Maps of The Moon by Thomas A. S. Haddad
Maps of The Moon by Thomas A. S. Haddad
Map History
Editor-in-Chief
Editorial Board
Volumes published in this Brill Research Perspectives title are listed at brill.com/rpmh
Maps of the Moon
Lunar Cartography from
the Seventeenth Century to the Space Age
By
Thomás A. S. Haddad
LEIDEN | BOSTON
This paperback book edition is simultaneously published as issue 1.2 (2019) of Map History,
doi:10.1163/25893963-12340002.
Typeface for the Latin, Greek, and Cyrillic scripts: “Brill”. See and download: brill.com/brill-typeface.
Copyright 2019 Thomás A. S. Haddad. Published by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands.
Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Brill Hes & De Graaf, Brill Nijhoff, Brill Rodopi,
Brill Sense, Hotei Publishing, mentis Verlag, Verlag Ferdinand Schöningh and Wilhelm Fink Verlag.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system,
or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise,
without prior written permission from the publisher.
Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Koninklijke Brill NV provided
that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910,
Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change.
Thomás A. S. Haddad
University of São Paulo (USP), Brazil
thaddad@usp.br
Abstract
When does a depiction of the moon become a lunar map? This essay addresses this
question from theoretical and historical standpoints. It is argued that moon maps are
of crucial importance to the history of cartography, for they challenge established no-
tions of what is a map, how it functions, what are its purposes, and what kind of power
it embodies and performs. The work also shows how terrestrial cartography has shaped
the history of lunar mapping since the seventeenth century, through visual and no-
menclature conventions, the cultural currency of maps, mapmakers’ social standing,
and data-gathering and projection practices. It further demonstrates that lunar cartog-
raphy has also been organized by an internal principle that is born of the fundamental
problem of how to create static map spaces capable of representing a referent that is
constantly changing to our eyes, as is the visible face of the moon. It is suggested that
moon maps may be classed on three broad categories, according to the kinds of solu-
tions for this representational problem that have been devised over the last 400 years.
Keywords
None of the convicts could have had an idea of their destination. Before
them yawned a terrifying void of time and space. (…) If they had been
told they were off to the moon, the sense of loss, deracination and fear
could hardly have been worse—at least one could see the moon from
England, which could not be said for Botany Bay.
Roberts Hughes, The Fatal Shore (1986)
The opening words show art critic and literary author Robert Hughes trying to
capture the dread and despair that must have taken hold of the first convicts
deported from Britain to Australia. For them, in the late eighteenth century,
when Hughes’s novel is set, Botany Bay was at best a drawing on a map, per-
haps not even that. The moon, however, had always been there, as it had for
every other person in history. Better be sent to a familiar other world than to an
unimaginable place that was part of “this world” only by convention (and car-
tographic artifice). Hughes’s convicts could hardly have known, but at the time
of their suffering there existed many more maps of the lunar surface than of
Botany Bay’s shores, where they would meet their fate. Indeed, starting around
the middle of the previous century, dozens, maybe hundreds, of maps of the
moon were drawn, printed, copied and debated. They came in all flavors and
sizes: some were inserted in books, others stood alone, some were sketches
or diagrams used to make a point in a cosmological argument, others looked
almost like large-scale regional maps. They resembled terrestrial maps in many
of their visual features: lines, blank spaces, hachuring, stippling, graduated
scales, graticules, ornamentation, and inscriptions. A large number of them
even showed the names of hundreds of places on the moon, places collec-
tively called oceans, seas, valleys, mounts, capes and so on. Unlike Botany Bay,
however, no one had ever been to the moon—and would not be for another
two centuries.
This “distant closeness” of the moon is by no means a flight of fancy from
a late-twentieth century novel such as Hughes’s. “The moon, for early mod-
ern Englishmen,” writes historian David Cressy, “was comfortingly familiar yet
achingly distant” (Cressy 2006, 961). Although he writes specifically of early
modern England, there is no doubt that elsewhere too the moon and its phases
had “helped regulate mundane activities, from the planting of crops to the let-
ting of blood, as well as governed the washing of the tides.” In Europe, specu-
lation about the inhabitability of the moon came all the way from antiquity,
with strong opinions in favor as well as to the contrary. Questions revolved
around the physical nature of the moon, God’s designs for creation, and the
place of the earth in the universe. In the early modern period, this speculation
“was stimulated by Renaissance voyaging and geography, with frequent com-
parisons to America, which had been unknown before Columbus, and to the
Antipodes, most of which remained undiscovered” (Cressy 2006, 962). Literary
works that reached considerably large audiences helped move the debate out
Maps of the Moon 3
of scholarly circles to much wider publics: from Plutarch and Lucian to Cyrano
de Bergerac and John Wilkins, through Juan de Maldonado, Johannes Kepler,
Francis Godwin and many others, narratives of voyages to the moon consti-
tuted almost a genre and helped create visions of what the moon might look
like on close inspection (see Montgomery 1999, chapters 4 and 9; Nicolson
1948). Necessarily, such accounts carried expectations of what the moon could
be in terms of geography, and were firmly based on our sole experience of
space—terrestrial space—, multifarious as such experience and its represen-
tations, including cartographic ones, might be.
Inhabited or not, the moon was unquestionably out of reach. Early modern
audiences knew all too well that fictional accounts of voyages to our sister ce-
lestial body were moralizing tales or allegories, and not anticipations of any-
thing that they or their immediate descendants would be able to undergo. Yet,
starting in the seventeenth century, this unreachable world has been mapped
countless times and its most minute surface features have been given names,
thousands of them. Moon maps appeared in expensive books and cheap man-
uals, as ornaments to terrestrial maps and as broadsheet engravings with lavish
forms of ornamentation of their own. They are to be found in encyclopedias
and textbooks, t-shirts and mugs, as glossy-paper wall posters, and folded maps
published by the exact same companies that produce roadmaps of this kind.
But a moon map will not help anyone find their way when lost or planning an
itinerary; it will not help in visualizing one’s “place in the world” (or convincing
one that there is such a thing); it cannot be used in territorial claims or border
disputes, or to settle property quarrels, place troops, mark treasuries, estimate
travel times, change trains, or represent the spatial distribution of industries,
activities, average temperatures or whatever else one can come up with.1 At
first sight, moon maps seem absolutely unable to perform any single function
usually ascribed to maps—and in this they are, in a way, refreshingly “useless.”
We cannot avoid asking, then, what is a moon map after all?2
Before moving on to some possible ways of approaching the question
(which does not mean it has a definitive answer), which I will attempt to do
in the first part of this essay, let us start by considering in general terms how
“mainstream” work on the history of terrestrial cartography can be brought to
1 I am obviously thinking of thematic cartography in the last few examples. Nevertheless, one
should not rush into believing the moon does not have its own brand of thematic maps,
representing spatial distributions of properly lunar properties. Indeed, there are many maps
of lunar surface temperatures, soil composition, or geological structure, to name the most
well-known.
2 Here and in much of what follows I am strongly indebted to Christian Jacob’s seminal essay
“What is a map?” (Jacob 2006, chapter 1).
4 Haddad
3 Harley’s ideas on silences and “external power” come together in such an unreasonably per-
fect way in the fact that the earliest maps of the far-side of the moon named all surface
features after Soviets—who were responsible for the first images of that side—that one is
tempted to look for less obvious cases (for the question of external power, see Harley 1988b).
On empty space, see also Hiatt (2002) and Lois (2018a).
Maps of the Moon 5
4 On the subject of map catalogs and descriptions, it should be mandatory to mention the
immense work of the International Cartographic Association’s Commission of Planetary
Cartography, which maintains an online database of thousands of lunar and other planet’s
maps from 1600 to 2017. (On last consultation the database included 2,506 planetary and
moon maps of all different kinds.) See: https://planetcarto.wordpress.com/resources/.
5 There are also many shorter works that are, nevertheless, equally broad in scope and rigor-
ously descriptive in purview: see for instance Raposo (2018), Wolfschmidt (2013), van Gent
and Van Helden (2007), Pigatto and Zanini (2001), or Paluzie i Borrell (1967).
Maps of the Moon 7
descriptive detail and the wealth of information they convey. Highly specialized
or all encompassing, these works represent an approach to map history that is
based on the premise that documents will speak for themselves. One should not
demand from these works something they never intended to present in the first
place, like “theory” (in a grand sense) or even the kind of dense contextualiza-
tion we have grown used to expecting to find in historical works in general.
Deep attention to context in particular is to be found in a second category of
approaches to the history of moon maps, which leads us into firm cultural his-
tory ground. Here we can expect “thick descriptions” of the contexts in which
lunar maps appeared, how they functioned in these contexts, and the social
practices attendant to their creation, circulation, usage, permanence, or obliv-
ion. Many outstanding examples of this approach are to be found, for instance,
in a recent collection edited by Carmen Pérez González, whose chapters range
from an investigation of moon maps and their collectors in Edo Era Japan, to
a connected history of astronomical observatories, lunar maps, photography,
and urban planning in modern Persia, to the establishment and transforma-
tions of the scientific practice of astrophotography in German observatories,
among other very important contributions (Pérez González 2018). Another re-
markable achievement is Nydia Pineda’s doctoral dissertation, hopefully to be
published soon, which ranks as the most thorough contribution to the cultural
history of seventeenth-century selenography to date. In her work, Pineda mas-
terfully weaves threads from the history of science, the history of the book and
print culture, and patronage studies to come up with a complexly nuanced un-
derstanding of lunar maps as artifacts at once technical and symbolic (Pineda
de Ávila 2017).
Keeping in mind the previous broad characterization of the field, I should
now warn readers that my intention in this essay is evidently not to offer yet
another exhaustive examination of 400 hundred years’ worth of moon maps,
with exacting descriptions of dozens of specimens and biographical notices of
their makers. Even less so can I claim the objective of offering a “total” cultural
history of the whole enterprise of lunar mapping. This would be an impossible
task by definition, given the sheer variety of contexts in which they appeared,
the myriad uses they have been put to, and the uncountable fortunes they have
met with, together with those of their respective authors and viewers. Instead,
my intention is to invite a conversation on how the history of cartography as
a more or less discrete discipline (or set of intellectual practices, approaches,
and insights bearing upon maps throughout history) may inform and shape
approaches to the history of moon maps.
The history of cartography is remarkable for how much it welcomes episte-
mological speculation, probably because its main object—the map—remains
8 Haddad
so elusive. This does not mean the existence of a lack of rigor either when
addressing maps as material objects that must be carefully described and
read, or when investigating their contexts using other kinds of documents.
Nonetheless, the history of cartography recognizes the value, for example,
of comparisons between different maps (not in order to judge which one is
“better”) or cartographic practices in ways that other lineages of historical in-
quiry usually reject. In other words, it allows for different preoccupations and
different standards of evidence, which together may cast a different light on
some aspects of moon maps, or suggest new research perspectives.
Of course I cannot claim that this essay will in any way make moon maps
a standard subject in the history of cartography. Additionally, I have no inten-
tion of making it compulsory to historians of science or art, or cultural histori-
ans (the main workers on the rather narrow theme of lunar maps), to redirect
their investigations to meet whatever is emerging from the quarters of the his-
tory of cartography. Yet, any increase, however small, in mutual interest and
cross-pollination between those fields is worth the effort, and if my essay helps
prompt even a single adventure across disciplinary boundaries by some other
explorer, I will be very satisfied. My own exploration here will be guided by one
overarching theme, developed along three interrelated lines. The overarching
theme was already announced in the question, “What is a moon map?” In other
words, I am interested in the specificity of moon maps, if they have one at all.
This is the problem that, in turn, unfolds along three lines. The first relates to
the long-standing tension between naturalistic and more schematic modes of
representation of the moon. Is the “mapness” of an image that has the moon as
its referent somehow connected to the image’s place in this one-dimensional
axis stretching from naturalistic renderings to diagrams? The second line along
which to search for the specificity of lunar maps is the investigation of the
historical relationships that lunar cartography established with its terrestrial
counterpart. Now the focus is not so much on the images, but on the prac-
tices attendant to their creation and from where they extract meaning. Are
there differences between making or viewing a map of the moon and a map of
the earth?
If the previous two lines of inquiry into the specificity of moon maps are
hardly surprising, there is, however, a third one that may claim to be more un-
anticipated: my contention will be that much of the history of lunar mapping
may be profitably seen as a history of specific solutions that were given to the
problem of representing an object that is continuously changing its appear-
ance over time. The moon is obviously, visibly, in a permanent state of change.
At first, one might think this time variation is easy to tame, for it is repeti-
tive and predictable. Selenography would just have to keep clear of the most
Maps of the Moon 9
ostensible changes in appearances (above all the monthly phase cycle) and
chase the underlying, permanent “reality.” But, as the telescope revealed before
the seventeenth century even reached its midpoint, things are more compli-
cated. The moon changes its appearance over time in ways, as we will see, that
are exceedingly difficult to capture in a steady image. The organizing principle
of lunar mapping, the “epistemology of selenography,” would thus be the visual
representation of time as space; not real, physical space, but map space. In
a nutshell, the problem resides in the fact that we do not just see half of the
moon’s surface, but more. Truly, on any given single instant we can see at most
half, but over time the moon reveals more than that. So mapmakers were con-
fronted with the challenge of representing more than half of a spherical sur-
face inside a circular flat space, something that had important consequences
for how moon maps were created and what they made visible.
To my view we can identify at least three different kinds of answers to this
fundamental problem of reducing the moon’s temporal change to a spatial
order that exists only on maps. Each kind of answer represented a roughly suc-
cessive (but not exclusive) trend in selenography. We could name each trend as
the “concretion,” “abstraction,” and “elimination” of time; the first was typical of
the seventeenth century, the second rose to prominence in the mid-eighteenth
century, and the last one became dominant toward the end of the nineteenth
century. This periodization is far from rigid, of course: not only did those trends
live alongside each other on many occasions, but also they cannot be taken to
determine or explain everything there is to be known about moon maps. We
cannot underestimate the determining force of terrestrial cartography in shap-
ing the end results of selenography, i.e., moon maps themselves. They could
not but emulate earth maps in most formal aspects. Terrestrial cartography
was the cultural fountainhead from which lunar mapmakers borrowed most
of their semantics, even if they had to invent new syntactical forms to face the
problem of time.
…
The structure of the essay is as follows: in Section 1 I return to the problem
of the “mapness” of moon maps in general terms, borrowing from work in
the history of (terrestrial) cartography that has made use of concepts coming
from, among others, semiotics or visual studies. Besides expounding in more
detail some ways in which the history of cartography may shed light on the
specific problem posed by lunar maps, I will also explicitly state the issue of
“naturalistic vs. schematic representation” as it appears on maps of the moon,
using examples.
10 Haddad
i.e., as a triangulation of points, and realized that the effects of changing ap-
pearance over time could be abstracted from a moon map. A few examples of
ulterior maps, showing this new dominance of map space over “optical space,”
are then submitted to readers’ judgments, again as a visual series, with spare
textual commentary.
Finally, Section 6 considers the third mode of dealing with the problem of
time in lunar mapping, the mode I have called “elimination.” Its root lies on a
change of scale: instead of insisting on fitting all that can be seen of the moon’s
surface inside a circular, unitary representation space, mapmakers increasingly
focused on limited areas, amenable to projection onto spaces bounded by four
straight edges. By slicing the moon’s surface into smaller sections, change over
time was eliminated from the picture, and what is more, the point of view from
which the representation made sense moved away from the earth. As I briefly
show toward the end of Section 6, the observer was relocated to none other
than a place that would only be physically attained in the Space Age. After this
a few concluding remarks follow, along with perspectives for further research.
We have already met the general question, “What is a moon map?” Replying
casually that it is “a flat graphic representation of the moon’s visible surface”
will not suffice. Any drawing, painting, or photograph that represents some-
thing is, by definition, a “flat graphic representation,” but in the overwhelming
majority of cases they are simply not perceived as maps.6 Even representa-
tions of the earth itself are frequently not maps—whatever we take a map to
be—, but some different kind of visual artifact, subject to regimes of legibility
foreign to the map; it suffices to think of photographs of the planet, like the
one first taken by Soviet cosmonaut Yuri Gagarin, or satellite images. But take a
6 J. H. Andrews famously compiled in a journal article 321 “definitions” of maps that have been
attempted since the mid-seventeenth century up to the 1980s. The general trend is the same
emphasis on flatness and graphics, but there is also an underlying assumption that the rep-
resentation must be “to scale,” and, most importantly, the external referent is tacitly or ex-
plicitly always taken to be the earth (Andrews 1986). In the general preface to the History
of Cartography series, J. B. Harley and David Woodward fittingly downplay the importance
of scale, defining maps as “graphic representations that facilitate a spatial understand-
ing of things, concepts, conditions, processes or events in the human world” (Harley and
Woodward 1987, xvi). Although I fully endorse the view that the moon, like any other “natu-
ral” object, is truly part of “the human world,” this conceptualization of a map is so capacious
that it does not seem to go a long way to shedding more light on the question of what makes
a moon image a map.
12 Haddad
satellite image and superimpose a line drawing to reinforce edges and bound-
aries, a few place names, arrows, dots, a grid: the whole thing starts to resemble
a map, at least to a community whose members share by learning, culture, and
social practice some tacit assumptions about what a map is, without the need
for any explicit definition.
So the question we should pose seems to become, “What does it take for an
image of the moon to become a map for a certain group of viewers?” To adopt
Christian Jacob’s apt formulation, the problem is to investigate the “threshold
of cartographical perception” after which a given flat representation of the
moon starts to be perceived as a map by those who have contact with it.7 The
answer cannot lie simply on the mapmaker’s intentions: “What is a map,”
writes Matthew Edney, “is not defined by the maker but by the user, and by
the context of use.” In other words, it is not enough that the maker wants her
creation to be perceived as a map, or even explicitly calls it a map. It is also
not enough that the artifact itself possesses “map-like features,” so to speak,
for as Edney adds, “ ‘mapness’ is not inherent to an image, but is determined
by the reader” (Edney 2007, 95).8 However, one must be careful in interpreting
this last statement, lest we be content with the impression that, in the end, it
is up to the reader to arbitrarily decide what she will count as maps and what
she will not. This would amount to a simple shift of focus from the suppos-
edly absolute power of a mapmaker’s intentions, perfectly encapsulated in the
formal characteristics of her products, to individual readers’ arbitrary deci-
sions. Of course, as much as there are no all-powerful makers and no perfectly
autonomous images, readers do not simply decide whether they want to call
something a map.
Perhaps it would be more productive to consider that the “threshold of
cartographical perception” depends on the relation between the viewer and
the representation itself, a relation that must take into account the maker’s
intentions and the graphic content of the artifact, as well as on the context
of perception. This context, in its turn, is mediated by the whole ecosystem
of visual representations—its specific visual culture—amidst which makers,
viewers, and graphic artifacts are located. Representing and viewing are
grounded in s ocial practices that leave no space for solipsism from any party.
7 Jacob only employs the exact words “threshold of cartographical perception” in a caption
to Figure 2 that accompanies his aforementioned essay, “What is a Map?,” while in the main
text he develops the idea more fully: “A map can be identified, up to a certain threshold of
perception, on the basis of the form of the document and its general graphic organization,
including the distribution of its inscriptions over the surface of the map and the effects of
relief shading” (Jacob 2006, 16).
8 Notice that the terms “user,” “viewer,” and “reader” are being employed interchangeably.
Maps of the Moon 13
“A map is defined perhaps less by formal traits than by the particular conditions
of its production and reception,” writes Jacob (2006, 21). In this way, the thresh-
old emerges from a “semiotic web” that involves actors, objects (including their
“formal traits”), and practices of making and seeing. Indexicality, i.e., the ca-
pacity of signs to point to other things, is enacted by this web, and is what
triggers cartographic perception.9 In a way, then, the map is a speech act that,
just like a natural-language utterance, is as much declarative or propositional
as performative (see Austin 1962).10 This means that it not only “says” some-
thing, but it “does” something too, such as interfering in the conditions of
its own reception: in our case, it would amount to triggering cartographical
perception. As with any speech act, there are no previous guarantees that it
will perform what was intended (if something was intended at all), instead
of something else, as well as no assurance that the results will not change
over time.
To make things more palpable, let us consider one of Galileo Galilei’s
engravings of the moon as seen through a telescope, part of a group of four
different lunar representations included in his epochal 1610 book, Sidereus
Nuncius (Figure 1). Presented in virtually every work on the history of sele-
nography as the veritable cornerstone of the whole field, Galileo’s images are
nevertheless usually not classed as moon maps, but as “pictures,” perhaps
“portraits.” In this, Galileo’s images do not differ much from artistic depic-
tions of the moon such as one can see in Adam Elsheimer’s oil-on-copper
painting Flight into Egypt, from about 1609 (Howard and Longair 2011), and
Ludovico Cardi, called Cigoli’s 1612 fresco in the dome of a chapel in the
Roman basilica of S. Maria Maggiore, depicting the Virgin with a thoroughly
Galilean moon beneath her feet (Ostrow 1996).11 What they do seem to share is
mimesis—the illusion of vanishing mediation—as the governing principle of
representation.
9 It is interesting to compare this to what science studies scholars John Law and Solveig
Joks say about reality itself: “Since reals are embedded and enacted in webs of practices,
realities cannot be willed into being: there is no comfort here for ‘alternative facts’” (Law
and Joks 2018, 425). These “webs of practices” that largely determine what will count as a
“fact” for a given social collectivity are weaved through actors’ necessarily shared histori-
cal, cultural, and material experiences. What I am suggesting is that exactly the same goes
for what counts as a “map.”
10 For maps as specific devices, see Lois (2018b).
11 Erwin Panofsky highlights that Galileo and Cigoli were united in “a life-long and truly
reciprocal friendship” (Panofsky 1954, 3).
14 Haddad
FIGURE 1 One of the four different copper engravings of the moon “as seen” through the
telescope, published by Galileo in his 1610 Sidereus Nuncius (folio 9v). Notice the
large crater on the lower middle region, right between light and darkness: Galileo
purposefully exaggerated its size and depth to highlight the ruggedness of the
lunar surface.
SOURCE: LIBRARY OF CONGRESS
But let us now turn our gaze to Figures 2 and 3. Even before learning what they
represent, how they were made, or what their makers’ intentions were, one
may legitimately wonder: can these images be anything other than maps? The
cartographical threshold seems to have been crossed, even if one does not have
the slightest idea what the external referent is. Just from looking at the images
one would be hard pressed to tell they refer to patches of the moon’s surface.
Even a trained viewer, who is able to recognize that the moon is the images’
external referent, might have difficulty telling exactly what portion of the sur-
face is being represented. The images may be taken to be signifiers without a
signified: their referent may be anything from a patch of the earth itself to an
Maps of the Moon 15
FIGURE 2 Section V of Walter Goodacre’s 1910 lunar map in 25 sections. If assembled, they
would result in a moon 1.5 meters wide. Like many other lunar mapmakers,
Goodacre was an “amateur” astronomer, working from his own telescopic obser-
vations. He also used photographs to measure some features’ coordinates, but the
map was entirely hand-drawn. Topography is represented with simple line forms,
and the map does not attempt to reproduce the so-called “albedo,” i.e., variations
in brilliance that are not due to relief alone.
COURTESY UNIVERSITY COLLEGE LONDON FACULTY OF MATHEMATICAL &
PHYSICAL SCIENCES
imaginary place—but they are still identifiable as some kind of map. Family
resemblance seems to be the key factor at play here: the use of line drawing, an
underlying grid, lettering, hachuring, level curves, the page layout itself (in the
case of Figure 3), all point to other artifacts that viewers are collectively used
16 Haddad
FIGURE 3 Map from NASA’s Lunar Astronautical Chart (LAC) Series, published by the
U.S. Air Force’s Chart and Information Center between 1962–1967, in the
framework of the ongoing Apollo Program.
SOURCE: LUNAR AND PLANETARY INSTITUTE
12 As before, “to point” should be understood semiotically: these signs are not simply part of
propositions (like “the distance from point A to point B is such”), but are performative—
they produce an effect that is not reducible to their descriptive content (Austin 1962).
Maps of the Moon 17
13 Christian Jacob has in passing suggested a distinction that seems to have gone unnoticed,
but merits being pursued further: “One should probably introduce a distinction between
views and maps, the former being an attempt to give a vision of the moon as seen through
the telescope, and through various pictorial means, such as perspective and shading ef-
fects, while the map is the graphic transformation of vision into a schematic drawing,
with semiological conventions” (Jacob 2002, 166).
14 I will leave it open to the reader’s consideration whether these images could be profitably
treated as “cartifacts” (Post 2001; Smits 2009).
18 Haddad
4a 4b
4c 4d
FIGURE 4 Four depictions of the moon that appeared in books published by Jesuit
astronomers in the two decades following Galileo’s first observations. They were
always used to make the point, developed in the texts, that the telescope had
revealed the surface relief.
As outlined in the introduction, the aim in this part is to explore in greater de-
tail the origins of the “naturalistic tradition” of depicting the moon, which are
inseparable from the origin of telescopic observational practices themselves.
Galileo Galilei will be the focus of attention, with our gaze once again turning
to Figure 1. After this discussion, I will propose an experiment in assembling
a visual series of naturalistic moons. The aim is to allow for some measure of
visual discourse too, restraining the textual action.
15 Galilean scholarship is too vast to be cited here, let alone reviewed. Works on his depic-
tions of the moon, and, more generally, his visual practices of representation of heavenly
phenomena also abound, but a few essential readings would be Panofsky (1954), Righini
(1975), Gingerich (1975), Whitaker (1978), Cohen (1982), Edgerton (1984), Winkler and Van
Helden (1992), Reeves (1997), Bredekamp (2000; 2007), and Jacob (2011).
Maps of the Moon 21
16 Contrary to a view that is held even in scholarly circles (e.g., Bredekamp 2000, 425),
perfect smoothness was not the only acceptable idea about the moon with currency in
Galileo’s time: “These [ideas] included [the moon] being (a) a mirror, reflecting the ter-
restrial oceans and continents; (b) a polished, translucent crystalline sphere; (c) a body
of condensed fire, etc.; and (d) a terrestrial type of spherical body with seas, mountains,
valleys, plains, etc.” (Whitaker 1989, 122). In fact, Galileo had a particular interest in pro-
moting a version of this last view (d), which, although not really espoused by a great many
astronomers, was nevertheless well known to them.
22 Haddad
probable to Father Clavius that it is not that the surface is uneven, but that
the lunar body is not uniformly dense, having denser parts and more rarefied
parts” (Favaro 1929–1939, vol. 11, 87–88 and 92–93). In other words, apart from
the aging Clavius, all the others see the same thing as Galileo.
Galileo’s moon drawings show no hint of concern with identifying features
on the image itself, much less of a full-fledged toponymy. His is a relieved
moon, not as in topographical maps, of course, but nevertheless definitely not
smooth. Galileo has no interest whatsoever in ascribing names to the surface
features he represents, because his interest lies elsewhere, on the cosmological
argument. This is not to say that he was not aware of the power that naming
things after powerful people has in the court society he lived in. On the con-
trary, with a view to obtaining the patronage from the Medici, he was quick in
calling the satellites of Jupiter “Medicean stars.” In fact, he had already dedi-
cated the Sidereus Nuncius to Cosimo II, patriarch of the Florentine family.
Instead of giving names of important patrons to features on a moon whose
possible heavenly perfection he was striving to disprove, the “new stars” he
discovered orbiting Jupiter seemed more fitting for baptism (see Biagioli 1993).
17 Lois in turn took inspiration from Aby Warburg’s general treatment of images (not only
cartographic ones) through coupling and decoupling, approximation and distancing.
This is why I feel justified in proposing to readers a visual series of objects of whose
“mapness” I am confessedly uncertain, but which are, in any case, images.
Maps of the Moon 23
5a 5b
5c 5d
The naturalistic tradition that we have just considered betrays a double ges-
ture: learning to put/see on paper what was seen on the telescope. It starts
with eyes turned upward, and ends with eyes turned downward. In this part
I will consider the exact opposite: how some people decided to learn how to
see on the telescope what was seen on paper, inverting the direction of the
gaze—first the “map,” then the “terrain.”
the moon with a telescope about the same time, and on February 6, 1610,
he wrote something to Harriot that says much of their shared perceptions
and references: “[the image] looks like unto the description of coasts, in the
Dutch books of voyages” (quoted in Alexander 1998, 351). In fact, writes Amir
Alexander, “[w]hatever [Harriot’s] precise beliefs [about the physical nature of
the moon], it is clear that [he] mapped the face of the moon as if he were chart-
ing oceans and continents,” adding that Harriot “was outlining the coastlines
of the moon” (Alexander 1998, 361–362, emphasis in the original).
Although Harriot never published his observations and drawings of the
moon, he epitomizes a specific sensibility that others would independently
develop in the next few decades, at odds with the tradition inaugurated by
Galileo’s published images and arguments. We can say that a moon will appear
by cartographers alongside a moon by (natural) philosophers or astronomers.
The latter will frequently opt to represent the lunar disk on the waxing or wan-
ing phases, during which the oblique illumination from the sun enhances the
perception of ruggedness. When they take part on cosmological arguments,
even those images that clearly deviate from naturalistic conventions usually
depict the moon on an intermediary phase. Such is the case with the lunar
images in Jesuit astronomers’ books we discussed before (Figures 4a–d). Like
Harriot’s, cartographers’ renderings of the moon, on the other hand, are gen-
erally of the full body, when perpendicular solar illumination blurs the relief,
enhances the large divisions between light and dark, and fills the surface with
bright spots.
3.2 Non Sufficit Orbis: Claiming the Moon for a King, or a Politics of
Lunar Cartography
In 1644, Michael Florent van Langren, cosmographer and mathematician to
the king of Spain in Flanders, published at his own expense a scant booklet of
13 pages, under the title La Verdadera Longitud por Mar y Tierra: Demostrada
y Dedicada a su Majestad Catholica Philippo IV. On the very first line he an-
nounces that the purpose of the work is to inform His Majesty of some grave
matters pertaining to the problem of establishing longitudes, and redress a
great injustice. After stating that his father and grandfather had made “a pro-
fession of the arts, such as astronomy and geography,” and that the former had
already held the position of royal cosmographer for 26 years in the Flemish
States, Van Langren comes to his chief purpose: to make it known to the
monarch that, “having exercised himself on those arts and discovered things
hitherto unknown,” he had “found something considerable in the matter”
of establishing the true longitude at sea and land (Van Langren 1644, 3). He
claimed nothing less than having found a complete solution to the problem
Maps of the Moon 27
of establishing the longitude of any site on the planet, including a ship sailing
the oceans.
Born in Amsterdam in 1598, Van Langren had learned mapmaking from his
father, Arnold Florent van Langren, who was himself the son of another suc-
cessful cartographer and globe maker. The family was originally from Utrecht
and Amsterdam, but as Roman Catholics, they moved to Belgium around 1600.
Arnold van Langren quickly became archducal “spherographer,” in keeping
with the tradition of mapmaking privileges the family already enjoyed in the
Netherlands, more than once challenged by Jodocus Hondius. In 1628, Arnold
van Langren would receive the task from Balthasar Moretus of preparing a re-
vised edition of Ortelius’s Theatrum Orbis Terrarum, certainly bringing wider
recognition to his already profitable globe and map business (Keuning 1956;
Van der Krogt 1995).
In the 1644 text, Van Langren claimed that in 1621 he had already unraveled
that “great secret” of finding longitude, and around 1625 had told about it to
the archduchess Isabel Clara Eugenia, daughter of Philip II and governor of
the Spanish Netherlands in the name of her grandnephew Philip IV. From an
early age Van Langren had been a client of Isabel’s inner circle of patronage.
Throughout the 1620s and 1630s, the archduchess would commission impor-
tant undertakings from father and son, such as maps of the new canals that fur-
rowed Flanders, and ambitious projects for a port at Mardyck, near Dunkirk,
to house the Spanish fleets increasingly harassed by the Dutch on the North
Sea. To the handsome income Michael van Langren secured with the maps,
engineering projects, and associated privileges, was added royal favor, start-
ing in 1633, amounting to an annual pension of almost five thousand florins
(Montucla 1802, 506).
La Verdadera Longitud offers a description of previous, and, we are told,
unsuccessful attempts to uncover the secret of longitude and, no less im-
portant, claim the prize of six thousand ducats that Philip III had promised
back in 1598 to whomever got it right. Van Langren wrote that all the past
proposals were unreliable, giving, as an example, the 12 different values they
gave to the longitude of Rome in relation to the meridian of Toledo. Only Van
Langren’s own method could bring order to this chaos, according to his claim,
and the moon played the main role in his approach. Zealously, he does not
enter into details; instead, the text ends with an encrypted paragraph where
the method is supposedly presented, along with a vow to disclose the cipher
if the king considers that Van Langren deserves the prize. He ends the book
asserting that eternal glory will befall the monarch in whose honor, and under
whose protection such a momentous achievement is attained (Van Langren
1644, 10–12).
28 Haddad
that Van Langren claimed he was able make with great precision, valid for
some set meridian on earth. The difference between measured and predicted
values would finally translate into the difference in longitude between the lo-
cation where the observations took place and the meridian of reference.
This method was strictly impracticable. The required measurements, es-
pecially of the times of illumination or darkening of surface features, sim-
ply could not be made because the terminator is far from sharp, even with a
telescope. The full-moon measurements amounted to the well-known lunar
distance method, but they were impossible to execute at that time aboard a
ship. And, in any case, the required lunar tables would not be available for an-
other hundred years, and we have no reason to believe Van Langren was able
to calculate them. Be that as it may, the proposal obviously asked for a map
showing details of the lunar face, and, on top of that, a practical system for
identifying such details on the map itself and on the tables—a toponymy, that
is. It was for this map and the associated toponymy that he had great designs
and expectations.
Although Van Langren left Madrid unable to secure the recognition he
sought for his method, he got Philip IV interested in the lunar map required
by the proposal. Indeed, in a letter from May 1633, the king addressed the arch-
duchess in the following terms:
The “luminaries” or “stars” the king is mentioning are the moon’s surface
features that Van Langren wanted to employ in his longitude determination
method (either to measure their angular separation from stars or the times
when they entered or left darkness). The king’s words left no doubt as to the
importance Van Langren ascribed to the naming of these lunar places, which
were to be the “Austrian Philipian luminaries,” after all (“Austrian” being an
overt reference to the house of Habsburg).
30 Haddad
Thus, even though the Council did not examine Van Langren’s proposal
(or, what is more probable, did not find it deserving of the prize, as it ultimately
could not solve the longitude problem), Van Langren would not give up on his
pretensions to the prize, since the king himself seemed to be on his side. By
the time he published La Verdadera Longitud, he was engaged in feverish cor-
respondence with Wendelin and Puteanus about the map, and, at the same
time, was requesting privileges from the Privy Council in Brussels. He feared
others might be on the way to publishing a lunar map with place names, which
would strip him of all priority. More catastrophically, a map from another au-
thor could mean that Philip might end up not being glorified on the moon.
18 The map is extant in three different engraving states. There is also a hand drawn version
that Van Langren presented to the Privy Council, a later edition from 1670, and a forgery
(Whitaker 1999, 37–42).
Maps of the Moon 31
FIGURE 7 Van Langren’s 1645 map Plenilunii / Lumina Austriaca Philippica, engraved by
himself, is the first published chart of the moon including a very detailed
nomenclature. In the lengthy inscription, Van Langren narrates the process
that culminated in the map, announces he intends to publish a complete lunar
atlas, and claims priority and exclusive privileges for himself, appealing to King
Philip IV’s protection.
SOURCE: BIBLIOTHÈQUE NATIONALE DE FRANCE (Département Cartes et
plans, GE D-17925)
32 Haddad
Carlos, and Queen Anne of Austria. Major secretaries find their place: Haro,
Aytona, Mazarin, Arundel. There is no lack of Galileo, Copernicus, Tycho
Brahe, and Van Langren himself, as well as his friends De La Faille, Wendelin
or Puteanus. In addition, the moon of Van Langren accommodates moral vir-
tues: Land of Temperance, Wisdom, Dignity, Work. Van Langren offers Philip IV
much more than a purported instrument for the practical determination of
longitudes: he offers, on the mirror of the moon, the image of royal power
over a world beyond this world (Bouza 2008). It was not gratuitous, after all,
that Philip’s royal grandfather on occasion employed the motto Non sufficit
orbis—the world is not enough—, whereas Philip IV himself was known as the
“planet-king” (Kagan 2005; Pereda and Marías 2002).
The story of how Van Langren came up with the hundreds of names he gave
to the moon places shows the clear understanding he had of maps as artifacts
with elevated symbolic value as well as their central role in claims of territorial
sovereignty over any place—even the moon’s surface.19 Moreover, the story
highlights the importance of cartographic priority to buttress both mapmak-
ers’ leverage on the symbolic value of their products and their patrons’ am-
bitions of territorial control. For 15 years or more before publishing the map,
Van Langren had been in close connection with Wendelin and Puteanus, the
first supporters of his longitude method. Now, in the early months of 1645,
the recurring theme of their correspondence is the best name to ascribe to
each lunar feature. In particular Puteanus seems to consider the enterprise as
much his as Van Langren’s, suggesting more and more place names in each
letter he sends, to the general agreement of Van Langren. The humanist of
Louvain is thrilled with the prospect of baptizing the whole face of the moon,
fully realizing the symbolic power that comes with the ability to name places
on a map—particularly when the places to be named lay on unclaimed terri-
tory, like the moon’s surface. Van Langren provides Puteanus with drawings
that show new details every time, creating the very space to be named, and
Puteanus reacts with considerations of importance and dignity and decorum
in order to suggest the most appropriate names for each place. His vision be-
trays a metageography that places higher value on centers than on margins,
on large expanses than on limited areas, besides a thoroughly gendered and
socially stratified view of human affairs. For several months after the map’s
publication, Puteanus’s letters still revolve around the map, only that this
19 See Pineda de Ávila (2017, 154–167) and Montgomery (1999, 157–168) for thorough anal-
yses of Van Langren’s naming project and the cultural resonances of his nomenclature
scheme.
Maps of the Moon 33
time the subject is not who is on the map, but who will receive a copy of it,
courtesy of Puteanus. Thus, we get to know that he sent copies to Constantijn
Huygens, Isaac Vossius, Cassiano dal Pozzo, and perhaps even Pope Innocent X
(see Bosmans 1903 for a selection of the correspondence).
As Scott Montgomery points out, it is the dense “semiotic environment” of
Van Langren’s moon, including the toponymy, which invites viewers to call
the engraving a map, or better, to see it as a map. Van Langren’s image “is car-
tographic because of its dense textuality, because it is surrounded, framed,
nested, and invaded by writing in exactly the same way as were mapped regions
of the Earth” (Montgomery 1999, 157). Thus, the product extracts its legibility
as a map, its “mapness,” from the hybridization of text and image. Moreover,
the visual part itself does not function as “an ‘observation,’ an actual visual
portrait of the lunar surface” (ibidem). Here, Montgomery is implying that the
intended function of the artifact adds to its identification or intelligibility as a
map: “[Van Langren’s] images were specifically intended to solve the problem
of longitude. They are true maps, stylized plots of features across a flat plane,
unburdened by the demands of naturalism. They are cartographic abstractions
whose ‘science’ exists in the accuracy of placement and size of individual fea-
tures, not in their depiction” (ibidem). Of course, as I have argued, being an in-
strument for determining longitudes is second to the map’s symbolic function
as a royal gift—and this only places it even more firmly within contemporary
cartographic culture.
The lengthy Latin inscription beneath the engraving serves the function
of “surrounding” or “framing” the image with something that points to the
world of maps, even if one cannot or does not read it, but just glances at the
heavy textual block. If we pay attention to the words, however, yet another
layer of cartographic texture is revealed. At the outset, Van Langren claims his
is a geographical undertaking: “The lunar globe is the most familiar celestial
body, however the most unknown geographically (…) [The king] allowed me to
name this selenographical description, or lunar geography, as Lumina Austriaca
Philippica.”20 Thus, Van Langren claims he is not doing anything different from
what geographers do when they describe the globe of the earth. He goes on to
talk about islands and mountains, and the naming scheme. Importantly, Van
Langren reveals something telling:
20 This and the subsequent quotations come from the Latin inscription under the map.
34 Haddad
indicate on these images all the details of the lunar surface, such as the
islands and the mountain summits. Often distant from the continents,
these features appear instantaneously while the moon is waning and dis-
appear suddenly when it is waxing. They offer the best way for finding
longitudes, and can be employed on almost any day.
Now we can appreciate the true breadth of Van Langren’s cartographic proj-
ect: he wanted to produce a veritable atlas of the moon, the published broad-
sheet being just a way to ascertain his priority in the attribution of names and,
evidently, a gift he expected the king to reciprocate by offering support for the
larger undertaking.
Van Langren was able to secure all the privileges he required from the Privy
Council in Brussels. The inscription on the map ends with a clear threat: “By
royal decree, all are forbidden to make any changes to the names on this figure,
under penalty of indignity.” No one paid attention to the prohibition, and all
places on the moon were to be baptized anew not once, but twice over the next
few years.
4 Time Concreted
The first maps of the moon that are specifically, unmistakably of the moon
are the ones published by Johannes Hevelius in 1647. What is special about
them is not that they are of the moon but the fact that they face the problem
of time head-on, grabbing time and putting it on paper. The impermanence of
the face of the moon is not swept aside, but, quite to the contrary, it is rendered
concretely on map space itself. After analyzing the “Hevelian way,” I discuss at
some length an interesting sub-genre of lunar cartography, which is the eclipse
map. Not only Hevelius’s eclipse maps, but also Cassini’s are discussed and
shown to be functional, instrumental maps. Finally, I suggest viewing the fig-
ure who is invariably presented as Hevelius’s selenographic nemesis, the Jesuit
Giovanni Battista Riccioli, as a Hevelian at heart.
was certainly not a problem for this wealthy brewer and soon-to-be city mag-
istrate in his native Gdansk. Born there in 1611, Hevelius had spent the early
1630s studying and traveling in the Netherlands, England, and France (where
he made the acquaintance of Gassendi). After returning to his hometown,
Hevelius decided to build a private observatory on the roof of his own house.21
Perhaps this self-reliance and the fact that astronomy was always circum-
scribed to Hevelius’s domestic space help us understand why, unlike so many
books of the time, Selenographia is not dedicated to anybody: Hevelius is at
once the author, financial backer, protagonist, and guarantor of the work. Even
Galileo, who adorns the allegorical frontispiece beside the Arab astronomer
Ibn al-Haytham (Alhazen), symbolizing the importance of the senses for as-
tronomy, is disparaged by Hevelius. The latter wonders that what he considers
to be the appallingly low quality of the moon drawings in the Sidereus Nuncius
can only be explained if Galileo was either a careless observer, was unskilled
in draftsmanship, or had a very bad telescope (Hevelius 1647, 205). In fact, po-
sitioning himself as more careful and attentive to detail than Galileo is part of
Hevelius’s bid for his readers’ trust.
Selenographia is at the same time a monument to observational astronomy
and to the power of visual representation. It has 111 full-page figures, includ-
ing three foldout maps, plus two-dozen illustrations embedded in the printed
text, all of them copperplate engravings. With the exception of a handful,
every image in the book was drawn and engraved by Hevelius himself, and
he never loses an opportunity to remind the reader of this, from the “Author
sculpsit” almost invariably inscribed on a corner of the illustrations to textual
reiterations of his ultimate responsibility for the images and everything else
in the book. The index includes precise instructions regarding the placement
of the full-page figures, and Hevelius addresses bookbinders in order to pro-
vide details on how they must handle these sheets (Hevelius 1647, last page of
index).
The importance of the printed image for Hevelius’s endeavor in Seleno
graphia and, far more importantly, to a far-reaching reconfiguration of early-
modern astronomy as a whole was forcefully demonstrated by Mary G. Winkler
and Albert van Helden. Against a received view of Hevelius as a dilettante, al-
beit talented astronomer who contributed nothing original to the field, Winkler
and van Helden argue that he was responsible for nothing less than the estab-
lishment of a “visual language” that was bound to be almost immediately taken
21 Scholarship on Hevelius’s life and work (of which Selenographia is but his first produc-
tion) has been steadily growing over the last few years. I would recommend, as a most
up-to-date starting point, the collection edited by Kremer and Włodarczyk (2013).
36 Haddad
[i]n the second half of the seventeenth century pictures of heavenly phe-
nomena observed through the telescope became common, and these pic-
tures spoke for themselves. In fact, they sometimes contained information
that was not explained until much later. (…) Hevelius’s authority flowed
from his copious use of visual evidence whose reliability he was able to
impress upon the reader. Yet, by the end of the century Selenographia
was already obsolete. As others discovered that some of his observations
were in error, the influence of Hevelius’s work in telescopic astronomy
waned, and by the time of his death it had been superseded. His method
of visual communication had, however, by then become an accepted part
of astronomy and science in general. Indeed, it had become so common
that this achievement of Hevelius had become invisible.
WINKLER AND VAN HELDEN 1993, 116
Contrary to what one might be tempted to believe from the remarkable suc-
cess of the Sidereus Nuncius, up to the mid-seventeenth century, astronomy
had almost no reliance on depicting celestial phenomena. Pictures, here nar-
rowly understood as naturalistic renderings of observation, played close to no
role in the communication of astronomical discoveries, in arguments in favor
of their reality, or in reasoning about phenomena (Winkler and Van Helden
1992, note 2 and passim). Indeed, with the exception of the five moon illus-
trations in the Sidereus Nuncius, plus a few images of sunspots on the solar
disk from his important 1612 work on the subject, even Galileo never again em-
ployed pictures (in that specific sense), either in his published works or in his
notebooks. Moreover, for Galileo these pictures of the moon and sun served
only to make points that were developed in the text; in other words, they did
not stand by themselves in any meaningful way. Not that astronomers did not
resort to visual tools or visual reasoning, of course: on the contrary, astronomi-
cal books continued to carry plenty of images, as they had always done. Those
images, though, were not naturalistic depictions, but kept with the age-old tra-
dition of astronomical diagrams, i.e., schematic representations of geometric
configurations, spatial relations or motions, and not the visual appearance of
celestial objects.
We are to believe that Hevelius profoundly changed the way in which astro-
nomical practice and communication came to rely on images, inaugurating a
Maps of the Moon 37
new visual language. Selenographia is a treatise on the moon and its motions
as much as a treatise on how to observe and represent its face. It may be read—
or gazed at—as a visual narrative that strives to create several kinds of reality
effects. Like any other astronomical book of the time, it has scores of diagrams
sketching the relative positions of objects and the observer, angles of illumina-
tion, the behavior of light rays, and spatial relations in general. But there is
something else as well: as Winkler and van Helden argue, Hevelius carefully
sets a credible scene, which has himself working at the observatory. His obser-
vational procedures and equipment are thoroughly described in words as well
as depicted through images. Besides writing at length about the details of his
practice, discussing the best ways to manufacture a telescope, debating other
astronomers’ choices, he uses a novel (in astronomical books, at least) kind
of picture as a powerful conveyor of meaning. These pictures painstakingly
represent details of lens-grinding machinery, telescope parts, dark rooms, and
so forth, and they stand on an equal footing with the text. A kind of climax is
reached in a picture representing Hevelius himself in the very act of observing
the skies through a telescope.
All this textual and visual technology has the effect of recruiting the reader
as a witness, a “virtual witness,” to Hevelius’s work, which thus merits trust
because it hides nothing. It is as if Hevelius were saying, “Look at me look-
ing at the skies,” immediately to add, “And look at what I have seen.” Having
taken the reader with him into the observatory, having described and depicted
what happens there, Hevelius can now show what he discovered through the
telescope. Trust in Hevelius’s representations increases as the reader is re-
minded that Hevelius was not just the telescopic observer, but also draftsman
and engraver, as I have already mentioned. With so many semiotic indices
pointing to Hevelius’s trustworthiness, as well as the text’s scathing criticism
of previous attempts to represent the moon, the reader is apparently ready to
look at any of the multiple lunar images in Selenographia, let her eyes wander
across the surface, so impossibly near, clear, and palpable, and believe Hevelius
has rendered the moon “as it is.”
As it is? Christian Jacob eloquently argues that this is not the case: “The sel-
enographer draws not the image as seen through the telescope, but a mental
image, a series of details that he must put as fast as possible in their places on
the complete image,” he writes. The gap between eye and hand is impossible
to fill completely: “A drawing, painting, or engraving do not restitute whatever
was not already inscribed in one’s memory (…) Between observation and map
lies a space of loss, displacement, and oblivion” (Jacob 2011, 623). Memory and
indecision about what has just been seen thus appear as the key elements gov-
erning the very bodily work of the selenographer, in a manner rather unknown
38 Haddad
[a]t the very point of time when we sketch the figure and start a picture,
we find out quickly that most, if not all, escapes our memory. It is there-
fore necessary that every little point is observed ten times or more before
the proper place of some spot, its figure and its form, can truly correctly
and accurately be reproduced on the paper.
HEVELIUS 1647, 209
FIGURE 8 Two successive views of the crescent moon included by Hevelius in his
Selenographia (the left one between pages 416 and 417; the right one between
pages 430 and 431). The inscriptions give information on the precise hour and dates
of the observations (which were in fact not successive) and the celestial coordinates
of the moon. However, they should not be taken to represent truly “instantaneous”
views, for Hevelius had to go back to the telescope many times before he was able to
finish each one of the 40 images like these in the book. Near the right-hand limb it
is clearly possible to notice a slight change in the positioning of the surface f eatures,
resulting from the moon’s libratory motion during the intervening months.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 8932 q, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-238)
the fact that [the reader] is looking at images (re-)designed for a printed book”
(Müller 2010, 357).
Take the portraits of the moon in different phases. Selenographia includes
no less than 40 illustrations of this kind, interspersed among almost 200 pages
of text. Each picture differs from the previous one through the addition of a
tiny new slip of illuminated surface or the subtraction of what has fallen into
obscurity, as the moon wanes and waxes every month. The accompanying text
offers a lengthy description of the new formations revealed, the changes in
aspect of those that were already visible due to varying angles of illumination,
and the conditions surrounding the observation. The whole sequence unfolds
in time as a story in words and images, with an unequivocal narrative quality.
But then, if we inspect any one of these phase portraits (Figure 8), there is
something uncanny about them. As happened in Galileo’s case, these portraits
are at once seemingly familiar, indeed they look like naturalistic representa-
tions of something, and yet strangely unfamiliar, when, after looking around,
40 Haddad
one fails to recognize anything that really looks like them. It is impossible to
achieve a sense of scale, for the images stand alone, without any standard of
comparison. Granted, each phase portrait is invaded by textual signs that point
to the external referent. All of them have a title such as, for instance, “This is
the moon as observed from Gdansk on this specific date, its celestial coordi-
nates being such and such.” But raise your eyes to the moon on the same phase,
and it simply does not look that way, even if magnified through a telescope.
Indeed, telescopes and observational practices vary widely in the seventeenth
century, and, just as with any other scientific instrument, one has to learn how
to “see” any desired effect (Van Helden 1994).
But even for observers sharing the same observational standards, the gap
between Hevelius’s pictures and any instantaneous image will remain irre-
deemably open. The images are in fact composites of observations performed
across different days, one phase almost invading the other, so to speak, in order
for Hevelius to resolve features that were possibly hard to observe, retouch,
or ascertain shapes and sizes of whatever he chose to draw. To this we should
add that the orientation of the lunar disk in relation to a viewer’s local horizon
is continuously changing, besides being dependent on the observer’s location
on earth. Indeed, if one looks at the moon when it is rising, say, and mentally
draws a “horizontal” line across the disk, a few hours later the same line will
be “inclined;” and if the moon is observed at the same time from two differ-
ent latitudes, one view will have to be rotated in order to perfectly coincide
with the other. This is why the waxing moon looks like a ‘D’ on the northern
hemisphere, and a ‘C’ on the southern. The result is that Hevelius’s portraits of
lunar phases can only “correspond” to the optical sensory experience of gazing
at the moon, even with the aid of a telescope, if they are manipulated, rotated,
and forced to fit the visual appearance. For naked-eye and telescopic observ-
ers alike, the endless details are nothing short of a new reality, a new visibility
that is being imposed on the moon. The images are “both something less and
something more than real space” (Jacob 2006, 14)—not unlike maps, even if
they arguably do not cross the cartographic threshold.
So we are dealing at once with the persistence of memory (the act of passing
from telescope to paper), the creation of a narrative (the sequence of repre-
sented phases), and a compositional act (adding up series of observations to
produce a single image). Besides that, we have to keep in mind that Hevelius
tries to portray something that is never “there,” as his referent is permanently
moving and changing. All of this indicates the centrality of time in Hevelius’s
endeavor: the time that is always threatening memory, the time along which
the visual narrative unfolds, the scattering over time of the many partial views
that add up to one composed picture, the impermanence of the moon itself.
Maps of the Moon 41
The central question in Hevelius’s work seems to be, more than naturalistic
representation, nothing less than putting time under control: he strives to find
ways to depict realities that are ever mutating, to impose a synchronic order to
asynchronous processes.
Nowhere more than in the full-moon maps that come with Selenographia
is this quest more apparent, and in important ways they are maps precisely
because of the way Hevelius finds to represent time in them.
FIGURE 9 The first image of the full moon in Selenographia (between pages 220 and 221),
already showing the double rim, i.e., Hevelius’s solution to the problem of how to
represent the changing face of the moon resulting from libration. Topographical
features are subdued in order that variations in total brilliance (albedo) may be
highlighted.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 8932 q,
DOI 10.3931/e-rara-238)
globe from two different angles at once: there is more information than may
be squeezed onto a flat disk. At any given instant, half of the surface area of the
lunar body is observable—to be thorough, not exactly half of the moon’s sur-
face is visible to us at any single instant, because the moon is not at an infinite
Maps of the Moon 43
distance from the earth; but this is negligible. As weeks and months pass by,
though, some observable features gradually fall out of sight, as they seem to
approach the edge of the disk and then vanish, whereas others become visible
at the diametrically opposite region. The two superimposed disks are the way
Hevelius found to represent the extreme possible views: one shows the maxi-
mum “southeast” portion of the moon that can possibly be viewed, with the
“northwest” crescent region out of sight, and the other disk shows the opposite
extreme. Most of the time, an observer will not see either one of the disks,
but some intermediary situation. The lunar features located on the crescent-
shaped wedges vary in their visibility.
The phenomenon that Hevelius sought to represent by superimposing the
two disks is what is known as the optical libration of the moon.22 It results from
a combination of properties of the moon’s orbital motion around the earth. In
order to understand it in very simplified terms, we must first notice that the
moon’s own axis of rotation is not perpendicular to its orbital plane but in-
clined along a fixed direction in space. As a consequence, an observer on the
earth’s surface will at times be able to see the region around the moon’s north
pole, with the south pole falling out of view, and at other times she will see
the opposite. This results in an apparent “wobbling” oscillation of the “north-
south coordinates” of visible features. Another wobble, this time in longitude,
is related to the fact that the moon’s orbit is not circular, but elliptical, which
causes an observer to see more of the western or eastern regions of the lunar
surface at different times. (There is also a small amount of wobbling that re-
sults from the fact that no one observes the moon from the earth’s center, but
from its surface, causing a parallax shift.) The different kinds of libration add
up in a complicated way, with the consequence that any given instantaneous
visual appearance of the moon will not be repeated when it reaches the same
phase on the next month, as one might intuitively expect, but only after a few
years. In other words, the disk that is visible on, say, this month’s first day of
the full moon is slightly different from next month’s, which is different from
the next, and so forth. The difference lies on the surface features that can or
cannot be observed close to the limb, as well as the placement of the geometric
center of the lunar disk as it appears to one’s vision: the center is not fixed on
any given observable feature, such as a crater or valley.
There is much discussion as to whether Galileo had already identified the
existence and causes of the moon’s librations over time, but undoubtedly it
was Hevelius who brought the matter to the fore, making it a central concern of
23 Van Langren explicitly mentions libration in the inscription on his map, and announces
he has a complete description of the phenomenon, which he claimed would be demon-
strated with the aid of a lunar globe he was supposedly making.
Maps of the Moon 45
FIGURE 10 The same image as before, but now enlarged (foldout between pages 222 and 223)
and framed by putti and scale keys.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 8932 q, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-238)
a large book open, while the other sits on a stool and draws on the book with a
compass; below them there is a scale showing real distances in German miles.
Finally, the putti at the lower right corner are shown making measurements:
one of them observes the moon with a telescope that he holds with one hand,
a graduated staff in the other, and the second one draws in a sketchbook. Both
capture aspects of Hevelius’s own work. Below them one can see another scale,
this time angular, in degrees of the ecliptic. It can almost go without saying
that the corner scenes, with banners, inscriptions, scales, and instruments of
the trade are indices of the sheet’s belonging to what any reader would identify
as the class of objects called maps.
Now, let us remember that another effect of libration is that the geometric
center of the visible face of the moon will keep changing its location in rela-
tion to surface features themselves. The path described by the visual center
is not a simple figure, such as the line-segment joining the two centers of the
46 Haddad
11b
FIGURE 11
Hevelius came up with a
provisional graphical device
to locate the center of the
effectively visible lunar
disk at any moment of the
libration cycle, seen here on
Figure 11a. The device was
placed on the central region
of the map, as shown on the
detail (Figure 11b).
COURTESY
ETH-BIBLIOTHEK
ZÜRICH (Rar 8932 q, DOI
10.3931/e-rara-238)
11a
disks representing the states of maximum libration. Hevelius was able to come
up with an ingenious, albeit provisional, graphical device that allowed observ-
ers to approximately pinpoint, on the image, the location of the center at in-
termediary states of libration—it was provisional because, to Hevelius’s own
admission, the device would stop furnishing the roughly correct position of
the center within observational limits after a few years. He succeeded in this
because he found a way to express the state of libration as a function both of
the moon’s position along its orbit and the earth’s position around the sun.
The graphical device was a diamond-shaped graticule that Hevelius described
in general terms, with great care (Figure 11a), and also placed on the central
region of the double-disk image (Figure 11b). In possession of the values of the
aforementioned moon-earth and earth-sun orbital parameters, the reader only
had to locate them along the oblique axes of the graticule and plot the point
that corresponded to the coordinate pair. This point was the approximate geo-
metric center of the visible disk for the specific moment in time that was en-
capsulated in the orbital configuration itself. From this center the observable
Maps of the Moon 47
position of the limb at that precise same moment could be traced with a com-
pass (Włodarczyk 2011).
Notice then how Hevelius was offering his readers what looks like a map-
instrument, even more than a map-image. Of course it could not be used to go
anywhere, to place anything, but it could still solve, graphically, a specific kind
of problem. Hevelius created a cartographical object that could not only be
rotated to “match” visible reality (however carefully we have to interpret this
operation), but he was doing something much more profound: cartographic
space itself, not only the material object, was in a way open-ended. He gave two
possible appearances of the lunar surface, but readers might find using their
own means what the disk would “look like” on any other occasion. Hevelius
furnished a cartographic base-space whose limits change over time, and it was
up to readers to find the boundaries of this space at a given moment.
The two superimposed libration disks that make up the cartographic base-
space in this map and the previous one represent the full moon under direct
solar illumination, i.e., the “real” condition of visibility. The effect of direct il-
lumination, as we have seen before, is to make topography difficult to discern,
with edges losing sharpness and small-size features getting fainter or totally
disappearing. The next map addresses these problems directly, in a very radical
way (Figure 12). Again we are in front of the two libration disks and ornamented
corners. The banner carried by the upper-left corner putti in Figure 12 gives the
map’s title as Tabula Selenographica, adding that it is “a true orthographic de-
lineation, made with the aid of the telescope, of the seas, bays, islands, conti-
nents, promontories, lakes, wetlands, mountains, plains, and valleys that exist
on the visible surface of the moon.” Hevelius willingly surrenders to terrestrial
cartographic conventions. All of a sudden, the lunar surface is filled with earth-
like “geographical accidents,” marked on the image with proper names coming
straight out of ancient geography: Mare Mediterraneum, Insula Corsica, Pontus
Euxinus … The textual surroundings of this outline map reinforce the transfor-
mation of the moon in a kind of earth, as effected in and by the map. In the text
pages among which the map was to be inserted, Hevelius discusses at length
how he came to his nomenclature, noting that the definitive step was taken
when he had the revelation that the moon’s surface was the exact mirror of the
earth’s. The resort to ancient and biblical geography to baptize the features of
the moon’s surface, in which he believed he saw the Ptolemaic ecumene, was
an irenic gesture. He borrowed toponyms from Abraham Ortelius’s Thesaurus
and the Bible, consciously avoiding Van Langren’s overtly political decisions.
The result, writes Nydia Pineda, “was not just an accommodation of terrestrial
cartography onto a survey drawn from the telescope, but was in itself a repre-
sentation of cultural transfer: the geography of most interest to humanist and
48 Haddad
FIGURE 12 In the second foldout map included in Selenographia (between pages 226 and
227), Hevelius sacrificed albedo to topography and nomenclature.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 8932 q, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-238)
biblical scholarship was projected onto the moon. The reader would revisit
mythology, history, and texts conveyed through the nomenclature” (Pineda de
Ávila 2017, 176–177).
Van Langren had organized his map space according to a metageography
based on stark, simple oppositions: lands and seas, large and small, central
and peripheral. The symbolic order imposed by Van Langren’s choice of no-
menclature was accordingly organized in the same dualistic way: large and/
or central areas are named after powerful patrons, which in turn determine
the names that should or should not be given to nearby features. Hevelius of-
fers instead a more nuanced hierarchy of forms, sizes, and relationships. The
banner on the upper-right brings a legend with the key to the legibility of the
map: M is for mountains, I for islands, Pr for promontories and so on. Not only
is the map now covered with toponyms, the visual representation itself has
undergone a profound transformation: what on the previous map was simply
shaded now gains a rich texture, and small hills or mounds abound along the
Maps of the Moon 49
FIGURE 13 Detail of the map in Figure 12, showing Hevelius’s use of rows of
“mounds” and broken, wavy lines to create topographical texture.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH
(Rar 8932 q, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-238)
boundaries between dark and light regions. What is more, Hevelius inverts the
overall shading scheme, in such a way that “bodies of water” are no longer dark,
but vast blank spaces populated by occasional “islands,” as viewers were used
to find in terrestrial maps (Figure 13). The putti at the lower corners seem not
to be contemplating from a distance any longer, but actively engaging in survey
work. One of them holds a telescope that is not pointing upwards, to the sky,
but straight ahead, to the “field.” The distance scale becomes a ruler that can
be grabbed and applied to the terrain. The moon is barely a celestial object
anymore, but a world as near and palpable as the earth; the moon map looks
almost undistinguishable from a terrestrial one.24
24 The third foldout full moon map is similar to the one shown in our Figure 10, but high-
lighting the surface relief, with an oblique source of illumination (of necessity artificial,
for the real full moon occurs under conditions of direct incidence of sunlight).
50 Haddad
By the late seventeenth century, though, there was hope that improvements in
instrumentation could mitigate those problems. Thus, eclipse maps registering
the local time for a number of successive positions of the shadow boundary
might, after all, meet with their intended use. But there was another important
question that had to be faced before that: there was no point in comparing two
eclipse maps if they did not record the same events. In other words, the observ-
ers would have to agree beforehand on exactly what surface features would
Maps of the Moon 53
have the instant of their shadowing recorded. This could be solved if a central
authority determined which surface features should command observers’ at-
tention, and then collected and compared the records made by astronomers
positioned on different locations.
Giovanni Domenico Cassini was the individual with the necessary resources,
including personal and institutional power, to promote this kind of central-
ization, that is, to establish a standardization of observational protocols, or at
least to gather a large enough number of not necessarily uniform records (and
then see if it was still possible to compare them in some way). The dominant
figure of French astronomy since the 1670s, when he founded the Paris Royal
Observatory on Colbert’s invitation, an intimate of Louis XIV, and an influen-
tial member of the Académie des Sciences, Cassini spent decades overseeing
large astronomical and cartographic projects that could only come into being
through the mobilization of large networks of practitioners.
In the Mémoires of the Academy meeting of August 30, 1692, we find Cassini
reporting at length on the lunar eclipse that had taken place on July 28. After
learning that bad weather in Paris prevented the Royal Observatory from re-
cording the eclipse from start to end as minutely as Cassini had hoped for, we
read that “in several other towns where M. Cassini maintains correspondence
with talented astronomers, who were thoroughly prepared to observe the
eclipse, the weather has not been more favorable.” Some of these astronomers
were under Cassini’s direct orders, as we are told: “M. Beauchamps, gentleman
of Avignon, has been expressly dispatched to Carpentras to observe the eclipse
therefrom (…); in Aix, M. Brochier was prepared to make the observation; and
M. Cassini’s eldest son was placed in S. Malo” (Cassini 1730, 151–152). Four other
astronomers are also mentioned, but it is not clear except in one case whether
they had been “expressly dispatched” by Cassini or had voluntarily sent in their
results to the Royal Observatory.
Even if all observations were hampered by bad weather, preventing the ob-
servation of the same events along the shadow’s progression, Cassini was able
to devise a method that could still extract something from the data. He showed
that with records from at least three different observers, it was possible in princi-
ple to work out mathematically the longitudinal differences even if they had not
registered exactly the same events. The demonstration was textual and graphi-
cal, and for the latter Cassini employed a typically Hevelian template map.
Cassini was also involved in the establishment of a heavily reproduced,
used, and circulated map that first appeared in the same context of eclipse
observations. Much less schematic than the Hevelian templates, it was prob-
ably based on an earlier, somewhat ill-fated attempt to produce a highly de-
tailed, very large engraving that Cassini had undertaken in the 1670s, which we
54 Haddad
have already encountered in Figure 5b.25 A version of this map first appeared
in the almanac of the Paris Observatory, La Connoissance des Temps, in 1702,
and over the next few decades returned in slightly different versions. In 1730
it came out in its most iconic, frequently reproduced form (Figure 16), when
the Académie the Sciences decided to print the mémoires of its seventeenth-
century meetings. There is a dense textual layer, with letters referring to no-
table features that Cassini had selected as especially important for eclipse
observers. The title is interesting in itself, for it suggests that the image repre-
sents the “mean libration.” In reality, it is not in any sense an “average” over all
possible views of the moon’s face as it changes due to libration, as one may in-
advertently suppose, but an estimated, and once again, “eyeballed” depiction.
25 For a careful analysis of this project and the resulting image, see Pineda de Ávila (2017,
108–110 and 121–123, and references therein).
Maps of the Moon 55
FIGURE 16 Cassini’s large moon engraving prepared by Jean Patigny (Figure 5b) reached
a very restricted audience. Another, very simplified version of the image,
had e normous success during the eighteenth century, and was reproduced
innumerable times in almanacs, textbooks, encyclopedias, and periodi-
cals. Shown here is a version included by Pierre-Charles Le Monnier in his
Institutions Astronomiques of 1746, itself a version of a famous astronomical
textbook by John Keill, published in Latin in 1718 (with many subsequent edi-
tions). Le Monnier’s map is, in turn, a faithful reproduction of the one that had
already appeared in 1730 in the first printing of Cassini’s 1692 communications
on lunar eclipses to the Académie des Sciences.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 4053, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-2554)
56 Haddad
FIGURE 17 Riccioli and Grimaldi’s moon map (included between pages 204 and 204 ½
of the first volume of the Almagestum Novum) adheres to Hevelius’s solution
to the problem of how to represent libration, with the pair of offset circles,
although Riccioli proposes another graphical device to locate the visual cen-
ter of the lunar disk (the small circle at the center). The map does away with
Hevelius’s naming scheme, however, putting in place a system based on rules
about what names could appear in each one of the octants clearly discern-
ible in the image. A balance between topography and brilliance is attempted
by a clever use of the varying spacing and angles of the line incisions.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH
(Rar 9471, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-520)
Hevelius’s (see, e.g., Whitaker 1999, 60–68; Montgomery 1999, chapter 12;
Vertesi 2007; Pineda de Ávila 2017, 177–183). In very important and consequen-
tial ways they really are. Great importance is accorded to the fact that Riccioli
devised yet another nomenclature scheme, which he explains in full detail
in the text. His system of choosing names for the features on the lunar sur-
face was poised to supersede Hevelius’s, and, to some measure, is still in use.
Maps of the Moon 57
FIGURE 18 Immediately following the previous map, this second image clearly puts greater
weight on volumes and suggestions of tri-dimensionality. It is not topographic,
though, but much more in line with the naturalistic tradition. Also absent is the
double outer edge.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 9471, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-520)
Riccioli’s name choices and their distribution over the moon are overtly politi-
cal, unlike Hevelius’s irenic proposal. But their politics is also not the same as
Van Langren’s: it is the politics of the Republic of Letters itself that is allowed to
be represented on the map. Innumerable astronomers and philosophers from
Antiquity onwards receive their share of lunar territory, accorded to each one
on the basis of merit, but also of religious allegiances. Unsurprisingly, Roman
Catholics get the “best” spots, i.e., larger, more central ones or those nearer to
pleasant regions such as the Sea of Tranquility, not the Ocean of Storms.26
26 It is interesting to note that the Latin inscription below the map’s title translates as
“Neither do men inhabit the moon, neither do souls migrate there.” Riccioli is thus clearly
rejecting any credence of earth-moon parallelisms based on assumptions of a real mirror-
ing, and openly embracing the artificial, arbitrary character of the politics he projects on
the lunar surface.
58 Haddad
5 Time Abstracted
This Section will take us to the Enlightenment and the emergence of a new
cartographic epistemology, which was in fact a model of a rising knowledge
practice based on gathering data through quantitative measurements, and
guessing new, unmeasured data through mathematical procedures. What
comes to mind is the cartographer-surveyor, who proceeds from a set of pri-
mary coordinates to triangulated ones. This is the epistemic environment of
Tobias Mayer, when he found a job at the successful Homann cartographic of-
fice in 1740s Nuremberg. The firm was expanding, and, as we will see in detail,
Mayer put the moon to use for terrestrial ends: longitude strikes again. But the
intelligibility of the moon was now of a different kind: it was only full—its
intelligibility—if the moon was to be subject to the same knowledge-making
procedures that lay behind a cartographic triangulation, and this is what
Mayer did. In the process, he invented a new way of dealing with the problem
of libration, by abstracting the effects of time, to the extent that all he cared
about was to represent absolute values of coordinates, without references to
human observers. The Section ends with another visual exercise, an assem-
blage of “surveyors’ moons.”
determinism” in this statement. It was obviously not the only such condition,
far from it: moon maps owe their existence to myriad factors, including among
others the general dynamics of patronage systems, competing traditions of
thinking about the moon and its relation to the earth, the transformations
in the status of images in astronomical investigations, the creation of publics
for such images (comprising scholars, patrons, collectors and so on), and, cru-
cially, the increasing availability and cultural significance of terrestrial maps
and the practices attending their production, circulation, and consumption.
And yet the telescope stands out as the material pre-condition for the appear-
ance of selenography, besides being itself part and parcel of the social, cultural,
and epistemological determinants I have just alluded to.
In the mid-eighteenth century, selenography become something differ-
ent from what it had been to that moment, and once again a material condi-
tion had to be met. Again, this has nothing to do with techno-determinism.
Now, the material operator resided on telescope eyepieces armed with mi-
crometers, something that had become quite common since the end of the
seventeenth century. It was only in the 1740s, though, that cultural, epistemic,
and economic conditions enmeshed this previously existent piece of ap-
paratus in a new practice of seeing and representing the moon. This would
deeply condition the practice of lunar mapping until around the rise of as-
tronomical photography in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
Arguably, even photography did not represent as significant a break as did this
eighteenth-century transformation, at least if we are interested in the episte-
mological aspects of lunar mapmaking. In contrast to the situation in the early
seventeenth century, when selenography started to take shape even as tele-
scopic astronomy was being invented,27 what happened in the mid-eighteenth
century was that a well-worn piece of equipment was put to a new use, in
order to produce a type of information about the moon that had not been
sought before.
Simply put, a micrometer eyepiece allows for quantitatively precise mea-
surements of apparent linear distances between pairs of celestial objects in
the field magnified by the telescope. These distances may, in turn, be converted
to angles with the use of mathematical procedures, for angles are the truly rel-
evant data for positional astronomy. Although Galileo had already contrived
ways of combining rulers with his telescopes in order to investigate the precise
positioning of the satellites of Jupiter, usable micrometer eyepieces started to
27 Albert Van Helden suggested, in a classic paper, that even if selenography was made possi-
ble with the appearance of the first telescopes, fierce competition to produce moon i mages
may have been a driving force in attempts to improve the instrument (Van Helden 1974).
60 Haddad
Indeed, for all their continuing claims of being unmediated visual represen-
tations of space as would be directly “seen” from enough distance, eighteenth-
century maps were the brainchildren of a different epistemology, one that
regarded mapmaking as “the process of establishing the relations (…) between
known entities and then using those relations to interpolate new entities” (Edney
1999, 186). These “new entities” were the unknowns of any well-posed problem,
and they were not to be directly measured or experienced. They could be the
deduced (i.e., interpolated) geographical coordinates of places that would not
be directly established. The more “precise” the first order measurements were,
the more reliable the deduced entities. Mapping, thus understood, became
a proxy for Enlightenment epistemology at large, considered as a process of
“knowledge creation through the reconciliation of differences between obser-
vations and the laying out of the relations between individual pieces of data”
(Edney 1999, 186). Observation/precision, reconciliation/standardization, de-
duction/interpolation: those are the dimensions that determine the “knowl-
edge space” of the time. Behind all of this obviously lies an epistemology that
places extreme value on quantification and measurability.28
In mapmaking, this focus on quantitative data and their mathematical pro-
cessing entailed a new relation between map space itself and mapped space
in general. From Descartes to Newton to Kant, space became physical and
geometrical; it is tempting to say that the map projection then finally gained
a kind of metaphysical status, inasmuch as it revealed the deep structure of
physico-geometrical reality. Projected space increasingly became more real
than reality itself. It was only when this epistemological shift was well under-
way that the pre-existing instrumental condition afforded by the availability of
micrometer eyepieces could produce noticeable effects in lunar cartography.
The visible surface of the moon now emerged not as an “immediate” visual im-
pression that could be rendered in drawing, but as a kind of abstract, geometri-
cal, and coordinatized space that had to be made visible by an application of
the principle of interpolating unknown locations on a previously established
basic network of “knowns.”
Survey-based, coordinatized selenography first came to fruition in the work
of German cartographer and astronomer Tobias Mayer (1723–1762). It is a car-
tographic practice that developed against that background of a changing epis-
temology that I have sketched, but, more concretely, it came into being in a
context of cultural and economic anxieties brought about by growing compe-
tition between German private cartographic business enterprises and French
28 For more on the Enlightenment’s “quantifying spirit,” see the papers in Frängsmyr,
Heilbron and Rider (1990).
Maps of the Moon 63
29 Biographical information on Mayer and detailed expositions of the technical content
of his work are to be found in a number of works by Eric G. Forbes (1967; 1970a; 1970b;
1972; 1980).
64 Haddad
30 In all likelihood, Mayer must have had the opportunity to skim through the prepara-
tory material for the then recently (1742) published Atlas Coelestis of Johann Gabriel
Doppelmayr. The atlas contained two insets with highly magnified details of the moon’s
surface (originally drawn by Robert Hooke and Francesco Bianchini), several outlines
of the full-moon disk, and a side-by-side comparison of Hevelius’s and Riccioli and
Grimaldi’s maps, nomenclature and all.
66 Haddad
From the start, Mayer placed the highest value on astronomical data that
could lead to precise determinations of latitudes and longitudes of key loca-
tions, laying out from these the basic grid from which a map would develop.
(Forbes 1970b, 144–145, quotes manuscript evidence of Mayer’s early reliance
on astronomical methods.) “Like all other geographers,” writes Matthew Edney,
“Mayer had to define the positions of the towns from reconnaissance accounts,
either by geodetic calculations or by plotting routes between known points in
the graticule” (Edney 1999, 186). By and large an armchair cartographer not
engaged in practical field work, Mayer had to rely precisely on these “known
points in the graticule,” i.e., latitude and longitude values for the basic trian-
gulation networks. These he found severely wanting, pointing out that even
for places on the German lands there were only 22 well-established latitudes,
and not a single reliable longitude (Forbes 1967, 235). In fact, the situation was
even more depressing: one of the latest and most successful Homannian pub-
lications, Doppelmayr’s celestial atlas, featured a table (“Astronomical basis of
recent geography”), widely regarded as authoritative, presenting what experts
generally agreed were uncontroverted latitude-longitude pairs for places in the
whole world—and it listed only 139 such locations.
Mayer the cartographer thus realized it was necessary to engage in a large-scale
enterprise of coordinate determination, an undertaking for which astronomy
was to provide the necessary methods. In a piece included in the Cosmographic
Academy book, Mayer voices the “hope of establishing, by the phenomena that
appear in the sky, the geographical lengths between places on our earth with
such accuracy as is appropriate to the present state of geography” (Mayer 1750a,
41). The “geographical lengths” he alludes to are, obviously, longitudes.
This was a great prospect for longitude finders. Instead of relying on the
comparison of patchy data sets recording observations performed in different
places, records that could be totally incompatible and useless for determin-
ing the longitude differences, Mayer could hope for something much bigger: if
the unfolding of the eclipse could be accurately predicted, why not represent
the results on a map? In principle, this map could display the position of the
terminus of the earth’s shadow on the lunar disk at set intervals: every ten min-
utes, every 30 minutes, whatever was best. Each position would bring the exact
time it was predicted to occur, calculated for some location where the eclipse
was to be visible—say, Berlin. Mayer could make maps like this for any lunar
eclipse, and his employer would certainly be happy to commercialize these
objects. The buyer would have a very practical and easy way of determining her
own longitude in relation to the map’s chosen place of reference. (A means of
reliably establishing the buyer’s own local time was the only additional need.)
And the more maps were sold, the more longitudes would become known, not
to mention the increasing profits.
Mayer indeed prepared one such map, which was released by the Homann
firm in 1748, with the promise of an accompanying booklet (Figure 19). The
map displayed the time development of a lunar eclipse that was to take place
on August 8 of that year. The calculations had been made for Berlin local time.
It is a fascinating object: the moon’s face is clearly Hevelian, but the double
libration limits are omitted, since, in principle, the image represents the
moon as it was to be effectively seen on August 8. There are cartouches, scales,
inscriptions, and even a small map of the earth in stereographic projection,
showing the region where the eclipse should be visible. On the moon’s surface,
the successive shadow boundaries are finely displayed, and the (Berlin) timing
of each configuration can be easily read on a table that shares the space with
the other cartographic elements. All is written in German and French, adding
to the usability and commercial interest of the map.
But before his new eclipse map was released, though, Mayer realized it would
not work as intended (Mayer 1750b, 93). Libration was neglected in the calcula-
tions, so that what I have just written, that the double libration maxima were
omitted because the map should show the lunar disk as it would “effectively”
be seen on August 8, is only half-true. Like others before him, Mayer in real-
ity did not know what exactly the libration state of the moon would be on
August 8. He simply used a “mean” Hevelian moon, trusting that the effects of
libration would not change things noticeably. Besides, as a matter of fact, no
one really knew how to account for libration in the calculations: the equations
only gave the position of a single point, the center of the moon, and not of its
68 Haddad
FIGURE 19 Mayer created this multi-layered, highly complex image in 1747 or 1748, as a
display of what he still thought could be a protocol for the accurate establishment
of longitudes through the observation of lunar eclipses. It shows a Hevelian
moon, with the predicted projections of the edge of the earth’s shadow during
an upcoming eclipse, calculated for Berlin, as well as a stereographic terrestrial
map depicting the region of visibility. Additionally, the map contains detailed
information, in German and French, about the expected timing of important
events that should be noticed during the eclipse’s duration.
COURTESY NATIONAL LIBRARY OF AUSTRALIA
surface.31 Mayer’s realization, however, was that without accounting for libra-
tion, the map was bound to fail, as it did: on August 8, the calculated times for
the successive positions of the shadow proved wrong by several minutes.
Without a reliable theory to predict the libration state of the moon for any
instant in the future, Mayer set to empirically investigating the problem. In the
31 Hevelius’s theory did not work, nor did Riccioli’s and Cassini’s after his.
Maps of the Moon 69
course of months of patient telescopic observations, over the spring and sum-
mer of 1748, he realized it was possible to determine the “absolute selenograph-
ical coordinates” of points on the moon’s face under so-called “conditions of
mean libration.” To understand this, let us start remembering that the coordi-
nates of a lunar surface point, when referring to the visible disk of the moon,
are apparent. Since libration causes the visible disk to change, the apparent
coordinates change as well: a point that today appears to be exactly on the
center of the disk we see in the sky, tomorrow will be slightly off-center, and
continuously so, to be resumed again after a few years. The problem is that over
just a few days or weeks this variation can be so small that only a micrometer-
enhanced telescope can detect it, unless one observes over a long stretch, to
give time for the apparent positions to noticeably change. Thus, by employing
the micrometer, Mayer was able to quickly capture how the apparent position
of a few dozen points was changing as a consequence of libration. This pro-
vided him with the initial data for a theoretical determination of the rest of
their movement, in what amounted to a form of extrapolation. Now he could
finally determine the absolute coordinates of these points, defined as the av-
erage value of the apparent coordinates over the entire libration cycle. With
the absolute coordinates of those few dozen points, he could triangulate (i.e.,
interpolate) any other. Mayer’s moon becomes, thus, a perfect example of the
epistemological trends we discussed above: it was quantified, measured, trian-
gulated, and interpolated.
A consequence of Mayer’s new procedures for establishing lunar surface
coordinates was that, at least in principle, he should now be able to produce
eclipse maps that would not fail like his first one. But then he faced an obvious
problem: for each eclipse he would have to chart a slightly different moon, cor-
responding to the libration state in which it was predicted to be on the eclipse
date, a state that he now knew how to determine.32 He would have to render
this state on paper (not by eye, but by working out the orthographic projection
of the first-order points—now he knew how to do this, and there was no way
back). Over this projection he would then have to project the successive posi-
tions occupied by the terminus of the earth’s shadow, marking a local timing
for each one. This was simply not worth the immense labor it would demand,
and Mayer abandoned for good the idea of employing eclipse maps as a tool
for determining longitudes (Mayer 1750a, 41).
32 He would have to work back from the absolute coordinates of his first-order points to
the apparent values they were expected to have on the eclipse date, and then, as always,
interpolate the other points.
70 Haddad
Mayer did not abandon the moon, though. He decided to build a lunar
globe, because, first, he had the means to do so: the absolute coordinates of
a surface point, that he had just discovered how to determine, were nothing
less than true “globe coordinates;” second, he had a motive: by 1749, Franz was
enlisting subscribers to a new globe-making enterprise, and the moon speci-
men would be a nice item to sell (Gierl 2013, 275). In a prospectus for the globe
project published in 1750 to attract subscribers, Mayer wrote:
There is no doubt that selenography would become much more useful and
at the same time enjoyable if it were worked out better than it has hith-
erto been done. We have no more perfect drawings of the lunar spots
than the ones given by Hevelius and Riccioli after him. But one need only
compare them with the original, I mean with the moon itself, to see how
badly the similarity has been rendered. There is not a single spot to which
either its proper size or correct figure have been ascribed. Many, not only
the smaller, but also the larger spots, are altogether omitted, or wrongly
placed. (…) If I were to mention all the mistakes that have arisen from the
so-called libration, of which these renderings of the figure of the moon
have had a completely wrong concept, then I would need much more
time than my project allows. It will be enough to note that, since this
libration is now better understood, we know that the moon’s figure on
a surface cannot in any way be so drawn as to be of general use, and be
used in perpetuity.
MAYER 1750c, 5–6
For a number of reasons, Mayer’s moon globe never fully came into being, but
a few gores were actually engraved (Oestmann 2011). But as a by-product of
his labors on the globe, Mayer drew, in 1749, two maps that encapsulated his
new way of looking at the moon, and the new visibility imposed on it. The
maps, together with some 40 preparatory drawings, were also never published
in Mayer’s lifetime. It fell to Georg Christoph Lichtenberg to finally publish one
of the maps, the smallest, in 1775 (Figure 20), with a few additions and correc-
tions of his own.
By the time the map was finally published, what had gone into its creation
had already become standard knowledge for astronomers. Mayer had died a
respected professor, and had been awarded a prize from the British Board of
Longitude for his contributions to solving the problem (not through maps,
but through tables of lunar coordinates). Delayed and, in a way, neglected
by Mayer himself, the map may give a false impression of being of little rel-
evance. Visually, it has some kind of distinctively “modern” appeal: the relief is
Maps of the Moon 71
FIGURE 20 Mayer did not have a chance to publish the two hand-drawn maps he made using
the triangulation method of surveying that he had adapted to the moon, depicting
the “state of mean libration” (a photographic reproduction of one of the maps may
be found in Klinkerfues 1881, plate N). Lichtenberg had one of the maps engraved,
with some corrections, and included it in his own 1775 edition of Mayer’s Opera
Inedita. Here it is shown in yet another version, made by Johannes Hieronymus
Schroeter, based on Lichtenberg’s edition, and included in Schroeter’s 1791
Selenotopographische Fragmente (volume I, plate TV). Schroeter mainly added
place names and inverted the orientation of Mayer’s original image, so that the
moon is represented with the south up, as seen through a reflecting telescope.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 4281, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-1723)
carefully rendered, but not to the point of naturalistic illusion; then there is the
grid, the graduated parallels, and it appears we are done. But, after having seen
Hevelius’s “concretization” of time as a way to face the problem of representing
libration, and Mayer’s own dedication to the question, one may wonder: where
is libration here, after all? Has Mayer given up and depicted an “intermedi-
ary” moon surface? The answer, obviously, is no: what we see is the moon in
the state of mean libration. In other words, it is a rigorous assessment of the
average of all moon faces that we can ever see along a whole libration cycle,
orthographically projected onto paper. This is the moon as it would be seen by
an infinitely distant observer, whose line of sight crossed the lunar surface at
one specific point that does not coincide with the line of sight that any human
inhabitant of the earth would ever have, except possibly for a vanishingly small
moment. Moreover, it was constructed using the triangulation procedure.
72 Haddad
Mayer’s moon abstracts time entirely. It takes a “view from nowhere” as the
vanishing point for the representation. In a way, his map almost abstracts the
moon itself, as if all that counted were the internal relations of map space.
6 Time Eliminated
Even as surveying the moon quickly rose to become the dominant seleno-
graphical practice in the second half of the eighteenth century, and the elusive
“state of mean libration,” with time abstracted, became the standard mode of
representation, another change was already under way. We might say that, to a
great extent, this change emerged from the very same conditions and concerns
that made possible the kind of lunar mapmaking that has been associated with
Tobias Mayer in the previous Section of this essay.
Maps of the Moon 73
21a 21b
21c 21d
FIGURE 21 Another visual series, this time assembling together a group of four lunar maps
created following Mayer’s surveying approach. All of them show the moon in the
state of mean libration, in which, as argued on the text, time is “abstracted.”
21a John Russell’s 1805 image, already seen on Figure 5c, but now put in relation to
other similar images.
COURTESY WELLCOME COLLECTION (CC BY)
21b Johann Joseph von Littrow, Populäre Astronomie (Vienna, 1825), plate V of
volume II.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 4032, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-1534)
21d Adolf Stieler (editor), Handatlas über alle Theile der Erde und über das
Weltgebäude (Gotha, 1882), after an earlier, much larger, and highly successful
map by Wilhelm Wolff Beer and Johann Heinrich von Mädler.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH
(Rar KA 99, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-71709)
74 Haddad
FIGURE 22
An “extreme close-up” image of the moon,
included in Robert Hooke’s Micrographia
(London, 1665), plate XXXVIII. Although
devoted to the microscope, the book
ended with an ironic turn to the
telescope.
COURTESY BRITISH LIBRARY
33 More properly, I could have written that Galileo tried to derive this estimate from the
varying lengths of the dark features he interpreted as being necessarily cast shadows.
34 In other words, Mayer transposed on to his investigation of the moon the full range of
scales and approaches characteristic of eighteenth-century geodetic and topographic sur-
veying, the first of which had an immense bearing on the disputes around the shape of
the earth and the arc-length of a meridian that were taking place in Mayer’s time (for
an overview, cf. Widmalm 1990). I insist on this point because, as Matthew Edney has
warned, there is a “common misunderstanding that any surveying process involving the
construction of triangles, including graphic construction on a plane table or the trigono-
metrical solution of a simple system of intersecting lines, is ‘triangulation’” (Edney 2019,
90). What Mayer and the following lunar mapmakers have done is truly triangulation.
35 For an overview of Schroeter’s life and work, see Sheehan and Baum (1995, chapter 6).
An analysis of how Schroeter was perceived by his contemporaries and later historians is
provided by Oestmann (2002).
76 Haddad
FIGURE 23 One of the many “vertical aerial” views of the moon pre-
sented by Schroeter in his massive Selenotopographische
Fragmente of 1791 (here plate XVI of volume I).
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH
(Rar 4281, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-1723)
Maps of the Moon 77
36 On Gruithuisen’s firm conviction about extraterrestrial life, and how it shaped his lunar
research program, see Sheehan and Dobbin (2001, 75–85) and Crowe (1988, 202–204). It is
impossible not to be reminded of later attempts at mapping the planet Mars and its sup-
posedly artificial canals and large-scale infrastructure. This story has been beautifully told
and analyzed by Maria Lane (2010).
37 All aspects of the place occupied by observatories and observational networks on the
epistemic and social infrastructures underpinning nineteenth-century astronomy are ex-
plored in an important collection edited by David Aubin, Charlotte Bigg, and Otto Sibum
(2010). For two fascinating examples of the different reactions elicited by photography
and other visual technologies from individuals that were neither “professional” nor “ama-
teur” astronomers, but were nevertheless deeply invested on astronomical observations
and images, see the works of Laurence Guignard (2014) and Artemis Willis (2017). A more
general investigation of early lunar photography is to be found in Bigg (2018).
78 Haddad
24a 24b
FIGURE 24 Two photographs of plaster models included in James Nasmyth and James
Carpenter’s 1874 book, The Moon: Considered as a Planet, a World, and a Satellite
(London: John Murray). If Figure 24a can be clearly considered a vertical aerial
image, 24b places the viewer on the moon itself.
COURTESY THE PUBLIC DOMAIN REVIEW
Instead, they painstakingly created plaster models of small regions of the lunar
surface with all kinds of minutely imagined details, and took pictures of the
models. Artificial illumination was used to produce dramatic effects. Many of
the book’s images are aerial views, but so close that a reader can easily feel she
is about to land (Figure 24a). Others, however, are unmistakably what would
be taken by a photographer placed on the moon itself, even if on a high place
(Figure 24b). The viewer has been definitively transported to the moon, and is
surrounded by, or even part of, the moonscape.38
Schroeter, Gruithuisen, and Nasmyth and Carpenter represent a radical
close-up gaze directed at the moon. Most of their images are, in my view, not
prone to trigger that kind of “cartographic perception” that was mentioned
before. But there was also a second path along which the increasing access to
visual detail ultimately changed lunar representation practices and products
during the nineteenth century. Its origins can be traced down to the work of
38 For a penetrating study of Nasmyth’s work, see the recent essay by Omar Nasim (2018).
Maps of the Moon 79
FIGURE 26 The first of Lohrmann’s sectional maps included in Topographie der sichtbaren
Mondoberfläche (Dresden, 1824), making use of the possibilities opened up by
lithography, and employing hachuring conventions for topographical features
that had recently been developed in the realm of terrestrial cartography. Albedo is
soberly represented through the use of stippling.
COURTESY ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH (Rar 8933 q, DOI 10.3931/e-rara-2278)
39 This “quadrilateralization” of map space will have important consequences for lunar
maps drawn from photographs of limited areas of the moon’s surface. In the early-
twentieth century, such maps started to simply plot the x-y Cartesian coordinates of any
point, measured directly on the photographs, and no longer the (selenographic) latitudes
and longitudes (Whitaker 1999, 154).
82 Haddad
moon dweller would create of his or her own world. Their aspiration is thus to
represent the moon for itself, not for its earthly watchers, who cannot avoid the
changing appearance of the lunar face.
already in 1839 expressed hopes for a “photographic map” that would put to
rest traditional telescopic lunar mapping, “one of the most time-consuming,
painstaking and delicate undertakings in astronomy” (quoted in Bigg 2018,
121). For many decades, however, photography was no serious rival to human
eyes and hands equipped with telescopes, micrometers, notebooks, math-
ematical tables, pencils, and graded paper. Even though the moon had been
photographed innumerable times, it was only in the 1890s that a fully pho-
tographic atlas came into being, under the direction of Maurice Loewy and
Henri Puiseux, at the Paris Observatory (cf. Sicard 2013). Yet selenographers
stubbornly held onto their usual tried and tested eye-and-hand techniques,
embracing photographic images as an intermediary step for the preparation of
their maps, and not as the end product. This is why we come across Hugh Percy
Wilkins still hand-drawing his monstrously large and detailed moon maps in
the 1950s.
Satellite images were irresistible, though. They were at the same time sign-
posts of the Space Age and functional to its technical needs. Images taken in
ranges beyond the visible spectrum were essential for the geological mapping
of the moon, which was, in turn, necessary for decisions regarding landing
sites. A map such as the one shown in Figure 27, prepared in 1960 by Eugene
Shoemaker for the U.S. government from photographic images, epitomizes
the extreme “cartographicalization” undergone by lunar maps in their for-
mal aspects. Nothing about this map is specific to the moon; a satellite could
well have taken the same kind of picture of a region of the earth’s surface,
and then these images would be processed, projected, overlaid, colored, let-
tered, and embedded in the two-dimensional space of the page in exactly the
same manner.
Space Age maps, however, treated the problem of the moon’s changing ap-
pearance just like the sectional maps that had risen to prominence in the nine-
teenth century: time-dependency was simply out of the picture. For all their
techno-scientific clout, vibrant colors, unusual projections, and increasingly
thematic content, they still were—and are—drawn from the point of view of
that suspended, non-earthbound observer flying above the moon. The only dif-
ference is that previous mapmakers could only feel they were in this place;
Space Age creatures could be there, with their satellite eyes.
From the point of view of its cultural valence, the Space Age is dead. Of course,
artificial satellites still surround us by the thousands, playing essential roles in
many aspects of modern life; the International Space Station is flying over us
86 Haddad
somewhere; science fiction movies and literature keep feeding our dreams of
escaping from earth-boundedness; plans for a crewed flight to Mars resurface
every now and then, while corporate moguls play with their own rockets; by
now old photographs taken by the Hubble Space Telescope still give some ex-
perience of the sublime, even if in the form of wallpapers on the screens of our
electronic gadgets; and, although strangely absent from public discourse, nu-
clear missiles, the most lasting legacy of that period, are still capable of wiping
out life as we know it. The fiftieth anniversary of Apollo 11’s pioneering moon
landing may have briefly and nostalgically given a second chance to the Space
Age, in the form of innumerable exhibitions, television specials, and all other
kinds of recycling of material and visual artifacts of yore, including moon maps.
I seriously doubt this will last for long, though. In a recent collection of essays
suggestively subtitled Astroculture after Apollo, editor Alexander Geppert con-
vincingly makes the case that, following the lunar landings, “outer space itself
lost much of the political relevance, cultural significance and popular appeal
which it had been gaining worldwide since the mid-1920s, in particular after
the end of the Second World War” (Geppert 2018, 4).
The fact is that no one has been to the moon since 1972, and the waning of
the Space Age is directly related to this. As a consequence, lunar maps have
receded back into highly specialized niches, after briefly enjoying some degree
of popular appeal in the 1960s. To the public, they are at best those images in-
serted in terrestrial atlases and printed encyclopedias by the force of tradition,
not very meaningful in themselves. Perhaps they prove some point—only we
do not know exactly what. Do they demonstrate that the moon is rocky and
rugged? Do they remind us “we” were there? Or do they prove a kind of inter-
nal point, which is that “we” can create maps of wherever we please, including
of the moon? I am inclined to think this last alternative may be closer to the
truth, even if I have no means to prove it. To support my point, however, I think
we can go back to the previous practices of representing the moon that were
examined in this essay and ask: if it seems difficult to fathom the “whys” of
present-day lunar maps, was there any time when it was easy to do so?
The answer is obviously not. To go back to a point made right at the start,
maps of the moon have never performed in the same way as their terrestrial
counterparts. Let us recite once again: moon maps do not guide anyone from a
place to another, they do not play a role in settling border disputes, they are of
no help to invaders, conquerors or the like, they do not carry real claims of sov-
ereignty over people and places etc. Even during the hasty years of the Apollo
Program, it was for just a handful of people that the maps meant something
more than what was encapsulated in their material form. Here lies the whole
point: maps of the moon have always meant more than what they immediately
Maps of the Moon 87
materialized for just a handful of people. These people have varyingly been
astronomers, wealthy patrons, collectors, readers of astronomical treatises,
surveyors, perhaps some navigators, certainly astronauts. Lunar maps were
firmly conditioned by the surrounding practices of terrestrial cartography and
conventions of visual representation, but also presented a few problems of
their own, the most pressing of which was how to represent time, as I hope
to have shown. It may seem paradoxical, but it is precisely by virtue of their
specificity—social, cultural, technical—that maps of the moon have some-
thing to say for historians of cartography at large. Unencumbered by any kind
of expectation about how they should operate, one may profitably look back at
terrestrial cartography from its lunar counterpart.
Incidentally, it is this inverted gaze that Hans Blumenberg identified as the
far-reaching philosophical consequence of the Space Age. Barely one year after
the Sputnik flight, as a young philosophy professor at the University of Kiel,
Blumenberg was prompted by colleagues to apply for research funding, some-
thing they took to be an end in itself. With no real need for funding at that
moment, Blumenberg submitted an ironical project: he was to lay the founda-
tions of a new discipline called “astronoetics,” to compete with the increasingly
powerful field of astronautics. As recounted by Benjamin Lazier, Blumenberg
“proposed to do what Sputnik could not: he would explore the dark side of the
moon by ‘pure thought’ alone” (Lazier 2011, 620). But what started as a jest be-
came deadly serious for Blumenberg through the 1960s, as the Space Age came
into full being, especially after the wide distribution of a picture of the earth
taken in December 24, 1968, by an astronaut aboard the Apollo 8 mission (the
first crewed flight to orbit the moon).
The photograph shows a distant earth, rising over a lunar horizon. It has
been reproduced thousands, perhaps millions of times, to the point that it may
have become difficult for us to grasp its impact. It was the first picture of the
earth from that far, from inside a spacecraft not orbiting our planet. This was
the ultimate representation of the centrifugal, outwards (and out-worldly) im-
petus Blumenberg ascribed to the Space Age. The earth had been represented
from this point of view an uncountable number of times before, but it was
only at this moment that it had finally been seen from such a distance. What
Blumenberg realized was that the image of the terrestrial globe had always
been “noetic,” the result of pure thought alone, but not any longer. He would
then write that, “[i]t is only as an experience of turning back, that we shall
accept that for man there are no alternatives to the earth” (Blumenberg 1987,
685). Only after experiencing the centrifugal push of the Space Age did hu-
mans finally give in to the centripetal pull of the earth itself, at last seeing the
place they had come from, and from which there was no real escape.
88 Haddad
Different from the far side, and different, above all, from the “face of the
earth” itself, the visible side of the moon was never out of the reach of our eyes.
It was not accessible only by “pure thought,” and the consequences of this fact
on the ways the moon has been mapped, and how those maps were viewed,
are open for exploration. I think they include the question of time I have been
pursuing throughout this essay. But, most importantly, if we had to experience
the most radical deterritorialization to finally see our planet, whose global car-
tographic image had already been in the making for centuries (cf. Cosgrove
2001), it is not unreasonable to expect that by (metaphorically) placing our-
selves on the moon, through its maps, we might also learn something about
the maps of our own earth.
Bibliography
Alexander, Amir. 1998. “Lunar Maps and Coastal Outlines: Thomas Hariot’s Mapping of
the Moon.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29: 345–368.
Andrews, J. H. 1996. “What was a Map? The Lexicographers Reply.” Cartographica 33
(4): 1–11.
Andrews, J. H. 2001. “Introduction: Meaning, Knowledge, and Power in the Map
Philosophy of J. B. Harley.” In The New Nature of Maps. Essays in the History of
Cartography, by J. B. Harley, edited by Paul Laxton, 2–32. Baltimore and London:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Aubin, David, Charlotte Bigg and H. Otto Sibum (editors). 2010. The Heavens on Earth:
Observatories and Astronomy in Nineteenth-Century Science and Culture. Durham,
N.C. and London: Duke University Press, 2010.
Austin, John L. 1962. How to do things with words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Biagioli, Mario. 1993. Galileo courtier. The practice of science in the culture of absolutism.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Bigg, Charlotte. 2018. “Of Blurs, Maps and Portraits: Photography and the Moon.” In
Selene’s Two Faces: From 17th Century Drawings to Spacecraft Imaging, edited by
Carmen Pérez González, 114–146. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Bloom, Terrie. 1978. “Borrowed Perceptions: Harriot’s Maps of the Moon.” Journal for
the History of Astronomy ix: 177–122.
Blumenberg, Hans. 1987. The Genesis of the Copernican World. Translated by
Robert M. Wallace. Cambridge, Mass. and London: The MIT Press.
Bosmans, Henri F. 1903. “La Carte Lunaire de Van Langren conservée aux Archives
Générales du Royaume, à Bruxelles.” Revue des Questions Scientifiques 54: 108–139.
Bosmans, Henri F. 1910. “La carte lunaire de Van Langren conservée à l’Université de
Leyde.” Revue des Questions Scientifiques 67: 248–264.
Maps of the Moon 89
Bouza, Fernando. 2008. “Realeza, aristocracia y mecenazgo [del ejercicio del poder
modo calamo].” In Mecenazgo y humanidades en tiempos de Lastanosa. Homenaje
a Domingo Ynduráin, edited by Aurora Egido and José Enrique Laplana, 69–88.
Zaragoza: IFC-IEA.
Bredekamp, Horst. 2000. “Gazing hands and blind spots: Galileo as draftsman.” Science
in Context 13 (3–4): 423–462.
Bredekamp, Horst. 2007. Galilei der Künstler: Der Mond. Die Sonne. Die Hand. Berlin:
Akademie Verlag.
Brooks, Randall C. 1991. “The Development of Micrometers in the Seventeenth,
Eighteenth and Nineteenth Centuries.” Journal for the History of Astronomy xxii:
127–173.
Cassini, Jean Dominique [Giovanni Domenico]. 1730 [1692]. “Observation de l’Eclipse
de Lune du 28 Juillet dernier, avec une Méthode pour determiner les longitudes
par diverses Observations d’une mème Eclipse interrompuës & faites en differ-
ens lieux.” In Mémoires de l’Académie Royale des Sciences depuis 1666 jusqu’à 1699,
Tome X, 150–158. Paris: Par la Compagnie des Libraires.
Classen, J. 1969. “The First Maps of the Moon.” Sky and Telescope 37: 82–83.
Cohen, I. Bernard. 1982. “The Influence of Theoretical Perspective on the Interpretation
of Sense Data: Tycho Brahe and the New Star of 1572, and Galileo and the Mountains
of the Moon.” Annali dell’Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza di Firenze 6 (1): 3–13.
Cosgrove, Denis. 2001. Apollo’s Eye: A Cartographic Genealogy of the Earth in the Western
Imagination. Baltimore and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Cressy, David. 2006. “Early Modern Space Travel and the English Man in the Moon.”
The American Historical Review 111 (4): 961–982.
Crowe, Michael J. 1988. The Extraterrestrial Life Debate, 1750–1900: The Idea of a Plurality
of Worlds from Kant to Lowell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Daston, Lorraine and Peter Galison. 2007. Objectivity. Cambridge, Mass.: Zone Books.
Edgerton Jr., Samuel Y. 1984. “Galileo, Florentine ‘Disegno’, and the ‘Strange Spotted
nesse’ of the Moon.” Art Journal 44 (3): 225–232.
Edney, Matthew H. 1999. “Reconsidering Enlightenment Geography and Map Making:
Reconnaissance, Mapping, Archive.” In Geography and Enlightenment, edited by
David N. Livingstone and Charles W. J. Withers, 165–198. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press.
Edney, Matthew H. 2007. “Mapping Empires, Mapping Bodies: Reflections on the
Use and Abuse of Cartography.” Treballs de la Societat Catalana de Geografia 63:
83–104.
Edney, Matthew H. 2019. Cartography: The Ideal and its History. Chicago: The University
of Chicago Press.
Favaro, Antonio (editor). 1929–1939. Edizione nazionale delle opere di Galileo Galilei,
Firenze: G. Barbèra.
90 Haddad
Forbes, Eric G. 1967. “Life and work of Tobias Mayer (1723–1762).” Quarterly Journal of
the Royal Astronomical Society 8: 227–251.
Forbes, Eric G. 1970a. “Tobias Mayer (1723–1762): A Case of Forgotten Genius.” British
Journal for the History of Science 5 (1): 1–20.
Forbes, Eric G. 1970b. “Tobias Mayer’s Contributions to the Development of Lunar
Theory.” Journal for the History of Astronomy i: 144–154.
Forbes, Eric G. 1972. “Tobias Mayer’s method for calculating the circumstances of a
solar eclipse.” Annals of Science 28 (1): 177–189.
Forbes, Eric G. 1980. “Tobias Mayer’s Contributions to Observational Astronomy.”
Journal for the History of Astronomy xi: 28–49.
Frängsmyr, Tore, J. L. Heilbron and Robin E. Rider (editors). 1990. The Quantifying Spirit
in the Eighteenth Century. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Franz, Johann Michael. 1750a. “Vorrede.” In Kosmographische Nachrichten und
Sammlungen auf das Jahr 1748. Vienna: Joh. Paul Krauss.
Franz, Johann Michael. 1750b. “Vorschläge, wie die Erdbeschreibung in Absicht
Deutschlands zu verbessern sey.” In Kosmographische Nachrichten und Sammlungen
auf das Jahr 1748 (Part II: Kosmographische Sammlungen auf das Jahr 1748), 348–396.
Vienna: Joh. Paul Krauss.
Gachard, Louis-Prosper. 1845. “Lettre de Philippe IV à l’infante Isabelle, touchant
certains luminaires découverts au ciel par Michel-Florentius Van Langren.” Bulletins
de l’Académie royale des sciences et belles-lettres de Bruxelles XII: 261–262.
Geppert, Alexander C. T. (editor). 2018. Limiting Outer Space: Astroculture after Apollo.
Basingstoke, U.K.: Palgrave MacMillan.
Gierl, Martin. 2013. “Change of Paradigm as a Squabble between Institutions: The
Institute of Historical Sciences, the Society of Sciences, and the Separation of Cultural
and Natural Sciences in Göttingen in the Second Half of the Eighteenth Century.”
In Scholars in Action: The Practice of Knowledge and the Figure of the Savant in the
18th Century, Volume 1, edited by André Holenstein, Hubert Steinke, and Martin Stuber,
in collaboration with Philippe Rogger, 267–288. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Gingerich, Owen. 1975. “Dissertatio cum Professore Righini et Sidereo Nuncio.” In
Experiment and Mysticism in the Scientific Revolution, edited by M. L. Righini Bonelli
and William R. Shea, 77–88. New York: Science History Publications.
Graney, Christopher M. 2015. Setting Aside All Authority: Giovanni Battista Riccioli and
the Science against Copernicus in the Age of Galileo. Notre Dame, IN.: University of
Notre Dame Press.
Guignard, Laurence. 2014. “Le « tourment lunaire » de Jules Pierrot-Deseilligny.
Pratiques amateurs d’observation de la Lune.” Romantisme 166 (4): 65–78.
Harley, J. B. 1988a. “Silences and Secrecy: The Hidden Agenda of Cartography in Early
Modern Europe.” Imago Mundi 40: 57–76.
Maps of the Moon 91
Copernicana XLIV). Warsaw: Polish Academy of Sciences; Institute for the History
of Science, Copernicus Center for Interdisciplinary Studies.
Lane, K. Maria D. 2010. Geographies of Mars: Seeing and Knowing the Red Planet.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Law, John and Solveig Joks. “Indigeneity, Science, and Difference: Notes on the Politics
of How.” Science, Technology, & Human Values 44 (3): 424–447.
Lazier, Benjamin. 2011. “Earthrise; or, The Globalization of the World Picture.” The
American Historical Review 116 (3): 602–630.
Lewis, Martin W. and Kären E. Wigen. 1997. The Myth of Continents: A Critique of
Metageography. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Lois, Carla. 2015. “El mapa, los mapas. Propuesta metodológica para abordar la plurali-
dade de la imagem cartográfica.” Geograficando 11 (1).
Lois, Carla. 2018a. Terrae Incognitae. Formas de pensar y mapear geografias desconocidas.
Buenos Aires: Eudeba.
Lois, Carla. 2018b. “¿Geopolíticas de mundos efímeros?” Terra Brasilis (Nova Série) [On
line], 10 | 2018, URL: http://journals.openedition.org/terrabrasilis/3377; DOI 10.4000/
terrabrasilis.3377.
Mayer, Tobias. 1750a. “Beobachtungen einiger Zusammenkunften des Monds mit
Fixsternen, im Jahr 1747 und 1748 zu Nürnberg in dem homännischen Hause an-
gestellet.” In Kosmographische Nachrichten und Sammlungen auf das Jahr 1748
(Part II: Kosmographische Sammlungen auf das Jahr 1748), 41–51. Vienna: Joh. Paul
Krauss.
Mayer, Tobias. 1750b. “Abhandlung über die Umwälzung des Monds um seine Axe, und
die scheinbare Bewegung der Mondsflecken.” In Kosmographische Nachrichten und
Sammlungen auf das Jahr 1748 (Part II: Kosmographische Sammlungen auf das Jahr
1748), 41–51. Vienna: Joh. Paul Krauss.
Mayer, Tobias. 1750c. Bericht von den Mondskugeln, welche bey der kosmogra-
phischen Gesellschaft in Nürnberg, aus neuen Beobachtungen verfertiget warden.
[Nuremberg]: zu finden in der Homännischen Officin.
Montgomery, Scott L. 1999. The Moon and the Western Imagination. Tucson: The
University of Arizona Press.
Montucla, Jean-Étienne. 1802. Histoire des mathématiques, Tome IV (edition completed
and expanded by Jérôme Lalande). Paris: Henri Agasse.
Müller, Kathrin. 2010. “How to Craft Telescopic Observation in a Book: Hevelius’s
Selenographia (1647) and its images.” Journal for the History of Astronomy xli: 355–379.
Nasim, Omar W. 2018. “James Nasmyth on the Moon: Or on Becoming a Lunar Being,
without the Lunacy.” In Selene’s Two Faces: From 17th Century Drawings to Spacecraft
Imaging, edited by Carmen Pérez González, 147–187. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Nicholls, Mark. 2012. “Last Act? 1618 and the Shaping of Sir Walter Ralegh’s Reputation.”
In Thomas Harriot and his world: mathematics, exploration, and natural philosophy in
early modern England, edited by Robert Fox, 165–182. Farnham, Surrey, U.K.: Ashgate.
Maps of the Moon 93
Nicolson, Marjorie Hope. 1948. Voyages to the Moon. New York: McMillan.
Oestmann, Günther. 2002. “Astronomischer Dilettant oder verkanntes Genie? Zum Bild
Johann Hieronymus Schroeters in der Wissenschaftsgeschichte.” In Astronomie von
Olbers bis Schwarzschild: Nationale Entwicklungen und internationale Beziehungen
im 19. Jahrhundert (Acta Historica Astronomiae, Band 14), edited by Wolfgang R.
Dick and Jürgen Hamel, 9–24. Frankfurt: Verlag Harri Deutsch.
Oestmann, Günther. 2011. “The reconstruction and production of Tobias Mayer’s lunar
globe.” Globe Studies 57 (58): 37–48.
Ostrow, Steven F. 1996. “Cigoli’s Immacolata and Galileo’s Moon: Astronomy and the
Virgin in Early Seicento Rome.” The Art Bulletin 78: 218–235.
Paluzie i Borrell, Antoni. 1967. “Historia de la Cartografía Lunar.” Urania 266: 203–271.
Panofsky, Erwin. 1954. “Galileo as a Critic of the Arts: Aesthetic Attitude and Scientific
Thought.” Isis 47 (1): 3–15.
Pereda, Felipe and Fernando Marías. 2002. “Introducción: El Atlas del Rey Planeta:
Felipe IV y Pedro Texeira.” In El Atlas del Rey Planeta: La “Descripción de España y
de las costas y puertos de sus reinos” de Pedro Texeira (1634), edited by Felipe Pereda
and Fernando Marías, 9–28. Hondarribia: Editorial Nerea.
Pérez González, Carmen (editor). 2018. Selene’s Two Faces: From 17th Century Drawings
to Spacecraft Imaging. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Pigatto, Luisa and Valeria Zanini. 2001. “Lunar Maps of the 17th and 18th Centuries.
Tobias Mayer’s Map and its 19th-Century Edition.” Earth, Moon and Planets 85–86:
365–377.
Pineda de Ávila, Nydia. 2017. Selenographies in the seventeenth century: making, pub
lishing and copying maps of the moon. Doctoral dissertation. School of English and
Drama, Queen Mary, University of London.
Post, J. B. 2001. “A Map by Any Other Name.” Mercator’s World 6 (5): 36–37.
Pumfrey, Stephen. 2009. “Harriot’s maps of the Moon: New interpretations.” Notes and
Records of the Royal Society of London 63 (2): 163–168.
Raposo, Pedro P. M. 2018. “One World is Not Enough: Remarks on the History of
Selenography.” In Selene’s Two Faces: From 17th Century Drawings to Spacecraft
Imaging, edited by Carmen Pérez González, 34–60. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Ré, Pedro and Carmen Pérez González. 2018. “From Astronomer-photographers to
Astronaut-photographers: Close-up Detailed Observations Performed by Spacecraft
and Manned Exploration of the Moon.” In Selene’s Two Faces: From 17th Century
Drawings to Spacecraft Imaging, edited by Carmen Pérez González, 230–273. Leiden
and Boston: Brill.
Reeves, Eileen. 1997. Painting the Heavens: Art and Science in the Age of Galileo.
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Righini, Guglielmo. 1975. “New Light on Galileo’s Lunar Observations.” In Experiment
and Mysticism in the Scientific Revolution, edited by M. L. Righini Bonelli and
William R. Shea, 59–76. New York: Science History Publications.
94 Haddad
Sheehan, William and Richard Baum. 1995. “Observations and inference: Johann
Hieronymous Schroeter, 1745–1816.” Journal of the British Astronomical Association
105 (4): 171–175.
Sheehan, William and Thomas A. Dobbins. 2001. Epic Moon: A History of Lunar
Exploration in the Age of the Telescope. Richmond, VA.: Willmann-Bell.
Sicard, Monique. 2013. “L’Atlas photographique de la Lune, de MM. Loewy et Puiseux.”
Revue de la BNF 44 (2): 36–43.
Smits, Jan. 2009. “Cartifacts, a Completely Different Kind of Map!” Journal of Map &
Geography Libraries 5 (2): 177–186.
Spiegel, Richard J. 2015. “John Flamsteed and the turn of the screw: mechanical un-
certainty, the skilful astronomer and the burden of seeing correctly at the Royal
Observatory, Greenwich.” British Journal for the History of Science 48 (1): 17–51.
Van de Vyver, Omer. 1971a. “Lunar Maps of the XVIIth Century.” Vatican Observatory
Publications, 1 (2): 71–114.
Van de Vyver, Omer. 1971b. “Original Sources of Some Early Lunar Maps.” Journal for the
History of Astronomy ii: 86–97.
Van der Krogt, Peter. 1995. “Das ‘Plenilunium’ des Michael Florent van Langren.”
Cartographia Helvetica 11: 44–49.
van Gent, R. H. and Albert Van Helden. 2007. “Lunar, Solar, and Planetary Repre
sentations to 1650.” In The History of Cartography, Volume 3: Cartography In The
European Renaissance, edited by David Woodward, 123–134. Chicago: The University
of Chicago Press.
Van Helden, Albert. 1974. “The Telescope in the Seventeenth Century.” Isis 65 (1): 38–58.
Van Helden, Albert. 1994. “Telescopes and Authority from Galileo to Cassini.” Osiris 9:
8–29.
Van Langren, Miguel Florencio. 1644. La Verdadera Longitud por Mar y Tierra:
Demostrada y Dedicada a su Majestad Catholica Philippo IV. Antwerp?: [?].
Vertesi, Janet. 2007. “Picturing the moon: Hevelius and Riccioli’s visual debate.” Studies
in History and Philosophy of Science 38: 401–421.
Weinek, Ladislaus. 1890. “Drawings of the Moon.” Publications of the Astronomical
Society of the Pacific II (10): 201–214.
Wepster, Steven. 2010. Between Theory and Observations: Tobias Mayer’s Explorations of
Lunar Motion, 1751–1755. New York: Springer.
Whewell, William. 1837. History of the Inductive Sciences, from the Earliest to the Present
Times, Volume II. London: John W. Parker; Cambridge: J. and J. J. Deighton.
Whitaker, Ewen A. 1978. “Galileo’s Lunar Observations and the Dating of the Com
position of ‘Sidereus Nuncius’.” Journal for the History of Astronomy ix: 155–169.
Whitaker, Ewen A. 1989. “Selenography in the seventeenth century.” In The General
History of Astronomy, Volume 2: Planetary astronomy from the Renaissance to the rise
Maps of the Moon 95