
walked among awe-struck artists and intellectuals of postwar Paris, a more
detached and philosophical expositor of doctrines he had once tried to
realize, back in the day, a day that still lived in the memories of friends and
associates, who were willing to tell tales (how tall?) of his—and their—for-
bidden doings. His personal charisma had, if anything, grown more
charged, though he always spoke gently and carried himself with a clerical
gravity perfectly suited to his reputation as the high priest of transgression
and reminiscent as well of the orthodox piety of his youth. But Georges
Bataille also reflected in writing on the ideas that drove him. Those
reflections perpetuated his glamor and left a legacy that lived on in the
work of others, in the work of Michel Foucault in particular:
Perhaps the importance of sexuality in our culture derives from nothing else
than this correspondence which connects it to the death of God. … By
denying us the limit of the Limitless, the death of God leads to an experi-
ence in which nothing may again announce the exteriority of being, and
consequently to an experience which is interior and sovereign … such an
experience … discloses … the limitless range of the Limit, and the emptiness
of those excesses in which it spends itself and where it is found wanting …
88
Says James Faubion in the Introduction to Death and the Labyrinth (XX): “Foucault’s
relationship to Roussel is noticeably protective … its most telling gesture is that of a hand—
or pen—raised against any and all of those roving psychologists who would … treat (and so
invalidate) his oeuvre as a mere catalogue of symptoms … [in his book] Foucault proposes
that Roussel’s suicide in Palermo is … a corporal demonstration of the imperative that the
oeuvre “must be set free from the person who wrote it” (156).
TEXTS AND BODIES 289
89
It says a lot about Foucault’s reputation after the publication of his History of Madness in
1961 that this homage to Bataille was published in an issue of Critique, the journal he
founded immediately after WWII.
290 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Bataille’s final letter … noted, “the sacred, in my opinion, first and foremost
counters utility and those passions whose object conforms to reason … we
always find some prohibition forbidding behavior that is convulsive, foreign
to selfish calculation, and that originates in the animal world.” But this
debate inevitably hearkens back to the late 1930s, when Bataille was launch-
ing his secret society, Acephale, driven by the project of human sacrifice.…
[M]ore or less coextensive with the College of Sociology, Acephale (whose
metaphorical name, “headless,” had in mind both Nietzsche’s death of God
and “the headless crowd”) anarchically attacked any kind of hierarchical
system) … recent publication of Acephale’s internal documents illuminate
the group’s decision to go underground. … In 1974, Caillois further
explained, “Bataille believed that accomplishing a human sacrifice would be
an irreversible point. … It came close to happening. The victim had been
TEXTS AND BODIES 291
found, it was the sacrificer who was missing. Bataille offered me the role.
Because I had written a panegyric about Saint-Just while still in high school,
he probably supposed that I had the latter’s inexorable character. Things
didn’t get beyond that. (Claudine Frank in The Edge of Surrealism: A Roger
Caillois Reader 2003, 27–30)
90
James Miller may have gone too far in The Passion of Michel Foucault (1994). But we
need not agree with his reading completely to recognize some resonance of his sex life in his
work. A devotee of sado-masochism doesn’t just happen to name a book Discipline and
Punish—and, yes, “passion” in the title carries a Christ-on-the-cross connotation.
91
Gary Gutting stressed the importance of this aspect of language for Foucault (2013,
5–18). If it weren’t for its subject obliterating effects (and the requirements of fashion), it is
not clear that Foucault would have engaged much with language, even in his “structuralist”
phase.
292 T. DE ZENGOTITA
the problem of language appeared, and it was clear that phenomenology was
no match for structural analysis … in which the subject (in the phenomeno-
logical sense) did not intervene to confer meaning. … Psychoanalysis—in
large part under the influence of Lacan—also raised a problem. … For the
unconscious could not feature in any discussion of a phenomenological
kind. (Foucault 1988, 21)92
9.4.3 The Works
This brings us to the works for which Foucault is known. A brief summary
of the principal stages in his development and the arguments that marked
them will suffice for present purposes. What is wanted is enough to estab-
lish the depth and extent of his influence in his own time and also to
account for the persistence of that influence in the anglophone academy:
Sex is “not even the individual’s fundamental or primitive desire; the very
texture of its processes exists prior to the individuals. … If we wish to know
what we are, we must abandon what we imagine about our individuality, our
ego, our position as subject.” (Foucault, letter to Pierre Guyot in Macey
[1970] 1995, 255–56)
92
Compare this with a more moderately framed dispute between anglophone philoso-
phers: “Searle’s central question [is] … ‘how do we get from the bits of paper to dollar bills?’
Now, this really is a question about ontology—about what it is for something to be money,
not just about what the intentional content of our mental states is when we interact with or
have thoughts about or use money. So it might seem obvious, as Searle suggests, that the
phenomenologists have no way of grappling with or even understanding this question”
(Kelly 2004, 9; italics mine). Kelly goes on to argue that it isn’t obvious!
TEXTS AND BODIES 293
has been noted, even during this structuralist phase, it was the trans-
subjective aspect of the episteme that most interested Foucault. Like
Deleuze, he never showed a real interest in the explanatory formalisms
that preoccupied Levi-Strauss, Lacan, Kristeva and Sollers, Genette, and
the early Barthes and he went out of his way, as soon as circumstances
allowed, to distance himself from the “priority of the signifier” (see
O’Conner in Silverman 1997). This made it possible for Foucault to shift
his emphasis, more or less seamlessly, to overtly materialist and historical
processes without giving up his focus on discourse. With Discipline and
Punish (1975), Foucault consolidated the decisive power/knowledge
phase of his work, explicitly post-Marxist but also definitively poststruc-
turalist, with its emphasis on Nietzschean genealogies (no telos, only
contending forces) of discursive practices and the governance of human
bodies in institutional settings as the focus.93
But it was a much earlier book, The Order of Things (1966), written
when Structuralism was ascendant, in which Foucault gave the essential anti-
humanism of theory its most influential expression. He there announced that
the concept of “man,” constituted at a particular historical moment, as the
anchor for a particular episteme, was now in dissolution, thanks to
Structuralism and Lacanian psychoanalysis. With a flourish, he concluded
that book by proclaiming that “man is in the process of perishing as the
being of language continues to shine ever brighter upon our horizon” and
may eventually be “erased, like a face drawn in sand at the edge of the sea”
(1966, 385–387).94 But it was not really the generic “man” that Foucault
93
Foucault was criticized for moving away from Marx as early as 1966 in The Order of
Things, and he was in a later context heard to say to a reporter who asked him about Marx
during a street demonstration, “I don’t want to hear that name any more.” But, in spite of
such rejections, the grip of conventional commitments was strong. As late as 1972, in con-
versation with Deleuze in a journal of the American new left, Foucault concluded (with
Deleuze shamelessly agreeing) by reassuring his audience that “Women, prisoners, con-
scripted soldiers, hospital patients, and homosexuals” who “have now begun a specific strug-
gle … naturally enter as allies of the proletariat. … They genuinely serve the cause of the
proletariat by fighting in those places they find themselves oppressed” (Deleuze and
Foucault 1973, Telos 16). Identity politics instead of socialism? Not to worry.
94
Recognizing yet another barb, Sartre responded by calling Foucault “a positivist in
despair.” For Sartre, a superficial “objectivity” was the only conceivable alternative to the
philosophy of the subject in history. He never really understood the abstractions of
Structuralism—just as he couldn’t countenance the modernist retreat from lived experience
in general (See above on Barthes’ Writing Degree Zero [1953] 1984). Foucault had, rather
cruelly, identified the problem when he described the Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960)
TEXTS AND BODIES 295
as “a nineteenth-century man’s magnificent and pathetic attempt to think the 20th century”
(in Bourg 2007, 48). A perfect illustration of what Kojevian Marxism looked like to French
Nietzscheans of the 1960s. It was marred, above all, by the persistence of nineteenth-century
evolutionism’s telos.
296 T. DE ZENGOTITA
95
Foucault had not relinquished his critical stance entirely. The friendship he focused on
(though not exclusively) was friendship between gay men—an especially promising prospect
precisely because it had to be cultivated outside conventional parameters. A free creation,
then—just like the “techniques of the self” the Greeks had enjoyed.
96
See, for example, Jurgen Habermas “Taking Aim at the Heart of the Present” in
Foucault: A Critical Reader, Oxford 1986; Christopher Norris “What is enlightenment?” in
The Cambridge Companion to Foucault, Cambridge 1994; Paul Rabinow Ethics, Subjectivity
and Truth, The New Press 1997.
298 T. DE ZENGOTITA
I’m not going to say that there is a metaphysics, the metaphysics or its clo-
sure, concealed in this “textualization” of discursive practices. I’m going to
go much further. I am going to say that it is a minor pedagogy, one thor-
oughly historically determined, that manifests itself in a way that is highly
visible. This pedagogy teaches the pupil that there is nothing outside the
text. … This pedagogy gives the teachers voice that unlimited sovereignty
which allows it to repeat the text indefinitely. (Eribon 1992, 121)
Having broken with the “priority of the signifier” as the wheel of fash-
ion came around, Foucault could now advance a meta-response to Derrida
that seemed weighty enough to displace the relatively trivial issue of how
to interpret a few lines in Descartes’ text. In fact, he never satisfactorily
addressed Derrida’s reading of the relevant passage and no wonder, for
Derrida was transparently correct about the place of “madness” in
Descartes’ argument. That deserves to be emphasized, first of all:
it can no longer literally be said that the Cogito would escape madness
because … as Foucault says, “I who think, I cannot be mad”; the Cogito
escapes madness only because at its own moment, under its own authority
300 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Generally speaking, Madness and Civilization accorded far too great a place,
and a very enigmatic one, to what I called an “experiment,” thus showing
to what extent one was still close to admitting an anonymous and general
subject of experience. (1971, 16)97
97
Lee Braver argues in A Thing of this World (2007) that Foucault believed there was
something like true madness that wasn’t being expressed by reason, but was nevertheless
there. The next section of Braver’s book is called “no remainder” and claims that, in The
Archaeology of Knowledge, Foucault finally gets away from his residual realism (2007,
347–353). It also seems likely that he was simply embarrassed into taking a more categorical
position—and, in any case, it didn’t last.
302 T. DE ZENGOTITA
9.4.5 Coming to America
I think that if one wants to analyze the genealogy of the subject in Western
civilization, he has to take into account not only techniques of domination
but also techniques of the self … [which] … permit individuals to perform,
by their own means, a certain number of operations on their own bodies, on
their own souls, on their own thoughts, on their own conduct, and this in
such a way that they transform themselves. (Foucault in Braver 2007, 406)
98
Too biased to be generally reliable, Ferry and Renault can nevertheless be specifically
insightful. See, for example, their account of what constituted the “unthought” at the
moment the “Classical” human sciences were being conceived according to Foucault in The
Order of Things. The objects and processes that came to constitute the subject matter of biol-
ogy, linguistics, and economics were not unthinkable, they just hadn’t been “thought”
(1990, 103–104).
TEXTS AND BODIES 303
nothing but contempt for the French poststructuralists and for the impen-
etrable language of the so-called theory they exported to the anglophone
academy. He is convinced that the whole thing was a scam and—worse—
an excuse for a political passivity. But he was willing to concede a bit to
Foucault, reporting that “we even have a several-hour discussion … on
real issues, and using language that was perfectly comprehensible”
(http://mindfulpleasures.blogspot.com/2011/01/noam-chomsky-on-
derrida-foucault-lacan.html). And his response to Foucault’s work fell
short of blanket dismissal, though it was not exactly positive: “Some of
Foucault’s particular examples (say, about 18th century techniques of
punishment) look interesting, and worth investigating as to their accuracy.
… As to ‘posturing,’ a lot of it is that, in my opinion, though I don’t par-
ticularly blame Foucault for it: it’s such a deeply rooted part of the corrupt
intellectual culture of Paris that he fell into it pretty naturally, though to
his credit, he distanced himself from it” (see Wolters 2013).
Searle was even more forgiving of Foucault, saying that lumping him in
with Derrida was “very unfair to Foucault. He was a different caliber of
thinker altogether.” Searle’s more positive assessment may have had some-
thing to do with Foucault providing Searle with a meme-worthy quote
accusing Derrida of practicing a “terrorism of obscurantism” (in Searle
(Feb 2000)). That was welcome support for Searle in the contretemps
described earlier. Finally, and in spite of the extended attention Foucault
gave to some of the sciences in his early work, he was not singled out in
Sokal and Bricmont’s Fashionable Nonsense, nor was he typically accused
of outright fraud by anglophone critics of French theory.
But there is a more specific reason, still having to do with language, for
his enduring influence. And once again, timing was key. Foucault’s critique
of power/knowledge was also a license for those who were seeking to craft
forms of power/knowledge to replace the conventional discourses and
institutional practices they were opposing. Foucault seemed to understand
that a political discourse that denied the existence of “facts” and “truths”
as they had once been naively understood was in danger of undermining
itself.
France) and had a broad, if shallower, influence on the whole society. And
the questions that arise as we assess the situation now include: has an inher-
ently oppositional postmodern moment been lapsing because its affirma-
tive claims have been so widely admitted, at least in certain quarters, in the
bicoastal precincts where cultural “elites” hold sway? Can Queer Theory,
for example, survive marriage equality? But, more urgently at the moment
of this writing, when so much that has been associated with the postmod-
ern is apparently now serving the interests of identity politics on the right—
a hoary old question must again be asked: what is to be done?
References
Allen, Graham. 2003. Roland Barthes. London: Routledge.
Austin, J.L. (1962) 1971. How to Do Things with Words: The William James
Lectures Delivered at Harvard University in 1955. London: Oxford.
Baring, Edward. 2011. The Young Derrida and French Philosophy, 1945–1968.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Barthes, Roland. (1953) 1984. Writing Degree Zero: & Elements of Semiology,
65–75. London: J. Cape.
———. (1957) 1972. Mythologies. London: J. Cape.
———. (1968) 1977. The Death of the Author. In Image-Music-Text. Trans.
Stephen Heath. Glasgow: Fontana/Collins.
———. (1971) 1986. Mythology Today. In The Rustle of Language, 65–68. Trans.
Richard Howard. New York: Hill and Wang.
———. 1975a. The Pleasure of the Text. Trans. Richard Miller. New York: Hill and
Wang.
———. (1975b) 1977. Roland Barthes. Trans. Richard Howard. New York:
Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Bataille, Georges. (1962) 1986. Eroticism: Death & Sensuality. Trans. Mary
Dalwood. San Francisco: City Lights.
Beaulieu, Alain. 2011. The Status of Animality in Deleuze’s Thought. Journal for
Critical Animal Studies IX (1/2): 69–88.
Bell, Jeffrey, and Claire Colebrook, eds. 2009. Deleuze and History. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
Bogue, Ronald. 2007. Deleuze’s Way: Essays in Transverse Ethics and Aesthetics.
Aldershot: Ashgate.
Bourdieu, Pierre. (1979) 1984. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of
Taste. Trans. Richard Nice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bourg, Julian. 2007. From Revolution to Ethics: May 1968 and Contemporary
French Thought. Montreal: McGill-Queens University Press.
Bowden, Sean. 2011. Priority of Events: Deleuze’s Logic of Sense. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
TEXTS AND BODIES 307
———. (1967b) 1973. Speech and Phenomena, and Other Essays on Husserl’s
Theory of Signs. Trans. David B. Allison. Evanston: Northwestern University
Press.
———. (1967c) 1976. Of Grammatology. Trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
———. (1967d) 2001. Cogito and the History of Madness. In Writing and
Difference. Trans. Alan Bass, 36–76. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.
———. (1967e) 2001. DifferAnce. In Writing and Difference. Trans. Alan Bass.
London: Routledge.
———. (1967f) 2001. Violence and Metaphysics. In Writing and Difference.
Trans. Alan Bass, 118. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
———. (1972) 1981. Positions. Trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
———. (1980) 1987. The Post Card: From Socrates to Freud and Beyond. Chicago:
University of Chicago.
———. 1988. Limited Inc. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Descombes, Vincent. (1979) 1980. Modern French Philosophy. Trans. L. Scott Fox
and J.M. Harding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dosse, Francois. 1997. The History of Structuralism: Volume 2: The Sign Sets, 1967–
Present. Trans. Deborah Glassman. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
———. (2007) 2010. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari: Intersecting Lives.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Dreyfus, Hubert, and Paul Rabinow. 1983. Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism
and Hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Eribon, Didier. 1992. Michel Foucault. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Fanon, Frantz. (1961) 2004. The Wretched of the Earth. Trans. Richard Philcox.
New York: Grove Press.
Ferry, Luc, and Alain Renault. 1990. French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on
Antihumanism. Trans. Mary H. S. Cattani. Amherst: University of
Massachusetts Press.
Foucault, Michel. (1966) 1994. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human
Sciences. New York: Vintage.
———. 1970. Theatrum Philosophicum. Critique 282: 885–908.
———. 1971. The Discourse on Language. In The Archaeology of Knowledge.
New York: Pantheon.
———. (1975) 1995. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York:
Vintage.
———. (1976) 1978. The History of Sexuality: Volume 1, The Will to Knowledge.
Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Vintage Books.
TEXTS AND BODIES 309
Ong, Walter. 1967. The Presence of the Word: Some Prolegomena for Cultural and
Religious History. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Parr, Adrian, ed. 2010. The Deleuze Dictionary. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press.
Patton, Paul, and John Protevi, eds. 2003. Between Deleuze and Derrida.
New York: Continuum.
Peeters, Benoit. 2013. Derrida: A Biography. Trans. Andrew Brown. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Proust, Marcel. (1913) 1998. Swann’s Way: In Search of Lost Time: Volume 1.
New York: Modern Library.
Rapaport, Herman. 2001. The Theory Mess: Deconstruction in Eclipse. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Reich, Wilhelm. 1946. The Mass Psychology of Fascism. Trans. Theodore P. Wolfe.
https://archive.org/stream/WILHELMREICHTheMassPsychology
OfFascism/WILHELM+REICH+-+The+Mass+Psychology+of+Fascism_djvu.
txt
Roffe, Jon. 2012. Review of The Priority of Events: Deleuze’s Logic of Sense, by Sean
Bowden. Parrhesia 15: 106–111.
Rorty, Richard. 1989. Solidarity or Objectivity. In Contingency, Irony, and
Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1991. Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Reification of Language. In Essays
on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Roudinescu, Elisabeth. 2010. Philosophy in Turbulent Times: Canguilhem, Sartre,
Foucault, Althusser, Deleuze, Derrida. New York: Columbia University Press.
Roussel, Raymond. (1935) 1975. How I Wrote Certain of my Books. Trans. Trevor
Winkfield. New York: SUN.
Santini, Sylvano. 2002. Michel Foucault: Literature and the Arts: A Report from
the Colloquium at Cerisy-la-Salle, June 23–30, 2001. SubStance 31 (1): 77–84.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. (1948) 2001. What Is Literature? Trans. Bernard Frechtman.
London: Routledge.
Schrift, Alan. 1995. Nietzsche’s French Legacy: A Genealogy of Poststructuralism.
New York: Routledge.
Searle, John R. 1969. Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. London:
Cambridge University Press.
———. 1977. Reiterating the Differences: A Reply to Derrida. Glyph 1 (1977):
198–208.
———. 1983. The World Turned Upside Down. New York Review of Books 30
(1983): 74–79.
Sellars, Wilfrid. (1956) 1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Silverman, Hugh J., ed. 1997. Philosophy and Non-philosophy Since Merleau-Ponty.
Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
312 T. DE ZENGOTITA
this thing from France … for which one created the name and the concept
of “theory,” yet another purely American word and concept. (Derrida
2001)1
1
See also Barsky on how “French theory may be primarily an American dream” in
SubStance #97: 8.
and Milos Forman’s film (1975) starring Jack Nicholson (who also
appeared with Dennis Hopper in Easy Rider (1969)) specifically shared
the attitude of the “anti-psychiatry” movement with which Foucault and
Guattari were affiliated. R.D. Laing’s The Divided Self (1960) was in many
a knapsack in the 1960s, along with Herbert Marcuse’s One-Dimensional
Man and Paul Goodman’s Growing Up Absurd. Many of these Americans
were already in the academy, as students. They were the ones at the barri-
cades at Columbia University in 1968, for example, and Kent State in
1970; some among them—the most earnest among them, it must be
said—became academics and proponents of postmodernism, of “theory,”
as they grew older. Which, of course, they did; and in this simple fact lies
a lot of explanation: as the 1970s rolled on, agents of the counter-culture,
diversifying now into identity groups as women and African-Americans and
Gays and Lesbians laid claim to their places at the table, were taking posi-
tions of responsibility in “establishment” institutions. Naturally, they set
out to remake those institutions in their own image, to the degree possi-
ble, especially cultural institutions, especially universities—but also many
secondary schools, museums, libraries, publishing.
But even the 1960s people, at least the ones who chose academic
careers, even the ones who might have been in on an anarchic joke at a
Schizo-Culture conference, even they would eventually feel the heavy
hand of academic conformity upon them. Credentials, publications, posi-
tions—above all, the manners—became more and more important as time
went by and institutional life took hold.
Sum it up this way: if the editors of some Tel Quel-like equivalent of
SocialText got caught publishing Alan Sokal’s famous hoax paper, they
would have known better than to dilute their claims to revolutionary
panache by fulminating about violations of collegial trust and “inappropri-
ate” academic behavior—they would have said something like: “of course
we knew it wasn’t for real, but it was too clever to ignore: ‘Transgressing
the Boundaries: Towards a Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum
Gravity.’ Perfect! Alfred Jarry would have loved it!”
But it didn’t happen that way. Over the years, those who learned their
“theory” second hand, from English translations of French texts and from
leading anglophone followers of the original creators, were bound to lean
too hard on jargon and lose the spirit of the original enterprise as the jargon
hardened into its own kind of doxa, just as Barthes foretold. At the same
time, however, they assumed control over substantial educational infra-
structure and resources, made fundamental administrative and curricular
decisions, and attracted and educated generations of students into seeing
316 T. DE ZENGOTITA
themselves and the world in something like the way they did; a better way.
So they were not selling out—they were doing what you had to do if you
really wanted change, displacing what Foucault would have called “intoler-
able discursive practices” with better ones.
The picture just painted, in the broadest brush strokes, does no more
than outline an extremely complicated process that looked very different in
different places and in different disciplines. What was common across the
board was the way in which whatever versions of “theory” were appropri-
ated in those contexts, they all served a “deconstructive” purpose, with that
word understood much more broadly now than Derrida intended. It came
to mean something like “dismantle or otherwise debunk the categories,
aims, methods, and institutional perogatives of established disciplines” by
showing how they imposed stabilizing assumptions and categorical con-
straints upon fluid realities that ought to be dealt with in more open-ended
and reflexive ways. That was especially apparent when those constraints
excluded whole groups of people from consideration, either as subjects of
study on their own terms or as participants in that study—that is, as scholars
in their own fields, defining those fields for themselves and their colleagues
and students. What had been set had to be unsettled and the authorities
who presided over what had been set would themselves, inevitably, be
unsettled; they would resist. Sometimes, in some places and disciplines, that
resistance frequently prevailed (cognitive psychology, economics). In other
places and disciplines, insurgent discourses succeeded in establishing them-
selves (anthropology, comparative literature).2 A complex process. We can
do no more here than sample some representative instances.
Attention will be given instead to J. Hillis Miller, who is in any case more
representative of the broad swath of academics in the humanities who
were moved to engage with “theory.” Some were inspired, others felt
obliged, still others were downright afraid of missing the coming wave.
Miller very definitely fell into the first category and so acted as a leader/
mediator for other, less certain, participants in the theory movement in
literary studies. He was very close to Derrida (who followed Miller to
Irvine) and his election to the presidency of the Modern Language
Association in 1986 caused one of those deeply serious, ultimately comic,
academic uproars (compare Rorty’s election to the same post in the
American Philosophical Association in 1979). It seemed to many immedi-
ately involved to mark the triumph of a “hermeneutical mafia” in the insti-
tutionalized humanities, when in fact the postmodern tide was at that
moment turning against “high theory” in favor of more broadly conceived
and politically vested fields like Cultural Studies, Gender Studies, and so
on (see especially H. Rapaport 2001). Opposition from the neo-Marxist
left was of course ongoing—perhaps most famously represented by Jurgen
Habermas (see The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity 1987)—and, of
course, as already mentioned, by Fredric Jameson and David Harvey.
Miller began his career under the spell of modernist formalism (see
Chap. 3, above), and so, like most of his cohort at Yale and beyond, he saw
deconstruction as “a natural extension of the New Criticism” because of
its apparent focus on the workings of texts in the usual sense of that word.
Derrida, especially, was held responsible and came under attack for this
textual formalism from more political postmodern movements, in spite of
their shared opposition to closure and concern for “the other” (Rapaport
2001, XVIII, 59–60).3 Meanwhile, critics of deconstruction on the tradi-
tional left were inclined to a complementary gesture that could be just as
confusing. Gerald Graff, for example, in his influential critique Literature
Against Itself (1979), reprised Georg Lukacs’ attack on the modernist
retreat to form by indicting postmodern theory for fleeing “political real-
ity.” Like Christopher Lasch (The Culture of Narcissism 1979) and other
non-dogmatic Marxists, Graff was often lumped in with critics of
3
Does this explain why anglophone practitioners of deconstruction in literary disciplines
so often seemed to overlook the significance of Derrida’s “general text” of “all possible ref-
erents?”. That would make them partly accountable for egregious misrepresentations of
Derrida more generally. Was their narrow interpretation a lingering effect of the New
Criticism? Did Derrida, who spent many months at Yale, allow this misunderstanding to
persist for the sake of keeping his followers productive and content? That would not be
inconsistent with his history, as we have seen.
318 T. DE ZENGOTITA
to get the story straight becomes this: why were most traditional human-
ists able to tolerate, and even embrace, modernist formalism but not
deconstruction?
And the answer is this: Hillis Miller was wrong. The account given
above of the essential difference between the “intentional fallacy” of mod-
ernism and the “death of the author” of postmodernism (see above, Chap.
9.1.2) shows us why. Deconstruction was not a “natural extension” of the
New Criticism. It was a radical refusal of formalism, of synchronic abstrac-
tion; it was a return to time and history—but a return that, as has been
shown, not only maintained but radicalized the ban on the subject. The
result was performance with no actor, parole with no speaker, meaning
with no intention, text with no author—that was the impossible anti-
humanism of theory.
And that was the underlying reason, not always explicitly articulated,
that modernists in all the humanistic disciplines, however ready they might
have been to experiment with form in the spirit of Wimsatt and Beardsley,
instinctively resisted deconstruction and its affines. They rightly under-
stood that they were themselves—and not just the canonical texts they
cherished—the targets of theory.
To be sure, postmodern jargon could give the appearance of “abstrac-
tion” because it was so far removed from the concrete concerns of our
everyday lived experience as human subjects—but, if the word “abstrac-
tion” applies at all, it does so in a very different way. In fact, as we have
seen, French ultra-structuralism, in spite of some lingering structuralist
influence on its discourses, grew more and more overtly opposed to the
formalism upon which various manifestations of modernism had thrived,
Structuralism in particular. Barthes 2.0 looked back on the enterprises of
Barthes 1.0 with something approaching embarrassment. Nary a text of
Derrida’s displays a chart or formula. Levi-Strauss, on the other hand,
never made the turn Barthes took, never wavered from the formalist (sci-
entific) path as he oversaw the naturalization of his Structuralism into the
1990s (see Dosse 1997, chap. 37). “High theory” in the humanities was
doomed from the outset because of this fundamental misunderstanding
and its inevitable demise was hastened by an explosion of interest in another,
much more readily accessible, form of postmodernism—one in which the
everyday experience of human subjects of (almost) every description was
not just recognized but celebrated. From The Graduate (1967) to Thelma
and Louise (1992), from The Crying Game (1992) to Angels in America
(1991), from Mudbound (2017) to Black Panther (2018) to Everyperson’s
320 T. DE ZENGOTITA
5
Incidentally, my very politically engaged 30-something daughter, a public defender,
remembers Cindy Lauper as an early influence on her lifelong concern with social justice. I
don’t quite get it, but there it is.
THE ANGLOPHONE RECEPTION OF FRENCH THEORY: LITERARY… 323
strategies devoted to identity, made its ascendancy in the academy all the
more inevitable and its susceptibility to appropriation by skillful marketers
all the more apparent. Students could always find something to “identify
with” in that environment; Hillis Miller and high theory never had a chance.
asleep, which he often seemed to be, so tiresome (said his manner) had the
same old analytic back and forth become.6
That world-weary air is essential to understanding Rorty’s influence. It
was a significant aspect of the way he dramatized the moment of moving
on, of leaving the “Plato–Kant canon” behind. Deflating quips directed at
the pretensions of philosophers were cast in tones suggesting that the war
was actually over—the old guard just hadn’t realized it yet.
Strong in learning, buttressed by a sturdy New Deal liberalism rooted in
childhood experience of Communist cant, Rorty was not threatened by
exotic continental formulations in philosophical critique or in politics. He
was not driven to blanket dismissal out of provincial rigidity or fear of ideo-
logical intoxication. He could spend the night with Heidegger and return
to Dewey in the morning, his original commitment intact. The doctrines of
pragmatism were like vaccinations against excesses of all kinds and they
allowed him to proceed indulgently to an assessment of the works of all his
fellows, however alien they might at first appear. His glowing accounts of
Derrida, for example, showed no trace of contamination by the jargon.7 He
left that sort of (possibly craven?) mimicry to lesser lights. He was as lucid
in discussion of de Man as of Quine, and that weighed heavily at implicit
levels of professional reception, where so much jockeying for academic
prestige takes place. See—he was saying sotto voce as he explained the con-
tinentals in plain old American English—that wasn’t so hard, was it? Which
suggested in turn: what is your problem, what are you afraid of? Could it
be the dawning realization that, yes, even linguistic philosophy in the twen-
tieth century is a historical formation, a fallible exercise of our finite pow-
ers, bound like all such exercises to fade away when its time is past? (And
after all that crowing! See Schlick quote above, Chap. 5.1).
Like Clifford Geertz in anthropology, Rorty managed to frame the
debates he took part in, political as well as intellectual, so that people who
still believed in Truth or Being or History (“Something Very Large,” as he
liked to put it) ended up looking immature—at best.
Rorty was cool.
But his impact was hot.8 He infuriated those to whom he condescended
because he proposed their overcoming, not by way of argument, but in an
6
See, for example, his video dialogue with Donald Davidson on YouTube.
7
It was the Derrida of Glas and The PostCard, the literary experimentalist, whom Rorty
claimed to admire—for “doing something different.” He found Derrida’s earlier work—the
work discussed in this book—too transcendental.
8
As the newly elected president of the American Philosophical Association in 1979, Rorty
ruled in favor of the renegade “pluralists” and against the analytic establishment, a betrayal
THE ANGLOPHONE RECEPTION OF FRENCH THEORY: LITERARY… 325
emerging culture which would simply have no place for their idea of phi-
losophy. That claim was so capacious that it could not be countered by
argument either. Rorty’s vision suspended internal questions of validity in
the very act of turning “philosophy” into an object of anthropological/
historical speculation. And the general mood in intellectual circles in the
1980s and 1990s worked very much in Rorty’s favor. You didn’t have to
read Baudrillard to notice what was becoming of world culture and to
sense that it did not bode well for the Plato–Kant canon.
Rorty—a small “p” patriot, who took the trouble to write a book
designed for the general reader (Achieving Our Country 1998)—con-
stantly found ways to stress the “Americanness” of pragmatism, going
back to Peirce, James, and especially Dewey. Significantly, that emphasis
on Dewey can be maintained thanks to a substantial overlap between prag-
matism and phenomenology—the same debt to and rejection of Hegel,
the same convergence with Nietzsche and, above all, the determination to
philosophize about experience as it actually is, about life as it actually goes
on. William James’ foundational “stream of consciousness” descriptions
were regarded by leaders of the phenomenological movement in Germany
as a significant contribution to their research (Gobar 1970).
But, as striking as that common ground in content may be, the contrast
in attitude is even more so. There was something very American—down to
earth, suspicious of the highfalutin’—about the pragmatists from the
beginning (Charles Peirce was perhaps an exception). The way Hegel’s
influence on Dewey persisted—though shorn of metaphysical preten-
sions—is mirrored today by Robert Brandom (Rorty’s student) in his
ongoing efforts to provide a more complete and explicit pragmatist reading
of Hegel (see Good 2006). So, given the pivotal role that phenomenology
played in shaping French theory, it is not surprising to find that an American
pragmatist as broadly educated as Richard Rorty could read through the
jargon, tease out the essentials, and, at the same time, elude the humiliation
of conversion. That latter saving grace, however, may have been owed as
much to his more immediate professional engagements with the philo-
sophical tradition he was abandoning and criticizing. Rorty praised Derrida
for “doing something else,” but he himself remained largely focused on
undoing the canon and discomfiting his analytic rivals—though he eventu-
ally ventured into discussions of literature and, especially, politics.
that many never forgave. An epic uproar ensued over which Rorty presided with characteris-
tic imperturbability. The message of his manner was the message of his philosophy: our
doings just aren’t that important. With Rorty especially, staging and rhetoric spoke
volumes.
326 T. DE ZENGOTITA
10.3.2 Intimate Enemies
Rorty’s millennial musings on the fate of philosophy were launched in
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979). There he took on the image
of mind as an internal “mirror of nature” that twentieth-century philoso-
phers inherited from seventeenth-century epistemology—and from Kant,
who positioned that mirror as “ground” for other departments of knowl-
edge and activity. From Rorty’s point of view, that image of mind—the
very one that was the initial focus of this book—was Descartes’ “inven-
tion,” an artificial “coalescence of beliefs and sensations into Lockean
ideas.” Rorty professed surprise that Descartes could “convince himself
that something which included both pains and mathematical knowledge
was ‘a complete thing,’” and did so in a way that “captured Europe’s
imagination” (136, 56, 223).
Actually, the account given in the first chapter of this book suggests an
explanation—and does so in precisely the cultural/contextual terms Rorty
recommended but did not actually deploy.9 Take, for example, the corre-
spondence between the situation of the cogito and the position of the believ-
ing Protestant in relation to God and the world as outlined in Chap. 2.10
Modern subjectivity would have emerged even if Descartes, a sickly boy
during his school days, had passed away in his dormitory at Le Havre. He
may have articulated that development with inspiring clarity for his fel-
lows in the Republic of Letters (thus “grasping the age in thought”), but
he did not invent it. Heidegger and, in his own way, Derrida may be the
only significant post-Hegelians who truly believe that the categories of
metaphysics determine the categories of the general culture and the way in
which history unfolds.
But Rorty, at this point in his career, was too wedded to his intimate
enemy to give serious attention to cultural context—though his postphilo-
sophical program would increasingly call for just that. He wasn’t really
addressing Locke and Kant in their time and place at all; he was using them
to argue with his contemporaries about the “privileges” of sense data and
propositional correspondence. Because Rorty represents the most credible
and enduring “postmodern” position in the anglophone academy, it might
9
For a fuller account, see my “The Functional Reduction of Kinship in the Social Thought
of John Locke” in Functionalism Historicized (1984).
10
The tutor to the Dauphin and a theologian of some note is reported to have perused The
Meditations for a few moments before slamming it down on the table, exclaiming, “Bah!
Protestantism in metaphysics!”
THE ANGLOPHONE RECEPTION OF FRENCH THEORY: LITERARY… 327
be helpful to show just how and why he fell short of his own intentions in
this inaugural work, conditioned as it was by his close involvement with the
academic philosophers with whom he was arguing.
Rorty wanted to expose the cogito—the mind as the subjective “mirror”
of an objective nature—as a cultural-historical formation, because he
wanted to undermine its claims to privileged knowledge in philosophy, a
much narrower aim than his continental counterparts entertained. He
rightly argued that “as soon as it is admitted that empirical considerations
(e.g. the discovery that there are spots on the moon, the discovery that the
Etats-General would not go home) incited but did not require ‘conceptual
change’ (e.g. a different concept of the heavens or of the state), the divi-
sion of labor between the philosopher and the historian no longer made
sense” (272). But he did not take up an extended study of that culture-
historical incitement. I am not saying Rorty should have written a differ-
ent book—but I do want to show how his historically oriented argument
against foundational explanation was allowed to escape his larger claim
that ideas are justified just insofar as they work. Rorty forgot, or had not
yet encountered, a teaching of Nietzsche that the poststructuralists learned
so well—if you just invert the binary instead of surpassing it, you actually
preserve it.
Rorty began by indicting Locke for confusing explanation and justifica-
tion in his account of mind, a confusion which led, in ways the book as a
whole describes, to philosophy’s grandiose claims for foundational episte-
mology, for absolute and objective “truth.” At the same time, Rorty was
arguing in general that context and outcome is what justifies beliefs and
that (short, perhaps, of syllogism) more or less justified (as opposed to
“true”) is all that knowledge can hope to be. But in ascribing to the view
that truth is a compliment we extend to beliefs that pay off in one way or
another, Rorty opened himself up to this question: in its context, wasn’t
the mirror of nature in fact justified as epistemology precisely because it was
“confused” with explanation in a particular way? How could anyone claim-
ing that the division of labor between historian and philosopher no longer
makes sense and that “cultural anthropology (in a large sense which
includes intellectual history) is all we need” (381), justify calling other
ways of construing the world “confused”—if it can be shown that they
“pay off”? How could Rorty maintain his postphilosophical commitment
to edification and the invention of vocabularies that work and condemn
the naturalism and psychologism in Locke’s philosophy? There can be no
doubt that it paid off, for centuries.
328 T. DE ZENGOTITA
If we try to make out what Rorty meant when he granted that empiri-
cists “were doubtless right in commending Galileo for preferring his eyes
to his Aristotle, but this epistemological judgment has no particular con-
nection with their theory of perception” (246), the word “particular”
jumps out. It carries the whole burden of his argument. He was trying to
leave room for the Galilean context as an incitement to a philosophical
account of perception and belief while closing off the possibility that such
a context might justify the philosophy in some sense other than the one to
which he himself subscribes. But why? It was, as we have just seen, justified
in that sense! But it was not justified in the sense to which his twentieth-
century interlocutors subscribe—that is, as the correspondence of
transparent propositions to objective reality—and Rorty was actually talk-
ing to them.11
The case is even clearer when the Locke’s “moral science of man” is cast
in terms we would recognize as moral today. The whole Lockean project
of progressive remedy, of curing natural history, depended on an analysis
of how the mind, and the rest of nature, worked. Consider the most fun-
damental case, in its Lockean origins. The “divine rights” of patriarchal
monarchs were explained away (like “goblins and sprites”) and self-
government by free and rational individuals was justified by a “science of
man” grounded on evidence of divine design in nature, an inbuilt right-
way-to-work. As a matter of anthropological cultural-historical fact
(Rorty’s “all we need”), modern humanity granted itself civil rights on
that basis. Modernity discovered, beneath the appearances of inherited
station (and later race and sex) the common sense and reason with which
each individual is endowed by Nature and the Maker, and so on—the
language runs clear from Descartes to Jefferson and Danton to civil rights
movements of the twentieth century. Is Rorty saying that our beliefs about
our rights are not justified by those explanations of our nature? He is, and
rightly so, if “justified” means something like “logically derived from.”
But he’s ignoring how the beliefs were, in fact, justified by those explana-
tions for the looser reason to which he himself subscribes: namely, in the
context of modernity’s social practices, this vocabulary paid off. Can Rorty
say, well, you can pretend to use, or mistakenly believe that you are using,
11
In his interview with Claire Parnet (Deleuze from A to Z: H is for the History of
Philosophy 2012), Deleuze was only echoing pragmatist principles when he prioritized “the
problem” philosophers of the past were facing in their context: “if one cannot identify the
problem, one cannot understand the concept and philosophy will remain abstract … to
engage in the history of philosophy is to restore these problems.”
THE ANGLOPHONE RECEPTION OF FRENCH THEORY: LITERARY… 329
explanations about how the mind works to justify moral and epistemologi-
cal beliefs but you really aren’t justifying them?
The only way Rorty might say such a thing is by dealing with Locke and
Descartes as contemporaries—and that is essentially what he did. He
would not, I think, have denied that Locke was justified in believing what
he did by virtue of explanations of human nature if those explanations are
taken as constituents in just another set of social practices. But Rorty, in this
case only, did not so take them. He took them at face value—as absolute
claims to knowledge that satisfy “the urge to see social practices of justifi-
cation as more than just such practices” (1979, 390). But that urge ought
not be ascribed to Locke but to Carnap and Moore. For Locke, it was
God’s practices that were “more”—not his own.
But when it comes to present-day politics, Rorty’s opposition to abso-
lute justification serves him well—and would do the same for all of us if we
could cauterize the thrills of righteous indignation that are coursing through
our body politic in all directions like Deleuzean schizo pulsions on digital
steroids. It may be true, as well as witty, to say that “the problem with
pragmatism is that it doesn’t work”—and, to my mind at least, Rorty’s
manifestly well-intentioned Achieving our Country (1998) is a case in
point. In that book, he tries to persuade his fellow citizens that they are
capable of political action without metaphysically secure foundations to
convince them of the rightness of their cause. He tries to persuade them
that, like certain elite intellectuals—the “liberal ironists” he celebrates in
Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989)—they can be politically commit-
ted without being transcendentally motivated, that they can admit to an
inherent fallibility in their perceptions and vocabularies and still march and
organize and vote. But what was most noticeably missing from Achieving
our Country, in spite of its heartfelt appeal, was the one thing that actually,
in fact, does motivate people in general to take such action: inspiration
(etymologically: “immediate influence of God or a god”).
That limitation is regrettable but not unbreachable. There are, in fact,
some people—usually highly educated people—who become liberal
ironists and can, like Rorty himself, find inspiration in words like these:
Berlin ended his essay by quoting Joseph Schumpeter, who said, “To realise
the relative validity of one’s convictions and yet stand for them unflinchingly
is what distinguishes a civilized man from a barbarian.” Berlin comments, “to
demand more than this is perhaps a deep and incurable metaphysical need;
but to allow it to determine one’s practice is a symptom of an equally deep,
and more dangerous, moral and political immaturity.” (Rorty 1989, 46)
330 T. DE ZENGOTITA
ous forms of identity politics in the American academy, all of which con-
verged on undermining conventional modern selves and inviting whoever
felt moved to become, through performance, something “other” to just go
ahead and do it.
Gender Trouble (1990) was a huge success in the academy and in the
culture more generally. One reason, so obvious that it can escape notice, is
that the book dealt with arcane poststructuralist notions of socially deter-
mined identity, yes—but it did so in relation to “sex,” perhaps the most
engaging of all topics, especially for young people. And besides—since the
rise of the women’s and gay rights movements in the late 1960s, who wasn’t
having trouble with gender? But the book also gave Butler an opportunity
to exercise her remarkable talent for writing in a register that managed to
synthesize the academic and the vernacular. She fluently deployed the latest
slang and commented knowingly on goings-on in what had been—and, for
some people, still were—“underground” venues, wreathed in the glamor of
taboo. You just knew she knew what she was talking about there. At the
same time, she imported a battery of notions from yet another glamorous
venue, from the haunts of the intellectual avant-garde in Paris—and you
just knew she knew what she was talking about there too. The result was
that young people, struggling to make sense of both French theory and
their own sex lives, were doubly rewarded. Gender Trouble probably
helped more people get at least some sense of how to talk postmodern than
all the little Oxford and Routledge introductory paperbacks combined.
One example: because she was never far removed (in Gender Trouble)
from concrete experiences of sexuality and gender performance, young
Americans of a certain class, engaged since grammar school and Sesame
Street with debunking stereotypes, were quick to catch on to what she
meant by the “heterosexual matrix.” They readily assimilated it to the
familiar idea that “society” imposes categories on you and that you are
entitled to object to that. And that’s not a bad reading, for starters; it
provides enough insight to sustain a term paper on Foucault’s discursive
practices and, with a little massaging, could take on his idea of power/
knowledge as well.13
Almost as important to the book’s popularity, I think, was the way
Butler lightened the burden of hopeless subjection in which the French
13
Alan Schrift rightly calls Gender Trouble “a profoundly Foucauldian enterprise” (2006,
54) and it is reasonable to credit it for a lot of Foucault’s staying power in the anglophone
academy, where “identity studies” of various kinds became a lasting legacy of French
theory.
332 T. DE ZENGOTITA
10.4.2 Butler’s Kristeva
Kristeva accepts the assumption that culture is equivalent to the symbolic,
but the symbolic is fully subsumed under the “Law of the Father…” the
only modes of non-psychotic activity are those which participate in the sym-
bolic. … Her strategic task is not to replace the symbolic with the semiotic
nor to establish the semiotic as a rival cultural possibility, but rather to vali-
date those experiences within the symbolic that permit a manifestation of
the borders which divide the symbolic from the semiotic. (Butler 1989a,
110; italics mine)
14
The ban on subject talk, it should be recalled, applies to a style of writing that treats
subjects as effects of language rather than as agents of actions, including thinking and speak-
ing. To those implementing the ban, treating subjects as agents seemed to imply that subjects
exist outside of the language they use as a tool for representing their experience; in other
words, “pre-discursive” subjects—Cartesian or even Aristotelian substances.
334 T. DE ZENGOTITA
We have already noted the significant role the idea of the pre-discursive
played in the theoretical work of the most difficult of the ultra-structuralists,
Deleuze and Derrida. And, yes, Derrida was given to denying the possibil-
ity of talking about the pre-discursive—the phrase itself says as much!
And, yes, the crimes committed by the metaphysics he was deconstructing
were typically carried out in language claiming to refer to the pre-discursive
(presence, etc.). But that reading, while valid up to a point, misses the
characteristic Derridean ambivalence about the metaphysical project
itself—the aim of the project was, for him, not the same as its execution in
specific terms and that aim was close to his heart, always. It misses, that is,
the importance of his “aconceptual concepts” and the “quasi-transcendental
ontology” they made possible (see above, Chap. 8.2). A deeper reading of
Derrida shows an underlying obsession with finding some access to what
Butler dismissed out of hand because it wasn’t “even a knowable experi-
ence.” The lead quote for the section on Derrida in this book foregrounds
that fact (“I am profoundly convinced, against Wittgenstein … that, what
we cannot speak about we must (not) pass over in silence” (see above,
Chap. 9.2). And of course Deleuze made no bones about it at all: every
important philosophical move he made, from the subjectless “transcen-
dental empiricism” of his Hume studies to becoming-other through sheer
sensation in radical art works, was motivated by his desire to escape lin-
guistic containers that (mis)represented the seething molecular as stable
molarity.
But that longing for an “outside” that haunted so many of the creators
of French theory did not seem to take hold of Butler, at least not during
the Gender Trouble period. For that reason, I believe, she misread the dis-
tinction between Kristeva’s semiotic and symbolic—she missed the unrep-
resentable way in which the “boundary” between them fused as much as
separated the respective processes. Pam Morris attributes Butler’s misread-
ing to this oversight as well:
Morris then reminds us that Kristeva had also been consulting with
Emile Benveniste on subject-transcending discourse theory, looking for a
synthesis with Mikhail Bakhtin’s dialogical account of texts. This was when
she was presenting her intertextuality “gadget” at Barthes’ seminar at
EPHE (see above, Chap. 7.3)—the whole function of the gadget being to
neutralize the subject as agent in the writing and reading process and, in
so doing, to collapse the distinction itself, to make reading and writing
aspects of each other. Yet another category defying merger. Morris flags
down a number of other leading notions in Kristeva’s work, all of which
reflect a consistent effort to blend distinctions into process—and finally,
after describing Kristeva’s key concept of a “threshold site,”15 Morris
concludes:
nor as is so often claimed, does [Kristeva] oppose the symbolic with a pre-
cultural archaism. For her, all speaking subjects and their discourse, the
semiotic disposition as well as the symbolic, are always already implicated in
history. … The child enters the world as the site of polymorphous instinctual
drives but these are always already implicated with the social; even in the
womb the child hears and responds to the mother’s voice. (32)
15
Based on Bakhtin’s account of “carnival,” where the “threshold site” is a “boundary site
bringing together food and defecation, gluttonous Gargantuan ingestion and obscene expul-
sion, birth, sex and death, pain and laughter.”
336 T. DE ZENGOTITA
These are not the “drives” of Freud—not even of Lacan’s Freud. As the
italicized language makes clear, these are Nietzschean forces as Deleuze
and Guattari deployed them in Anti-Oedipus (1972). The whole point
was to see “desire” as permeating the entire natural and social order, seam-
lessly implicated in the motions of weather and of machinery in factories
and cars on the street—as well as the embraces of maternal fluids and tis-
sues enveloping a spastic, babbling infant. That book, let it be recalled,
was a sensation among intellectuals in Paris and it is unthinkable that, in
1974, conceiving her semiotic and her chora, that Kristeva could have
escaped the influence of this most radical of all visions of “desire,” a vision
in which all stasis melted into process eventually and at some level.
If you pass over Kristeva’s persistent efforts to highlight the fusional
dimension that process brings to categories in motion, then it is possible
to read the distinction between the semiotic and the symbolic the way
Butler does. That fusional dimension is itself, admittedly, unintelligible—
that is, as it were, the whole point of becoming as opposed to being, the
very occasion of the crime against empirical reality that concepts, by their
nature, commit (See Kojeve and Nietzsche references throughout this
book). But for Butler, who has dismissed the pre-discursive because it isn’t
“even a knowable experience”, Kristeva’s reach inevitably falls outside her
ken and we are left with the two levels of language—interacting however
you like—but distinctly themselves throughout. Kristeva’s examples of
how, in poetry and baby talk and psychotic discourse, the semiotic can
“erupt into” or “disrupt” or otherwise make itself “manifest” at the level
of the symbolic—to Butler, such examples all look like interactions (per-
haps breaches or incursions) between two terms that remain what they
are. Hence, descriptions like this one, cited above: “the only modes of
non-psychotic activity are those which participate in the symbolic to some
extent … [and so] validate those experiences within the symbolic that
THE ANGLOPHONE RECEPTION OF FRENCH THEORY: LITERARY… 337
permit a manifestation of the borders which divide the symbolic from the
semiotic” (Italics mine). When, of course, the whole point for Kristeva is
that they don’t simply divide, they blend and fuse.
Imagine a poet engaged in the passionate repetitive chanting of a refrain
or a baby and mother engaged in reciprocal and simultaneous cooing of
the sweetness-recognizing syllable “Awwww ….” For Kristeva there’s a
blend, like Russian dressing; for Butler, there’s catsup mixed with mayon-
naise. I can see it both ways, so why not live and let live?
Politics.
Judith Butler’s problem with Kristeva’s pre-discursive semiotic had lit-
tle to do with the organization of the human psyche or the nature of lan-
guage. She was not that interested in purely intellectual issues. Here is
what she really didn’t like about Kristeva’s pre-discursive:
And the possibility of that cultural practice trumps all other consider-
ations—for Butler is, first and foremost, an artful polemicist serving a
noble cause and she has arrived to spread the good word. We can fix this
situation, if we just act (perform) in it:
on my reading, the repression of the feminine does not require that the
agency of repression and the object of repression be ontologically distinct.
… If subversion as possible, it will be a subversion from within the terms of
the law [i.e. the symbolic], through the possibilities that emerge when the
law turns against itself and spawns unexpected permutations of itself. The
culturally constructed body will then be liberated, not to its “natural” past
nor to its original pleasures, but to an open future of cultural possibilities.
(1989a, 117)
10.4.3 Butler at the Barricades
But in this book we are interested in actual truth—albeit with a small “t,”
the kind of truth we expect from friends when important matters are
before us. To conclude, then, with an attempt at a just placement of Judith
Butler in the theory firmament at this stage in her career: she was on the
conservative end of the spectrum, a Foucauldian materialist but not really
an ultra-structuralist, not really looking to think the impossible or other-
wise access or even privilege what lies beyond thought and language.
Conventional thought and language in the pre-postmodern era—that she
was out to transgress and disrupt at every turn. Those were boundaries she
was eager to violate but not, like Derrida or Deleuze, the very boundaries
of conceptuality per se, of language itself. At that point, Butler shows her-
self to be a more conventional—even American—philosopher, not a
French experimentalist looking for what is truly other to all of us as speak-
ing and thinking beings. She implied as much herself, in her 1999 preface
to Gender Trouble, which reflected almost ten years of engagement with a
host of critics and admirers since its original publication:
16
For example, “the body is … directly involved in a political field; power-relations have an
immediate hold on it; they invest it, mark it, train it, torture it, force it to carry out tasks, to
perform ceremonies, to emit signs” ([1975] 1995, 25). For the image of the body “emitting
signs,” Foucault is surely indebted to his friend Deleuze.
340 T. DE ZENGOTITA
lifelong Nietzschean elitists or—as with most of the thinkers we have con-
sulted here—a strange combination of both: the ban on subject talk made
it possible for many of these radicals to avoid looking too closely at their
own motives for abandoning their class destiny and aligning themselves
with workers, third-world peasants, and eventually with other exploited
and marginalized groups as well. For them, it would never do to speak of
anything so sentimental and ideal as “compassion” or “a sense of justice”
or “human rights,” those conventional sources of inspiration for reform,
smugly handing down their help to “those in need” from the center and
on high. But in the mid 1970s, the so-called new philosophers (Andre
Glucksmann, Bernard Henri-Levy, Christian Jambet, Guy Lardreau et al.),
reacting as disillusioned Maoists to Solzhenitsyn’s revelations in The Gulag
Archipelago (1973) and to the heroism of other dissenters in the
Communist world, fostered a turn to “ethics” and made concepts like
“justice” and “human rights” viable again (see especially Julian Bourg’s
From Revolution to Ethics; May 1968 and Contemporary French Thought
(2007)). It was that turn—happening, once again, with astonishing
speed—that principally (along with the centralized French educational
system) accounts for the abrupt demise in France of what the anglophone
academy would call “theory” and which some would practice diligently
for decades to come.
Foucault, with his uncanny ability to catch the next wave, was affiliated
with that turn by the early 1980s, as we have seen (it cemented his
estrangement from Deleuze, who liked to refer to the new philosophers
as “TV buffoons”). So it is worth reflecting a bit on Foucault’s earlier
preference for the word “intolerable” to explain why he spent precious
time and energy organizing on behalf of prisoners or the Iranian revolu-
tion or whatever it might be. Like Rorty’s “cruelty,” the word tries to
shift agency over to circumstances that are “intolerable” or “cruel” with-
out quite succeeding in masking the fact that someone, some human sub-
ject, is feeling and judging the situation and, in common sense (hence
forbidden) terms, being moved to action. In any case, and by way of
summarizing an obvious but, I think, decisive point—this straight-up
observation: one of the best ways to rescue the common sense view of
human motivation in ethics and politics is to invoke the example of so
many of these radical activists themselves. The straight white men among
them were, for the most part, bourgeois intellectuals who chose to deny
in theory or ideology motivations they manifestly served in practice. They
dedicated great chunks of their lives to causes that did not serve their
THE ANGLOPHONE RECEPTION OF FRENCH THEORY: LITERARY… 341
material interests—but instead served ideals and values that have been
motivating modernizing progressives since the eighteenth century.
Another case of intellectuals caught up in a “great silliness,” no doubt;
but, as in MacIntyre’s case (see above Chap. 3.2.2), with the possibility of
a new humanism on the horizon, there is much to be learned from it.
Since the first Romantics set out to vanquish modern subjectivity, it has
been like some vampire, reviving again and again no matter how many
stakes are driven through its heart. And it managed to do that for the obvi-
ous reason that the social-historical world has remained essentially modern
through all the intellectual changes and, with subjectivity understood as
being-in-the-world, its persistence was inevitable. Nietzsche thought he
had bested Cartesian metaphysics in its Kantian guise, but Heidegger
showed that he remained in thrall to a vision of individual centrality and
agency. Heidegger, in turn, believed he had dismantled subjectivity as sub-
stance once and for all—returned it to the world as the very meaning of
the world’s Being. But Derrida smoked out that self-same subject in
Heidegger, caught it gazing into the mirror of presence. And Derrida
himself? Like many in his cohort, he took out what looked to be a fail-safe
insurance policy, one that implicitly admitted the impossibility of success
for his project in his social-historical context. He smothered the subject/
object distinction in a wholesale destabilization of all the binary concepts
(ideal/material, culture/nature, internal/external) associated with
Western metaphysics while admitting at the same time that one couldn’t
actually function without those binaries for the foreseeable future, perni-
cious though they might be. Free at last?
References
Abrams, M.H. 1971. Natural Supernaturalism: Tradition and Revolution in
Romantic Literature. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Bourg, Julian. 2007. From Revolution to Ethics: May 1968 and Contemporary
French Thought. Montreal: McGill-Queens University Press.
Butler, Judith. 1987. Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in 20th-Century
France. New York: Columbia University Press.
———. 1989a. The Body Politics of Julia Kristeva. Hypatia 3 (3): 104–118.
———. 1989b. Foucault and the Paradox of Bodily Inscriptions. The Journal of
Philosophy 86 (11): 601–607.
———. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York:
Routledge.
342 T. DE ZENGOTITA
Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
———. 1989. Solidarity or Objectivity. In Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1998. Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century
America. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Salih, Sara. 2002. Judith Butler. London: Routledge.
Thompson, Edward Palmer. 1963. The Making of the English Working Class.
London: Victor Gollancz Ltd.
Williams, Raymond. (1958) 1983. Culture and Society: 1780–1950. New York:
Columbia University Press.
CHAPTER 11
Sartre here sums up the story of modernity as it has been told in this book
and, if only by implication, the argument that followed from it. The gist is
this: as modernity took hold of nature and history, the status of Maker fell
more and more to those who actually fashioned the settings that consti-
tuted people’s lives. As we became the self-conscious makers of our
being—of our skills, careers, moods, appearance, health, sexual perfor-
mance, “life-styles”—proprietorial entitlement followed in accordance
with modern “natural law.” But what now and what next?
Most strikingly, this: the convergence of digital and biotechnologies
means that the enterprise of self- and world-making is becoming more
literal. Virtual environments, avatars, chimeras, clones, and proliferating
prosthetic enhancements of all kinds promise liberation from all catego-
ries, including those we are born into. Some apparently qualified people
expect liberation from embodiment itself.1 And the fact that quadriplegics
with their brains wired into computers can control the movement of a cur-
sor with their thoughts makes that expectation rational in principle, at
least. What that fact says is that the code doesn’t care what the platform is
1
Ray Kurzweil and Larry Page (co-founder of Google) are only the most prominent fig-
ures seriously preparing for a time in the near future when it will be possible to “upload” (or
“download”?) a mind/brain onto a computer.
3
“I will suppose … that some malignant demon, who is at once exceedingly potent and
deceitful, has employed all his artifice to deceive me; I will suppose that the sky, the air, the
earth, colors, figures, sounds, and all external things, are nothing better than the illusions of
dreams. … I will consider myself as without hands, eyes, flesh, blood, or any of the senses,
and as falsely believing that I am possessed of these” (1975 (1641), 100).
BEFORE THE ANNUNCIATION CAME THE VIRTUAL 349
References
Butler, Judith. 1987. Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in 20th-Century
France. New York: Columbia University Press.
Descartes, Rene. 1968. The Discourse on Method (1637) and the Meditations
(1641). Harmondsworth: Penguin Classics.
4
Compare Fredric Jameson on “pastiche” and “surface” in The Cultural Logic of Late
Capitalism (1991).
BEFORE THE ANNUNCIATION CAME THE VIRTUAL 351
1
Besides speculative ideas about the “coming singularity” (Kurzweil 2005), more serious
academic accounts include Katherine Hayles’ How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in
Cybernetics, Literature and Informatics (1999); Francis Fukuyama’s The Posthuman Future
(2005); and Cary Wolfe’s What is Posthumanism? (2010).
2
Frantz Fanon in The Wretched of the Earth “All the elements of a solution to the great
problems of humanity have, at different times, existed in European thought. But Europeans
have not carried out in practice the mission which fell to them” ([1961] 2004, 237). He was
giving up on Europe in that book—but he recognized the essential problem nevertheless.
CONCLUSION: TOWARD A NEW HUMANISM 355
5
Husserl thought that Being and Time, in rejecting the transcendental ego and focusing
on average everydayness, had lapsed into mere anthropology (compare “psychologism” as
the modernist philosopher’s epithet). And creators of French theory dismissed all phenom-
enology—indeed, any discourse that privileged the subject and its object world as “anthro-
pology” (Kant, e.g., modern humanism in general). See Gutting (2013, 39–42). The shoe
fits, and I wear it comfortably.
358 T. DE ZENGOTITA
References
de Zengotita, Thomas. 2003. Common Ground: Finding Our Way Back to the
Enlightenment. Harper’s Magazine, January, 35–44.
———. 2006. Mediated. New York: Bloomsbury.
———. 2013. Ethics and the Limits of Evolutionary Psychology. The Hedgehog
Review 15 (1): 34–45.
Fanon, Frantz. (1961) 2004. The Wretched of the Earth. Trans. Richard Philcox.
New York: Grove Press.
Gutting, Gary. 2013. Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Kurzweil, Ray. 2005. The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology.
New York: Penguin.
References
Abrams, M.H. 1953. The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical
Tradition. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 1971. Natural Supernaturalism: Tradition and Revolution in Romantic
Literature. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
———. 1977. The Deconstructive Angel. Critical Inquiry 3 (3): 425–438.
Adorno, Theodor W. (1951) 2006. Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged
Life. Trans. E.F.N. Jephcott. New York: Verso.
———. (1964) 2003. The Jargon of Authenticity. London: Routledge.
———. 2004. Aesthetic Theory. Trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor. New York:
Continuum.
Allen, Graham. 2003. Roland Barthes. London: Routledge.
Althaus, Horst. 2000. Hegel: An Intellectual Biography. Trans. Michael Tarsh.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Aronowitz, Stanley. 2015. Against Orthodoxy: Social Theory and Its Discontents.
New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Arp, Jean. 1948. In On My Way: Poetry and Essays, 1912–1947, ed. Robert
Motherwell. New York: Wittenborn, Schultz.
Austin, J.L. (1962) 1971. How to Do Things with Words: The William James
Lectures Delivered at Harvard University in 1955. London: Oxford.
Banfield, Ann. 2003. Time Passes: Virginia Woolf, Post-impressionism, and
Cambridge Time. Poetics Today 24 (3): 471–516.
Baring, Edward. 2011. The Young Derrida and French Philosophy, 1945–1968.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Barsky, Robert F., and Eric Méchoulan. 2002. Introduction. SubStance: Special
Issue: The American Production of French Theory 31 (1): 3–8.
Barthes, Roland. (1953) 1984. Writing Degree Zero: & Elements of Semiology,
65–75. London: J. Cape.
———. (1957) 1972. Mythologies. London: J. Cape.
———. (1968) 1977. The Death of the Author. In Image-Music-Text. Trans.
Stephen Heath. Glasgow: Fontana/Collins.
———. (1970) 1982. Empire of Signs. New York: Hill and Wang.
———. (1971) 1986. Mythology Today. In The Rustle of Language, 65–68. Trans.
Richard Howard. New York: Hill and Wang.
———. 1975a. The Pleasure of the Text. Trans. Richard Miller. New York: Hill and
Wang.
———. (1975b) 1977. Roland Barthes. Trans. Richard Howard. New York:
Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
———. 1987. Criticism and Truth. London: Athlone Press.
Barzun, Jacques. 1964. Science: The Glorious Entertainment. New York: Harper &
Row.
Bataille, Georges. (1962) 1986. Eroticism: Death & Sensuality. Trans. Mary
Dalwood. San Francisco: City Lights.
Baudelaire, Charles. (1863) 1964. The Painter of Modern Life. In The Painter of
Modern Life and Other Essays. Trans. and ed. Jonathan Mayne. London:
Phaidon.
Baudrillard, Jean. (1977) 2007. Forget Foucault. Trans. Nicole Dufresne.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
———. 1993. Symbolic Exchange and Death. Trans. Iain Hamilton Grant. London:
Sage Publications.
Beaulieu, Alain. 2011. The Status of Animality in Deleuze’s Thought. Journal for
Critical Animal Studies IX (1/2): 69–88.
Beckett, Samuel. 2009. In The Cambridge Edition of the Letters of Samuel Beckett:
1929–1940, ed. Martha Fehsenfeld, Lois More Overbeck, George Craig, and
Daniel Gunn. London: Cambridge University Press.
Bell, Jeffrey, and Claire Colebrook, eds. 2009. Deleuze and History. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
Bernstein, J.M. 2006. Against Voluptuous Bodies: Late Modernism and the Meaning
of Painting. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Boer, Roland. 2007. Althusser’s Catholic Marxism. Rethinking Marxism 19 (4):
469–486.
Bogue, Ronald. 2007. Deleuze’s Way: Essays in Transverse Ethics and Aesthetics.
Aldershot: Ashgate.
Borch-Jacobsen, Mikkel. 1991. Lacan: The Absolute Master. Trans. Douglas Brick.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
REFERENCES
361
Descombes, Vincent. (1979) 1980. Modern French Philosophy. Trans. L. Scott Fox
and J.M. Harding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dosse, Francois. 1997. The History of Structuralism: Volume 2: The Sign Sets, 1967–
Present. Trans. Deborah Glassman. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
———. (2007) 2010. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari: Intersecting Lives.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Dreyfus, Hubert, and Paul Rabinow. 1983. Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism
and Hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Duchamp, Marcel. 1975. The Creative Act. In The Essential Writings of Marcel
Duchamp. London: Thames and Hudson.
Dunn, John. 1969. The Political Thought of John Locke: An Historical Account of
the Argument of the “Two Treatises of Government”. London: Cambridge
University Press.
Durkheim, Emile. (1895a) 1938. The Rules of Sociological Method. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
———. (1895b) 1982. The Rules of Sociological Method. Trans. W. D. Halls.
New York: The Free Press.
Eagleton, Terence. 1983. Literary Theory: An Introduction. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Elias, Norbert. 1978. The Civilizing Process: The History of Manners. Trans.
Edmund Jephcott. New York: Urizen Books.
Eliot, T.S. 1920. Tradition and the Individual Talent. In The Sacred Wood, 47–59.
London: Methuen.
Eribon, Didier. 1992. Michel Foucault. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Fanon, Frantz. (1961) 2004. The Wretched of the Earth. Trans. Richard Philcox.
New York: Grove Press.
Ferretter, Luke. 2006. Louis Althusser. New York: Routledge.
Ferry, Luc, and Alain Renault. 1990. French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on
Antihumanism. Trans. Mary H. S. Cattani. Amherst: University of
Massachusetts Press.
Ffrench, Patrick, and Roland-Francois Lack, eds. 1998. The Tel Quel Reader.
London: Routledge.
Fish, Stanley. 2011. The Old Order Changeth. The New York Times, December 26.
Flaubert, Gustave. 1982. The Letters of Gustave Flaubert: 1857–1880. Trans.
Francis Steegmuller. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University
Press.
Foucault, Michel. (1961) 1965. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in
the Age of Reason. Trans. Richard Howard. New York: Random House.
REFERENCES
365
———. (1963) 1986. Death and the Labyrinth: The World of Raymond Roussel.
Trans. Charles Ruas. Garden City: Doubleday.
———. (1966) 1994. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences.
New York: Vintage.
———. 1970. Theatrum Philosophicum. Critique 282: 885–908.
———. 1971. The Discourse on Language. In The Archaeology of Knowledge.
New York: Pantheon.
———. (1975) 1995. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York:
Vintage.
———. (1976) 1978. The History of Sexuality: Volume 1, The Will to Knowledge.
Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Vintage Books.
———. 1977. A Preface to Transgression. In Language, Counter-Memory,
Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews. Trans. Donald F. Buchard and Sherry
Simon. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
———. 1980. Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. In Language, Counter-Memory,
Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews. Trans. Donald F. Buchard, and Sherry
Simon, 139–164. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
———. 1981. Friendship as a Way of Life. By R. de Ceccaty, J. Danet, and J. Le
Bitoux. Gai Pied (April 1981). Trans. John Johnston. https://caringlabor.
wordpress.com/2010/11/18/michel-foucault-friendship-as-a-way-of-life/
———. 1984a. What Is Enlightenment? In The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul
Rabinow, 32–50. New York: Pantheon Books.
———. (1984b) 1985. The History of Sexuality: Volume 2, The Use of Pleasure.
Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Vintage Books.
———. (1984c) 1986. The History of Sexuality: Volume 3, The Care of the Self.
Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Vintage Books.
———. 1987. The Thought from Outside. In Foucault/Blanchot. Cambridge:
MIT Press.
———. 1988. Critical Theory/Intellectual History. In Politics, Philosophy, and
Culture: Interviews and Other Writings, 1977–1984, ed. Lawrence Kritzman,
17–46. New York: Routledge.
Foucault, Michel, and Sylvere Lotringer. 1996. Foucault Live: Interviews,
1961–1984. New York: Semiotext(e).
Francis, Mark. 2007. Herbert Spencer and the Invention of Modern Life. Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.
Frank, Thomas. 1997. The Conquest of Cool: Business Culture, Counterculture, and
the Rise of Hip Consumerism. Chicago: University of Chicago.
Frank, Claudine. 2003. Introduction. In The Edge of Surrealism: A Roger Caillois
Reader. Trans. Claudine Frank and Camille Naish. Durham: Duke University
Press.
Frank Lloyd Wright. Directed by Ken Burns. [1997] 2014. Public Broadcasting
System (PBS.)
366 REFERENCES
Freud, Sigmund. (1899) 2010. The Interpretation of Dreams. New York: Basic
Books.
———. (1913) 1998. Totem and Taboo: Resemblances Between the Mental Lives of
Savages and Neurotics. New York: Dover Thrift Editions.
———. (1930) 1961. Civilization and Its Discontents. Trans. James Strachey.
New York: W.W. Norton.
———. (1939) 1967. Moses and Monotheism. New York: Vintage Books.
Galilei, Galileo. (1623a) 1957. Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo: Including the
Starry Messenger. Trans. Stillman Drake. Garden City: Doubleday Anchor
Books.
———. (1623b) 1970. Two Kinds of Properties. In Philosophy of Science: Readings
Selected, ed. and Introduced by Arthur Danto and Sidney Morganbesser.
New York: Meridian Books.
Garver, Newton, and Seung-Chong Lee. 1994. Derrida & Wittgenstein.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Gay, Peter. 1969. The Enlightenment, an Interpretation: The Science of Freedom.
New York: Knopf.
Gillispie, Charles Coulston. 1960. The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History
of Scientific Ideas. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Giroux, Henry A. 1991. “Towards a Postmodern Pedagogy,” Section of the
Introduction. In Postmodernism. Feminism, and Cultural Politics. Albany: State
University of New York Press.
Gobar, Ash. 1970. The Phenomenology of William James. Proceedings of the
American Philosophical Society 114 (4): 294–309.
Good, James A. 2006. A Search for Unity in Diversity: The “Permanent Hegelian
Deposit” in the Philosophy of John Dewey. Lanham: Lexington Books.
Gordon, Peter Eli. 2007. Hammer Without a Master: French Phenomenology
and the Origins of Deconstruction (Or, How Derrida Read Heidegger). In
Histories of Postmodernism, ed. Mark Bevir, Jill Hargis, and Sara Rushing,
103–130. New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.
Graff, Gerald. (1979) 1986. Literature Against Itself: Literary Ideas in Modern
Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Green, F. 1931. 18th Century France, Six Essays. New York: D. Appleton.
Greif, Mark. 2015. The Age of the Crisis of Man: Thought and Fiction in America,
1933–1973. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Grosz, Elizabeth. 2005. Bergson, Deleuze, and the Becoming of Unbecoming.
Parallax 11 (2): 4–13.
Guattari, Félix. 2009. In Flux. In Chaosophy: Texts and Interviews. Los Angeles:
Semiotext(e).
Gutting, Gary. 2013. Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
REFERENCES
367
———. 2002. Intimate Revolt: And, the Future of Revolt. Trans. Janine Herman.
New York: Columbia University Press.
———. 2004. The Subject in Process. In Antonin Artaud: A Critical Reader, ed.
Edward Scheer, 116–124. London: Routledge.
Kritzman, Lawrence D., ed. 2006. The Columbia History of Twentieth-Century
French Thought. New York: Columbia University Press.
Kuehn, Manfred. 2001. Kant: A Biography. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Kurzweil, Ray. 2005. The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology.
New York: Penguin.
Lacan, Jacques. 1977. Écrits: A Selection. Trans. Alan Sheridan. New York:
W.W. Norton & Company.
Landow, George P. 1991. Hypertext: The Convergence of Contemporary Critical
Theory and Technology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Lasch, Christopher. (1979) 1991. The Culture of Narcissism: American Life in an
Age of Diminishing Expectations. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.
Latour, Bruno. 2004. Why Has Critique Run Out of Steam? From Matters of Fact
to Matters of Concern. Critical Inquiry 30 (2): 225–248.
Lawlor, Leonard. 1998. The End of Phenomenology: Expressionism in Deleuze
and Merleau-Ponty. Continental Philosophy Review 31 (1): 15–34.
———. 2012. Phenomenology, and Metaphysics, and Chaos: On the Fragility of
the Event in Deleuze. In The Cambridge Companion to Deleuze, ed. Daniel
W. Smith and Henry Somers-Hall, 103–125. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Le Corbusier. (1923) 1986. Towards a New Architecture. Trans. Frederick Etchells.
New York: Dover Publications.
Lehmann, William C. 1971. Henry Home, Lord Kames, and the Scottish
Enlightenment: A Study in National Character and in the History of Ideas. The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Leston, Robert. 2015. Deleuze, Haraway, and the Radical Democracy of Desire.
Configurations 23 (3): 355–376.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. (1949) 1969. The Elementary Structures of Kinship. Trans.
James Harle Bell and John Richard von Sturmer. Boston: Beacon Press.
———. (1955) 1992. Tristes Tropique. New York: Penguin Group.
———. 1963. Totemism. Trans. Rodney Needham. Boston: Beacon Press.
———. (1964) 1969. The Raw and the Cooked. In Introduction to the Science of
Mythology. New York: Harper and Row.
———. 1966. The Science of the Concrete. In The Savage Mind. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
370 REFERENCES
Lilla, Mark. 2015. The Strangely Conservative French. Review of How the French
Think: An Affectionate Portrait of an Intellectual People by Sudhir Hazareesingh.
New York Review of Books 62, 16.
Locke, John. (1689a) 1986. The Second Treatise on Civil Government. Buffalo:
Prometheus Books.
———. (1689b) 1996. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Abridged
and ed. Kenneth P. Winkler. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
Longenbach, James. 1988. Stone Cottage: Pound, Yeats, and Modernism. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Lotringer, Sylvere. 2001. Doing Theory. In French Theory in America, ed. Sylvère
Lotringer and Sande Cohen, 125–162. New York: Routledge.
Lowith, Karl. (1941) 1991. From Hegel to Nietzsche: The Revolution in Nineteenth
Century Thought. Trans. David E. Green. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Lukács, Georg. 1938. The Young Hegel: Part IV: The Breach with Schelling and the
Phenomenology of Mind (Jena 1803–1807). https://www.marxists.org/
archive/lukacs/works/youngheg/ch42.htm
———. 1971. The Theory of the Novel: A Historico-Philosophical Essay on the Forms
of Epic Literature. London: Merlin Press.
Lyotard, Jean-Francois. (1974) 1993. Libidinal Economy. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
———. (1979) 1984. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Trans.
Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Macdonald, Iain, and Krzysztof Ziarek, eds. 2008. Adorno and Heidegger:
Philosophical Questions. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Macey, David. 1995. The Lives of Michel Foucault. New York: Vintage.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1984. After Virtue. Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press.
Mackay, Robin, ed. 2007. Collapse: Philosophical Research and Developments,
Volume III. Falmouth: Urbanomic.
Macpherson, Crawford Brough. 1962. The Political Theory of Possessive
Individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Maher, Chauncey. 2012. The Pittsburgh School of Philosophy: Sellars, McDowell,
Brandom. New York: Routledge.
Malthus, Thomas. 1798. An Essay on the Principle of Population, as It Affects the
Future Improvement of Society; with Remarks on the Speculations of Mr. Godwin,
M. Condorcet, and Other Writers. London.
Manuel, Frank. 1962. The Prophets of Paris. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Marinetti, Filippo Tommaso. (1909) 1996. The Futurist Manifesto. In From
Modernism to Postmodernism: An Anthology, ed. Lawrence E. Cahoone.
Cambridge: Blackwell.
REFERENCES
371
Schlick, Moritz. 1968. The Future of Philosophy. In The Linguistic Turn: Recent
Essays in Philosophical Method, ed. Richard Rorty. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Schmidt, James, ed. (1784) 1966. An Answer to the Question: What Is
Enlightenment? In What Is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-Century Answers and
Twentieth-Century Questions, 58–64. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Schoenberg, Arnold. 1952. My Evolution. The Musical Quarterly 38 (4): 517–527.
Schrift, Alan. 1995. Nietzsche’s French Legacy: A Genealogy of Poststructuralism.
New York: Routledge.
———. 2006. Twentieth-Century French Philosophy: Key Themes and Thinkers.
Malden: Blackwell.
Schulman, Michael. 2013. LGBTQIA. New York Times, January 10, E.1.
Sean, Kelly. 2004. Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty. In The Cambridge Companion
to Merleau-Ponty, ed. Taylor Carmen and Mark B.N. Hansen, 74–110.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Searle, John R. 1969. Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. London:
Cambridge University Press.
———. 1977. Reiterating the Differences: A Reply to Derrida. Glyph 1 (1977):
198–208.
———. 1983. The World Turned Upside Down. New York Review of Books 30
(1983): 74–79.
———. 2000. “Reality Principles.” By Edward Feser and Steven Postrel. Reason
31 (9): 42.
Sellars, Wilfrid. (1956) 1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Sennett, Richard. 1974. The Fall of Public Man. London: Faber and Faber.
Shelley, Mary. 1818. Frankenstein, or, the Modern Prometheus. London: Lackington,
Hughes, Harding, Mavor, & Jones.
Silverman, Hugh J., ed. 1997. Philosophy and Non-philosophy Since Merleau-Ponty.
Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Sjoholm, Cecilia. 2005. Kristeva and the Political. London: Routledge.
Smart, Barry. 1994. Michel Foucault: Critical Assessments. London: Routledge.
Smith, Daniel W. 2001. The Doctrine of Univocity: Deleuze’s Ontology of
Immanence. Filozofski Vestnik 22 (1): 163–179 https://philpapers.org/rec/
SMITDO-10.
———. 2005. The Concept of the Simulacrum: Deleuze and the Overturning of
Platonism. Continental Philosophy Review 38 (1–2): 89–123.
Smith, Daniel W., and Henry Somers-Hall, eds. 2012. The Cambridge Companion
to Deleuze. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sokal, Alan D. 1996. Transgressing the Boundaries: Toward a Transformative
Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity. Social Text 46/47: 217–252.
REFERENCES
375
Sokal, Alan D., and Jean Bricmont. 1998. Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern
Intellectuals’ Abuse of Science. New York: Picador, St. Martin’s Press.
Sollers, Philippe. 1983. Writing and the Experience of Limits, ed. David Hayman,
and Trans. Philip Barnard with David Hayman. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Spencer, Herbert. (1857) 1881. Progress: Its Law and Cause, with Other
Disquisitions, 233–34, 236, 238, 243. New York: J. Fitzgerald. http://media.
bloomsbury.com/rep/files/primary-source-131-herbert-spencer-progress-its-
law-and-cause.pdf
———. 1896. Study of Sociology. New York: D. Appleton and Company.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. 1990. The Post-colonial Critic: Interviews, Strategies,
Dialogues. New York: Routledge.
———. 2010. Can the Subaltern Speak? In Can the Subaltern Speak?: Reflections
on the History of an Idea, ed. Rosalind C. Morris, 21–80. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Stanford University Metaphysics Research Laboratory. 2004. Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University Metaphysics Research Lab.
Stanislavski, Constantin. 1924. My Life in Art. Trans. J.J. Robbins. Boston: Little,
Brown & Co.
Starr, Peter. 1995. The Logics of Failed Revolt: French Theory After May 68’.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Staten, Henry. 1986. Wittgenstein and Derrida. Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press.
Steiner, George. 1975. After Babel: Aspects of Language and Translation.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Strauss, David Friedrich. 1846. Life of Jesus, Critically Examined. London:
Chapman Bros.
Surya, Michael. 2002. Georges Bataille: An Intellectual Biography. London: Verso.
Taine, Hippolyte Adolphe. (1867) 1931. The Ancient Régime. New York: Smith.
Taylor, Charles. 1979. Hegel and Modern Society. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
“The Intellectuals and Power: A Discussion Between Michel Foucault and Gilles
Deleuze.” 1973. Telos 16 (Summer): 103–109.
“Theory and Theorists: Watch Noam Chomsky Attack Foucault’s ‘Regimes of
Truth’ in 2011 Q&A.” 2013. Critical Theory. August 19. http://www.critical-
theory.com/noam-chomsky-argues-foucaults-ghost/
Thompson, Edward Palmer. 1963. The Making of the English Working Class.
London: Victor Gollancz Ltd.
Thompson, Michael. 2015. Radical Intellectuals and the Subversion of Progressive
Politics: The Betrayal of Politics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Turkle, Sherry. 1981. Psychoanalytic Politics: Freud’s French Revolution. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
376 REFERENCES
von Hofmannsthal, Hugo. (1902) 2005. The Lord Chandos Letter. In The Lord
Chandos Letter: And Other Writings. Trans. Joel Rotenberg. New York:
New York Review Books/Classics.
Weber, Max. (1905) 2014. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.
Kettering: Angelico Press.
———. (1918) 1946. Science as a Vocation. In From Max Weber: Essays in
Sociology, Trans. and ed. H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Weber, Marianne. (1926) 2017. Ancestors. In Max Weber: A Biography, Trans. and
ed. Harry Zohn, 1–30. New York: Routledge.
Wernick, Andrew. 2001. Auguste Comte and the Religion of Humanity: The Post-
theistic Program of French Social Theory. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Whitney, Lois. 1965. Primitivism and the Idea of Progress in English Popular
Literature of the Eighteenth Century. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.
Willey, Basil. 1950. The 18th Century Background: Studies on the Idea of Nature in
the Thought of the Period. New York: Columbia University Press.
———. 1953. The Seventeenth Century Background Studies in the Thought of the
Age in Relation to Poetry and Religion. Garden City: Doubleday.
Williams, Raymond. (1958) 1983. Culture and Society: 1780–1950. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Williams, James. 2012. Difference and Repetition. In The Cambridge Companion
to Deleuze, ed. Daniel W. Smith and Henry Somers-Hall, 33–54. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Wimsatt, William K., Jr., and Monroe Curtis Beardsley. 1946. The Intentional
Fallacy. The Sewanee Review 54 (3): 468–488.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. (1921) 1961. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans.
D.F. Pears and B.F. McGuinness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
———. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Wolters, Eugene. 2013. Theory and Theorists: Foucault on Obscurantism: ‘They
Made Me Do It!’. Critical Theory, July 11. http://www.critical-theory.com/
foucault-obscurantism-they-it/
Woolf, Virginia. (1925) 1984. In The Common Reader, ed. Andrew McNeillie. San
Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, A Harvest Book.
———. (1927) 1989. To the Lighthouse. New York: Harvest Books/Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich.
Zangouei, Javad. 2012. Joyce the Deconstructionist: Finnegans Wake in Context.
K@ta 14 (1): 31–36.
Zizek, Slavoj. 2012. Organs Without Bodies: On Deleuze and Consequences.
New York: Routledge.
Author Index1
1
Note: Page numbers followed by ‘n’ refer to notes.
Hegel, Georg W. F., 5n4, 20, 32, Johnson, Samuel, 28n9, 30, 31
34–50, 49n27, 57, 75, 97, 98, Joyce, James, 61, 63, 66, 141, 143,
102, 120, 122, 137–139, 139n4, 205n16, 233, 233n46, 237
169, 183, 217, 220, 233, 241, Judt, Tony, 187
245, 247, 250, 273, 325, 332,
333, 347n2, 355
Heidegger, Martin, 20, 93, 94, 96–98, K
122, 122n4, 124, 130, 137, 139, Kandinsky, Wassily, 62, 72, 73, 161,
152, 152n3, 156, 174, 208, 198
213n27, 228, 236n48, 241, Kant, Immanuel, 30n10, 34–36, 49,
241n53, 244n54, 248n55, 81, 121, 122n4, 220, 243,
252n60, 262n69, 324, 326, 341 272n77, 279, 282n83, 296, 326,
Hobsbawm, Erik J., 27 355, 357n5
Horkheimer, Max, 20, 34, 92, 92n1, Karl, Frederick Robert, 57
129, 130 Kauppi, Niilo, 124n7, 156, 164, 165,
Houdebine, Jean-Louis, 175, 207 170, 182, 183, 271
Houghton, Walter E., 40n16 Kelly, Sean, 134n6, 293n92
Howe, Irving, 7 Keynes, Maynard, 82
Hughes, Joe, 241, 246, 249, Klossowski, Pierre, 240, 286n85
253, 264n72 Kojeve, Alexandre, 97, 137–139,
Hume, David, 28n9, 34, 104, 196, 139n2, 143, 151, 183, 193, 295,
242–245, 254, 279, 334, 332, 336
348, 349 Kristeva, Julia, 87n13, 138, 140–142,
Husserl, Edmund, 20, 35, 43n21, 77, 153, 158, 159–160n10, 161,
91–93, 92n1, 95–97, 96n3, 119, 162, 165–177, 183, 184, 187n6,
130, 132n5, 138, 168n16, 205, 194, 199, 229n42, 272, 294,
208, 210–213, 224, 229, 301, 332–338
229n43, 234, 241, 248n55, Kritzman, Lawrence D, 169
323, 357n5 Kuehn, Manfred, 35
Hyppolite, Jean, 241 Kurzweil, Ray, 19, 345n1, 353n1
I L
Irigaray, Luce, 174 Lacan, Jacques, 117, 124, 138, 139,
142, 147–155, 167, 168, 173,
181, 192, 270, 271, 292–294,
J 314, 332–334, 336
Jameson, Fredric, 155, 239n52, 317, Landow, George P., 172
346, 350n4 Lasch, Christopher, 317
James, William, 209n23, 323, 325 Latour, Bruno, 20, 278n82
Jarry, Alfred, 69n8, 141, 314, 315 Lawlor, Leonard, 97n4, 246,
Jefferson, Thomas, 8, 34–35, 58, 328 264n72, 265
AUTHOR INDEX
381
Le Corbusier, 64, 70, 72 Marx, Karl, 6n5, 19, 21, 25, 37,
Lehmann, William C., 28 43n20, 99, 113, 115–125, 132,
Leston, Robert, 261 138, 142, 148–151, 149n2, 155,
Levinas, Emmanuel, 18, 226n40 199, 204, 205, 241, 250, 274,
Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 99, 101, 275, 295, 295n93, 320
106–112, 117, 138, 140, 157, Marx-Scouras, Danielle, 99, 149,
169, 185, 192, 212, 293, 156n7, 157–160, 164, 167,
294, 319 175, 186n5
Lilla, Mark, 161, 350 Massumi, Brian, 246, 256, 263n71,
Literature (literary), 141 264n72
Locke, John, 11, 12n1, 13, 21–25, 33, Mathy, Jean-Philippe, 98n6, 124n7
36, 49, 57, 58, 326–329, 326n9, Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 93, 134n6,
346, 347 138, 151, 174
Longenbach, James, 63n5 Merquior, José Guilherme, 99n9
Lotringer, Sylvere, 314 Micale, Mark, 86n12
Lowenthal, Leo, 127, 128 Miller, Henry, 270
Lowith, Karl, 42, 42n18, 44, 44n23 Miller, James, 283, 285, 286, 288,
Lukács, Georg, 129, 317 292n90
Lyotard, Jean-François, 34, 139, Miller, J. Hillis, 317–319, 323
142n6, 181, 275, 276n80, 295 Moi, Toril, 173
Montefiore, Alan, 147
Moore, G. E., 73–88, 92, 261,
M 279, 329
McAfee, Noelle, 169 Morris, Pam, 334, 335
Macdonald, Iain, 139n4 Mossner, Ernest Campbell, 28n9
Macey, David, 131n3, 285, 292 Muller-Doohm, Stefan, 127, 128n1,
Machery, Pierre, 148, 152 129, 134, 135
MacIntyre, Alasdair, 23, 82, 83,
130n2, 341
Macpherson, Crawford Brough, 12n1 N
Maher, Chauncey, 209n24 Newton, Isaac, 12, 21, 29, 36, 44, 97
Mallarmé, Stéphane, 71, 141, 143, Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 19,
158, 205n16 34–36, 40, 57, 58, 62, 63, 64n6,
Malthus, Thomas, 37, 38 98n8, 113, 115–125, 130, 132,
Mann, Thomas, 120, 298 137, 138, 141–144, 144n7, 148,
Manuel, Frank, 37n12 150, 155, 156, 166, 196, 217,
Mao Tse-tung (Maoism), 159, 160, 220, 226n40, 234, 237, 240,
160n10, 163 242–245, 250, 252, 253n62, 255,
Marcuse, Herbert, 315 256, 258, 259, 262, 282, 283,
Marinetti, Filippo Tommaso, 65, 66, 285, 286, 286n85, 290, 296,
69–71, 69n8 298, 303, 325, 327, 336, 341
Maritain, Jacques, 17n3 Nisbet, Robert, 37n12
382 AUTHOR INDEX
1
Note: Page numbers followed by ‘n’ refer to notes.
A-subjective, 244, 254 Chance, 15, 57, 202, 244, 245, 254,
Auto-affection, 211 259, 262, 323
Avant-garde, 1, 3, 28, 65, 66, 69, China, 28, 115, 123, 159, 160,
110, 141, 149, 154, 161, 162, 160n10, 174–176, 196, 357
164, 175, 176, 186, 187, 203, Chora, 169, 173, 333, 336
286, 291, 314, 331 Christianity, 41, 42, 44n23, 49,
Average everydayness, 63, 96, 241, 296
152n3, 357n5 Class, 27–29, 35, 82, 115, 116, 158,
196, 225, 240, 284, 321, 331, 340
Classical, 15, 23, 31, 76, 96, 116,
B 133, 148, 152n3, 157, 183, 184,
Bayreuth, 120, 121 230n45, 248–250, 299, 300,
Becoming, 44, 84, 96, 143, 150, 159, 303, 303n98
176n23, 177, 188n7, 189, Clone, 345
196n10, 201, 225, 228, 230, Cluny, 171
238, 244, 245, 247, 251, 260n68, Code, 76, 83, 96, 99, 104–107, 111,
261–263, 265, 270, 274, 276, 140, 149, 157, 168, 169, 176,
278, 281, 303, 325, 336, 345 187, 189n8, 190, 191, 195,
Being and Time, 93, 230n44, 357n5 203, 208, 214, 228, 229, 259,
Being-in-the-World, 5, 58, 59n1, 345, 346
93–95, 97, 104, 341 Cogito, 18, 23, 35, 58, 60, 97, 98,
Bill of Rights, 24 130, 140, 165, 211–213,
Binary/binaries, 111n9, 192, 225, 213n27, 248n55, 273, 299, 327,
230, 269, 327, 334, 341 347–349
Bloomsbury, 66, 82 College de France, 181, 182, 292,
Bourgeois, 5, 6, 24, 27, 35, 58, 82, 293, 347n2
116, 121, 125, 128, 130, 131, The College of Sociology, 290
134, 141, 148–150, 155, 156n8, Commodity fetishism, 130, 135n7
163, 176, 185, 196, 200, 202, Communism/communist/communist
221, 240, 290, 296, 297, 339, party, 25, 47, 99, 116, 125, 129,
340, 347 130, 140, 150, 152, 154, 159,
Bugger, 123n6, 242, 256, 266, 279 160, 160n11, 163, 171, 175,
273, 280, 298, 324, 340
Convention (conventional), 19, 32,
C 64–66, 77, 99, 129, 130, 137,
Canon, 1, 2, 209, 324, 325, 353 149, 150, 152, 156n8, 161, 166,
Capital, 24, 115, 164, 171, 182, 167, 168n17, 182, 183, 186,
186, 274 194, 195, 202, 204, 219n32,
Catholic, 21, 27, 28, 45, 148, 150, 222, 223, 225, 238, 250, 255,
151, 163n13, 203 268, 273, 287, 291, 295n93,
Centre for Contemporary Cultural 298n95, 303, 304, 318, 323,
Studies, 320 331, 338, 340, 349, 355
SUBJECT INDEX
387
Parole, 60, 106, 140, 187, 191, 206, Presence, 13, 49, 59, 67, 95, 104,
208, 210, 213, 234, 264n72, 142, 153, 168, 176n23, 205,
279, 291, 319 208–214, 227, 305, 334, 341
Pataphysics, 69n8, 314 Progress, 11, 21–27, 30, 35, 37,
Phenomenology, 1–8, 32, 60, 91–99, 37n12, 47, 58, 59, 61, 78, 87,
111n9, 119, 130, 134n6, 135, 122, 127, 221, 354
138, 140, 142, 168n16, 172, Propositions, 75, 102, 103, 209n24,
174, 205, 206, 208–212, 221, 217, 227, 248, 266–268, 328, 349
228, 233, 241, 241n53, 245, Protestant, 12, 23, 28, 42n18, 326
248n55, 252–282, 292, 300, Psychology, 4, 60, 64, 74, 76–78, 80,
325, 349, 357n5 85, 86, 92, 117, 118, 118n1,
Philosophical Investigations, 104, 151, 153, 197, 198, 218n31,
208n20, 213n27, 230n44 242, 316, 349
Phonologocentrism, 211–212 Pulsion, 98, 167, 204, 270, 273, 329
Physics, 3, 19, 20n7, 45, 107, 118,
121, 217, 249
Political correctness, 277n81, Q
321n4, 356 Quantum theory, 255
Politics, 1–3, 5, 6, 13, 21, 24, 25, 27, Queer theory, 1, 124, 305, 306, 330
31, 35, 38, 44n23, 88, 99, 116,
124, 128, 135, 142, 147, 149,
154, 156, 157, 159–164, R
166, 173–177, 196, 199, 202, Race, 98, 182, 284, 321, 328, 330
214, 215, 224, 236, 275, Recuperation, 154, 272
277n81, 280–282, 290, 291, Repetition, 133, 215, 218, 219, 230,
295n93, 302, 303, 305, 306, 234, 247, 253, 332
313–341, 355–357 Representation (by language), 42, 58,
Positivism (positivist), 44n23, 45–47, 77, 118, 158, 199, 207, 233,
48n26, 87n13, 98, 102, 111, 247, 250, 251, 251n58, 264,
131, 141, 174, 204, 220, 264, 267, 268, 280, 282n83, 314,
277, 301, 337 320, 349, 350, 356, 357
Postcolonial studies, 305, 330 Resemblance, 106, 242, 243, 247,
Posthumanism (Posthuman), 277, 353 251, 268, 349
Post-structuralism, 5, 68, 97, 105, Rhizome, 246, 248, 264
106, 150, 153, 157, 171, 193, Romanticism, 32, 33n11, 34, 40,
197, 208, 210, 234, 238n50, 120, 220
298, 320
Power/knowledge, 124, 202, 294,
295, 304, 305, 331, 337 S
Pragmatism, 32, 313–341 Schizophrenia (schizoid),
Pre-discursive, 300, 333, 333n14, 261, 269–282
334, 336, 337, 339 Schrodinger’s cat, 249, 252
392 SUBJECT INDEX