How To Show That Various Numbers Either Can or Cannot Be Constructed Using Only A Straightedge and Compass
How To Show That Various Numbers Either Can or Cannot Be Constructed Using Only A Straightedge and Compass
June 4, 2010
1 Introduction
It has been found that a circular area is to the square on a line equal to the quadrant of
the circumference, as the area of an equilateral rectangle is to the square on one side...
-Indiana House Bill No. 246, 1897
Three problems of classical Greek geometry are to do the following using only a compass and a
straightedge:
1. To ”square the circle”: Given a circle, to construct a square of the same area,
2. To ”trisect an angle”: Given an angle, to construct another angle 1/3 of the original angle,
3. To ”double the cube”: Given a cube, to construct a cube with twice the area.
Unfortunately, it is not possible to complete any of these tasks until additional tools (such as a
marked ruler) are provided. In section 2 we will examine the process of constructing numbers using
a compass and straightedge. We will then express constructions in algebraic terms. In section 3
we will derive several results about transcendental numbers. There are two goals: One, to show
that the numbers e and π are transcendental, and two, to show that the three classical geometry
problems are unsolvable. The two goals, of course, will turn out to be related.
1
2.1 Using the compass and straightedge
The following constructions and theorems will be taken without proof, refer to [5] for complete
proofs. That it is possible to construct the midpoint of a line segment, to construct a line perpen-
dicular to a point on a line, that the ratio of the corresponding sides of similar triangles are equal,
and that it is possible to bisect an angle.
One difficult restriction on constructions we might want to make is the fact that we cannot
directly construct circles with radius equal to the distance between any two points. We must use
the distance between the point we have chosen as the center of the circle and some other point we
have chosen as a point on its radius. However, this is an unnecessary restriction, as the following
theorem makes clear.
Proof. The points W and B both lay on the same circle, C(Q, W ). Hence |QW | = |QB|. The points
B and C both lay on the same circle C(A, B). Hence |AB| = |AC|. And the point A lays on the
intersection of two circles centered at P and Q. Hence |AQ| = |AP |. Then |P C| = |AC| − |AP | =
|AB| − |AQ| = |QB| = |QW |. So the circle C(P, C) has radius |QW |.
A C
P
Q W
From now on, then, it is possible to define a circle in a third way: Given points P , Q, and W ,
we write C(P, |QW |) to denote the circle centered at P of radius |QW |.
2
2.2.1 Some definitions
First, we identify Euclidean space with the complex plane. Choose two points, O and R. Define
|OR| to be the unit distance, 1. Construct a line L perpendicular to L(O, R) through O and define
I = C(O, R) ∪ L. Then by construction |OI| = |OR| = 1. The line L(O, R) is the real axis, or
x-axis; L(O, I) is the imaginary axis, or y-axis; and O is the origin. Also, we have a coordinate
system defined by |OR| = 1, e.g., O = (0, 0), R = (1, 0), and I = (0, 1). So we can identify a
point in the complex plane, x + iy, with a point (x, y) in Euclidean space. From now on, the two
notations will be used interchangeably. For example, we might take P = (x, y) to be a point in
Euclidean space and write z = P + i, or P . This will be understood to mean z = x + i(y + 1) or
x − iy.
Note that there are only countably many constructable points, because the set of 0-constructable
points has order 3, and given the set of n-constructable points there are only finitely many more
elements in the set of n + 1-constructable points. So we have already established that almost all
points are not constructable – we’re over 99% there. But to say more about the real number line,
we’ll need to establish a correspondence between constructable points and real numbers.
Proof. We must verify that given a, b ∈ K ∩ R, that a + b, ab, −a, a−1 ∈ K ∪ R. The general idea
will be to present the appropriate geometric proof that all of these complex numbers are identified
with constructable points. So let A = (a, 0) and B = (b, 0). Also, assume that a 6= 0 and b 6= 0,
otherwise the following results are trivial.
a + b This is easily shown by drawing C(A, |B|). It intersects the real axis at two points, by
construction, these points are (a + b, 0) and (a − b, 0).
−a Obvious: Draw C(O, A) and let P1 be its other intersection with the real axis. Then P1 =
(−a, 0).
3
P3
P3
P1
O A RB P2 O R P2 P1
√
(a) ab (b) a
ab Assume a > 0 and b > 0. Draw C(O, B) and call the upper point where it intersects the
imaginary axis P1 = (0, b). Because R, A ∈ K we have already shown that (1 + a, 0) ∈ K.
Let P2 = (1 + a, 0). Draw L(P1 , R), and construct a line through P2 parallel to it, call the
point where it intersects the imaginary axis P3 .
Then by construction the triangles ORP1 and OP2 P3 are similar triangles, hence |OP2 |/|OR| =
|OP3 |/|OP1 |, which means that a + 1 = (b + |P1 P3 |)/b, therefore, |P1 P3 | = ab. If either a < 0
or b < 0, then we have constructed −ab and hence by (b) we have ab ∈ K. If both a < 0 and
b < 0 then we have constructed ab.
a−1 The proof for this is similar to the previous proof. Let P1 = (1 + a, 0). Let P2 be the upper
intersection of C(O, P1 ) with the y-axis. Define P3 to be the intersection of the x-axis and
the line through P2 parallel to RA. As in the previous proof, we have similar triangles, and
|RP3 | = a−1 .
√
a Let P1 = (1 + a, 0). Let P2 be the midpoint of OP1 . Let P3 be the upper intersection of
C(P2 , O) with the vertical line through R. Then by construction the triangles ROP3 and
RP1 P3 are similar, so that |OR|/|RP3 | = |RP3 |/|RP1 |. So |RP3 |2 = |OR||RP1 | = |RP1 | = a,
√
i.e., |RP3 | = a.
Lemma 2. P = (x, y) is constructable if and only if P1 = (x, 0) and P2 = (y, 0) are constructable.
Proof. Assume that P1 = (x, 0) and P2 = (y, 0) are constructable. Let P3 = (0, y). Then P is the
intersection of the line through P1 perpendicular to the x-axis and the line through P3 perpendicular
to the y-axis.
Now assume that P = (x, y) is constructable. The point P1 is the intersection of the x-axis and
the line through P perpendicular to the x-axis, and the same for P2 .
Theorem 2. K is closed under addition, multiplication, square roots, every element has a multi-
plicative inverse (except O), and every element has an additive inverse.
4
Proof. This is a consequence of the preceeding two lemmas. For let P1 and P2 be points in K
and denote their corresponding complex numbers by x1 + iy1 and x2 + iy2 . Then P1 + P2 =
x1 +x2 +i(y1 +y2 ) is in K by lemmas 1 and 2. And P1 P2 = (x1 +iy1 )(x2 +iy2 ) = x2 −y 2 +i(x1 y2 +y1 x2 )
is in K by the same lemmas. And if we denote P1 as reiθ , then√eiθ/2 ∈ K, because every angle can
p √ √
be bisected, and r = x2 + y 2 is in K ∩ R, hence so is r, so P1 = reiθ/2 ∈ K.
Proof. This is easy to see: Since 1 ∈ K ∩ R and K ∩ R is closed under addition and has additive
inverses, we have Z ⊆ K. And since K is closed under multiplication and has multiplicative inverses,
it also contains all elements of the form p/q where p, q ∈ Z, which is Q.
Now we can write down some easy results. For example, if a, b, c ∈ K, then the roots of the
quadratic equation az 2 + bz + c are given by the quadratic formula, which involves only addition,
multiplication, and the square root. So the roots of the equation are also in K.
Proof. One direction is obvious: If z has been obtained by adding, multiplying, and taking square
roots of rational numbers, then by theorem 2 it is constructable.
Now assume that z is n-constructable, and denote the point in the Euclidean plane identified
with z by Pn . Note that this theorem is trivially true for numbers which are 0-constructable,
because those numbers are all rational numbers anyways. We’ll proceed with a proof by induction
on n. Assume that this theorem holds for all points which are n − 1-constructable.
Since z is n-constructable there exist points P1 , . . . , Pn−1 such that Pn is either
5
In the second case, we have the intersection
p of a line and a circle. Again we might express the
circle as something of the form y = ± (x − kx )2 − |Pk Pl |2 + ky and the line as something of the
jy − ij
form y − iy = (x − ix ). And again, note that to find a solution for x and y we would use
jx − ix
addition, multiplication, and square roots. p
2 2
pcase, we have the intersection of two circles. Then if we have y = ± (x − ix ) − |Pk Pl | +
In the third
ky and y = ± (x − kx )2 − |Pk Pl |2 + iy we again will use addition, multiplication, and square roots
to find a solution for x and y.
In all these cases we are adding, multiplying, and taking square roots of numbers which by
assumption were formed by adding, multiplying, and taking square roots of rational numbers.
Hence by induction z satisfies the conditions of the theorem.
hence cos 3θ = 4 cos3 θ − 3 cos θ. We have cos θ = 21 , and cos π = −1. Let θ = π/9 and u = 2 cos θ,
and we get the polynomial u3 − 3u − 1 = 0. This polynomial is irreducible, (i.e., it has no
factorization into polynomials with rational coefficients of degree greater than zero) and it is an
easily-believed fram from algebra that since the degree of the polynomial is 3, u cannot be expressed
as a combination of addition, multiplication, and square roots of rational numbers. So by theorem
3 it is impossible to trisect an angle.
This last proof leads into the next section. If we want to show that it is impossible to square
the circle, we must use a less clumsy term for the conditions of theorem 3 then ”can be expressed
as a combination of sums, products, and square roots of rational numbers”.
3 Transcendental numbers
...the fourth important fact, that the ratio of the diameter and circumference [of the
circle] is as five-fourths to four; and because of these facts and the further fact that the
rule in present use fails to work both ways mathematically, it should be discarded as
wholly wanting and misleading in its practical applications.
-Indiana House Bill No. 246, 1897
6
Definition 4. A number z ∈ C is algebraic if it is the zero of a polynomial with rational coeffi-
cients.
Note that if z is transcendental, then clearly it is not constructable. In this section, we will first
look at a specific proof that the number e is transcendental. Then we will examine why the methods
used in the proof were appropriate. Finally, we will prove that π is irrational, a consequence of
which will be that it is impossible to square the circle.
3.1 e is transcendental
Pn n
Before we begin, let f (x) = k=0 ak x be a polynomial of degree n with rational coefficients, and
define Z t
If (t) = et e−x f (x) dx, t > 0.
0
Now, since f 0 (x) is a polynomial with rational coefficients of degree n − 1, we can apply the same
process of integration by parts to the integral in (1). Applying the process n + 1 times to If (t) we
get the following equation:
n
X
If (t) = et f (k) (0) − f (k) (t) . (2)
k=0
Pn
Now define F (x) = k=0 |ak |xk . Then clearly F (t) > F (0) for t > 0 and n at least 1. We use
this fact and the triangle inequality to obtain the estimate
Z t
−x
t
|If (t)| = e
e f (x) dx
0
Z t
t −x
≤ |e | |e ||f (x)| dx
0
Z t
t −x
≤ |e | |e |F (x) dx
0
t
≤ |e | (tF (t)) . (3)
Later, in section 3.2 we’ll examine the motivations for choosing the particular integral we did
for If (t).
Theorem 6. e is transcendental.
7
Proof. Although various details have been fleshed out, the following proof is found in [2].
PnAssume otherwise. Then there is some polynomial a0 + a1 x + . . . + an xn of degree n such that
k
k=0 ak e = 0, and where a0 , . . . , an ∈ Q. Without loss of generality, multiply both sides by a
scalar factor to get a0 a positive integer. Define
where p is some large prime number at least as big as n and at least as big as a0 . Define J =
a0 If (0) + a1 If (1) + . . . + an If (n).
We will now proceed to show that (p − 1)! ≤ |J| ≤ cp , for some constant c.
Proof that (p − 1)! ≤ |J|: Note that the degree of f is (p − 1) + np = (n + 1)p − 1. By (2), we
have
(n+1)p−1
X
If (t) = et f (k) (0) − f (k) (t) .
k=0
Hence
n
X
J= ak I(k)
k=0
n (n+1)p−1
X X
= ak ek f (j) (0) − f (j) (k)
k=0 j=0
n (n+1)p−1 (n+1)p−1
X X X
= ek f (j) (0) − f (j) (k)
k=0 j=0 j=0
n
! (n+1)p−1
n (n+1)p−1
X X X X
k (j)
= ak e f (0) −
ak f (j) (k) , (5)
k=0 j=0 k=0 j=0
where in (5) P
we used the distributive law to expand the sums. But by assumption, e is
algebraic, so nk=0 ak ek = 0. Therefore, the first term in (5) is zero, and we get
n (n+1)p−1
X X
J =− ak f (j) (k). (6)
k=0 j=0
8
In other words, we can write
n n(p+1)−1
X X
(j−1)
J = a0 f (0) + ak f (j) (k) = a0 M (p − 1)! + N p! = (p − 1)!(a0 M + N p), (7)
k=0 j=p
where M = (−1)np (n!)p and N is just some large number representing the result of dividing
n n(p+1)−1
X X
ak f (j) (k)
k=0 j=p
Proof that |J| ≤ cp : On the other hand, note that by the triangle inequality F (k) (which we
defined near the beginning of this section) satisfies
Armed with this inequality, and (3), (and the fact that 1 + 2 + . . . + n ≤ n2 ), we are prepared
to estimate |J| again. Let a = max(|a1 |, . . . , |an |). Then
We have shown that (p − 1)! ≤ |J| ≤ cp , so (p − 1)! ≤ cp . But clearly for large p we have
(p − 1)! ≥ cp , which is a contradiction. So e is transcendental.
9
The proof that e was transcendental involved taking a transformation of a function, If , and
making several estimates on it. But it is an unsatisfying proof, because there is no indication of
the reason why If should be a good candidate for making estimates. The reason it is unsatisfying
is because it skips the full process through which Hermite proved that e is transcendental. In this
section, we will examine the subject of Padé approximants, which are useful in proving things like
irrationality and transcendence.
Definition 6. Let f (z) be a function analytic on a domain, and choose z0 in that domain. Then
if P (z), Q(z) are polynomials of degree less than or equal to some integers m and n respectivally,
such that the lowest order term of the series expansion of Q(z)f (z) − P (z) around z0 has order at
P (z)
least n + m + 1, then we call Q(z) the Padé approximant to f (z) of order n, m at z0 .
Note that this is equivalent to saying that as z → z0 we have
P (z)
f (z) = + O((z − z0 )n+m+1 ),
Q(z)
assuming that such a P (z) and Q(z) exist, which they may not. If they do exist, then it happens
that they are unique, although this is not particularly relevant.
The reason why we are considering Padé approximants is shown in the following lemma:
Lemma 3. Let x ∈ R. If there exists series of integers {pn }, {qn }, such that
lim qn x − pn = 0, (9)
n→∞
but
qn x − pn 6= 0, for all n, (10)
then x is irrational.
Proof. Suppose that x is rational. Then x = pq for some integers p, q. So
p qn p − p n q
qn x − pn = qn − pn = .
q q
By (10), this fraction is nonzero for all n, which implies that qn p − pn q is nonzero for all n. All of
these numbers are integers, hence |qn p − pn q| ≥ 1 for all n. Then |qn x − pn | ≥ 1/q, but by (9), this
quantity becomes very small for n large. So it cannot be bounded from below. Hence x must be
irrational.
Padé approximants provide a method of approximating numbers with rational functions, so it’s
possible to use this lemma in conjuction with them to show that e and π are irrational. But in
order to say something about whether a number is transcendental, we will have to introduce a
modification of Padé approximants. As we shall see, by making appropriate modifications in the
above lemma and Padé approximants, almost the same reasoning will suffice to show that a number
is transcendental.
Definition 7. Let f1 (z), . . . , fr (z) be r functions analytic on some domain. Define ~n = (n1 , . . . , nr )
and m~ = (m1 , . . . , mr ) where m1 , . . . , mr , n1 , . . . , nr ∈ N. Denote n1 +. . .+nr by |~n|, and m1 +. . . mr
by |m|.
~ Say there exists a polynomial Q(z) such that the degree of Q(z) is less than |~n|, and say
there exist r polynomials P1 (z), . . . , Pr (z) such that deg Pj (z) ≤ mj for 1 ≤ j ≤ r. If the lowest
order term of the series expansion of Q(z)fj (z) − Pj (z) around z0 has order at least nj + 1 for all
j, then these polynomials are called the Hermite-Padé approximants to f1 (z), . . . , fr (z) at z0 .
10
Note that these are similar to Padé approximants, the different being that we are using r rational
functions with a common denominator to approximate r functions.
The usefulness of these polynomials arises from the following lemma:
lim qn z j − pj = 0 (11)
n→∞
Proof. Suppose thatP z is not transcendental. This means that there is some sequence of integers
a0 , . . . , ar such that rj=0 aj xj = 0. So
r
X r
X r
X r
X
k k
aj (qn x − pj,n ) = aj (qn x ) − aj pj,n = − aj pj,n .
j=0 j=0 j=0 j=0
But by (11), every term in the sum goes to zero as n → ∞, so the sequence of sums cannot be
bounded from below. Hence z must be transcendental.
Note the suprising similarity between this lemma and the previous one, suprising because the
definitions for algebraic and rational seem in a certain sense to be fundamentally different.
Now we will prove again that e is transcendental. This is in the vein of the original proof used
by Hermite to prove e irrational, and it explicitly makes use of estimates and equations we derived
in the previous proof that e was transcendental in order to derive Hermite-Padé approximants to
the function ez .
Theorem 7. e is transcendental.
11
where T (x) is some polynomial. Notice that this is simply the Laplace transform of T (x) multiplied
by z |~n|+N +1 and recall that this will yield a polynomial of degree (|~n| + N ) − k, where k is the
degree of the lowest order term of T (x). Define
Z ∞
Pj (z) = z |~n|+N +1 T (x + j)e−zx dx,
0
for 1 ≤ j ≤ r. This is the Laplace transform of T (x + j) multiplied by z |~n|+N +1 , and it will yield a
polynomial of degree (|~n| + N ) − k 0 , where k 0 is the degree of the lowest order term of T (x + j).
We are trying to find polynomials which are the Hermite-Padé approximants to ez of a certain
order to satisfy the conditions of the lemma. Specifically, we want the degree of Q(z) to be of order
|~n|, and we want the degree of Pj (z) to be of order mj . This suggests that we choose a polynomial
T (x) such that T (x) has a zero of order N at x = 0 and a zero of order mj at x = j. The following
obvious choice presents itself:
Note that T (x) has degree N + |m|. ~ Recall by the previous discussion that Q(z) has degree
(|~n| + N ) − k, where k is the lowest degree term of T (x). By construction, that is N , so Q(z) has
degree |~n|. And similarly, Pj (z) has degree |~n| + N − k 0 , where here k 0 = nj by construction, so it
has degree |~n| + N − nj = mj .
Now the reason for choosing (4) becomes more clear – it has zeros of appropriate orders at the
appropriate places to ensure that the Hermite-Padé approximants are close enough to ez .
So we have successfully defined polynomials Q(z), P1 (z), . . . , Pr (z) which have the appropriate
degrees. Now we compute
Z ∞ Z ∞
jz |~
n|+N +1 −zx |~
n|+N +1
jz
Q(z)e − Pj (z) = e z T (x)e dx − z T (x + j)e−zx dx
0 0
Z ∞ Z ∞
zj |~
n|+N +1 −zx
=e z T (x)e dx − T (x)ejz−zx dx
0 j
Z j
= ezj z |~n|+N +1 T (x)e−zx dx, (13)
0
where we used a change of variables substitution on the second integral there. Notice that we have
seen something similar to (13) before – see (1). We established in (2) that
Z j NX
+m
~
T (x)e−x dx = ej T (k) (0) − T (k) (j) .
0 k=0
Note that by construction T (k) (j) = 0 for k ≤ N + mj . Then the order of the lowest nonzero
term of (13) must be N + |~n| + 1 − N − mj = |~n| − mj , which is the appropriate condition for the
Hermite-Padé approximant.
12
Now take z = 1, and denote the ith prime by p(i). Take N = p(i) − 1 and nj = p(i) for
1 ≤ j ≤ r. Let qi = Q(1)/(p(i) − 1)! and pj,i = Pj (1)/(p − 1)!. We already showed in the first proof
that qi is not divisible by p(i) and pj,i is divisible by p(i). So qi + rk=0 ak pk,i is not divisible by
P
p(i) for all i, which implies that
Xr
qi + ak pk,i 6= 0.
k=0
So we have satisfied the second condition of lemma 4. On the other hand, using the estimate we
derived in (8) we have |T (x)| ≤ (2r)(r+1)p−1 , so we have
Z j
ej ej (2r)(r+1)p−1 j −x
Z
i −x
qi e − pj,i = T (x)e dx ≤ e dx → 0
(p − 1)! 0 (p − 1)! 0
as i → ∞, because the factorial function grows much faster than the power function. So we have
satisfied condition 1 of lemma 4, hence e is transcendental.
In the original proof, these sorts of estimates were used to provide a contradiction, in other words
lemma 4 was built into the proof itself. Here the reason for choosing If (x) in (1) becomes clear:
It allowed us to precisely control the lowest order nonzero term in the polynomials we produced
and thus ensured that the polynomials would approximate ez in just the right way. Combined
with lemma 4, this was enough to show that e is transcendental. Now we will show that π is
transcendental, a proof which Lindemann was the first to write down after Hermite’s proof of
the transcendence of π. As we shall see, it uses the same underlying technique. However, a few
results are neccesary from outside this paper, specifically the fact that the product of two algebraic
numbers is algebraic and a result regarding certain types of polynomial.
And remember, a consequence of theorem is that it is impossible to square the circle.
Theorem 8. π is transcendental.
Proof. The following proof is copied almost verbatim from [2] and [6].
Assume otherwise. Note that since the imaginary number i is the root of x2 + 1 it is algebraic.
It is a non-trivial result that the product of two algebraic numbers is itself algebraic, refer to [4]
for a proof. So iπ is algebraic, so it is the root of some polynomial. Let d be the degree of the
polynomial of least degree of which iπ is a root. Since this polynomial has rational coefficients,
assume without loss of generality that it has integer coefficients (by multiplying through by some
constant). Let l be the coefficient of the leading term. By the fundamental theorem of algebra
there are d roots of this polynomial. Denote the roots of the polynomial by θ1 , . . . , θd . Using the
well-known identity eiπ = −1, we must have that
Expanding the left side of this equation, we get a series of 2d exponents raised to a power of
the form eΘ , Θ = 1 θ1 + . . . + d θd , where j = 0 or 1. Some of these powers are nonzero, let n be
the number of nonzero powers and denote the nonzero powers by Θ1 , . . . Θn . We then have
Note that since at least one of the powers is zero, 2d − n is a positive integer.
13
Define If (t) as in the proof that e was transcendental. Again let p be some large prime number.
Define
J = If (α1 ) + . . . + If (αn ),
where
f (x) = lnp xp−1 (x − α1 )p . . . (x − αn )p .
By (2) and (15) we get
(n+1)p−1 (n+1)p−1 n
X X X
(j)
J = −q f (0) − f (k) (αj ),
k=0 k=0 j=1
where recall that l is the coefficient of the leading term of the polynomial which iπ is a root of.
The sum over j is a symmetric polynomial in lα1 , . . . , lαn , i.e., interchanging these numbers
with each other does not change the polynomial. It is a result of the fundamental theorem of
symmetric functions that this sum will be an integer. By the same argument as in theorem 6, we
have f (k) (αj ) = 0 when j < p so it is trivially divisible by p!, f (k) (0) an integer divisible by p! when
j 6= p − 1, and
f (p−1) (0) = (p − 1)!(−l)np (α1 . . . αn )p
an integer divisible by (p − 1)! but not by p! if p is large enough. So for p > 2d − n we have
|J| ≥ (p − 1)!. But by 3 we have that
for some constant c independent of p. For sufficiently large p we have (p − 1)! > cp , which is a
contradiction, so π is transcendental.
Proof. To square the circle means to construct a square of area equal to the area of the unit circle.
√
The unit circle has area π, so this would mean constructing a square with sides of length π. But
√ √ √
π cannot be constructable, for then π π = π would be algebraic, and we have shown that this
is not the case.
14
References
[1] Van Assche, William. Padé and Hermite-Padé approximation and orthogonality. Surveys in
Approximation Theory, Vol. 2, pp. 61-91. 2006.
[2] Baker, Alan, Transcendental Number Theory, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1975.
[3] Cohn, Henry. A Short Proof of the Simple Continued Fraction Expansion of e. The American
Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 113, No. 1, pp. 57-62. 2006.
[4] Ireland, Kenneth; Michael Rosen. A Classical Introduction to Modern Number Theory. Springer-
Verlag, New York, NY. 1990.
[5] Martin, George. Geometric Proofs. Springer-Verlag, New York, NY. 1997.
[6] Niven, Ivan. Irrational Numbers, The Mathematical Association of America, Rahway, NJ, 1956.
[7] Olds, C.D. The Simple Continued Fraction Expansion of e. The American Mathematical
Monthly, Vol. 77, No. 9, pp. 968-974. 1970.
[8] Rotman, Joseph, Galois Theory, Springer-Verlag, New York, NY. 1990.
15