Note 22: Private Information, Adverse Selection and Market Failure
Note 22: Private Information, Adverse Selection and Market Failure
Market Failure
David Autor, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
• We will cover Akerlof’s seminal 1970 paper on the topic, which sets up the following scenario:
imagine that you are selling a product (e.g., used cars). Potential buyers that come onto your
lot know the distribution of product quality (they know that some used cars work well, and
others are “lemons,” i.e. total garbage). How much should the buyer be willing to pay for a
used car? The intuitive answer might be the expected value of the product.
• But this preliminary answer ignores an important consideration: you (the seller) get to choose
which individual car you actually sell, and you may know which cars are valuable and which
are lemons. So if the buyer offers a certain price, you might accept that price but sell her a
lemon. Since the buyer knows this, she will offer a lower price in the expectation that she’ll get
a bad car. In which case, you certainly should not sell her one of your better cars. Knowing
she will certainly get a worse car (because she has lowered her offer price), she lowers her offer
price again...
• In equilibrium, you could face a scenario where both agents would be happy to make a deal
on a given product. But one agent has private information about the product and the other
player knows they might get ripped off, and nobody trades in the end. This same principle
comes up in other important markets – most famously, health insurance – but we will get to
that after establishing this theory formally.
1
1 Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons (Akerlof, 1970)
1.1 The fundamental problem:
1. Goods of different quality exist in the marketplace.
2. Sellers of goods know more than potential buyers about the quality of goods that they are
selling.
3. Akerlof’s critical insight: Potential buyers know that sellers know more about the quality of
goods than they do.
• This information asymmetry can substantially affect the market equilibrium. It is possible
that there will be no trade whatsoever for a given good, even though:
1. At any given price p0 , there are traders willing to sell their products.
2. At price p0 , there are buyers willing to pay strictly above p0 for the good that traders
wold like to sell.
• Akerlof (1970) was the first economist to analyze this paradox rigorously. His paper was
nominally about the market for used cars. It’s always been folk wisdom that it’s a bad idea to
buy used cars—that ‘you are buying someone else’s problem.’ But why should this be true?
If used cars are just like new cars only a few years older, why should someone else’s used car
be any more problematic than your new car after it ages a few years?
– There are 2 types of new cars available at dealerships: good cars and lemons (which break
down often).
– The fraction of lemons at a dealership is λ.
– Dealers do not publicly distinguish good cars versus lemons; they sell what’s on the lot
at the sticker price.
– Buyers cannot tell apart good cars and lemons. But they know that some fraction λ
∈ [0, 1] of cars are lemons.
– After buyers have owned the car for any period of time, they also can tell whether or not
they have bought a lemon.
G = $20, 000 to buyers and lemons are worth B L =
– Assume that good cars are worth BN N
$10, 000 to buyers.
– For simplicity (and without loss of generality), assume that cars do not deteriorate and
that buyers are risk neutral.
2
• What is the equilibrium price for new cars? This will be
• Since dealers sell all cars at the same price, buyers are willing to pay the expected value of a
new car.
• Now, consider the used car market. Assume that used cars sell at at 20 percent below their
new value. So good used cars and lemons sell for
• Since cars don’t deteriorate, used car buyers will be willing to pay BUG = $20, 000 and BUL =
$10, 000 respectively for used good cars and lemons. There the buyer and seller together gain
a a surplus of $4, 000 or $2, 000 from each sale. (Which actors actually gets the surplus may
depend on bargaining power, but it isn’t important for this model.) Selling either a good car
or a lemon is potentially Pareto improving.
• Recall that buyers cannot distinguish good cars from lemons, while owners of used cars know
which is which. Sellers will only part with their cars if offered a price that is greater than or
equal to their reservation price. Recall that reservation selling prices SUL = 8, 000, SLG = 16, 000.
So, for PU ≥ 8, 000 owners of lemons will gladly sell their cars. However, for PU < 16, 000,
owners of good cars would prefer to keep their cars.
• Given these reservation selling prices, the quality of cars available depends on the price. In
particular, the share of Lemons is as follows:
1 if P < 16, 000
U
P r(Lemon|Pu ) =
λ if P ≥ 16, 000
U
• That is, quality is endogenous to price. More specifically, we can say that expected reservation
selling price reflects quality of cars available for sale:
8, 000 if PU < 16, 000
E[SU |PU ] =
8, 000 · λ + (1 − λ) · 16, 000 if P ≥ 16, 000
U
3
• (Side Note: Recall that in recitation we discussed how, in markets with imperfect information,
the composition of products in the market changes as the price changes. This happened in
the Spence signaling model, where job offers that employers post changes whether high- and
low-ability workers apply for the job. This also happens in the insurance market on Problem
Set 6, where the price an insurer offers changes how sick the pool of buyers is on average. The
exact same fundamental mechanism is happening here.)
• The willingness of buyer’s to pay for used cars also depends upon the market price (a result
we have not previously seen in consumer theory).
• If there will be trade in equilibrium, buyers’ willingness to pay must satisfy the following
inequality: BU (E[SU |PU ]) ≥ PU . At the realized transaction price PU , the quality of cars
available for sale (as reflected in E [Su |Pu ] ) must be worth at least that price to buyers.
• First, consider the case where λ = 0.4. Consider the price PU = 16, 000. At this price, the
expected value (to a buyer) of a randomly chosen used car—assuming both good cars and
lemons are sold—would be
BU (PU = 16, 000, λ = 0.4) = (1 − 0.4) · 20, 000 + 0.4 · 10, 000 = 16, 000.
Here, used good cars sell at exactly the average price at which potential sellers value them.
Owners of good cars are indifferent and owners of lemons get a $8, 000 surplus. In math, this
equation satisfies the condition BU (E[SU |PU ]) ≥ PU .
• But now take the case where λ = 0.5. At price PU = 16, 000, the expected value of a randomly
chosen used car is:
BU (PU = 16, 000, λ = 0.5) = (1 − 0.5) · 20, 000 + 0.5 · 1, 0000 = 15, 000.
Hence, BU (E[SU |PU ]) < PU . Since owners of good used cars demand $16, 000, they will not
sell their cars at $15, 000. Yet, PU = 15, 000 is the maximum price that buyers will be willing
to pay for a used car, given that half of all cars are lemons. Consequently, good used cars will
not be sold in equilibrium, despite the fact that they are worth more to buyers than to sellers.
Thus, only lemons sell in equilibrium.
• More generally, if λ > 0.4, then good used cars are not sold and lemons sell for Pu ∈
[8, 000, 1, 0000].
4
• Bottom line: If the share of lemons in the overall car population is high enough, the bad cars
will drive out the good ones. Although buyers would be willing to pay $20, 000 for a good used
car, their inability to distinguish good cars from lemons means that they will not be willing
to pay more than $15, 000 for any used car. With λ high enough, no good cars are sold, and
the equilibrium price must fall to exclusively reflect the value of lemons.
• (Side Note: You may notice a parallel between this and our discussion about “Ban the Box.”
Banning the box made it difficult for employers to distinguish between non-felons and felons,
which then made them reluctant to interview minorities (who, in the United States, are more
likely to be felons). Loosely speaking, by prohibiting employers from distinguishing among
applicants who may be more or less desirable, “Ban the Box” generates an adverse selection
problem: employers cannot tell felons from non-felons; and felons have no incentive to reveal
this information once the “Box” is banned. Akerlof’s model shows that adverse selection
can potentially ‘shut down’ a market, such as the market for used cars. Agan and Starr’s
paper provides evidence that banning the box had the effect of ‘shutting down’—or at least
substantially harming—the job market prospects of minority applicants.)
• Buyers understand this, and so must adjust the price they are willing to pay to reflect the
quality of the goods they expect to buy at that price.
• In equilibrium, the average good available at a given price must be worth that price. If they are
not, then there will be no equilibrium price and it’s possible that no trade will occur.
• The underlying economics of adverse selection are very nicely exposited in the 2011 paper
on your reading list, “Selection in Insurance Markets: Theory and Empirics in Pictures,” by
Liran Einav and (our very own) Amy Finkelstein. The examples in their paper are geared
towards the health insurance market, but they apply equally well to any market setting where
adverse selection is present. (These figures recall Chapter 7 of Schelling’s book Micromotives
and Macrobehavior, which we discussed in an earlier lecture.)
• Here’s a useful brief excerpt from their paper: “The link between the demand and cost curve
is arguably the most important distinction of insurance markets (or selection markets more
generally) from traditional product markets. The shape of the cost curve is driven by the
demand-side customer selection. In most other contexts, the demand curve and cost curve
are independent objects; demand is determined by preferences and costs by the production
technology. The distinguishing feature of selection markets is that the demand and cost curves
5
are tightly linked, because the individual’s risk type not only affects demand but also directly
determines cost.”
In this paragraph, the “demand side” of the market refers to consumers who differ in their
expected health costs—i.e., some are sicker than others—and the “cost curve” refers to insurers’
cost of providing health insurance to these consumers. Adverse selection arises because, in
most realistic cases, consumers are better informed about their expected health costs than
are insurers. The insight of the paragraph is that insurers’ costs of providing policies depend
on which consumers buy the policies, which is itself determined by what the policies cost.
Specifically, the insurer’s cost depends on the health of the consumers who choose to purchase
the policy at a given price.
Figures 1, 2a and 2b of Einav-Finkelstein provide a nice graphical depiction of these insights.
Figure 1 corresponds to a case where adverse selection causes an efficiency loss in an insurance
market, but the market does not shut down entirely. Figure 2a corresponds to a case where
adverse selection causes no efficiency loss (though it does transfer consumer surplus from low-
risk consumers to high-risk consumers). Figure 2b depicts a case where adverse selection leads
the insurance market to shut down: no one receives insurance even though all consumers are
risk averse and hence willing to pay more than the actuarially fair cost of an insurance policy.
1.4 Keep in mind: Underneath the hood, we are invoking the Nash equilibrium
We implicitly invoked the Nash equilibrium concept in solving the used car example above. I’d like
to take a few paragraphs to make this concept explicit, so that you can recognize a Nash equilibrium
when you see one.
• We first worked out the strategies of used car sellers, taking as given the price offered by
buyers. We concluded that if the offer price was less than 16, 000, only lemons were sold. If
the offer price was ≥ 16, 000, both lemons and good cars were sold.
• We observed that buyers have two primary strategies available: offering 8, 000 and offering
16, 000.
• We then asked which of these buyer strategies constituted a Nash equilibrium given the strate-
gies of sellers.
• Offering 8, 000 is always a Nash equilibrium. If a buyer offers 8, 000, then sellers will offer only
lemons. Since these cars are worth 8, 000 to the seller and 10, 000 to the buyer, the buyer and
seller are both happy with this outcome and have no desire to change their behavior. These
strategies therefore constitute a Nash equilibrium. Neither party wishes to deviate from their
strategy (e.g., offer more, sell a good car) given the strategy of the other player.
• We next asked whether offering 16, 000 could also be a Nash equilibrium. The answer, as we
saw, depends upon λ, the population share of lemons. At offer price 16, 000, both lemons and
6
good cars are sold (that’s the sellers’ strategy). For this to be a Nash equilibrium, buyers
must be happy to pay a price of 16, 000, given the sellers’ strategies when facing this price.
We calculated that the value to buyers of cars available at offer price 16, 000 is:
For Pu = 16, 000 to be a Nash equilibrium, it must be the case that BU = 1.25×E [SU |PU = 16, 000] ≥
16, 000, which requires that λ ≤ 0.4. So if λ ≤ 0.4, the pooling equilibrium where both cars
are sold is indeed an equilibrium. If λ > 0.4, then the pooling equilibrium cannot hold, and
only lemons are sold.
We can visualize the Nash equilibrium logic of the used car example above by plotting SU (PU ) and
BU (SU (PU )) for different values of λ, as in Figures 1 and 2 below. These figures plot SU (PU ) and
BU (SU (PU )) on the y−axis and PU on the x−axis. Nash equilibria are visible as ranges (highlighted
in dark red) where BU (SU (PU )) lies above the 450 line, implying that BU (SU (PU )) ≥ PU at price
PU .1
To match the following figure—generously donated by 14.03/003 alumnus Sergey Naumov—we
will deflate all values used in this illustration by 10. Thus, good cars and bad cars are worth,
respectively, 2, 000 and 1, 000 to buyers. Good and bad cars are worth, respectively, 1, 600 and 800
to sellers.
In Figure 1, λ = 0.3, and there are two ranges of Nash equilibria: PU ∈ [800, 1000] and PU ∈
[1, 600, 1, 700]. (Why is PU capped at 1, 700 not 1, 800? Because SU (PU ≥ 1, 600) = 0.3 (800) +
0.7 (1, 600) = 1, 360 and 1, 360 × (1/0.8) = 1, 700. So BU (SU (PU (1, 600))) = 1, 700.)
1
Many thanks to Sergey Naumov for these nice figures.
7
Figure 1: Potential Nash Equilibria of Used Car Market with λ = 0.3
In Figure 2, λ = 0.5, and there is only one range of Nash equilibria: PU ∈ [800, 1000]. For PU ≥
1, 600 we have SU (PU >= 1, 600) = 0.5 (800) + 0.5 (1, 600) = 1, 200 and BU (SU (PU >= 1, 600)) =
1, 500, which is less than PU . Thus, there is no Nash equilibrium above PU = 1, 000.
8
Figure 2: Potential Nash Equilibria of Used Car Market with λ = 0.5
• Are there any markets that simply don’t exist because of adverse selection (or moral hazard)?
9
– Lifetime income insurance
– Why is health insurance so expensive for the unemployed?
– Why doesn’t my life insurance policy cover suicide during the first five years after pur-
chase?
– Why can’t I buy insurance against getting a low GPA at MIT?
• Health insurance:
• Auto insurance: You can choose your deductible, but your premium rises nonlinearly as you
chooser lower and lower deductibles. Why?
• What if MIT allowed new Economics professors to choose between two salary packages: low
salary plus guaranteed tenure or high salary but no tenure guarantee. Assume there is no
moral hazard problem (i.e., professors don’t slack-off if tenured). Will this personnel policy
yield a desirable faculty?
Note that this CE calculation came from the equation 0.5 × ln (150) + 0.5 ln (90) = ln(x). Thus,
i = 0.60 is willing to pay a $4 risk premium ($120 − $116) to obtain full insurance.
Generalizing this calculation to any consumer i, we can write that i has the following wealth,
expected utility, certainty equivalent income, etc.:
10
U (E [wi ]) = ln (150 − 0.5 × 100 × i)
We can also calculate consumer i0 s willingness to pay for insurance in excess of its actuarially fair
value:
Assume that each consumer knows his or her type i but that insurers cannot distinguish individual
types.
Notice that the lefthand side of this equation is the expected utility of i0 if uninsured whereas the
righthand side is wealth of i0 if insured (in that case, i0 pays the $25 premium and so faces no risk
of losing Li ).
11
0.5 × ln (150) + 0.5 ln 150 − 100 × i0 = ln (125)
Thus consumers on the interval i0 ∈ [0.46, 1] will buy the policy. Notice that consumers with
i ∈ [0.46, 0.50) would expect to lose money on the policy—since their expected losses are less than
$25 whereas the policy cost is $25. These consumers are buying the insurance despite it being
actuarially unfair for them, because they are risk averse.
However, this policy will lose money on average. Expected costs per insured consumer on this
policy are E [Li |i ≥ 0.46] = 100 × 0.5 × 1+0.46
2 = $36.50. But the proposed plan has the insurer
selling insurance for $25. So this “naive” policy cannot be an equilibrium policy.
The problem that the insurer is facing is adverse selection. At the actuarially fair average price
for the entire market, only the highest risk 46% of consumers are buying the insurance policy. The
remaining 54% are choosing to bear the risk on their own rather than paying a premium that far
exceeds their expected losses.
1 + i00
E Li |i ≥ i00 = 100 × 0.5 × = 25 × 1 + i00 .
2
After a bunch of algebra (or some spreadsheeting), the solution to this problem is i00 = 0.75. Thus,
only one quarter of the population purchases insurance, and the premium for this policy is 43.75 (b/c
0.5 × (100 + 75) /2 = 43.75). This low rate of insurance is again due to adverse selection. Those who
have highest demand for insurance are those with the greatest expected losses. This means that the
premium will typically be much higher than the expected loss in the full population (which is $25).
12
Demand#and#Supply#for#Insurance#
Figure 3: Demand and Supply for Insurance
$70#
$60#
$50# WTP#for#
Insurance#
$40#
Marginal#Cost#
$30#
Preferences(and(endowments( Average#Cost#
$20#
U(W)(=(ln(W)(
W(=(150(
Pr(Li)(=(0.5( $10#
L((~(U[0,(100](
Li(=(100*i,(E[L](=(50(
$0#
100# 90# 80# 70# 60# 50# 40# 30# 20# 10# 0#
Loss#Amount#Condi8onal#on#Loss#(Li#=#100#*#i)#
This high premium deters lower cost consumers from buying insurance, and hence only a subset of
consumers insure, even though all are risk averse and would benefit from actuarially fair insurance.
The high risk types impose a negative externality on the low risk types by driving up the cost of an
insurance policy.
Quoting again from Einav-Finkelstein: “The fundamental inefficiency created by adverse selection
arises because the efficient allocation is determined by the relationship between marginal cost and
demand, but the equilibrium allocation is determined by the relationship between average cost and
demand. Because of adverse selection (downward sloping MC curve), the marginal buyer is always
associated with a lower expected cost than that of infra-marginal buyers.”
Given this inefficiency, why doesn’t the market completely unravel—leading to no one buying
insurance? The answer is risk aversion, as we saw in Problem Set #6. Consumers with highest
likelihood of experiencing a loss are willing to pay a substantial premium in excess of their expected
cost to obtain insurance. These consumers will prefer a policy that it is actuarially unfair for them
(within limits) because they prefer a ’bad deal’ on insurance to no insurance at all.
13
has zero risk). Therefore an efficient market solution involves all consumers obtaining insurance.
Since the marginal cost of insuring each consumer is less than or equal to her willingness to pay for
this insurance, all consumers should be insured. As with the naive policy, the efficient policy has a
premium of $25, but this policy is mandatory.
Notice that not every consumer is better off under the mandatory policy. As we saw with the
naive policy, consumers with i0 < 0.46 would prefer not to buy the $25 policy. So, in what sense
is it efficient to require them to do so? This is tricky. You should think of the mandatory policy
as having two parts: an insurance value and a transfer value. The transfer is from low cost to high
cost consumers. Consumers with i < 0.50 effectively subsidize consumers with i > 0.50. While the
insurance component makes consumers better off, the transfer component makes consumers with
i < 0.50 worse off (and for consumers with i < 0.46, the net effect of the insurance and transfer is
to lower utility relative to a case with no insurance. But remember that this transfer is just that: a
transfer to other consumers. So we view it as a wash. (Notice that in the mandatory insurance case,
each consumer has the same wealth and hence the same marginal utility of wealth in equilibrium.
Transfers at the margin therefore do not effect social welfare; one person’s loss is exactly offset by
another’s gain.)
As is implied by this logic, some simple calculations (perhaps made using a spreadsheet) will
demonstrate that average consumer welfare is higher under the mandatory insurance policy than
either in the no-insurance or the free market insurance case.
14
Expected$U5lity$Under$Three$Insurance$Schemes$
Figure 4: Expected Utility Under Three Insurance Schemes
5.05$
5.00$
4.95$
4.90$
4.85$ EU(No$
insurance)$
4.80$
Expectd$U5lity$
4.75$
EU(Individual$
4.70$ insurance)$
4.65$
EU(Pooled$
4.60$
insurance)$
E[U$i|No$Insure]$=$.5ln(150)$+$.5ln(150$9$100*i)$ 4.55$
E[U$i|Individual$Insure]$=$ln(1509100*i)$ 4.50$
E[U$i|Pooled$Insure]$=$ln(150925)$
4.45$
4.40$
100$ 90$ 80$ 70$ 60$ 50$ 40$ 30$ 20$ 10$ 0$
Loss$Amount$Condi5onal$on$Loss$(Li$=$100$*$i)$
$
the mandatory policy. Why? Again, the mandatory policy does two things: it provides insurance
and it transfers income from rich to poor (that is, from those with low expected losses to those
with high expected losses; we know this because every policyholder i pays the same premium, and
the policy breaks even). The mandatory policy provides both risk pooling and risk spreading. The
break-even policy with testing provides risk pooling but not risk spreading. You can again quickly
demonstrate this result to yourself (perhaps again using a spreadsheet). Average social welfare is
lowest in this example with no insurance, highest with the mandatory $25 policy, and somewhere in
between with the free market policy with testing. (See Figure 4)
4 Summary
When information is private, the usual efficiency results for market outcomes may not hold. This
simple insight is highly relevant to the operation of many markets, health insurance markets being
the leading example. Unobservable quality heterogeneity creates important problems for market
efficiency—market failures or incomplete markets quite likely.
The problem is not the uncertainty per se. As we demonstrated during previous lectures, there
are market mechanisms for trading risk efficiently. But in those models, no agents were privy to
special, private information. The fundamental problem in the adverse selection models above is
that asymmetric information leads to a market equilibrium where sellers use their informational
15
advantage strategically. Buyers respond strategically to sellers’ choices. This means that the pool
of actors on the other side of the market responds (“is endogenous”) to price, and the equilibrium of
these strategic games are not likely to be first-best efficient.
• Consider the market for ‘fine’ art. Imagine that sellers value paintings at between $0 and
$100, 000, denoted as Vs , and these values are uniformly distributed, so the average painting
is worth $50, 000 to a seller.
• Assume that buyers value paintings at 50% above the seller’s price. Denote this valuation as
Vb . If a painting has Vs = $1, 000 then Vb = $1, 500.
• The only way to know the value of a painting is to buy it and have it appraised. Buyers cannot
tell masterpieces from junk. Sellers can.
• An equilibrium price must satisfy the condition that the goods that sellers are willing to sell
at this price are worth that price to buyers: Vb |E [Vs (P )] ≥ P.
• There is a range of sellers, each of whom will put their painting on the market if P ≥ Vs .
• What is the expected seller’s value of paintings for sale as a function of P ? Given that paintings
are distributed uniformly, it is:
0+P
E [Vs |P ] = .
2
So, if P = 100, 000 then all paintings are available for sale and their expected value to sellers
is $50, 000. If P = 50, 000, the expected seller value of paintings for sale is $25, 000.
• Now take the buyer’s side. Since the Vb = 1.5 · Vs , buyers’ willingness to pay for paintings as
a function of their price is
0+P 3
E [Vb |E [Vs |P ]] = 1.5 · E [Vs |P ] = 1.5 = P.
2 4
• Since that buyers’ valuation of paintings lies strictly above sellers’ valuations, this outcome is
economically inefficient—that is, the gains from trade are unrealized. What’s wrong?
16
• The sellers of low-quality goods generate a negative externality for sellers of high quality goods,
since they are pooled together from the buyer’s perspective. For every $1.00 the price rises,
seller
value onlyincreases by $0.50 because additional low-quality sellers crowd into the market
∂E[Vs |Ps ]
∂P = 0.5 .
• Consequently,
dollar that the price rises, buyers’ valuations only increases by $0.75,
for every
∂E[Vb |E[Vs |P ]]
∂P = 0.75 . There is no equilibrium point where the market price ‘calls forth’ a
set of products that buyers are willing to buy at that price.
• In the example above, sellers of good products do not disclose their art’s quality because we
have stipulated that the value of a piece of art can only be assessed ex-post (by experience or
appraisal). Sellers of good paintings therefore have no credible means to convey their products’
quality.
• Your first instinct might be that, since buyers are willing to pay $75, 000 for a painting of
average quality, any seller with a painting that would sell for at least $75, 000 if appraised—that
is, an above-average painting—would choose to get an appraisal.
• This intuition is on the right track but incomplete. It neglects the fact that the decision by some
sellers to have their paintings appraised affects buyers’ willingness to pay for non-appraised
paintings.
17
• If only sellers with above average paintings had their paintings appraised, what would be the
market price of non-appraised paintings?
• But if the market price is only $37, 500, then sellers with paintings at or above this price will
also get them appraised. What is the new market price of non-appraised paintings?
• And so on...
• You can keep working through this example until you eventually conclude that all sellers will
wish to have their paintings appraised. Why? Because each successive seller who has his
painting appraised devalues the paintings of those who do not. This in turn causes additional
sellers to wish to have their paintings appraised. In the limit, the only seller who doesn’t have
an incentive to obtain an appraisal is the seller with Vs = 0. This seller is indifferent.
• This example demonstrates the Full-Disclosure Principle. Roughly stated: If there is a credible
means for an individual to disclose that he is above the average of a group, she will do so. This
disclosure will implicitly reveal that other non-disclosers are below the average, which will give
them the incentive to disclose, and so on... If disclosure is costless, in equilibrium all parties
will explicitly or implicitly disclose their private information. If there is a cost to disclosure,
there will typically be a subset of sellers who do not find it worthwhile to disclose.
• The Full Disclosure Principle is the inverse of the Lemons Principle. In the Lemons case,
the bad products drive down the price of the good ones. In the Full Disclosure case, the
good products drive down the price of the bad ones. What distinguishes these cases is simply
whether or not there is a credible disclosure mechanism (and what the costs of disclosure are).
1. The net price of a painting that the seller would obtain if the painting were appraised
(net of the appraisal fee) (A = 1)
2. The net price if not appraised (A = 0)
3. The value of the painting to the seller (remember that sellers won’t sell for a net price
less than Vs ).
18
• The following conditions must be satisfied in equilibrium:
1. Buyer’s willingness to pay for an appraised painting is greater than or equal to seller’s
value of painting:
Vb (A = 1) ≥ Vs + 5000
and
Vb (Vs < Vs∗ , A = 1) − 5, 000 ≤ Vb (Vs < Vs∗ , A = 0) .
1. IR condition:
Vb (A = 1) ≥ Vs + 5000
1.5Vs ≥ Vs + 5000
VsIR∗ ≥ 10, 000
This condition says that sellers who value their painting at less than 10,000 will choose not to
get them appraised. This is because the market price less the appraisal cost is less than their
private value of the painting.
2. SS condition
This condition simply says that an individual seller must not be able to do better by switching
their painting from appraised to non-appraised status or vice versa given the market equilib-
rium. Remember that the market value of a non-appraised painting is equal to 1.5 times their
expected value to sellers. So, the self-selection constraint is:
V SS ∗
Vb Vs ≥ VsSS ∗ , A = 1 − 5, 000 ≥ 1.5 × s
2
SS ∗
1.5 × Vs − 5, 000 ≥ 0.75 × VsSS ∗
0.75 × VsSS ∗ ≥ 5, 000
VsSS ∗ ≥ 6, 666
and of course, the second inequality is also exactly satisfied at VsSS ∗ = 6, 666.
19
• Combining these results, we have
Thus, the operative constraint is not that the market price for an non-appraised painting is
higher than the market price for an appraised painting (which is SS) but that the seller’s own
valuation of an appraised painting net of appraisal cost must be greater than the market price
of that painting when appraised (which is IR). Stated differently, when the IR constraint is
satisfied, the SS constraint is also satisfied. But satisfaction of the SS constraint is necessary
but not sufficient for satisfaction of the IR constraint. Hence, Vs∗ = VsIR∗ = 10, 000 is the
threshold at which paintings are appraised.
20
MIT OpenCourseWare
https://ocw.mit.edu
For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: https://ocw.mit.edu/terms.