Self, No Self
Self, No Self
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's
objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford
New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid
Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto
With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala
Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey
Ukraine Vietnam
Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford
University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate
reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above
should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above
You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same
condition on any acquirer
Notes on Contributors xi
Introduction
Mark Siderits, Evan Thompson, Dan Zahavi 1
Index 333
Preface
GEORGES DREYFUS was the first Westerner to receive the title of Geshe
after spending fifteen years studying in Tibetan Buddhist monasteries. He then
entered the University of Virginia where he received his PhD. in the History
of Religions program. He is currently Professor of Religion of the Department
of Religion at Williams College. His publications include Recognizing
Reality: Dharmakirti and his Tibetan Interpreters (SUNY Press 1997), The
Svatantrika-Prasangika Distinction (co-edited with Sara McClintock,
Wisdom 2003), and The Sound of Two Hands Clapping: The Education of a
Tibetan Buddhist Monk(University of California Press 2003), as well as many
articles on various aspects of Buddhist philosophy and Tibetan culture.
When I see a bright blue sky and hear the wind stirring the leaves, there is
awareness of the blue color and the rattling sound. Is there also the awareness
of my seeing the blue and hearing the sound? Does being conscious
necessarily involve being self-conscious in some sense? And if it does, would
this count as evidence for the existence of a self? These are the sorts of
questions that the papers in this volume are meant to explore. The
explorations embarked on here employ tools and techniques drawn from a
number of distinct philosophical traditions: phenomenology, analytic
philosophy of mind, and classical Indian and Buddhist philosophy. While
these traditions have all investigated the questions of the self and the reflexive
nature of awareness, they have for the most part done so independently of one
another. So it might be best to begin by attempting to develop a common
framework within which to locate the different approaches they employ.
To ask whether, when I am aware of blue I am also aware of my
awareness of blue, is to ask whether consciousness is necessarily reflexive or
self-intimating. To use the latter expression is to do two things: to suggest that
being conscious is a matter of being intimate or ‘in touch’, of bringing the
object into proximity with the self understood as what is ‘within’, and to invite
the question whether the reflexivity at issue involves anything that might
properly be called my self. To start with the second point: it might be said that
consciousness' being reflexive would be no different than a statement's being
self-referential. The statement ‘This sentence contains five words’ can be
described as reflexive just in the sense that in assessing its truth we need look
at nothing else besides the very statement itself. In this case the reflexivity of
the reference relation is nothing more than this binary relation's involving not
the normal two relata but just one. If the thesis that consciousness is reflexive
or self-intimating were understood this way, there would be no suggestion that
the thesis is at all connected to the claim that there is a self. To think it is
would be to conflate the quite distinct expressions ‘myself’ and ‘my self’.
MARK SIDERITS, EVAN THOMPSON, DAN ZAHAVI
Some will welcome such a diagnosis, since it would mean that we can
investigate the reflexivity thesis without having to enter into the murky
question of the self's existence and nature. Among them will be those who
deny the existence of a self on other grounds. But some will find this
dismissal all too quick. They will claim that what we find when we carefully
scrutinize the self-intimating nature of our states of awareness is quite
different from the simple self-linking exhibited by self-referential statements
and the like. If it is true that consciousness is aware of itself not just in bouts
of introspective reflection but always, then perhaps this serves as a clue to the
nature of subjectivity and hence of the subject. The idea is that a careful
investigation of the self-intimating nature of consciousness will bring into
clearer focus the phenomenal character of experience, thereby allowing us to
discern an otherwise elusive common element in all our conscious states. It is
widely held that what is distinctive about experiential states is their ‘what-it-
is-like-ness’ or phenomenal character: there is something it is like to be in the
state of seeing that blue color, and it is the presence of this phenomenal
character that marks the difference between a sentient being and a mere color-
detection mechanism. The present suggestion is that the reflexivity of
consciousness is at least partly constitutive of what-it-is-like-ness, and that
this in turn tells us something important about that for which it is so like, the
subject of phenomenal states.
Critics may still have their doubts. The suggestion just mooted involves
what can be described as a move from subjectivity to subject, and one might
question the legitimacy of such a move. One might agree that what is
distinctive about consciousness is precisely its subjective or phenomenal
character, its ‘what-it-is-like-ness’, yet wonder why this should require us to
supply something to serve as the subject to which the seemings are presented.
Even if it is granted that ‘what-it-is-like’ demands completion with a dative—
‘what-it-is-like-for’—it might still be said that the reflexive nature of
consciousness allows us to fill that slot without invoking anything that could
be called a self. For, such a critic would insist, the consciousness whose self-
intimation is at least partly constitutive of the experience of seeing blue, can
play that role for that experience, while another consciousness fills a similar
role for the experience of hearing the rattling of the leaves. These being
distinct episodes of consciousness, the move to a self as unifying subject of
distinct experiences is illegitimate.
INTRODUCTION
This little debate brings out something that might have seemed obvious all
along: that before we can investigate a possible linkage between the thesis that
consciousness is reflexive and the question of the existence of a self, we must
enter the murky waters and clarify just what a self might be. The parties to the
above debate hold what are sometimes called egological and non-egological
views of consciousness respectively. But what is this ‘ego’ or self about
whose possible involvement in and disclosure through consciousness and self-
consciousness they are debating? It is generally agreed that each of us has a
sense of self: the (perhaps somewhat elusive) feeling of being the particular
person one is. It might seem that the best way to answer the present question
would be by exploring this sense and trying to find its underlying structure.
And much of the Western philosophical discussion of the issue has followed
this path. But the Indian tradition suggests otherwise. Indian philosophical
investigations of the self begin with the suspicion that the sense of self that
everyone seems to have might be importantly mistaken—indeed that this
might be the cause of our being bound to the wheel of saṃsāra or
beginningless rebirth. So while our commonly acknowledged sense of self
might be worth investigating, we should not assume that doing so will lead
directly to an understanding of what the self is.
A word might be in order at this point concerning the soteriological
concerns that stand behind much of the Indian philosophical tradition. In this
tradition it is often claimed that one should study philosophy in order to
overcome the ignorance that results in bondage to a cycle of potentially never-
ending rebirths: philosophy will help us find whatever truth lies behind our
possibly mistaken views about our identity. Since very few philosophers today
subscribe to the view that we are trapped on a wheel of saṃsāra, this fact
about the Indian context might make it seem implausible that there could be
much fruitful dialogue between the Indian and Western traditions on the topic
of the self. But this response might be over-hasty. For it might be that at least
some of the concerns that motivate discussions of the self in the Western
tradition are, at bottom, similar in nature. To look for the self is to look for
what might be thought of as the essence of the person. And essences are often
thought to determine what something is good for. Knowledge of the self is
sometimes sought because of the promise that such knowledge might help
resolve concerns about the meaningfulness of the lives of persons. Now, such
concerns might be thought to stem from the realization of human finitude.
And those Indian philosophers who see persons as subject to a process of
MARK SIDERITS, EVAN THOMPSON, DAN ZAHAVI
rebirth that is without beginning and possibly without end seem to be denying
human finitude. But this overlooks two points: rebirth also means re-death,
and endless repetition can drain things of all meaning. While the ethical
dimension is often left out of current discussions of the self, it might be an
unacknowledged presence that helps shape the debate all the same. That
Indian philosophers explicitly thematized this dimension might actually give
their deliberations added value.
Initially we might classify views about the self as falling into three broad
types: substantialist, non-substantialist and non-self theories. While non-self
theorists deny the existence of a self, substantialist and non-substantialist self
theorists affirm its existence but disagree about its nature. A substantialist
view is one that takes the self to be a substance or property-bearer, the
substrate in which different properties are all located at one time or, for
substances thought to persist, at different times. Taking as a model the
common-sense idea of a thing as an entity that bears a variety of qualities,
substantialist theorists see the self as at least minimally the subject of
experience, that entity to which conscious states are given. It may then be
asked whether the self ever occurs devoid of the property of being conscious.
Descartes is generally understood to have claimed not, thereby committing to
the view that we are conscious even in dreamless sleep and when comatose.
Others hold instead that consciousness is but one of a variety of properties that
the self bears at different times. Among its other properties are typically those
that also make the self the agent of actions, and thus a fit object of moral
appraisal. But the key point for our present concerns is that, according to one
form of substantialist view, consciousness stands to the self as red color does
to the pot: as a quality to a substance in which it contingently inheres.
Non-substantialist self theorists hold that the self is not a substance or
property-bearer standing in relation to a consciousness that is in some sense
distinct from it. (Note that even a substantialist who holds that the self is
essentially conscious, while claiming that the self never fails to be conscious,
thinks of the self as a substance, with consciousness as its essential nature—
hence belonging to a distinct ontological category from that of consciousness.)
Instead the non-substantialist sees the self as just consciousness itself. Non-
substantialists disagree over just how many selves there are, with the Indian
school of Advaita Vedānta famously claiming that there is just one (and that
this is the only thing there is). But they agree that the self is something that is
just of the nature of consciousness, and that we are mistaken in attributing
INTRODUCTION
agency, or any other property that might involve variation, to the self. The self
is just ‘the witness’, or perhaps better, ‘a witnessing’.
It is open to such self theorists (as it also is to substantialists) to claim that
the self is momentary, coming into existence with each occurrence of
cognition in a mental stream and then going out of existence, ordinarily to be
replaced by another. But self theorists have largely avoided anything like
Galen Strawson's ‘pearl self’ view, according to which a self lasts only as long
as does an individual state of consciousness. This avoidance stems at least in
part from widespread agreement that, in addition to serving as the subject of
conscious states, a self should also explain various diachronic unities. These
unities might include that of a person across different stages in a life (or even
across lives), and that involved in agency for projects that unfold over time.
But the central unity involved in these discussions is the unity involved in the
ability of an experiencer to place the current content of consciousness
alongside past and potential future contents in a single stream. It is of course
possible for a non-substantialist self theorist to claim that all such diachronic
unities can be accounted for without supposing the self to persist. In doing so,
however, they would be moving closer to the non-self view.
While the non-self view is hardly unknown in the West (where its best
known champions are Hume and Parfit), it has been most extensively explored
in the Indian Buddhist tradition. In that context it begins with the common
concern that our ordinary sense of self is the source of a certain sort of deep-
seated suffering. But rather than say that our mistake lies in identifying with
the wrong thing (e.g. the body), or the wrong kind of thing (e.g. a substance),
it locates the error in identification as such. Buddhist monastic practice is
generally aimed at eradication of all identification or ‘appropriation’
(upadāna). Buddhist philosophical practice contributes to this by attempting
to prove that there is no entity that might serve as the referent of ‘I’, and to
explain how the belief that there is such an entity might have arisen. Various
strategies are used in different schools, but one common element is an attempt
to show that nothing persists in the way that a self would presumably have to.
Like Hume, Buddhist philosophers typically point to the fleeting nature of all
we find when we carefully observe the inner states of the person. That we
should nonetheless believe there to be a persisting subject of those states is
explained by the example of the row of ants: what from a distance seems to be
a single enduring thing turns out on closer examination to be a large collection
of distinct things each of which is replaced by a new member at the next
MARK SIDERITS, EVAN THOMPSON, DAN ZAHAVI
moment. The claim is that the ‘I’ is posited to explain the felt unity among the
inner states, when that feeling of unity can instead be explained by appeal to
our cognitive limitations: there seems to us to be a single thing, the row of
ants, only when we look from afar.
This kind of approach to defending the non-self view might be criticized
in a variety of different ways. One might, for instance, challenge the
assumption that the self must persist, or one might argue that wholes such as
the row of ants do exist as persisting things even as their parts are replaced.
Perhaps more fundamentally, one might ask whether the search for the self
should be construed as the search for an entity of any kind. There is an activity
that is commonly called ‘seeking one's self’, and this is not the search for
some entity, but for some core set of convictions and other dispositions that
gives structure and unity to one's life-plans and projects. In recent discussions
of the self, the concept of a narrative self has figured prominently, and that
concept may be useful here. The basic idea is that as agents acting in the
world in time, we require some scheme for fitting individual affordances into
an overall hierarchy that facilitates prioritizing our responses. This is provided
when we view our lives as narratives that we are simultaneously living out
and making up. By viewing ourselves as both the author and the central
character in the story of our lives, we achieve the ability to formulate long-
term plans and projects, work out subordinate goals, and thus avoid paralysis
each time we are presented with a new opportunity for action. If this is true of
us, it would explain why the question of personal identity is so commonly
taken not as the question of the necessary and sufficient conditions for
diachronic identity of persons, but instead as the characterization question:
‘Who am I?’ understood as a request for an account of core values and
commitments. This leads to the question whether the search for the self should
not be understood as just the attempt to answer the characterization question.
If so then the non-self theory might be readily dismissed on the grounds that it
is simply asking the wrong question.
To this challenge, the non-self theorist will respond that to simply
acquiesce in the characterization question is to leave untouched its underlying
presupposition: that there is an entity that is both the author and the central
character in one's life-story. It is this presupposition that requires proper
philosophical scrutiny, using the tools of metaphysical inquiry. Is there a core
self that might fill the role marked out for it by the characterization question?
Indeed, it is not just the non-self view that is threatened by a narrative self-
INTRODUCTION
the debate. Self-illumination theorists pointed out that the lamp that
illuminates the objects in the room is itself illuminated. Other-illumination
theorists responded that it makes no sense to say that light is illuminated: to be
the sort of thing that might be illuminated, something must also be such that it
can exist in the dark, and light cannot exist in the dark. But the use of the
illumination metaphor suggests an answer to a different question: why did this
debate take place in the Indian tradition while the issue has not been much
discussed in modern Western philosophy? One suggestion is that this has to
do with the status of representationalist theories of perception in the two
traditions. More specifically, the suggestion is that when representationalist
theories of perception come to be widely accepted, they bring with them a
view of consciousness that may make the reflexivity thesis appear self-
evident.
The conceptual resources available to us to explain just what
consciousness is are extremely limited. To be conscious, we may say, is to be
aware, to be awake, to cognize, but these are all just near-synonyms. In these
circumstances, a widely used metaphor may play an important role in guiding
our thought along certain lines. When we think of consciousness in terms of
the notions of disclosure or intimation, we may be thinking of it as what
brings the outside world within. The metaphor of illumination suggests
something different. Illumination is something that takes place outside. When
I turn on the light in the room, the illuminated objects stay where they are,
apart from me. But now that they are illuminated I can see where they are, and
what they are, and can put that information to use. Illumination makes them
available to me as items of use. This metaphor would be perfectly acceptable
to someone who held a direct realist theory of perception. It would fit in with
a conception of perceiving according to which consciousness goes out in the
world by way of the sense organs and grasps objects as they themselves are.
Of course the metaphor is also acceptable to someone who thinks of
perception along representationalist lines: consciousness is then what
illuminates the inner theater of the mind, thereby making visible the image of
the object that has been fashioned by the sense organs and brought into the
theater. While direct realist theories of perception do have their supporters,
they do not enjoy the broadest support today; the representationalist picture is
thought by many to better cohere with what we now know about perceptual
processing and the properties of physical objects that are involved in that
processing. But classical Indian philosophers engaged in a spirited debate over
INTRODUCTION
direct realism and its rivals (representationalism and subjective idealism). And
to a direct realist it is not obvious that all conscious states have a subjective
character. For them, to be conscious is just to have a state that represents the
object.
If this is right, it will come as no surprise that among the Indian self
theorists, it was the substantialists who held the other-illumination view.
Substantialists see the self as ontologically distinct from consciousness. If
what consciousness does is represent the object, then it may no longer seem
mandatory to hold that conscious states have a subjective character. If that to
which conscious states represent the object is a self, then given that the self is
distinct from those states, it seems possible that the self might be informed
about the object without being informed about the state whereby it came to
have that information. Of course Descartes was a substantialist, and is widely
taken to have held the self-illumination view. But Descartes also held that the
self is essentially conscious. This, together with his embrace of a
representationalist theory of perception, push him in the direction of the
metaphor of intimacy or presencing, whereby one cannot fail to be conscious
of what is closest and most immediately present. Other substantialists, by
making consciousness a contingent property of the self, leave the door open to
holding that the self is only occasionally aware of its cognitive activity (just as
it is only occasionally aware of its activity of adjusting the posture of the
body).
Non-substantialism quite naturally lines up with the self-illumination
view. The case of the non-self view is more complicated. Hume seems to have
held the reflexivity thesis (see Treatise I.iv.2.37, 137), but most Buddhist
schools are other-illuminationist. The exceptions are two schools that affirm
representationalist and subjective idealist accounts of perception respectively.
This could be taken as additional evidence concerning the role of indirect
theories of perception in suggesting a model of consciousness that is
supportive of the reflexivity thesis. More important to our present purposes,
however, is the question how these self-illuminationist non-self theorists
distinguish their view from that of a non-substantialist self-illumination
theorist who holds that the self is momentary. Buddhist self-illuminationists
are of course concerned to maintain the Buddhist orthodoxy that there is no
self, but if every occurrence of consciousness grasps itself in grasping its
object, why does that not make such an occurrence a plausible candidate for
the role of referent of ‘I’? Buddhists generally insist that our concept of the
MARK SIDERITS, EVAN THOMPSON, DAN ZAHAVI
self is that of a persisting entity, but why not suppose that it is this belief, and
not the belief in a self, that is in error? The Buddhist self-illuminationist's
answer is interesting. They claim that the concept of the self is necessarily the
concept of a subject of experience. But, they maintain, the distinction between
subject and object of experience, while necessary for thought, is nonetheless a
conceptual superimposition that distorts the nature of reality. When it is
correct to say ‘It is raining’, it would be a mistake to suppose that the state of
affairs that makes this sentence true includes an agent that performs the
activity of raining. The ‘it’, we say, is supplied just to meet the demands of
syntax. In reality there is just the single event of raining, which our grammar
then represents in terms of a two-component model. The claim is that the
demand for a distinct subject and object in experience is similar. If this is
right, then it is the non-substantialist theory that collapses into the non-self
view, and not the other way around.
Indian theorists were careful to keep separate the questions how cognition
is cognized and how the self is known to exist. While Descartes' Second
Meditation would have it that in thetic awareness of our own awareness we
are directly acquainted with the self, other views are possible. A substantialist
might hold that, in general, in perceiving a quality of a substance one
perceives that substance, or they might instead hold that, at least in certain
cases, some further cognitive operation is required in order to cognize the
substance that bears that quality. So a self-illuminationist substantialist could
hold that, while we are always directly aware of our cognitions, the self is
cognized only through introspection, or by inference or abduction. Similar
complexities attend the non-self view: one might, for instance, hold that a
cognition cognizes itself, yet still insist that further inquiry is needed to
ascertain that the occurrence of cognition is not evidence for the existence of a
self. Only in the case of self-illuminationist non-substantialism does there
seem to be a particularly tight connection between the answers to the two
questions. If one takes the self to be nothing but cognition, then one will
naturally think of reflexive awareness as cognition of the self. But since
reflexive awareness could not by itself tell us whether the cognition being
cognized endures, if the self is thought to be persisting, then once again
additional evidence is needed to make the identification go through.
The cogito was not, for instance, unknown to Indian philosophers. But unlike
Descartes, Indian self-theorists did not take it to make their case for them.
Their suspicions concerning the ubiquitous I‐sense held them back.
INTRODUCTION
people possess. In particular, it brings to the fore the link between self and
well-being: living well is thought to require that one's life be seen as having a
trajectory, a narrative arc. Metaphysical approaches, even those that affirm a
self, can at best be only half-hearted in their defense of this requirement; often
they are downright dismissive, calling the narrative self a mere useful fiction.
Yet another line of support derives from the fact that the reflexivity thesis,
with its affirmation of interiority, makes possible the sort of rich inner life at
the heart of the narrativity approach. The thought here is that even if the
reflexivity thesis fails to deliver convincing evidence that the self exists, it
does secure an inner dimension to human existence, and with it the possibility
of richly meaningful lives. The convergence of these lines of support does not
constitute a proof that the narrative approach is the right one to pursue. But it
may give us a better sense of what a total package might look like at this end
of the continuum. And this may in turn clarify what lies at the other end, as
well as what the range of intermediary positions could look like.
The papers in this volume reflect a variety of stances on this fundamental
question of whether the metaphysical approach is a viable one for philosophy,
or one that should be replaced by the (more modest?) project of working from
within human experiential reality and trying to limn its structures. Each takes
up a position in the continuum of possible views and combinations of views.
The first essay in this collection, by Joel Krueger, argues in favor of a non-self
theory that accepts the reflexivity thesis. The argument begins with a survey
of rival views that will serve as a useful introduction to themes explored by
many other papers in this volume. To be rejected, Krueger claims, are views
that deny the reflexivity thesis, since these are unable to account adequately
for the phenomenal character of consciousness. But this leaves in place a
variety of rival views, all charging that subjectivity requires a subject—that
there must be a self for which things seem a certain way—and thus that a non-
self theory is to be rejected. Krueger chooses the egological view of Dan
Zahavi as his chief target. Krueger uses an investigation of the notion of
narrative selfhood to show how one might plausibly arrive at Zahavi's idea of
the minimal self as the form of self-theory that is best supported by careful
consideration of phenomenality. Narrative approaches, Krueger argues, can
answer the characterization question, but not the identity question; they cannot
supply the sort of self that seems required if we are to at all explain our ability
to look for a story in our lives. What the careful consideration of phenomenal
character can support is a minimal self, the subject whose existence is
INTRODUCTION
Albahari agrees that our ordinary sense of self is illusory, and she shares with
the bundle theorist the need to explain how we could come to have such a
sense if it is in important respects erroneous. But she denies that the bundle
theorist's approach could succeed in showing both that the self is constructed
and that it is illusory. She distinguishes between two forms of bundle-
theoretical non-self view: the non-reflexive variety, that denies the reflexivity
thesis, and the reflexive variety that affirms that thesis. The argument against
both presupposes that the illusion of the self could be dissolved through direct
introspection, without reliance on philosophical argument or any other form of
inference. Given this stricture, the bundle theorist must hold it possible to
directly confirm in one's experience that the self is constructed, namely by
apprehending the impermanence of the cognitions that on their view constitute
the bundle. Albahari's claim is that, regardless of whether or not one takes
consciousness to be reflexive, this turns out to be impossible: no cognition
could decisively undermine the sense that, while the present cognition differs
from other cognitions in its intentional object, it does not differ in terms of
perspectival ownership—that there is a mere witnessing that is common to all
my experiential states.
This sketch raises the question how Albahari's view differs from Zahavi's.
Zahavi, it will be recalled, affirms the existence of a minimal or experiential
core self. Albahari positions herself on the side of non-self theories. Yet both
see in the self-givenness of consciousness important evidence for an enduring
perspectival owner of conscious states. The difference lies in what they take
‘self’ to mean. While Zahavi rejects any attempt at giving a univocal
definition of a concept that he takes to be multifaceted and multidimensional,
Albahari claims to give an analysis of the self that we ordinarily take
ourselves to be. Since Zahavi's experiential self lacks many of the features
revealed by that analysis, she considers it too thin to count as a self. The
witness consciousness that is revealed in the self-givenness of perspectival
ownership lacks the crucial feature of boundedness, and thus cannot play the
role of core self for the narrativity project. It is just a witnessing, and thus
cannot ground the sense of agency and separateness at the heart of the
ordinary conception of the ‘I’. This is the reality that underlies the illusion of
the self but is not to be thought of as a self. This move allows Albahari to
avoid the difficulties that attend any version of bundle theory, while
apparently also escaping troubling questions about a permanent self's relation
to changing empirical content. In this as well, her approach resembles that of
MARK SIDERITS, EVAN THOMPSON, DAN ZAHAVI
Advaita Vedānta; the interested reader would do well to consult the papers on
this topic by Fasching and Ram-Prasad. The question one might pose for
Albahari is whether she is willing to pay the price that Advaita accepts for an
enduring witness: that all diversity in content (or for that matter anything else)
turns out to be illusory.
The paper by Georges Dreyfus takes up the problem of defending from a
Buddhist perspective the claim that consciousness is reflexive but
ownerless—that there is subjectivity but no subject. As Dreyfus makes clear,
not all Buddhist non-self theorists accept the reflexivity thesis. But the non-
self thesis is sometimes taken to mean that persons are utterly lacking in
interiority or subjectivity, and Dreyfus is concerned to make clear that this is
not true for at least one part of the Buddhist tradition, namely the school that
affirms the reflexivity thesis. A self-theorist like Zahavi will then want to
know how one can affirm a dimension of subjectivity while denying that there
is a self that serves as subject of experiential states. Dreyfus' response
resembles that of Albahari. The self at issue for Buddhists is one that ordinary
people have a sense of being, hence something that might be at least intimated
in ordinary experience: the self whose existence Buddhists reject is thus not a
purely structural requirement.
Like Albahari as well, Dreyfus locates the core of the illusion of self in
the presence in each conscious moment of reflexive awareness. Dreyfus,
though, would not be willing to call this ‘witness consciousness’, since for the
view he defends, the distinction between the content of a cognition and a
cognition's grasping of that content is a mere conceptual superimposition. This
move would allow Dreyfus to answer Albahari's basic objection to all forms
of bundle theory: that they cannot solve the binding problem and thus account
for the felt sense of diachronic unity in our experience. The view Dreyfus
defends is a kind of bundle theory, since it claims that while a certain basic
form of consciousness is present at each moment in the life of a person, the
basic consciousness is constantly renewed. The appeal to the ultimate non-
duality of consciousness and content is not, though, the answer Dreyfus
actually gives to the question how we are to know that the reflexive awareness
occurring in any one cognition is not identical with the reflexive awareness
occurring at other times in the same mental stream (and thus something
distinct from the content of any particular cognition). To give that answer he
would have to reject a doctrine he embraces, that in certain meditative states
there occurs consciousness that is devoid of all content and merely discloses
INTRODUCTION
the point of the Advaitin insistence that the self is neither an object of
experience nor the subject of experience, but somehow transcends both.
Careful phenomenological investigation of the mode of givenness of
experience can, he thinks, help us make sense of this. What this leaves
unanswered, however, is why we should not distinguish between the
presencing that is constitutive of the currently occurring experience, and the
presencing that was constitutive of a past experience, given that the two
experiences have different contents. The Buddhist self-illuminationist will
appeal to this difference in content in deploying their impermanence strategy.
It is at this point that Advaitins have typically invoked their claim that all
difference is illusory, that ultimately there is only the one Self that is not to be
distinguished from pure Being (Brahman). It is recourse to this radical non-
dualism (a-dvaita-vāda) that they have relied on to answer the charge that a
non-substantial witnessing must be just as variable as its contents, and so must
be impermanent. Fasching wishes to avoid what to many has seemed like a
desperate metaphysics, and so confines his account to the phenomenology that
he takes to underlie the Advaita position. The question that might be asked,
however, is how one is to prevent a metaphysical stand-off over the status of
the mental stream. The non-self theorist holds that the stream is conceptually
constructed out of individual consciousness-events; the non-substantialist
holds it to be a single enduring thing. The soteriological concerns that
motivated the Indian debate suggest that an answer is required.
Chakravarthi Ram-Prasad, in his paper for this volume, takes this
Advaitin bull by its (non-dual) horn: he makes explicit the role of non-dualism
in Advaita's account of the self as pure luminosity. He starts with a discussion
of the rejection of a substantial self that is common to Buddhism and Advaita.
In this they are united in their opposition to those who wish to salvage as
much as possible of the common-sense view that the first-person pronoun ‘I’
refers to the self. Where they part company is over the correct analysis of ‘I’.
Buddhist non-self theorists typically claim that ‘I’ is just a useful way to refer
to a large collection of suitably arranged psychophysical elements, none of
which is a self; on this analysis our mistake lies in taking there to be one thing
when there are really only the many. Advaitins, instead, think our mistake lies
in taking there to be a many when strictly speaking there is just the one. This
is what lies behind their insistence that ‘I’ does not refer to the self. Their self,
as pure luminosity or presencing, is real but does not individuate, whereas ‘I’
must individuate. On this view, ‘I’ refers to the organ involved in the
INTRODUCTION
relation between the system and its constituents in such a way as to avoid the
absolute idealist conclusion that the only real is the one grand system. Another
problem is that it can be difficult to say when we are entitled to conclude that
the behavior of a complex system will forever resist reductive causal
explanation. Perhaps the key question to ask here, however, is how the ethical
concerns behind the Buddhist non-self project can be reconciled with the
claim that an emergent self is empty but real.
Galen Strawson's views on the self are well known. In his paper for this
volume, he extends those views to the question whether the self is aware of
itself. Like most other contributors, he accepts the reflexivity thesis. And since
his self is just the ‘thin subject’ or present-moment cognizing, it follows from
the reflexivity thesis that the self is aware of itself. But the awareness being
attributed here is non-thetic. What Strawson is interested in challenging is the
almost universally accepted claim that the self cannot be present-moment
directly and thetically aware of itself. A substantialist who accepts the
reflexivity thesis, but thinks of cognition as a mode of the self, could say that
in reflective consciousness the self is thetically aware of itself. But this thetic
awareness would not be direct, going as it does through direct awareness of
the cognition to indirect awareness of the self as subject of the cognition.
Strawson's subject is the cognition itself. Yet he claims that in certain
meditative states there is fully thetic awareness of the cognizing subject. Is it
after all possible that the fingertip can touch itself?
Strawson answers the last question in the negative, but he takes the case
of self-awareness to be different. This may be because he takes the distinction
between subject and object of cognition to be a conceptual superimposition on
something intrinsically non-dual. If so, he then faces the same challenge that
confronts the Buddhist non-self self-illumination theorist who takes this tack:
resolving the paradox of inexpressibility that results when one claims that the
true non-dual nature of cognition is inexpressible. If, on the other hand, he
wants to join Dreyfus in rejecting the claim that cognition is non-dual, on the
grounds that objectless cognition is possible, then like Dreyfus he will need
some way of answering Albahari's charge that his subject is just her enduring
witness and not anything transitory at all.
Our last paper, by Mark Siderits, is the only one to explore the option of
rejecting the reflexivity thesis. He begins with the standard Buddhist
formulation of non-self, and considers the objection that a reductionist
strategy can show that some putative entity is not ultimately real only if there
INTRODUCTION
is that to which it might appear that the entity is real. On this objection, any
attempt to show that the self just consists in purely impersonal entities must be
self-defeating, in that it requires that there be that to which it appears that the
self is real. Self-illumination theory is one way in which non-self theorists
have attempted to answer this objection. Siderits claims, though, that the
arguments for the reflexivity thesis are not sufficiently compelling to
overcome its strongly counter-intuitive character, so that it might be worth
exploring what the alternative is for the non-self theorist. Since none of the
many Buddhist schools that were other-illuminationist developed detailed
accounts of how cognition might be cognized, the answer Siderits develops is
speculative, based as it is on the views of non-Buddhist Indian other-
illuminationists. The resulting theory has it that cognitions are never directly
cognized, and are cognized only through an abductive inference from the
global availability—availability to such systems as the faculties of speech,
memory, and action-guidance—of information about the object. Since it then
follows that mental states have the property of being conscious only
extrinsically, through their relations to other states, consciousness itself turns
out to be reducible: cognitions are not among the ultimate constituents of
which persons are composed.
This strategy would certainly answer the objection. If its seeming to us as
if we are conscious is just a useful way for a certain sort of information-
processing system to manage the flow of information, then there need not be a
self to explain the fact that the system self-represents. Consistent application
of reductionist metaphysics would preserve the ethical aims behind the non-
self view. The question that must be asked here, though, is whether this is not,
as with Advaita, a desperate metaphysics. At the end of his paper, Siderits
explores the image of fully enlightened beings that one finds in some Buddhist
devotional literature. These beings are depicted as so skilled at exercising
compassion that they act in the world on full auto-pilot, never actually
cognizing the beings they help. When this image is read in the light of a
reductive approach to consciousness, the suggestion would be that the
soteriological aim behind non-self is to overcome the illusion that we are not
zombies. To say that most readers will find this implausible is probably not an
overstatement.
1
The Who and the How
of Experience
JOEL W. KRUEGER
1. Introduction
Does consciousness require a self ?1 In what follows, I argue that it does not.
I concede at the outset that this is a counterintuitive thesis. For, a central
feature of conscious states is that their mode of appearance (i.e. how they are
given) exhibits an irreducibly first-personal nature. My experiences are
distinctly my own, given to me and only me. This first-personal ‘how’ of
consciousness is what secures its phenomenal character. And it seems natural
to assume that this how points back to a ‘who’: a stable, enduring, conscious
subject at the receiving end of phenomenal states. But is the assumption that
a how requires a who warranted? I will argue below that, just because the
subjective character of consciousness gives rise to a sense of self—that is, the
felt sense of being a stable who, or owner of conscious episodes—it does not
follow that this who really exists in any autonomous or enduring sense.
First, I do some background work, briefly discussing the phenomenolog-
ical notion of the ‘minimal self ’ before then looking at a Buddhist concep-
tion of selfless subjectivity. Next, I examine the minimal self more carefully,
along with what is sometimes termed the ‘narrative self ’, and argue for the
experiential primacy of the former. I then argue that the phenomenal
character of consciousness, which the minimal self-model is supposed to
1 I am grateful for conversations with the participants of the ‘Self-No-Self ’ workshop in Copenha-
gen, Denmark, April 15–16, 2009, which greatly assisted my thinking about the issues discussed in this
paper. I am also especially grateful to Mark Siderits for his critical comments on an earlier version of this
paper, as well as the very helpful comments from two anonymous reviewers.
28 JOEL W. KRUEGER
2 As Galen Strawson notes, the realization that one enjoys privileged access to one’s interiority ‘comes
to every normal human being, in some form, in childhood. The early realization of the fact that one’s
thoughts are unobservable by others, the experience of the profound sense in which one is alone in one’s
head—these are among the very deepest facts about the character of human life’ (Strawson 1999a: 2). But
developmentally speaking, the experience of phenomenal interiority is probably even more basic than
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 29
Strawson concedes. Research on neonate imitation (discussed in more detail in section 4) suggests that
newborn infants have an immediate sense of their own interiority, and there are reasons to attribute this
primitive self-awareness to some nonhuman animals. One thus needn’t possess the concept of interiority
(which is generally thought to be an aspect of possessing a ‘theory of mind’) to have the experiential sense
of one’s interiority, of being the sort of thing (i.e. a self ) with an inner experiential dimension unique to
oneself.
3 I am indebted to both Georges Dreyfus (1997) and Matt Mackenzie (2008) for the discussion in this
section.
30 JOEL W. KRUEGER
all entities, events, and processes have no substantial reality outside of this
dynamic matrix of dependent origination. So, things like chariots, pots, and
persons are ultimately empty (śūnya) of fixed or intrinsic nature (svabhāva).4
Since the psychophysical complex of the person (or self ) is subject to the
same causes and conditions as everything else, it, too, is ultimately empty of
intrinsic nature. This is the other core doctrine of no-self (anātman), the
most well-known and controversial aspect of Buddhist thought. What is
perhaps less well known, however, is that some Buddhist thinkers argue that
the denial of the self does not necessarily go hand-in-hand with a denial of
subjectivity. These thinkers offer a model of consciousness that preserves its
phenomenal character while nevertheless denying that the phenomenal
character of consciousness is dependent upon the existence of a fixed,
enduring, or unconditioned subject. This is not the place to survey the
vast Buddhist literature on this topic. Instead, we can focus on two specific
forms of self-awareness discussed in the literature, one broad and one
narrow, and look at how they relate to an analysis of (no-)self and phenom-
enal consciousness.
The first of these notions is the broader form of self-awareness captured by
the term aham kāra, which denotes ‘I-maker’ awareness, the sense of oneself as a
single entity enduring throughout time. This is the sense of being an autono-
mous self, distinct from the flux and flow of ever-changing experiences.
Additionally, the term also captures the egocentric structure of human exis-
tence—our tendency to act and make decisions which reflect our own self-
interests (Mackenzie 2008: 247). The term svasam vedana, on the other hand, is
a narrower form of self-awareness. It refers to the immediate acquaintance we
have with both the content of our conscious states (i.e. the intentional object
that an experience is an experience of, such as a perception of a tree, a memory
of a childhood experience, or the image of a unicorn), as well as the character of
our conscious states (i.e. the first-person phenomenal mode of access to the
intentional content, such as the act of perceiving a tree, remembering a
childhood experience, or imagining a unicorn). Put differently, svasam vedana
refers to the ‘self-illuminating’ (svaprakāśa) character of conscious states. When
I have an experience of, for example, the sound of a car roaring by on the street
4 A central debate within Buddhist philosophy concerns whether all things are empty of intrinsic
nature, or whether there are some things (e.g. dharmas, or momentary, individual atoms or tropes) which
have intrinsic nature. See Siderits (2007) for a clear introduction to this debate (and others) within the
Buddhist philosophical tradition.
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 31
5 This form of self-awareness is implicit in that it is not the result of a voluntary act of introspection or
reflection. I will also characterize this form of self-awareness as ‘immanent’ to phenomenally conscious
states.
6 Dreyfus (1997) offers extensive analysis. Dunne (2004) is an excellent introduction to Dharmakı̄rti’s
thought as a whole.
7 He writes, ‘The [mind] understands by itself its own nature’ (quoted in Dreyfus 1997: 340).
8 One also finds versions of this argument in Aristotle, Descartes, Locke, Leibniz, Kant, and
Brentano, among others. See Kriegel (2003).
32 JOEL W. KRUEGER
9 Contemporary versions of these views, respectively, are defended by higher-order perception (or
‘HOP’) theorists such as Armstrong (1968) and Lycan (1997), and higher-order thought (or ‘HOT’)
theorists such as Rosenthal (1993).
10 Dharmakı̄rti offers another argument for svasam vedana, which we might term the ‘feeling-tone’
argument. For Dharmakı̄rti, all intentional objects are given through an affective valence or feeling-
tone—positive, neutral, negative—that colors how we experience these objects. But since this feeling-
tone is an experiential property (i.e. a property of the subject, not the object), and since, moreover, the
feeling-tone is always given simultaneously with the object, it follows that in every experience the
subject simultaneously apprehends both the object and herself (i.e. via the presence of a subject-referring
feeling-tone). We can thus conceptually distinguish two aspects of each mental state: its world-present-
ing objective aspect ( grāhyākāra) and its subject-referring subjective aspect ( grāhakākāra). However,
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 33
the point of this discussion is to indicate that within the Buddhist tradition
there is room for a view that admits the reality of subjectivity, while
nevertheless denying the ultimate existence of an enduring self. Dharmakı̄rti
insists that conceding the subjective or self-reflexive character of conscious-
ness is compatible with the core Buddhist notion of anātman. This is so, he
urges, because svasam vedana is the phenomenally continuous, first-person
perspective one has on the stream of one’s own experience. But this first-
person perspective or experiential dimension at the heart of consciousness is
not itself a self. It is a feature of the stream of experience, and not a self
standing behind the experience. As such, it is dynamic, relational, and
perpetually in flux, dependently conditioned by the continually changing
interplay of successive contents (i.e. the intentional objects of experiences)
and acts (i.e. the first-personal phenomenal modes of access to successively
changing contents). But again, there is nothing fixed, permanent, or un-
conditioned standing behind, or distinct from, this stream. There is simply
the first-personal stream itself.
Thus, while Dharmakı̄rti argues that consciousness is intrinsically person-
al, that is, it manifests in a first-personal how, or mode of givenness, it doesn’t
follow, he further insists, that there is a single, stable who serving as the
recipient of this stream. Dharmakı̄rti’s discussion of the self is in this way a
deflationary realism. The sense of self at the core of phenomenal conscious-
ness (svasam vedana) is indeed very real. This quality, for Dharmakı̄rti, is
subjectivity: it is what makes consciousness the unique phenomenon that it
is. And each act of cognition thus has this aspect of subjectivity. Additional-
ly, the sense of being a self with a temporally extended, historically con-
stituted identity (aham kāra) is also real. But to infer that subjectivity
(svasam vedana) entails the real existence of a stable phenomenal self, or to
infer that aham kāra refers to a permanent, stable historical self, is a mistake.
This mistake arises, Dharmakı̄rti argues, from our tendency to reify the
sense of self central to the phenomenal character of consciousness. That is,
we reify either, on one hand, the self-reflexive, first-personal character of
conscious states—falsely assuming that the mineness of experience picks out
a permanent, substantial me—or, on the other hand, the broader form of
‘I-maker’ self-awareness that emerges over time, and which is fed by the
phenomenologically and ontologically, these aspects are nondyadically conjoined within the unified
structure of each state. See Dreyfus 1997: 400–403.
34 JOEL W. KRUEGER
narratives we tell—narratives that we cannot help but tell, given the way our
brains are hardwired (Dennett 1991)—play a significant role in shaping and
even constituting the self. The self is thus a narrative construction.11 Daniel
Dennett famously writes: ‘Our tales are spun, but for the most part we don’t
spin them; they spin us. Our human consciousness, and our narrative
selfhood, is their product, not their source’ (Dennett 1991: 418).
What counts as a narrative remains a contentious issue within the current
literature; I have no aspirations of settling the debate here. However,
although a precise definition is unnecessary for present concerns, a glance
at possible candidates will be helpful both for establishing the general
contours of narrative approaches to the self as well as clarifying precisely
how narrative accounts of self sit next to minimal accounts of self. To begin
simply: narratives are constructed, and not merely discovered. Narratives
are thus a uniquely human enterprise. Moreover, narratives are distinct from
mere chronicles of temporally indexed events, such as the timeline of a
person’s life (Danto 1965). What is constructed in narrative must be a
relation between at least two events and/or states of affairs united by some
relatively loose, non-logical relation (Lamarque 2004: 394). But this thin
characterization of narrative says little of the temporal structure of narratives
and nothing of their social character. Nor does it say anything about their
role in constructing the self.
Alasdair MacIntyre (1981) offers an alternative. Although he fails to
define ‘narrative’ explicitly in After Virtue, MacIntyre nevertheless develops
a rendering that brings out the temporal, social, and self-constituting char-
acter of narratives. He writes:
The story of my life is always embedded in the story of those communities from
which I derive my identity. I am born with a past; and to try to cut myself off from
that past, in the individualist mode, is to deform my present relationships . . . What
I am, therefore, is a key part of what I inherit, a specific past that is present to some
degree in my present.
(MacIntyre 1981: 205–206)
11 Defenders of narrative accounts of self include both philosophers (e.g. Alasdair MacIntyre 1981,
Charles Taylor 1989, Daniel Dennett 1991, Paul Ricoeur 1992, Marya Schechtman 1996, Shaun
Gallagher 2003, David Velleman 2006, Daniel Hutto 2008, and Anthony Rudd 2009) and psychologists
(e.g. Donald Spence 1982, Jerome Bruner 1986, and Mark Freeman 1993).
36 JOEL W. KRUEGER
12 Paul Ricoeur insists that ‘the selfhood of oneself implies otherness to such an intimate degree that
one cannot be thought without the other’ (Ricoeur 1992: 3).
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 37
place. MacIntyre, for example, seems to endorse NEA when he insists that,
‘It is important to notice that I am not arguing that the concepts of narrative
or of intelligibility or of accountability are more fundamental than that of
personal identity’ (MacIntyre 1981: 203).13 Again, the salient point is that,
for NEA, the narrative self is a derivative notion dependent upon a more
basic pre-narrative self.
On the other hand, the stronger account of narrative selfhood offers a
constitution claim: namely, that the self is literally constituted by narratives.
The self is ultimately nothing but a dense constellation of interwoven
narratives, an emergent entity that gradually unfurls from (and is thus
constituted by) the stories we tell and have told about us. As we’ve already
seen, Dennett (1989, 1991) seems to hold this view. Again, recall his
insistence that ‘like spider webs, our tales are spun by us; our human
consciousness, and our narrative selfhood, is their product, not their source’
(Dennett 1991: 418). Drawing inspiration from Dennett (among others),
Marya Schechtman similarly characterizes her own ‘self-constitution’ view
as the claim that ‘a person exists in the convergence of subjective and
objective features. An individual constitutes herself as a person by coming
to organize her experiences in a narrative self-conception of the appropriate
form’ (Schechtman 1996: 134).
This brief characterization of narrative-self models hints at their theoreti-
cal richness for understanding the dynamic, relational, and situated nature of
the self. However, our discussion in the previous section has already
suggested a difficulty for NCA. Exploring this difficulty is the work of the
next section.
5. Pre-Narrative Selfhood
There is a difficulty with NCA that doesn’t plague NEA. It is this: the NCA
‘self as story’ story seems to weave an incomplete story of the self. Put
differently, in order to be a narrative-telling creature—in order to cast
oneself as the protagonist in one’s own narrative—one must already be
the possessor of, in addition to the linguistic capacities needed to construct a
13 Actually, MacIntyre’s view here isn’t entirely clear. See Williams (2009) for discussion and
criticism.
38 JOEL W. KRUEGER
14 For the sake of historical precision, it should be noted that not all schools of Indian Buddhism hold
that cognition is self-reflexive (e.g. Mādhyamika thinkers such as Candrakı̄rti (ca. 600–650) and
Śāntideva (fl. 8th century)).
15 To be clear, while Buddhism acknowledges a phenomenological distinction between the two
forms of self-experience I am here distinguishing, the terms ‘person’ and ‘self ’ are used somewhat
differently within Buddhist philosophy. A person (pudgalā) is simply a causally continuous, psychophysi-
cal complex of different aggregates (skandhas) arranged in the right sort of way. And with the exception
of the Pudgalavāda tradition of early Buddhism, most Buddhists believe that the person is ultimately
reducible to this psychophysical complex, that is, the person has no independent existence over and
above it. The self (ātman), as an experiential feature, is thus an aspect of this causal series, and is as
impermanent as is every other aspect.
16 See also Albahari (this volume) for more on ordinary, and ultimately delusive, forms of self-
experience.
40 JOEL W. KRUEGER
17 ‘Core consciousness’ is Damasio’s expression for our moment-to-moment sense of being an awake
and experiencing subject (i.e. a minimal self ) (Damasio 1999: 16).
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 41
the presented gesture (Meltzoff and Moore 1983). Neonate imitation pre-
supposes three significant pre-narrative capacities, all of which themselves
presuppose an experienced sense of minimal phenomenal selfhood: (1) the
capacity for experientially distinguishing self and other; (2) the capacity for
locating and using body parts proprioceptively, that is, without vision (since
neonates haven’t yet seen their bodies); (3) the capacity to recognize the
presented face as of the same kind as its own face (neonates don’t imitate non-
human objects). As Shaun Gallagher notes, ‘One possible interpretation of
this finding is that these three capacities present in neonates constitute a
primitive self-consciousness, and that the human infant is already equipped
with a minimal self that is embodied, enactive, and ecologically attuned’
(Gallagher 2000: 17). Of course, since neonates lack the linguistic capacities
needed to construct and comprehend narratives, they have no sense of
themselves as a narrative entity, that is, as a person. Nevertheless, neonate
imitation research indicates that a minimal sort of self-experience, the sense of
being a unified, embodied perspective on the world, is present from birth.
At this point, there are several potential responses that defenders of NCA
might offer. Schechtman, for example, concedes a conceptual distinction
between self and person but argues that narratives are nonetheless central to
both categories (Schechtman 2007: 171). In order to constitute oneself as a
narrative person, ‘one must recognize oneself as continuing, see past actions
and experiences as having implications for one’s current rights and respon-
sibilities, and recognize a future that will be impacted by the past and
present’ (Schechtman 2007: 170). A narrative self, Schechtman continues,
is constituted by assimilating temporally remote actions and experiences
into my present self-experience in such as way that these events ‘condition
the quality of present experience in the strongest sense, unifying conscious-
ness over time through affective connections and identification’ (Schecht-
man 2007: 171).
But the problem with Schechtmans’s distinction here is that, again, it is
pitched at too high a level of explanation, passing over features of phenom-
enal consciousness and forms of self-experience that seem to be independent
of narrative. It is also a strikingly disembodied account of self-constitution.
Which of these two forms of narrative constitution, for instance, as defined
by Schechtman, apply to Damasio’s David? Certainly not the first, since
David lacks a robust sense of having a created history that constrains his
present actions and decisions. Similarly, while David’s consciousness seems
42 JOEL W. KRUEGER
to present a unified character, it’s not clear that this phenomenal unity is the
result of any kind of narratively structured process of ‘affective connection
and identification’. David’s capacity for memory is simply too impoverished
to speak this way: the unity of his phenomenal experience must thus be due
to a different mechanism. Schechtman might respond by urging that, even
within a short forty-five second window, David can still construct ‘micro-
narratives’ that unify his experiences and allow him to make affective
connections with temporally remote actions and events (e.g. the door he
opened ten seconds ago while walking into the room, or the initiation of his
reach to grasp a light bulb that needs changing). But this is an awfully
strained way of using the term ‘narrative’, since the temporal extension
and social character of these sorts of micro-narratives is exceedingly limited.
Moreover, it’s not at all clear that we need appeal to narrative to explain
certain fundamental forms of embodied self-experience and skillfulness.
This becomes clear by returning to the neonatal imitation studies men-
tioned previously. Again, it’s difficult to discern how Schechtman’s distinc-
tion would be neatly applied to these cases. Far from a ‘blooming and
buzzing’ model of experience, it now appears that even very young infants
present a surprisingly rich form of self-awareness rooted in an ecological
experience of their body and their body’s practical relation to the world.
They seem to grasp implicitly that they have a body, and they feel that this
body can be made to do things, including imitate the expressions and
gestures of others—despite neither having seen their body nor possessing
any sort of linguistic or narrative understanding of it. This capacity points
towards a range of embodied self-experience and skills (e.g. neonatal imita-
tion, reaching for and grasping a cup, driving a car, responding to an
opponent’s volley while playing tennis) that operate without narrative
intervention. Additionally, our ability to enact pre-narrative embodied skills
so efficiently suggests that there exists a primitive form of bodily self-
experience that is independent of narrative articulation. The young infant
is immediately acquainted with its body and the things its body can do;
the skilled driver and tennis player enact dynamically coherent, context-
sensitive sequences of complicated motor actions that unfold without the
explicit guidance of narrative scripts. This immediate acquaintance with
oneself as an embodied perspective on the world is a phenomenologically
minimal form of self-experience.
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 43
18 Sartre argues that, ‘pre-reflective consciousness is self-consciousness. It is this same notion of self
which must be studied, for it defines the very being of consciousness’ (Sartre 1943/1956: 123).
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 45
kı̄rti’s assertion discussed above, Zahavi argues that, when I have an experi-
ence of an object, such as visually perceiving a tomato on a table, part of my
subjective experience is constituted by properties of the object (i.e. redness,
smoothness, roundness, etc.). These properties play a central role in fixing
the phenomenal character of a given state. But these properties, in fact, do
not exhaust the phenomenal character. There is another, more subtle,
phenomenological aspect present: namely, the phenomenal property of
experiencing myself experiencing. Put differently, I experience these features of
the object in a mode of first-personal givenness, a mode of disclosure that is a
phenomenologically basic form of reflexive self-experience. Zahavi writes:
This first-personal givenness of experiential phenomena is not something incidental
to their being, a mere varnish that the experiences could lack without ceasing to be
experiences. On the contrary, this first-personal givenness makes the experience
subjective. To put it another way, their first-personal givenness entails a built-in self-
reference, a primitive experiential self-referentiality . . . the experiential dimension
does not have to do with the existence of ineffable qualia; it has to do with the
dimension of first-personal experiencing.
(Zahavi 2005: 122–23)
Echoing Dharmakı̄rti once more, Zahavi insists that the dimension of first-
personal experiencing does not involve any sort of higher-order act of
reflection or perception.19 Rather, the minimal self is what originally
19 Zahavi is critical of higher-order (both HOT and HOP) theories of consciousness (Zahavi 2005:
17–20).
46 JOEL W. KRUEGER
20 Consciousness, Mark Rowlands observes, is essentially a ‘hybrid entity’ that can be both object and
act of experience (Rowlands 2001: 122). Zahavi insists that the modality of the former is dependent upon
the modality of the latter—and thus that consciousness-as-act (of which the minimal self is an essential
part) is phenomenologically primitive.
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 47
watching the movie. In short, there is an object of experience (the watching), and
there is a subject of experience, myself.
(Zahavi 2005: 99)
Yet there is a tension here. Recall Zahavi’s earlier claim that the minimal
self is simply a ‘feature or function’ of the first-personal givenness or ‘self-
luminosity’ (Zahavi 2005: 62) of the phenomenal stream. In fact, at one
point Zahavi urges that, in order to understand his insistence that the
minimal self be identified with the first-personal character of phenomenal
consciousness, we ought to ‘replace the traditional phrase “subject of
experience” with the phrase “subjectivity of experience”’ (Zahavi 2005:
126). This is because the former seems to imply an autonomous, stream-
independent ego—which Zahavi denies—whereas the latter adequately
captures the sort of immanent stream self Zahavi endorses. The minimal
self thus is, simply, the subjectivity of experience (which includes the various
features that Zahavi carefully analyzes). But if this is all that the minimal self
is, it seems that Zahavi is really endorsing the sort of non-egological view
he claims to be opposing! Nothing in this characterization of the self-
luminosity of the phenomenal stream is in conflict with Dharmakı̄rti’s
view—except for the final step Zahavi wants to make in reifying the stream
self into something permanent and invariant.21
To the question, ‘Where is the minimal self ?’, Zahavi clearly answers, ‘In
the stream of consciousness itself ’. But if we now return to our earlier
21 To be fair, Zahavi himself notes that the simple distinction between egological and non-egological
views of consciousness (e.g. Gurwitsch 1941) is far too crude, and therefore that more subtle ways of
characterizing the relation between consciousness and self-consciousness are needed (Zahavi 2005: 146).
However, Zahavi’s stated desire to pinpoint various ‘invariant’ structures of experience (e.g. the ipseity of
the 1st person experiential dimension)—coupled with, moreover, his argument that these structures
qualify as a minimal form of selfhood—would seem to indicate that Zahavi sees himself as aligned with
the egological camp, even if his particular approach is more nuanced than traditional egological views
(see Zahavi 2005: 99).
50 JOEL W. KRUEGER
it has no intrinsic self-nature. It isn’t some thing distinct from this interplay.
It is the interplay itself. As such, it is fundamentally impermanent, arising
and passing away within the continual stream of ever-new acts and contents.
Thus, Dharmakı̄rti would likely be content to speak of numerically distinct
minimal selves: dependently conditioned, temporary subjects that arise,
exist, and pass away within the span of an occurrent episode of conscious-
ness. And if this analysis of Zahavi’s view of the minimal self is correct, it
seems that Zahavi, too, is warranted only in speaking of a plurality of
numerically distinct, minimal phenomenal selves.23 For the first-personal
givenness of experience, according to Zahavi, is phenomenally conditioned
by experiential phenomena (i.e. objects of experience)—and vice versa.
Experiential phenomena are never given anonymously, but always first-
personally. Thus, first-personal givenness and experiential phenomena are
necessarily co-given. But since experience is always in flux, an ever-flowing
stream of (first-personal) acts and first-personally given experiential phe-
nomena (i.e. objects)—and since, moreover, the minimal phenomenal self is
identical with its experiences, as Zahavi argues—it follows that the stream
self is constantly changing. In other words, there is no numerically identical
minimal phenomenal self. Rather, there is simply a phenomenal continuum
of minimal selves, each ensuring that experiential phenomena are manifest
in a mode of first-personal givenness.
But this is not the end of the matter. For at times Zahavi also seems to
characterize the minimal self, not in terms of its stream character, but rather
its structural character, that is, the minimal self understood purely as a formal
structure of consciousness. For instance, he writes that, ‘As long as we focus
on the first-personal mode of givenness of the stream of consciousness, we
are dealing with a kind of pure, formal, and empty individuality which the
subject shares with all other subjects’ (Zahavi 1999: 165). But if the minimal
self is merely an empty structural feature of consciousness, how is the
phenomenal character of experience individuated? How does subjectivity
become my subjectivity? For a purely formal feature of consciousness—
whether it be minimal selfhood, intentionality, its field-like structure, or
something else—cannot in itself exhibit phenomenal character. Formal
features are conditions of possibility for consciousness to occur the particular
23 This would also bring Zahavi closer to Galen Strawson who, as Strawson himself notes, shares
some affinities with the Buddhist view of the self (Strawson 1999a: 18).
52 JOEL W. KRUEGER
way that it does; they cannot be given to consciousness, much the same way
that an eye cannot see itself. These features need to be phenomenally ‘filled
in’ via the dynamic interplay of acts and contents.
Zahavi recognizes this objection. He says that, as a formal feature of
consciousness, the minimal self ’s phenomenal character
only manifests itself on the personal level, in its individual history, in its moral and
intellectual convictions. It is through these acts that I define myself; they have
character-shaping effect. I remain the same as long as I adhere to my convictions.
When they change, I change. Since these convictions and endorsed values are
intrinsically social, we are once more confronted with the idea that the ego in its
full scope and concretion cannot be thought or understood in isolation from the
Other. The ego is only fully individualized when personalized, and this happens
only intersubjectively.
(Zahavi 1999: 166)
But the problem with this reply is that it seems to appeal to a narrative
conception of self to explain how the unique particularities of my identity
are constituted. And this is fine, except that narratives, too, are by definition
impermanent. They are the result of multiple authors, and are constantly
being retold and revised. Moreover, I am rarely the sole author of my own
self-narrative, and thus my identity is, to a very large degree, dependently
conditioned by others. My narrative self thus constantly develops and
changes, taking on new elements while abandoning other outmoded or
forgotten elements. As Zahavi puts it, ‘Therefore, I, we, and world belong
together’ (Zahavi 1999: 166). The narrative self depends on others for its
existence: it is relationally constituted. Put otherwise, it lacks intrinsic self-
nature, as the Buddhist would argue, and is thus empty of fixed or perma-
nent character. Additionally, appealing to narrative self-models to explain
how subjectivity is individuated still encounters the challenge discussed
earlier: namely, a failure to explain pre-narrative forms of phenomenal
self-experience. So, a story of the pre-narrative minimal stream self is still
needed to explain how the structural self is individuated, phenomenally
speaking. But as I have just argued, this way of characterizing the self cannot
establish the self ’s fundamental invariance, either. So it seems that, by
appealing to either narrative or minimal self-models (including the latter
understood either as stream or as structure), we’ve yet to pinpoint the
resting place for a stable, permanent, or enduring self.
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 53
8. Concluding Thoughts
In this paper, I have attempted to show that Buddhist philosophy offers a
characterization of consciousness that (1) foregrounds its phenomenal char-
acter, but which (2) denies that this phenomenal character entails the
existence of a fixed, enduring, or unconditioned self. I then examined
two contemporary self-models: the narrative self and the minimal self, and
summoned empirical research in support of my claim that the latter is
dissociable from, and, indeed, experientially prior to, the former. Finally,
I’ve looked more closely at Dan Zahavi’s lucid defense of the minimal self,
and offered reasons for thinking that, while his discussion rightly explicates
several core features of phenomenal consciousness, it nevertheless fails to
establish the necessary existence of a stable, fixed, or enduring self that stays
the same throughout the life of the conscious subject. Buddhism claims that
we are fundamentally empty persons—despite strong and persistent forms of
self-experience that seem to suggest the contrary. It remains to be seen, of
course, if this claim is ultimately true. But if the above analysis is correct, it’s
a view at least worth taking seriously.
References
Armstrong, D. (1968), A Materialist Theory of Mind (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul).
Bruner, J. (1986), Actual Minds, Possible Worlds (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
sity Press).
Damasio, A. (1999), The Feeling of What Happens (San Diego, CA: Harcourt).
Danto, A. (1965), Analytical Philosophy of History (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press).
Dennett, D. (1979), ‘On the Absence of Phenomenology’, in Donald F. Gustafson
and Bangs L. Tapscottt (eds.), Body, Mind, and Method (Dordrecht: Kluwer).
——(1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston : Little Brown and Company).
Dreyfus, G. (1997), Recognizing Reality: Dharmakı̄rti’s Philosophy and its Tibetan
Interpretations (Albany: SUNY Press).
Dunne, J. (2004), Foundations of Dharmakı̄rti’s Philosophy (Boston: Wisdom
Publications).
54 JOEL W. KRUEGER
Freeman, M. (1993), Rewriting the Self: History, Memory, and Narrative (London:
Routledge).
Gallagher, S. (2000), ‘Philosophical Conceptions of the Self: Implications for
Cognitive Science’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4: 14–21.
——(2003), ‘Self-Narrative, Embodied Action, and Social Context’, in Andrzej
Wiercinski (ed.), Between Suspicion and Sympathy: Paul Ricoeur’s Unstable Equilibri-
um (Festschrift for Paul Ricoeur) (Toronto: The Hermeneutic Press).
Gurwitsch, A. (1941), ‘A Non-Egological Conception of Consciousness’, Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research 1: 325–338.
Hutto, D., ed. (2007), Narrative and Understanding Persons (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
——(2008), Folk Psychological Narratives: The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding
Reasons (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Kriegel, U. (2003), ‘Consciousness as Intransitive Self-consciousness: Two Views
and an Argument’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33: 103–132.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (1985), The Origin, Development and Function of Early Infant
Imitation, PhD thesis, psychology, Uppsala University, Sweden.
——(1999), ‘Genesis and Development of Early Infant Mimesis to Facial and Vocal
Models’, in Jacqueline Nadel and George Butterworth (eds.), Imitation in Infancy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Lamarque, P. (2004), ‘On Not Expecting Too Much from Narrative’, Mind and
Language 19: 393–408.
Lycan, W. (1997), ‘Consciousness as Internal Monitoring’, in Ned Block, Owen
Flanagan, and Güven Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press).
MacIntyre, A. (1981), After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press).
MacKenzie, M. (2008), ‘Self-Awareness without a Self: Buddhism and the
Reflexivity of Awareness’, Asian Philosophy 18: 245–266.
Meltzoff, A. and K. Moore (1977), ‘Imitation of Facial and Manual Gestures by
Human Neonates’, Science 198: 75–78.
——(1983), ‘Newborn Infants Imitate Adult Facial Gestures’, Child Development
54: 702–709.
——(1997), ‘Explaining Facial Imitation: A Theoretical Model’, Early Development
and Parenting 6: 179–192.
Menary, R. (2008), ‘Embodied Narratives’, Journal of Consciousness Studies 15: 63–84.
Metzinger, T. (2003), Being No One: The Self-model Theory of Subjectivity
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
THE WHO AND THE HOW OF EXPERIENCE 55
1. Introduction
Let me start with three quotes from Sartre’s L’être et le néant—three quotes
that conjointly articulate a view of consciousness that I think is widespread
among phenomenologists, and which I personally endorse.
It is not reflection which reveals the consciousness reflected-on to itself. Quite the
contrary, it is the non-reflective consciousness which renders the reflection possi-
ble; there is a pre-reflective cogito which is the condition of the Cartesian cogito.
(Sartre 2003: 9)
What is Sartre saying here? First of all, on Sartre’s view, an experience does
not simply exist, it exists in such a way that it is implicitly self-given, or as
Sartre puts it, it is ‘for itself ’. This self-givenness of experience is not simply
a quality added to the experience, a mere varnish: rather for Sartre the very
mode of being of intentional consciousness is to be for-itself (pour-soi), that is,
self-conscious (Sartre 1967, 2003: 10). Sartre is, moreover, quite explicit in
emphasizing that the self-consciousness in question is not a new conscious-
ness. It is not something added to the experience, an additional mental state,
THE EXPERIENTIAL SELF: OBJECTIONS AND CLARIFICATIONS 57
1 Let me emphasize that the choice of the term ‘intrinsic’ is precisely meant to emphasize the
difference from a higher-order or reflection-based account of self-consciousness, where self-conscious-
ness is conceived in terms of a relation between two mental states. The term is not meant to indicate that
we are dealing with a feature that our experiences possess in complete independence of everything else.
To put it differently, to talk of self-consciousness as an intrinsic feature of experience is not to deny that
the (self-conscious) experience in question is also intentional and world-directed.
58 DAN ZAHAVI
with this locus of apprehension that generates the sense of self. But if this is
so, the self lacks an essential property of selfhood, namely ontological
independence (Albahari 2006: 72). In short, the illusory status of the self is
due to the fact that the self does not have the ontological status it purports to
have. Thoughts appear to be owned and initiated by an independently
existing unified self, but rather than preceding the experiences, rather
than thinking the thoughts, it is in reality the other way around. It is not
the self that unifies our thoughts and experiences, they do so themselves
with some help from the accompanying witness-consciousness (Albahari
2006: 130–132). To repeat, although it might seem to the subject as if there is
a pre-existing self which identifies with various intentional states, the reality
of the matter is that the self is created and constructed through these
repeated acts of identification (Albahari 2006: 58).
As I mentioned at the beginning, an interesting aspect of Albahari’s
proposal is that she considers many of the features traditionally ascribed to
the self to be real, it is just that they—in her view—become distorted and
illusory if taken to be features of the self (Albahari 2006: 74). For instance,
Albahari takes our conscious life to be characterized by an intrinsic, but
elusive, sense of subjective presence, one that is common to all modalities of
awareness, that is, one that is common to seeing, hearing, thinking, feeling,
introspecting, etc. (Albahari 2006: 112, 144, 156). What does this subjective
presence amount to? It includes the experience of being the perspectival
owner of various experiences. It also includes diachronic and synchronic
unity. Although we experience various objects, and although the objects we
experience might change from one moment to the next, there still appears
to be an unbroken consciousness that observes the change without itself
changing (Albahari 2006: 155). Indeed, while from a first-person perspective
it certainly makes sense to say that I have various experiences, we automati-
cally feel them to belong to one and the same consciousness. For Albahari,
all these features are properly ascribed to the witness-consciousness, and she
is adamant that we have to distinguish witness-consciousness from self.
Whereas the latter on her definition involves felt boundaries between self
and non-self, the former doesn’t.
Let me recapitulate. For Albahari, one can be aware without being
presented to oneself as an ontologically unique subject with personalized
boundaries that distinguishes a me from the rest of the world. One can be
aware without being aware of oneself as a personal owner, a thinker of
64 DAN ZAHAVI
4. Self vs No-Self
The debate between advocates of self and no-self accounts is complicated by
the fact that there is rather little consensus about what precisely a self
amounts to, just as there is little agreement on what a no-self doctrine
entails. Albahari’s account in Analytical Buddhism constitutes a neat example
of this. As we have just seen, Albahari basically denies the reality of the self
and argues that it is illusory. To that extent, she should obviously count as a
defender of a no-self account. At the same time, however, Albahari ascribes
a number of features to what she calls witness-consciousness—features
including invariance, unconstructedness, and ontological independence,
features that many defenders of a traditional notion of self would consider
essential and defining features of self. In fact, whereas I would suggest that
we replace the traditional notion of a ‘subject of experience’ with the notion
of a ‘subjectivity of experience’—the first phrasing might suggest that the
self is something that exists apart from, or above, the experience and, for
that reason, something that might be encountered in separation from the
experience, or even something the experience may occasionally lack, the
THE EXPERIENTIAL SELF: OBJECTIONS AND CLARIFICATIONS 65
2 Consider that although Albahari denies unconstructedness of self, she ascribes it to witness-
consciousness. As she puts it at one point, ‘awareness must be shown to exist in the manner it purports
to exist. Awareness purports to exist as a witnessing presence that is unified, unbroken and yet elusive to
direct observation. As something whose phenomenology purports to be unborrowed from objects of
consciousness, awareness, if it exists, must exist as completely unconstructed by the content of any
perspectivally ownable objects such as thoughts, emotions or perceptions. If apparent awareness . . .
turned out to owe its existence to such object-content rather than to (unconstructed) awareness itself,
then that would render awareness constructed and illusory and hence lacking in independent reality’
(Albahari 2006: 162). This seems to commit one to viewing awareness as an ontologically independent
region. It is not clear to me why one would want to uphold such a view of consciousness in the first
place.
3 Needless to say there is also a rather significant difference between claiming that experience is
fundamentally selfless and claiming that a dissolution or annihilation of self is an ultimate state we can
(and should) seek to attain.
66 DAN ZAHAVI
self-presencing that is part and parcel of our experiential life, and not to be
conceived of as an additional or separate act of cognition. In opposition to
some of the bundle theorists, Dreyfus consequently denies that experiences
are fundamentally impersonal, as if the attribution of first-personal self-
givenness to our experiential life is a post hoc fabrication. Rather, our
experiences are from the very start intrinsically self-specified (Dreyfus, this
volume, p. ??). But although Dreyfus, by implication, is prepared to accept
the reality of subjectivity, he insists that distortion arises the moment we
interpret this subjectivity as a bounded, unified self (Dreyfus, this volume,
p. ??). In short, the undeniable presence of a transient flow of self-aware
experiences doesn’t entail the existence of an enduring self-entity, rather the
latter is on Dreyfus’ view an illusory reification (Dreyfus, this volume, p.??).
More specifically, whereas Dreyfus wants to retain perspectival ownership
and synchronic unity—and claims that both features are guaranteed by
subjectivity—he argues that there is no diachronically unified self. There
is no enduring entity that stays the same from childhood to adulthood.
Let me divide my critical rejoinder into three parts.
1. First of all, I reject the univocal definition of self provided by Dreyfus
and Albahari. Both are very confident in spelling out what a self is, and after
having defined it, they then proceed to deny its existence. In my view,
however, the definition they provide is overly simplistic. There is no doubt
that some people have defended the notion of self that Albahari and Dreyfus
operate with, but I would dispute the claim that their notion is the default
notion, that is, that it is either a particularly classical notion of self or that it is a
particularly commonsensical notion, that is, one that is part of our folk
psychology. Consider again the claim that the self—if it exists—is some kind
of ontologically independent invariant principle of identity that stands apart
from, and above, the stream of changing experiences; something that
remains unchanging from birth to death; something that remains entirely
unaffected by language acquisition, social relationships, major life events,
personal commitments, projects, and values, something that cannot develop
or flourish nor be disturbed or shattered. Frankly, I don’t see such a notion
as being very much in line with our pre-philosophical, everyday under-
standing of who we are. As for the claim that the definition captures the
(rather than a) traditional philosophical understanding of self, this is also
something I would dispute. Just consider, to take some (not entirely)
THE EXPERIENTIAL SELF: OBJECTIONS AND CLARIFICATIONS 67
4 Though, as already pointed out, I am committed to the view that there is indeed a firm boundary
between self and other—as long as our concern is limited to the experiential notion of self. To quote
James, ‘Absolute insulation, irreducible pluralism, is the law. It seems as if the elementary psychic fact
were not thought or this thought or that thought, but my thought, every thought being owned. Neither
contemporaneity, nor proximity in space, nor similarity of quality and content are able to fuse thoughts
together which are sundered by this barrier of belonging to different personal minds. The breaches
between such thoughts are the most absolute breaches in nature’ (James 1890: 226).
70 DAN ZAHAVI
to—it is to pay lip service to the idea that we should take the first-person
perspective serious.
3. My third comment concerns the metaphysical framework we are
operating within. In recent years, quite a number of people have stressed
the existence of convergent ideas in Western phenomenology and Bud-
dhism. It has been claimed that both traditions represent serious efforts to
nurture a disciplined first-person approach to consciousness (cf. Varela and
Shear 1999), and some have even started to speak of Buddhist phenome-
nology (cf. Lusthaus 2002). I am not denying the truth of this, but when
appraising Buddhist views of the nature and status of self, one should not
overlook the fact that they are also driven and motivated by strong meta-
physical and soteriological concerns, and that this occasionally leads to
claims and conclusions that are quite far removed from phenomenology.
As an example, consider the Abhidharmic view that billions of distinct
mind-moments occur in the span of a blink of the eye (cf. Bodhi 1993: 156).
Dennett (1992) and Metzinger (2003) both deny the reality of the self,
and part of their reason for doing this, part of the reason why they think the
self is fictitious, is that a truly fundamental account of reality on their view
can dispense with self. Some Buddhist metaphysicians would share this view
(cf. Siderits’ and MacKenzie’s contributions to this volume). Although I
have sympathy with the idea that we shouldn’t multiply entities beyond
necessity, I think the view in question is far too austere. It is hard to see why
one shouldn’t declare social reality fictitious on the same account. If there is
no self, there can hardly be a you or a we either. In fact, it is hard to see why
we shouldn’t also declare the world we live in and know and care about
(including everyday objects and events like chairs, playing cards, operas, or
marriage ceremonies) illusory. Again, such a view is quite different from the
phenomenological attempt to rehabilitate our life-world.
In the preceding, I have discussed a thin experiential notion of self, and
have tried to present and defend this view. Ultimately, however, I favor
what might be called a multidimensional account of self. I think the self is so
multifaceted a phenomenon that various complementary accounts must be
integrated if we are to do justice to its complexity. I consequently don’t
think that the thin notion I have defended above is sufficient. It must be
supplemented by thicker notions that capture and do justice to other
important aspects of self. More specifically, I think our account of human
THE EXPERIENTIAL SELF: OBJECTIONS AND CLARIFICATIONS 71
reality is inadequate if we don’t also consider the self that forms plans, makes
promises, and accepts responsibilities, the self that is defined and shaped by
its values, ideals, goals, convictions, and decisions. Consider as a case in
point the issue of emotional investment: consider that we respond emo-
tionally to that which matters to us, to that which we care about, to that
towards which we are not indifferent. In that sense, one might argue that
emotions involve appraisals of what has importance, significance, value, and
relevance to oneself. Consider the extent to which emotions like shame,
guilt, pride, hope, and repentance help constitute our sense of self. Consider
in this context also the role of boundaries and limits. Your limits express the
norms and rules you abide by; they express what you can accept and what
you cannot accept. They constitute your integrity. To ask others to respect
your boundaries is to ask them to take you seriously as a person. A violation
of, or infringement upon, these boundaries is felt as invasive, and in some
cases as humiliating. To put it differently, when it comes to these facets of
self, I think boundaries, values, and emotions are extremely important, but I
don’t think an emphasis on boundaries has much to do with the endorse-
ment of an enduring soul-substance that remains the same from birth to
death. And I don’t see why opposition to the latter should necessitate a
rejection of the former as well. We are dealing with a culturally, socially,
and linguistically embedded self that is under constant construction. But is
this fact a reason for declaring the self in question illusory? I don’t see why,
unless, that is, one’s prior metaphysical commitments dictate it.
Very well, the skeptic might retort, but accepting that our experiential
life has a certain temporal density and extension is hardly the same as
accepting the existence of a persisting self from birth to death. Quite
right, I would reply, but even the former might be sufficient if you want
to defend the existence of transient short-term selves, as Galen Strawson has
consistently done (Strawson 2000), and I don’t think Dreyfus has provided
arguments against that specific notion of self.5 But more importantly,
although Dreyfus denies that in his own case there is an entity that has
endured from his childhood in Switzerland to his being a grown-up adult in
the US, he does concede that we, in the case of episodic memory, do not
have two absolutely different persons, the person remembering and the
person remembered. In fact, on his account, we do have to keep first-
personal self-givenness in mind, and although the remembering person is in
some sense different from the one being remembered, the difference is
certainly not as great as the one that separates me from other people
(Dreyfus, this volume, p.??). My present act of remembering and the past
act that is being remembered both share similar first-personal self-givenness.
They consequently have something in common that distinguishes them
from the experiences of others. As Dreyfus continues, when I remember a
past experience, I don’t just recall its content, I also remember it as being
given to me. Now on his account, there is something distorting about this,
insofar as the past experience is remembered as mine (thereby suggesting the
existence of an enduring self ), but as he continues, this isn’t a complete
distortion either (Dreyfus, this volume, p.??).
On my account, there is no experiential self, no self as defined from the
first-person perspective, when we are non-conscious.6 But this does not
5 In his defense of a no-self account, Krueger claims that a Who is neither necessary nor sufficient for
a How. In arguing for this view, Krueger repeatedly concedes that it might be legitimate to speak of
minimal selves (rather than of a minimal self ) (Krueger, this volume, p. ??). However, I find it quite hard
to understand how the existence of a plurality of selves is compatible with, or might even count in favor
of, a no-self theory, unless, of course, one stacks the deck by presupposing a quite particular definition
of self.
6 This is also why I don’t think the notion of experiential self will allow us to solve all relevant
questions regarding personal identity and persistence over time. Consider, for instance, the case of a man
who early in life makes a decision that proves formative for his subsequent life and career. The episode in
question is, however, subsequently forgotten by the person. He no longer enjoys first-person access to it.
If we restrict ourselves to what can be accounted for by means of the experiential core self, we cannot
speak of the decision as being his, as being one he made. Or take the case where we might wish to ascribe
responsibility for past actions to an individual who no longer remembers them. By doing that we
postulate an identity between the past offender and the present subject, but the identity in question is
74 DAN ZAHAVI
again not one that can be accounted for in terms of the experiential core self. But given my commitment
to a multidimensional account of self, I would precisely urge us to adopt a multilayered account of self.
We are more than experiential core selves, we are, for instance, also narratively configured and socially
constructed persons (cf. Zahavi 2007b). We shouldn’t forget that our life-stories are multi-authored.
Who we are is not something we exclusively determine ourselves. It is also a question of how we are seen
by others. Even if there is no experiential self (no self as defined from the first-person perspective) when
we are non-conscious, there are various other aspects of self that remain, and which make it perfectly
legitimate to say that we are non-conscious, that is, that we can persist even when non-conscious. For a
recent, very elaborate, and rather metaphysical discussion of these questions, cf. Dainton (2008).
THE EXPERIENTIAL SELF: OBJECTIONS AND CLARIFICATIONS 75
References
Albahari, M. (2006), Analytical Buddhism: The Two-Tiered Illusion of Self (New York:
Palgrave Macmillan).
——(2009), ‘Witness-Consciousness: Its Definition, Appearance and Reality’,
Journal of Consciousness Studies 16/1: 62–84.
Bodhi, Bhikkhu, editor (1993), A Comprehensive Manual of Abhidharma (Seattle,
WA: Buddhist Publication Society).
Campbell, J. (1994), Past, Space, and Self (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Dainton, B. (2008), The Phenomenal Self (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Dennett, Daniel Clement. 1992. ‘The Self as the Center of Narrative Gravity’,
in Frank S. Kessel, Pamela M. Cole, and Dale L. Johnson (eds.), Self and
Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum).
Ganeri, J. (2007), The Concealed Art of the Soul: Theories of Self and Practices of Truth
in Indian Ethics and Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Heidegger, M. (1993), Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (1919/1920). Gesamtaus-
gabe Band 58 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann).
Henry, M. (1963), L’essence de la manifestation (Paris: PUF).
——(1965), Philosophie et phénoménologie du corps (Paris: PUF).
Hobson, R. P. (2002), The Cradle of Thought (London: Macmillan).
7 One might here mention Ricoeur’s careful distinction between two concepts of identity: Identity
as sameness ( mêmeté) and identity as selfhood ( ipséité) (Ricoeur 1990). The first concept of identity, the
identity of the same (Latin: idem), conceives of the identical as that which can be re-identified again and
again, as that which resists change. The identity in question is that of an unchangeable substance, or
substrate, that remains the same over time. By contrast, the second concept of identity, the identity of the
self (Latin: ipse), has on Ricoeur’s account very little to do with the persistence of some unchanging
personality core. Whereas questions regarding the first concept of identity take the form of What
questions, questions regarding the second concept take the form of Who questions, and must be
approached from the first-person perspective.
THE EXPERIENTIAL SELF: OBJECTIONS AND CLARIFICATIONS 77
Husserl, E. (1954), Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale
Phänomenologie: Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie, Husserliana 6
(Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff ).
——(1966), Analysen zur passiven Synthesis: Aus Vorlesungs- und Forschungsmanu-
skripten 1918–1926, Husserliana 11 (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff ).
——(1973a), Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität: Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster
Teil: 1905–1920, Husserliana 13 (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff ).
——(1973b), Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität: Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter
Teil: 1929–1935, Husserliana 15 (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff ).
James, W. (1890), The Principles of Psychology I (London: Macmillan and Co.).
Lusthaus, D. (2002), Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara
Buddhism and the Ch’eng Wei-shih Lun (London: Routledge).
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002), Phenomenology of Perception (London: Routledge).
Metzinger, T. (2003), Being No One (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Neisser, U. (1988), ‘Five Kinds of Self-knowledge’, Philosophical Psychology
1/1: 35–59.
Reddy, V. (2008), How Infants Know Minds (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University
Press).
Ricoeur, P. (1990), Soi-même comme un autre (Paris: Seuil).
Rochat, P. (2001), The Infant’s World (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Sartre, J. (1967), ‘Consciousness of Self and Knowledge of Self ’, in N. Lawrence
and D. O’Connor (eds.), Readings in Existential Phenomenology (Englewood
Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall).
——(2003), Being and Nothingness (London: Routledge).
Seigel, J. (2005), The Idea of the Self: Thought and Experience in Western Europe Since
the Seventeenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Sorabji, R. (2006), Self: Ancient and Modern Insights about Individuality, Life and Death
(Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Stern, D. N. (1985), The Interpersonal World of the Infant (New York: Basic Books).
Strawson, G. (2000), ‘The phenomenology and ontology of the self ’, in D. Zahavi
(ed.), Exploring the Self (Amsterdam: John Benjamins).
Varela, F. and Shear, J. (1999), The View from Within: First-Person Approaches to the
Study of Consciousness (Thorverton: Imprint academic).
Wilde, O. (1969), De Profundis (London: Dawsons).
Zahavi, D. (1999), Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press).
——(2003) ‘Inner Time-Consciousness and Pre-reflective Self-Awareness’, in D.
Welton (ed.), The New Husserl: A Critical Reader (Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press).
78 DAN ZAHAVI
1. Introduction
2
This is not to deny that the Buddha did caution Brahmanical thinkers against becoming enamoured with
more theoretical elaborations of the self, involving eternal, non-physical impartite entities serving as the
vehicle of rebirth.
3
See Albahari (2006, chs. 2–4).
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
4
For a full definition and defense of the reality of witness-consciousness, see Albahari (2009). In Albahari
(2006), I specifically relate the notion of witness-consciousness to that of the consciousness aggregate
(Pali: khandhā; Sanskrit: skandha)–one of the five conditioned elements that Pali Buddhism claims to
constitute a person.
MIRI ALBAHARI
5
See, for example, Zahavi (2005a; 9–10) and Zahavi (2005b: 122–123). The distinction between witness-
consciousness and for-me-ness is discussed further in Albahari (2009: 67–68).
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
owner. In this manner, the subject does not merely approach the world and its
objects from an impersonal psycho-physical point of view (through whatever
sense modality); it deeply identifies with that viewpoint as a concrete place
where I, the self, am coming from. In tandem with perspectival ownership,
then, the sense of personal ownership is almost always in operation whenever
one alludes to such things as ‘my thoughts’, ‘my headache’, ‘my body’, or
‘my actions’.
While feelings of desire and attachment are possibly the most salient
phenomenal indicators of a sense of personal ownership (and hence identity as
a personal owner), these feelings need not be present for the sense of such
ownership to exist. This is particularly true in cases of profuse and mundane
phenomena such as thoughts, sensations, and one's body. The sheer ubiquity
with which such items are presented as personally ‘mine’ makes it quite
impossible, in normal cases, to discern the distinct phenomenal quality of such
‘mineness’. For, as it happens, most people do not know what it is like to lack
it. It is mainly pathological impairments, where the sense of personal
ownership seems lost or compromised, that draw attention to the fact that
there is this other major type (or sense) of ownership alongside the
perspectival and possessive varieties. Subjects of anosognosia, for instance,
may feel that a paralysed limb ‘does not belong’ to them, while subjects of
depersonalization commonly sense a disconnection in ownership from many
of their thoughts.6 While in cases of depersonalization the lack of personal-
ownership feelings tends not to be global (e.g. they still identify as the subject
of the dreadful condition that has befallen them), there is nevertheless a
notable lack of identification with the perspectival owner of those thoughts
from which they do feel disconnected. With reference to any object, then, a
lack of personal mineness goes in tandem with a lack of personal me-ness.
(Note that a possible suspension in the sense of personal ownership does not
by itself prove such ownership to lack independent reality, any more than its
suspension during deep sleep would prove its lack of reality. This point will
be returned to later).
Subsumed under the role ‘personal owner’ are other frequent modes of
identity that further delineate the type of self we take ourselves to be. Two
6
A level of disconnection in the sense of personal ownership may sometimes occur via the mode of
agency, such that one feels that someone else has authored a particular line of thought, such as during
‘thought insertion’ in schizophrenia. As I consider the sense of agency to be grounded in a sense of personal
ownership, the general point remains: a compromise in identification as author of the thought is a
compromise in some level of identification as its personal owner.
MIRI ALBAHARI
closely related such modes are agent and thinker. ‘The agent’ is the owner-
subject in its capacity of initiating actions. Taking pride or being ashamed of
perspectivally owned actions is an obvious way of identifying with the
perspectival owner qua agent, such that one deeply feels ‘I am the initiator of
this action’ (think of the proud winner of an Olympic medal). Such emotions
also provide evidence of regarding oneself to have special causal powers that
enable the active choice of one course of action over another, as opposed to a
passive determination by the flow of events. To feel guilty, for instance,
implies an assumption that one should not have acted in a particular way—and
hence, arguably, an assumption that one could have acted differently.
Intentional actions originate in thought, so the thinker is a closely related
mode of identity. Importantly, we take ourselves to be the originator,
controller, or observer of the thoughts, rather than to be, in essence, the
content of thought. Put in terms of an attribute, the assumed self is something
that is unconstructed—that is, not constructed from the content of thoughts
and perceptions, etc.—some underlying thing that is their precedent rather
than their product.
Any sense of identity, whether with a general role such as owner or agent,
or a specific idea about who one is (for example, a female ice-dancing
champion), evokes the elusive feeling of being bounded by that identity.
Faced with the world and its objects, the subject thus reflexively presents not
merely as a point of view, but as a unique and bounded thing with a point of
view. This attribute of boundedness is absolutely central to the assumed self:
it turns the perspectival into a personal owner. The bounded self seems,
moreover, to be perfectly unified, in that its differing and shifting roles and
identities (such as personal owner/actor/thinker, female/skater/champion)
appear seamlessly integrated within the very same subject. A feeling of
excitement at the upcoming ceremony may simultaneously trigger all the
different roles, but it does not feel to the subject as if each role or identity
corresponds to a numerically distinct self, or even to different compartments
within a single self. Importantly, the field of unity seems to extend beyond the
roles of the subject to share in the set of objects perspectivally and personally
owned by it. Perceptions, thoughts, and experiences, felt as belonging to the
subject, present as belonging to the subject's very same field of consciousness,
such that it seems natural to say: ‘I, the self, am simultaneously aware of the
white ice and the cheering crowd’, or ‘The very same self that a few minutes
ago saw the white ice heard the cheering crowd’. While the unity of
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
7
Galen Strawson defines an ‘Episodic’ person as such: ‘one doesn't figure oneself, the self or person one
now experiences oneself to be, as something that was there in the (further) past and will be there in the
(further) future’ (Strawson 2008: 210). He contrasts this with ‘Diachronic’ persons who do have a sense of
identity with their earlier and future selves.
MIRI ALBAHARI
How, in general terms, might this self turn out to be illusory? Could it be
illusory in more than one way? These questions are addressed in this section,
where I propose that the standard Western ‘bundle theory’ of no-self differs
markedly from how no-self ought to be understood if nirvana, as depicted in
Pali Buddhism, is possible. As already mentioned, this will involve a major
challenge to the typical forms of Buddhist reductionism that cast no-self in
Buddhism as a type of bundle theory.
What does it take, in general terms, for something to be illusory? Illusions
(including delusions and hallucinations) essentially involve a mismatch
between appearance and reality, such that something appears to be a particular
way, when, in reality, it is not actually that way. Typical cases include the
Muller Lyer Illusion (two lines appearing to be of unequal lengths when they
are actually of equal length), a hallucination of the pink elephant, the sense of
being watched by extra-terrestrials. In all these instances, the world does not
veridically underpin the way the world appears to be, whether the medium of
appearance is perceptual or cognitive. If the self is illusory, then the world
(which includes the world of subjectivity) must similarly fail to deliver at least
one of its defining characteristics as presented via the self's characteristic
mode of appearance.
Given that the self purports to be something that is entirely unconstructed
in all its defining features, a straightforward route to casting the self as
illusory suggests itself: argue that at least one of these features is constructed
from the content of those thoughts, experiences, and perceptions to which the
self seems opposed. In this way, the self will not be what it fundamentally
appears to be—it will be (at least in part) the product, rather than the
precedent, of thoughts and experiences. Put another way, the sense of self,
which presents as being thoroughly grounded in (and actually identical to) the
(unconstructed) self, will be grounded in factors other than this self.
A word about the sense of self is in order here, since ‘self’ and ‘sense of
self’ are sometimes confused. The sense of self is the appearance of a self,
pertaining to the reflexive feeling or conscious impression of being a self.
Throughout the discussion, I have been supposing that this feeling, although
elusive to attentive purview, is real enough. What is in question is the veracity
of its content: the self. Indeed, philosophers who deny the existence of the self
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
do not generally deny the sense of self, any more than those who deny the
existence of libertarian free will would deny the common feeling of such free
will. In fact, as libertarian free will is sometimes (although not always)
ascribed to the self in its capacity of being an agent, it can, because of the
history of debate on the subject, provide a useful illustration of just how it is
that a feature of the self (that we assume we are) may fail to reflect reality:
how the sense of self, in other words, may fail to be grounded in a self.
Suppose, then, that determinism is correct, leaving no ontological room
for an entity that could genuinely originate one course of action over another
(the past being what it is). Suppose also that we (most humans) have a sense
of being a self with this controversial sort of agency (a feeling that may be
evidenced through such emotions as guilt). The feeling of free will will
reflexively convey the cognitive content of being an entity that really does
exercise such agency—not just of appearing to exercise it. So if determinism
is to rule out the reality of such agency, then the sense of being a
self qua libertarian agent will not be grounded in an actual agent-self, as it
appears to be, but (at least partially) in the content of thoughts and feelings to
which the self seems ontologically opposed. The thoughts and feelings will, in
other words, be helping to create the conscious impression of there being a
source of agency that is able to exercise libertarian control over the thoughts
and feelings and actions—when, in reality, there is no such source of agency.
The self, qua libertarian agent, will thus be an illusion created by the content
of thought (etc.). It will fail to exist in the essential manner that it purports to
exist, as something that stands entirely behind the thoughts, authoring the
intentional actions.
To recapitulate: if the self exists, then it is an entity with a conjunction of
unconstructed essential roles and features. Should at least one of these roles or
features (such as agency) turn out to be mentally constructed, then the self, so
defined, will not exist. The usual (but unacknowledged) strategy at the heart
of most attempts to deny the existence of self is thus to argue that at least one
essential feature of the self is a mental construct. Seeing this strategy at work
will help to determine more exactly how the typical Western construal of no-
self could differ from the way in which the self would fail to exist if nirvana
were possible. I first examine some standard Western accounts of no-self
before comparing this analysis to the case at hand.
David Hume is commonly considered to have pioneered the Western
philosophical position on no-self, his work sometimes compared by scholars
MIRI ALBAHARI
The identity which we ascribe to the mind of man is only a fictitious [viz.,
constructed] one, and of a like kind with that which we ascribe to
vegetables and animal bodies. It cannot therefore have a different origin,
but must proceed from a like operation in the imagination upon like
objects.…identity [and simplicity] is nothing really belonging to these
different perceptions, and uniting them together, but is merely a quality
which we attribute to them, because of the union of their ideas in the
imagination when we reflect upon them. (Hume 1739: I, IV, vi)
common-sense insists that the unity of all the selves is not a mere
appearance of similarity or continuity, ascertained after the fact. She is
sure that it involves a real belonging to a real Owner [a source of unity],
to a pure spiritual entity of some kind. Relation to this entity is what
makes the self's constituents stick together as they do for
thought.(James 1890: 337)
The illusion is that there are two things: on one side, a self, an ego, an ‘I’,
that organizes experience, originates action, and accounts for our
unchanging identity as persons and, on the other side, the stream of
experience. If this view is misleading, what is the better view? The better
view is that what there is, and all there is, is the stream of experience.
‘Preposterous! What then does the thinking?’ comes the response. The
answer is that ‘the thoughts themselves are the thinkers’ (James, 1892,
83)8…We are egoless.(Flanagan 1992: 178)
Each normal individual of this species makes a self. Out of its brain it
spins a web of words and deeds and, like other creatures, it doesn't have to
know what it's doing; it just does it…Our tales are spun, but for the most
part we don't spin them; they spin us. Our human consciousness, and our
narrative selfhood, is their product, not their source…These strings or
streams of narrative issue forth as if from a single source…their effect on
8
Flanagan cites William James (1892), Psychology: The Briefer Course, G. Allport (ed)., New York:
Harper and Row, 1961.
MIRI ALBAHARI
any audience is to encourage them to (try to) posit a unified agent whose
words they are, about whom they are: in short, to posit a center of
narrative gravity. (Dennett 1991: 418)
These thinkers typify the way in which the self is denied in Western
philosophy, by giving constructed and thereby illusory status to the central
unified subject, where the unity is understood to be both synchronic and
diachronic. While the accounts differ in their details of how exactly the
impression of unity and unbrokenness is constructed—such as which mental
faculties contribute to the illusion—all of them deny the existence of self
principally via this avenue. The impression of unity and unbrokenness, as it
qualifies a minimal subject (or perspectival owner) standing opposed to the
stream of experience, must be entirely fabricated from the bundle of discrete
mental phenomena to which it seems opposed. Essentially, they are what are
known as bundle theories of the self.
I now ask: is this way of understanding the self as illusory—as a bundle
theory that denies unconstructed reality to unity and unbrokenness to the
self qua minimal subject—in line with how we should understand the status of
‘no-self’ if nirvana, as depicted in the Pali sutras, is to be possible? As I noted
in the Introduction, this is exactly how Buddhist philosophical tradition has
typically understood the doctrine of no-self. To this end, there are different
versions of the bundle theory. The more extreme version (a non-reflexive
reductionism inspired by Abhidharma tradition), has it that all impressions of
unity—synchronic and diachronic—are illusory constructs from an ontology
of momentary, causally connected aggregates. A less extreme version of
bundle theory (which I call ‘reflexive reductionism’, inspired mainly by
Yogācāra-Sautrāntika tradition) allows a measure of synchronic unity to exist
through each conscious experience being reflexively aware of itself (perhaps
for the length of a specious present).9 Such temporal unity, however, does not
extend beyond the specious present, and it belongs not to any subject, but to
the discrete experiences that form the changing stream of consciousness. All
variants of bundle theory within the gamut of Buddhist tradition thus uphold
the unreality or illusory status of an unbroken and unified witness-
consciousness which, as modus operandi of the (minimal) subject, stands apart
9
My use of the term ‘reflexive reductionism’ is intended to depict the allegiance to bundle-theory, rather
than reflect how its advocates would label their position (they would probably not, in their own context of
use, call it ‘reductionist’).
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
from and observes the stream of experience. (Note that while Dreyfus (this
volume) does not regard reflexive reductionism as a bundle theory, it counts
as a bundle theory for the purposes of this discussion). Now I am well aware
that the argument about to be offered, which defends nirvana (in the sutras) as
entailing the unbroken unity of observational witness-consciousness (at least
during the scope of waking life), flies in the face of many Buddhist
philosophical traditions—and so will in that sense be denied by many to be
truly ‘Buddhist’. So be it. What I do contend is that my position offers a more
coherent philosophical reconstruction of the early Buddhist sutras than the
bundle theory, and that the position, although not stated explicitly in the
sutras, is quite consistent with them.
Before commencing with the argument, I need to say more about how
reflexive and non-reflexive varieties of reductionism are to be distinguished.
According to reflexive reductionism (discussed in various forms by Dreyfus,
Thompson, MacKenzie, and Krueger in this volume) ‘consciousness cognizes
itself in cognizing its object’ (Siderits, this volume, p. 318), so there is nothing
more to consciousness than the cognizing experiences themselves. Put another
way, the immediate object of a cognition is not the object out there in the
world (such as the blueberry): it is the phenomenal experience of cognizing
the object and ‘the experience of seeing blue is just the occurrence of a
cognition that has blue color as its form’ (Siderits, this volume, p. 317). A
stream of different consciousnesses thus amounts to a stream of multi-modal
experiences: there is no separate cognizing subject. According to non-
reflexive reductionism (discussed by Siderits in this volume), consciousness is
not self-intimating in this way: it is an object-directed awareness that arises in
conjunction with the various sensory or mental objects (including
experiences) that form its intentional content. I address each version in turn,
beginning with the latter.
On Buddhist non-reflexive reductionism ‘consciousness arises in
dependence on contact between sense faculty and sensible object.…the
consciousness that takes the color of the flower as object must be distinct from
that which takes its smell as object a moment later’ (Siderits, this volume, p.
313). Each momentary consciousness imparts information to the next
moment: there is no temporal gap between each moment. Each composite
moment of object-directed consciousness (if it is, contra reflexive
reductionism, more than just the occurrence of the target mental or sensory
object) will presumably have built into it an invariant observational
MIRI ALBAHARI
a picture which, when taken literally, has the meditator experientially aware
that their discerning consciousness is impermanent. I contend that the best
way to make sense of such a passage is to suppose that the meditator is
actually aware of different directions that are being taken by consciousness (in
virtue of the objects)—a picture that does not entail Buddhist reductionism. So
when the Pali sutras speak of consciousness as being impermanent, I take this
to mean that the intentional content of consciousness—that to which
consciousness is directed—is constantly changing. One moment there is
consciousness of green and round, and the next, consciousness of crunching
and apple-taste. But this is not the same as saying that the observational
component that is directed towards these objects is itself arising and passing
away. So what is my argument against this interpretation of Pali Buddhism?
Let me first be clear on what I am not arguing. I am not arguing that the
impression of unified unbroken consciousness is impossible under reductivist
ontology. My argument is instead based upon an epistemic aspect that grows
out of the idea that the primary mode for understanding the mind, in nirvana,
is experiential. Nirvana is often depicted as ‘ultimate’ in the Pali sutras, not
only in an axiological but an epistemic sense. Statements made from the
nirvanic perspective are taken to be authoritative: there is never the idea that
they could be usurped by philosophical or scientific discovery. For example,
there is never any intimation in the Pali sutras that the Buddha or arahant
could be mistaken in saying such things as ‘conditioned phenomena are
impermanent, conducive to suffering and without a self’. I call this the
‘Experience Condition’:
Experience Condition: The primary mode of knowledge/wisdom/insight,
in the nirvanic state, is based on first-person experience and the first-person
perspective has authority over the third-person theoretical perspective. In
cases of a conflict between first‐personal nirvanic perspective and third-
person theoretical perspective, regarding the nature of the conscious mind, the
first‐person nirvanic perspective trumps the theoretical.10
10
Note that I am not defending the Experience Condition as a stand-alone condition in this paper, although
towards the end of the paper it re-emerges as a suggested way to save the appearances. In relation to the
concept of nirvana across Buddhist traditions, however, the Experience Condition may need further
defense. For example, Siderits (this volume) points out that in Yogācāra subjective idealism, consciousness
is regarded as ultimately non-dual in nature. Nirvanic realization will involve a complete dissolution of the
idea that there is an external world with its objects—and hence, according to Siderits, a dissolution in the
feeling of subjective interiority which must depend upon the subject/object split. Thus ‘Yogācāra subjective
idealism involves an explicit disavowal of the perspectival self argued for by Albahari’ (this volume p.
318). So if the ideal nirvanic state involves no sense of interiority or first-person perspective, then how can
MIRI ALBAHARI
I will argue that the Experience Condition entails (on the nirvanic
hypothesis) that the aspect of consciousness which cognizes the
impermanence of phenomena is neither discrete, nor reducible to the changing
stream—at least during wakefulness. I begin by asking: how would the
cognizance of an impermanent consciousness (by an impermanent
consciousness) work on a reductivist account? It could not be that each
moment of consciousness reflexively observes its own coming and going. For
regardless of whether or not we are dealing with reflexive consciousness, it
would entail the contradictory state of a conscious moment being present to its
own coming and going. The impermanence (or diachronic disunity) of the
discerning cognitions must therefore, on any reductivist account, be
experienced retrospectively.11 So let us suppose that a discerning cognition at
t3 is a momentary member in a causal chain of conscious moments t1- tn and
that it retrospectively (whether via memory or retention) discerns the
impermanence of prior members of the chain. As this cannot include itself (t3),
it will have to discern, say, the numerical transition from moments t1 and t2,
before itself becoming retrospectively discerned as impermanent by a later
cognition, say t5. And here is where I see the problem for non-
reflexive reductionism, for the only way that t3 can experientially distinguish
the transition from t1 to t2is by discerning the changing content of t1 to t2—the
object towards which each consciousness is directed. But this does not tell us
that at each moment, the observational component is in fact numerically
discrete—it just tells us that the objects are. There is in fact no way to
phenomenologically tell whether the underlying ‘objective’ scenario (if there
is a further truth to the matter) is that of a contiguous chain of numerically
nirvanic authority be indexed to a first-person perspective? Here we must tread carefully; ‘first-person
perspective’ or ‘interiority’ is ambiguous. If it means ‘experience confined to a dualistic subject/object
structure’ then I would agree that ultimate non-dual consciousness must lack this structure, and so the first-
person perspective must lack ultimate authority. But if it means that ‘there is something it is like to
experience non-dual consciousness’—and elsewhere (2006) I attempt to convey in some detail what this
could mean—then ‘first-person perspective’ would not be disavowed by non-dual consciousness. (I suspect
that it lies behind many of the intimations that nirvana is experienced, not inferred). Be that as it may, I
would insist that so long as objects are experienced, the dualistic (subject/object) first-person perspective,
with its perspectival subject, is unavoidable. And so long as the domain of judgment from the nirvanic
perspective is about subjective experience in its relation to its objects, then the Experience Condition, even
if construed narrowly, remains intact. If it cannot but seem as if objects are being witnessed by (a subject's)
unbroken conscious awareness, then (if nirvana is possible) this will indeed be how things are, even if the
unbroken awareness, in its intrinsic nature, is not confined to the perspective of a subject.
11
I put aside any problem that might arise with elusiveness of the discerning cognition, as it is not clear
that non-reflexive reductionists would accept this aspect, and I want to engage in the debate on their terms.
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
experience contains more than simply the flow with its first-personal
givenness. As a matter of phenomenal necessity, there will seem to be a
perspectival owner that stands apart from the stream, such that it cognizes the
experiences that are first-personally ‘given’ to it.12
Suppose the reflexive reductionists re-assess their phenomenological
stance, agreeing that the ascription of first-person givenness entails the
(elusive) appearance of a subject to which the experiences are given. They are
still free to defend the ontological side of their position by insisting that,
despite appearances, there is no separate subject of experience. If they are
correct in this assessment, then the witnessing subject will be a mere illusion
projected forth by the invariant dimension of an otherwise diverse stream of
experiences. If a subject-realist is correct in their ontological assessment, then
the appearance of the observing subject will reflect how things actually are.
And here is where reflexive reductionism does get into trouble. Just as the
dispute over whether the observational component is unbroken cannot be
resolved without going beyond the first-personal appearance and appealing to
philosophical analysis, the dispute over whether the minimal observing
subject (to whom experiences are given) is chimerical cannot be settled
without going beyond how things must appear. So if reflexive reductionists
are correct in supposing the subject of experience to be chimerical rather than
real, then nirvanic insight into this fact will have to be purely intellectual,
rather than experientially based. With no experiential avenue through which to
characterize the potential shift from incorrect to correct perspective, the
dramatic nirvanic insight into no-self will be left unaccounted for.
But as mentioned earlier, the Pali sutras do not leave such matters
unsettled: matters are arbitrated by the Experience Condition, which privileges
the first-person perspective of nirvana. If it must seem, from the nirvanic
perspective, that there is a minimal subject of our changing experience, then
this will not be a mere appearance that can be usurped by theoretical
inference. The limits of nirvanic appearance will dictate the scope of mental
reality. So if nirvana (as depicted in the Pali sutras) is possible, reflexive
reductionism does no better than the non-reflexive version at eliminating the
invariant and unbrokenly observing subject of experience. The cognitive
transformation of nirvana, I conclude, cannot be an insight into the fact that
12
I develop this line of argument from another angle in Albahari (2009).
MIRI ALBAHARI
our mental life lacks such a perspectival owner and entirely comprises fleeting
cognitions.
This leaves us with the question: in virtue of what features should we say
that the self is constructed (hence illusory), if nirvana, as depicted in Pali
Buddhism, is to be possible? How do we construe the cognitive
transformation whereby the constructed status of the self is seen through? I
contend that personal ownership and boundedness (and agency to the extent
that it requires identity as a personal owner of the actions) are the most likely
features of the self to be constructed. To reiterate: a personal owner is a
perspectival owner that has identified with a variety of roles (including the
basic role of perspectival owner), such that the bare witnessing perspective is
cemented into a definitive thing with an identity (a ‘me’). It is a subject with
personalized boundaries, which personally (not just perspectivally) owns its
thoughts, perceptions, feelings, experiences, and possessions. Given that there
are known pathologies which compromise the usually ubiquitous sense of
bounded identity, it is quite possible to conceive of a state, akin to global
depersonalization, where all sense of bounded identity is lost. This opens up
the distinct cognitive potential for a transformative experiential insight into
the reality of no-self, although by all accounts it will not be pathological.
On this hypothesis, the illusion of self will arise through the mechanism of
identification. Identification (to reiterate) is the appropriation of mental
content to the subject's perspective, such that the content seems to qualify (and
hence filter) the very outlook through which the world is approached. To the
untrained perspective, it will appear as if identification is not constructing, but
revealing various aspects of the self's permanent, prior existence. But the
bounded self will in fact, on this hypothesis, be constructed through the
process of identification. On the face of it, this sounds rather similar to how
MacKenzie describes the process of ‘self-appropriation’ (MacKenzie, this
volume p. 264). There is a crucial difference, however. On MacKenzie's
construal of Buddhism (a version of reflexive reductionism), the minimal
unbroken subject emerges from the act of appropriation, giving it a
constructed status (à la bundle theory), whereas on my construal of Buddhism,
the minimal unbroken subject is the unconstructed locus of appropriation.
With each act of identification, the perspectival owner imports its
unconstructed, unified and unbroken witness-consciousness into the illusion
of self, such that it appears that the bounded self is the originator of these
qualities. And with each act of identification, the discrete mental content
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
(identified with by the minimal subject) colors the perspectival outlook of the
subject, such that the unconstructed subject appears as a bounded personal
owner. (The dual constructed/unconstructed contribution is the reason I call it
the two-tiered illusion of self). To the extent that unity and unbrokenness are
ascribed to a subject that seems personally bounded, the unconstructed
features will themselves undergo a measure of distortion. Hence: thoughts,
feelings, perceptions, and experiences will seem presented to a personal
unified owner insofar as there is the sense of being a someone with a personal
boundary that operates from, and is in charge of, the unified perspective. The
personal unified owner/agent/thinker will assume a thicker diachronic identity
as the natural (moment-to-moment) unbrokenness of witness-consciousness
becomes folded into the impression of a bounded self with a life-history and
anticipated future that plans, remembers, deliberates, and wishes.
In view of this analysis, I propose that nirvana, as a deep and
transformative insight into no-self, be understood as the culmination of a
process whereby the trained use of witness-consciousness, through meditation,
brings about a full de-identification from all mental and physical
phenomena.13 The result will be the undoing of the self illusion. How exactly
the process of de-identification could work is a topic for further research, but
the general idea, I contend, is as follows. Identification is the appropriation of
highly impermanent mental content (objects) to a subject's first-person
perspective. So long as the objects remain appropriated to the subject's
perspective, as part of the self's ‘unconstructed’ identity, their status as
impermanent objects will be effectively rendered invisible, such that the
subject is change-blind to their coming and going. The process of meditation
will train the subject's attention to become increasingly percipient ofthe
degree to which mental phenomena do change. So long as objects are being
viewed for what they really are—as changeable objects—they cannot be
simultaneously appropriated to the subject's perspective. By extrapolation, a
full observation of all perspectival objects in their true state of transience,
from moment to conscious moment, will imply a complete lack of
identification with any of them. I anticipate that the process of de-
identification would gain extra momentum as the subject repeatedly observes,
13
The general strategy of attaining nirvana, through de-identifying from all phenomena, has support from
the famous Anattā-lakkhaṇa Sutta in the Pali Canon. In this, the Buddha urges his disciples to lose the
sense of personal ownership and identification towards all categories of object (mental and physical), such
that there is the discernment: ‘This is not mine. This is not my self. This is not what I am’.
MIRI ALBAHARI
with increasing clarity, the mechanism by which identification works (via its
undoing). Just as uncovering a magician's trick makes it impossible to keep on
being fooled by it, lifting the veil of identification will make it impossible to
remain fooled by its content of self-identity. Viewing the real nature of
consciousness as unbounded by ties of identification is, I hold, what nirvanic
insight actually entails. It may be tempting to hold that in view of such a
realization, the arahant now believes ‘I am not a bounded self—I am witness-
consciousness’. This is misguided, for such a belief would incur further
identification and hence a new binding identity. Nevertheless, I contend that
nirvana involves a direct realization that consciousness, in the impersonal
sense, is ownerless, in the personal sense.
[The patient] would have remained awake and attentive enough to process
the object that came next into his perceptual purview, but inasmuch as we
can deduce from the situation, that is all that would go on in the mind.
There would have been no plan, no forethought, no sense of an individual
organism wishing, wanting, considering, believing. There would have
been no sense of self, no identifiable person with a past and an anticipated
future—specifically, no core self and no autobiographical
self.(Damasio 1999: 98).
Now to the second worry. Accepting that the personal owner (as a whole)
is constructed, is there reason to suppose that the perspectival owner (a
component of the personal owner) is not? I have only argued, so far, that the
appearance of the perspectival owner is real—that there must seem to be a
unified subject to which the stream is given. But it might turn out that the
perspectival owner, even if operating as the locus of identification, is itself a
mental construct, rather than unconstructed as it purports to be. In such a case
it seems conceivable that its mental construction could occur through some
avenue other than identification, perhaps through the innate action of memory
and the imagination, as Hume claims. In such a case, the constructed synthesis
of unity and unbrokenness (as it applies to witnessing perspective) could
occur below the threshold of what we could ever be aware of, ruling out any
hope of cutting through the illusion of self in the manner that Buddhist
practice thinks possible. The advantage of such a hypothesis parallels that of
the previous argument. It seems more scientifically parsimonious to favor a
theory that appeals to relatively known quantities, such as thoughts,
perceptions, memory, imagination, and the brain, than to quantities that are
metaphysically mysterious. The presence of an intrinsically unified, invariant
and unbroken witness-consciousness that qualifies the perspectival owner
does, by comparison, seem to be more mysterious, not only because it resists
reduction to the more familiar psychological components, but because, unlike
thoughts and perceptions, it is elusive to attentive observation, making it more
resistant to both scientific and introspective methods.
I've argued elsewhere (e.g. Albahari 2009) that the unified perspectival
subject cannot be illusory (as conditions for the possibility of an illusion
taking hold require there to be a perspectival subject). I now wish to present a
different but related argument for the reality of such a (unified) subject, which
focuses on conditions for the possibility of a stream of experience. Putting
aside versions of eliminative materialism (that altogether deny reality to
subjective life),17 advocates of a bundle theory will insist that any impression
of a unified perspectival subject (should they agree to such an impression) is
an illusory projection from the stream of discrete, causally connected, multi-
modal experiences. Why illusory? Being a causal projection from the stream,
the subject will not be unconstructed by the stream, as it purports to be. But
what, then, can it mean for the stream to cause the subject (or its appearance
17
I discuss an eliminative materialist brand of no-self in Albahari (2006: 165–167).
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
While this version of the Experience Condition needs further defense and
elaboration (it should not easily allow for the existence of libertarian free will
or the self, for instance), it goes some way towards establishing that moment-
to-moment, unbroken, invariant witness-consciousness is real. This in turn
goes some way towards establishing that the bundle theory, which bestows
constructed status to such witness-consciousness, is false.
The possibility of nirvana, I argued earlier, implies a two-tiered illusion of
self. In this section, I have argued that (a) the architecture of the mind is
empirically compatible with a model of two-tiered self-illusion, in that it
allows the absence of a sense of personal ownership to be coupled with the
presence of what would seem to be perspectival ownership and (b) the best
explanation for this empirical data is one that supports a two-tiered illusion of
self (as opposed to self-realism or the bundle theory). This provides the
possibility of nirvana with an independent measure of support.
Nirvana is the undoing of the self-illusion, and on the account offered, it will
be a process by which the perspectival owner de-identifies with any idea held
about ‘who one is’. The sense of being a bounded personal owner will be
gradually eroded, freeing the (personally) ownerless consciousness intrinsic to
nirvana. Having established the architecture of mind as potentially suitable for
such de-identification, one might suppose that an easy tasklies ahead in
proving the psychological possibility of nirvana. This is far from true. A major
obstacle pertains to the very case studies that served to buttress my earlier
arguments. In all the cases where Damasio alludes to a sense of personal
ownership being notably absent, the pathology is so severe that the patient is
unable to function in the world. Ownerless consciousness has been
malfunctioning consciousness. These sorts of considerations lead Damasio to
conclude that ‘a state of consciousness which encompasses a sense of self as
conceptualized in this book is indispensable for survival’ (Damasio 1999:
203–204).
A major challenge for those defending the psychological possibility of
nirvana is thus to show how it could be possible for the sense of self to be
MIRI ALBAHARI
eroded in ways that avoid debilitating pathology. A clue may well lie in the
quality of attention that is cultivated during meditation. In all the cases
enlisted by Damasio, where the sense of personal ownership is entirely
suspended, the quality of attention has been abnormally low (e.g. in epileptic
automatism, Alzheimer's disease and akinetic mutism). The high quality of
attention that is cultivated in the meditative states may thus offset the
pathological side-effects, especially as Damasio notes higher-quality attention
to be a reliable indicator of mental acuity (Damasio 1999; 182–183). With the
mounting studies outlining the neuropsychological benefits of meditation, a
measure of empirical support may well, already, be forthcoming.19
References
19
My thanks to Mark Siderits, Evan Thompson, Dan Zahavi and the anonymous reviewers for their critical
feedback on earlier drafts. My thanks to the philosophy department at the University of Calgary for
providing a venue from which to take on the critical feedback during my sabbatical leave.
NIRVANA AND OWNERLESS CONSCIOUSNESS
1. Introduction
scholars of that tradition, a process that involves not just the philological
exploration of new sources, but also the development of the philosophical
concepts necessary to connect this old tradition to contemporary concerns.
This process has started recently2 but has still some way to go before we can
say with confidence that the Indian views about the mind and consciousness
have been well understood and integrated into the contemporary discussions.
The goal of this essay3 is to contribute to this process by attempting to
relate some of the Buddhist views to contemporary discussions concerning
consciousness. It should be clear, however, that in dealing with this topic I
have no pretension to provide ‘the Buddhist view of consciousness’.
Buddhism is a plural tradition that has evolved over centuries to include a
large variety of views about the mind. Hence, there is no one view that can
ever hope to qualify as ‘the Buddhist view of consciousness’. Moreover, the
exploration of a difficult concept such as consciousness should not be thought
of as a matter that can be completed easily. Buddhist traditions contain a
wealth of material relevant to the mental, but such wealth is not always
obvious. Hence, the inclusion of Buddhist views of consciousness should be
thought of as an ongoing process of translation in which the richness of the
Buddhist tradition is gradually connected to contemporary discussions rather
than as a finished product.
In discussing consciousness within the Buddhist context, it is difficult to
avoid broaching another very large topic, that of the self. Buddhism is often
presented in the contemporary philosophical literature as advocating a
thorough denial of the reality of the self akin to the bundle theory of the
person attributed to Locke, Hume, and Parfit. This no-self view of the person
is also at times understood to entail not just the thorough denial of the reality
of any self-entity, but also to enable us to dispense with notions such as
consciousness, experience, and subjectivity. In this essay, I argue that,
although the bundle theory of the person has support within the Buddhist
tradition, it is not as universally admitted as is often assumed, and certainly
does not represent ‘the Buddhist view of the person’. For one, a significant
minority of Buddhist Indian thinkers reject altogether the no-self view,
2
See, for example, Waldron (2002) and Dreyfus and Thompson (2007).
3
I would like to thank all the people who have helped me in sorting these difficult ideas. I cannot mention
all of them, but particular thanks are due to Joseph Cruz, Evan Thompson, Mark Siderits, John Dunne, Miri
Albahari, Jeffrey Hopkins, Gerald Hess, Jay Garfield, Robert Roeser, and many others, for their useful
comments and feedback.
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
advocating a position according to which the self exists as a process based on,
but not reducible to, the body–mind complex (Priestly, nd.). But even among
the majority of thinkers who rally to the dominant no-self standpoint, there are
substantial differences about the ways in which the person is conceptualized
within a no-self paradigm. This seems particularly true of the Yogācāra
tradition, which offers an account of the person as being selfless and yet
centered around the notion of reflexive subjectivity, a view that goes well
beyond the bundle theory of the person and stands in stark contrast with the
elimination of notions such as consciousness and experience, as I show here.
In arguing for what I believe is a more defensible Buddhist view of
consciousness and the person than is often presented in the secondary
literature, I offer a philosophical reconstruction, rather than an historically
accurate rendering of what the original texts actually said. Hence, I feel free to
mine Indian and Tibetan sources without being bound to adopt all the views
that these texts advocate. For example, I often rely on the Abhidharma,
particularly its Yogācāra version, and its Tibetan offshoots, which I believe
contain a wealth of psychological and philosophical insights relevant to
contemporary concerns but not yet fully exploited. But in arguing for a
Yogācāra-inspired view of the person and consciousness I do not feel
compelled to take a stance on the often debated question of whether the
Yogācāra view entails a form of idealism or not.4 My concerns here are quite
different, being limited to cognitive and phenomenological considerations,
which are not always usefully connected to metaphysical or ontological
questions.
In the following pages, I discuss the nature of the person in Buddhist
philosophy within a phenomenologically informed perspective that examines
the sense that we have of ourselves rather than focusing on purely ontological
considerations. I rest my analysis on the distinction between self and
subjectivity, arguing that we need a Buddhist account of the latter, not as an
objective self-entity, but as a process of self-awareness. In making my case, I
address the phenomenological tradition and its views of subjectivity,
particularly through the work of Dan Zahavi, who has shown the contributions
that phenomenology can make to an account of consciousness within the
context of contemporary cognitive science and analytical philosophy. I also
4
This topic has been the focus of an enormous literature that cannot be listed here. For two interesting
recent contributions, see Lusthaus (2002) and Hopkins (2002).
GEORGES DREYFUS
The basics of the Buddhist conception of the mind I defend here derive from
the Abhidharma tradition. Briefly, the object of the Abhidharma is to analyze
the realm of sentient experience and the world given in such experience, in a
language that undermines the postulation of an enduring unified subject. The
Abhidharma analyzes experience into its basic elements (dharmas), listing and
grouping them into the appropriate categories. In this project, the Abhidharma
is following the central tenets of Buddhist philosophy, the twin ideas of non-
substantiality and dependent origination. On this view, the phenomena given
in experiences are not unitary and stable substances, but complex and
ephemeral formations of basic events arising within complex causal nexuses.
This is particularly true of the person, who is not a substantial self but a
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
I will defend a view of the mind that embraces this perspective, limiting
myself to the discovery of the phenomenology of mental states and leaving
ontological questions to the side. It is in this context that I understand the
distinction that most Ābhidharmikas draw between the real components of the
mind–body complex and the fictional, or illusory, self. Whereas traditional
Ābhidharmikas hold this distinction to have some ontological implications
and to provide the basis for an event dualism, I limit its purview to the
phenomenological domain. The cognitive processes taken here to be real are
so taken because they are irreducible to more basic phenomenologically
available components, not because they are taken to be the ultimate building
blocks of the universe, for if we were to consider their ontology we would
have to face the difficult question of their relation to the domain of sub-
personal brain states.8
For the Abhidharma, the mind is composed, we said, of a series of mental
states. Each state can be conceptualized as being a moment of awareness
(citta, sems) endowed with various characteristics, the mental factors
(caitesika, sems byung). Awareness, which is also described as consciousness
(vijñāna, rnam shes), is primary, in that it is aware of the object and cognizes
it, whereas mental factors qualify this awareness and determine it as being
pleasant or unpleasant, focused or unfocused, calm or agitated, positive or
negative, etc. Vasubandhu describes consciousness (i.e. awareness) as the
‘apprehension of each object’.9 Similarly, a basic Theravāda Abhidharma
manual defines it as ‘nothing other than the process of cognizing the object’
(Bodhi, 2000:27). Most Buddhist thinkers, both inside and outside of the
Abhidharma tradition, agree on this description of the mental as consisting of
moments of awareness with various characteristics. What they disagree about
is the analysis of the way in which consciousness cognizes its object.
Many Abhidharma thinkers (belonging to various schools such as
Vaibhāṣika, Theravāda, etc.) argue that consciousness simply consists of a
naked encounter with reality in which the mind grasps the object itself. These
thinkers do not posit any appearance as an intentional object or cognitive
mediator over and above the object itself. Others, at times described as
belonging to the Sautrāntika or the Yogācāra traditions, have argued that this
idea of a bare encounter with reality does not explain the nature of
8
For a brilliant, but inconclusive, take on this topic, see Kim (1998).
9
Poussin (1971: I. 30). Translation from the French is mine.
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
cognition.10 For what does it mean for the mind to apprehend an object? Either
apprehension is just a metaphor (that of physical grasping) for a process in
need of further clarification, or it is a hopelessly naive view deprived of
explanatory power. According to these thinkers, consciousness does not grasp
its object directly, but through the disclosure of its appearance. The object
does not appear directly or nakedly to consciousness but through the
phenomenal form (ākāra, rnam pa, literally ‘aspect’) it gives rise to in the
cognitive process, its manifestation within the field of
11
consciousness. Awareness of the object is then the beholding by
consciousness itself of the phenomenal form of the object. The implication of
this view is that consciousness is intrinsically self-aware.
Dignāga articulated this view of consciousness through the doctrine of
self-cognition (svasaṃvedana). Dharmakīrti developed this view, presenting
self-cognition as a kind of apperception, the sense that we have of being able
to register our mental states as being our own.12 This self-awareness is neither
introspective nor reflective, for it does not take inner mental states as its
objects. Rather, it is the self-specifying function of every mental episode that
brings about a non-thematic awareness of mental states as our own so that the
person automatically knows whose experiences he or she is experiencing. This
self-awareness is pre-reflective, providing the basis for introspection, the
paying attention to some of our mental states. Hence, the reflexivity that is at
play here does not require a separate cognition but is the necessary
consequence of the analysis of consciousness as the beholding of a
phenomenal form within the field of consciousness.13
10
These two ways of understanding consciousness as being first and foremost object-directed or reflexive
represent two distinct ways of conceptualizing consciousness in Indian philosophy. The Nyāya school of
brahmanical realism, for example, argues that consciousness first and foremost illuminates another object,
and that self-awareness is necessarily reflective, whereas the idealist Vedānta holds that consciousness is
self-luminous (svayamprakāṣa), in that it is directly aware of itself and only indirectly aware of the object.
See Ram-Prasad (2007), as well as this volume.
11
Chim Jampeyang (1989: 126–127). A similar view is found in Sazang Mati Penchen (n.d), 32–33. This
discussion follows Tibetan doxographical categories. For a modern scholarly examination of these
categories, see Mimaki (1979). For a critique of these categories, see Cabezon (1990: 7–26).
12
For a discussion of this important doctrine, see Dreyfus (1997: chs. 19 and 25). For a discussion of
earlier views on self-cognition, see Yao (2005).
13
There are here obvious parallels with the phenomenological view of consciousness as involving a pre-
reflective self-awareness as articulated by Husserl and Sartre. For an excellent discussion of these views
within a perspective informed by contemporary cognitive sciences and analytic philosophy of mind, see
Zahavi (2005).
GEORGES DREYFUS
14
This is not unlike Husserl's description of the natural attitude in which we assume that the world of
ordinary objects is given immediately to us and exists simply out there for us, at hand. See Welton (1999:
60).
15
Karma Chagme (1998: 108). A critical study of the Nyingma views of the mind, with a view of its
connection to the Yogācāra tradition, seems to be of obvious interest and yet remains to be written. There
are also interesting parallels within the Theravāda tradition. See Collins (1982: 246–47).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
18
This colorful expression is due to Dennett (1991).
19
This point is made forcefully and cogently by Petitot, Varela, Pachoud, and Roy (1999: 11).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
20
I am using Cartesianism as defined by O. Flanagan, that is, as the view that ‘each person is in an
epistemically privileged position with respect to the content of his or her mind…’ (1999: 66). Whether this
actually corresponds to Descartes' own position is a different matter.
21
For thoughtful discussions of Dennett's views on experience, see the special issue ofPhenomenology and
Cognitive Sciences 6 (2007). For a view of the controversy surrounding the issue of whether our sense that
experiences, particularly visual ones, have a rich phenomenological content is a grand illusion or not, see
the special issue of the Journal of Consciousness Studies 9.5–6 (2002).
GEORGES DREYFUS
articulated here, our mistake is not to think that things appear to us, but to
assent to the ways things appear to us and thus take for real our own mental
creations. The view articulated here aims for a middle ground that steers clear
of two extreme positions. By denying the transparency of consciousness, I
seek to avoid the extreme of reification, here the Cartesian assertion of a
transparent subject able to know with certainty ideas, feelings, and emotions.
By asserting that there is a phenomenological asymmetry between first- and
third-person perspectives and by taking seriously the fact of being appeared
to, I seek to escape from the other extreme, the complete elimination of any
notion of subjective experience. Both extremes short-change the cognitive
process and provide overly simplistic models of consciousness that fail to
account for its complexities, as will become clear below.22
This view of consciousness as reflexive is not, however, without
important questions concerning the doctrine of no-self. For if consciousness
entails self-awareness, does it not follow that there is a unified subject, and
hence a self that is not just a convenient label used to designate a bunch of
aggregates? And if this is so, doesn't this contradict the cornerstone of most
Buddhist philosophy, the unambiguous repudiation of the self? In the
following pages I respond to these questions by making an important
distinction between subjectivity and self. I argue that this distinction can
provide a strong basis for a defense of the no-self position, while giving
ordinary subjectivity its due place within the Buddhist philosophy of the
person.
This question of the connection between the notions of consciousness and self
is obviously important for Buddhist philosophy, both in its classical
formulations and in the attempts that some of us are engaged in to address
contemporary discussions from a Buddhist perspective. It also parallels
important discussions within the Western philosophical tradition where in the
last few years the topic of the self has received renewed attention. A number
of thinkers, such as Parfit, Dennett, Strawson, Metzinger, etc., have argued for
22
It should be said, however, that the kind of rich phenomenological discussions of meditative experiences
that one would expect in a tradition like Buddhism, where meditation is supposed to play a central role,
have yet to be produced, or if they exist, analyzed by Western scholars at great length. There are here and
there interesting suggestions, but as far as I know, the range of descriptive accounts available is still very
limited.
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
the present subjects but I am becoming aware of what I, the unified self,
experienced earlier.
This phenomenological defense of the self represents an important
challenge for the kind of Buddhist view of consciousness articulated here, and
zeroes in on what I take to be the central issue in the debate between
proponents of the self and their adversaries, namely, the question of
diachronic unity. For if consciousness is pre-reflectively self-aware, that is, if
(ordinary) experiences are given as having an intrinsic mineness, does it not
follow that there must be an I in relation to whom experiences can be said to
be mine? And if this is so, does this not show that there exists a self that
transcends the present moment? This challenge also represents a welcome
opportunity to elaborate a richer Buddhist view of the person, a view that
accounts, not just for the ontological rejection of a self entity, but also
includes within the purview of the Buddhist philosophy of the person the
experiential dimensions that are fundamental to a number of practices, and
without which sense cannot be made of many aspects of the Buddhist
tradition.
To respond to Zahavi's arguments it may be useful to include in the
conversation Miri Albahari's recent contribution to the Buddhist philosophy of
the person. In her insightful and important work, Albahari (2006) argues, if I
understand her correctly, that an adequate view of the person within the
context of Buddhist philosophy requires a crucial distinction between the self
and the subject. Whereas the former is an illusion to be deconstructed, the
latter is quite real. For Albahari, the subject is characterized by its ability to
witness. She says:
The modus operandi of a subject seems, to put the point broadly, to be its realized
capacity to observe, know, witness and be consciously aware. I shall use the term
‘witnessing’ (or ‘witnessing consciousness’) to cover all these modes of
apprehension, but when I do so I am to be taken as talking only about the
phenomenal cases of such apprehension. By ‘phenomenal’ I mean that there is
something it is like to be undergoing the apprehension…Minimally construed,
witnessing can be described as the broadest mode of phenomenal apprehending,
subsuming all species of conscious experiencing, perceiving, thinking and
introspecting, whether these apprehendings are attentive or inattentive, human or
non-human. (Albahari 2006: 7–8)
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
23
Albahari (2006: 51) states: ‘On the Buddhist position, we are to understand that the witnessing subject
makes the (deeply mistaken) assumption of being a self through its very act of assuming various khandās.’ I
think that this formulation, which seems to imply that the witnessing consciousness mistakes itself for a
self, is problematic. It seems that if the subject is unconditioned and unbroken in its presence, as Alabhari
argues, it cannot be mistaken and hence cannot make wrong assumptions. Rather, it seems that what needs
to be said is that other mental states (desire, ignorance) take the subject to be a self. This is in fact the
Yogācāra view, as I will show below.
GEORGES DREYFUS
24
Tsongkhapa is one of the most famous Buddhist thinkers to have argued that identifying the self to be
refuted is an important step in the process of insight. In fact, his whole approach to the no-self doctrine is
based on the drawing of an explicit distinction between the self that is to be refuted and the self that exists
conventionally. See Tsongkhapa (2002: III.126).
25
For Jamyang Zhaypa, this example illustrates the self rejected by most Buddhist schools (what he calls
the coarse object of refutation), not the most subtle form of self-delusion. Like Tsongkhapa, Jamyang
Zhayba believes that there is a more subtle level of misconception of the self that is the special target of
Prāsaṅgika reasonings. See Hopkins (2003: 651, fn. B); Lopez (2006: 170).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
Body is not a self. If body were a self then it might be that it would not lead to
sickness; then it might be possible to say, ‘Let my body be like this, let my body
not be like this’. But since body is not a self, so it leads to sickness, and it is not
possible to say, ‘Let my body be like this, let my body not be like this’.
(Gethin 1998: 136)
This argument from the lack of control, as well as the others that cannot
be examined here,26 quite clearly points to a sense of the self as defined by its
being in control of the aggregates, being an agent in charge of acting, as well
as being an enduring entity clearly separated from the rest of the world and
worthy of special concern. It is this sense of bounded self closely connected to
our sense of agency that is the target of Buddhist arguments, which seek to
expose its illusory nature.
Thus, it seems that we have here the basis for a Buddhist response to
Zahavi's challenge. This response rests on the distinction between two senses
of who we are: the subject, or, rather subjectivity, that is, the continuum of
momentary mental states with their first-personal self-givenness, which are
central to being a person (more on this shortly), and the self, which is an
illusory reification of subjectivity as being a bounded agent enduring through
time, rather than a complex flow of fleeting self-specified experiences. Hence,
the perceptions, thoughts, and memories that arise within the continuum of my
mind are not impersonal. They are clearly mine in the sense of there being no
possible doubt about who is the subject of these experiences. But this does not
entail that there is an act-transcendent pole of identity, an entity that endures
before and after the moment of experience, in relation to which I can establish
that these experiences are mine, for all that there is a succession of self-aware
subjective states.
26
The Pali Canon presents two other arguments. The first argues against a permanent self, whereas the
second argues against the self from mereological considerations. See Collins (1982: 97–103).
GEORGES DREYFUS
recall their content, but I also remember them as being given to me. It is true
that the I who underwent the experience is not the same as the one
remembering. Hence, when I recall these experiences as being mine, this
memory involves a partial distortion. But inasmuch as I remember these
memories in a first person mode, this remembering is not completely illusory
either, and captures something that separates these memories from those of
everybody else. Hence, Buddhist thinkers are not wrong to assert that the
remembering and the remembered persons are not identical but that they are
also not completely different either, since they share in the ways in which
experiences are given to them.
Moreover, the proponents of no-self are also not without justification in
raising doubts about Zahavi's assumption that the unity of our subjective life
requires an act-transcendent pole of identity enduring through the multiplicity
of experiences. For, what is the nature of this act-transcendent pole of self-
identity? Zahavi answers that the self is constituted by the invariant structure
of first-person self-givenness shared by the various experiences. This structure
supports the process of temporalization that is necessary to experience. That
is, we do not just have one experience after another, but rather we perceive
them to stand in a temporal order. This process of temporalization is based on
the retentive and protentive abilities of consciousness to keep track of past
experiences and to anticipate new ones.28 If I understand him correctly, Zahavi
holds that the self is this structure, which stands unchanged through the
temporalized experiences, much like James' rainbow appearing on a waterfall
(Zahavi 2005: 67). But the very use of this metaphor seems to raise doubts
about the reality of the self rather than prove its existence. For what is real
here? Is it the rainbow, or is it the waterfall, its water, and the sunlight? Is it
not the case that the structure that is conceived to be the unified self is an
abstract structure superimposed on the passing of experiences, much like the
rainbow is a visual illusion created by sunlight and the drops of water?
From the nominalist perspective that is at the heart of most Buddhist
traditions, the unity of this self-givenness is conceptually constructed on the
basis of the passing of the causally related temporalized experiences. What is
real for the Abhidharma tradition whose standpoint is reflected here are the
28
I am here rapidly glossing over the complex topic of time consciousness, one of Husserl's greatest
insights. I take it that the view of consciousness as being retentive of past moments and protentive toward
future ones is far from being incompatible with Buddhist anti-substantialism, and may even offer important
resources to further its philosophical project. For a remarkably clear presentation of this difficult subject,
see Zahavi (2005: 49–72). For a discussion in relation to the neurosciences, see Thompson (2007: ch. 11).
GEORGES DREYFUS
causally effective elements that make up reality (the dharmas): here the
various transient experiences that we undergo in temporal order, and the
memories we have of them. The diachronic unity that we conceive them to
share is just a construct created by memory on the basis of the fact that each
experience is given in a first-person mode and inscribed within a temporal
order. Hence, although the unity that is conceived to encompass various
experiences is not completely divorced from reality, it is not fully real either.
It is a fiction that conceptually stands for the complex causal connections that
exist in reality. It is a convenient way to understand reality, what Buddhists
call a conventional truth, not a causally effective part of the fabric of reality.
Does it follow then that the person is just a convenient fiction imposed on
a group of impersonal elements? And if this is so, are we not back to the
bundle theory of the person that we sought to reject in the first place? The
conclusions that we can draw from this discussion are, I believe, quite clear.
The view of the person argued for here differs from the bundle theory in the
understanding of the basis necessary for the attribution of the concept of
person. The bundle theorist argues that the person is conceptually constructed
to account for the complexity and continuity of impersonal and anonymous
elements, and that the personal character attributed to these components arises
only through a post hoc fabrication. The view I am arguing for agrees that the
person is a conceptual fiction, but holds that there is, at the phenomenological
level, a minimal self-consciousness present in any experience necessary to the
attribution of this concept. When we attribute to ourselves personhood, we do
so, not just through a retrospective imputation on the impersonal elements of
our mind–body complex, but on the basis of the self-givenness of our
experiences, which are not given in a neutral mode and then retrospectively
made into our own, but, rather, arise as belonging to a minimal I (the
constantly changing stream of pre-reflective self-aware experiences, not the
reified self). Hence, the experiences on the basis of which we understand
ourselves as persons are not impersonal but intrinsically self-specified, and
this is why they are immune to any possible doubt as to whom the subject of
the experience is.29
From this perspective, the Buddhist doctrine of no-self is not just an
ontological or a metaphysical take on the question of personal identity, it is
29
For a thoughtful discussion of this process of self-specification, both at the experiential and the pre-
personal levels, see Legrand (2007).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
For Strawson, the inquiry into the nature of the self needs to relate to the
ways in which we actually conceive of ourselves. This requirement that
30
This is obviously ignoring the deeper level at which the subject-object structure disappears.
GEORGES DREYFUS
This discussion of the nature of the person has intriguing parallels in recent
discussions in cognitive science about the self, particularly Damasio's
distinction between the proto-self, the core self, and the autobiographical self.
The starting point of Damasio's explanation of selfhood is the feeling that
whatever action I do, I always have the sense that it is I, rather than somebody
31
It should be clear that I am using here the term ‘empirical’ rather loosely. In particular, it is not meant to
indicate any connection to a scientific approach, but just to signal that the Abhidharma view delineated here
differs in important ways from Husserl's transcendental approach.
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
else, who is doing the action. Thus, there is a quiet presence of a sense of self
in my conscious life, a presence that never falters as long as I am actively
engaged.32 This sense of self corresponds to the core self, which remains
stable across the life of the organism. It is not exclusively human, does not
depend on conventional memory, language, or reasoning. It is not, however,
continuous, but arises transiently, being constantly re-generated anew for
every activity in which we are engaged. It is also remarkably stable, being
constantly recreated in essentially the same fashion. This core self is based on
a proto-self, which is the neural system of coordination of the functions
necessary to keeping the organism alive, being in charge of maintaining
homeostatic regulation within the organism's physical boundaries. As such, it
is not conscious, and becomes so only when it is represented as the core self.
Finally, the core self is extended through its being represented by memory and
language. This extended self is not punctual but covers the whole of our life.
This sense of self is narratively constructed, being born out of our interactions
with others. Hence, as Macintyre (1985) puts it, it is not our exclusive
creation, for ‘we are never more (and sometimes less) than the co-authors of
our own narratives’.33
This presentation of three levels of selfhood seems to be quite germane to
our distinction between self and subjectivity, and our description of the sense
of self as the boss in charge of leading the mind-body complex, a sense that is
to be undermined by Buddhist arguments and practices. The idea of a core self
seems to match quite closely the Buddhist description of the (mistaken) sense
of self as based on a basic level of agency. In the simple actions in which we
engage in daily life (grabbing a chair, holding a pot, going to a place, etc.) we
feel that we are in command. We freely decide to act and initiate the action,
which we try to bring to a successful conclusion. Obviously the result of our
action is not in our control, but the action itself is, or so we think. This basic
sense of agency, the sense that I have of being an active entity in charge of
directing the mind-body complex, corresponds quite well to Damasio's core
self.
But our sense of self is not just a way to create unity and coordinate the
mind–body complex. It is also a way to mobilize emotional resources for the
actions necessary to maintain the integrity of our organism. We do not just
32
Damasio (1999). This discussion of Damasio also relies on the useful summaries presented by Zahavi
(2005: 138–139), and Albahari (2006: 182–188).
33
A. MacIntyre (1985: 213). Quoted by Zahavi (2005: 109).
GEORGES DREYFUS
35
James (1983: 285). For a similar argument about the evolutionary advantages that a sense of self brings
about, see Humphrey (2006).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
nascent sense of self. This core sense of self develops dramatically during the
later stages (particularly, but not only, during the sensorimotor stage) when
babies become capable of differentiating and coordinating the landscapes that
were previously experienced as discrete. This enables them to interact with
people through full sequences of actions rather than just rudimentary actions.
Babies start to initiate conversations through loud vocalization in the context
of visual contact with the caretaker. They also start to play with their
caretaker, initiating actions of reaching, grabbing, etc. Those are the early
signs of the emergence of a full-blown sense of agency that is experienced in a
more continuous fashion, and hence extends beyond the spatial and temporal
boundaries of individual situations. It is also the period in which the first seeds
of reflective self-representation are planted, when babies start to look at their
own bodies and form models of their own capacities. These cognitive and
affective capacities concerning the self further develop through various stages
that are well outside of the purview of this essay.36
The core sense of self that emerges through this developmental process is
central to how we act at the most basic level. It starts at a very early age and
gradually matures in ways that allow the person to become autonomous with
all the cognitive and affective capacities associated with human agency. This
development relies on the symbolic capacities that allow us to conceive of
ourselves as extending through long periods of time, rather than being limited
to the immediacy of the present. But the existence of this extended sense of
self should not obscure the fact that, although our core sense of self is greatly
extended by our acquisition of language, it is not created by language, for it
exists prior to the development of symbolic capacities. Hence, contrary to the
extended self, it exists in any animals that can act in a coordinated fashion,
even in the absence of any symbolic capacity.
This core sense of self seems to correspond to the Tibetan Buddhist
descriptions introduced earlier, the idea of an innate apprehension of the
self (bdag ‘dzin lhan skyes), the sense that we have of being the CEO of the
mind–body complex (see above). Tibetan thinkers distinguish this core sense
of self from the acquired apprehension of the self (bdag ‘dzin kun gtags), the
extended sense of self that develops on the basis of symbolic capacities,
36
My discussion is based on Case (1991). It should be clear that the few points made here have no
pretension at discussing adequately the early developmental process (a complex topic well beyond my
competence) but are just meant to illustrate the ways in which some of the Buddhist discussions of the self
intersect with some of the contemporary concerns. I must thank here R. Roeser for drawing my attention to
this interesting article.
GEORGES DREYFUS
however rudimentary they may be. From a Buddhist perspective, however, the
presence of this core sense of self and its extension through symbolic systems
do not have only evolutionary or developmental advantages, but also bind us
into a condition of suffering (what Buddhists call duḥkha, i.e. suffering, dis-
ease, dissatisfaction, restless struggle, etc.). It leads to our being bound by
afflictive states such as attachment and anger, states that are based on the
illusory sense of the self. For without such a sense of self, we would still
experience emotions, but they would not be invested with the extremely
compelling power they ordinarily have. We would then have a capacity to act
more freely, that is, without being compelled by our usual self-centered
reactive patterns and negative habits, but would still be able to tap into the
source of energy that emotions provide.
The idea that one can be free from the sense of bounded self is quite
radical and raises many questions, particularly concerning the nature of
action.37 For if the deconstruction of the self entails the removal, or at least the
radical transformation, of our sense of agency, how is such a liberated person
(the Arhat) to act? This question concerns not only the intention that may push
such a person to act but also the kind of unity necessary for action. How can a
person without a self feel involved and act? What is the phenomenology of
such a sense of agency as distinguished from our ordinary self-based sense of
agency? These are obviously important questions that cannot be treated in
such a short essay.38 One thing that should be clear, however, is that from a
Buddhist perspective, the deconstruction of the self does not affect the person
as subjectively conscious. This point is not without some importance, for in
many contemporary discussions there is often a tacit identification of
consciousness and self. For example, Damasio often uses the two notions
interchangeably, speaking of core consciousness as synonymous with core
self (Damasio 1999: 7, 10, 27). This conflation may make some sense, given
that for ordinary beings the two often go together. Nevertheless, from a
Buddhist perspective, even in ordinary beings the two are not identical.
Stressing such a difference seems to be one of the contributions that Buddhist
philosophy can make to the contemporary discussion about the self.
To clarify this point, we need to go back to our Abhidharmic discussions
and examine the nature of the subject as it is articulated by the Yogācāra
37
For a series of extremely interesting discussions about agency and its relation to notions of self, see
Roessler and Eilan (2003).
38
For some insightful thoughts on this question, see Siderits (2003: ch. 5).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
For Albahari, the subject is to be sharply distinguished from the self. Contrary
to the latter, the subject cannot be found as such in our ordinary states of
mind, but only in what she calls ‘nibbānic consciousness’. This consciousness
is the state of mind that a fully liberated person, an Arhat, experiences. It is
unconditioned, and hence beyond the limitations of time, space, quality, and
relation. It involves immeasurable peace and happiness, being untainted by
any suffering or human limitation. Its mode of operation is witnessing and
hence it suffuses ordinary states of mind, though it remains unavailable as
such to the ordinary beings mired in ignorance (Albahari 2006: 29).
This view of the subject is somewhat surprising, and seems at times to
have more in common with Vedānta than with Buddhist sources. This is not to
say that there are no Buddhist sources that would support such a position.
Albahari provides a number of quotations from the Pali canon that at least
partly support her position, but I must confess that I remain unconvinced. For
one thing, Albahari presents her view as ‘the Buddhist position’, a pretension
that cannot be sustained in view of the diversity of views within any Buddhist
tradition, as argued above. Her view certainly qualifies as a Buddhist view,
and would be well supported by some of the views found in the Mahāyāna
tradition, where the idea of an enlightened state of mind existing in ordinary
sentient beings (the tathāgatagarbha) is well known,39 though far from being
universally accepted. But more importantly, I find this description of
subjectivity as a transcendent and static presence not terribly helpful, for it
seems to fly in the face of the constantly changing nature of subjectivity. For
although we have a sense of a constant presence in our psychic life, this
constancy seems to be better accounted for as a constantly changing but
always renewed background of awareness, rather than an unchanging
39
For an explanation of this concept, see Ruegg (1969 and 1989).
GEORGES DREYFUS
presence. This does not mean that we should entirely reject Albahari's
analysis, but we need to avoid speaking of ‘the subject’ as some kind of
transcendent entity, and instead find more grounded ways to articulate the
nature of subjectivity by focusing more particularly on the relation between
consciousness and embodiment. To do so, we turn to the Yogācāra sources
and their discussion of the eight types of consciousness.
In most Abhidharma systems, there are six types of consciousness: five
born from the five physical senses (sight, hearing, smell, taste, and touch) and
mental cognition. Each type of sensory cognition is produced in dependence
on a sensory basis, one of the five physical senses, and an object. This
awareness arises momentarily and ceases immediately, to be replaced by
another moment of awareness. The sixth type of consciousness is mental. It is
considered by the Abhidharma as a sense-consciousness, like the five types of
physical sense-consciousness, though there are disagreements about its
basis.40
Some Abhidharma thinkers, such as Asaṅga, argue that these six types of
consciousness do not exhaust all the possible forms of awareness. To this list,
they add two types of awareness: the basic consciousness (ālaya-vijñāna, kun
gzhi rnam shes) and the ego consciousness (kliśṭa-manas, nyon yid, lit.,
afflictive mentation).41 The idea of a basic consciousness, a constant, neutral,
and subliminal baseline consciousness, has evoked various reactions among
Buddhist scholars, both traditional and modern. Conze is perhaps the most
outspoken critic of this idea, which he described as ‘a conceptual monstrosity’
(Conze 1973: 133). The reason for his objection is that the idea of a basic
consciousness seems to reintroduce the continuity of a self, within a tradition
that emphasizes change and discontinuity as being at the core of the person.
Classically, the doctrine of the basic consciousness is meant to answer the
objection that if there is no self and the mind is just a succession of mental
states, how can there be any continuity in our mental life? How are
propensities and habits transmitted if mind merely consists in a succession of
fleeting mental states? And more importantly, how can Buddhists explain,
within such an unstable configuration, the doctrine of karma, which
40
For an extended discussion of the nature of this sixth consciousness, see Guenther (1976: 20–30).
41
Rahula (1980: 17). Although the Theravāda Abhidharma does not recognize a distinct basic
consciousness, its concept of bhavaṇga citta, the life constituent consciousness, is quite similar. For a view
of the complexities of the bhavaṇga, see Waldron (2003: 81–87).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
The Yogācāra response is that the mental processes included within the
scope of the basic consciousness may be outside of ordinary forms of
awareness, but are not in principle removed from phenomenological inquiry.
Hence, they can be thought of as being forms of awareness, rather than totally
unconscious. This view of a ‘non-conscious’ awareness may seem surprising
but has been defended by some contemporary thinkers. Robert Hanna and
Michelle Maiese, for example, have argued that the connection between
information processing and subjectivity is deep and intrinsic (what they call
‘the Deep Consciousness thesis’, Hanna and Maiese 2009: 28–57). For them,
all the cognitive processes that take place below the threshold of ordinary
awareness are nevertheless conscious in some minimal sense. This is so
because consciousness and embodiment have an intrinsic and mutual relation
that goes, so to speak, all the way down. As long as we are alive, the body
itself has a subjective feel to it that is connected to the many cognitive
processes that take place below the threshold of ordinary awareness. Hence,
these processes are not entirely outside of the purview of phenomenological
inquiry. Even deep sleep, often cited as the paradigm of a non-conscious state,
has a certain phenomenological feel to it. It is part of the constantly changing
flow of experiences that we undergo, and is retained as such. When we wake
up from deep sleep, we do not feel that there was nothing before, but, rather,
we feel that we are emerging from a particular mode of experience that is
different, for example, from a comatose state.43
This idea of a basic consciousness functioning at a level deeper than
ordinary awareness dovetails with Damasio's idea of a non-conscious proto-
self at the same time that it challenges its clear demarcation between the
conscious and the non-conscious. In opposition to Damasio's non-conscious
proto-self, Yogācāra sources argue that there is a basic level of awareness not
usually identified as consciousness but not completely non-conscious either.
In this perspective, the separation between the conscious and the non-
conscious becomes a matter of degree. The basic consciousness is the baseline
of consciousness, the passive level out of which more active and manifest
forms of awareness arise in accordance with the implicit preferential patterns
that structure emotionally and cognitively this most basic level of awareness.
Hence, consciousness is a multi-layered process that ranges from the inchoate
43
It should be noted that, for the Yogācārins, consciousness exists in its basic form even in coma, as we
will see shortly.
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
(Hopkins 2003: 439). I take this rather surprising characterization of the basic
consciousness as a self to refer to its being a process of constantly changing
moments of self-aware experience on the basis of which the person self-
identifies. This is how the Yogācārins understand the basic consciousness, that
is, as the basis mistaken by the ego consciousness as being a self. In this way,
the core sense of self is constructed out of the misapprehension of the basic
consciousness as being an entity that is bounded, in control of our actions, and
enduring through time. Hence, it should be clear that although the basic
consciousness has a close connection to the notion of the person, it is not a
self in the sense delineated here, since it is neither enduring (moment-
transcendent), nor is it bounded or endowed with a sense of agency.
The close connection between the person and the basic consciousness
appears quite clearly in the arguments given by Yogācārins to support their
views. The first among eight arguments infers the existence of the basic
consciousness from its close link to the person within the context of the
process of taking birth. This is the central argument among the eight, for it
goes to the heart of the traditional Indian Buddhist conception of the person as
being part of a continuity that extends over multiple past and future
lifetimes.45 This continuity, popularly misdescribed as reincarnation, is not to
be understood as entailing the existence of a continuous entity that undergoes
multiple lives but, rather, as being based on a constantly changing and yet
always renewed process of awareness, much like consciousness in this
lifetime is not an enduring entity but a series of changing and yet connected
mental states given in the first-person mode. The doctrine of the basic
consciousness is, in large part, an attempt to show how the continuity of
multiple lives is possible within an event ontology in which there is no
enduring substance.46
The Yogācāra argument for the basic consciousness is that, without such a
consciousness, the process of dying and taking birth cannot be satisfactorily
explained. This is so because the six consciousnesses operate only
intermittently, being produced only when suitable objects are
45
My discussion of the arguments for the basic consciousness is based on a work written by Tsongkhapa
during his youth. See Sparham (1993: 123–142).
46
For a detailed study of the tension within the Buddhist view of consciousness between the synchronic
analysis of consciousness as a stream of momentary mental states and the diachronic necessity to posit
some kind of continuity to explain the multiplicity of lives, see Waldron (2003).
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
encountered.47 At the times of death and birth, all the coarse states of mind
have ceased, and the person is plunged in a comatose subliminal state. In such
a state the manifest forms of awareness cannot arise. And yet, from the
traditional Buddhist perspective, there is the need for consciousness to be
present, otherwise there would be no dying and no birth. For the Yogācāra, the
stream of consciousness that undergoes the process of dying and being born is
the basic consciousness, which is constantly recreated anew as a subliminal
state of mind. As long as we are alive, there is an element of subjectivity that
is present, a minimal feel of how it is for the person to undergo this process.
For the Yogācārins, being a person entails more than being a mere body where
a series of ongoing vegetative processes take place. Rather, it implies being a
subject of experience, that is, having a sense of ownership of one's body. I can
exist only when I own my body, that is, when I feel my body as undergoing an
experience, however inchoate such experience may be. Such sense of
ownership implies a phenomenal mineness that comes in degrees. I am not
aware of my body in the same way when I am asleep or when I am awake. But
for the Yogācārins, as long as the person is alive, there is always an ongoing
sense of experiencing one's body from the inside, however minimal it may be.
This sense of experiencing the body from the inside, which Albahari aptly
describes as perspectival ownership,48 is what characterizes subjectivity, and
hence also the person. This sense of ownership may be extremely minimal,
but for the Yogācāra it is necessary. It is to be distinguished from the sense of
agency, the sense that one is the author of one's thoughts and actions. Such
sense may dissolve, as in the case of some schizophrenics who feel that they
have no control over their thought processes. It seems reasonable to argue that
what is impaired in these unfortunate people is not their sense of ownership
but their sense of agency. They appear to be still experiencing their thought
processes and their body from the inside, but they have lost any sense of
control over their subjectivity and are left helplessly exposed to all its
phantasmic creations, an experience that must be all the more terrifying in that
it is felt to be one's own.49
47
The ego consciousness is also not suitable as a candidate for the consciousness of death and rebirth in the
absence of the basic consciousness. This is so because the ego consciousness takes the basic consciousness
as its object and hence presupposes this consciousness. Sparham (1993: 126).
48
Albahari (2006: 53) distinguishes perspectival ownership, the impression of inhabiting the body from the
inside, from personal ownership, the sense of identifying oneself as the owner of one's body.
49
For a similar point, see Gallagher (2000: 203–239), quoted in Zahavi (2005: 143–144).
GEORGES DREYFUS
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
Throughout this essay, I have used quite liberally the concept of experience to
discuss the topic of consciousness, in defiance of the suspicion that has
surrounded this concept within the humanities. This rejection of the notion of
experience is all the more unfortunate in that it comes at a time when there is a
willingness in some quarters to include the subjective aspects of mental
processes within the purview of the mind sciences. Within Buddhist studies,
the foremost proponent of this critique of experience has been Robert Sharf,
who has brilliantly and provocatively argued against the use of this notion.
Reacting to the previous exaggerated emphasis on experience as providing a
metaphysical basis for the justification and explanation of Buddhism, Sharf
has taken to task those who use the notion of experience as part of a crypto-
theological project to create a realm of privacy in which religion can escape
the suspicion that has undermined its credibility within the more educated
public. As Sharf rightly argues, it is simply not credible to claim that the
meaning of texts, rituals, and institutions is to elicit in the mind of the
practitioners some inner experience, for this ignores most of what is going on
in a religious tradition in order to focus on and distort a few rarefied
expressions.
But his provocative and welcome critique of experience goes much
further and impugns the very use of this notion, which for Sharf is hopelessly
mired in Cartesian metaphysics. Quoting Dennett with approval, Sharf states
his case in this way:
51
This is the description given by Ju Mipham, trans. Doctor (2004: 355). Readers who know this author
may notice that my approach to the Yogācāra views of the mind bears a certain similarity to those of
Ṡāntarakṡita's views as interpreted by Mipham. It should also be clear, however, that my discussion here is
simplified to the point of caricature. In particular I am glossing over a number of extremely complex issues
concerning the relation between ordinary and enlightened states of mind. For Mipham's views on this topic,
see Hopkins (2006).
GEORGES DREYFUS
I cannot address here all the points made by Sharf, but it should be clear
that there is a fundamental difference between the target of his Dennettian
critique and the phenomenological views that have informed this essay. Sharf
assumes in his critique of experience that its use necessarily implies a view of
consciousness as being private, transparent, and immune to mistake. I believe
that this essay shows that this is simply not the case. It is true that the notion
of experience entails a view of the mind as having a subjective side, a side that
is often difficult to pin down, but this hardly entails that the mind is enclosed
in a private realm, immune to external scrutiny. In fact, phenomenologists
such as Husserl, Heidegger, Scheler, and Merleau-Ponty have taken great
pains to show that the concern with human experience in no way implies the
sealing off of the mind in a realm of transparent absolute privacy. On the
contrary, these thinkers have emphasized the opacity of subjectivity and its
limitations, and argued that a convincing account of experience cannot isolate
what is going on in one's mind, but must consider its inter-subjective
dimensions. These dimensions are multiple and complex, ranging from the
ways in which bodies interact to the role of empathy and the place of
symbolically mediated social interactions.52 But all these thinkers concur in
the same conclusion, that it is only by taking into considerations these
dimensions that we can hope to have an adequate sense of what is entailed by
the concept of experience.
52
(52) For a brief summary of various views on intersubjectivity, see Zahavi (2005), 147–177. For a
thoughtful discussion of the role of empathy, see Thompson (2007), 382–411.
SELF AND SUBJECTIVITY: A MIDDLE WAY APPROACH
Hence, it should be clear that although the use of the term ‘experience’
does signal the importance of subjectivity for a Buddhist account of the
person, it does not entail the kind of Cartesian position caricatured by Sharf. I
believe that it is time to rehabilitate the notion of experience, and to avoid
assuming that its use necessarily leads to a crypto-theological project mired in
hopeless metaphysics.53 I also believe that this rehabilitation is of some
importance for the study of Buddhism and its philosophy, importance that
goes well beyond the present essay. It will allow the inclusion of the traditions
whose views rely more specifically on notions derived from meditative
experiences within the purview of Buddhist philosophy. This is perhaps the
case of the Yogācāra tradition, whose views are often derived from meditative
experiences (hence its name), but remain surrounded by some suspicion
within Buddhist studies, despite the considerable resources that they offer for
the elaboration of Buddhist views of the mind as shown here. This is also true
of the tantric tradition, which is often considered as merely practical without
much philosophical importance. The neglect of its philosophical content is
due to a number of factors that cannot be analyzed here but has had the
unfortunate result of removing tantric material from the purview of those who
are interested in understanding Buddhist views of consciousness and its
relation to the person. Considerable attention has been devoted to the textual
material of the tantric tradition, its historical evolution, and its relation to
vernacular cultures. Those are all important topics worthy of consideration,
but they leave out important areas of inquiry such as the bearing of tantric
ideas on our understanding of the person, consciousness, embodiment, etc. To
include these views within the purview of Buddhist philosophy, we will need
to accept notions that make sense within the context of yogic practices, and
hence be open to include within the purview of our conversations the
experiential aspects of the tradition. Only then can scholars of Buddhist
studies hope to do justice to the full range of Buddhist views of consciousness
and the person and, perhaps, be in a position to make significant contributions
to our understanding of consciousness.
53
(53) For a response to Sharf and a defense of the place of experience within Tibetan Buddhism, see
Gyatso (1999).
GEORGES DREYFUS
Bibliography
1. Introduction
1
A full treatment would require situating these two debates in relation to at least two other broad debates in
Western and Indian philosophy—higher-order theories of consciousness versus same-order theories (see the
papers collected in Genarro 2004, and Kriegel and Winniford 2006), and reflectionist/other-illumination
(paraprakāśa) theories of self-awareness (e.g. Nyāya) versus reflexivist/self-illumination (svaprakāśa)
theories (e.g. Yogācāra). But space demands that I set aside these debates here. See Mackenzie (2007) and
Ram-Prasad (2007: 51–99) for further discussion.
EVAN THOMPSON
makes no sense to ask, ‘What are you jumping?’) (Legrand 2009). Although
the ‘what question’ can arise for the transitive component of an intentional
experience, it cannot arise for the intransitive component of pre-reflective
self-awareness. In sum, according to this view, every transitive consciousness
of an object is pre-reflectively and intransitively self-conscious. Or as Sartre
would say, ‘all positional consciousness of an object is necessarily a
nonpositional consciousness of itself’ (Sartre 1967: 114).2
5
Note that I say ‘reconstruction’ because I make no claim that my presentation coincides with traditional
presentations of the argument by either its advocates or its critics. I do claim, however, that my
reconstruction captures the philosophical premises and reasoning that constitute the heart of the argument.
SELF‐NO‐SELF? MEMORY AND REFLEXIVE AWARENESS
usually the past occurrence (X), not the past experience of it. In other words, it
is usually the objective side of the experience (the noema in
phenomenological parlance), not the subjective side (the noesis). If the
intentional object of the memory is the past experience as such, that is, the
subjective side of the experience, then the memory is a reflective memory.
Usually, however, the re-presenting of the past experience figures only
implicitly and pre-reflectively in one's memory of the past event or situation.
In this way, the memory is unreflective.
Husserl maintains that the phenomenal temporal distance between the
present and the past is possible only insofar as the present act of remembering
evokes both the object and the elapsed consciousness of it. If we suppose that
the act of remembering reproduces only the past object, then we cannot
explain how this object retains its character of being past or belonging to the
past. Yesterday's blue sky is gone, so the only way to reproduce it is in the
form of an image. But if yesterday's blue sky appeared only as a mental image
apprehended in the present, then how could this image retain the character of
pastness? The reason the object recollected in the present retains its character
of pastness is that the remembering consciousness comprises two distinct
intentional acts—the present act of bringing back the past object, and the past
perception of that object. Once again, the present remembering does not really
contain the past perception: it contains it only intentionally. The experience of
remembering thus involves a kind of doubling of consciousness, for in being
the conscious re-presentation of a past object, remembering is also the
conscious re-presentation of a previous consciousness. It is precisely this
doubling that accounts for the past remaining separated from the present, even
though it is remembered in the present (Bernet 2002; Stawarska 2002).
This account of memory clearly grounds the phenomenological claim
made in Premise 1 of the memory argument: The memory of yesterday's blue
sky intentionally implicates yesterday's experience of seeing the blue sky.
Therefore, unless the opponent of the memory argument can provide a
superior, or at least equally satisfactory, alternative analysis of the
phenomenology of memory, Premise 1 can be taken as an established
phenomenological datum about memory in need of explanation. The reflexive
SELF‐NO‐SELF? MEMORY AND REFLEXIVE AWARENESS
In the first part of this paper I have defended the memory argument for
reflexive awareness against Garfield's (2006) criticisms. The question that
now arises—especially given the enlistment of Husserlian phenomenology in
support of the memory argument—is whether reflexive awareness implies a
self. Or to put the question another way, is reflexive awareness compatible
with the doctrinal Buddhist insistence on no-self?
the conceptual distance between the self and the subject (or subjectivity) of
experience.8
Let me be more specific. The price to pay for the Husserlian shoring up of
the memory argument for reflexive awareness is a robust notion of
subjectivity, one that considerably lessens the distance between the notion of a
mere subject of experience and a self. In this phenomenological account of
memory, the subject (or subjectivity) of experience is precisely the selfhood
(ipseity) of time-consciousness—the pre-reflective self-awareness of the
stream of consciousness as a stream, including the automatic givenness of past
experience from within as one's own past experience in retention (primary
memory) and remembering (secondary or reproductive memory).
Of course, this phenomenological notion of selfhood is far from the notion
of the self as an enduring entity distinct from the flow of mental and physical
events. But no phenomenologist would allow that this highly restricted notion
of the self should be our touchstone for assessing the phenomenological and
metaphysical status of the self (see Zahavi 2005; this volume).9
of the reflective act. The ego or ‘I’ is always an intentional object (hence
transcendent) and never a (transcendental) subject: The ego belongs to the
content of the reflected experience, whereas both the original unreflected
experience and the act of reflection (itself an unreflected experience) lack an
ego.
Sartre supports his nonegological position with considerations about
memory (Sartre 1991: 43–48). He states that one can recall a past event in two
ways: (i) one can focus on the object of the past experience (yesterday's blue
sky), or (ii) one can focus on the past experience itself (yesterday's perception
of the blue sky). The first kind of recollection, Sartre maintains, is impersonal
or nonegological—it does not include an experience of the ego as the subject
who perceived the object in the past. The second sort of recollection is
reflective and egological—it takes the past act of consciousness as its object
and gives rise to the illusion that this act was accompanied by an experience
of the ‘I’ or ego.
How do we know that the past experience was not accompanied by an
experience of the ego? Sartre thinks we can revive the past experience in
memory, direct our attention to the revived past object without losing sight of
the past unreflected experience, yet all the while not turn the memory into a
reflective one, and thereby not objectify the past experience. When we, as it
were, relive the past experience in this way we see clearly that no experience
of the ego figured in its content.
Sartre's conclusion is that the ego does not pre-exist recollection but is a
product of recollection. The ego is a kind of retrospective objectification.
Objectifying recollection makes it seem as if the ego were there all along, but
this appearance is illusory, for the ego is not present in consciousness at the
moment when the perception takes place. Consciousness, therefore, at its
basic unreflective level, is nonegological.
Suppose one argued as follows: One has to maintain that there is reflexive
awareness because otherwise, when at a later time, I say, ‘I saw…’ and remember
the remembered object, and when I think, ‘I saw’, there could not be a memory of
the awareness of the object of that thought. (as quoted by Garfield 2006: 203).
The second and third come from Paul Williams, explaining Tsong Khapa's
understanding of the argument (Tsong Khapa follows Candrakīrti in rejecting
the argument):
4. Conclusion
In this paper I have defended the memory argument for reflexive awareness,
and the reflexive awareness thesis as a phenomenological thesis about the
nature of consciousness. At the same time, I have suggested that mounting a
proper defence of the memory argument requires a robust account of memory
and subjectivity that puts pressure on certain versions of the Buddhist no-self
EVAN THOMPSON
References
1 The five so-called skandhas or ‘ingredients’ that combine into individual thoughts or experiences: rūpa,
vedanā, samjñā, samskāra, and vijñāna. For details, see Ganeri (forthcoming).This flexible doctrine is trans-
˙ ˙
formed in various ways by later Buddhist thinkers, beginning with Asaṅga and Vasubandhu in the c. 4th ce.
2 Sad:vijñānadhātavaś caksurādyāśrayā rūpādyālambanāvijñāptayah: (Vasubandhu, Pañcaskandhaka 135).
˙ ˙
3 Thereby adding a new sense for this term, which in its everyday use in Abhidharma is simply
synonymous with conscious attention (citta, vijñāna). Kramer (2008) translates klista-manas as ‘notion of I’,
˙˙
and observes that the incorporation of this new concept represents a modification in the traditional system
of the five skandhas, a modification that is evident in Sthiramati’s commentary on Vasubandhu’s
Pañcaskandhaka. She says: ‘In particular the function of vijñāna-skandha—the original role of which was
SUBJECTIVITY, SELFHOOD AND THE USE OF THE WORD ‘I’ 177
actual perception—was widened through the inclusion of subliminal forms of mind, like the ‘store mind’
(ālaya-vijñāna) and the “notion of I” (klista-manas). The strong emphasis placed by Sthiramati on vijñāna is
˙˙
evident, for instance, when he states that ordinary people—those who have not perceived reality—regard
the vijñāna as the self (ātman), whereas they view the other four skandhas as “mine” (ātmı̄ya)’ (2008: 155).
She adds that ‘[i]nterestingly, Sthiramati also mentions alternative concepts of the self, for example that of
the Sāmkhya tradition. According to his understanding, the Sāmkhyas only regard rūpa-skandha [matter]
˙ ˙
as ātmı̄ya, and all the other four skandhas as ātman. He thus claims that for the Sāmkhyas the self is not only
˙
identical to vijñāna but also consists of the other factors accompanying the mind (caitasika)’ (2008: 155).
Galloway (1980) translates klista-manas as ‘passional consciousness’, and derives interesting information
˙˙
about the notion from Gunaprabhā’s commentary on the Pañcaskandhaka. See below. Dreyfus and
˙
Thomson (2007: 112) translate klista-manas as ‘afflictive mentation’, and comment that ‘[t]his is the inborn
˙˙
sense of self that arises from the apprehension of the store-consciousness as being a self. From a Buddhist
point of view, however, this sense of self is fundamentally mistaken. It is a mental imposition of unity
where there is in fact only the arising of a multiplicity of interrelated physical and mental events’.
4 See Galloway (1978) for a detailed argument that as a Yogācāra technical term, manas should be
translated as ‘consciousness’ rather than neutrally through its cognate in English, ‘mind’.
5 Mahāyānasamgraha 1.7; trans. Anacker in Potter (2003) from the extant Chinese and Tibetan
˙
translations.
6 Galloway (1980: 18) reports from Gunaprabhā’s commentary on Vasubandhu’s Pañcaskandhaka:
˙
[Vasubandhu:] ‘In reality, the consciousness (manas) has the storehouse perception for its phenomenon.’
178 JONARDON GANERI
How are we to make sense of what is going on here? The import of the use
of the terms ‘conceptual fabrication’ (vikalpa) and ‘metaphorical designation’
(upacāra), in connection with the self, is that the end-result of the transforma-
tion of pre-attentive self-consciousness is the sort of first-person psychologi-
cal judgment one would express in the words ‘I am F’. The transformation
has made the self into a conceptual thought-content (vikalpa), but the
expression of that thought-content uses a word, ‘I’ for example, in at most
a ‘metaphorical’ sense, or at any rate some usage that is not one of genuine
literal reference. (As I will point out below, upacāra is not quite metaphor, but
nearer to metonymy.)
Let me represent the picture schematically. The claim is that three distinct
phenomena are involved in self-consciousness:
1. Conscious attention to one’s own states of mind (manovijñāna).
This must have a ‘support’ (āśraya). The support is:
2. ‘Self-consciousness’ (manas)—a pre-attentive mode of being self-aware.
[Gunaprabhā:] This means that it phenomenalizes [sees] the storehouse perception as a self.[Vasubandhu:] ‘It
˙
is that which is associated with the constant delusion of self (ātmamoha), view of self (ātmadrsti), egoism of self
˙˙˙
(ātmamāna), and lust for self (ātmarāga), and so on.’[Gunaprabhā:] It is explained as operating always, and
˙
arises as good (kuśala), bad (akuśala), and indifferent. His saying ‘It is of one class’ means that it has a
passionate (klista) nature. ‘It is continually produced’ means that it is momentary.
˙˙
7 Trimśikākārikā: ātmadharmopacāro hi vividho ya pravartate | vijñānaparināme ’sau || Tvk la-c || tasya
˙ ˙
vyāvrtirarhatve tadāśritya pravartate | tadālambam manonāma vijñānam mananātmakam || Tvk 5 || vijñāna-
˙ ˙ ˙
parināmo ’yam vikalpo yadvikalpyate | tena tannāsti || Tvk 17a-c ||. The translation is from Anacker
˙ ˙
(1984), slightly modified.
SUBJECTIVITY, SELFHOOD AND THE USE OF THE WORD ‘I’ 179
It is to this task that our Buddhists address themselves when they say that
conscious attention to one’s own mental life (mano-vijñāna) must have a
support, which they claim is a pre-attentive mode of being self-aware
(manas). I think that the point of this argument is easy enough to understand
as long as we remember that it is impossible to think about one of one’s own
mental states, a particular feeling of hope for example, and yet not be sure
whose mental state it is. There is no question of having a first person
perspective on one’s mental life, without that mental life presenting itself
to one as one’s own. In a much-quoted passage, Peter Strawson says:
It would make no sense to think or say: This inner experience is occurring, but is it
occurring to me? (This feeling is anger; but is it I who am feeling it?) Again, it
would make no sense to think or say: I distinctively remember that inner experi-
ence occurring, but did it occur to me? (I remember that terrible feeling of loss; but
was it I who felt it?) There is nothing that one can thus encounter or recall in the
field of inner experience such that there can be any question of one’s applying
criteria of subject-identity to determine whether the encountered or recalled
experience belongs to oneself—or to someone else.
(P. F. Strawson 1966: 165)
(Sartre 1957: 45). Dan Zahavi has redescribed it as ‘an immersed non-
objectifying self-aquaintance’ (Zahavi 2005: 21). Sartre argues that an infinite
regress will ensue if such a mode of self-acquaintance is not acknowledged,
and it is interesting to observe that we find the infinite regress argument used
too by one of Vasubandhu’s immediate followers, Diṅnāga, in a defense of
reflexivism (Ganeri 1999; see also the contributions by Evan Thompson and
Mark Siderits to this volume).
8 Indeed, in Zahavi (1999), Zahavi makes it a ‘minimal demand to any proper theory of self-
awareness’ that it ‘be able to explain the peculiar features characterising the subject-use of “I”; that is,
no matter how complex or differentiated the structure of self-awareness is ultimately shown to be, if
the account given is unable to preserve the difference between the first-person and third-person
perspectives, unable to capture its referential uniqueness, it has failed as an explanation of self-
awareness’ (1999: 13).
9 Joel Krueger (this volume) seems to share my reservation about the selfhood of the ‘minimal self’.
To put the point in an Indian vocabulary, the ‘minimal self’ is somewhat akin to the impersonal Advaitic
ātman, present equally in all. Zahavi sometimes, however, appeals to an embodiment criterion, rather
than to first-person givenness per se, as what individuates distinct minimal selves, and that would
certainly adequately distinguish the notion from the Advaita conception.
SUBJECTIVITY, SELFHOOD AND THE USE OF THE WORD ‘I’ 183
10 The history of the Yogācāra concept of the store-consciousness is rather complicated. Originally
conceived merely as a vehicle for the perpetuation of mental forces when the normal six types of
awareness are absent, it was a technical solution to what would otherwise be a difficulty in the Yogācāra
theory of individual persistence. Dreyfus and Thompson (2007: 112) say of it that ‘[t]his continuously
present subliminal consciousness is posited by some of the Yogācāra thinkers to provide a sense of
continuity in the person over time. It is the repository of all the basic habits, tendencies and propensities
(including those that persist from one life to the next) accumulated by the individual’. Reaffirming this
description in his article in this volume, Dreyfus offers the translation ‘basic consciousness’, and discusses
an illuminating range of associations and resonances.The detailed studies by Lambert Schmithausen
(1987) and Hartmut Buescher (2008) have revealed much greater complexity in the use of the notion in
early Yogācāra than scholars had previously acknowledged. Schmithausen comments that ‘it may well be
that ālayavijñāna was, initially, conceived as a kind of ‘gap-bridger’, but hardly in such a way that its
occurrence in ordinary states had been denied’ (1987: }2.13.6). Items in the store do not themselves carry
a feeling of mineness, but ground the feeling of mineness which attaches itself to the stream’s conscious
self-attention. They comprise a sort of database for the mind, information which can be drawn upon in
the activity of bringing the states of the stream into conscious attention.
SUBJECTIVITY, SELFHOOD AND THE USE OF THE WORD ‘I’ 185
Our Buddhists think that the evolution of the concept ego brings with it all
manner of moral defilements, and one form of justification for that claim is
that the concept rests in this way on an error. Sthiramati’s comment on the
first of the 30 Verses bears the point out: he says that the concept of self
presents only an apparent (nirbhāsa) referent, just as the perception of
someone with an eye-disease presents only apparent hairs and circles. It is
‘metaphorically designated’ (upacaryate) because it is said to be there when it
is not, as if one were to use the word ‘cow’ when there is an ox. Sthiramati’s
example, incidentally, shows that the notion of upacāra is much closer to
metonymy than to metaphor, as traditionally understood.11
With P. F. Strawson’s assertion that ‘no use whatever of any criteria of
personal identity is required to justify [a person’s] use of the pronoun “I” to
refer to the subject’ (P. F. Strawson 1966: 165), Vasubandhu would appear
to dissent. For his view seems to be that the use of the pronoun ‘I’ never
refers to a subject of experience. Strawson’s point is that we don’t need any
extra conceptual resource in order to make explicit self-references, and in
particular we don’t need a criterion of identity. The pronoun ‘I’ is not a
term which we can correctly use only if we have successfully identified its
referent, because if it were then there would be the possibility of error
through misidentification relative to it. Strawson infers that ‘I’ refers to its
subject without there being a criterion of identity. Perhaps what Vasu-
bandhu would do would be to agree with this argument but contrapose it.
His point would then be that all genuine reference involves the identification
of a referent, and given that there is no question of such an identification in
the case of the first person, the pronoun ‘I’ cannot be a genuine referring
term. In saying that it is instead a ‘metaphor’ (upacāra), there seems to be a
gesture at the possibility of a different, non-referential, account of its use. To
say ‘I feel hopeful’ is, it might to be thought, to speak non-referentially of the
existence of a hope which presents itself pre-attentively as mine. I will argue
that, although this is not actually Vasubandhu’s strategy, it is nevertheless a
viable one.
In another place, Wittgenstein speaks of ‘two different cases in the use of the
word “I” (or “my”)’, the ‘use as object’ and the ‘use as subject’ (1960: 66–7).
The ‘use as object’ is the use to which it is put when we refer to ourselves as
human beings, embodied entities in a public space, the use it has when, for
example, one person says to another, ‘I am just going to the shops to get the
paper’, or ‘I have twisted my ankle’. Having distinguished between these
two uses, one strategy would be to identify one of these uses as the primary
use, and analyze the other use as being in some way derivative upon the first.
Indeed, it is more in keeping with Indian theory about non-literal language
to speak in this way of primary and derivative uses, rather than in terms of a
distinction between literal and metaphorical use. The derivative use is
metonymic rather than metaphorical: that is, the term is used to refer to
something else, which stands in some relation to the primary referent.
Among the contemporaries of Asaṅga and Vasubandhu are Vaiśesika phi-
˙
losophers, who argue that the primary use of ‘I’ is to refer to a self (ātman),
and that its use to refer to oneself as an embodied being, in statements like
‘I am fat’, is an act of derivative reference, that is, reference to something
which stands in an ‘is the body of’ relation to the primary reference.12
A variant on this approach is advocated by Galen Strawson. Strawson
argues that the two uses are both genuinely referential, and neither is
primary, in short, that ‘I’ is not univocal. One use is to refer to what he
describes as a ‘thin subject’, a thin subject being ‘an inner thing of some sort
that does not and cannot exist at any given time unless it is having experi-
ence at that time’ (2008: 156; cf. 2009: 331–8). The other use is to refer to
‘the human being considered as a whole’:
Are we thin subjects? In one respect, of course, we are thick subjects, human beings
considered as a whole. In this respect we are, in being subjects, things that can yawn
and scratch. In another respect, though, we are in being subjects of experience no
more whole human beings than hands or hearts: we are—literally—inner things, thin
subjects, no more things that can yawn or scratch than eyebrows or thoughts . . . —
But ‘What then am I?’ Am I two different sort of things, a thin subject and a thick
subject? This is ridiculous . . . My answer is that ‘I’ is not univocal. We move naturally
between conceiving of ourselves primarily as a human being and primarily as some
sort of inner subject (we do not of course naturally conceive of ourselves as a thin
subject). Sometimes we mean to refer to the one, sometimes to the other; sometimes
our semantic intention hovers between both, sometimes it embraces both.
(G. Strawson 2008: 157–8)
Elsewhere, G. Strawson (2007) is clear that the relation between the two
uses is one of metonymy, and indeed that the underlying relation is one of
whole to part:
I think that we do at different times successfully use ‘I’ to refer to different things, to
human beings considered as a whole and to selves. In this respect the word ‘I’ is like
the word ‘castle’. Sometimes ‘castle’ is used to refer to the castle proper, sometimes
it is used to refer to the ensemble of the castle and the grounds and associated
buildings located within the perimeter wall, sometimes it can be taken either way.
The same goes for ‘I’, but ‘I’ is perhaps even more flexible, for it can sometimes be
taken to refer to both the self and the whole human being, indifferently. Our
thought (our semantic intention) is often unspecific as between the two.
(G. Strawson 2007: 543)
If it turns out that the best thing to say about selves is that there are no such things,
then the best thing to say about ‘I’ may well be that it is univocal after all, and that
the apparent doubleness of reference of ‘I’ is just the echo in language of a
metaphysical illusion. If this is right, then ‘I’ is not in fact used to refer to selves
as distinct from human beings even when its users intend to be making some such
reference and believe that they are doing so. On this view, the semantic intentions
of ‘I’-users sometimes incorporate a mistake about how things are. I disagree.
The suggestion that there is a non-referential account of the use of ‘I’ was
developed in one direction by Anscombe (Anscombe 1975). Anscombe,
however, does not distinguish two uses, and argues that the first person does
not refer, even in cases like ‘I have a broken arm’. Other writers have tried,
following the lead of P. F. Strawson, to argue that immunity of error does
not commit one to a non-referential account of ‘I’, and indeed to reconcile
immunity with the idea that ‘I’ refers univocally to the embodied human
being (see for example Campbell 2004; McDowell 2009). In an insightful
remark about Anscombe, Campbell suggests that the best way to understand
her position is as claiming that the patterns of use involving the first person
do not require justification in a semantic foundation:
An alternative reaction would, of course, be to say that we ought to abandon the
search for a semantic foundation for our use of the first person. There are only the
patterns of use, and no explanation to be given of them. This was essentially
G. E. M. Anscombe’s position in her famous paper, ‘The First Person’, in which
she claimed that the first person does not refer. This claim is generally rejected,
simply because philosophers have thought that when there is a use of the first
person, there is, after all, always someone around who can be brought forward as
the referent. But this is an extremely superficial response to Anscombe’s point. Her
claim is best understood as making the point that the ascription of reference to the
first person is empty or idle; it does no explanatory work.
(Campbell 2004: 18)
I have argued at length elsewhere that something along these lines is just
the move made by the Mādhyamika philosopher Candrakı̄rti (Ganeri 2007,
ch. 7). His position, I have claimed there, is that we can give a fully
explanatory use-theoretic account of the role of the first person in perfor-
mances of self-appropriation, an account in which it is otiose to assign a
reference. Asaṅga and Vasubandhu, on the other hand, say that in the
movement from a pre-attentive self-awareness to an explicit use of ‘I’, a
transformation of some sort is involved, one which involves conceptual
work (vikalpa), and that the use of ‘I’ is metaphorical or metonymic. Their
view is that the use of ‘I’ is indeed referential, and that the use as object and
the use as subject are to be understood as making reference to, on the one
hand, the human being, and on the other, an inner subject of experience,
this second use being derivative from the first. There is, however, no subject
of experience, and so the subjective use of the first person is an error.
190 JONARDON GANERI
5. Conclusion
I have argued that the new theory of Asaṅga and Vasubandhu consists in an
account of the first-person perspective. Their further claim that the first
person itself, the word ‘I’, is used ‘metaphorically’ in reporting the contents
of the first-person perspective, rests on a prior commitment to the non-
existence of an inner subject of experience. Only this permits them to claim
that its use is one of what I have called ‘disingenuous reference’. I have
distinguished a different strategy, which is to begin with the observation that
such reports are immune to error through misidentification, and to argue
that it follows that in the proper account of the use in first person psycho-
logical judgments of the word ‘I’, the assignment of a referent is explanato-
rily superfluous. Some of the parts of this strategy are to be seen at work in
various thinkers. Anscombe argues that ‘I’ is not a referring expression, but
does not distinguish the two uses of the term. Candrakı̄rti explains the use of
‘I’ in a way that makes the assignment of a referent superfluous, through an
appeal to the thought that its role has to do with self-appropriation (upā-
dāna), but he does not base this claim on the phenomenon of immunity.
The full strategy being defended here emerges only as a ‘fusion’ of compo-
nents drawn from our various sources.13
References
Anacker, S. (1984), Seven Works of Vasubandhu, the Buddhist Psychological Doctor,
Religions of Asia Series (Delhi : Motilal Banarsidass).
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1975), ‘The first person’, in Samuel Guttenplan (ed.), Mind
and Language (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Buescher, H. (2007), Sthiramati’s Trimśikāvijñaptibhāsya: Critical Editions of the San-
˙ ˙
skrit text and its Tibetan Translation, Sitzungsberichte / Österreichische Akademie
13 In his contribution to this volume, Matthew MacKenzie argues that the performativist model
which I find in Candrakı̄rti needs to be supplemented rather with embodied and enactivist elements.
Such a move “fuses” the Buddhist theory with ideas drawn from recent phenomenological literature, a
theme of many of the contributions to this volume. I have tried instead to ‘fuse’ the Buddhist theory with
elements taken from the recent analytical tradition, and the existence of both such possibilities suggests to
me that Indian theory might well serve to create the intellectual space for a rapprochment between those
hitherto separated strands of Western thought.
SUBJECTIVITY, SELFHOOD AND THE USE OF THE WORD ‘I’ 191
1. Introduction
1
Although my main point of reference is the Advaitic understanding of the self, I will primarily focus on
aspects it shares with Sāṃkhya/Yoga and many other Indian schools, i.e. independent of its monistic
commitments. (For an attempt to make sense of the Advaitic idea that ultimately only one self exists,
cf. Fasching 2010.)
2
I must stress that I intend to pursue, as the subtitle says, ‘phenomenological reflections’ on the Advaitic
understanding, and not engage in a staunch exegesis of the details of the various Advaitins' theories. I wish
to discuss philosophically what I take to be a basic intuition about the nature of consciousness that seems to
provide something like a foundation of the Advaitic speculations.
2. Self vs No-Self: The Buddhist Challenge
The central question of Advaita Vedānta is that of the nature of one's own self
as the subject of experience. I evidently have manifold constantly changing
experiences at each moment, and it is no big problem to observe them
introspectively; but who am I who has all these successive experiences? It is
the nature of this experiencer of the experiences that the whole thinking of
Advaita revolves around—not in the sense of some reputed ‘experience-
producer’ (so that today one could be tempted e.g. to assume the brain is the
‘true self’), but in the sense of a subject-‘I’ as belonging to the nature of
experiencing as such, however it may causally come about.
Buddhism famously denies the existence of such an experiencing ‘I’.
In Saṃyutta Nikāya XII.12, for example, the Buddha answers the question
of who it is who feels by saying: ‘Not a fit question…I am not saying
[someone] feels. And I not saying so, if you were to ask thus: “Conditioned
now by what, lord, is feeling?” this were a fit question’ (Rhys
Davids/Woodward 1972–79, vol. II: 10; bracketed addition by the translators).
So, in the Buddhist perspective, the mental life is to be characterized as a flux
of permanently changing substrate-less mental events, each caused by some
other, previous event, rather than in terms of a persisting experiencing self
(an ātman). Experiences take place, but there is no one who experiences them.
It goes without saying that in the various schools of Buddhism
the anātman doctrine has seen numerous interpretations (not all implying an
outright denial of the existence of a self;3 indeed, in Mahāyāna and Tibetan
Buddhism one can find views that are quite compatible with the Advaitic
concept of witness-consciousness4). However, for the sake of contrast I here
construe the no-self thesis primarily in the sense of a strictly reductionist
theory, as espoused by the Abhidharma schools. Even in this reading, the
denial of the existence of an experiencing subject is not meant to deny, at least
on a conventional level, the existence of something like a unitary ‘person’
(pudgala), just as Buddhists would not deny that there are chairs or states. Yet
3
For example, MacKenzie (this volume) argues that the Madhyamaka school holds—in contrast to the
reductionism of the Abhidharma—that the self is not reducible to more basic phenomena, but ‘is an
emergent phenomenon that, while real, is not a substantial separate thing’ (ibid. : p. 258). (Whether or not
this makes a crucial ontological difference naturally depends on the precise definition of ‘emergence’.)
4
Miri Albahari even interprets the Pali Canon as implicitly, but centrally, assuming the existence of a
witness-consciousness—‘a reading’, as she admits, ‘that aligns Buddhism more closely to Advaita Vedānta
than is usually acknowledged’ (Albahari 2006: 2; cf. also Albahari this volume).
a chair is wholly constituted by its parts and the way they are assembled, and
is nothing over and above this, and similarly, the existence of a person does
not involve the existence of a self over and above the manifold ephemeral
phenomena that form, if sufficiently integrated, what we call ‘one person’. A
person is, in the Buddhist view, nothing but a certain ‘psychophysical
complex’, that is, an ‘appropriately organized collection of skandhas’5
(MacKenzie 2008: 252). A person in this sense ‘has’ her experiences only in
the sense that a whole ‘has’ parts, and not in the sense of some self-identical
‘I’-core as the ‘bearer’ of its experiences, that is, as an experiencer.6
The account of persons in classical Indian Buddhist Abhidharma texts is,
in its rejection of a substantial self, quite in accord with the (at least by
implication) dominant modern Western view on this topic (cf. Siderits 2003):
it corresponds to what Derek Parfit calls the ‘reductionist view of personal
identity’, that is, the thesis that a person's enduring existence consists in (and
is therefore reducible to) more fundamental facts, namely certain relations of
connectedness and continuity between physical and mental events
(Parfit 1987: 210–214)—and that in no way is the trans-temporal identity of a
person due to the continued existence of something like a ‘self’ as a
‘separately existing entity’ (ibid.: 210). The many experiences of one person
are not unified by each being connected to one enduring subject, but by being
connected with one another, and the very ‘oneness’ of the subject is, the other
way around,constituted by this (longitudinal) unification of the experiences.
This sounds plausible enough: What should there be in addition to the
physical and mental events and their interrelations? What else should a person
be but a ‘psychophysical complex’ of some sort? Nevertheless the ‘orthodox’
schools of India vehemently challenge the Buddhist anātman (‘no-self’)
thesis, and insist on precisely what the Buddhists reject: that there is more to
the existence of a person than this complex of skandhas, that there exists a
‘self’ in addition to the body and the experiences, which is the ‘who’ of
experiencing.
Is this more than just a dogmatic assumption? Can anything be said in
favor of this view? I think, on closer consideration, one has indeed to admit
5
The term skandhas refers to the five types of phenomena (dharmas) that constitute the person according
to Buddhism.
6
Expressions like ‘Devadatta's desire’, as the Buddhist argues in Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha'sNareśvaraparīkṣā,
do not imply that there is something beyond the desire as its agent, but are ‘just indicating that [the desire]
is connected with a particular stream of cognition, like [such expressions] as “the flow of the Vitastā
[river]”’ (Watson 2006: 190; bracketed additions by Watson).
that it is hard to avoid feeling a certain unease about a purely ‘selfless’
account of one's own existence. Is it really true that there is no experiencing
‘I’? Are there really only experiences, but no one who experiences them?
Undeniably there seems to be a clear difference between an experience being
experienced by me and an experience not being experienced by me. Speaking
only of mental events, connected by some interrelations on the basis of which
a permanent ‘I’ is constructed, deals with experiences more or less as if they
were just objective occurrences, without taking their subjective mode of
being—their ‘first-person ontology’ (Searle 1992: 16)—sufficiently into
account. After all, experiences do not just lie about like stones or chairs,
equally accessible in principle to everyone: Experiences only exist in being
subjectively experienced, and that seems to mean: in being experienced by a
respective subject. And obviously, all of my experiences, no matter how
different they may be, have this one thing in common: that I experience them.
In this sense, experiences are not thinkable as being ‘ownerless’: they are
essentially experiences of an experiencing ‘I’. And the big question of Advaita
Vedānta is precisely what this ‘I’ that experiences its experiences (this ‘first
person’ of their ‘first-person ontology’) is.
Yet, the anātmavādin (denier of a self) might reply that even if one
concedes this subjective character of experience, this does not at all
necessitate positing an additionally existing subject. Rather, the subject
searched for (the ‘experiencer’) is simply the experience itself and not
something ‘behind’ it (cf. e.g. Strawson 2003). The experiences, as the taking
place of subjective appearance (as ‘events of subjectivity’, as Strawson puts it:
2003: 304), constitute the respective ‘inner dimension’ of a subject, and are
therefore not ‘had’ by an additionally existing self.
This is indeed the position advanced by Yogācāra Buddhism and the
school of Dignāga: This line of Buddhist thought expressly acknowledges the
subjectivity (the being-subjectively-experienced) of experience, but rejects
interpreting this fact as the experience's being experienced by a subject—
rather it is supposed to refer to its self-givenness (svasaṃvedana) belonging
to the very nature of experience:7 An experience, in revealing its object, is
simultaneously revealing itself, ‘self-illuminating’ (svaprakāśa) (just as a
lamp does not need to be illumined by a second lamp in order to be visible).
7
Cf. MacKenzie 2007: 47–49; MacKenzie 2008; Dreyfus 1997: 339–340, 400–402; and the contributions
of Dreyfus, Krueger and Thompson in this volume.
‘Svasaṃvedana thus provides a continuous, immediate, and internal first-
person perspective on one's own stream of experience’ (MacKenzie 2008:
249), without presupposing a ‘first person’ in addition to experience itself.
The stream of experience is given to itself and not to a self.8
Of course I do not experience myself qua experiencer as just being the
present experience experiencing itself, but as someone who, as one and the
same, lives through permanently changing experiences, and hence is to be
distinguished from them. Yet for the Buddhist/reductionist account, this
apparent diachronic identity of the subject is wholly constituted by relations
between the experiences (most prominently memory-relations): The
experiential life of a person is, in this view, a series of causally connected
mental events without any underlying enduring self, and an important part of
the relevant causal connections that constitute the unity of one person is that
the contents of one experience leave memory-traces in the succeeding one.
Nothing more (especially not an enduring self) is necessary to account for my
remembering ‘my’ past experiences (and hence my experience of my
continued existence) (cf. Dreyfus this volume p. 133; Siderits this volume pp.
314–15; Watson2006: 153–165). It is true that I do not just remember that,
anonymously, experiences have occurred, but my past experiencing them9—
but this is simply due to the fact that the very meaning of the sameness of the
self, of ‘one person’, is co-constituted by these very memory-connections (cf.
Siderits2003: 25): I remember my experiences as mine not because I
remember my ‘I’ experiencing them, but because they are mine
precisely insofar as I can remember them (i.e. insofar as they stand in the right
form of causal connection to my present experience).
Advaita Vedānta, in contrast, insists that the subjectivity of experience
refers to an experiencing subject. Just like Yogācāra Buddhism, it rejects the
Nyāya thesis that an experience of an object only becomes itself manifest by
becoming the object of another, subsequent experience (comparable
to modern ‘higher-order representation theories’): rather, for an experience, to
be means to be conscious.10 But at the same time they reject the Yogācāra idea
8
This view is comparable to non-egological accounts in phenomenology, for example by Sartre, Gurwitsch
and the Husserl of the Logical Investigations.
9
As Śaṅkara stresses against the Buddhist view: Brahmasūtrabhāṣya II.2.25, Deussen 1920: 353–354.
10
Cf. Chatterjee 1982: 342: ‘The Advaitists say, that when we have an awareness of an object, the object is
indeed manifested, but it is not the only thing revealed; here we have an automatic awareness of the
awareness too. The two awarenesses are simultaneous, but they are not of a similar structure, in fact they
are the two aspects of the same awareness.’
that it is each experience that is conscious of itself, ‘self-illuminating’
(svaprakāśa)—rather I, the subject, am immediately aware of my experiences
as they come and go (cf. Timalsina 2009: 20–21).11 For example, if I am in a
melancholy mood, this mood is not conscious of itself—for Vedānta this does
not make much sense—rather the mood exists in virtue of my experiencing
it (cf. Chatterjee 1982: 343).
And indeed, one might question whether it is really sufficient to account
for the subjectivity of experience—its being-experienced-by-me
(respectively)—in terms of its phenomenal self-givenness (svasaṃvedana), as
‘an awareness of what one's experience is like both in the sense of how the
experience represents its object and how it feels to undergo the experience’
(MacKenzie 2008: 249). The question is for whom there is something it is like
to be in a particular mental state. And it is far from clear that it really makes
much sense to say that it is for the mental state itself to be (in) this state.
This ‘who’ of experiencing is an additional fact with regard to the
experience and its phenomenal character: No facts whatsoever about an
experience or its ‘what-it-feels-like-ness’ can ever imply its being
experienced by me (except, precisely, that it is I who experiences it). It
appears to be perfectly conceivable that this very experience with all its
relations to other experiences of the same stream of consciousness, to this
body and to the rest of the world, could have existed without the ‘I’ which
experiences it being me. This seems to be a contingent (and even, as Thomas
Nagel states, ‘outlandish’ (Nagel 1986: 55)) fact (as I argue in Fasching 2009;
cf. also Madell 1981; Klawonn 1987).
This quite enigmatic additionality of the being-experienced-by-me with
regard to all other properties of an experience, changes, I believe, the
perspective on the question of the diachronic unity of the subject. It seems
that what happened once can happen again: that an experience happens as the
taking place of me. This refers to something radically different from the
question of whether there are experiences that are connected to,
or continuous with, my present one. When I ask whether I will still exist
tomorrow, I do not ask whether there will be experiences that, for example,
have a first-personal access to my present one. I do not refer to any aspects of
11
Śaṅkara argues against the Yogācārins that even if the experience, like a lamp which need not be
illuminated by a second lamp in order to be visible, is revealed by itself, it still has to be revealed to a
subject (otherwise it would be ‘like lamps, and be they thousands, burning in the midst of a mass of rocks’
(Brahmasūtrabhāṣya II.2.28, Deussen 1920: 361–362), i.e. without anyone seeing them). Cf. Ingalls 1954:
301.
the contents of some experiences in the future at all, but simply and
irreducibly to the question of whether these experiences will be
experienced by me.12 And this seems to be logically compatible with a
complete loss of memory or any other kind of psychological change (cf.
Williams 1973).
3. Self as Consciousness
What, then, is this ‘me’? Interestingly, for Advaita Vedānta13 the true ‘I’ (or
rather ‘self’: cf. Ram-Prasad this volume) is in no way some trans-experiential
entity (as is the view of Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika), but is in a certain sense
nothing but experience itself. For Advaita, ‘the self is the object-
experiencing…, i.e., ‘experiencing of something’, and is not only becoming
manifest in it as something which stands, as it were, behind or beyond it'
(Hacker 1978: 275). So in this view experience does not take place for a
subject, but simply as the subject.
Where, then, is the dissent from Buddhism and its rejection of an
experiencing self in addition to experience? The crucial difference is that
‘experience’ is meant here in the sense of consciousness (citor caitanya),
which in Advaita Vedānta is strictly distinguished from the mind (in the sense
of the changing mental states). When, for example, Advaitins speak
of jñāna (‘cognition’ or, in the terminology of this paper, ‘experience’) as
being the essence of the self, they expressly distinguish it from what they call
the vṛtti-jñānas, that is, the manifold transient mental states (Chatterjee 1982:
342; cf. also Hiriyanna 1956: 344 and Timalsina 2009: 17).14
12
Cf. Brahmasūtrabhāṣya II.2.25 where Śaṅkara stresses that my continued existence refers to strict
numerical identity and not to some similarity (Thibaut 1962: 415; this sentence is missing in Deussen's
translation)—and observes that while, with regard to external things, it is admittedly possible to mistake
similarity with identity, this is impossible with regard to oneself as the subject (which today is called the
‘immunity to error through misidentification’).
13
Just as for Sāṃkhya and Yoga, and, by the way, for the Śaiva Siddhāntin Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha: cf. the
interesting study by Alex Watson (2006) . In his Nareśvaraparīkṣāprakāśa, Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha initially
lets the Buddhist win over Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika, which assume the existence of a self as a further entity
beyond cognition. But while Buddhism concludes that there actually is no self, only the cognitions,
Rāmakaṇṭha holds that cognition itself is the self (ibid.: 213–217). He thereby repeats earlier debates
between Buddhism and Sāṃkhya (whose view of the self he largely inherits) (ibid.: 93).
14
Quite similarly, Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha differentiates between two meanings of jñāna, namely on the one
hand the many transient cognitions, and on the other, the one abiding cognition which is our very self (and
which he also terms, when it comes to contrasting the two senses of jñāna, prakāśa = ‘illumination’
or saṃvit = ‘consciousness’): the latter being a permanent witnessing or experiencing of the passing
cognitions (Watson 2006: 354–373).
So, in Advaita Vedānta, consciousness is not equated with the single
ephemeral experiences or with some property of them. Rather, it is understood
as something that abides as that wherein the coming and going experiences
have their manifestation (being-experienced). Consciousness is, so to speak,
thewitnessing (experiencing) of the experiences, and while the experiences
change, experiencing itself abides. After all, the succession of the experiences
consists precisely in one experience after another becoming experientially
present, which presence as such therefore does not change.
Just like Yogācāra Buddhism, Advaita Vedānta espouses the idea of the
‘self-luminosity’ (svaprakāśatva) of experience—yet not as a feature of the
individual mental states—these are things that become manifest in experience
(qua consciousness)—but rather of consciousness itself (cf. Chatterjee 1982:
342–344, 349).15 Consciousness, like light, is the medium of visibility of all
things and does not have to be illuminated by another light (i.e. become
the object of consciousness) in order to be revealed—it is the shining itself as
the principle of revealedness.16 Light is not visible in the way illuminated
objects are, but at the same time, it is not concealed:17 It is present, and it is
precisely its presence that is the medium of the presence of everything—first
and foremost of the experiences whose very existence consists in their being-
present.18
Hence for the Advaitins—although they hold that mental states are
manifest essentially, and not by virtue of being the object of some further,
higher-order mental states—it is not adequate to say that they are
15
In Brahmasūtrabhāṣya II.2.28, Śaṅkara lets the Buddhist ask whether, with his stressing of the self-
revealedness of the cognizer, he is not actually adopting, only in other words, the Buddhist's own view of
the self-givenness of cognition, and answers: ‘No! Because cognition is to be distinguished [from the
cognizing subject] insofar as it is originating, passing away, manifold, etc.’ (Deussen 1920: 362, addition in
brackets by Deussen).
16
Cf. e.g. Śaṅkara's Upadeśasāhasrī I.15.40–41: ‘[It] has the light of knowledge as Its nature; [It] does not
depend upon anything else for [Its] knowledge. Therefore [It] is always known to me. The sun does not
need any other light for its illumination’ (Mayeda 1992: 145–146, bracketed additions by Mayeda).
17
Cf. Upadeśasāhasrī I.15.48 and 50: ‘Ātman Itself…is by nature neither knowable nor not knowable’.
‘Just as there is neither day nor night in the sun, since there is no distinction in the nature of light, so is there
neither knowledge nor ignorance in Ātman, since there is no distinction in the nature of knowledge’
(Mayeda 1992: 146). ‘Though light is an illuminator, it does not illumine itself [since it has in itself no
difference as between illuminator and illuminated]…In like manner Ātman [which has homogeneous
knowledge] never sees Itself’ (ibid.: I.16.12 , Mayeda 1992: 150, bracketed additions by Mayeda). Cf.
Ram-Prasad this volume, section 5, and Ram-Prasad 2007: 78–79.
18
For an insightful discussion of the understanding of consciousness as ‘luminosity’ in Indian philosophy,
cf. Ram-Prasad 2007: 51–99.
immediately self-aware. Rather, they exist in manifesting themselves in the
medium of the luminosity of consciousness, which is immediately self-
revealed. Experiences have their very being in their being-consciously-present
(in being manifest in ‘primary presence’, as Erich Klawonn (1987,1998) calls
it), and while these experiences are permanently fleeting, conscious presence
as such abides (Klawonn 1998: 59; cf. Zahavi 1999: 80; Zahavi this volume:
p. 59).
So, in this view, the manifold transient experiences have their
manifestation in one consciousness. Yet why should we assume this? Why
should we draw a distinction between the individual experiences and
consciousness, thereby obviously hypostasizing consciousness into a
‘something’ in addition to experience? Why should we assume an irreducible
sameness of consciousness, if, quite evidently, constantly new consciousness-
events are transpiring? Conscious experiences admittedly share the feature of
being conscious, but it seems to be an obvious fallacy to speak here of
something like a persisting consciousness-entity. So is there any justifiable
sense in which consciousness is to be distinguished from the individual
experiences and in which a multitude of experiences can be the taking place of
the same consciousness?
I think there is. Already in a purely synchronic perspective, consciousness
comprises manyexperiences, that is, I am actually seeing, hearing, thinking,
etc. manifold things at the same time. The question is how one should account
for this oneness of the experiencing ‘I’ across its manifold simultaneous
experiences (i.e., what binds these experiences together as ‘mine’). Naturally,
the reductionist cannot explain the synchronic unity of experiences by their
being experienced by one subject (by me). For, in her view, there is simply no
subject one could presuppose as explanans; rather, it's the other way around:
just like diachronic unity, the unity of being-experienced-by-one-subject at a
time is to be explained by the being-unified of the experiences by unity
relations that hold between them.
Yet what sort of relations could these be? One must not forget that it is not
just any relation,any unity between experiential contents that is at stake here,
but the unity of being-present-in-one-consciousness. Certain experiential
contents can be more strongly associated than others, and thereby bound
together to form experiential ‘fields’ (experiential unities) in contrast to a
background; they can be coordinated as constituting one coherent space, and
the like—but all such relations that might bind together experiences into ‘total
experiences’ actually presuppose their being-present-together (cf.
Dainton 2006: 240–244). Only what is co-present in this sense can be
associated.
And this presence is nothing other than the being-experienced of the
experiences in which, in the sense of their ‘first-person ontology’, the
experiences have their being. So they do not exist and additionally become
somehow unified. Rather, it is their very being (namely their being-
experienced) wherein they have their unity.
One could counter that it was inadequate to speak of many simultaneous
experiences in the first place. Rather, it is one total experience with an inner
complexity.19 But the crucial question is precisely wherein the unity of this
‘one total experience’ lies. Nothing on the content-side can do this job. So one
obviously has to distinguish between the one experience and the many
experiential contents that manifest themselves within it. And if one wishes to
call the latter ‘experiences’, it is important to understand that the one
experience is not a sum or a composition of these many experiences (qua
experiential contents), but rather it is ‘experience’ in the sense of
the experiencing of the experiences (cf. Zahavi 1999: 80): that wherein they
have their being-experienced, their primary presence—quite in the sense of
the Advaitic notion of jñāna (or sākṣi-jñāna, as it is occasionally called) in
contrast to the vṛtti-jñānas. So when we speak of many simultaneous
experiences, their difference lies in what is present, not in presence itself.
This, I would suggest, is how the talk of ‘witnessing’ in Advaita Vedānta
should be interpreted: We stated that the ‘witness’ (sākṣin) is not understood
as an observing entity standing opposed to what it observes, but as the very
taking place of ‘witnessing’ itself, and ‘witnessing’ is nothing other than the
taking place of the experiential presence of the experiences, in which the
experiences have their very being-experienced and thereby their existence. In
this sense, consciousness can be understood as the existence-dimension of the
experiences (cf. Klawonn 1987; Zahavi 2005: 131–132; Zahavi this volume:
p. 58; Fasching 2009: 142–144). A dimension comprises a multitude of
elements that stand in manifold relations to each other, yet it is not the sum of
these elements or a result of their interrelations, but what makes them,
together with all their relations, possible in the first place. In this sense, ‘the
self’ qua consciousness is to be distinguished from its experiences, but not as
19
Cf. the suggestion of Bayne and Chalmers in Bayne, Chalmers 2003: 56–57.
a ‘separately existing entity’—just as space is not a separately existing entity
in addition to the spatial objects, yet also not identical to them or reducible to
their relations (since any spatial relations presuppose space).20
So the unity of being-experienced-together is irreducible to the many
experiences and their relations, being rather that wherein they have their
being, and this is nothing other than what Advaita Vedānta calls the ātman as
‘the immediately co-experienced unity of experiencing’ (as Paul Hacker
characterizes Advaita's ātman, using a formulation of Scheler's about the
‘person’: Hacker 1978: 274; cf. ibid.: 275).
When Advaita Vedānta equates the self with consciousness, this is not
supposed to mean that the subject is composed of the many contents of
consciousness. I qua consciousness am not an agglomeration of phenomenal
contents, properly organized, but rather their thereness, their presence (and
that is the one presence of the manifold contents).21
Now the question is: What is the nature of the temporal abiding of
experiential presence through the permanent succession of experiences? Does
a new presence with new contents not take place each moment? Is there a
20
Cf., e.g. Upadeśasāhasrī II.2.58 and I.14.50: ‘Ātman, like space, is by nature not composite’; ‘there is no
distinction at any time in the Seeing which is like ether’ (Mayeda 1992: 237 and 140–141).
21
In her very lucid paper on the concept of witness-consciousness, Miri Albahari (2009) rigorously
distinguishes it from the ‘for-me-ness’ or ‘mineness’ (i.e. ‘first-personal givenness’), which Dan Zahavi
posits as the core sense of self. While mineness is a property of experience, witness-consciousness is
‘the modus operandi of the subject that has them’ (Albahari 2009: 68), i.e. of a ‘separate me’ (ibid.: 73 )
(whereas for Zahavi ‘the self…does not exist in separation from the experiences, and is identified by the
very first-personal givenness of the experiences’: Zahavi 2005: 132). I agree that experiences and
consciousness have to be distinguishedin a certain sense (this being the very idea of ‘witness-
consciousness’), yet I disagree with breaking them apart as if they were separate existences, as Albahari
seems to do. Witness-consciousness is, according to Albahari, the ‘mode-neutral awareness’ that is
supposed to account for the experiences' accessibility to reflection, and for the unity of consciousness
across manifold experiences (Albahari2009: 71–72), thus obviously our pre‐reflective awareness of our
own experiences. Yet this is precisely what Zahavi calls ‘mineness’ qua first-personal givenness. To
‘witness’, according to my understanding of the term, does not literally mean that the subject ‘observes’ the
experiences (as Albahari formulates: ibid.: 68 ), as if the witness were a separately existing entity that
watches experience-objects existing outside of it. Rather, it should be understood as the experiencing of the
experiences in which they have their very being. It is simply not the case that the being-present (first-
personal givenness, for-me-ness) of the experiences and the witnessing as themodus operandi of the subject
are two different things. And according to the Advaitic (and my) understanding, the ‘me’ of the for-me-ness
(i.e. the self) is—quite in agreement with Zahavi—not something to be posited in addition to this presence
(for-me-ness), but something that consists in nothing other than the witnessing/experiencing itself.
Furthermore, Albahari holds that this for-me-ness is, as an aspect of experience, something introspectively
detectable, and also in this respect stands in contrast to witness-consciousness which, as ‘built into the very
act of being aware’, can never become an object of awareness (Albahari 2009: 68–69). I have my doubts
about the former claim. ‘Mineness’ is about as much a ‘real predicate’ as is ‘being’ according to Kant. It is
in no way a content towards which one could direct one's attention, no introspectively examinable quality
(no ‘feeling’: Albahari 2009: 70) my experiences have in addition to other qualities (such as the specific
character of my pain) (cf. also Zahavi this volume: p. 59)—it is rather precisely the first-personal thereness-
for-me of my experiences, together with all their qualities.
succession of presences together with the succession of contents (after all, the
presence-of-this now and the presence-of-that then are
obviously different presence-events)? Or is it, rather, not one and the same
consciousness, in which the experiences have their coming and going? In
other words: Can two presence-events at different times be the taking place of
the same presence, that is, is there an irreducible sense in which two such
presence-events can be the taking place of (one and the same) me? Vedānta
insists that what changes when one experience follows the other (presence-of-
this being succeeded by presence-of-that), are actually the contents of
consciousness, not consciousness itself (cf. Sinha 1954: 329). And indeed, as
soon as one distinguishes consciousness from the experiences, the assumption
that the diachronic identity of consciousness has to consist in unity relations
between the experiences appears less compelling. And if one takes a closer
look at the nature of the presence of the momentary experience, it becomes
outright implausible: The ‘primary presence’ (the current being-experienced)
of an experience always and essentially is the presence of the
temporal streaming of experience transpiring right now. And that means:
presence is irreducibly presence of the current taking place of temporal
transition. (Otherwise no time-experience, no experience of change and
persistence, would ever arise.)
So the indubitable evidence of my experiences in their very being-
experienced is always their evidence as passing the thereby ‘abiding
dimension of first-personal experiencing’ (Zahavi 2005: 131). And, therefore,
the absolute evidence of my present existence is the evidence of my present
living through these streaming experiences. The being-experienced of the
streaming experiences as streaming implies the permanence of the actuality of
experiencing itself, which is the being of my ‘I’.22 Therefore
I, qua consciousness, am not the passing experiences, but rather their
manifestation as passing, which does not pass with them: the abiding
experiencing of the changing experiences (Fasching 2009: 144–145).23
22
Cf. Śaṅkara in Upadeśasāhasrī II.2.75 (in answering the question of how the perceiver, perceiving now
this, then that, can be said to be changeless): ‘If indeed you were subject to transformation, you would not
perceive the entire movement of the mind…Therefore, you are transcendentally changeless’ (Mayeda 1992:
240). ‘There must be some constant continuous principle to see their [the cognitions’] origin and
destruction…And this continuous consciousness is sākṣin' (Chatterjee 1982: 349).
23
Along comparable lines, Rāmakaṇṭha argues against the Buddhists that there is no need to assume that
the change of the objects of consciousness implies a change of consciousness itself: For even the Buddhists
cannot deny that many objects are conscious in one single consciousness at one point in time (and it is of no
help for the Buddhist to hold that this is due to a unifying cognition: it is still necessary to appeal to the
So the question of whether the subject is something that can exist, in an
irreducible sense, as one and the same at different times, must, I believe, be
answered in the affirmative: It only exists as now-transcending from the start;
in contrast to the fleeting experiences it abides as the presence of the
streaming experiences as streaming. Experiences only exist in being
experienced, that is, experientially present, and they are essentially present as
streaming, which implies the abidance of this presence itself. This abidance
cannot be constituted by relations between momentary ‘experience-stages’,
because there simply are no experience-stages that would not have their
primary presence as temporally passing. That is: There is no experiential
evidence prior to the evidence of the ‘standing’ of the experiencing ‘I’.
This abidance of the ‘I’ cannot properly be conceived of as the enduring
of an object in time that derives its persistence from unity relations between
its temporal stages. For presence is not so much something that takes
place in the respective present, but rather it is this very present itself—not in
the sense of the objective time-point that is now present and then sinks into
the past, but in the sense of the presentness of the respective present
moment:24 What marks a particular moment as being now is no objective
feature of this special point on the timeline (cf. Nagel 1986: 57), rather it is
the ‘now’ only in relation to the experiential presence of the subject (cf.
Husserl 2006: 58, 390, 406). Consequently, the abiding of the ‘I’ is not so
much the enduring of an inter-temporal object (with its coming and going
temporal ‘object-stages’), but should rather be conceived of in terms of the
‘standing’ of the present itself, in which the very passing of time (the
permanent becoming-present of ever-new time-points and object-stages)
consists:25 that is, of the phenomenon that it is always now. While the
temporal stages of an object one is conscious of continually sink into the past,
consciousness itself doesnot elapse: ‘…even though the object of knowledge
changes’, says Śaṅkara, ‘the knower, being in past, future, and present, does
not change; for his nature is eternal presence’ (i.e. the presentness of the
possibility of a single cognition having many objects). So, Rāmakaṇṭha argues, if the multiplicity of objects
at one time does not affect the singleness of consciousness, why should the multiplicity of
objects over time? It is the contents of consciousness that change, not consciousness itself (Watson 2006:
335–348).
24
Cf. Husserl 1966: 333: ‘…the now-consciousness is not itself now’.
25
Cf. UpadeśasāhasrĪ I.5.3: ‘Just as to a man in the boat the trees [appear to] move in a direction opposite
[to his movement], so does Ātman [appear to] transmigrate…’ (Mayeda 1992: 114; bracketed additions by
Mayeda).
present) (Brahmasūtrabhāṣya II.3.7, Deussen 1920: 389). So the evidence of
the abiding of the subject is not the experience of some object-persistence, but
the condition of the possibility of any experience of persistence.26
28
Consciousness is no object we could find anywhere and is in this sense ‘invisible’. But this does not
mean that it is concealed. The transparency of consciousness does not mean that the cognitive processes
through which we represent objects are not themselves again represented and thereby normally unknown to
us (as Metzinger understands it: Metzinger 2003: 163–177), but rather that there simply is nothing to
represent, because consciousness is nothing but the thereness of whatever it happens to be
consciousness of and nothing beyond that: It is not an object we fail to be conscious of, but no object at all.
inner-worldly subject with particular empirical (psychophysical) properties
(a jīva, ‘person’).
To say that I am not only conscious, for example, of this desk I see, but
also of my seeing it actually means that I am aware of myself sitting here and
looking at the desk and of the fact that the desk appears in this particular way
precisely because it is given to me as someone viewing it from this particular
angle, with these particular sense-organs, and so on. So that which I am aware
of here, is my localization in the world, and of my own body to which I relate
the rest of the appearances. When I experience an unchanging object in
changing modes of givenness, I experience this change as being due to the
changing relations between the experiencing subject and the experienced
object: that is, together with the object, experienced in changing modes of
givenness, a ‘subject’ is experienced for whom the manifestations are
manifestations, a ‘subject’ which is itself something that is objectively located
within the objective world, standing in manifold—physical and psychical—
relations to other things.
And this is essential to object-givenness in general. Objectivity means
appearance-transcendence: We apprehend the subjective appearance as not
being the object itself, but as only being an aspect of this object, that is, this
object as seen from a certain viewpoint, in certain respects. Hence the from-
where of seeing is necessarily co-constituted with the seen object—co-
constituted as a ‘subject’ that is itself part of the objective world
(cf. Husserl 1952: 56, 109–110, 144; Albahari 2006: 8–9, 88). So in a way the
experience of objects is ipso facto also self-experience, in the sense of the self-
localization of the subject within the realm of the objects.
This not only holds for our being conscious of ourselves as a body, but
also with regard to the mental aspects of what we experience as our ‘I’: For
example, the field of givenness is never a mere homogeneous plane, but
features an attentional relief which indicates a mental ‘I’ to which certain
things are attentionally ‘nearer’ than others: I can direct my attention to this or
to that within the field of what is consciously there for me, so that my ‘I’ is
obviously to be distinguished from this field (cf. Husserl 1952: 105–106), an
‘I’ with particular personal interests and the like.
This ‘self-experience’ as a particular psychophysical being means that we
identify a certain special sphere of what is experientially given to us as
‘ourselves’: that is, we constantly distinguish within the realm of phenomenal
contents between what belongs to ‘ourselves’—one's body, one's thoughts,
and so on—and what is located ‘outside of ourselves’ (cf. Albahari 2006: 51,
56–60, 7329). This is what is called adhyāsa (‘superimposition’) in Advaita
(see below).
So object-givenness implies the givenness of the subject (an indicated and
experienced from-where of experiencing) as a necessary moment of the
structure of the field of the objectively given. Now the point is that
the experiencing itself—consciousness—is not a structural moment of what is
given, but isthe very taking place of givenness itself. The whole inner/outer
(self/not-self) distinction constitutes itself within the realm of experiential
contents—and consequently experiencing itself is not located within some
‘inner sphere’. My consciousness is not to be found on one side of this inner-
outer distinction in which what we experience is necessarily structured, but is,
again, the taking place of experience itself. The viewpoint is part of the
structure of the field of presence and therefore not presupposed, but
constituted by it.
Hence consciousness of myself as an ‘inside’ as opposed to an ‘outside’ is
not a way of being aware of consciousness as such, which is not a special
inner realm opposed to the outer objects, but the thereness of these
objects, the appearing of what appears (be it ‘inside’ or ‘outside’). This ‘pre-
interior’ consciousness is what Advaita Vedānta means by ‘self’: ‘[T]he self
which is of the nature of consciousness … [is] the witness of both the seer and
the seen’ (Śaṅkara, Ātmajñopadeśavidhi III.7, quoted in Gupta 1998: 38),
therefore it is ‘the pure “subject” that underlies all subject/object distinctions’
(Deutsch 1969: 49), ‘the “field” of consciousness/being within which the
knower/knowing/known distinctions arise’ (Fort 1984: 278).
6. Conclusion
32
Cf. Upadeśasāhasrī I.6.6: ‘The learned should abandon the “this”-portion in what is called “I”,
understanding that it is not Ātman’ (Mayeda 1992: 116). (Formulations like this seem to contradict the
claim, such as Ram-Prasad (this volume) makes, that in Advaita Vedānta the term ‘I’ does not at all refer to
the ātman.)
Nikāya XXII.59). This insight leads us to the liberation from the illusion of
self. Yet the question is: If there is nothing but these transient phenomena that
constitute our being (in other words: if this simplyis what we are)—who is it
then that is not identical to all this? Who is it who can say of her body, her
thoughts, etc. ‘this am not I’? This ‘who’ is, I wish to suggest, nothing but the
experiencing consciousness in which all the passing phenomena have their
manifestation and which Advaita Vedānta regards as our ‘self’.33
References
33
This article was conceived and written in the framework of the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) research
project Experiential Presence (P21327). I wish to thank Himal Trikha, Chakravarthi Ram-Prasad and the
editors for their comments and suggestions.
—— (2010), ‘Fremde und eigene Gegenwart: Über Anderheit, Selbst und
Zeit’, in Matthias Flatscher and Sophie Loidolt (eds.), Das Fremde im
Selbst‐das Andere im Selben (Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann).
Fort, A. O. (1984), ‘The Concept of Sākṣin in Advaita Vedānta’, Journal of
Indian Philosophy 12: 277–290.
Gupta, B. (1998), The Disinterested Witness: A Fragment of Advaita Vedānta
Phenomenology(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press).
Hacker, P. (1978), Kleine Schriften, ed. Lambert Schmithausen (Wiesbaden:
Franz Steiner).
Hiriyanna, M. (1956), Outlines of Indian Philosophy (London: George Allen
& Unwin).
Husserl, E. (1952), Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und
phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische
Untersuchungen zur Konstitution, ed. Marly Biemel (The Hague: Nijhoff
(Husserliana IV)).
—— (1966), Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins (1893–1917),
ed. Rudolf Boehm (The Hague: Nijhoff (Husserliana X)).
—— (2006), Späte Texte über Zeitkonstitution (1929–1934): Die C-
Manuskripte, ed. Dieter Lohmar (Dordrecht: Springer (Husserliana
Materialien VIII)).
Indich, W. M. (1980), Consciousness in Advaita Vedānta (Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass).
Ingalls, D. H. H. (1954), ‘Śaṃkara's Arguments against the
Buddhist’, Philosophy East and West 3/4: 291–306.
Klawonn, E. (1987), ‘The “I”: On the Ontology of First Personal
Identity’, Danish Yearbook of Philosophy 24: 43–75.
—— (1998), ‘The Ontological Conception of Consciousness’, Danish
Yearbook of Philosophy 33: 55–69.
MacKenzie, M. D. (2007), ‘The Illumination of Consciousness: Approaches
to Self-Awareness in the Indian and Western Traditions’, Philosophy East
and West 57/1: 40–62.
—— (2008), ‘Self-Awareness without a Self: Buddhism and the Reflexivity
of Awareness’, Asian Philosophy 18/3: 245–266.
Madell, G. (1981), The Identity of the Self (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press).
Mayeda, S., ed. and trans. (1992), A Thousand Teachings: The
Upadeśasāhasrī of Śaṅkara (Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press).
Metzinger, T. (2003), Being No One (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Nagel, T. (1986), The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University
Press).
Osborne, A., ed. (1997), The Collected Works of Ramana Maharshi (Boston,
MA: Weiser Books).
Parfit, D. (1987), Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Prabhavananda, S. and Isherwood, C., trans. (1978), Shankara's Crest-Jewel
of Discrimination (Viveka-Chudamani) (Hollywood, CA: Vedanta Press).
Ram-Prasad, C. (2007), Indian Philosophy and the Consequences of
Knowledge: Themes in Ethics, Metaphysics and Soteriology (Aldershot:
Ashgate).
Rhys Davids, C. and Woodward, F. L., ed. and trans. (1972–79), The Book of
the Kindred Sayings (Saṃyutta-Nikāya), 5 vols. (London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul).
Searle, J. R. (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press).
Sharma, A. (1993), The Experiential Dimension of Advaita Vedānta (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass).
Siderits, M. (2003), Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy: Empty
Persons (Aldershot: Ashgate).
Sinha, D. (1954), ‘The Concept of Sākṣin in Advaita Vedānta’, Our
Heritage 2: 325–332.
Strawson, G. (2003), ‘What Is the Relation between an Experience, the
Subject of the Experience, and the Content of the
Experience?’ Philosophical Issues 13: 279–315.
Thibaut, G., ed. (1962), The Vedānta-Sūtras with the Commentary by
Śaṅkarācārya, 2 vols. (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass).
Timalsina, S. (2009), Consciousness in Indian Philosophy: The Advaita
Doctrine of ‘Awareness Only’(London: Routledge).
Watson, A. (2006), The Self's Awareness of Itself: Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha's
Arguments against the Buddhist Doctrine of No-Self (Wien: Sammlung de
Nobili).
Williams, B. (1973), ‘The Self and the Future’, in Problems of the Self:
Philosophical Papers 1956–1972 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press).
Zahavi, D. (1999), Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological
Investigation (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press).
—— (2005), Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person
Perspective (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
8
Situating the Elusive Self
of Advaita Vedānta1
CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD
1 I would like to thank Miri Albahari, Wolfgang Fasching, Jonardon Ganeri and, especially, Mark
Siderits for responses to an earlier draft of this paper.
218 CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD
2 However, I approach the distinction with different concerns. Velleman calls the selfhood that holds
between persons across times a metaphysical relation, and that which holds between first-person-sharing
subjects a psychological one. To me, it seems as if it is the other way around: What makes for a person,
through identification, are psychological ties, together with other factors such as narrative and social
relationality, and what makes for subjective selfhood is the metaphysics by which a unity of conscious-
ness holds across time. I am unsure whether this means we are talking of different things, whether this is
purely terminological, or whether there is some important difference in approach here.
220 CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD
3 In many ways, Nyāya’s robust metaphysical realism about the ātman is closer to Thomas Nagel’s
idea of an objective self, in which, while it is contingently true that the self has a perspective on the
world, it is itself only an element in that very world, so that the perspective it seeks is completely
objective (the famous ‘view from nowhere’) (Nagel 1986). Even more pertinently, its position in some
ways resembles Richard Swinburne’s ‘simple self ’ (1984), although we have to be careful about mapping
the details of Swinburne’s dualism onto the Hindu schools.
S I T U A T I N G T H E E L U S I V E S E L F O F A D V A I T A V E D Ā N T A 221
question of ‘who’, which speaks of existence itself, and the other by ‘what’,
which is that person who is present, or to hand, as the object of any
investigation (Heidegger 1962: 62–77).4 It would seem here that in both
cases, the phenomenological core of being is a self that does not contain the
constitutents of personal identity, the first-personal nature of awareness
being the minimal structure of phenomenal consciousness. In this, all the
brahmanical systems, barring Advaita, have a somewhat similar attitude
toward the ātman, which is picked out by the ‘I’ (aham).
˙
Drawing on phenomenology, Zahavi has eloquently made the distinc-
tion between a phenomenologically constitutive minimal self which is the
perspectival subject, and a more extended sense of self, constituting person-
hood, given by a richer and more robust psycho-social being (Zahavi.
2005). Zahavi argues for a minimal conception of self, based on the phe-
nomenology of mineness: he derives this conception from his interpretation
of the German phenomenologists’ notion of in-each-case-mineness (Jemei-
nigkeit), which he reads as ‘formal individuation’. Again, although this leads
to specific aspects of phenomenological interpretation, it has striking paral-
lels with my reading of the nature of ātman, especially in the non-Advaitic
brahmanical schools, as having only formal identity. For the Advaitins, this
applies to the jı̄va, the ātman being the impersonal reflexivity of persistent
consciousness, as we will see below.
The idea that consciousness is primarily about phenomenality–the what-
it-is-likeness that conscious beings undergo–and the idea that that phenom-
enality contains within it the sense that a self undergoes it, were barely
recognized in Anglophone philosophy twenty years ago. But now, even
those who take their philosophy to derive from close study of cognitive
science, like Thomas Metzinger, agree on these two points. But Metzinger
has an interesting claim regarding the phenomenality of self, or the sense
within consciousness that such consciousness is that of a self. His scepticism
about the self starts with an examination of whether a study of the stable
physical world can reveal anything that might count as a self. His claim,
which has quickly become well known in the field, is that, ‘nobody ever
was or had a self ’ (Metzinger 2003: 1).
4 There is also the further, very tricky issue of Heidegger’s distinction between authentic and
inauthentic modes of being the self, which has some resonance with the brahmanical search for a
similar-sounding difference.
S I T U A T I N G T H E E L U S I V E S E L F O F A D V A I T A V E D Ā N T A 223
has granted enough for his, Zahavi’s, purposes.5 Zahavi is not interested in
defending conventional Western theories of a substantial self that Metzinger
rejects.
Two main points relevant to my interpretation of Advaita emerge: First,
there is a self-model in phenomenal consciousness, which is not a self
(Metzinger 2003: 550); under this model, where presence is transparent to
consciousness, phenomenality is represented as a relationship between a
perspectival subject (the ‘self ’) and its objects. In that sense, Metzinger does
bear similarity to Advaitins and Buddhists, in charging that the self built out
of the interaction of consciousness and world (howsoever their ontological
status is conceived) is illusory, and not a legitimate type of selfhood.6
Secondly, however, in stating that, if phenomenal consciousness does not
depend on an independent self whose consciousness it is, then there is no
self at all, Metzinger is only denying particular conceptions of selfhood,
which require ‘an “individual” in the sense of philosophical metaphysics’
(Metzinger 2003: 563). That would include such theories as those of the
Hindu schools of Nyāya or Mı̄māmsā, for whom consciousness is a quality
˙
of the ātman, and therefore secondary to its existence. For Naiyāyikas or
Mı̄māmsakas, if phenomenal consciousness has perspective (i.e. is structured
˙
as being from some specific perspective, that of the self ) that is only because
there is actually a self which possesses that consciousness. For them, the
transparency of consciousness to its objects is explicable through there being
a subject-self which directly grasps those objects at all only because it
possesses the determinative quality of consciousness (Ram-Prasad 2001:
chs. 1 and 2).
In arguing that consciousness is not intrinsically that of an individual
self, even a minimally phenomenological one, Metzinger does offer a view
that has something in common with Advaita and with (most conventional
interpretations of ) Buddhism. Zahavi might simply decide that that is
sufficient to call that consciousness a minimal self, just because that is how
5 Zahavi in correspondence.
6 Zahavi, by contrast, wants a different account of this sort of self, an extended and richer self which is
equally real, but on an account different from the strict phenomenological one. Incidentally, there is
much in the classical Indian material on such a view, in which the socially embedded person, regardless
of his or her constructivity, is still an ethically relevant and real entity, whose metaphysical status does not
alter the significance of virtue and conduct. This is the so-called ‘human-ends’ (pursārtha)-oriented view
˙
concerned with dharma or the ordered, virtuous life.
226 CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD
7 J. L. Mackie makes a similar distinction (although, of course, for very different purposes), saying that
there are two different rules for the use of ‘I’: one linking it directly to the human being, and the other, to
the subject, whatever it may be (Mackie 1980: 56).
S I T U A T I N G T H E E L U S I V E S E L F O F A D V A I T A V E D Ā N T A 229
between the transcendental ‘I’ and all its ascribed qualities is in fact a meta-
physical one between true and inauthentic selves is a further argument within
that project. But finally, both Bhāttas and Naiyāyikas argue that the ‘I’, when
˙˙
stripped of all ascriptions, is the self free of all personal qualities.)
The Advaitins, on the other hand, say something much more radical: the
‘I’ itself is part of egoity, everything about it is made up. The ‘I’ simply does
not pick out ātman. They are sensitive to the actual function of the ego in
the life of human beings, but given their interpretation of ātman, the
individuation denoted by the ‘I’ is precisely what they must reject.
Śaṅkara notes that there can be no account of the epistemic life which
does not involve the use of the reflexive pronoun in all its psychological
complexity. Without the appropriation (abhimāna—a possessive pride) that
‘I’ and ‘mine’ deliver, there can be no epistemic subject (pramātr.) and the
operation of the epistemic instruments (the pramānas). Vācaspati, in his
˙
commentary on Śaṅkara, explains how this extended and gnoseologically
misleading sense of self functions through two types of paradigmatic asser-
tions: ‘I am this’ and ‘this is mine’. The first, primary claim of identity
between ātman and the bodily apparatus individuates the self, and distin-
guishes it from other loci of such identification. The secondary claim is an
appropriation of relationships, in which the individuated being’s identity
becomes extended socially; ‘this is my son’ is Vācaspati’s example. The self ’s
two-fold (dvividha) appropriation sustains the march of the world (lokayā-
tram), including the means for the attainment of liberation (Vācaspati:154).
˙
The Advaitins go so far as to say that all uses of the reflexive pronoun only
pick out the extended self, the person, and not the authentic, ‘innermost
ātman’ (pratyagātman). The Mı̄māmsaka might say that the misleading inti-
˙
macy that leads to erroneous identification is between the ‘I’ and the
qualities attributed through the ‘this’. But the Advaitin says this intimacy is
in fact between consciousness as such and the ‘I’ (which are co-present like
fire and wood are burner and burnt, in Sureśvara’s picturesque analogy).
The ‘I’ too is truly just a ‘this’ for the seer (Sureśvara: 3.59, 3.61). This
suggests that even the barest awareness of individuation—howsoever
stripped of specific thoughts or feelings or perceptions—does not desig-
nate the ātman; it only designates the individuated self represented in
consciousness (i.e. jı̄va-consciousness).
In common with the other schools, the Advaitins agree that the ‘I’ picks
out an object idiosyncratically: the user of the ‘I’ succeeds in referring to that
230 CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD
very user and it alone. They agree with their brahmanical interlocutors that the
states the ‘I’-usage represents the subject as being are not themselves part of
the authentic self. But they part company with the others when it comes to the
claim that the bare consciousness of self present in the ‘I’ is in fact the ātman.
Here we must be very careful in seeing just what is going on. The Advaitins do
not disagree with the others that the ‘I’-form picks out something uniquely
and idiosyncratically, and that, moreover, there is a plurality of such entities,
each with its own locus of awareness. But whereas the others call this the
ātman, and take it as an element in the ultimate order of metaphysical
existence, the Advaitins call it the form of consciousness-as-jı̄va. In other
words, they argue that ‘I’ only designates a constructed self, namely, a repre-
sentation of consciousness individuated by and through its psychophysical
locus. What the Advaitins call ātman, however, is not the self of individ-
uated consciousness. For them, ātman is simply the consciousness itself that
does the taking (we can say, using the Metzingerian term, ‘the modeling’)
of itself as an individual. Consciousness as such is not designated even by
the bare ‘I’.
If by the use of the word ‘self ’ we mean necessarily an individuated locus
of consciousness idiosyncratically designated by the ‘I’, then the ātman of the
Advaitins is not a self at all, for they reject mineness as a fundamental feature
of reality, arguing that appropriation is a mark of the inauthentic self. At the
same time, there is a more nebulous usage of ‘self ’, which adverts to the
quintessential nature, the very basis of a being’s reality, which is what makes
it what it is. Now, our standard view of the fundamental nature of a being is
construed in terms of distinguishing it from what it is not. In the other
brahmanical systems, the ‘I’ functions admirably to thus distinguish the
ātman which uses it idiosyncratically from all others who use it in their
own way. So we find it reasonable to think that the ātman should be
translated as ‘self ’ for them, howsoever different this usage is from the richer
notions of personhood found in the larger tradition. But if the whole point
of the Advaitic ātman is to deny ultimate distinction between individual loci
of consciousness and treat it simply as the generic name for reflexive
presence, then it does seem strange to use the word ‘self ’ for it.
What then does the ‘I’ pick out (because, after all, it does function to
designate something idiosyncratically)? The ‘I’ in fact refers to the mind, for
the Advaitins. The mind for them is an internal organ or mechanism
(antah.karana), in itself part of the physical functions of the body. The
˙
S I T U A T I N G T H E E L U S I V E S E L F O F A D V A I T A V E D Ā N T A 231
11 On the Advaitic position on the status of the world of objects through a variety of concepts, see
Ram-Prasad 2002.
S I T U A T I N G T H E E L U S I V E S E L F O F A D V A I T A V E D Ā N T A 235
7. Conclusion
Metzinger’s argument that the constructedness of the individual self is
transparent to consciousness appears to apply equally to both Advaita and
most schools of Buddhism. If we set aside the historical development of a
Buddhist commitment to the view that all elements of reality, consciousness
included (or consciousness alone if it constructs the rest of reality), are
momentary, then Metzinger might be made to fit some reinterpretations
of both Advaita and Buddhism. After all, in this volume, Albahari sets aside
the reality of momentariness within a Buddhist denial of self. However,
if more conventional interpretations of Buddhism preserve the doctrine
of momentariness, then a Metzingerian account that does not appear to
require any denial of a unified system of consciousness, nor ask explicitly for
consciousness to be a sequence of momentary states, appears more easily to
allow of a cross-cultural comparison with Advaita than with Buddhism.
This is because the heart of the Advaitic critique of Buddhism is a two-fold
argument: one in support of the unity of consciousness, and the other
against the doctrine of momentariness (Śaṅkara 1917: 2.2.18–25). (Fasching
has more to say about both these Advaitic arguments, albeit from another
text attributed to Śaṅkara.) But in the end, the interesting point about
Metzinger is that he seems to offer possibilities for cross-cultural articula-
tions (both Advaitic and Buddhist) of how our most robust and intuitive
sense of self might be an illusion, intrinsic though it may be to how
consciousness functions in relation to the world.
Zahavi certainly yields riches for the cross-cultural philosophy of self, his
concept of the minimal self being very amenable to being read through
Advaitic lenses. The slight differences in emphasis between my paper and
Fasching’s—especially my argument that the Advaitic position is somewhat
more radical than Zahavi when it comes to the first-person—drives home
the point that there is still much to be done with such genuine cross-cultural
philosophical engagement.
Advaitins, then, within the specific debate about the nature and existence
of the formal subject-self (ātman) of phenomenal consciousness, while
seeming to side against the Buddhists in affirming the existence of ātman,
mean something very different about it than the objective self with the
quality of consciousness espoused by Nyāya or Mı̄māmsā. Their insistence
˙
S I T U A T I N G T H E E L U S I V E S E L F O F A D V A I T A V E D Ā N T A 237
Bibliography
Albahari, M. (2006), Analytical Buddhism (New York: Macmillan).
Baker, L. (1998), ‘The first-person perspective: A test for naturalism’, American
Philosophical Quarterly 35: 327–47.
Citsukha (1956), Tattvapradı̄pikā, ed. Swami Yogindrananda (Varanasi: Udasina
Samskrta Vidyalaya).
Dainton, B. (2005), ‘The Self and the Phenomenal’, in Galen Strawson (ed.), The
Self? (Oxford: Blackwell).
Duerlinger, J. ( 2003), Indian Buddhist Theories of Persons: Vasubandhu’s ‘Refutation of
the Theory of a Self ’ (London: RoutledgeCurzon).
Ganeri, J. (2007), The Concealed Art of the Soul (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Heidegger, M. (1962), Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward
Robinson (Oxford: Blackwell).
Husserl, E. (1989), Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological
Philosophy—Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution, trans.
R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer (Dordrecht: Kluwer).
Kant, I. (1933), The Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London:
Macmillan).
Kumārila Bhatta (1899), Ślokavārttika, ed. Ramasastri Tailanga (Benares: Chow-
˙˙
kambha Sanskrit Series).
Locke, J. (1979), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. Nidditch
(Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Mackie, J. L. (1980), ‘The Transcendental “I”’, in Zak van Straaten (ed.),
Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Madhusūdana Sarasvatı̄ (2005), Advaitasiddhi, ed. N. S. Ananta Krishna Sastri
(Delhi: Parimal Publications).
Metzinger, T. (2003), Being No One (Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press).
238 CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD
Nagel, T. (1986), The View from Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Pārthasārathi Miśra (1915), Śāstradı̄pikā, ed. Dharmadatta Suri (Bombay: Nirnaya-
sagar Press).
Ram-Prasad, C. (2001), Knowledge and Liberation in Classical Indian Thought
(Basingstoke: Palgrave).
——(2002), Advaita Epistemology and Metaphysics: An Outline of Indian Non-Realism
(London: RoutledgeCurzon).
——(2007), Indian Philosophy and the Consequences of Knowledge (Aldershot:
Ashgate).
Śaṅkara (1913), Katha upanis.adbhās.ya, ed. Rajavade Sarma (Poona: Anandashrama
Sanskrit Series).
Śaṅkara (1914), Br.hadāranyaka upanis.adbhās.ya, ed. Kasinatha Sastri Agase (Poona:
˙
Anandashrama Sanskrit Series).
Śaṅkara (1917), Brahmasūtrabhāsya with Vācaspati’s Bhāmatı̄, ed. N. A. Krishna
Shastri and V. L. Sastri Pansikar (Bombay: Nirnayasagar Press).
Sureśvara (1988), Nais.karmyasiddhi, ed. R. Balasubramaniam (Madras: Madras
University Press).
Swinburne, R. (1984), ‘Personal Identity: the Dualist Theory’, in Sydney
Shoemaker and Richard Swinburne, Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell).
Udayana (1995), Ātmattvaviveka, ed. N. S. Dravid (Shimla: Indian Institute of
Advanced Study).
Vācaspati, Bhāmatı̄. See Śaṅkara 1917.
Vātsyāyana (1939), Nyāyabhās.ya to Gautama’s Nyāyasūtra, ed. Ganganatha Jha
(Poona: Poona Book Agency).
Velleman, D. (1996), ‘Self to Self ’, The Philosophical Review 105.4: 39–76.
Zahavi, D. (2005), Subjectivity and Selfhood. Investigating the First-Person Perspective
(Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press).
——(2009), ‘Is the self a social construct?’ Inquiry 52.6: 551–73.
9
Enacting the Self: Buddhist and
Enactivist Approaches to the
Emergence of the Self
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
I. Introduction
The conception of the self as a substance separate from the body and the
rest of the natural world (e.g. the Cartesian ego) is widely rejected today. Yet
many accounts of the self are developed based on assumptions, such as
substantialism and objectivism, that arguably remain basically Cartesian (cf.
Dennett 1991; Metzinger 2003). In contrast, both Buddhism and enactivism
present fruitful alternatives to broadly Cartesian approaches to cognition,
subjectivity, embodiment, and the nature of the self. Indeed, the enactive
approach to cognition and its allied method of neurophenomenology explicitly
and systematically draw from Buddhist thinkers, ideas, and practices in order
to move beyond Cartesianism. In this paper, I take up the problem of the self
through bringing together the insights, while correcting some of the
shortcomings, of Indo-Tibetan Buddhist and enactivist accounts of the self. I
begin with an examination of the Buddhist theory of non-self (anātman), and
the rigorously reductionist interpretation of this doctrine developed by the
Abhidharma school of Buddhism. After discussing some of the fundamental
problems for Buddhist reductionism, I turn to the enactive approach to
philosophy of mind and cognitive science. In particular, I argue that human
beings, as dynamic systems, are characterized by a high degree of self-
organizing autonomy. Therefore, human beings are not reducible to the more
basic mental and physical events that constitute them. In a similar vein,
Francisco Varela argues that the self emerges through the processes of self-
organization, and that the self is thus merely virtual (Varela 1999). I critically
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
examine Varela's enactivist account of the self as virtual, and his use of
Buddhist ideas in support of this view. I argue, in contrast, that while the self
is emergent and constructed, it is not merely virtual. Finally, I sketch a
Buddhist-enactivist account of the self. I argue for a non-reductionist1 view of
the self as an active, embodied, embedded, self-organizing process—what the
Buddhists call ‘I’-making (ahaṃkāra). This emergent process of self-making
is grounded in the fundamentally recursive processes that characterize lived
experience: autopoiesis at the biological level, temporalization and self-
reference at the level of conscious experience, and conceptual and
narrative construction at the level of intersubjectivity. In Buddhist terms, I
will develop an account of the self as dependently originated and empty, but
nevertheless real.
2. Non-Self
The doctrine of non-self (anātman) is perhaps the best known and most
controversial aspect of Buddhist thought. On the Buddhist view, phenomena
arise in dependence on a network of causes and conditions. This is the
fundamental Buddhist notion of dependent co-arising (pratītyasamutpāda).
The Buddhist analysis of any particular entity, event, or process will focus on
the dynamic patterns of interaction within and through which it arises, has its
effects, and passes away. It is against the backdrop of this basic analytical and
ontological commitment that we can understand the Buddhist account of the
self.
First and foremost, the doctrine of non-self is a rejection of the ātman, the
enduring substantial self. On this view, the ‘self’ (ātman) is not just another
term for the empirical person (pudgala), but is rather the substantial, essential
core of the person—the inner self whose existence grounds the identity of the
person. Within the Brahmanical religious and philosophical tradition,
the ātman is generally given a strongly metaphysical interpretation. It is the
unitary, essentially unchanging, eternal, spiritual substance that is said to be
one's true self. However, the ultimate target of the Buddhist theory of non-self
is not the rarified spiritual conception of self commonly defended by various
1
‘Reductionism’ is often used very liberally in the literature on personal identity, such that an account of
personal identity is reductionist so long as it does not rely on either a Cartesian ego or a brute ‘further fact’.
My view does not easily fit into these categories, but rather is an emergentist self-constitution view of the
self.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
Compare Strawson's view to Miri Albahari's account of the ātman (Pāli: atta)
in early Buddhism:
These five skandhas are not to be taken as independent things, but instead are
seen as interdependent aspects of a causally and functionally integrated
psycho-physical (nāma-rūpa) system or process (skandhasantāna: an
‘aggregate-stream’ or ‘bundle-continuum’).
The rūpa-skandha (material form) refers to the corporeal aspect of the
human being, including the organizational structure of the person as an
organism. The vedanā-skandha denotes affective dimensions of the person
and their experience (pleasant, unpleasant, or neutral). The saṃjñā-
skandhadenotes the more fully cognitive faculty of perception, including the
ability to identify and re-identify objects of experience.2 The operation of this
capacity depends on sensory contact (sparśa) with the environment as well as
sensory-motor skills (such as exploratory behavior) and is often taken to
involve the use of concepts. Next, the saṃskāra-skandha (conditioning)
includes the various dispositions, capacities, and formations—such as
sensory-motor skills, memories, habits, emotional dispositions, volitions, and
cognitive schemas—that both enable and constrain the person and her
experiences. This category also includes our basic conative impulses—
attraction, repulsion, and indifference—which are in turn closely tied to our
feelings and the affective modalities (vedanā) of experience. On the Buddhist
view, typically one's whole being in the world is driven by this sedimented
conditioning—and not always for the better. Indeed, the basic conative
impulses often manifest in pathological ways, as the ‘three poisons’ of greed,
hatred, and ignorance. As Dan Lusthaus remarks, ‘such predilections are
always already inscribed in our flesh, in our very way of being in the world,
even while we ignore—or remain ignorant of—the causes and conditions that
2
The term saṃjñā (sam: ‘together’ + jña: ‘knowledge’) is cognate to ‘cognize’ and can have the sense of
‘synthesis’ as well as ‘association’. Lusthaus translates saṃjñā as ‘associational knowledge’
(Lusthaus2002: 47).
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
have given rise to them’ (Lusthaus 2002: 49). Finally, the vijñāna-
skandha denotes discerning or discriminating intentional consciousness.
Therefore, in the standard Buddhist analysis, the person is not an entity
that can exist independently of the five skandhas. Take away the complex,
impermanent, changing skandhas and we are not left with a constant,
substantial self: we are left with nothing. Moreover, the diachronic identity of
a person consists in the appropriate degree of continuity and connectedness of
the skandhas—that is, it is a matter of there being a causally and functionally
integrated series or stream of skandhas.
Having briefly sketched the theory of non-self, let us examine two lines of
argument against the existence of the self (ātman): the criterial argument and
the epistemic argument. First, it is argued that none of
the skandhas individually, nor the whole complex of skandhas could be the
self—that is the independent, substantial, enduring, inner controller and owner
of the skandhas. Upon examination, none of the five skandhas meets these
criteria of selfhood.3 The various mental factors (nāma-skandha) are simply
too transitory, too mutable to constitute the stable, enduring essence of the
person. Moreover, the mental factors are revealed in experience as a stream
(santāna) or flow, rather than as a substance or object. The body is perhaps
more stable, but the fundamental problem is the same: like any complex
phenomenon, the body is in perpetual flux. How should we specify the
persistence-conditions of the body? One might attempt to identify the body's
unique ontological boundary or some essential part of the body that explains
its persistence. But neither of these strategies looks particularly viable. The
physical boundaries of the body are vague, and even if one could find the
essential part of the body, it is doubtful that this essential part could meet the
other criteria of selfhood. Thus it appears that none of
the skandhas individually, neither mental factors nor the body, could be the
substantial enduring self.
What, then, of the skandhas taken together, the nāma-rūpa or psycho-
physical complex? Could this be the self? One problem with this response is
that the psycho-physical complex is the empirical person, whereas the self is
being posited as the essence of the person which grounds and explains the
persistence of the person. The empirical person, like the individual skandhas,
3
The classic version of the criterial argument occurs in Saṃyutta Nikāya 3.66–68. Cf. Holder (2006)for a
translation.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
4
This argument occurs in the ‘Refutation of the Theory of the Self’ 1.2. Cf. Duerlinger (2003) for a
translation.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
3. Buddhist Reductionism
The account of human beings as selfless persons is held by all major Buddhist
schools, but there has been a great deal of disagreement as to the full
ontological implications of the rejection of a substantial self. For the
Abhidharma or Buddhist reductionist schools, the doctrine of anātman is at
the center of a radically reductionist, anti-substantialist empiricism. Everyday
entities such as pots and people are not ontologically basic (dravyasat), but
rather are reducible to aggregations of basic entities. On this view, the
seemingly objective, mind-independent unity of everyday composite objects is
illusory—these entities have only a secondary, conceptual existence
(prajñaptisat). The ontologically basic entities to which everyday things are
reducible are called dharmas. These are simple, fleeting events individuated
by their intrinsic defining characteristic (svalakṣaṇa). Moreover, the
Abhidharma's basic ontology is fairly austere—according to one school, there
are only seventy-five types of dharmas. As the Abhidharma philosopher
Vasubandhu explains the view:
That of which one does not have a cognition when it has been broken is real in a
concealing way (saṃvṛti-sat); an example is a pot. And that of which one does
not have a cognition when other [elemental qualities (dharmas)] have been
excluded from it by the mind is also conventionally real; an example is water.
That which is otherwise is ultimately real (paramārtha-sat). (Ganeri 2007: 170)
7
It might be argued that the concept of a causal sequence is innate, but this response is not available to the
empiricist Ābhidharmikas. Even if it is claimed that the concept of a causal sequence is inherited from a
past life, the concept, at some point, must have been derived from experience. Thus the move to an innate
concept of causal sequence simply pushes back the problem.
8
There is in fact a debate about whether dharmas have only momentary existence, as argued by the
Sautrāntikas, or whether, as argued by the Sarvāstivādins, dharmas exist in the past, present, and future. In
either case, though, dharmas are only causally efficacious in the fleeting present. Thus there remains a
problem of continuity on either view.
9
Śrīdhara intends this argument to establish the necessity of an enduring substantial self. However, as I
argue below in my discussion of time-consciousness, what is required is not a substantial self, but a more
robust account of the experiential continuity.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
The consciousness of ‘I’, which conforms to the distinctions of the nature of the
object, and which does not depend upon memory of marks, the possessor of the
marks, and their relationship, is direct acquaintance just as is the cognition of
physical form. Concerning what you yourself, with perfect confidence, establish
to be direct acquaintance, in virtue of what is it that it is [said to be] direct
acquaintance? You must establish it as being consciousness alone, which does not
depend upon the relationships among marks, etc., and which is self-presenting.
So then you think there is an I-cognition, but that its object is not the self? Well,
then show us its object! (Kapstein 2002: 98)
10
‘First-personal givenness’ is often used interchangeably with ‘subjectivity’. Cf. Zahavi (2005) for a
discussion of this.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
(basic dharmas) and, at the same time, an unwarranted nihilism about other
phenomena (conventional entities).13 Moreover, as with the Abhidharma's
merelogical reductionism, we will argue that there are good reasons to
question this reified account of phenomena. Indeed, if the Buddhist
Mādhyamikas are right, the Abhidharma view is not just unwarranted, but also
incoherent.
If this view is correct, sentient beings, as living autonomous systems, are not
amenable to the reductive analysis of the Abhidharma. Sentient beings are not
sufficiently decomposable (if decomposable at all) to be exhaustively
analyzed and explained in terms of the intrinsic properties and causal powers
of independently specifiable components. In addition, the self-organizing,
self-maintaining, and self-regulating capacities of living beings rely on both
local-to-global and global-to-local influence, and therefore the causal
capacities of the system qua system are both real and not determined by the
intrinsic properties of their most basic components. In the case of autonomous
systems such as human beings, we have mereological dependence without
strict mereological reduction. On the other hand, it is important to note that
the enactive approach is not a return to substantialism. Autonomous systems
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
are not static, ontologically independent substances. Rather the autonomy and
irreducibility of living beings derives from dense networks of relationality and
interdependence. That is, autonomous systems are dependently originated
(pratītyasamutpanna).15
A turn toward the enactive approach and its autonomy perspective can help to
find a middle way between substantialism and reductionism about persons.
Persons can be understood in dynamic-relational terms as autonomous
systems. So far, however, the focus has been on persons as sentient beings—
that is, as embodied and embedded biological systems. I will now turn to the
importance of the deeply entrenched human sense of self. In addition, just as I
have used the enactive approach to expand upon and modify a Buddhist
analysis, I will in turn use later developments in Buddhist thought (in
particular the Madhyamaka school) to correct what I take to be shortcomings
in Francisco Varela's enactivist account of the self.
Varela (1999, 2001), explicitly drawing on Buddhist philosophy, argues
that the human self is both emergent and virtual or empty (śūnya). He
therefore rejects the existence of a substantial, bounded, enduring self. The
self, he argues, emerges from the human organism's endogenous
neurobiological dynamics and from its embeddedness in its natural and social-
linguistic environment. Thus we create and re-create ourselves from moment
to moment through the dynamic interaction of brain, body, language, and
world. He writes:
Why do emergent selves, virtual identities, pop up all over the place creating
worlds, whether at the mind/body level, the cellular level, or the transorganism
level? This phenomenon is something so productive that it doesn't cease creating
entirely new realms: life, mind, and societies. Yet these emergent selves are based
on processes so shifty, so ungrounded, that we have an apparent paradox between
the solidity of what appears to show up and its groundlessness. (Varela 2001)
15
See Siderits (this volume) for a reductionist response. It is worth reiterating that if there are autonomous
systems, they would not be somehow outside the network of cause and effect. That is, even if merelogical
reductionism is false for autonomous systems, those systems are still dependently originated.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
Varela's view, the self is a virtual or fictional construct that emerges from the
distributed activity of a natural, autopoietic system and, in the case of the
human self, the system's use of language and its embeddedness in a linguistic
community.
Now the resonance between Varela's account and Buddhism should be
obvious. And, of course, Varela draws heavily from Buddhist ideas and
practices in the formulation and defense of his account of the virtuality of the
self, especially the concept of emptiness (śūnyatā) as developed in the
Madhyamaka, or Middle Way, school of Buddhism. Indeed, he argues that the
emptiness of the self ‘is the golden thread that unites our self-understanding
with an external and scientific account of mental functioning’, and further that
ethical wisdom rests on first-hand acquaintance with the empty nature of the
self (Varela 1999: 36). However, a proper understanding of emptiness casts
doubt on Varela's account of the self as merely virtual.
As mentioned at the outset of this paper, the account of human beings as
selfless persons (pudgalanairātmya) is held by all major Buddhist schools, but
there has been a great deal of disagreement as to the full ontological
implications of the rejection of a substantial self. In contrast to the
reductionists, some Mādhyamika thinkers allow for an ontologically
deflationary account of the self. The self is said to have an experiential and
practical reality, while they still insist that this minimal self is not to be
reified. As the Dalai Lama explains the latter view, ‘both body and mind are
things that belong to the I, and the I is the owner, but, aside from mind and
body, there is no separate independent entity of I. There is every indication
that the I exists; yet, under investigation, it cannot be found’ (Gyatso 2000:
65). This minimal self—what is called the ‘mere I’ or ‘mere self’
(Tibetan: nga tsam)—is an emergent phenomenon that, while real, is not a
substantial separate thing, and therefore disappears under analysis.16
The difference between the Abhidharma reductionist fictionalism and the
later Buddhist deflationary non-reductionism turns on competing accounts of
the concept of emptiness. To be empty, on the reductionist view, is to lack
ontological independence and an intrinsic nature and, therefore, to be nothing
more than a conceptual construct or convenient fiction. In contrast, the
Madhyamaka school—which Varela, Thompson, and Rosch claim as one
16
The analysis here is the type of ontological analysis that looks for the substantial reality of the object.
Thus, insofar as the self has no substantial reality, it is not found in this type of analysis.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
When we say that a phenomenon is empty, we mean that when we try to specify
its essence, we come up with nothing. When we look for the substance that
underlies the properties, or the bearer of the parts, we find none. When we ask
what it is that gives a thing its identity, we stumble not upon ontological facts but
upon conventions. For a thing to be non-empty would be for it to have an essence
discoverable upon analysis; for it to be a substance independent of its attributes,
or a bearer of parts; for its identity to be self-determined by its essence. A non-
empty entity can be fully characterized nonrelationally. (Garfield 2002: 38)
So, according to the Mādhyamikas, any thing that exists depends on other
things for its existence and nature, and depends (in part) on our practices of
individuation for its identity-conditions.18
17
It is in this sense that the Ābhidharmikas can be accused of nihilism, despite the fact that their
reductionism is not intended to be a form of eliminativism.
18
Hence, the Mādhyamika holds that all phenomena are interdependent and also rejects the idea of the
‘ready-made world’ characteristic of metaphysical realism.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
Returning to the question of the self, one can see why Varela's
identification of virtuality with emptiness is problematic. On the Mādhyamika
account of emptiness, which Varela himself endorses, emptiness simply does
not entail virtuality in either its weaker or stronger senses. To call the self
virtual is to imply that it is either unreal or less real than other things. But
showing that the self emerges from, and depends on, lower-level processes,
that it is not an independent substance, that in trying to specify its identity-
conditions we make reference to our interests and practices, or that it has no
absolute ontological primacy, does not cast doubt on its existence. Rather, it
shows that the self is empty, just like everything else. To think otherwise, on
the Madhyamaka view, is to accept an ontological foundationalism and
essentialism that they argue is incoherent.19
The larger point here is that, insofar as all phenomena are embedded in a
network of relations (causal, mereological, emergence, etc.), there is nothing
especially virtual about the emergent self. In aligning his account of the
emptiness of the self with the fictionalist views of the Abhidharma schools
(Varela, et al. 1991: 58–81) and Dennett, Varela implicitly reifies lower levels
of stable organization, while simultaneously negating the conventional reality
of the emergent self. In contrast, Thompson is in agreement with the
Madhyamaka school when he insists that, ‘Phenomena at all scales are not
[independent] entities or substances but relatively stable processes, and since
processes achieve stability at different levels of complexity, while still
interacting with processes at other levels, all are equally real and none has
absolute ontological primacy’ (Thompson 2007: 441). To claim, as Varela
seems to do, that the emergent global pattern is virtual, but that the
components from which it emerges are actual, is to miss the full implications
of the dynamic-relational ontology at the heart of both Buddhism and the
enactive approach.
Mādhyamikas argue that the self is empty, but that it is neither a mere fiction,
nor reducible to the body–mind continuum.20 The great Tibetan Madhyamaka
19
See Garfield (1995), Siderits (2003), and Westerhoff (2009) for in-depth discussions of Madhyamaka
arguments.
20
The Mādhyamikas do say that the self is illusion-like in that it appears to have substantial existence, but
is in fact empty. But, again, according to this view all phenomena are illusion-like in this sense.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
There are two senses of the term ‘self’: a self conceived in terms of intrinsic
nature that exists by means of intrinsic being, and a self in the sense of the object
of our simple, natural thought ‘I am’. Of these two, the first is the object of
negation by reasoning, while the second is not negated, for it is accepted as
conventionally real. (Jinpa 2002: 71)
That which is self to you, the focal point of your sense of ‘I’ (ahaṃkāra) and
self-interest (ātmasneha), that indeed is not self to me; for it is not the focal point
of my sense of ‘I’ and self-interest. This then is the fixed rule from which it
follows that it is not [a real thing]. There is no essence to such a self as it is not
invariably present. One should give up the superimposition of [such] a self, for it
is something the content of which is unreal (asadartha). (Ganeri 2007: 192)
Having a sense (or concept) of self entails being able to draw a distinction
between self and other, and to experience things as mine and not mine.
However, substantialitist or entitative views of the self, according to
Āryadeva, cannot ground this indexical, perspectival distinction because they
take the self to be a kind of thing.
Yet the reductionist view, despite denying the existence of the self, fares
no better. The project of Buddhist reductionism is to account for persons in
impersonal terms, that is, in terms of causal connections between fleeting
mental and physical events. In shifting to an impersonal and non-perspectival
standpoint, the reductionist loses sight of the first-person perspective, and it is
unclear in this case how to derive the perspectival from the non-perspectival.
23
On this point, the Mādhyamikas agree with the Nyāya critics of Buddhist reductionism.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
24
Thompson defines sentience as ‘the feeling of being alive’ (2007: 161), while neuroscientists
Damasio (1999) and Panksepp (1998) posit a primitive ‘feeling of self’.
25
See Dreyfus (1996), Garfield (2006), MacKenzie (2007), MacKenzie (2008), and Williams (1997)for
further discussion.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
(Tibetan: nga tsam) here refers to the ahaṃkāra, not svasaṃvedana.26 Here
again, Tsongkhapa's view of the self differs from Varela's. Recall that, on
Varela's account, the ‘I’ arises from our ‘recursive linguistic abilities and their
unique capacity for self-description and narration’ (Varela 1999: 61), whereas
the minimal self in Tsongkhapa's account is experientially prior to linguistic
construction.27
Furthermore, on Tsongkhapa's view, the minimal self has a diachronic
dimension.28 He explains:
The self that is the focus of Devadatta's instinctual sense ‘I am’ when not thinking
of a specific temporal stage [of his existence] is the mere I that is within him
since beginningless time. The individual selves [of Devadatta] when he
appropriated the body of a celestial being and so on are only instances of the
former [mere I]. Therefore, when an I-consciousness arises in Devadatta focusing
specifically on a particular form of existence [e.g., as a human], the object of his
I-consciousness is a particular instance of Devadatta's self. (Jinpa 2002: 123)
The idea here is that the mere I is not confined to the present, but rather
provides a basic form of continuity throughout the different phases or
temporal stages of one's life. Indeed, it is precisely the continuity of this basic
first-person perspective that explains why the various forms of existence are
parts of the same life history. Each of the ‘individual selves’ is based upon the
minimal self, each tokening of an I-thought is a particular instance or
expression of this mere I.
Tsongkhapa further argues that the minimal self allows us to explain the
coherence of our personal plans and projects. When we plan for the future or
undertake a particular project, he argues, we do not ‘make distinctions
between the self of this time or that time. Rather, these endeavors are
motivated by the simple wish for the self to be happy and overcome suffering.
And since the self as a generality does pervade all temporal stages [of a
person's existence], these acts also cannot be said to be deluded’ (Jinpa 2002:
26
Unlike, Tsongkhapa, I do accept the notion of svasaṃvedana. On my view, the minimal self (ahaṃkāra)
emerges from the more basic inherent reflexivity of consciousness. Thus my view is closer to the
Madhyamaka of Śāntarākṣita (in India) or the Kagyu and Nyingma traditions (in Tibet).
27
This is not to say that linguistic construction plays no role in Tsongkhapa's account, but only to point out
that the minimal self is pre-linguistic.
28
The Madhyamaka account of the minimal self, therefore, differs from Antonio Damasio's notion of the
core self in that the core self has no long-term temporal extension.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
8. Self-Appropriation
Not only does the self depend for its existence on the constituents, but the
constituents acquire their existence as distinct parts of the stream of mental
and physical events only by being associated with a single self, which,
regarded as a constitutive property, produces the basis for postulating the
individual in which the various properties of the self inhere. It is precisely
this reason which keeps the Mādhyamika from regarding the constituents as
ultimate existents (dravya) and the self as merely imputed (prajñāpti).
(Westerhoff 2009: 163)
That which is appropriated is the fuel, the five [types of] appropriated element.
That which is constructed in the appropriating of them is said to be the
appropriator, the thinker, the performing (niṣpādaka) self. In this is generated
[the activity of] ‘I’-ing, because from the beginning it has in its scope a sense of
self. (Ganeri 2007)
The self, then, is the appropriator (upādātṛ), and the various elements are the
appropriated (upādāna-skandha), and yet Candrakīrti insists ‘the self is not a
real, existent thing’. That is, the self lacks inherent existence (i.e. it is empty),
29
See Nāgārjuna's MMK X: 15 on the relevance of the analogy and X: 10, and X: 12–14 on the issue of
mutual dependence.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
and it is not any kind of thing or object. Rather, the self is ‘I’-ing (ahaṃmāna)
or ongoing self-appropriative activity (Ganeri 2007). Furthermore, ‘I’-ing is
an inherently perspectival activity: it appropriates phenomena as ‘me’ and
‘mine’, incorporates them into its own ongoing dynamic, by indexing (or
tagging) them to the I. Appropriation, then, functions as a self-referential loop.
According to Jonardon Ganeri, the Madhyamaka theory is
a performativist theory of the self (2007). On his interpretation,
In retention the subject does not just have the experience of the retained, it
experiences itself having this experience, i.e., as retaining the retained.
Accordingly, when it grasps an object through a series of retained contents, it
prereflectively grasps itself in its action of retention. This grasp is a grasp of itself
as having experience, i.e., of itself as a subject. Such self-experience implies that
the self-referential character of retention grounds the subject as nonpublic, i.e., as
referring (or being present) only to itself. (Mensch 2001: 107)
Neonates less than an hour old are capable of imitating the facial gestures of
others in a way that rules out reflex or release mechanisms, and that involves a
capacity to learn to match presented gesture. For this to be possible the infant
must be able to do three things: (1) distinguish between self and non-self; (2)
locate and use certain parts of its own body proprioceptively, without vision; and
(3) recognize that the face it sees is of the same kind as its own face (the infant
will not imitate non-human objects). One possible interpretation of this finding is
that…the human infant is already equipped with a minimal self that is embodied,
enactive and ecologically tuned. (Gallagher 2000: 18)
32
Husserl thought that temporality was central to the nature of the transcendental ego. However, it is not at
all clear that Husserl's notion of a transcendental ego would constitute a substantial self. Moreover, like
Sartre and other phenomenologists, I take Husserl's account of time consciousness to be consistent with a
non-egological view of consciousness.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
perception and action. Thus, on this account, the minimal self is embodied and
enactive, as well as temporal.
Finally, to move beyond the minimal self to a more robust form of
personhood requires long-term memory, concepts, language, and social
embeddedness. Indeed, on the Buddhist-enactivist account I have sketched
here, the robust self or person is a complex conceptual, linguistic, and social
construction (abhisaṃskāra). In particular, the robust self involves narrative
construction. As Zahavi remarks, ‘human activities are enacted narratives; our
actions gain intelligibility by having a place in a narrative sequence’
(Zahavi 2005: 107). This narrative conception of persons fits well with
traditional Buddhist accounts that emphasize the conventional nature of
personhood. Indeed, the narrative construction of the self can be seen as a
further extension of the basic dynamic of self-appropriation discussed above.
On the downside, however, from a Buddhist point of view, this narrative
is the tale of a being trapped in saṃsāra. And a central factor that perpetuates
this vicious cycle is the conceit ‘I am’ (asmimāna). This conceit is the hub
around which the wheel of saṃsāra turns. It is grounded in self-grasping
(ātmagraha) and the recursive, open-ended proliferation of concepts
(prapañca) made possible by language. We have already seen how the
emergence of an embodied self through organizational closure brings with it
an intimate, but precarious relation to the environment. At this basic level,
closure creates identity, but also need and danger. At the level of the narrative
self, the conceptual and linguistic resources that make possible the fully
articulated narrative self also create a form of conceptual-linguistic closure
(through self-reference) which, in conjunction with deeply ingrained afflictive
tendencies (kleśa), amplifies and perpetuates the suffering and dysfunction
that characterizessaṃsāra. Simply put, we become self-centered: grasping
after what is self-serving, suppressing and denying what goes against the self,
and being ignorant of, or indifferent to, what does not serve the self.
Moreover, because the conceit ‘I am’ emerges along with the narrative self
itself—that is, the conceit is the default mode of the narrative self—its status
as a construction is occluded. The emergent, dependently originated, empty
self—the ‘whirlpool of self-appropriating action’—mistakes itself for a
bounded, enduring, substantial entity.33
33
It is worth noting that my view of consciousness is remarkably similar to George Dreyfus' in this
volume. We both agree (as does Krueger) that consciousness is inherently reflexive, but is not, at its most
basic level, egological. Rather, the sense of self arises from a more basic flow of reflexive consciousness.
MATTHEW MACKENZIE
9. Conclusion
This sense of self or minimal self is illusion-like in the sense that sentient beings with a sense of self take
themselves to be enduring, bounded, substantial selves when they are not. Dreyfus, Krueger, and I agree
that there are no substantial selves. However, Dreyfus seems to reserve the term ‘self’ for the substantial
self. On the other hand, Krueger and I allow for a dependently originated, empty self. The mistake involved
in the sense of self, then, is twofold: first, one mistakes the empty self for a substantial self; second, one
mistakes the sense of self for the most basic level of subjectivity when it in fact emerges from the egoless
reflexivity of consciousness.
ENACTING THE SELF: BUDDHIST AND ENACTIVIST APPROACHES TO THE EMERGENCE OF THE SELF
References
Bibliography references:
I. Experience
I want to consider the claim that the subject cannot in the present moment of
awareness take itself as it is in the present moment of awareness as the object
of its awareness. In the first two sections I'll set out some assumptions.
First, I'll assume that materialism is true. By ‘materialism’, though, I
mean real or realistic materialism, that is, materialism that is wholly realist
about the experiential-qualitative character or what-it's-likeness of our
conscious mental goings on—I'll call this ‘experience’—and accordingly
takes it to be wholly physical. When real materialists say that experience—
colour-experience, pain-experience—is wholly physical, they're not saying
that it's somehow less than we know it to be in having it; that wouldn't be real
materialism, realistic materialism, because it would involve the denial of
something that obviously exists. Rather, they're saying that the physical must
be something more than it's ordinarily supposed to be—given that it's
ordinarily supposed to be something entirely non-experiential—precisely
because experience (what-it's-likeness considered specifically as such) is itself
wholly physical.
Experience is necessarily experience-for—experience for someone or
something. I intend this only in the sense in which it's necessarily true, and
without commitment to any particular account of the metaphysical nature of
the someone-or-something. To claim that experience is necessarily
experience-for, necessarily experience-for-someone-or-something, is to claim
that it's necessarily experience on the part of a subject of experience. Again I
intend this only in the sense in which it's a necessary truth, and certainly
without any commitment to the idea that subjects of experience are persisting
things. Some say one can't infer the existence of a subject of experience from
the existence of experience, only the existence of subjectivity, but I
understand the notion of the subject in a maximally ontologically non-
committal way—in such a way that the presence of subjectivity is already
*
§§IV–VII of this paper develop ideas in Strawson 1999: 498–502; see also Strawson 2009: 176–81. When
I cite a work I give the date of first publication, or occasionally the date of composition, while the page
reference is to the edition listed in the bibliography.
GALEN STRAWSON
sufficient for the presence of a subject, so that ‘there is subjectivity, but there
isn't a subject’ can't possibly be true.1
Consider pain, a regrettably familiar case of experience. It is, essentially,
a feeling, and a feeling is just that, a feeling, that is, a feel-ing, a being-felt;
and a feel-ing or being-felt can't possibly exist without there being a feel-er.
Again I'm only interested in the sense in which this is a necessary truth. The
noun ‘feeler’ doesn't import any metaphysical commitment additional to the
noun ‘feeling’. It simply draws one's attention to the full import of ‘feeling’.
The sense in which it's necessarily true that there's a feeling and hence a feeler
of pain if there is pain, is the sense in which it's necessarily true that there's a
subject of experience if there is experience and, hence, subjectivity. These
truths are available prior to any particular metaphysics of object or property or
substance or accident or process or event or state. (Descartes is very clear
about this in his Second Meditation.)
Some like to think that there can be subjectivity or experience without a
subject. That's why it's important to bring out the full import of the notion of
subjectivity or experience by stressing the fundamental sense in which it can't
exist without a subject. But there's a no less important point in the other
direction. If all you need to know, to know that there is a subject, is that there
is subjectivity or experience, then you can't build more into the notion of a
subject than you can know to exist if subjectivity or experience exists. I think,
in fact, that the object/property distinction is metaphysically superficial—that
there is no ‘real distinction’ between (a) the being of an object, considered at a
given time, and (b) the being of that object's propertiedness, that is, its whole
actual concrete qualitative being at that time, that is, everything in which its
being the particular way it is at that time consists. But that is a difficult issue
for another time.2
current experience right now. Imagine that this neural activity somehow exists
on its own—nothing else exists. In this case a subject of experience exists. It
must exist, because experience exists. This last claim is not just the
epistemological claim that we can know that a subject exists because we know
that experience exists. It's the metaphysical claim that whatever constitutes the
existence of your experience must already suffice to constitute the existence
of a subject of experience. Otherwise it couldn't suffice to constitute the
existence of your experience, which it does by hypothesis.
The conception of the subject as a persisting neural structure or process
is probably the most common materialist conception of the inner subject, but I
prefer the more minimal ‘thin’ conception of the subject. According to the
thin conception, the presence of experience is not only sufficient for the
existence of the subject but also necessary. No experience, no subject of
experience. There's a new subject of experience every time there's a break in
experience. There's no subject of experience when one is dreamlessly asleep.
We already have it as a necessary truth that [existence of experience →
existence of subject of experience]. Now we add the converse [existence of
subject of experience → existence of experience].
This is the thin subject. According to the present proposal, this isn't just a
way of thinking of the subject, a way of isolating an aspect of the subject,
where the subject proper must be supposed to be the whole human being, or a
persisting neural structure, or some such. Rather, when we consider the
subject as defined by the thin conception of the subject we have to do with
something that is, whatever its metaphysical category, at least as good or solid
a candidate for qualifying as an entity, a thing, an object (a substance, if you
like) as the whole human being, or a persisting brain structure.
This is not to say that reality contains anything that actually makes the
grade as a thing or object or substance. The Buddhist doctrine of ‘dependent
origination’ suggests that nothing does. An alternative view is that only one
thing does—the universe. On this view, Parmenides and a number of leading
present-day cosmologists are right. There's really only one A-Grade thing or
object or substance: the universe. (Nietzsche and Spinoza agree that nothing
smaller will do.)
That's one important view. The present claim is neutral on this issue. It's
simply that the claim thin subjects are as good, as candidates for thinghood, as
anything else. In fact I think they're better candidates than a persisting brain
structure, or any ordinary physical object, and indeed any supposed
fundamental particle.4 I'm stressing the point to counter the thought that thin
subjects are somehow not real things, ontologically worse off than persisting
brain-structures, for example. This view isn't sustainable, I think, when
metaphysics gets serious and stops spending its time trying to square ordinary
language and ordinary thought categories with reality.
4
I support this claim in Strawson 2009: 294–320, 379–88.
GALEN STRAWSON
Having said that, I should add that most of the claims I'm going to make
will apply to the persisting-brain-structure subject as well as to the thin
subject. The difference between these two conceptions of the inner subject
isn't really at issue when it comes to my main present purpose, which is to
consider the old claim that the subject can't in the present moment of
awareness take itself as it is in the present moment of awareness as the object
of its awareness. The thin subject is my favourite candidate for the title ‘self’,
if we're going to talk of selves at all, but this issue too—the issue
between those who agree with me about this and those who feel that any
candidate for the title ‘self’ must be something more enduring—may be put
aside for the purposes of this paper.
I'm going to use various numbers and letters to set things out, and
apologize to those who don't like this sort of thing. I hope that my approach to
the issues I discuss may contrast helpfully with some of the Indian approaches
considered in this book precisely because of my ignorance of the Indian
approaches.
3. Present-Moment Self-Awareness
Some claim that the subject can no more take itself as the object of its
awareness than the eye can see itself, or, putting aside the word ‘taking’, that
(i) the subject can no more be the object of its awareness than the eye can
see itself.
Some make the more restricted claim that the subject cannot in the present
moment of awareness take itself as it is in the present moment of awareness as
the object of its awareness, or, putting aside ‘taking’ again,
(ii) the subject in the present moment of awareness cannot be the object
of its awareness in the present moment of awareness,
which has already been argued for (and is in any case evident, given that it is
legitimate to talk of properties at all), and
[3] any awareness, A1, of any awareness, A2, entails awareness of the
subject of A2
that is,
[5] is in fact the only defensible version of [4]—as Aristotle pointed out—
given the threat of an infinite regress of awarenesses of awarenesses that [4]
poses as it stands.10 I'll call [5] the AOI thesis, ‘AOI’ for ‘awareness of itself’,
‘AOI’ for short.
The claim is, then, that AOI plus the two principles [P1] and [P2] entails
USA. More briefly: AOI and [3] entail USA. The argument isn't formally
valid as it stands, but the idea is clear.
It may be allowed that [5] all awareness involves awareness of itself, but
doubted that
on the grounds that there is always a time lag, or an episode of what Ryle calls
‘swift retrospective heed’ (1949: 153). But it seems that this is not possible, if
[5] is true at all, because the last moment in any episode of awareness couldn't
in this case involve awareness of itself (all streams of awareness would have
to last for ever).
The substantive premiss is AOI. The question is, why believe AOI?
Why—to strengthen it slightly—believe
[12] all awareness on the part of any subject at any moment comports
awareness, at that moment, on the part of that same subject, of that
very awareness at that very moment
or, shortening [10] to what I hereby designate as the canonical version of AOI,
Good question, about which there is a lot to say. I think AOI is initially
difficult, but compelling on reflection. It's endorsed by many,
including Descartes, Arnauld, Locke, Brentano, Husserl, Sartre, and most
thinkers in the Phenomenological tradition.12 All of them insist that the
awareness of awareness that is held to be partly constitutive of all awareness
mustn't be thought of as involving some ‘higher-order’ mental apprehension,
A1, say, bearing on an ontically distinct, separate, ‘lower-order’ mental
apprehension, A2 (for this triggers an infinite regress). The relevant awareness
of awareness is, rather, an intrinsic feature of any episode of awareness
11
One can rewrite [13] as [13a] all awareness comports self-awareness—so long as one is clear that the
occurrence of ‘self-’ in ‘self-awareness’ is merely reflexive, so that [13a] means exactly the same as [13],
and doesn't imply any awareness of something called a self.
12
See, e.g. the quotations from Sartre in Zahavi, this volume, p. 56.
RADICAL SELF-AWARENESS
but [14] is paradoxical, at least initially, in a way that [13] isn't, because it
seems clear that awareness is, necessarily, a property of a subject of awareness
(as [13] still allows, given the word ‘comport’), and can't properly—or indeed
possibly—be said to be a property of awareness itself. That said, I think that
[14] is an acceptable way of putting things. First, it's an acceptable shorthand
for [11]: all awareness on the part of any subject comports awareness, on the
part of that same subject, of that very awareness. Secondly, and more strongly,
the fact that all awareness is, necessarily, awareness on the part of asubject of
awareness—the fact that reference to a subject must enter into any fully
articulated description of what is going on when there is awareness—does not
in any way undercut the truth of [14], according to which it is a constitutive
feature of the phenomenon of awareness itself that it comports awareness of
itself. Thirdly (a much stronger and much more difficult point), I think that
there is a metaphysically fundamental conception of the subject (by which I
mean the thin subject) given which
or in other words
accepts it, then [14], the further proposed version of AOI, can be understood
to be fully equivalent to [2] = USA. That is,
If S = A is too strong for you, you may be able to accept the weaker claim that
If you think [P1] & [P2] are trivially true, you can shorten this to
[AOI → USA].
All I've done, in moving from [5] to [13] ± [14], is re-express AOI in a
number of different ways, but one might also say that all I've done is re-
express USA in a number of different ways. (The AOI thesis is focused on the
nature of awareness, whereas the USA thesis is focused on the nature of the
self or subject, but they are of course closely connected.)
Arnauld puts AOI well when he writes that ‘thought or perception is
essentially reflective on itself, or, as it is said more aptly in Latin, est sui
conscia’, is conscious of itself.16 In endorsing the AOI thesis, as he does here,
he also endorses USA, given that he follows Descartes in accepting the S = A
thesis.
Ryle also puts it well, although with disparaging intent, when he speaks
of the idea that consciousness is ‘self-intimating’ in some constitutive way, or
‘self-luminous’, or ‘phosphorescent’ (1949: 158–9; see also 162–3, 178).
Frankfurt is also helpful, although parts of this passage are potentially
misleading:
from the concrete being of its attributes at that time (whatever modes of the attributes are currently
instantiated).
16
1683: 71; he uses ‘thought or perception’ to cover all conscious mental goings on.
RADICAL SELF-AWARENESS
awareness but also the awareness of it. It is like a source of light which, in
addition to illuminating whatever other things fall within its scope, renders itself
visible as well (Frankfurt 1987: 162).17
The claims that are most likely to mislead in Frankfurt's passage are.
but [a] doesn't I think say more than [13], the AOI thesis that all
awareness comports awareness of itself, and [b], which may presumably be
adjusted to (or at least entails) being conscious is identical with being self-
conscious, may be understood to be the same as to [2], USA, the key thesis
that the subject of awareness is always present-moment-aware of itself. The—
in my opinion correct—suggestion is (once again) that USA falls out of the
AOI thesis as a necessary consequence of it, given principles [P1] and [P2] on
pp. 280–1 above. If one also accepts [16], the S = A thesis, the ultimate
identity of the subject and its awareness, then [a] and [b] come to the same
thing.
[O2] The fact that AOI is true is constitutive of the intrinsic nature of
awareness in such a way that that intrinsic nature can't be specified
independently of the fact that AOI is true.
Locke endorses the second view, when he writes that ‘thinking consists in
being conscious that one thinks’.18 Arnauld's position in the quoted passage is
17
On the claim that consciousness is self-consciousness, compare again the quotations from Sartre in
Zahavi, this vol. p. 56. Among Indian philosophers, Dignāga, Dharmakīrti, Śaṃkara, and others regularly
use the trope of the light that illuminates itself. See e.g. Dreyfus and Ram-Prasad, this vol., pp. 120, 234.
18
1689: 2.1.19; he uses ‘thinking’ in the broad Cartesian sense to cover all experiential goings on.
GALEN STRAWSON
is seen to follow from a substantive thesis, the AOI thesis, which I've put
through a series of formulations, beginning with
passing through
[11] all awareness on the part of any subject at any moment, comports
awareness, at that moment, on the part of that same subject, of that very
awareness at that very moment,
The move made here, from the claim that the subject is necessarily aware of
its awareness to the claim that it is necessarily aware of itself, is guaranteed
given [P1] and [P2] (sc. [3]). AOI itself may still need defence, and even
when its truth is granted questions about its fundamental metaphysics will
remain. But these are matters for another occasion.
The most fundamental sense of selfhood involves the experience of self not as
an object of awareness but, in some crucial respects, as an unseen point of origin
for action, experience, and thought…. What William James called…the ‘central
RADICAL SELF-AWARENESS
nucleus of the Self’ is not, in fact, experienced as an entity in the focus of our
awareness, but, rather, as a kind of medium of awareness, source of activity, or
general directedness towards the world. (Sass 1998: 562)
Objects are present by being attended to, but subjects are present [to themselves]
as subjects, not by being attended to, but by attending. As the parade of objects
marches by, spectators do not have to slip into the parade to be present to
themselves. (Lonergan 1967: 226)
In knowing the object I know myself, not in the sense that I contemplate myself,
for I do not do so, but in the sense that I live through this experience of myself.
(Alexander 1924: 1.xiv)
Arthur Deikman makes the same point: ‘we know the internal observer not by
observing it but by being it…knowing by being that which is known
is…different from perceptual knowledge’ (1996: 355).19 This is knowledge
‘by acquaintance’. There's a narrow, philosophically popular, independent-
justification-stressing conception of knowledge that makes it hard for some to
see this is really knowledge, but the claim doesn't really need defence. Rather
the reverse: this particular case of knowledge, self-knowledge in non-thetic
self-awareness, shows the inadequacy of the narrow conception of knowledge.
The general point is backed up, most formidably, by the fact that knowledge
of this kind must lie behind all knowledge of the narrower justification-
involving sort, as a condition of its possibility. This is because it's a necessary
truth that all justification of knowledge claims is relative to something already
taken as given.
Certainly the eye can't see itself (unless there is a mirror). The knife can't
cut itself (unless it is very flexible), and the fingertip can't touch itself. The
idea that the subject of experience can't have itself as it is in the present
moment as the object of its thought—the idea that ‘my today's self’, in Ryle's
words, ‘perpetually slips out of any hold of it that I try to take’ (1949: 187)—
has many metaphorical expressions. Laycock says that it is part of ‘perennial
Buddhist wisdom’ (1998: 142), and so it is, considered as a truth about the
limitations of a certain particular sort of thetic, object-posing self-
apprehension. But it is, so taken, fully compatible with the claim that there's
another non-thetic form of occurrent self-apprehension in which the subject
19
Plainly ‘knowing by being that which is known’, or rather, perhaps, knowing (oneself) by being that
which is knowing, does not require knowing everything there is to know about that which is known. On a
standard materialist view, one may grant that that which is known, in this sort of self-presence of mind, has
non-experiential being whose nature is not then known at all.
GALEN STRAWSON
can be directly aware of itself in the present moment, for example in the way
just indicated by Lonergan, Sass, Alexander and Deikman. Dignāga and
Dharmakīrti also hold that a cognition cognizes itself, and is in the present
terms non-thetically aware of itself, although they don't in this context
distinguish explicitly between thetic and non-thetic awareness.20
Does it follow, from the fact that this form of occurrent present-moment
self-awareness is non-thetic, that it isn't explicit in any way? Is it some sort
of implicit awareness? No: there's a key sense in which the implicit/explicit
distinction lacks application when ‘awareness’ is used to refer to occurrent
experience, as here. ‘Awareness’ also has a dispositional use, as when we say
of someone who is dreamlessly asleep that she's aware of your intentions, and
this makes it seem natural enough to contrast implicit awareness with explicit
awareness, just as we contrast implicit with explicit understanding, and
implicit with explicit belief. The implicit/explicit distinction applies naturally
enough in the dispositional realm, as when we say of a dreamless sleeper that
she explicitly believes or understands or is aware that p, given that she has
actually consciously entertained and assented to the thought that p at some
time, or that she implicitly believes or understands or is aware that q, given
(say) that she would assent to q but hasn't ever actually consciously thought or
realized that q. The fact remains that there's no such thing as implicit
occurrent awareness, because ‘awareness’ is currently defined (p. 247) as
something that involves what-it's-likeness, which ‘implicit’ rules out.21 Non-
thetic occurrent awareness can't be said to be implicit occurrent awareness,
then: it's simply awareness of content that isn't in the focus of attention, or
rather, more simply, in attention.22 We can also call it background awareness,
perhaps, for background awareness isn't ‘implicit’ awareness either, any more
than dim or peripheral awareness is.
Another way to put the point, perhaps, is to say that all occurrent
awareness is ipso facto and eo ipsoexplicit awareness just in being, indeed,
awareness, occurrent awareness, genuinely given in awareness, part of the
actual content of experience that is experienced by the subject. This is,
admittedly, a non-standard use of ‘explicit’, inasmuch as it allows that explicit
awareness can be very dim, but one can use the word ‘express’ to do most of
the work usually done by ‘explicit’, and the basic distinction is in any case
clear: it's the undeniably real, if soft-bordered, distinction between express,
20
See e.g. Dreyfus, this vol, p. 120. On the terms of the thin conception of the subject and the S = A thesis,
then, Dignāga and Dharmakīrti can also be said to agree that the subject can be non-thetically aware of
itself.
21
This is not to say that one couldn't give sense to a notion of implicit awareness.
22
‘In attention’ is often better than ‘in the focus of attention’, because the notion of focus seems to contain
the foreground/background distinction, and to exclude the possibility that there may be nothing more to
one's experience, when one is attending, than what is in attention.
RADICAL SELF-AWARENESS
foreground, attentive, thetic awareness, on the one hand, and more or less dim,
peripheral, non-attentive, background, non-thetic awareness on the other.23
The distinction can be refined. There's a sense in which self-awareness of
the sort described by Sass, Lonergan, and Deikman can be said to be in the
foreground even though it isn't thetic. Such self-awareness is, or can be, a
centrally structuring part of experience, in such a way that it's rightly
classified as a foreground aspect of experience, even though there's also a
respect in which it normally passes unnoticed, being entirely non-thetic. In the
penultimate paragraph I suggested that we can equate ‘non-thetic’ with
‘background’, but I'm now inclined to overrule this by introducing a wider
notion of foreground and claiming that
25
There is also the case of Winnie the Pooh, Piglet and the Heffalump (Milne 1928).
26
One such method is Patricia Carrington's Clinically Standardized Meditation (1998).
GALEN STRAWSON
—the Thetic PSA thesis, for short. It claims that thetic SA (present-moment
self-awareness) is possible. It incorporates the idea that the neural time lag
objection mentioned at the end of §2 doesn't apply. In Yogācāra, it classifies
as a case of ‘objectless cognition’, a phenomenon whose possibility was much
debated in that tradition.
27
See, for example, Forman 1998, Shear 1998. See also Parfit 1998. It may be what Karme Chagme is
describing in the passage quoted by Dreyfus (this vol., pp. 121–2).
RADICAL SELF-AWARENESS
that is,
(the Express PSA thesis, for short) if the word ‘thetic’ is judged to be
irretrievably out of bounds. In the rest of this paper, though, I'm going to
continue to defend the Thetic PSA thesis: I'm going to take the word ‘thetic’
to be principally tied simply to the idea of attention, attentiveness, full
attention, and attempt to cultivate a sense of how attention (and cognition) can
have forms that don't involve anything like discursively structured operations
of positing or positioning things as objects of attention.
GALEN STRAWSON
can also occur more naturally, without being engineered for purposes of
philosophical research, as it is here. It can happen in cases when one passes
from thetic concentration to a state of absorption, artistic or otherwise.
One can do the same with the sensation of blue that one has when one
looks at the blue sky. One can take the sensation of blue as thetic object of
attention even as one continues to look at the sky (Reid and Moore make
related but different points),31 When one does this in a standard way, as a
philosophical exercise of the sort prescribed by Reid, one's awareness of the
sensation of blue will comport some sort of awareness of the fact that the
sensation of blue is being taken as object of attention. But one can also go
beyond this, I propose, into a state of direct thetic having-is-the-knowing
acquaintance, a state of holding the sensation of blue in full attention, in
which one's experience ceases to have, as any part of its content, the structure
of subject-attending-to-something.32
If this is right, we now have a model of thetic direct acquaintance in the
sense/feeling cases, and it's not clear why we should suppose that some huge,
further gulf must appear when we turn from such cases—pain, or blue-
experience—to the case of the subject. In fact, if the S = A thesis is correct,
as I think it is, then direct thetic acquaintance with pain or blue-experience is
already direct thetic acquaintance with the subject. Relative to such cases, the
special, alert, unpointed way of coming to awareness of oneself as a mental
presence (or as mental presence) described in §7 is special only in that it
doesn't involve any particular content like pain or blue-experience, and is
therefore a candidate for the title ‘pure consciousness experience’.33
—Even if you've now secured a case of thetic present-moment direct
acquaintance, you've done it only for the sense/feeling case, and you still need
to show how there can be non-sense/feeling present-moment direct
acquaintance.
Well, again it's not clear that we need to build a bridge from the proposed
cases of direct and thetic present-moment acquaintance with sense/feeling
content in order to understand, or at least acknowledge the possibility or
31
It's not easy: it requires practice, as Reid pointed out: ‘it is indeed difficult, at first, to disjoin things in
our attention which have always been conjoined, and to make that an object of reflection which never was
before, but some pains and practice will overcome this difficulty in those who have got into the habit of
reflecting on the operations of their own minds’ (1785: 196). See also James: when we consider perception,
we see ‘how inveterate is our habit of not attending to sensations as subjective facts, but of simply using
them as stepping-stones to pass over to the recognition of the realities whose presence they reveal’ (1890:
1.231). Some philosophers of perception mistakenly think that it is a mark of philosophical sophistication to
hold that this can't be done.
32
This isn't possible in Reid's model of attention to sensation, in fact, in which attention can only be paid to
sensation that is—however fractionally—already past. See Yaffe 2009.
33
It's still pretty special. Hume gives a correct (if widely misunderstood) report of the results of ordinary
reflective mental self-examination when he denies that he ever has any such experience: ‘when I enter most
intimately into what I call myself, I always stumble on some particular perception or other…. I never can
catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe any thing but the perception’
(1739/40: 252).
RADICAL SELF-AWARENESS
reality of, Thetic SA: direct, present-moment acquaintance of the subject with
itself. Thetic SA must presumably be a non-sense/feeling matter, hence a
cognitive matter, in some sense of cognitive—at least in part. But we already
have it that there is such a thing as cognitive experience (it pervades every
moment of our lives), and there is, as observed, a fundamental sense in which
it's essentially constitutive of something's being experiential content at all that
its subject or haver is in a relation of direct acquaintance with it—whether it
be sense/feeling content or cognitive-experiential content.34
I've claimed that Thetic SA must be an essentially non-sense/feeling
matter, at least in part, but I'm not sure quite what this amounts to, if only
because currently standard classifications of what one may call
the experiential modalities are extremely crude. Many assume that all
experiential modalities are sensory or sense/feeling modalities: they exclude
the idea that there are cognitive experiential modalities from the start. And
even those who admit that there is a distinctively cognitive experiential
modality may wish to exclude the idea that there may be a non-
propositional or non-discursive experiential modality which is nonetheless a
non-sense/feeling experiential modality, and indeed a genuinely cognitive
experiential modality. They're also likely to assume that the division between
sense/feeling content and cognitive experiential content is absolute, as I have
done for purposes of argument (without committing myself to the view that
either can occur wholly without the other).
These are difficult issues, about which I feel unsure. I do, however, feel
sure about the Thetic PSA thesis, the possibility of having direct thetic (in the
wider sense) awareness of oneself as subject in the present moment of
awareness. And I'm strongly inclined to think that this is, precisely, a non-
propositional, non-discursive form of awareness, which is nonetheless
properly said to be a matter of cognition.
11. Conclusion
I've proposed that the mental subject can be immediately relationally aware of
itself, both in the non-thetic, everyday Sass-Lonergan-Deikman way, and also,
exceptionally, in the express, thetic ‘pure consciousness experience’ way.40
Evidence? Each must acquire it for himself or herself in foro interno. This
doesn't mean it isn't empirical: it's wholly empirical. It does mean that it isn't
publicly checkable, and it will always be possible for someone to object that
the experience of truly present self-awareness is an illusion produced—say—
by Rylean flashes of ‘swift retrospective heed’ (1949: 153). I think, though,
that this notion of heed has the flying coat-tails error built into it, and there is
another larger mistake that can I think be decisively blocked.
Suppose that it's in the nature of all naturally evolved forms of
experience/consciousness that they are, in the usual course of things,
38
Fichte 1794–1802. The notion of ‘intellectual intuition’ is precisely an attempt to characterize a kind of
knowledge-of-x-involving relation with x that does not involve being affected by x in a way that inevitably
limits one to knowledge of an appearance of x. Note that if one goes into a state of Thetic SA, one's
awareness is bound to be genuinely awareness of oneself, the subject that one is—by the nature of the case.
39
Is one present-moment aware of oneself as being oneself? One might think ‘Yes, but in some non-
conceptual way’, or, ‘No, inasmuch as nothing that really qualifies as a sense of individuality remains.’
40
According to Fasching, Indian soteriological traditions, such as Advaita Vedānta and Sāṃkhya-Yoga,
equate this with realization of the ‘self' —'which is nothing other than becoming aware of experiential
presence (consciousness) as such’ (Fasching, this vol., p. 207).
GALEN STRAWSON
41
Naturalism, by which I mean real naturalism, acknowledges experience or consciousness as the most
certainly known natural fact.
42
I think it must be; see, e.g. Strawson 2006a.
43
It may be that everything physical is experiential in some way, but I'll put this point aside.
44
To speak of such forms of consciousness is not to reject the possibility that functional equivalents of,
e.g., visual and auditory experience could exist in the complete absence of consciousness.
45
My thanks to Mark Siderits for his very helpful comments.
RADICAL SELF-AWARENESS
References
1. Introduction
and,
1
I have greatly benefitted from discussions with Georges Dreyfus, Galen Strawson, Evan Thompson, and
Dan Zahavi on the topics discussed here.
MARK SIDERITS
2
Yao (2005: 6–41) claims that the Mahāsāṃghikas also accepted the thesis that all cognitions are reflexive
or self-cognizing. The evidence he cites is equivocal, however. The context in which this claim is attributed
to them is a discussion of the knowledge of a liberated person. The question is whether such a person
knows the nature of all ultimately real entities at one time. While other Abhidharma schools claim that such
knowledge occurs serially, the Mahāsāṃghikas say there can be a single cognition that cognizes
all dharmas or ultimate reals. Since this cognition is itself a dharma, this means it is included in the set of
all dharmas whose nature is cognized. What is unclear is whether the cognition involved here is perceptual
in the strong sense of what Nyāya calls non-conceptual perception. Only if it is would we have in this claim
an anticipation of Dignāga's view.
3
By ‘Abhidharma’ I mean what is also sometimes called Śrāvakayāna, the teachings of the so-called 18
schools of ‘Hearers’. Representative works of Abhidharma thought include the Theravāda
compendium Visuddhimagga by Buddhaghosa, and Abhidharmakośabhāṣya by the Sautrāntika philosopher
Vasubandhu. (Strictly speaking Sautrāntika is not an Abhidharma school, but its project is sufficiently like
that of the 18 schools that it may usefully be put under that rubric here.)
4
For Bhāviveka's rejection of reflexivity see Eckel 2008: 288, 437.
5
I should say in advance that this outlandish position was not to my knowledge held by any Indian
Buddhist school. I arrive at it through a combination of rational reconstruction and speculation based on
positions actually held by various Indian philosophers. I engage in this exercise because I think there may
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
The Buddha said that suffering arises because of our ignorance about our
identity. We are each trapped on the wheel of saṃsāra because we have a
false view about what the ‘I’ truly is. Thus far his teachings are not unlike
those of other Indian emancipatory projects (see Fasching and Ram-Prasad,
this volume). What sets his apart is the doctrine of non-self (anātman). The
Indian philosophical tradition, both Brahmanical and Buddhist, took this to be
the ultimate rejection of any entity that might serve as referent of the ‘I’, as
owner of the states of the person.6 Of course the Buddha did not deny that
persons experience such things as pleasure and pain. Indeed one of the
Buddha's core teachings is that there is suffering, and it is virtually axiomatic
that suffering is adjectival on a sufferer, or more generally that experience
requires an experiencer. In his teachings, the Buddha follows the common-
sense way of understanding such things when he attributes such states to
persons. This appears to conflict with his teaching of non-self. The tradition
sought to resolve this conflict by claiming that, in such teachings, the Buddha
is merely using the common parlance, that such teachings are merely
‘conventionally true’ and not ‘ultimately true’. It is out of this hermeneutical
device that there emerges the articulation of the non-self doctrine that I call
Buddhist Reductionism.
Buddhist Reductionism is based on the claim that if ‘I’ is a referring
expression then its referent might be one of two things: it might be the self,
defined as that one part of the psycho-physical complex that is its essence, or
it might be the person, the whole that is constituted by the psycho-physical
elements when properly arranged in a causal series. Buddhist Reductionists
claim that there is no self, and that the person is only conventionally, and not
ultimately, real. To say that the person is only conventionally real is to call it a
kind of useful fiction. The idea is that, strictly speaking, there are only
impersonal psycho-physical elements in a causal series, but the cognitive
be interesting things we can learn when we take seriously the resources provided by the Indian
philosophical tradition.
6
Some modern scholars (e.g. Albahari 2006) claim that the Buddha meant to deny only an empirically
accessible self, not the self tout court. While I am skeptical that the Buddha intended to affirm a
transcendent self, or even to leave his teachings open to the interpretation that there is such a thing, this is
not the place to engage in a dispute over ‘what the Buddha really meant’. What is, I think, beyond dispute is
how the Indian philosophical tradition subsequently took the Buddha's teaching of non-self, namely as the
straightforward denial that anything ultimately real might serve as experiencer, controller, and ground of
diachronic personal identity.
MARK SIDERITS
7
I discuss the distinction between Reductionism and Eliminativism in more detail in chapter 1 of
Siderits 2003.
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
belief in a self for whom events in this life have meaning and value may be
useful (up to a point), such a self can at best be a useful fiction.
The point beyond which this fiction ceases to be useful is, of course, the
point at which the well-being promoted by its adoption is outweighed by the
suffering that results from taking it as more than a useful fiction. This
suffering is, paradigmatically, the frustration, alienation, and despair that
come with the realization of one's own mortality. This realization typically
threatens to drain one's life of all significance by revealing the happiness-
seeking project to be unsustainable in the long run: How can the events in my
life have meaning if in the long run that for which they have value will cease
to exist? The Buddhist soteriological project may be seen as at bottom an
attempt to show how to reap the benefits of the useful fiction of the person,
without paying the steep price exacted when we take it literally.8
This gives us an important criterion in assessing proposed accounts of
cognition from a Buddhist perspective. Buddhist philosophers tend to be wary
of anything that might be taken to be a self. Collins once claimed that this
represents no more than a linguistic taboo on words like ‘I’ and ‘self’
(Collins1982: 183). This wariness may instead stem from a genuine concern
that there be nothing that could serve as the basis for suffering-inducing
appropriation. In assessing accounts of cognition, the Buddhist philosopher
will want to know whether the appeal of a given account stems, covertly, from
its appearing to affirm such things as human value and dignity, or the richness
of a fully human life. As other contributors to this volume have pointed out,
there are any number of different sorts of self on offer, with varying degrees
of thinness or thickness.9 It is conceivable that some sort of self is necessary
for an adequate account of human cognition. Perhaps subjectivity does require
a subject, not only conventionally (as the Buddhist Reductionist readily
grants) but ultimately as well. The Buddhist simply cautions that acceptance
of such an entity should be based on compelling evidence, and not just on the
desire that it be possible for our lives to have value and dignity.
8
For more on what it might mean to live in this mode, see Siderits 2006, Goodman 2009.
9
For instance, the sort of ‘embodied self’ that is required to explain motor control (discussed by
Thompson, Krueger, and MacKenzie, this volume) is probably too thin to arouse Buddhist suspicions. That
an animate organism must be able to tell its body from the surrounding environment, to locate its movable
parts within that environment, and to predict the results of motion of its body parts, is indisputable. But as
neuroscience uncovers more about the brain mechanisms that support these abilities, it becomes
increasingly clear that they involve no more than the most straightforward of feedback loops, and thus
nothing that could provide much solace to those seeking the basis for a sense of rich narrative depth. It
seems unlikely that sea slugs experience existential suffering.
MARK SIDERITS
Buddhist philosophers were, of course, familiar with the view that the self
is just of the nature of consciousness (found in the Upaniṣads, and held by
Sāṃkhya, and later by Vedānta—see Fasching, this volume), or that
consciousness is one of the qualities of the self (held by Nyāya). One very
early response is that consciousness cannot be the self since it is impermanent.
Consciousness is here acknowledged as among those psychophysical elements
(skandhas) that make up the person, and as thus itself real. But, it is claimed,
since consciousness arises in dependence on contact between sense faculty
and sensible object, and the senses of vision and smell are distinct, the
consciousness that takes the color of the flower as object must be distinct from
that which takes its smell as object a moment later. The assumption at work
here is that the self is meant to be the ground of diachronic personal identity,
and as such would have to endure as long as the person endures.
A different assumption about the self is the target of another argument
developed later in the Abhidharma tradition. This assumption is that the act-
object model is appropriate for understanding the nature of consciousness.
That this assumption would prove useful in trying to establish the existence of
a self is evident from its role in the Cartesian cogito. In the hands of Nyāya
and Mīmāṃsā philosophers it is deployed by way of the grammatical point
that a construction involving a verb and an occurrence of the accusative case
requires an occurrence of the nominative: the cutting (verb) of the tree
(accusative) requires that there be a cutter (nominative). So consciousness
requires a subject, which is understood to be just the self.
One Abhidharma response to this argument builds on the thesis that all
existents are not just impermanent (as the Buddha claimed) but momentary,
lasting but an instant before perishing and being replaced by others. This
thesis has the interesting consequence that there can be no such thing as the
performance of an action. To speak of someone or something performing an
action is to presuppose that an entity can continue to exist through three
distinct times: when the action is yet to be performed, when the action is being
performed, and when the action has been completed. If all existing things are
momentary, then nothing endures through two times, let alone three. Applied
to the case of consciousness, this not only undermines the argument for the
self as the agent of the action of being conscious. It also subverts the view,
implicit in Sāṃkhya and explicit in Advaita Vedānta, that the self is not a
substance, but just the pure activity of witnessing. As Vasubandhu puts it,
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
The fact that we can ‘compute the embryo’ (Rosenberg 1997) certainly
suggests that we can predict macro-level properties of the organism from
micro-level knowledge of its causal antecedents. The feedback loops of such
organic processes as immune system functioning are also readily
decomposable, along the lines of such models as audio (mike-amp-speaker)
feedback, and the self-controlling home heating system. Once we prise apart
ontological and semantic reduction, we may come to see that the appearance
of system-level causation often stems from our need to treat the system as one
big thing in order to manage our cognitive economies. It is sometimes claimed
that since RNA is a self-assembling structure, its causal powers cannot be
reduced to those of its constituent molecules. But this consequence does not
follow from the structure's being self-replicating. It would only follow that
RNA has irreducible causal powers if the structure could not have first
appeared through the unprecedented combination of molecular components.
There is ongoing research into the question whether terrestrial processes could
have brought this about. It would be presumptuous to make any claim about
this in advance of definitive research results. But given the past history of
emergentism, it would surely be rash to take our current lack of knowledge
about how it might have happened as evidence that it cannot have happened.11
the contact of sense faculty with sensible object and the occurrence of sensory
cognition. Since the object lasts only a moment, it no longer exists when the
cognition occurs, so it cannot be the object of that cognition. The direct object
of sensory cognition must instead be a mental image or representation. Now it
was open to Sautrāntika to retain the old model of sensory cognition as a
mental act operating on a distinct object, only ‘internalize’ the object by
making it a separate mental state that then serves to represent the external
object with which the perceptual process began. But this was not the path they
ultimately chose. And perhaps with good reason, since a representationalism
of this sort invites an understanding of the mind as Cartesian theater, with
consciousness as spectator viewing the images brought in by the senses.
Instead, in later Sautrāntika we find the claim that awareness of sensory
content occurs through the arising of a cognition that bears the form of the
physical object. The experience of seeing blue is just the occurrence of a
cognition that has blue color as its form. Consequently, a cognition cognizes
itself.
Dignāga is widely held to have first developed this reflexivity claim, but it
seems likely to have originated somewhat earlier, in Sautrāntika.12 Dignāga is
the founder of the Yogācāra-Sautrāntika school of Buddhist epistemology, the
aim of which is to develop a theory of knowledge acceptable to both the
representationalist-realist Sautrāntika and the subjective idealist Yogācāra.
Yogācāra took the logical next step following Sautrāntika's
representationalism, playing Berkeley to their Locke. But Yogācāra also
developed some interesting views about the nature of consciousness
(discussed in greater detail by Dreyfus and by Ganeri, this volume). Of
particular importance here is their claim that consciousness is ultimately non-
dual in nature. This first comes out in their assertion that subjective idealism is
soteriologically effective in the quest for nirvana because the feeling of
interiority that is central to the sense of self depends on contrast with an
external world, so that all sense of self must dissolve once one realizes that
there is no external world. This suggests that Buddhist Reductionists had
begun to worry about the problem of subjectivity—the problem that the
phenomenal character of cognitive states seems to require that there be a
subject for which they have this character. This might then be part of the
motivation behind Dignāga's formulation of the reflexivity claim. Also worth
12
Yao (2005: 97–118) discusses the evidence for the claim of a Sautrāntika origin.
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
whom the impersonal entities and events appear. Reductionisms try to demote
their targets to a second-tier ontology of entities that are in some sense
‘subjective’. But when the target is the person, such demotion may seem
problematic, in that it is unclear how there can be such a status in the absence
of a real subject. Shoemaker (1985) may have had something like this
difficulty in mind when, in his review of Parfit's Reasons and Persons, he
claimed that the ontological reduction of persons that Parfit seemed to wish
for would require a reduction of the mental as well, to either the physical or to
events characterized functionally. So whether or not Dignāga had this problem
in mind when he formulated his reflexivity claim, it is still worth inquiring
whether his view offers Buddhist Reductionism any aid on this score.
Might Dignāga's approach succeed in answering the subjectivity
objection? Strawson's (2008) discussion of the relation between experiential
content and (thin) subject sheds some helpful light here. Now Strawson does
call it ‘a necessary truth’ that there is a subject whenever there is subjectivity
(2008: 183). And what Dignāga must give the Buddhist Reductionist is a way
of affirming subjectivity or what-it-is-like-ness that does not require an
experiencing subject. Strawson's thin subject exists only for a moment, and so
would be considered unobjectionable by Abhidharma standards. But we are
supposing Dignāga is concerned that even a fleeting subject of experience can
serve as grounds for existential suffering, and wants to show that phenomenal
content is possible without even this thinnest of subjects. Strawson's claim
must be read with caution however, for this comes in the context of a
sustained argument for the conclusion that the distinction between subject and
content of experience is at best only conceptual, not real. And this sounds very
much like Dignāga's claim that cognition's two forms (the form of the object
and the form of its nature as cognizing) are only conceptually and not
ultimately distinct. It seems then that Strawson's ‘necessary truth’ holds only
conventionally—which for Dignāga means for purposes of discourse, the
ultimate truth being inexpressible. Ultimately, cognition is non-dual, but this
non-duality being inexpressible, it cannot be stated and so cannot be the
content of any sort of true statement.
This identity of subject and content would go some way toward
explaining the much-touted immunity from error through misidentification
allegedly possessed by our awareness of our own conscious states. That we
cannot be wrong in thinking that a given state is our own is sometimes seen as
evidence, not only for the existence of a subject of experience (as Fasching,
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
this volume, interprets it), but also for reflexivity. It could thus serve as
support for the self-illumination view (though Dignāga did not so use it). The
idea is that since subjective states are simply and immediately given as one's
own, it must be the case that in undergoing such a state one is immediately
aware, not only of its content but of its being experienced as well. If, as
Dignāga and Strawson seem to be saying, cognizing and content are only
conceptually and not ontologically distinct, then it follows that cognizing of
content just is cognizing of the cognizing. So it is hardly any wonder that one
cannot go wrong in identifying an experience as belonging to this (thin)
subject. But now the reflexivity claim begins to look a little odd. If the
cognition of cognition is no more than the occurrence of phenomenal content,
in what sense can it be said that some operation is being carried out on that
content by that very content itself? The demand for a subject began with the
claim that what-it-is-like-ness requires that for which it is so like. We are
taking Dignāga to have sought to answer this with his reflexivity claim. One
begins to suspect that the ‘for’ in ‘that for which it is so like’ reflects the
functional role of cognition, not its intrinsic nature: content presents itself to
the system for which it serves a role in action guidance. And of course this
system is a complex series, not something ultimately real.15
In any event, Dignāga's view is not without its philosophical difficulties.
First, Indian philosophers generally accept a principle of irreflexivity, to the
effect that an entity cannot operate on itself. Even the most skilled acrobat, it
is said, cannot stand on their own shoulders. The alleged counter-example of
light, that supposedly illuminates itself while illuminating other things, is
questionable. Strictly speaking what is visible when we say we see a beam of
light is dust motes illuminated by the light, not the light itself.16 Likewise,
mereological reductionism shows how to dispose of such other alleged
counter-examples as the sentence that refers to itself, or the doctor who heals
herself. Proper analysis shows such cases to invariably involve one part of a
larger system operating on another part. It is our belief in real wholes that
leads us to suppose there are genuinely reflexive operations in the world.
15
Perhaps Dignāga would agree that cognition is self-illuminating only in the weak sense that cognitive
content presents itself to the system without the need for any other source of illumination. According to
Williams (1998), certain Tibetan exegetes took Dignāga and Dharmakīrti this way. But this can be confused
with self-reflexivity only if one presupposes a certain sort of internalist model of cognition according to
which one is aware that p only if one is aware that one is aware that p.
16
But see Fasching, this volume, for an alternative way of taking the claim that light illuminates itself.
MARK SIDERITS
17
For a survey of the debate between self-illuminationists and other-illuminationists, see Sinha1958: 199–
221. More recent discussions include Ganeri 1999, and Chapter 2 of Ram-Prasad 2007.
18
Perrett 2003: 226f makes a similar point about Sartre's version of the argument. For further discussion,
see Chatterjee 2008. For an analysis of Dharmakīrti's formulation of the infinite regress argument that
reveals it to be equally question-begging, see Kellner (forthcoming).
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
19
See, e.g., PV 3.10, PV 3.299, TSP ad TS 1120–1. There are good neuroscientific reasons to suppose that
there must be discriminable differences between perceptual representations and representations generated
internally (such as memory images and simulations). On the forward dynamic model of action control, the
agent produces an ‘efference copy’ of the motor command which is then compared with the sensory
consequences of one's action. As such, this forward copy must be perceptually attenuated. This explains
why, e.g. a ticklish person cannot tickle themselves. See Choudhury and Blakemore 2006: 40–1. Perceptual
attenuation might correspond to what the Buddhist authors mean by ‘indistinct’.
MARK SIDERITS
Other Buddhist schools hold that one becomes conscious of a cognition only
through a distinct cognition. This is the view of Theravāda, Vaibhāṣika, early
Sautrāntika and Prāsaṅgika Madhyamaka. But I know of no systematic
development and defense of the other-illumination view by any Buddhist
philosopher. Now, because all these schools hold that consciousness is
momentary but that a self must endure, they would not see a difficulty if it
turned out that an occurrence of consciousness plays the role of subject in a
particular cognition. But suppose we agreed with Strawson (1997) and the
Yogācārins that anything that may be seen as playing the role of conscious
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
cognition that has it as intentional object. Hence we arrive back at the need to
countenance the direct cognition of cognition.
To this it is replied that the cognizedness in the object is just the property
of the object's being available for speech and action: to say there is
cognizedness in the pot is just to say that the pot can now be referred to and
employed in various ways. To this it is objected (Sinha 1958: 210) that it is
tantamount to denying the existence of cognition. The thought behind this
objection is that if there is no more to cognizedness than the availability of the
object for systems like memory, speech, desire, and action-guidance, then
‘consciousness’ comes to seem like an empty place-holder. And there is, I
think, something to this objection. If all there were to cognizedness was being
such as to be available to a single system, such as action-guidance, there
would be no reason to posit anything like consciousness in order to explain
the phenomena. For this is just what we find in cases of blind-sight: the
subject navigates around obstacles while claiming to see nothing. In such
cases we say that the object directly plays a causal role in the guidance of
action, without consciousness as an intermediary. We do not think the
thermostat is conscious of the temperature of the air in the room: the
thermostat serves as an intermediary between the temperature of the air and
the operation of the heating/cooling system. But why should things be any
different where the object is available to multiple systems? The flow of
information is more complex, but such flow is still along what are, after all, no
more than causal pathways, just more of them. The suggestion is that if
cognizedness is just global availability, then the abductive inference to
consciousness fails to go through.20
A Buddhist Reductionist other-illumination theorist would no doubt want
to resist this consequence of their view, that consciousness becomes a mere
empty place-holder. First there are considerations of orthodoxy. To call
consciousness an empty place-holder is in effect to call it a conceptual fiction.
Yet the Buddha spoke of consciousness as one of the psychophysical elements
(skandhas) to which the person is said to be reducible. So to call
consciousness a conceptual fiction would be to call the Buddha's authority
into question. But there are also considerations stemming from the role of
meditation in Buddhist practice. For meditation looks like a kind of
phenomenological investigation; in meditation one carefully examines the rise
20
For a useful discussion of the term ‘global availability’, see Metzinger (2003: 31).
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
might be said, is just such an illusion. Of course this must count as the mother
of all illusions, since without it there could be no gap between how things
seem and how things are. But it nonetheless makes sense to speak of it as an
illusion, since it leads the system in which it occurs to misrepresent its
environment. There is no what-it-is-like-ness for the thermostat, yet we speak
naturally of our fooling the thermostat into taking the room to be warmer than
it is by holding a candle nearby. So we might say that the psycho-physical
system misrepresents its environment as containing a subject to which things
seem a certain way. One's grasping of this point may include an instance of
just such a seeming. But this need not be paradoxical. Once we see how the
illusion is generated, and why it persists (due to its utility for systems like
these), we can understand that it is a misrepresentation, and why such a
misrepresentation occurs.
A second possible response is that the illusion may be dispelled by
knowledge of its source. In the Buddhist tradition one sometimes encounters
the claim that when fully perfected enlightened beings exercise their
compassion, they do not cognize the unenlightened beings who are the objects
of their compassion, but nonetheless act appropriately toward them in a purely
spontaneous, intuitive fashion. One might dismiss this as the sort of hyperbole
that is often generated when devotionalist sects compete over the relative
merits of their ideal figures. But in this case there is at least something more
going on. In Yogācāra thought all conceptualization is said to be deceptive in
that it conceals the non-dual nature of reality. Since enlightened beings know
the ultimate nature of reality, it follows that their grasp of the world must be
non-conceptual. Yet unenlightened beings inhabit a world that is structured by
a set of conceptual tools. And it would seem that the enlightened can help the
unenlightened only by sharing in that distorted vision. One response to this
dilemma is to claim that enlightened beings act directly on their perception
without any intervening thought, yet their actions are ideally suited to benefit
the unenlightened. This notion of a Robo-Buddha sounds implausible, but it
might be worth looking to see if sense can be made of it in the present context.
The other-illumination theorist holds that a cognition need not itself be
cognized in order to perform its function of illuminating the object. (Note that
for the Buddhist Reductionist I have in mind, consciousness is a target for
reduction, not elimination, and so is conventionally real: they hold the other-
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
22
For a clear statement of the difference between reductionism and eliminativism about the mental, see
Kim 2004: 138.
MARK SIDERITS
subject, not even a momentary one, nor is there the inner subjective realm.
Consciousness is only conventionally and not ultimately real. That there are
Robo-Buddhas would show that the difference between zombies and us is just
one of our taking all too seriously the merely useful device of self-
representation.23
Abbreviations
References
Bibliography references:
23
Dretske (2003) appeals to the evidence concerning early childhood acquisition of the concept of belief in
arguing for the claim that one's thinking and experiencing are constituted by external, historical relations. A
useful summary of this evidence is to be found in Gopnik (2009). On the resulting view, self-representation
is not only an acquired skill, but also one the exercise of which introduces distortions into our view of
ourselves. This might suggest an alternative reading of Dignāga's claim that the subject-object distinction
results from conceptual superimposition. On this reading, phenomenality is the by-product of the useful
practice of self-representation, a practice made possible by the use of concepts. And all conceptualization
falsifies the nature of reality by making reality conform to our interests and cognitive limitations. One
might, then, in turn interpret the methodological stance taken by Dreyfus (this volume), of conducting
phenomenological investigation while steering clear of ontological questions, as a stance that is compatible
with thoroughgoing ontological reduction. The idea would be that while the other-illuminationist is right
that mental states are not intrinsically self-intimating, and thus that self-illuminationism is not ultimately
true, the useful device of self-representation gives rise to the appearance of phenomenality and self-
cognition, and careful exploration of this realm can be helpful in dispelling our belief in a subject of
experience. Yogācāra would then represent a lesser form of conventional truth.
BUDDHAS AS ZOMBIES: A BUDDHIST REDUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY
abductive inference 322, 326, 329 boundary 69, 81, 82, 129, 252, 254
Abhidharma 116–20, 133, 141, 196, 245–7, Brahman 220
250, 251, 254, 258, 309n. 3, 313–15 Buddhism 29, 39n. 15, 115, 118, 195, 213,
adhyāsa, see superimposition 236
Advaita Vedānta 195–8, 200, 201, 204, 209– bundle theory 81, 92, 93, 109, 115, 133
13, 217–26, 236, 237
agent 86, 89, 129, 241 Campbell, J. 189
ahaṃkāra, see ‘I-maker’ Candrakīrti 171, 189, 190, 261, 264, 265
ālayavijñāna, see consciousness, store Cartesianism 124n. 20, 239
Albahari, M. 60–7, 127–30, 140, 141, clones 68
204n. 21, 218, 241 cognitive phenomenology 296
anātman, see no-self, in Buddhism cognitive science 136, 148, 257
anonymity 67 cognizedness 322, 325, 329
anosognosia 85, 105 conceptual fabrication 178, 181
Anscombe, G.E.M. 189, 190 conscious attention 176, 178, 180
antaḥkaraṇa, see internal organ consciousness, see also awareness:
AOI thesis, the 280–7 discerning 95, 97, 98
Appropriation 5, 102, 103, 128, 229, 230, formal 221
311 impermanent 96
arahant/arhat 79, 95, 104, 139, 140 intransitive 158–61, 172
Aristotle 36 as irreflexive 309, 324
Āryadeva 261 store 142–50, 178, 184n. 10, 327n. 21
Asaṅga 142, 176, 177, 180, 184, 189 conscious system 224
ātman 201n. 17, 204, 212, 218– continuity 75, 76, 142, 146, 247–50, 263,
22, 226, 228–32, 240–4 266–8
attention 112, 176, 180, 182, 210, 289, 294–8
attentional blink 124 Dainton, B. 71, 276n. 3
auto-luminosity, see self-illumination Damasio, A. 40, 411, 87, 106, 107,
autonomous systems 251–5 108n. 16, 112, 136, 140, 144, 263n. 28
autopoiesis 252, 256 Dasein 221
awareness 65n. 2, 118–22, 142–6, 148, 228, de-identification 103, 211
231, 280–90, 293, 294, 301, 315, 317 Dennett, D. 35, 37, 70, 92, 125n. 21
dependent origination 29, 30, 118, 250, 251,
Bergson, H. 71 258
bhavaṅga citta 148 depersonalization 62, 64, 85, 105
boundedness 69, 86, 102, 129 de se thought 182–184
de-superimposition 211 Fasching, W. 83, 217, 218, 302n. 40
Dharmakīrti 31–3, 47, 50, 120, 160, 288 fictionalism 251, 256, 258
dharmas 133, 245–7, 248n. 8, 250, 251, first-person 70, 94, 133, 146, 171, 179, 197,
309n. 2 218, 227, 231, 249
Dignāga 120, 160, 161, 288, 317–21, 324 first-person givenness 43–7, 50, 51, 58–60,
discerning cognition 96, 97 68, 76, 99, 101, 109, 132, 173
draṣṭā, see seer first-person perspective 33, 34, 38, 50, 59,
Dretske, F. 329n. 23 63, 67, 74, 83, 84, 95, 97–9, 190, 261–3
Dreyfus, G. 65–7, 73, 177n. 3, 184n. 10, Flanagan, O. 91, 124n. 20
269n. 33 for-me-ness 58, 59, 67, 84, 99, 100, 204n. 21
dynamic co-emergence 253
Gallagher, S. 38, 41, 268
ego 49, 52, 169–73 Ganeri, J. 65, 265, 268
egoity 221, 227–9, 231 Garfield, J. 163, 258
egological 3, 47, 48, 49n. 21, 161, 162, 169– gnoseological project 221, 228
71, 173 grāhyākāra, see objective aspect
egology 226 grāhakākāra, see subjective aspect
ego-sense 193, 209, 211 Guṇaprabhā 117n. 6
elusiveness 84, 218 Gupta, B. 83
embodied 38, 40–2, 83, 186, 240, 268, 271, Gurwitsch, A. 169
312n. 9
embodied skills 42 Heidegger, M. 69, 221, 222n. 4
embodiment 143, 226–8 Henry, M. 59
emergent process 240, 253 heteronomous systems 252, 253
emotions 71, 86, 89, 108n. 16, 137, 139, 296 higher-order consciousness 9, 32n. 9, 45, 46,
empirical apperception 219 57, 158, 161, 162, 172, 283
emptiness 255–9 Hobson, R.P. 67
enactive 251, 255, 259, 268 Hume, D. 81, 87, 90, 108, 115, 299n. 33
enactivism 239 Husserl, E. 28, 58, 71–74, 121n. 14, 152,
encephalitis 40 158, 159, 163–9, 221, 266–8, 280, 283
enlightenment 64, 80, 223, 224 Hutto, D. 34
epileptic automatism 64, 106, 107, 112
erroneous cognition 228 identification 5, 61–3, 85–7, 102–4, 108,
experience 109–11, 117, 121–8, 131–4, 138, 128, 129, 183, 185, 210n. 29, 229
144, 147–52, 158, 161 identity 33, 52, 66, 74–6, 86, 87, 90, 91,
experience condition 95–99, 101, 110, 111 102, 104, 131, 132, 185, 229, 252, 259,
extended consciousness 40, 72 286, 320
extrinsic nature 246, 250 diachronic 75, 103, 198, 205, 243
illusion 62, 88, 124, 128, 327, 329
of self 60, 64, 79–82, 89, 91, 94, 102–8, MacIntyre, A. 35–7, 136
131, 193, 223, 256 MacKenzie, M. 102, 169n. 8, 190n. 13,
illusory 60–4, 72, 88, 91–3, 107, 109–11 195n. 3
imagination 90, 91, 108, 164 Madhyamaka 161n. 4, 162, 163, 195n.3, 251,
‘I-maker’ 30–4, 209, 227, 249, 250, 261, 257–65, 309, 316n. 11
268 manas, see mind
immunity to error through misidentification materialism 274
13, 180, 188, 200n. 12, 320 eliminative 107, 109
indexical 231, 261 meditation 103, 112, 114, 125n. 22, 326
individuality 51, 221, 226, 232 memory 73, 74, 132, 136, 161–74, 198, 248,
individuation 67, 68, 229 261, 321–3
in-each-case-mineness 222 memory argument 161–74, 321–23
‘I’-ness 219 memory loss 40, 106, 200
infinite regress 31, 32, 57, 72, 181, 281, 321 mental construct 90, 108
intentionality 157, 160 mental construction 107, 108, 121
longitudinal 267 Merleau–Ponty, M. 28, 74, 152, 158
transverse 267, 268 Metaphysics 80, 151, 152, 225, 277, 287,
internal organ 230, 231 301
intrinsic nature 30, 50, 234, 246, 250, 251, Metzinger, T. 50, 70, 97, 126, 208n. 28, 217,
258, 260, 286 221–6, 232, 236
invariability 61, 87, 90, 129, 241 micro-narratives 42, 43
ipseity 49n. 21, 58, 169, 172, 173, 181 Mīmāṃsā 220, 225, 227, 228, 235, 236
‘I’-thoughts 227 mind 59, 80–2, 90, 95, 97, 104, 105, 111,
114–16, 118–20, 123, 142, 151–3,
James, W. 69n. 4, 71, 82, 91, 100, 118, 133, 176, 177, 230–2, 292
137, 266, 287, 291, 298n. 31 mithyājñānam, see erroneous cognition
jemeinigkeit 222 mode of presentation 38, 45, 59, 68, 182, 183
jīva 209, 221, 222, 230 momentary 5, 94, 96, 236, 248, 266, 313
jñāna 200, 203 Montaigne, M. 67