Buchdahl - Philosophical Basis of Physics
Buchdahl - Philosophical Basis of Physics
Contemporary Physics
Publication details, including instructions for authors and
subscription information:
http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/tcph20
To cite this article: Gerd Buchdahl (1962) The philosophical basis of physics, Contemporary
Physics, 3:5, 382-394, DOI: 10.1080/00107516208205316
Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the
“Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis,
our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to
the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions
and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,
and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content
should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources
of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims,
proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever
or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or
arising out of the use of the Content.
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any
substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,
systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms
& Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/
terms-and-conditions
The Philosophical Basis of Physics
by GERD BUCHDAHL
Cambridge University
Our first reaction to the very suggestion that physics is in need of a basis is
probably much like that of Sir Oliver Lodge when he wrote (in M a n and the
Universe, 1908, p. 50):
“ To say that a system does not rest upon one special fact is not to impugn its
stability. The body of scientific truth rests on no solitary material fact or group of
facts, but on a basis of harmony and consistency between facts: its support and ultimate
sanction is of no material character.”
So we might insist that physics is not in need of a basis, and that the paradigm
Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 12:35 24 November 2013
of something ‘ supported ’, either from above or below, is the wrong one. But
perhaps this is a misunderstanding; we cannot tell until we have seen this picture
in its historical setting. Perhaps that also will teach us something about the
possible justification of the picture, though we shall see that there is an important
element of insight in Lodge’s remark.
The history of science reveals all three approaches. The works of the great
17th century methodologists and philosophers display the first brilliant sketches
defining the various methodological principles and precepts, and illustrating
the corresponding procedural routes. And because they come to it fresh and
with an open mind, their writings for ever repay renewed study; the doctrines
which they develop, and which later generations have turned into hardened
dogmas, we are here able to observe emerging and growing in their proper
context. They often therefore yield insights denied to us when concentrating
solely upon the more normal developments of later ages. Descartes’ scientific
and metascientific writing offers one of the best illustrations of the rich variety
of ideas introduced into the field of methodology and logic at that time.
Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 12:35 24 November 2013
A. Deductive approaches
“ Apprehension of first principles ” and “ mathematization of physics ”
instance showing how this method may be understood to work in detail; the steps
in his discovery of the law of refraction, often called ‘ Snell’s Law’, are as follows.
Let us assume the discussion of refraction in terms of ‘ rays of light ’; mere
observation then will yield the (qualitative) information that the ray is broken
towards the normal to the interface between the media when entering the
‘ denser ’ medium (e.g. air into water). We now feed into this information an
account of the ‘hypothetical mechanism’ (and Descartes refers to it expressly as
a mere hypothesis) in terms of which we describe the passage of light. Descartes’
account here mentions an all-pervasive ether possessing a particulate structure,
the passage of light being defined as the passage of a ‘ shock-wave ’ travelling
from the luminous body to the illuminated surface. As the ether is not ‘ corn-
Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 12:35 24 November 2013
pressible’, the wave moves with ‘ infinite speed’. This is still difficult to
understand, for the concepts are not sufficiently clear. We shall therefore dig
still more deeply: to this end we must consider the passage of any natural power
be it a wave or a particle.
So far all is qualitative. Descartes now ‘ tightens ’ his account by intro-
ducing a geometrical model to derive the law of refraction quantitatively.
In other words, he develops a conceptual model to which he then applies those
general laws of motion which he had already developed elsewhere and which
he believed to be of very general application. His model does not exactly
reproduce the (already hypothetical) structure; the reason is that with the
absolute freedom of genius he considers the matter in terms of the motion of a
particle, of whose laws he has a knowledge which he lacks concerning the
hypothetical wave motion. The derivation is not ‘ pure ’ : there is (as in most
‘ real ’ scientific situations) considerable ‘ fitting ’ of the account to the desired
result; we need not reproduce it in any further detail. Yet the general procedure
is clear: the introducing of the hypothetical mechanism; the search for the
fundamental operative process, the tightening of this in terms of a quantitative
model, reasoning round which ultimately leads us back to the desired ‘ law ’
accounting for the qualitative and quantitative relationships. There are here
the essential ingredients of a genuine ‘ motion ’ from ‘ effect ’ to ‘ cause ’ : the
tentative introduction of a theoretical schema (making it once more possible to
‘ reason deductively ’) ; the rapid shuffling backwards and forwards between
phenomena and explanation; the ’side-reference to external principles; the
employment of models not necessarily isomorphic with the putative hypothetical
or theoretical structure.
The statement that this was an instance of a ‘ motion ’ from effect to cause,
needs some qualification. There is ‘ motion ’ in that direction only in the sense
that we began with the set of obskved pairs of angles of incidence and refraction,
rising from this to a consideration of the qualitative behaviour of light rays; and
we ended with the formula-‘ the hypothesis ’ in accordance with which the
values of the angles of incidence and refraction are computable. However,
there was clearly no step-by-step ascent in mechanical fashion from the explican-
dum to the hypothesis! Less still should the phrase ‘ motion from effect to
cause ’ mislead us into thinking that here is a method which guarantees a deduction
of the explanation from the explicandum. (Scientists often speak of a certain
law, e.g. the law of constant proportions, as having been inferred from certain
experimental results, a phrase which frequently causes much misunderstanding.)
But as already mentioned, Descartes’ notion of analysis also covered-in addition
C.P. 1B
3 86 Gerd Buchdahl
account for a set of data, this would give us formal validity. Likewise, if an
hypothesis can be shown to imply a consequence contrary to fact, it is thereby
formally invalidated. But between these logical cornerstones there lies the
vaguer though more substantial region of positive affirmation. If the hypothesis
has led to verified data; and if it has not been falsified; and if it fits into a more
general network of other non-falsified hypotheses; in short if it comes up to the
standards of procedural performance discussed in section I, above: are we then
' entitled ' to ' infer ' that this hypothesis holds universally ?
At the outset, we must recognize that in recent times vital objections have
been raised against the whole conception of non-deductive inference as such:
objections which if sustained would go a long way towards showing that our
question was misconceived, even senseless, and with it the whole baneful notion
of a ' basis '. Moreover this suggestion is supported by the consideration that
no satisfactory answer to our question has ever really been proposed. These
objections occur in two versions, the first of which is due to Karl Popper, the
second to Gilbert Ryle, both representing a movement of considerable contem-
porary thought. (4)
(1) Since retroductive and inductive inferences are formally invalid, we cannot
thus define at all the form taken by scientific reasoning. Instead we need
to replace this by a formally valid inference schema, which involves a falsifica-
tion procedure, according to which a scientific test can yield an assured result
only if (and in the sense that) it disconjirms a proposed hypothesis. It is then
only a ' convention ' to hold on to an hypothesis so long as it has not been
disconfirmed; but as such, non-negative tests have no logical significance for
a verification-procedure. (5)
(2) This is a slightly more extreme version of the first, and holds that we should
disabuse ourselves of the idea that scientists at work ever pass on to the
business of making an inference of any such kind (excepting deductive
explications). Rather, they merely show that certain hypotheses work by
showing them working, i.e. through leading to verifiable consequences. We
can show our hypothesis working-i.e. observe it as ' work-in-progress ',
but we do not in addition pass on to any sort of inference: ' . . . therefore it
is true ' . ( 6 )
I am not sure that either of these objections to non-deductive inference are
really serious. Let us consider them briefly in turn. T h e first and the
methodological prescription which it entails, seem to possess a certain plausibility
for many scientists. This is due, I think, only to a lack of realisation of the
The Philosophical Basts of Physics 387
3. INDUCTIVE
INFERENCE
applies to ‘ real things ’ solely because we autonomously select only those features
of the physical world which agree with the mathematical ‘ archetypes ’. (Essay,
iv. 4, 6). This doctrine which has had a far-reaching influence down to our
own days, was epitomized in Kant’s dictum that every ‘‘ systematic study of
nature contains only as much science properly speaking as there is in it mathe-
matics applied to its data ” (Metaphysical Foundations of Science, Preface.(*)).
For Locke, this view had certain scepticist consequences. For it seemed to
follow that all ‘ knowledge ’ based on the empirical observation of material bodies
was “but judgement and opinion, not knowledge and certainty” (Essay, iv. 12.10).
“ Certainty and demonstration are things we must not, in these matters pretend
to ”, he wrote (Essay, iv. 3. 26); and his terminology suggests (and his argument
implies) that this is because information gathered through ‘ observation and
experiment ’ does not come up to the ideal of yielding necessary connexions ’
found in the ‘ demonstrations ’ of the mathematicians.
This again is a ‘ philosophical complaint ’, and not a ‘ scientific ’ one. Locke
was fully aware of the success of Newton’s Principia. His preoccupation is
with epistemological questions ; he struggles to hammer out an adequate con-
ception of ‘ scientific knowledge ’, a struggle which is brought on by the conflict
that he seems to find between the paradigm of mathematical knowledge on the
one hand, and what he calls experience ’ on the other.
The origins of this conflict lie in the Lockean conception of ‘ experience ’
as being equivalent to the perception and combination of ‘ ideas ’. These ideas
he views each as being quasi-self-contained logical ‘ atoms ’ ; they “ enter the
mind by the senses simple and unmixed” (Essay, ii. 2. 1.) Hence, complex
ideas (and most of our ideas, including ‘ generalizations ’, are complex) must be
compounded, the result of a ‘ subjective ’ synthesis.
Though based on small psychological evidence, this story is a myth for the
following doctrine :
( a ) All knowledge is based on experience. This entails that the character
of the known is essentially determined by the character of the ‘ process ’
of knowing, an important mark of which is that the knower is able to
consider the known as it is presented ‘ in itself ’, apart from all relations
to other knowable objects (or ideas). This doctrine of the ‘ presentational
immediacy ’ of the object of knowledge, together with the premisses just
This is however not Locke’s point. For he would certainly grant as much but
add that ‘ in experience ’ qualities are only united ‘ here-and-now ’, whereas
the unity which we mean by an ‘ object ’ entails a combination which holds
universally and with necessity (what Locke calls ‘ the real essence ’)-once more
a conceptual matter (Essay, iv. 12. 9). And this kind of unity is certainly not
‘ given ’ but is “ made voluntarily ” (Essay, ii. 12. 2), and hence though certainly
‘ real ’ is not ‘ objective ’. As he puts it at iv. 3. 14 of the Essay:
“ Let our complex idea of any species of substances be what it will, we can hardly,
from the simple ideas contained in it, certainly determine the necessary coexistence of
any other quality whatever. Our knowledge in all these enquiries reaches very little
farther than our experience.”
This, then, is the background to the problem with which philosophers since
the 17th century have been wrestling, and I think we understand it better by
tracing it back to its origins. What is the foundation of that relation (called by
the 17th and 18th century philosophers ‘ necessary connection ’, though we
might want to generalize this) in virtue of which we transcend the given moment
of ‘ presentational immediacy ’ (to use Whitehead’s term) ; more generally even:
what makes it possible-in the sense of logical justification-to speak of ‘ external
objects ’, of ‘ objective ’, lawlike connections ?
4. THE“ FOUNDATION
OF SCIENTIFIC
INFERENCE
”: SOME HISTORIC SOLUTIONS.
It would be possible to approach such questions in various ways.
(1) Investigate the general philosophical nature of such questions. For instance
we might pursue the consequences of arguments involving considerations of
philosophical paradigm-cases (cf. end of section 111) and reflect on the nature
and power of this type of philosophical treatment. For instance: what kind
of considerations, and what sort of answer do conceptual questions deserve,
once we have severed them (as we have found necessary) from their material
basis ?(9)
(2) Investigate the nature, meaning and logic of concepts like ‘induction ’,
‘ inference ’, ‘ law ’, ‘ necessity ’, etc.
(3) Ask what generates the idea of an objective causal connection, and what is
the general justification of this idea.
It is only during our own century that a conscious start has been made on
the exploration of the first two of our questions ;whilst the remaining question set
the tone in terms of which most philosophical systems of the 17th and 19th
centuries, from Hume through Kant, have debated this matter. Nor should
we think that their perspectives were necessarily fashioned by intellectual
The Philosophical Basis of Physics 391
being such as it presents itself; and the thing is deprived of its arbitrariness by
showing that without the relation we could not speak of a scientific experience
at all; not a very surprising conclusion since Kant has so contrived his analysis
that what his sceptical doubt has taken away from the observational data, his
definition of knowledge must subsequently put back again.
Moreover, the ‘ necessitarian ’ character of the concept of relation is made
good also in a second sense by the argument that the character of the combination-
being ‘ spontaneous ’-would be wholly ‘ subjective ’ unless we conceive it in a
‘ determinate way ’. But that we so conceive it, is actually entailed by an analysis
of the character of even the simplest experience: say of the content of our thought
which asserts ‘ This is so ’: or, ‘ This follows that ’; or, This is simultaneous
with that ’. Thus, in the very conception of an objective state of affairs ’ (e.g.
of a ship going down a stream) there is contained the thought that your ideas-
antecedently conceived atomistically, and ‘ loose and separate ’-in the required
act of combination must be considered as related in a determinate order; the
model for this order being a ‘ rule ’ or ‘ function ’, the paradigm for which is
once again the formula of mathematics. (As with Locke and Hume, this ‘ act
of synthesis ’ is, I think, a philosophical myth, which, when translated into a
logical terminology, can be seen to yield some important results.) The specific
form of such a principle expressing a ‘ determinate order ’ would then depend
upon the type of experimental proposition involved. Thus, the statement
X is followed by Y ’ carries the built-in categorical form expressed in the
principle that ‘ everything that happens presupposes something which determines
it in accordance with a rule ’, the so-called principle of causation.?
This was however a costly answer. Remember that we began with the
complaint that whilst we could ‘ observe ’ united qualities in the moment of
presentational immediacy, we required a justification of the assumed feat of
universal and necessitarian connection,-or better : of this concept of connection;
a concept which entailed transcendence beyond the ‘ specious present ’. But
now we find that in order to guarantee the absolute tightness of the argument to
the ‘ reality ’ of the relation, the synthesis-Kant’s necessary synthesis-must
7 It will be noted that when thus stated, the principle is not inconsistent with the
statistical aspect of contemporary quantum physics, since the form and nature of the ‘ rule ’
is left open. It was an historical accident that Kant thought that the unique model for such
a rule would be Newton’slaws of motion. The correct question hence becomes :what should
be the preferred paradigms for causal action? In this way we can see some of the com-
temporary perplexities concerning causation and indeterminism might receive some
enlightening re-interpretations.
The Philosophical Basis of Physics 393
generation of such forms on the part of the creative scientist be counted as such.
On the other hand, he simply offered his readers the consideration that the
discovery and verification of actual individual laws (as contrasted with the
postulation of the concept of lawlikeness) is purely a matter of application of
the methods of the scientists; methods involving as a matter of fact the procedures
of axiomtization and systematization, and the application of regulative ideas,
which we met with in Section I-the whole thing becoming thereby, it will be
seen, a slightly circular procedure.
The passage of this episode in the history of the problem is fairly typical of
other first rate philosophical problems, or of the same problem in different
epochs ; except that the Hume-Kant case-study offers us the supreme example
both of magnificent brilliance of performance yielding novel insights for all time
(achievements as well as failure being all the more obvious to us given our know-
ledge of hindsight), and also a clear picture of the mode whereby a relentless
pursuit of a problem when genuinely metaphysical comes to evaporate in a
peculiar way.
In the sequel one may discern one or two pronounced tendencies emerging
from the Hume-Kant ruin. There is on the one hand a strong feeling that it
isn’t so much that the problem of induction (and the related one of ‘ necessary
connexion ’) is insoluble, but rather that it is bereft of any genuine significance.
The most one will concede is that there is a definite meaning to the concept of
law, adding perhaps, like the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus, that
“ If there were a law of causality, it might run: ‘ There are laws of nature ’. But
of course one can not say this: it shows itself. In the terminology of Hertz one might
say: Only lawlike connexions are thinkable.” (op. cit., 6. 36-6. 361).
It will be seen that this rather Kantian passage (written over 40 years ago)
already contains the germ of the ‘ procedural ’ or ‘ work-in-progress ’ doctrines,
assuming that we can make sense of the notion of lawlike form. On the other
side, there are still many who persist in the less spectacular and somewhat tedious
task of elucidating the principles and modes of a justification of induction,
though deliberately avoiding for this purpose the concept of necessary connection,
and largely operating with some version of the idea of ‘uniformity’.(14) The
first group has a tendency to subside into more or less historical accounts of the
various forms of successful scientific argumentation; (15) the second aims at
formalization and quantification of certain types of argument, and particularly
emphasises the related problems of probability and statistical reasoning.
Between these, is anything of philosophical (as contrasted with technical)
importance still left?
3 94 Gerd Buchdahl
The Author:
First studied engineering, and after some years, spent as a structural design engineer,
he succumbed to his interest in general philosophical matters by acquiring graduate and
postgraduate qualifications in philosophy. Between 1948-58 he built up the School of
History and Philosophy of Science in the University of Melbourne. He has been Visiting
Lecturer in Philosophy of Science at Oxford University. At present he is Lecturer in
Philosophy of Science, and in charge of History and Philosophy of Science and the
Whipple Science Museum, University of Cambridge, as well as Assistant Lecturer in
Moral Science, King’s College, Cambridge.