Juris Rough
Juris Rough
Central to Nozick’s work is individuals’ rights which are evident from his
audacious statement on the preface to his book that “individuals have rights
and there are things no person or group may do to them (without violating
their rights)”. Nozick, in particular, is critical of John Rawls, arguably the
most important political philosopher of the twentieth century whose book, A
Theory of Justice [2], generated more discussion and commentary than any
other book of political and social theory published since World War II.
Central to Nozick’s criticism of Rawls’ theory targets the end-result oriented
methods, but the theory of redistribution, in particular. Nozick absolutely
rejects the idea of redistribution and maintains that it contradicts the idea of
self-ownership. He further stresses that redistribution makes others “a part-
owner of you giving] them a property right in you”. As an alternative to
Rawls’ theory, Nozick suggests his entitlement theory. One of the main
problem with Nozick’s arguments is the “abstractness of the individualism
they presuppose” and individualism, according to Lukes, is a “distorting lens
that satisfies the intellect while simplifying the world”. Nozick attempts to
isolate people with individualism which is contrary to the fact that “people
are constituted by the societies into which they are socialised and live”. This
article will explore Nozick’s theory of justice, justice in holdings, individual
rights and the minimal state as to whether these concepts can stand as
universal theory taking into account the surrounding academic literature.
In the minimal state when disputes arise and enforcement of law is required,
Nozick hypothetically argues, that people might form “mutual protection
associations” in order to defend themselves and to exercise their right to
rectification [6]. Under such an arrangement, all members of the association
are “on call” to defend and enforce the rights of other members meaning that
everyone is always “on call” and any member may call upon any other
member or members for protection. This begs the question if everyone in
real world would be ready to be “on call”. One does not have to be a cynic to
dispute with this notion but a mere depiction of human nature in any context
would serve to disagree with this imaginary Good Samaritan role which is
rather unscrupulous of human nature and behavior. Nozick contends, initially
there may be several protective associations within the same geographical
area. When clients from different agencies enter into dispute and the
agencies cannot agree on how to resolve the matter, they too will enter into
conflict. The result of such conflict will be that over time a natural monopoly
will occur. Eventually there will be only one protective association within a
geographical area: the “dominant protective association [7]”. The evolution
process of the “dominant protective association” invites criticism such as
Nozick is calling for conflict rather that providing a pragmatic solution. The
theory also fails detail whether this dominant protective association would be
private or public entities and whether it would be charging people any fee or
if it is free of cost. Ironically, Nozick does not consider how the state comes
about. He opines, self-interest in his state of nature will ultimately give rise
to the state. A critical mind would stop short of acceding to this claim as to
how self-interest could give rise to a state, if at all. Even if one were to defer
to this involuntarily for the sake of an argument, would it not lead to chaos
and conflict similar to the events from which the dominant protective
association evolve albeit a much greater magnitude of chaos and conflict
would ensemble prior to the evolution of the state which Nozick indicated.
“If the world were wholly just, the following inductive definition would
exhaustively cover the subject of justice in holdings. (1) A person who
acquires a holding in accordance with the principle of justice in acquisition is
entitled to that holding. (2) A person who acquires a holding in accordance
with the principle of justice in transfer, from someone else entitled to the
holding, is entitled to the holding. (3) No one is entitled to a holding except
by (repeated) applications of 1 and 2”.
To put it simply a person’s holdings are just if acquired through (1) just
original acquisition or (2) just transfer or (3) through rectification of
injustices in the two senses.
Even the briefest survey of human history reveals that the current
distribution of property is as much the consequence of theft and conquest as
it is the product of libertarian entitlement. Nozick explains, historical
entitlement is subject to the principle of rectification which attempts to use
historical information to reproduce “what would have occurred… if injustice
had not taken place”. While many injustices can be traced, many others are
buried and forgotten and hence the principle has very limited application
unless it is assumed that the least well off are most likely to have been the
victims of historical injustice. Nonetheless, an attempt to rectify past
injustices can affect ‘innocent’ owners and undermine the certainty of legal
title, suggesting that claims for rectification might be barred beyond a
stipulated period of time. A commentator argues that the rectification
principle is almost ridiculous hit in Nozick’s own theory-it could lead to
dictatorship and to very endresult determined societies. It may, therefore, be
submitted that with its temporary application, the rectification principle lacks
the criteria to be a universal one [13].
Rights as Trumps
Nozick, in general, contends that people are born
with fundamental individual rights. These individual rights are paramount
and that there is no need for a system to achieve moral equilibrium. He
rejects all end-result theories, i.e. distributive theories such as Rawls theory
of justice. Nozick rather adopts the 18th century philosopher Immanuel
Kant’s principle of “individual inviolability” that cannot be violated as a
means to achieve particular ends, meaning the significance of each person’s
possessions of self-ownership is that people should not be used as resources
or a means of achieving some end and this is exactly what Rawls proposes to
do, Nozick criticizes [14]. It is wrong to treat people as if they are merely of
instrumental worth or to sacrifice one person for another. He claims that the
rights of others determine constrains on our actions.
According to Nozick, the “classical liberal” view is that the right of people to
control their bodies and actions is a property right, the right of self-
ownership. He further argues for his entitlement theory where it is
permissible for people to have and hold property on however an unequal
basis provided it was acquired legitimately in the first place. Thus, if
someone acquired a holding justly, any interference with his holdings i.e. via
imposition of tax, would violate his rights. Nozick claims, a redistributive
system invades that right making others “a part owner of you giving them a
property right in you”. Thus, a redistributive system institutes partial
‘ownership by others of people and their actions and labour’. Consequently,
he argues that taxation of labour income is “on a par with forced labour
[15]”.
When a person shapes her or his life in accordance with some overall
plan, that person gives meaning to her or his life.4 Persons, as such,
are separate entities capable of determining the meaning and direction
of their lives. Put slightly differently, we are all separate existences
capable of leading separate lives.5 According to Nozick, the
significance of each person’s possession of self-ownership is that
people should not be used as resources or as a means of achieving
some end. It is wrong, he states, to treat people as if they are merely of
instrumental worth, or to sacrifice one person for another. 6
The separateness of each person means that each person’s body and
liberty are separate and distinct from those of others. They belong to
each person and not to someone else. As such, Nozick states, only
each person has the right to decide what happens to her or his life,
body, liberty or property. Being inviolable and exhaustive, these rights
are absolute.
Nozick claims that the rights of others determine the constraints on
our actions.7 That is, a person’s rights are not merely superficial
claims that can be overridden. Rather, they are boundaries not to be
crossed without the free consent of the person whose rights they are.
Elaborating on this, Nozick writes:
[T]hat there are different individuals with separate lives and
so no one may be sacrificed for others, underlies the
existence of moral side constraints, but it also leads to a
libertarian side constraint that prohibits aggression against
another.8
Nozick on Rawls
Rawls’ idea of the role and nature of government as required by
“justice as fairness” is vastly different to that envisaged by Nozick.
This is due to their very different understandings of justice and the
relationship between equality and liberty.
In competition with Rawls’ “justice as fairness”, Nozick proposes
“an entitlement theory of justice”. Nozick claims:
[If the world] were wholly just, the following inductive
definition would exhaustively cover the subject of justice in
holdings:
(1) A person who acquires a holding in accordance with the
principle of justice in acquisition is entitled to that
holding.
(2) A person who acquires a holding in accordance with the
principle of justice in transfer, from someone else entitled
to that holding, is entitled to the holding.
No one is entitled to a holding except by (repeated)
applications of 1 and 2.46