Recent Developments in The Philosophy of Category Theory: Ralf Krömer
Recent Developments in The Philosophy of Category Theory: Ralf Krömer
Ralf Krömer
My view in 2007
I undecidable (Gödel)
I In particular, ZFC could be inconsistent
I but this could only be proved by finding one day a
contradiction.
I Bourbaki: trust in the consistency of ZFC on “empirical”
grounds (no contradiction discovered so far)
“In the 40 years since one has formulated with sufficient precision the
axioms of [set theory] and has drawn consequences from them in the
most various domains of mathematics, one never met with
contradiction, and one has the right to hope that there never will be
one. (. . . ) We do not pretend that this opinion rests on something
else than experience.” [Bourbaki(1954)]
“As far as sets occur and are necessary in mathematics (at least in
the mathematics of today, including all of Cantor’s set theory), they
are sets of integers, or of rational numbers (. . . ), or of real numbers
(. . . ), or of functions of real numbers (. . . ), etc.; when theorems about
all sets (or the existence of sets) in general are asserted, they can
always be interpreted without any difficulty to mean that they hold for
sets of integers as well as for sets of real numbers, etc. (. . . ). This
concept of set, however, according to which a set is anything
obtainable from the integers (or some other well defined objects) by
iterated application of the operation “set of”, and not something
obtained by dividing the totality of all existing things into two
categories, has never led to any antinomy whatsoever; that is, the
perfectly “naive” and uncritical working with this concept of set has so
far proved completely self-consistent.” [Gödel(1947), p. 518f]
Grothendieck universes
“It is certain that one needs to be able to consider categories,
functors, homomorphisms of functors and so on . . . as mathematical
objects on which one can quantify freely and which one can consider
as in turn forming the elements of some set. Here are two reasons for
this necessity: to be able to carry out for functors the types of
properly mathematical reasoning (induction and so on. . . ), without
endless complications installed in order to save the fiction of the
functor which is nothing but a specific metamathematical object;
because the sets of functors or of functorial homomorphisms, with the
various natural structures which one has on them (group of
automorphisms of a given functor and so on) obviously are
mathematically important, and because many structures
(semi-simplicial structures and so on) are most naturally expressed
by considering the new objects to be defined as functors.”
“The well known fact that some basic constructions applied to large
categories take us out of the universe seems to me to indicate that
the constructions are not yet properly presented. The discovery of
proper presentations is too difficult, though, for all work on these
constructions to wait for it.” [Isbell(1966)]
“Our intuition tells us that whenever two categories exist in our world,
then so does the corresponding category of all natural
transformations between the functors from the first category to the
second.” [Lawvere(1966), 9]
Feferman replies:
(R1) Form the category of all structures of a given kind, e.g. the
category Grp of all groups, Top of all topological spaces, and
Cat of all categories.
(R2) Form the category B A of all functors from A to B, where A, B are
any two categories.
(R3) Establish the existence of the natural numbers N , and carry out
familiar operations on objects a, b, . . . and collections A, B, . . .,
including the T Qof {a, b}, (a, b), A ∪ B, A ∩ B, A − B,
S formation
A × B, B A , A, A, Bx [x ∈ A], etc.
Ernst’s result
I M. Ernst [Ernst(2015)] showed that “unlimited category
theory” in the sense of [Feferman(2013)] is inconsistent,
i.e. that presupposing (R1)-(R3) leads to a contradiction.
I Ernst’s strategy: build a proof in analogy to the proof that
there can be no set of all sets using Cantor’s theorem.
I Cantor’s theorem says that there is no surjection between
any set and its powerset; established by a diagonal
argument
I In Ernst’s proof (relying on Lawvere’s 1969 work on
transporting diagonal arguments to the language of
category theory) the set-theoretical notion of “surjection” is
replaced by a notion of onto mapping in a
category-theoretic sense, and “set of all sets” and
“powerset” by corresponding objects in a certain category
of graphs.
Recent developments in the philosophy of category theory
The debate up to 2007 My view in 2007 Ernst’s recent result Consequences for my approach
Some comments
Bénabou, J.
Fibered categories and the foundations of naive category
theory.
J. Symb. Log. 50 (1985)(1): 10–37.
MR87h:18001.
Bourbaki, N.
Foundations of mathematics for the working
mathematician.
J. Symb. Log. 14 (1949): 1–8.
—.
Eléments de mathématique. Première partie. Livre I:
Théorie des ensembles. Chapitre 1: Description de la
mathématique formelle. Chapitre 2: Théorie des
ensembles.
Paris: Hermann, 1954.