John Rawls
John Rawls
D. J. BENTLEYt
I
It may be helpful to those who are not familiar with Rawls to
plot his position against a better-known moral theory, namely utilitari-
anism. At any rate, on this side of the Atlantic, where no modern
charter contains the compact under which we consent to be governed,
the defence of truth and justice has most often in the last hundred
years appeared to be in the hands of the utilitarians. This raises two
immediate questions: first, is justice a "special department" of moral-
ity? And second, do we by this mean to commit ourselves further to
the position that the province of justice is not (whatever be the case
for the rest of morality) governed by the principles of utility? After
looking at these questions, we can go on to assess the particular solution
proposed by Rawls.
It is perfectly possible to be, broadly, an utilitarian and yet to
give the principles of justice a special status. For instance, in The Con-
cept of Law, Professor Hart carefully distinguishes "fairness" (which
roughly covers justice) from morality in general.' And Hart, I suppose,
is a modern utilitarian. Why should the two ever have been confused?
The explanation can be found by looking at Mill's chapter on the con-
nection between justice and utility.2 Mill rightly saw the idea of justice
as an obstacle to the simple test of utility in assessing right and wrong.
People, that is, went on referring to this rather old fashioned notion,
and seemed remarkably attached to it, despite being urged to look to
expediency instead. But to Mill, this notion of justice had to be either
irrational or the reflection of the operation of a perhaps concealed
principle of utility.
I Tutor and Lecturer in Jurisprudence, Christ Church, Oxford. B.C.L. 1957, MA.
1960, Oxford University.
I H.LA. HART, Tim CoNcEPT or LAw 153-55 (1961).
2 J.S. MiLL, U=TmaNixTr, LiBExR, w REPRESENTATIVE GovmanmNT 51-80
(1951).
RAWLS' THEORY OF JUSTICE
To arrive at this position Mill took one sure and one false step.
As he rightly says, "[t] hat a feeling is bestowed on us by Nature, does
not necessarily legitimate all its promptings. '8 To feel that something
is just or unjust cannot be the test of its justice or injustice unless, as
Mill says, one believes that justice is some special quality ("intrinsically
peculiar") which can only be perceived by what amounts to a "special
revelation." This is a pretty familiar sort of argument of course. But
then Mill offers a false choice for us: either the feelings of justice are
sui generis perceptions like taste or smell, so that debates about justice
are to be resolved by asking "does it feel just?," as one might ask
whether a cup of tea has enough sugar, or justice is only a combination
of certain other qualities of a thing "presented under a peculiar aspect."
Mill goes for the latter, and his treatment of justice appears at times
more akin to social psychology than moral philosophy, for he regards
the powerful sentiments evoked in this area as what are really in need
of explanation. The resulting index of justice is simple: utility.
In fact, the choice Mill puts before us-utility or the special
quality-is, at least as he presents it, too restricted. There is a middle
way, which a theory like Rawls' exemplifies, though no doubt other
non-utilitarian but rational theories of ethics can be devised. This view
accepts readily that justice is "a thing intrinsically peculiar, and distinct
from all . . . other qualities"4 but denies that it is to be discovered
by the "peculiar revelation" which Mill rightly distrusts. Briefly, this
sort of theory would assert (a) that justice is a special department of
morality; and (b) that what makes it special is not simply the ground
it covers (by which I mean fair procedure, etc.) but also the kinds of
arguments that are deployed over that territory. It is one of the more
entertaining consequences of this divergence of approaches that when
Mill considers the thoroughly Rawlsian maxim "so act that thy rule of
conduct might be adopted as a law by all rational beings," he turns
Kant into a utilitarian:8 but what else could Mill have done?
It is now time to look a little more closely at the way Rawls treats
justice; after that, I shall take up some points which, I am sure, are
both important and yet by no means obvious.
II
Rawls sets out his main thesis at an early stage; much of the
rest of the book is concerned with refining the early broad statement
3Id. 51.
4 Id. 52.
GId. 64-65.
1072 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 121:1070
III
I want now to look a little more closely at certain aspects of this
theory. First, I should like to go back to the question of what makes
this conception a moral one: why are we entitled to say that what men
would choose is what they are right to choose? Briefly, the answer is
that it is not what they choose, but the way they choose, that insures
the morality of their choice. The terms of the contract are settled by
men in a situation in which they know very little about themselves
10Id. 8-9.
1074 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 121:1070
are or rate them highly enough. My reason for making this suggestion
is that Mill has also set out a list of situations in which the precepts
of justice apply, and identified their common factor in the notion of
a right, or rather, rights. For Mill, to act morally one must act accord-
ing to a universalisable principle, so that there would be no way of
subverting the rights of any individual that would not also justify the
invasion of the rights of the other members of society. And Mill is
clear that the disutility of this state of affairs would be overwhelming.
(Which comes very close to the position of one who relies on an appeal
to "the very notion of a right.")
In short, where Rawls relies on a hypothetical contract, Mill
says simply that the world would be a much nastier place to live in,
but for the principles of justice.' 2 At least this seems a possible way
for the utilitarian to argue, even if I have read too much into Mill.
I now wish to turn to some matters which I find very difficult, but
which are, I am sure, essential ingredients in any critical account of
Rawls' theory. They are connected to the notion of the "original
position," and are similar to the sort of criticism of Rawls that points
to the unreality of the choices made by wholly ignorant contracting
parties. But I am not so concerned with the difficulty of knowing what
such people-and hence such choices-would be like. My problem
arises from the distinction that Rawls draws between strict and partial
compliance theory, which I have already mentioned. Rawls deals for
the most part with a perfectly just society in which "[e]veryone is
presumed to act justly and to do his part in upholding just institu-
tions."' 3 Partial compliance theory, on the other hand, treats injustice.
"It comprises such topics as the theory of punishment, the doctrine
of just war, . . . the justification of the various ways of opposing un-
just regimes" as well as "questions of compensatory justice."' 4 Only
by considering the just society, however, does Rawls think we can
hope to find the answers to the problems of our own imperfect societies.
I confess that I find this hard to accept confidently. For one thing, it
is not clear how this perfectly just society would work in practice.
This is not as silly an objection, I hope, as it may at first sound. It is
one thing to criticise existing institutions in light of standards external
to those of the society in which the institutions are to be found 3 5
12 See Mill's account of the "useful accommodation of language" by which "the
character of indefeasibility attributed to justice is kept up, and we are saved from the
necessity of maintaining that there can be laudable injustice." Id. 79.
13 J. RAwLs, supra note 6, at S.
14Id.
15
H art does this when making out a case against Devlin. See H.L.A. HART, LAW,
Lma'v" Aam Moam= (1963).
1076 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 121:1070
How does this fit the statement that I have just quoted of the basic
structure of society? Of course, if legal systems have no gaps, then
in some sense all our activities can be placed under some rule of the
system; liberty is no longer the silence of the laws. But any serious
account of the basic structure of a society would presumably take that
for granted and would be concerned with the actual norms, whether
legal or not, according to which activity is in practice directed, and
additionally, where the norms are legal, with the function of the norms
as distinct from their content (as, for instance, Karl Renner uses the
notion of the functional transformation of norms). 8 What makes laws
basic in the usual case is simply that they do as a matter of fact lie
at the root of certain societies. 9 But the law comes a bad second in
comparison to other factors that necessarily determine this quality of
institutions, though there is a whole possible area of study which could
trace in given cases just how bad.
A last instance of what I find to be an insecure foundation, some-
where between heaven and earth, can be found in the chapter on
Distributive Shares,2" in which Rawls attempts to set out an arrange-
ment of institutions-neutral as between private property systems and
socialism-that will fulfill the requirements of his theory of justice.
There is no doubt that this must be taken as being a very important
and explicit statement of Rawls' views. But what status does Rawls
intend his precepts for the institutions of the just society to enjoy?
Are they supposed to work? This is not at all straightforward. One is
surely in the realm of partial compliance theory here, yet Rawls is
defining standards rather than predicting contractual arrangements,
and this apparently on the basis of the original position, that is, strict
compliance theory. Nor am I clear as to the usefulness in practice of
the Archimedean viewpoint"- from which society is to be measured
against Rawlsian justice. On the one hand, one is estopped, as it were,
from arguing that the fundamental arrangements of society simply
will not do, since the theory is neutral at this point. But one is still
expected to be able to show (remind?) erring members of society
that their desires and aspirations are incompatible with justice. There-
fore I repeat: anyone who is going to hitch his wagon to Rawls will
I8K. RENNim, THE INSTITUTIONS Or PRIVATE LAW AND THEm SociAL FUNCTIONs
81-95, 205, 251-60 (1949).
19Rawls' comparison with the rules of a game is a giveaway in this regard. See
J. RAwLs, supra note 6, at 235-43. To talk of what is basic, unless it is treated in an
ad hoc way, can be misleading.
20 Id. 258-332.
21Id. 261.
1078 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW
have to think very hard about the way the concepts he is using are
related to each other and the world. 2
IV
One last point may be made before I try to sum up my comments.
This is a grand theory, and perhaps it tries to do a little too much at
times. It is true that Mill puts all questions of justice under the rule
of utility, and that this may lead to an unsatisfactory or less than
entirely clear account of the problem. But I feel that some of the
questions traditionally considered by theorists of justice fit even less
readily into a scheme based on an original contract. As an example,
I wonder whether it is only the fact that they belong to "partial
compliance theory" that makes such notions as mens rea appear to
fit awkwardly into Rawls' theory. Similarly, Rawls says that "[i]t
would be an intolerable burden on liberty if the liability to penalties
was not normally limited to actions within our power to do or not
to do." 23 But the objection to punishing an unfree man cannot be
that the criminal law thereby operates as a limitation on his freedom
of choice, at least if that is why Rawls here invokes the notion of
liberty, since the man was, by hypothesis, not free to choose. The real
offense to our notions of responsibility and desert is rather that the
connection between the legal and the moral wrong is broken.
CONCLUSION
As I said in my opening remarks, this piece does not aim very
high. In it I have attempted two things: to sketch the way in which
Rawls diverges from the utilitarians, and to record some of the diffi-
culties that I have experienced while following his argument. Briefly,
these latter can be placed under two heads: the problem, stemming
from the notion of the "original position," of relating strict compliance
theory to the real world, and the problem of whether it is desirable to
refer all questions of justice directly or mediately to a single grand
theory. Of one thing I am convinced: Rawls will be ill-served by any
follower who falls to realise that the argument of this book, though
of great power, is neither simple nor self-evident.
22 Cf. the account of the various "branches of government," which is reminiscent of
the eulogies of the working of the separation of powers. Id. 277-84.
23 Id. 237.