100% found this document useful (1 vote)
1K views8 pages

PS1 Solution

The document is an answer key for an economics exam. It contains answers and explanations to multiple choice and true/false questions about concepts like preference relations, indifference curves, and convex sets. The answers show the properties of different relations like weak preference, strict preference, and indifference as well as the definitions and applications of concepts like transitivity, convexity, and monotonicity.

Uploaded by

Colin Jennings
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
1K views8 pages

PS1 Solution

The document is an answer key for an economics exam. It contains answers and explanations to multiple choice and true/false questions about concepts like preference relations, indifference curves, and convex sets. The answers show the properties of different relations like weak preference, strict preference, and indifference as well as the definitions and applications of concepts like transitivity, convexity, and monotonicity.

Uploaded by

Colin Jennings
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8

Econ 210A PS1 Answer Key

1 Jehle-Reny
1.2 (a) In order to prove this, we must show that every element in  is
in the set . Let x, y ∈ X s.t. x  y. Therefore, x, y ∈. By
definition, x  y and x, y ∈. Therefore ⊂
(b) In order to prove this, we must show every element in ∼ is an
element in . Let x, y ∈ X s.t. x ∼ y. If x ∼ y then, we have
by definition x  yAN Dy  x . Since x  y, then x, y ∈ and
∼⊂
(c) In order to prove this we must show containment both ways. That
is, ( ∪ ∼) ⊂ and ⊂ ( ∪ ∼). Starting with ( ∪ ∼) ⊂:
Let x, y ∈ ( ∪ ∼). Then by definition, x, y are either a member
of  OR ∼. Therefore, by definition either, x  y AND NOT
(y  x) OR x  y AND y  x. In either case, x  y and
x, y ∈. Proving the other containment: let x, y ∈ s.t. X  y.
There are two possibilities between the relationship between y
and x. Either, y  x or NOT(y  x) (these are complementary
scenarios). Since we have x  y AND (y  x OR N OT (y  x)),
x, y ∈ ( ∪ ∼) by definition and ⊂ ( ∪ ∼). Since we have
shown containment both ways, = ( ∪ ∼).
(d) To show the set is empty, we do this by contradiction. Assume
that there exists x, y ∈ ( ∩ ∼). Then, (x  y AND NOT y  x
AND y  x) AND (x  y AND y  x). But, one cannot have
NOT(y  x) and y  x. Therefore, there ∃ no x, y ∈ ( ∩ ∼)

1.3 (a) For any x, y ∈ X where x ∼ y we can have neither x  y nor


y  x. For any x, y ∈ X where x  y, we can have neither x ∼ y
nor y ∼ x.
(b) Suppose x1  x2 . Then N OT x2  x1 . This means that N OT x2 
x1 OR x1 ∼ x2 . The case of x2  x1 can be shown by symme-
try. Suppose x1 ∼ x2 . Then it cannot be true that x1  x2 or
x2  x1 , since a necessary condition for either relation is that
N OT x1 ∼ x2 .

1.4 (a) : Let x1 , x2 , x3 ∈ X and assume that x1  x2 and x2  x3 .


Show that x1  x3 .

1
This implies that x1  x2 and x2  x3 and by transitivity of ,
x1  x3 . It is also true that x2 N OT  x1 and x3 N OT  x2 (∗) .
Assume that x3  x1 . This is necessary if x3  x1 . This implies
that x3  x2 by transitivity. But this contradicts the earlier
statement.
(b) Suppose x ∼ y and y ∼ z.
x ∼ y implies that x  y and y  x. y ∼ z implies that y  z
and z  y.
By transitivity of , x  y and y  z implies that x  z.
Also, because z  y and y  x, z  x.
Since x  z and z  x, it must be that x ∼ z.
(c) Finally, show that if x1 ∼ x2  x3 , then x1  x3 .
Assume x1 ∼ x2 and x2  x3 .
If x1 ∼ x2 ⇔ x1  x2 and x2  x1 . Since x1  x2 and x2  x3 ,
by transitivity of , then x1  x3 .

1.5 (b) We must again show containment both ways. Let y ∈ (x0 ).
Then, by definition y  x0 . Further, there are two possibilities
either x0  y OR NOT(x0  y) because these are complementary
qualities. Thus, by definition y ∈∼ (x0 ) ∪  (x0 ). Let y ∈∼
(x0 ) ∪  (x0 ). Then y  x AND x  y OR y  x AND NOT
x  y. But we already have that y  x, so y ∈ (x0 ) and we
have containment both directions and the sets are equal.
(c) By contradiction. Suppose y ∈∼ (x0 ) ∩  (x0 ). Then y  x
AND x  y AND y  x AND NOT x  y. Since x  y AND
NOT x  y can’t be both true it is a contradiction.
(g) Contradiction. Suppose x ∈ X,, but x ∈ / y ∈∼ (x0 ) ∪  (x0 ) ∪ ≺
(x0 ) . Then neither x  x0 , x ∼ x0 , and x ≺ x0 . By definition,
neither x  x0 nor x  x0 and this violates the completeness of
the preference relationship.

1.6 Many examples, but something like when consumer goods are indivis-
ible i.e. cars and refrigerators.

1.7 Let  represent convex preferences. Let x0 , x1 and x2 ∈ X where


x1  x2  x0 . Then x1 , x2 ∈  x0 . For any t ∈ [0, 1], consider the
bundle tx1 + (1 − t) x2 . By convexity of , tx1 + (1 − t) x2  x0 , which
is true if f tx + (1 − t) x ∈ x . Therefore,  x0 is a convex set
1 2 0


for any x0 ∈ X.

2
1.8 Case 1: Take two points, xa and xb along the indifference curve. To
show that the preferences are convex, it is seen that for any t ∈ [0, 1],
txa + (1 − t) xb  xa . We have shown Axiom 5 in this case. We
can take this a step further and say that txa + (1 − t) xb  xb and
txa + (1 − t) xb ∈∼ (xa ). Because any two points on the line, txa +
(1 − t) N OT xb  xa ⇒the preferences are not strictly convex. We
have shown how Axiom 5’ does not apply.
Case 2: Take two points, xa and xb such that xa  xb and let t ∈ (0, 1).
Then by construction, xa lies to the northeast to xb . Since t > 0,
that implies txa + (1 − t) xb lies to the northeast of xb . Therefore,
txa + (1 − t) xb  xb and we have shown Axiom 5.

1.9
Strict Monotonicity Axiom 4: ”Preferences increase northeasterly” translates to if xa  xb ,then
xa  xb . The fact that ”indifference sets are parallel right angles
that ’kink’ on the line x1 = x2 ” along with with ”preferences
increase northeasterly” implies that if xa  xb . These facts assert
that  satisfy strict monotonicity.
Strict Convexity Axiom 5: Pick any two point along a ”leg” of an indifference
 curvesuch as
(α, α) and (α, β), where α < β. The point α, 12 (α + β) lies in

3
between these two and on the same indifference  curve
 as (α, α)
1
and (α, β). Therefore, we cannot have α, 2 (α + β)  (α, α),
illustrating that these preferences are not strictly convex.
Convexity Axiom 5’: Consider any x, y ∈ X ⊂ R2 such that x ∼ y. Given the na-
ture of these preferences, it must be true then that min [x1 , x2 ] =
min [y1 , y2 ] . For any t ∈ [0, 1] consider the point tx + (1 − t) y. If
we can show that min [tx1 + (1 − t) y1 , tx2 + (1 − t) y2 ] ≥ min [x1 , x2 ] =
min [y1 , y2 ] , then we have shown that these preferences are con-
vex.

A.1.2 a Let x ∈ S then we must show x ∈ S ∪ T . S ∪ T contains all


elements in S and T . Therefore, since x ∈ S, x ∈ S ∪ T .
b Same proof
c Let x ∈ S ∩ T . That implies that x is in both S and T . Therefore
x∈T
c Same proof
A.1.5 Let A = [a1 , a2 ] and B = [b1 , b2 ], where a2 < b1 . Since ta2 +(1 − t) b1 ∈
/
A ∪ B for t ∈ (0, 1) , A ∪ B is not convex.
x
A.1.7  convex. For example, (0, 1) and (1, e) ∈ {(x, y) |y = e },
a Thisset is not
but 12 , e+1
2 / {(x, y) |y = ex } .

4
b This set is convex.
Let (x1 , y1 ) , (x2 , y2 ) ∈ S = {(x, y) |y ≥ ex } . Since y = ex is a con-
tinuous function, it is sufficient to show that (tx1 + (1 − t) x2 , ty1 + (1 − t) y2 ) ∈
S forany particular t ∈ (0, 1). 
Set t = 12 . Our task is to show
1
that 2 (x1 + x2 ) , 12 (y1 + y2 ) ∈ S. 1
2 (y1 + y2 ) ≥ 1
2 (ex1 + ex2 ),
1
since yi ≥ exi for i = 1, 2. Also, 21 (ex1 + ex2 ) ≥ e 2 (x1 +x2 ) =
x1 x2 x1 x2 x1 x2
e 2 · e 2 ⇔ ex1 + ex2 ≥ 2e 2 · e 2 ⇔ ex1 − 2e 2 · e 2 + ex2 ≥ 0 ⇔
(ex1 − ex2 )2 ≥ 0.
   
1 1 9 1
c This set is not convex. For example, 10 , 2 , 1 10 ,2 ∈ S =
  
(x, y) |y ≥ 2x − x2 ; x > 0, y > 0 . However, 1, 12 = 1 1 1

  2 10 , 2 +
1 9 1
2 1 10 ,2 ∈
/ S.
(d) This set is convex.
Consider any (x1 , y1 ) , (x2 , y2 ) ∈ S = {(x, y) |xy > 1, x, y > 0}.
For any t ∈ [0, 1],
(tx1 + (1 − t) x2 ) (ty1 + (1 − t) y2 ) = t2 x1 y1 +t (1 − t) (x1 y2 + x2 y1 )+
(1 − t)2 x2 y2
> t2 + (1 − t)2 + t (1 − t) (x1 y2 + x2 y1 ), since xi yi > 1.
= 1 + 2t2 − 2t + t (1 − t) (x1 y2 + x2 y1 )
= 1 + 2t (t − 1) + t (1 − t) (x1 y2 + x2 y1 )
= 1 + t (1 − t) (x1 y2 + x2 y1 − 2) ≥ 1 if f x1 y2 + x2 y1 ≥ 0
x1 y2 + x2 y1 = x1 y1 yy12 + x2 y2 yy21 − 2 > yy21 + yy12 − 2 ≥ 0
y1 − 2y1 y2 + y2 ≥ 0
(y1 − y2 )2 ≥ 0, which is always true and therefore, (tx1 + (1 − t) x2 , ty1 + (1 − t) y2 ) ∈
S which is convex.
  
1 1
e S is convex ⇐ 2 ln (x1 ) + ln (x2 ) ≤ ln 2 x1 + 12 x2
 
1 1
⇔ 2 ln (x1 x2 ) ≤ ln 2 x1 + 12 x2
 
⇔ (x1 x2 )1/2 ≤ 1
2 x1 + 12 x2
1/2
⇔ x1 − 2 (x1 x2 ) + x2 ≥ 0
1/2 2
 
1/2
⇔ x1 + x2 ≥ 0, which is always true.

A.1.8 R is not complete because there can be no R relation between any two
people who do not know each other.
R is not transitive, the obvious counter example being man R wife,wife
Rwife’s mom, but man not R wife’s mom. That is although a man

5
may love his wife, and wife may love her mom, the man may not love
her mother in law.

A.1.9 Suppose there exists x such that x ∈ B but f (x) ∈


/ f (A). Since x ∈ B
and B ⊂ A, then x ∈ A. Then, f (x) ∈ f (A) which contradicts our
initial assumption.

A.1.10 Suppose there exists x such that x ∈ B f −1 (x) ∈


/ f −1 (A) . Since x ∈ A
and A ⊂ B, then x ∈ B. Then, f −1 (x) ∈ f −1 (A) which contradicts
our initial assumption.

A.1.16 (a) Let −x1 , −x2 ∈ −S. Then x1 , x2 ∈ S. Convexity of S implies


that for any t ∈ [0, 1], tx1 + (1 − t) x2 ∈ S, which implies that
− [tx1 + (1 − t) x2 ] = t (−x1 ) + (1 − t) (−x2 ) ∈ −S. Therefore,
−S is convex.
(b) Let x1 , x2 ∈ S − T . Then there are s1 , s2 ∈ S and t1 , t2 ∈ T ,
such that x1 = s1 − t1 and x2 = s2 − t2 . Since S and T are
convex, λs1 + (1 − λ) s2 ∈ S and λt1 + (1 − λ) t2 ∈ T for any
λ ∈ [0, 1]. Given this and the fact that
λx1 + (1 − λ) x2 = λ (s1 − t1 ) + (1 − λ) (s2 − t2 )
= [λs1 + (1 − λ) s2 ] − [λt1 + (1 − λ) t2 ], λx1 + (1 − λ) x2 ∈ S − T ,
illustrating that S − T is convex.

A.1.17 (a) Part 1-prove 2 convex sets intersect and form a convex set. See
theorem A1.1 in Jehle and Reny page 414.
Part 2-Show that additional sets formed from the intersection of
convex sets is also a convex set.
Define A12 = A1 ∩ A2 which is convex. A12 ∩ A3 must also
be convex from part 1. This can be done for An = ∩ni=1 Ai and
An ∩ An+1 .
(b) Suppose x ∈ XAi , x = (x1, x2 , ..., xn ) . Suppose that y ∈ XAi ,
y = (y1 , y2 , ..., yn ). The convex combination of x and y is then:
z = (tx1 + (1 − t) y1 , tx2 + (1 − t) y2 , ..., txn + (1 − t) yn ) . Since
txi + (1 − t) yi ∈ Ai ∀i, Z ∈ Xi=1n A and X n A is convex.
i i=1 i
(c) Proof: If x ∈ ΣAi , ∃x1 ∈ A1 , x2 ∈ A2 , ..., xn ∈ An , s.t. Σxi = x
and
y ∈ ΣAi , ∃y1 ∈ A1 , y2 ∈ A2 , ..., yn ∈ An , s.t. Σyi = y.
Therefore, tx1 + (1 − t) y1 ∈ A1 , tx2 + (1 − t) y2 ∈ A2 , ..., txn +
(1 − t) yn ∈ An and Σ (tx1 + (1 − t) y1 ) ∈ ΣAi

6
t (Σxi ) + (1 − t) (Σyi ) ∈ ΣAi and tx + (1 − t) y ∈ ΣAi and ΣAi is
convex.
(d) See part (c).

A1.18 Proof: Suppose that Ω is not convex. The there exists x1 , x2 ∈ Ω,


x1 6= x2 and t ∈ (0, 1) for which tx1 + (1 − t) x2 ∈ / Ω. Thus for some
j ∈ {1, ..., m}, f (tx1 + (1 − t) x2 ) < 0 ⇒ a [tx1 + (1 − t) x2 ]+bj < 0.
j j

But this contradicts the fact that, since f j (x1 ) = aj x1 + bj ≥ 0 and


f j (x2 ) = aj x1 + bj ≥ 0 ⇔ t aj x1 + bj ≥ 0 and (1 − t) aj x2 + bj ≥
 

0 ⇔ t aj x1 + bj + (1 − t) aj x2 + bj = aj [tx1 + (1 − t) x2 ] + bj ≥ 0.
Hence, Ω must be convex.

2 Rubinstein
Problem 1 Show  satisfies property (1), which is saying that indifference curves
do not cross.
Consider any x, y ∈ X such that I (x) 6= I (y). Suppose that I (x) ∩
I (y) 6= 0, so that there is some z ∈ I (x) ∩ I (y). Then z ∈ I (x)
and z ∈ I (y), implying that z ∼ y and z ∼ x. From transitivity
it follows that z1 ∼ z2 for any z ∈ I (x) , z ∈ I (y), both z1 and
z2 ∈ I (x) ∩ I (y). Thus, I (x) = I (y) ,contradicting the premise that
I (x) 6= I (y). Therefore, I (x) ∩ I (y) = 0, if I (x) 6= I (y). Now
suppose that I (x) = I (y). Then x, y ∈ I (x) ∩ I (y) 6= 0.
Show  satisfies property (2), indifference sets are non-empty.
Proof: For any x ∈ X, x ∈ I (x). So for y = x, x ∈ I (y) .

Problem 2 Solved in class

Problem 4 Induction has three steps. First what are we inducting on? The size
of the set X.

Step 1 Base Case: i = 2. Let X have two elements x and y. Because


of the definition of asymmetry, WLOG, let xP y. Then we have
established an ordering and it is complete because both x and y
are described.
Step 2 Assume for cases up to i = n, that there is a complete ordering.
Step 3 Prove for case i = n + 1 that there is a complete ordering. Let
x1 , x2 , ..., xn+1 ∈ X of size n+1. We know that sets of size n have
a complete ordering. Lets take elements x1 , ...., xn and form a

7
new set. WLOG, we know that we can rank x1 P x2 P...xn . Now
construct a new set with xn+1 and x1 . By our base case, we
know that either x1 P xn+1 or xn+1 P x1 . If, xn+1 P x1 , then we
are done and we have our ordering xn+1 P x1 P x2 P...xn . If not,
we make a new set with x2 and xn+1 which we know we can
rank. If, xn+1 P x2 , then we are done and we have our ordering
x1 P xn+1 P x2 P...xn , we repeat this process n − 2, a finite number,
more times. If xn+1 does not outrank any of them we have our
complete ordering x1 P x2 P...xn P xn+1 , otherwise as specified we
have our complete ordering.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy