Theo 12226
Theo 12226
doi:10.1111/theo.12226
Editorial
Does Research Ethics Apply to Us?
WHEN ETHICAL REVIEW OF research proposals was introduced in the 1970s and
1980s, it met with harsh and vociferous resistance. Researchers in the social sci-
ences and humanities contended that any prior ethical review of their research
constituted a serious threat to academic freedom. Important academic organiza-
tions protested against ethical reviewing, and prominent researchers spent most of
their time campaigning against it (Schrag, 2010). In the 1990s, resistance
receded, but it has been revitalized in the last ten years or so. Books and articles
criticizing the review system have been published, and meetings have convened
in order to create an international front against it (Dingwall, 2006; Schrag, 2010;
van den Hoonard, 2011; Iphofen, 2017; Sluka, 2018). Ethical review of social sci-
ences and the humanities has been described as “censorship” (Bell and Elliott,
2014), “unethical” and “anti-democratic” (Dingwall, 2006), “founded on igno-
rance, haste, and disrespect” (Schrag, 2010, p. 192), and as an “ethics rupture”
(Iphofen, 2017). Some critics have even claimed that ethical review may cause
the social sciences to “wither away” (van den Hoonard, 2011, p. 286).
The most prominent arguments against ethical review in the social sciences
and humanities can be summarized as follows:
No danger?
Opponents of ethical review in the social sciences and humanities claim that con-
trary to medical research, these disciplines do not pose any real dangers to
research subjects.
H[umanities and] S[ocial] S[cience] researchers do nothing that begins to compare with injecting
someone with potentially toxic green stuff that cannot be neutralised or rapidly eliminated from
their body if something goes wrong. At most there is a potential for causing minor and reversible
emotional distress or some measure of reputational damage. However, these are risks that research
participants are well able to assess for themselves. All HSS research is based on the same methods
that ordinary people use in their everyday life: observing other people, asking them questions,
reading documents or looking at pictures. (Dingwall, 2008, p. 3)
Another critic says that in order to justify ethical reviewing, there must be “a
proven record of abuses”, and “no such record exists for the social sciences and
humanities” (Schrag, 2011, p. 123). That, however, is not true. Although the dis-
cussions that led up to the introduction of ethical reviews had their main focus on
a series of highly problematic medical research projects (Beecher, 1966), several
studies in the social sciences contributed significantly to public concern about the
ethical conduct of academic research. The most famous of these studies was the
so-called tearoom trade study, in which a social scientist under cover observed
people involved in sexual activity, shadowed them to their homes, and later inter-
viewed them under the pretence of a public health survey (von Hoffman, 1970;
Babbie, 2004). Many other social science studies were criticized at the time for
unethical practices. A paper published in 1967 provided the following list:
In recent years, a handful of studies have been reported in the literature based on the work of
observers who deliberately misrepresented their identity in order to enter an otherwise inaccessible
social situation. Some of these studies have already provoked a good deal of comment – among
them, for instance, the cases of the anthropologist who posed as a mental patient by complaining
of symptoms he did not feel, the sociologists who joined a gathering of religious mystics by prof-
essing convictions they did not share, the Air Force officer who borrowed a new name, a new birth
date, a new personal history, a new set of mannerisms and even a new physical appearance in
order to impersonate an enlisted man, and the group of graduate students who ventured into a
meeting of Alcoholics Anonymous wearing the clothes of men from other social classes than their
own and the facial expressions of men suffering from an unfortunate disability. (Erikson, 1967,
p. 367; see also Fitzgerald, 2004, pp. 321–322)
Today, ethical review boards regularly deal with database studies that combine
individual data from different sources in ways that may intrude on the subjects’
privacy, interviews with victims of serious crimes such as rapes and war crimes,
who may potentially need psychological help after the interview, and various
studies in which it is part of the research design to keep the subjects less than
fully informed of the purpose of the research. In some cases, such as research on
terrorism and organized crime, human lives may be at stake. In 2007 the Eco-
nomic and Social Research Council in Britain had to withdraw its call for
research on “Combating Terrorism by Countering Radicalism” in a programme
funded by the Foreign Office, after academic organizations warned that the
programme’s connections with British counter-terrorism activities could endanger
the lives of researchers working in the field. It is now generally recognized that
research on terrorism and other violent activities can put the lives of both
researchers and informants at risk (Gorriti, 1991; Attwood, 2007; Mills et al.,
2019). The claim that research in the social sciences poses no danger to research
subjects cannot be upheld.
Unforeseeable effects
Some critics claim that research in the social sciences cannot be reviewed before-
hand because it is much less foreseeable than research in natural and medical
science:
[Q]ualitative researchers often begin their work not knowing what they will find, or even what
questions they will form. The ethical problems they do encounter may be equally surprising, so
that ethics review prior to fieldwork both wastes their time and fails to address the challenges that
do emerge. (Schrag, 2011, p. 128)
Academic freedom
Some researchers have claimed that ethical review, in particular in the humanities
and social sciences, violates the freedom of speech and/or academic freedom.
(The distinction between these two freedoms has often been blurred in these dis-
cussions.) Although much promoted by some academics, these claims do not
have much substance.
The freedom of speech includes a right to publish the results of one’s investiga-
tions, but it does not per se include a freedom to perform investigations. Aca-
demic freedom includes a right to perform research, but it does not provide
academic researchers with a right to use other human beings for that purpose
without their consent or with consent obtained under false pretence. Academic
Ethical regulation is becoming a smokescreen behind which our rivals in social investigation and
commentary can proceed unchecked, while those of us whose practice is disciplined by a profes-
sional ethic and a regulative ideal of truth-telling are handicapped in our access to the public
realm. (Dingwall, 2008, p. 6)
However, the fact that one group of professionals is allowed to collect informa-
tion in a particular way is not a sufficient reason for allowing another group of
professionals to do the same. For instance, journalism and social research have
quite different purposes and therefore also widely divergent timeframes, modi
operandi, and mechanisms for checks and controls. Presumably, few academics
would be willing to work under a managing editor who decides what can and can-
not be published. On the other hand, meetings with ethical review boards cannot
easily be fitted into the timeframes of day-to-day journalism. Criminologists and
terrorism researchers interviewing habitual lawbreakers have freedoms that the
police do not have, such as a freedom to refrain from reporting specific informa-
tion that they obtain about serious crimes to the prosecutor. But on the other
hand, police officers extracting information from the same offenders can use
investigative methods that are inaccessible to criminologists. As these examples
show, differences in investigative purpose and in the social roles of investigators
justify different rights and obligations. Investigative practices to be applied in
academic research have to be justified with reference to the specific purposes and
roles of scientific and scholarly research.
References
ATTWOOD, R. (2007) “ESRC ‘Ignores’ Danger Fears.” Times Higher Education, 20 July.
BABBIE, E. (2004) “Laud Humphreys and Research Ethics.” International Journal of Sociol-
ogy and Social Policy 24(3–5): 12–19.
BEECHER, H. K. (1966) “Ethics and Clinical Research.” New England Journal of Medicine
274: 1354–1360.
BELL, K. and ELLIOTT, D. (2014) “Censorship in the Name of Ethics: Critical Public Health
Research in the Age of Human Subjects Regulation.” Critical Public Health 24(4):
385–391.
DINGWALL, R. (2006) “Confronting the Anti-Democrats: The Unethical Nature of Ethical
Regulation in Social Science.” Medical Sociology Online 1(1): 51–58.
DINGWALL, R. (2008) “The Ethical Case against Ethical Regulation in Humanities and Social
Science Research.” Twenty-First Century Society 3(1): 1–12.
ERIKSON, K. T. (1967) “A Comment on Disguised Observation in Sociology.” Social Prob-
lems 14: 366–373.
FITZGERALD, M. H. (2004) “Punctuated Equilibrium, Moral Panics, and the Ethical Review
Process.” Journal of Academic Ethics 2(4): 315–338.
GORRITI, G. (1991) “Terrorism, Research and Public Policy: An Experience, Some
Thoughts.” Terrorism and Political Violence 3(1): 103–116.
HANSSON, S. O. (2011) “Do We Need a Special Ethics for Research?” Science and Engineer-
ing Ethics 17: 21–29.
IPHOFEN, R. (2017) “The ‘Ethics Rupture’ and the New Brunswick Declaration.”R. Iphofen
(ed.), Finding Common Ground: Consensus in Research Ethics Across the Social Sci-
ences, pp. 151–155. Bingley: Emerald Publishing Limited.
MILLS, T., MASSOUMI, N., and MILLER, D. (2019) “The Ethics of Researching ‘Terrorism’ and
Political Violence: A Sociological Approach.” Contemporary Social Science. https://doi.
org/10.1080/21582041.2019.1660399.
SCHRAG, Z. (2010) Ethical Imperialism. Institutional Review Boards and the Social Sciences,
1965–2009. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
SCHRAG, Z. (2011) “The Case against Ethics Review in the Social Sciences.” Research Ethics
7(4): 120–131.
SLUKA, J. A. (2018) “Too Dangerous for Fieldwork? The Challenge of Institutional Risk-
Management in Primary Research on Conflict, Violence and ‘Terrorism’.” Contempo-
rary Social Science. https://doi.org/10.1080/21582041.2018.1498534.
VAN DEN HOONARD, W. (2011) The Seduction of Ethics. Transforming the Social Sciences.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
VON HOFFMAN, N. (1970) “Sociological Snoopers and Journalistic Moralizers.” Trans-action 7
(7): 4–6.
WHITEHEAD, J. (2004) “Stopping Clinical Trials by Design.” Nature Reviews Drug Discovery
3(11): 973–977.