Expression Unleashed 070921 For Psyarxiv
Expression Unleashed 070921 For Psyarxiv
page 1 of 51
Abstract
Human expression is open-ended, versatile and diverse, ranging from ordinary language use
tion. Here we present and defend the claim that this expressive diversity is united by an in-
terrelated suite of cognitive capacities, the evolved functions of which are the expression and
munication to narrow domains of statistical mutual benefit, and how they are unleashed in
humans. The relevant cognitive capacities are adaptations to living in a partner choice social
ecology; and they are, correspondingly, part of the ordinarily developing human cognitive
phenotype, emerging early and reliably in ontogeny. In other words, we identify distinctive
features of humans’ social ecology to explain how and why humans evolved the capacities
that, in turn, lead to massive diversity and open-endedness in means and modes of expres-
sion. We make cross-species comparisons, describe how the relevant capacities can evolve in
a gradual manner, and survey how unleashed expression facilitates not only language use but
novel behaviour in many other domains too, focusing on the examples of joint action, teach-
ing, punishment and art, all of which are ubiquitous in human societies but relatively rare in
other species. We aim to help reorient cognitive pragmatics, as a phenomenon that is not a
rather the foundation of the many of the most distinctive features of human behaviour, soci-
chology
page 2 of 51
1. Introduction
Why is human expression so rich and multifaceted? Living things communicate in a great
variety of ways, from the quorum sensing of bacteria, to songbirds, to the gestural and vocal
communication of primates, but humans are expressive in ways and to an extent that is
clearly distinctive. There is language use of course, but also points, nods, winks and other
behaviours that although not linguistic are still conventionalised; and also many ad hoc, im-
provised behaviours, such as a small hand gesture used to visually park a topic of ongoing
conversation, subtle body movements that connect dance partners, and the open-ended ex-
pressiveness of music, painting and other art forms (Green, 2007). It is likely that humans
are not naturally sensitive to many forms of interaction in non-humans, and as such there is
much still to discover from a comparative perspective; but at the same time, non-human ex-
pression is, on all available evidence, limited to finite domains. Bees, for instance, communi-
cate about the location of flowers and the quantity of their nectar but, apparently, little or
nothing else. The gestural communication of non-human great apes is more diverse and flex-
ible than most other cases (Cartmill & Byrne, 2010; Fröhlich & Hobaiter, 2018; Graham et
al., 2018), but its scope is still clearly limited relative to humans.
phasise the combinatorial and generative quality of natural language: the fact that individual
constituent parts can be recombined in many ways, making infinite use of finite means. An
emphasis on combinations and codes is, moreover, sometimes linked with particular as-
sumptions about evolution: that as complex systems of words, rules and combinations, nat-
ural languages are enrichments of the communication systems of other species (e.g. Progov-
ac, 2015; Sterelny, 2017; Leroux & Townsend, 2020). This picture is attractive because it de-
scribes human and non-human communication systems in terms that appear continuous.
However, as a broad explanation of human expression, this focus on the evolution of com-
binatorics faces a number of fundamental problems, of which we here highlight two. First, it
says very little about quasi- and non-linguistic means of communication and expression.
Second, the evolutionary story of complex combinations evolving from more simple ones
does not address the “central problem” (Maynard Smith & Harper, 2003, p.v) for the evolu-
page 3 of 51
tion of communication, viz. stability in the face of incentives to deceive. This is not an incid-
ental critique. On the contrary, the problem of evolutionary stability is, we shall shortly ar-
gue, fundamental, for it holds expression on a leash, keeping it constrained to narrow do-
and explaining expressive versatility are deeply interlinked problems. One cannot be re-
and open-ended richness of human expression, based not on combinatorics but cognitive
pragmatics. That is, we describe the evolution of distinctly human means of communica-
mechanisms of social cognition targeted at navigating distinctive features of the human so-
cial ecology; and we specify how these cognitive mechanisms in turn unleash expression.
More specifically, we argue that expression can be unleashed in partner choice social ecolo-
spontaneous prior assumptions that communicators are cooperative, and (ii) for expressive
behaviour to exploit this assumption. Natural languages, in all their combinatorial richness,
are a means by which we exploit unleashed expression, rather than being the source of un-
leashed expression. If we are right about this, then our account provides an overtly adapta-
tionist answer to the ‘Why humans?’ question about language origins, that is clearly different
tion is evolutionarily grounded in cooperative social ecologies, and that key cognitive pro-
of social cognition shared with other primate species (e.g. Sperber, 2000; Hurford, 2007;
Tomasello, 2008; Fitch et al., 2010; Frith & Frith, 2010; Arbib, 2012; Sterelny, 2012; Levin-
son & Holler, 2014; Scott-Phillips, 2015; Moore, 2017; Seyfarth & Cheney, 2018; Hrdy &
Burkart, 2020; Johansson, 2021). Going beyond this point of agreement, we provide an es-
pecially focused description of the relevant cognitive capacities, grounded in a precise theory
of cognitive pragmatics. In other words, we describe the computational tasks the interaction-
page 4 of 51
al engine must perform. We also describe how these cognitive capacities are employed for
use in a wide range of domains, extending far beyond how communication is ordinarily con-
strued. In doing this we do not make recourse to notions such as second-person or ‘we’ in-
tentionality, which are, in our view, not descriptions of cognitive processes, but phenomena
problem of leashed expression in the next section, and we explain how it is resolved (§5)
after we have provided a taxonomy of ways in which individuals can affect the minds of oth-
ers (§3), and make adaptive inferences based on others’ behaviour (§4).
Figure 1: Structure of the article. We first elaborate on how the key problem of
evolutionary stability leashes expression (§2). We then describe a series of suc-
cessively embedded, graded subsets of the different ways in which individuals
might affect the minds of others (§3), and make adaptive inferences based on the
behaviour of others (§4). We bring these two sides together by describing how the
innermost subsets on each side of the equation combine to unleash expression
(§5). Three further sections elaborate and enrich this point in different ways. We
identify the social ecology in which the relevant cognitive mechanisms are mutu-
ally supportive and can hence gradually co-evolve (§6); we make relevant com-
parisons with other species, chimpanzees in particular (§7); and we describe how
the framework presented here unifies and provides new insights on otherwise di-
verse and disparate means of human expression (§8). As the figure suggests, the
arguments made in these later sections are mutually supportive but largely inde-
pendent of one another. To conclude, we summarise how this evolutionary and
cognitive perspective redefines the domain and goals of pragmatics as a scientific
discipline (§9).
page 5 of 51
2. Expression leashed
We use ‘expression’ to describe any trait or behaviour whose function is to inform others.
This characterisation is solely functional in nature, and not mechanistic. In this way, it is
sufficiently broad to be inclusive of whatever means this function might be achieved, includ-
ing, for instance, emotional expression; but also sufficiently narrow so as not to include any
and all cases of information flow, regardless of function. In this section we describe how ex-
pression in this functional sense is leashed rather than freely open-ended. In later sections
we focus on one specific manifestation of expression, namely behaviours that result from in-
formative intentions.1
Crucially, an organism’s expressive range is limited by the fact that only a specific and
finite range of stimuli will actually generate a psychological reaction in other organisms. Af-
ter all, organisms attend only to a limited subset of other organisms’ behaviour, and will take
from this only a limited range of information. This makes the expression of, for instance, fu-
ture events, or the location of far away food sources, effectively impossible without mecha-
would not—and could not—express the location of pollen if other bees had no mechanisms
specifically dedicated to exactly that, i.e. interpreting dances as indicators of the location of
pollen.
the production of stimuli the function of which is to generate a psychological reaction, com-
munication involves the production of stimuli the function of which is to generate a reaction
Phillips et al., 2012). By ‘complementary’, we mean that each mechanism can perform its
function only in conditions when the other mechanism is in place. Bee dance, for instance, is
1 From the perspective of evolutionary theory we are defining ‘expression’ at the ultimate/functional
level of analysis, with the goal to focus, in later sections, on its proximate manifestation in humans,
and potentially other species (for elaboration of the ultimate-proximate distinction see Scott-Phillips
et al., 2011).
page 6 of 51
their function (to learn about pollen) if bee dance actually takes place. In contrast, frighten-
ing behaviour can be expressive but not communicative: it can generate a reaction, but not
with different functions. Expression thus involves producing either communicative or non-
producing specifically communicative stimuli for the same function. As such, the evolution-
is not the same as unleashing expression: see below.) This distinction between expression
and communication is useful and important because it frames the important questions in the
right way. First, it raises the question of whether or not an expressive function is met com-
Second, it raises the questions of how and why expressive and interpretative capacities might
co-evolve.
usually unleash expression, because communication systems are tied to domains of statistic-
al mutual benefit (Maynard Smith & Harper, 2003; Searcy & Nowicki, 2005; inter alia). This
tion means that for communication to be evolutionarily stable, it must be beneficial, on aver-
age, to both communicator and audience. This does not imply that communication is always
of mutual benefit, or that deception never occurs. However, it does imply that communica-
tion must be sufficiently beneficial, sufficiently often, for both parties, otherwise it would col-
lapse, because on one side or the other there would be selection against the interaction. Ex-
plaining why this does not happen is the central theoretical issue in animal signalling theory
(ibid.).
page 7 of 51
In some cases this mutual benefit derives from genetic relatedness, such as with ant
pheromones or bee dance. In other cases it derives from direct fitness effects on communica-
tor and audience. For instance, the pattern on the wings of many poisonous butterfly species
the butterfly and the potential predator. The function of the pattern is to inform the potential
predator, and the function of the predator’s reaction is to avoid feeding on such butterflies.
Clearly deception can occur: other species of butterfly can be and have been selected to mim-
ic the focal species, even if they (the other species) are not themselves poisonous. Missing
out on the possibility of preying on the mimic species is an opportunity cost for the predator,
but this is outweighed by the benefits of avoiding poisonous butterflies. If this were not so—
if, in other words, the same pattern is used by so many actually palatable organisms that the
predator’s opportunity costs outweigh the risks of eating unpalatable prey—then the com-
munication system would collapse. The predator will, under these circumstances, not evolve
any mechanism for attending to the signal in the first place; or, if they already have such a
mechanism, it will be selected against (Scott-Phillips et al., 2012). These and other dynamics,
such as those associated with the differential costs of signalling (see e.g. Lachmann et al.,
is certainly not restricted to any particular topic: humans can communicate about potentially
anything. Moreover, we commonly and ordinarily take people at their word, even for state-
ments that can have immediate and serious fitness consequences, such as, for instance, a
about phenomena for which no directly observable evidence could ever be provided, such as
statements about past or future events. Given this vast expressive range, audiences should be
massively vulnerable to misinformation and deception; and what should follow, on ordinary
evolutionary logic, is the collapse of the communication system itself (see above). Yet this
does not happen. Explaining why this is so is, we believe, not only necessary for explaining
the evolution and the expressive richness of human communication, but fundamental.
page 8 of 51
Let us summarise. Expression can be enriched when supplemented with complemen-
tary mechanisms for interpretation, generating a communication system. This does not how-
ever unleash expression: this does not make expression open-ended. On the contrary, stan-
dard evolutionary considerations tell us that communication systems are still expressively
limited because they are only evolutionarily stable when there is little gain (in the aggregate)
not seem to be restricted in the same way. How is this paradox resolved? Why would it be
adaptive for humans to have the sort of interpretative mechanisms they do, given the central
evolutionary problem of stability? The assertion that human expressivity is enabled by com-
binatoriality offers no answer to this problem. We will provide an answer (§§3-7) by relating
ically function to allow humans to make the most informative use of social interaction. These
mechanisms are, we shall argue, both a consequence and a cause of a partner choice social
ecology.
The study of cognitive mechanisms for human expression is traditionally the domain
of cognitive pragmatics: the study of the capacity of mind that facilitates human communic-
ative competence. The relevant literature has its most important origins in the work of philo-
sopher Paul Grice (1957; 1975; 1989). Grice was particularly concerned with meaning, and
his key originality was to approach it as a primarily psychological phenomenon, and a lin-
guistic phenomenon only derivatively. In particular he developed the idea that intentions
might play a key role in determining meaning itself. This work provides the foundations on
which a cognitive theory of communication and expression can be built, and since Grice an
extensive literature has developed this approach in various ways, including from evolution-
ary and developmental perspectives (e.g. Bach & Harnish, 1979; Sperber & Wilson,
1986/1995; Clark, 1996; Levinson, 2000; Tomasello, 2008; Csibra & Gergely, 2009; Wilson
& Sperber, 2012; Scott-Phillips, 2015; Moore, 2017; inter alia). Specific approaches differ
from one another in some of the detail, but all agree that the expression, recognition and epi-
stemic evaluation of intentions together play a foundational role. In what follows we adopt
and enrich the post-Gricean approach commonly known as Relevance Theory (Sperber &
page 9 of 51
Wilson, 1986/1995; Carston, 2002; Wilson & Sperber, 2012; Clark, 2013; Padilla Cruz, 2016;
see also the Relevance Theory Online Bibliographic Service), but our analysis could poten-
tially be adapted to fit with more classically Gricean or neo-Gricean approaches (for focused
arms race between means of affecting the minds and behaviours of other organisms—la-
(1978; 1984; see also Guildford & Dawkins, 1991). Manipulation is a broad term, to include,
for instance, the handling of objects in a goal directed way. Krebs and Dawkins’ insight was
achieved in humans. In the next section we do the same for the audience side.
are many and varied. They might be, for instance, physiological, as in the case of, say, butter-
fly wing patterns; or chemical, as in the case of, say, quorum sensing (Diggle et al., 2007).
Our focus is on cognitive means, and more specifically the expression and recognition of in-
on each with examples (Figure 2). Each of the following subsections begins with a concise
2 Despite the pejorative tone of ‘manipulation’ in everyday language, here it is used just to describe
actions on others, regardless of whether those actions are pro- or anti-social.
page 10 of 51
Figure 2: Embedded subsets of manipulative intention. Aligning with our func-
tional characterisation of expression (§2), here we differentiate expression as ac-
tion based on informative intention, from ostensive communication, which is ac-
tion based on communicative intentions. This implies that, for instance, conspic-
uous consumption can express wealth, but does not communicate it.
The broadest set are behaviours that are intentional and manipulative. For instance, experi-
mental studies show how orangutan mothers will, if necessary, use their offspring as physical
tools (Völter et al., 2015). Because of their small size, infants can reach food in locations that
mothers cannot reach, so mothers can (and do) use them to reach the food, with the mother
In the second set are behaviours that are intended to inform others, and which can do so
without overtly bringing attention to the informative intention itself. For instance, an indi-
vidual might dress in a smart and conservative way, as a means to suggest to others compet-
ence and professionalism, yet without bringing excessive attention to oneself. Conspicuous
consumption is intended to provide evidence of wealth and other markers of status, but
without necessarily advertising this intent in a formally overt way. In the presence of others
we might adopt a bodily posture that suggests, say, social ease and competence, and while
page 11 of 51
this can be done in an overt or otherwise exaggerated way, it need not be. More generally,
sciously or otherwise, to generate and maintain a positive image in the eyes of others, but
without overtly bringing attention to this informative intent—is a common feature of human
social life.3
Such behaviour can generate a degree of shared knowledge about the actor’s informa-
tive intent. In other words, it may be salient that the actor has and is acting on an informa-
tive intention. That said, this need not necessarily be the case. In fact in some cases the actor
might have informative intentions but also have strategic motives to actively keep those in-
tentions hidden or at least deniable (called ‘hidden authorship’; see e.g. Grosse et al., 2013).
A criminal who plants misleading cues in a crime scene has an informative intention and is
acting on it, but simultaneously hiding that intention. A dinner guest who wishes to have
more wine but, recognizing it would be impolite to ask, might wait until her hosts’ attention
is elsewhere and then move her empty glass to a conspicuous location where it will, in due
course, be noticed. Many public acts of generosity fall within this category also: generous in-
dividuals want to be seen as generous, so they gain a positive social reputation, but often
they do not want their acts of generosity to be seen as simply attempts to gain a positive so-
cial reputation, because that would immediately undermine their purpose (Frank, 1988;
Berman et al., 2015; Hoffman et al., 2015; Karabegovic & Heintz, under review; see also §8.3
on punishment).
In all these cases, agents satisfy their informative intentions simply by means of
providing non-communicative, or ‘direct’, evidence for what they want to convey.4 If, for in-
3 A further example is ‘phatic communication’: pleasantries and other means of communication that
serve plainly social functions, and which mainly consist of expressing a willingness to engage and to
observe local conventions of politeness. Phatic communication often uses languages and other means
of communication from within §3.3, even though the informative intentions that are expressed in
phatic communication bear mostly on the willingness to engage, in and of itself, rather than on what is
linguistically expressed.
4 Precisely, we say that X is non-communicative evidence for Y if and only if X (might) generate, in the
audience, the inference that Y without the observer necessarily computing that the informer has the
informative intention that Y. Note also that this notion of non-communicative evidence is similar to
Grice’s ‘natural meaning’ (1957). Interestingly, many languages have grammatical evidential markers
for information acquired in this non-communicative (‘direct’) way.
page 12 of 51
stance, Amy puts three apples on the table with the intention of informing Barry that there
are three apples, she is providing non-communicative evidence for the presence of the three
apples. She can, moreover, do this without any indication that she actually has an informat-
ive intention: she can just place the apples on the table, without drawing any particular at-
tention to the fact that she is doing this. Looking comparatively, we take it as plausible that
non-human primates, and possibly some other species, have informative intentions, and sat-
isfy them by providing non-communicative evidence (see e.g. Genty & Zuberbühler, 2014 for
a plausible example; Zuberbühler, 2018 for a review; and Bar-On, 2013 for discussion). The
key comparative questions are, in our view, whether any non-human species act in the ways
described in the next subsection, in which we consider cases where the communicator
provides evidence for the informative intention itself Such cases are sometimes called
overtly intentional (because they involve making intentions overt) or, more simply, ostens-
ive.5
In this third set are behaviours performed not only with an intention to inform an audience,
as above, but, more than this, to make the actor’s informative intention mutually known.
To see the difference between this set and the one above, consider two possible ways
in which Mary might satisfy her intent that Peter be informed that some berries are edible
(see also Sperber, 2000; Wharton, 2006; Scott-Phillips, 2015). One way Mary might do this
is to simply eat the berries in Peter’s company (without Mary bringing any particular atten-
tion to the fact that she is doing this). In this case Mary has an informative intention which
she acts on by providing some evidence that the berries are edible, but without giving any
5 Regarding ‘ostension’, the word is used in slightly more broad or more narrow ways in different lit-
eratures. Within pragmatics the word was first used narrowly, for the actions described in §3.3 i.e.
making an informative intention manifest (Sperber & Wilson, 1986/1995). Since then sizable literat-
ures have developed studying ostension from many perspectives including development, evolution
and comparative cognition, and here the term is sometimes used more broadly, corresponding
roughly to the actions described in §3.2 (see e.g. Gómez, 1996; Tomasello, 2008; Csibra, 2010; Moore,
2017; Sperber, 2019).
page 13 of 51
overt evidence that she is acting on an informative intention. As such she relies on Peter
simply attending to her behaviour and drawing the inference that the berries are edible. In
this case, Mary’s behaviour belongs in the second embedded subset (§3.2). There is however
an alternative. Mary might not eat the berries at all, but instead mime eating them, perhaps
with exaggerated movements and while tapping her tummy. Here she has the same informa-
tive intention, but provides evidence only about the intention itself. She does not eat the
berries, after all. She provides only communicative evidence of their edibility.
The most salient and important special case of overtly intentional behaviour is, of
course, the use of conventional symbols, especially, but not only, in the context of language
use (§8.5). Grice’s work on meaning was focused on these cases, and his crucial insight was
that the sort of actions we are describing in this section—providing evidence about informat-
ive intentions—is what generates meaning. As he put it, “‘A meant something by x’ is
by means of the recognition of this intention’” (1957, p.385, italics added; the intention re-
That said, overtly intentional behaviour is also viable in cases where no conventions
are used to communicate. After all, almost any behaviour that humans can perform, they can
perform in an overtly intentional way. Sometimes we eat food, and sometimes we eat food in
an overt, exaggerated or otherwise ostensive way, to express to others that the food is tasty,
revolting, generous, or fancy. Sometimes we blink, and sometimes we blink with microscopic
exaggeration, such as with a slight delay in re-opening the eyes, to express, say, ironic sur-
prise. Such deviations from otherwise non-communicative behaviour have been experimen-
tally isolated in a number of studies, in both production and comprehension (e.g. Newman-
Norland et al., 2009; Scott-Phillips et al., 2009; McEllin et al., 2018a; Royka et al., 2018).
Again, like language use, such behaviour is Gricean. It provides evidence about informative
intentions.
We have so far presented the distinction between the three subsets in this section as
categorical, but they are in fact graded and continuous. That is, different means of manipula-
tion can, we suggest, vary in the extent to which the actor makes her informative intention
page 14 of 51
manifest. Grice’s characterisation of meaning, quoted above, describes one end of this con-
tinuum; the cases described in §3.1 represent the other end; and in between are many cases
this graded quality in §8, where we shall suggest that it helps to generate the massive diversi-
ty of human expression. (For related but different continua see Wharton, 2009; Sperber &
ly called ‘communicating’—has a distinctive property that is not present in the other subsets
described above. Crucially, the communicator is freed from the constraint of providing non-
communicative evidence (see also §5). Returning to the example above, Mary makes eye con-
tact with Peter and mimes eating berries in an exaggerated way, with the informative intent
that Peter believes the berries are edible, and in doing so she provides only communicative—
However, for this potential freedom of expression to be realised two related issues
must be addressed. First, freedom from the constraint of having to provide non-communic-
intentions, more-or-less accurately, on the basis just of whatever other, communicative evid-
ence communicators are able to provide (see §2 on the importance of complementary mech-
anisms). Second, expressive freedom also provides communicators with the opportunity to
deceive, leaving the system clearly prone to evolutionary instability (§2). To discuss how
All animal species have evolved adaptive reactions to the presence and behaviour of others.
As with manipulation (§3), we define these adaptive reactions functionally, recognising that
the specific mechanisms can be many and varied.6 For example, a chameleon’s adaptive re-
6 Note that our terminology here differs from Krebs and Dawkins, who used ‘mindreading’ instead of
‘adaptive reaction’ (1984). We have deviated from this usage because ‘mindreading’ is also widely used
in the social cognition literature to describe mechanisms rather than function i.e. at the proximate
rather than the ultimate level.
page 15 of 51
action to the presence of potential predators is (we assume) largely physiological. We focus
call these cognitive means ‘social vigilance’ (Heintz et al., 2017). Again we distinguish three
graded and embedded subsets (Figure 3), and we describe their relationship to the various
The first embedded subset includes inferences based on the capacity to anticipate and re-
spond adaptively to the intentional action of others. Humans do this routinely, of course.
Others’ intentions are relevant to us, such as when we decide whether to avoid or engage
with them as friends, rivals, or indeed any social relationship. The capacity to behave in ways
that take account of other individuals’ intentions has also been experimentally documented
in many studies with non-human great apes (Emery & Clayton, 2009; Call & Tomasello,
2010; Andrews, 2017; Bettle & Rosati, 2021). In one such experiment, chimpanzees are given
the opportunity to take a piece of food from a bucket, the location of which is either known
or not known by a dominant conspecific. The key finding is that the subordinate chimpanzee
page 16 of 51
is more likely to take the food if the location is unknown to the dominant (Hare et al., 2011).
The details of exactly which intentions and other mental states great apes attribute to others
remains a topic of active study; but in any case many experiments show that chimpanzees
are able, in some contexts at least, to adaptively modulate their behaviour in view of what the
conspecific is most likely to do, and what effects this might have on the focal individual. Sim-
ilar modulations have been documented in many non-primate species. Grey squirrels, for
instance, have been shown to modulate their caching behavior as a function of the presence
of onlookers e.g. moving a cache when the onlooker leaves (Leaver et al., 2007); and ravens
have been shown to guard their caches against discovery, taking into account other ravens’
In the second embedded subset are inferences about others’ informative intentions. The pos-
sibility of such inferences, and their nature, depends to a significant extent on whether the
informative intentions in question have been made overt (§3.3) or not (§3.2) by the actor, or
communicator.
If an informative intention is not overt and audiences do not recognise it, then what
is perceived is simply instrumental action, which like any behaviour might or might not be
relevant to the observer. If, alternatively, an informative intention is not overt but is recog-
nised nevertheless, audiences might take account of this absence of overtness, and the possi-
ble reasons for it, in their interpretation. Suppose, for instance, Claire leaves Dwight’s keys
on the table, with the informative intention that by virtue of seeing them Dwight does not
forget the keys when he goes to work. Dwight might simply see the keys and thus remember
to take them, not ever recognising Claire’s informative intention, which was after all not
7
Throughout this article, we have avoided using the terms ‘mindreading’ and ‘theory of mind’, be-
cause they are so widely contested. Nevertheless, a reviewer asked us to state our view and we are
happy to do so: we are mindreading ‘deflationists’ (e.g. Jacob & Scott-Phillips, 2020). We believe that
these notions are best used in a minimal way, to refer just to the spontaneous recognition of mental
states; and as such we believe that mindreading is much more akin to, say, visual cognition than to
conscious ‘thinking’. We think that mindreading in this deflationary sense is likely to be phylogeneti-
cally widespread, but enriched in various specialised ways in different species. The various cognitive
processes we describe in this article are just such specialised versions of mindreading in this defla-
tionary sense, falling within the broad functional category of social vigilance.
page 17 of 51
overt. Alternatively, Dwight might recognise that Claire had an informative intention even
though she did not make this overt, and he might hence infer that she thinks he is absent
minded but she does not want to embarrass him by saying so explicitly. In any case, humans
commonly act with informative intentions that they do not make overt, but which are some-
times recognised nevertheless. §8.1 on coordination smoothers and §8.3 on expressive pun-
tention (by definition: see §3.3). If the informative intention is nevertheless not recognised,
such as when, for instance, a raised hand, intended as a request to ask a question, is inter-
preted as a mere stretch of the arm, then that is a simple failure of communication. If, in
contrast, an overt informative intention is recognised as being overt, such as when a raised
hand intended as a request to ask a question is indeed recognised as a request to ask a ques-
tion—if, in other words, the audience recognises that the actor has not only an informative
ferentially powerful presumption about the behaviour. Specifically, the audience is warrant-
ed in presuming that the behaviour is the most effective one the communicator could pro-
duce, given the communicators’ goals, abilities, and the constraints acting on them. This in-
sight is central to Relevance Theory (Sperber & Wilson, 1986/1995; 2002; 2005), where it is
called the communicative principle of relevance. In the next section we describe in more de-
tail the nature of the inferential process that is triggered, in audiences, by this recognition of
communicative intent.
overtly, with the goal to make their informative intention mutually known. Here we discuss
Language use is a paradigmatic example, and one of Grice’s pioneering insights was
that the interpretation of utterances is guided by prior expectations about the cooperative
page 18 of 51
intent of communicators (mirroring his characterisation of linguistic meaning: see §3.3). 8
Further developments in cognitive pragmatics have specified and debated the nature of these
expectations in more detail. Relevance Theory, for instance, describes these expectations in
terms of a single assumption, that ostensively presented stimuli are optimally relevant for
the intended audience, given the speakers’ goals, abilities, and the constraints acting on
them. Or, in other words: audiences have a strong positive prior expectation that overtly in-
tentional behaviour is cooperative; and this prior expectation of cooperativeness in turn li-
censes a presumption that informative intentions are worth paying attention to i.e. are op-
timally relevant. Here and elsewhere, “optimally relevant” means, more precisely, that com-
municators strive to optimise the trade-off between cognitive effects and processing effort,
Here is an example. Amy and Barry are drinking in a bar. Amy’s glass, which is visible
to both her and Barry, is empty. This fact is on its own unremarkable. Suppose now that Amy
picks up the glass and gently waves it in front of Barry. Why would she do this? What could it
possibly ‘mean’, and how could Barry know? The Relevance Theory answer is that Amy’s be-
assumption that Amy’s behaviour is the most optimally relevant behaviour she could per-
form given her goals and the circumstances. The key point here, which features in some form
in all Gricean approaches, is that only with this cooperative assumption can Barry converge
on the conclusion that Amy’s behaviour is a suggestion that they stay for another drink. Oth-
erwise, without this assumption, Amy’s behaviour is simply mysterious. Many experimental
studies have shown how prospective audiences interpret communicative behaviours under
presumptions of optimal relevance (e.g. van der Henst et al., 2002; Gibbs & Bryant, 2008;
inter alia).
8 Note that the notion of cooperation used in the Gricean framework is not the same as that used in
standard evolutionary theory. The evolutionary notion is about evolutionary function, and describes
any behaviour that has a positive effect on another organism’s inclusive fitness. The Gricean notion is
about the assumptions that audiences make about the intent of the communicator. While these two
notions can align with one another, and are sometimes conflated, they are different levels of analysis
and not the same.
page 19 of 51
This is very similar to how other specialised cognitive mechanisms ‘embody’ know-
ledge about the nature of objects, magnitudes, species, and other basic, fundamental features
of the human evolutionary ecology (Carey, 2009; Spelke & Kinzler, 2007). In all these cases,
items perceived as being of a particular type (an object, a magnitude, and so on) trigger spe-
cific assumptions about the nature of that item. For example, items perceived as physical ob-
jects trigger assumptions that the item is physically cohesive, bonded, rigid, and cannot be
acted on at a distance (Spelke, 1990). In the present case, behaviour perceived as ostensive
triggers an assumption that the behaviour is optimally relevant for the audience, given the
communicator’s goals, abilities, affordances and constraints. This allows a specialised, ‘satis-
ficing’ process of interpretation to then derive the communicator’s intended meaning (Sper-
ber & Wilson, 2002; see also e.g. Ferreira & Patson, 2007 on ‘good enough’ approaches to
linguistic comprehension). This process is, moreover, spontaneous and largely unconscious,
such that we cannot ‘choose’ not to perform it even if we wish to. Consider film spoilers, for
instance: our desire to not recover the meaning of what is said does not and cannot suspend
the interpretive process. Again, this is akin to the recognition of objects, magnitudes and so
on, all of which we recognise and process in spontaneous and unconscious ways. We cannot
‘un-see’ objects, just as we cannot ‘un-understand’ spoilers. All in all, spontaneous interpret-
ation of ostensive stimuli is a functionally specialised form of social vigilance, targeted at the
As with the other side of the equation (§3), we have so far presented the distinction
between the subsets in this section as categorical, but they are in fact graded and continuous.
Specifically, there is on the audience side variation in the extent to which recognition of the
actor’s informative intention contributes to correct interpretation i.e. to satisfying the in-
We can now summarise how a system of communication predicated on the expression and
page 20 of 51
Crucially, the metarepresentational structure of ostensive communication generates a
which can in turn be about anything at all (see also Mercier & Sperber, 2009 on virtual do-
main generality in cognition more broadly). Consider again the example of Mary, who makes
eye contact with Peter and mimes eating berries in an exaggerated way. By doing so, she
provides evidence of her informative intention, that Peter understands that the berries are
edible; and this intention is informative about the actual edibility of the berries only in turn.
tion effectively open-ended (unleashed), even though the actual domain of the relevant cog-
nitive capacities is narrow and specific: it is just the communicator’s informative intentions.
pressively open-ended while still conforming to the central evolutionary constraint, that
should be tied to narrow domains of statistical mutual benefit, and we observed that human
communication appears to be in flagrant violation of this constraint. Now we can state how
the paradox can be resolved. The actual domain of the cognitive capacities that underpin os-
benefit, namely the communicator’s own informative intentions. At the same time, the
individual has towards another (‘She wants me to believe that the berries are edible’). Ac-
ceptance, in contrast, is targeted at what the informative intention is about i.e. what is ‘virtu-
al’. To accept is to actually update one’s own beliefs in light of what has been communicated
page 21 of 51
Together, these two consequences imply that audiences cannot actually gain from
communication unless they extend a degree of trust towards the communicator. The distinc-
tion between comprehension and acceptance, and the massive open-endedness of human
communication, together mean that audiences who do not extend a degree of trust towards
ostensive communicators would comprehend what others want to do to their minds, but
would never then actually update their beliefs in light of that knowledge. They would never
allow themselves to gain information in communication! Peter would understand that Mary
wants him to believe that the berries are edible, but Peter unless he extends some trust to-
wards her, he will never believe that the berries are actually edible. Of course, this trust must
be tentative and provisional, lest audiences be misinformed, but it must be extended in some
way, just for audiences to gain from communication in the first place.
tentions must be complemented by further capacities that allow audiences to trust what is
communicated but in a vigilant way, possibly questioning the competence or the benevolence
of the communicator. Commonly known as epistemic vigilance, these cognitive capacities are
(Sperber et al., 2010; Mercier, 2017). They also allow audiences to identify misleading com-
municators, and hence adjust the attention and trust they are willing to grant in the future.
ly, by a combination of cognitive capacities for the expression of informative intentions, cog-
nitive capacities for the recognition of informative intentions, and cognitive capacities of
epistemic vigilance, all of which are functionally tied to one another. Thus, to properly ex-
plain the expressive openness of human communication, what must be described is: (i) how
these cognitive capacities could all gradually co-evolve and be mutually supportive of one
another, such that they form a communication system; and (ii) the ecological reasons why
they have actually done so in humans. The next section addresses these questions.
page 22 of 51
Many authors have observed how human communication must have co-evolved in a highly
social ecology, one way or another (§1). Here we identify which specific and distinctive as-
pects of human social ecologies can generate the co-evolution of the cognitive capacities de-
scribed in §3 and §4, such that fully enriched ostensive communication can become uniform
and stable in the population. We also provide precise description of how this co-evolution
Arguably the most distinctive feature of the human cognitive niche is that it is highly
social. Humans tend to live in social groups that are loosely-defined but long-lasting, and
comprised of both kin and non-kin. To a degree that surpasses that of other great apes, this
social ecology generates many opportunities for win-win cooperation, and risks of exploita-
tion. More broadly, human social ecologies involve an especially delicate balance of coopera-
tion and competition, with substantial evolutionary pressure for behaviours that make the
most of this mix (Noë & Hammerstein, 1995; Ferriere et al., 2002; Tomasello et al., 2012).
Individuals acting in their own adaptive self-interest seek out others (‘friends’, ‘colleagues’)
with whom to engage in mutually beneficial enterprises, and they behave in ways that in-
crease their chances of being chosen as a partner for joint enterprise (Barclay, 2013; Krems
et al., 2021; inter alia). Humans have hence evolved a number of cognitive capacities adap-
ted for this ecology, including moral dispositions, mechanisms of social vigilance that identi-
and so on (see e.g. Origgi, 2004; 2005; Barrett et al., 2010; Delton & Robinson, 2012; Sper-
ber & Baumard, 2012; Baumard et al., 2013; Heintz et al., 2017; Curry et al., 2019; Engel-
mann & Tomasello, 2019; inter alia). These factors collectively constitute a ‘partner choice’
social ecology; or, possibly, an ecology of ‘self-domestication’. This means, minimally, that it
is advantageous to be selected as a partner for some joint enterprise (other than mating), and
page 23 of 51
that the selection of partners for joint enterprise is based on information about past actions.
In this partner choice ecology, the cognitive means of manipulation described in §3.3,
and the cognitive means of social vigilance described in §4.3, are each adaptive. Particularly
important is the role of social commitments. By providing evidence of their informative in-
tention, informers make themselves accountable to their audience, putting their reputation
at stake; and audiences can hence effectively assume the relevance of overtly expressed in-
formative intentions. This evolutionary dynamic is, incidentally, similar to that described by
partner choice approaches to fairness (André & Baumard, 2011; Debove et al., 2015; Barclay,
2013; 2016). In both cases, the adaptive value of maintaining one’s reputation in a partner
choice ecology constitutes a crucial selection pressure for psychological traits, which in turn
The following five paragraphs elaborate this argument in more detail. They hence
provide an existence proof of how and why the cognitive capacities described in previous sec-
tions could have evolved in a gradual manner (for similar but different approaches see e.g.
Wharton, 2006; Cornell & Wharton, in press). Indeed, ‘lineage explanations’, in which
changes in the phenotype result from incremental changes, are an important constraint on
Consider a social ecology with many, varied opportunities for win-win cooperation.
Here, informing others can be adaptive, because it can facilitate win-win cooperation or even
create new win-win opportunities. In particular, informing others can generate common
ground and hence facilitate many joint enterprises (such as, say, animal hunting, building
9
Three different notions of reputation can be distinguished. (1) An individual A can have a ‘reputa-
tion’ for X in the sense that another person believes X about A (this is sometimes called an ‘image
score’). (2) An individual A can have a ‘reputation’ for X in the sense that a community of others all
believe X about A. (3) An individual A can have a reputation for X in the sense that a community of
others all believe that they all believe X about A i.e. the notion that A is X is common ground. Our ar-
gument in this section turns just on notion (1) and (2). Clearly, the emergence of ostensive communic-
ation, which enables open-ended communication and hence gossip, will in turn facilitate the emer-
gence of (2) and (3), and can hence support cooperative phenomena such as indirect reciprocity (see
e.g. Nowak & Sigmund, 2005).
page 24 of 51
shelter, maintaining a fire, alloparenting). Informing others can also have fitness advantages
by allowing the social transmission of opaque skills to cooperative partners and kin.
These potential adaptive benefits in turn mean that it is adaptive to recognise and
attend to others’ attempts to gain attention (§4.2). That said, attention is limited and thus
should be modulated depending on whether others’ attempts to inform are likely to be worth
the attention indeed i.e. are revealing of relevant information. Individuals should be socially
vigilant towards others’ informative intentions, evaluating whether, or to what extent, the
intentions are indeed cooperative. It will hence be in informers’ own interests to actually be
relevant for their audience, because those who intentionally attract attention but fail to do so
in ways that are useful (relevant) will, in time, incur costs to their reputation and lose their
capacity to manipulate their conspecifics’ attention. In other words, there will be selection
for behaviours that intentionally attract others’ attention only when it is likely to be worth-
while for the audience to indeed pay attention (see also Dessalles, 1998).
At this point, expression has not yet ‘gone Gricean’ (we adopt this useful expression
from Bar-On, 2013), and as such humans are not yet ‘language ready’. This is because in-
formative intentions are not intentionally made overt, and so expression is not yet predic-
(Grice’s “by means of” clause: see §3.3). Expression is based just on behaviours that inform-
ers expect will be relevant to others; and ‘comprehension’ is based just on tentative assump-
tions that others’ expressive behaviour is likely to be relevant for the same reason. These
tendencies and dispositions do, however, constitute a new social ecology, and it is here that
Crucially, in this new social ecology—in which audiences might expect others’ infor-
mative behaviour to be relevant, and in which a reputation for being a good cooperator can
be gained and lost—it is adaptive to make manifest informative intentions themselves i.e.
make overt and common knowledge the intentions you have towards your audiences’ mind.
offer a credible commitment that the overtly presented behaviour will indeed be relevant for
the audience; which in turn increases the probability that the informative intention will in-
page 25 of 51
deed be satisfied. In other words: since the overt expression of an informative intention
makes that informative intention common knowledge; and since in a partner choice social
ecology there is the risk of developing a reputation for irrelevance and hence of losing the
their behaviour being useful (relevant) for the audience. This in turn makes it adaptive for
The social ecology is now one in which the overt expression of informative intentions
effectively commits informers to being relevant to their audience, and in which informers
indeed abide by that commitment (see also Scott-Phillips, 2010; Sperber, 2013). In this new
ecology, it is adaptive for audiences to evolve two kinds of specialised cognitive disposition.
(1) High prior expectations that others’ communicative behaviour will be relevant. These will
eventually become the spontaneous presumptions of relevance described in §4.3. (2) Forms
of social vigilance that assess how, and to what extent, beliefs should be updated in view of
others’ informative intentions. These will eventually become the epistemic vigilance de-
scribed in §5. Now audiences have these two kinds of specialised cognitive disposition, indi-
viduals can inform simply “by means of” (as Grice put it) making their informative intentions
Let us summarise. What we are arguing is that outside a partner choice social ecolo-
gy, communication and expression are highly prone to irrelevance, deception and instability;
but within a partner choice social ecology there is selective advantage for behaviour that is
relevant. Within this social ecology a gradual, cognitive co-evolution of specialised capacities
for ostensive communication is hence possible. As with other aspects of core cognition, these
capacities, which provide the foundations of human communication (§5), should become
part of the ordinarily developing cognitive phenotype, emerging at reliable and predictable
stages of ontogeny.
There is, correspondingly, abundant empirical evidence of this reliable and predict-
able cognitive development in humans, both in language use and communication more
page 26 of 51
broadly (e.g. Bates, 1979; Bloom, 2002; Goldin-Meadow, 2005; Tomasello, 2008; Bohn &
Frank, 2019; inter alia). In the next section we consider whether, or in what ways and to
what extent, the same cognitive capacities might be present in non-human primates.
7. Cross-species comparisons
How would we know? These questions are worth asking because non-human species, great
apes and dogs in particular, sometimes appear to understand some human ostensive be-
haviour, at least in some specific contexts. Here we outline how this question can be ad-
human and non-human great ape communication, and we reinterpret some key findings in
not any particular behaviour, but rather any behaviour motivated by a particular cognitive
phenomenon, namely informative intentions (§3.3). This makes it impossible to fully isolate
so the relevant cognitive capacities are not ascribed to the individual animal participants, or
species. One response to this methodological challenge has been to, effectively, abandon use
of the Gricean framework in the study of animal communication (e.g. Townsend et al., 2017).
In contrast, we suggest that experiments revealing the relevant intentions and interpretative
qua ostension (i.e. sensitive to the expression of an informative intention) can be tested by
contrasting two scenarios in which the exact same ostensive behaviour prompts spontaneous
depending only on what is in the common ground. Real-world human communication is re-
plete with examples. Ordinary utterances such as, say, “It’s raining” can, even if produced in
page 27 of 51
exactly the same way in each case, be interpreted in wildly different ways depending only on
the present common ground (‘Take an umbrella’, ‘Even the whether can’t lighten my mood’,
‘Your parents won’t be visiting after all’). The same can be true of non-verbal means of com-
munication, such as points and nods, not to mention spontaneous and ad hoc gestures, and
We predict, tentatively, that if any non-human primates do reliably pass tasks of this
sort, it will be individuals with extensive experience of altruistic human caregivers, and not
those living the natural social ecologies of non-human primates. Non-human primate social
ecologies involve fewer and less frequent opportunities for interactions of mutual benefit.
That is not to say such opportunities are absent, but they are much less prevalent relative to
the human case, and in consequence the relevant selection pressures are not (as) present. At
the same time, non-human primates living in captive conditions, with human caregivers who
and expectations ontogenetically (see e.g. Call, 2011 for discussion of how rearing conditions
could result from non-standard life history in non-human apes. If so, then we should expect
some recognition and interpretation of human ostensive behaviours qua ostensive in at least
some individuals, albeit in imperfect and happenstance ways. This prediction is of course
ultimately a matter for future empirical research, but it aligns with existing findings that
humans differ from other great apes in dispositions of trust and cooperation (see e.g. Moll &
Here is an analogy that helps to articulate this difference between specialised compe-
tences that are part of the ordinarily developing phenotype (as ostensive communication is
in humans), and latent competencies that might be refined in the right ecology (as might be
the case for ostensive communication in chimpanzees and some other non-human
primates). Consider humans swinging from trees. Human bodies are not especially well-suit-
10Note that the spontaneity of responses is especially important for future experimental design, be-
cause for a compelling test the differential interpretations of a specific stimulus should not be learned
by training on that same specific stimulus. Infants have been shown to pass a third-person version of
such tasks i.e. a version in which the infant observes interaction between two other agents (Tauzin &
Gergely, 2018).
page 28 of 51
ed to this task. We lack the specialised biological apparatus of other primates and we do not
develop the relevant dispositions as an ordinary part of ontogeny. At the same time, there is
no absolute barrier. Some humans can swing from trees in some limited ways and to some
extent, and this basic ability can be refined and enhanced with training: in other words, in
the right ecology. What we are suggesting, tentatively, is that ostensive communication in
other primates, living in the right sort of social ecologies, might be similar: not impossible
and not wholly absent, but still unspecialised, disfluent, not a regular part of the environ-
This perspective on non-human primate cognition can help make sense of otherwise
ples in particular: performance in the ‘object choice task’, and the phenomenon of overimita-
tion.
First, in the object choice task a desirable object is shown to the participant, and then
placed in one of two boxes, or bins. The participant does not know which of the two boxes
contains the desirable object. The two boxes are placed either side of the experimenter, who
then points to the box with the desirable object. The participant is then free to open the
boxes. Many non-human primates ‘fail’ this task: in many studies non-human primates do
not choose the indicated box at levels greater than chance (see Clark et al., 2019 for a recent
review). We suggest that this occurs simply because the relevant cognitive processes em-
ployed by the audience are, in non-human primates, not ordinarily predicated on a presump-
tion of cooperation, which in the context of pointing means communicative relevance. Dogs,
in contrast, perform far better at the object choice task (see below), as do human infants.
to them, including in particular those that are perceivably causally irrelevant (e.g. tapping a
box before opening it, even when the tapping makes no difference to whether or how the box
children, and not in chimpanzees or bonobos (Horner & Whiten, 2005; Lyons et al., 2007;
Johnson et al., 2016; Clay & Tennie, 2018; Hoehl et al., 2019). This finding has prompted
speculation that overimitation derives from a cognitive adaptation for acquiring generic, cul-
page 29 of 51
tural knowledge (e.g. Nielsen & Tomasello, 2010; Chudek & Henrich, 2011; Gergely, 2013;
Legare & Nielsen, 2015). We suggest, in contrast, that overimitation is best explained as a by-
product of audience presumptions of relevance. Overimitation reliably occurs only when the
copied behaviour has been performed in an overtly intentional (i.e. ostensive) way (see e.g.
Király et al., 2013 for experimental demonstration). This triggers in the audience a spontan-
hence delivering the (incorrect) conclusion that the demonstrated actions are useful, even if
that utility is currently opaque to the audience. We are suggesting, in other words, that the
reason only humans reliably demonstrate overimitation is that only humans reliably inter-
pret ostensive behaviour in terms of optimal relevance (see also Morin, 2016, p.244-245).
We note, consistent with this interpretation, that overimitation emerges in development very
Finally, dogs are also an informative point of comparison. Dogs have been subject to
a long period of domestication in which humans are often prosocial towards them. In this
ecology it can be adaptive for dogs to simply presume that when humans attempt to gain
their attention, it is indeed worthwhile to actually pay attention. Correspondingly, dogs seem
to be sensitive to some of the most salient human ostensive behaviours (see e.g. Topál et al.,
2014; Wynne, 2016 for reviews). This sensitivity, moreover, emerges early in development
and is highly heritable (Bray et al., 2021). Presumably, dogs do not make the same interpre-
tative inferences as humans, but they do show how, in the right evolutionary ecologies, it can
be adaptive to spontaneously presume that others—in this case, human owners—are being
In this section and the next, we suggest how the cognitive mechanisms described in previous
sections underpin many otherwise diverse means of human expression. We focus in particu-
lar on the examples of coordination smoothers (§8.1), teaching (§8.2), punishment (§8.3),
art (§8.4) and the emergence of symbols and grammar (§9). (This list of expressive domains
is of course not exhaustive.) In each case, we summarise how these different means of ex-
page 30 of 51
pression each employ the common, unified set of cognitive capacities described in previous
sections, but in different ways in each case. If we are right about this, then the evolutionary
emergence of specialised, cognitive means of manipulation (§3) and social vigilance (§4),
which together unleash expression (§5), is a root cause of many of the most distinctive as-
sion. In §3.3 we mentioned how there is a graded quality on the production side: different
means of expression can vary in the extent to which the actor makes her informative inten-
tion manifest. In §4.3 we mentioned how there is, in turn, variation on the audience side:
recognition of the actor’s informative intention can contribute to satisfying the informative
intention to different degrees in each case. In the subsections below, we describe how differ-
ent forms of human expression make use of these graded aspects in a range of different
ways; and we suggest that in general people aim to make their informative intentions mani-
fest just to the extent that the informative intention is likely to be satisfied, but no more so.
To coordinate with one another in joint actions, such as dancing with a partner, maintaining
a tempo, moving large objects together, and many others, individuals must be informed
about each other’s behaviour and likely future behaviour, often on a moment-by-moment
basis (Sebanz et al., 2006). This can occur passively, but individuals also behave in ways that
actively facilitate the flow of information for joint action. For instance, two people may have
a goal to lift and move a large table. In lifting their end of the table, each person might move
in slightly exaggerated ways, in order to be predictable. Such behaviours are called ‘coordina-
tion smoothers’: they enable predictability for coordination (Vesper et al., 2010; 2017). Some
cases of coordination smoothing are clearly communicative, such as road signs and forms of
language use targeted at easing the flow of conversation (‘discourse markers’, ‘procedural
meaning’: see e.g. Blakemore, 2002; Gibbs & Bryant, 2008). However, cases in which in-
formative intentions are less overt have only recently been explicitly analysed in terms of
page 31 of 51
Consider two people, Jane and Paul, walking towards one another on a relatively nar-
row street. Jane makes a clear movement towards one side in order to make her action pre-
dictable to Paul. This informs Paul that Jane intends to proceed on the right, and it can do so
even if Paul does not recognise that Jane has this informative intention. Alternatively, Jane
might exaggerate her movement to one side. This makes her informative intention more
manifest, and Paul can hence infer that she has an informative intention that he believes she
will proceed on the right, and trust in it. This raises the question: when, why and to what ex-
tent do individuals make their informative intentions manifest? When should Jane not just
clearly move, but exaggerate her movement to one side? And to what extent? Corresponding-
ly, on the audience side: to what extent does recognition of the actor’s informative intention
contribute to successful coordination smoothing? These are all empirical questions whose
answers depend on how individuals take into account the constraints and the affordances of
the situation, and how they navigate graded dimensions of human expression.
Many results in the experimental study of joint action suggest that people indeed ex-
aggerate or otherwise adjust their actions to the extent that it is useful to do so for the pur-
poses of informing others; or, in other words, they make the least costly difference that is
large enough to make a difference (e.g. McEllin et al., 2018a,b; Schmitz et al., 2018; Curioni
et al., 2019). Observers, in turn, attribute to others commitments to behaving in the predict-
ed way just to the extent that those others are perceived as acting on a communicative inten-
tion (see e.g. Gibbs & Bryant, 2008; Bonalumi et al., 2020; 2021). In sum then, we are sug-
gesting that coordination smoothing is a form of human expression, in which people navi-
8.2. Teaching
Human teaching is richly diverse. Ethnographies of teaching reveal practices that span the
full range of human expression, ranging from tolerated observation, in which a skilled indi-
vidual just allows others to observe her in practice, to, at the other extreme, direct verbal
statements from the teacher, which the learner is expected to internalise (e.g. Lave &
Wenger, 1991; Marchand, 2010; Sugiyama, in press). Most actual instances of teaching lie
page 32 of 51
between these extremes and also include, for instance, repeated demonstration, perfor-
mance, exaggeration, role-play and countless other forms of expression (see e.g. Kline, 2015
for one recent review). We suggest that, as with coordination smoothers, the diversity of
means of teaching vary in the extent to which the teacher makes her informative intention
manifest; and also the extent to which recognition of the teacher’s informative intention con-
Consider, for instance, a dance teacher (see e.g. Downey, 2008 for cognitively-in-
formed ethnography of dance teaching). At one extreme, she might simply repeat a dance
step multiple times, possibly from a range of different angles, allowing learners to observe,
without any further guidance about which aspects of the movement to attend to. Here the
teacher has an informative intention, and this intention is not hidden at all, but the teacher
does not make the intention manifest, and the learners employ means-end relations to learn.
Alternatively, at the other extreme, the teacher might openly exaggerate some of her move-
ments and hence highlight especially relevant aspects, which would otherwise remain unno-
ticed. By doing this the teacher makes her informative intention manifest. This triggers in
exaggeration from the actual target behaviour, and hence identify what is especially relevant
about the teacher’s movements. In between the extremes are cases where the teacher makes
her informative intention somewhat manifest, such as when she slows her movement but in
a slight way only. In these ways and others, teaching is a phenomenon that, in its diversity,
simply perform the target behaviour as usual and just allow observation, sometimes it is
sary that the teacher’s informative intention be made wholly manifest. In particular, by trig-
gering learners’ presumption of relevance, teachers can teach things even though what
makes those things relevant is opaque to the learners (Gergely & Csibra, 2006). A real-world
example is teaching the counting routine to children, who learn by presuming that the rou-
page 33 of 51
tine is relevant even though they do not yet understand its real utility. This mode of teaching
turn help to explain why teaching is prevalent in human societies but relatively rare in other
species (see e.g. Hoppitt et al., 2008; Thornton & Raihani, 2008 for comparative perspec-
tives). Human teaching involves the dynamic use of unleashed expression. Analogous behav-
iours are observable in other species, but not with the same dynamic, open-ended and flexi-
ble range of behaviours that are afforded by truly unleashed expression, and readily exploit-
8.3. Punishment
within cognitive science and cognate fields such as behavioural economics, punishment has
deters specific behaviours. The actual delivery of punishment is then necessary only to main-
tain the integrity of the incentive structure. Yet the rewards and punishment that humans
tend to produce are actually inefficient for this goal. That is, they do not incentivise the target
behaviour well, contrary to the intuitive model (Ho et al., 2019; Cushman et al., in press).
The way people punish is, rather, best explained in terms of expression (ibid.). More pre-
cisely, we suggest that punishment is used to inform others that future exploitative beha-
viour will result in future costs (see also e.g. Sripada, 2005).
But why, then, is this expressive function not patently apparent? In other domains
(linguistic communication, teaching, art) expression and communication are utterly plain to
see. We suggest that punishment is usually most effective when its communicative aspects
are somewhat hidden, even though its informative aspects are present. In short, punishment
The crucial point is that in ordinary social relations, punishment is credible only if
the incentives behind it are perceived to be stable; but in fact, in ordinary social relations the
incentives to inform are unstable. Specifically, they are dependent on the possibilities of fu-
page 34 of 51
ture collaboration: if we are unlikely to interact in the future, I have no substantive incentive
to inform you that your behaviour was unacceptable. So if the real incentives that motivate
punishment were actually made manifest, they would be revealed as unstable and would
hence undermine the credibility of punishment as a means of informing. In this respect pun-
ishment is akin to generosity. We mentioned in §3.2 that there is a slight paradox to generos-
ity, in the sense that while it can be motivated by an intention to advertise oneself as proso-
cial, this intention should not itself be too manifest, lest the act of generosity be seen as in-
sincere. We are suggesting that a similar dynamic plays out on the punishment side: pun-
ishment does not credibly demonstrate a willingness to retaliate against anti-social beha-
punishment have been long recognised: punishment is described as, for instance, “a conven-
tional device for the expression of attitudes of resentment and indignation, and of judgments
of disapproval and reprobation” (Feinburg, 1965, p.400; more recently see e.g. Primoratz,
1989; Hampton, 1992; Duff, 2001). The expressive dimension of punishment is straightfor-
wardly recognised in the legal domain because, we suggest, there is in this domain no real
doubt that the punisher (the nation state) has a long term, stable incentive to inform the au-
dience (citizens) about what is unacceptable. Nation states hence have no real need to hide
means of expression. Such studies would form an important bridge between cognitive prag-
matics and other fields, such as the newly emerging area of experimental jurisprudence (e.g.
Sommers, 2021). We also know of no existing research examining the expressive dimensions
page 35 of 51
8.4. Art
Art is clearly expressive in some way, and audiences interpret artistic outputs in open-ended
ways. Modern audiences in particular are granted a great deal of autonomy in how they en-
gage with art, and are encouraged to develop and seek out their own, often highly personal
interpretations. We suggest that, like the other examples above, the open-endedness of artis-
tic expression derives from the natural character of human expression more broadly; and
hence that the interpretations that audiences derive from artwork, which are often highly
personal, are nevertheless often prompted by and derive from the same set of cognitive pro-
Crucially, what differentiates artistic expression from ordinary behaviour is not any
fundamental aesthetic quality as such, but rather the overt presentation of an object as an
aesthetic experience worthy of attention. This is the conclusion of many lines of research and
argument from at least four different fields: traditional art theory (e.g. Danto, 1964; Dickie,
1987), cognitive pragmatics (e.g. Pignocchi, 2019; McCallum et al., 2020), philosophy of
mind (e.g. Fodor, 2012), and social anthropology (e.g. Dissanayake, 1988; 2003). The overt
‘Gricean’, or ‘making special’, in each of these four literatures. This consensus in turn sug-
gests that while proclivities towards aesthetic experience might be observable in other spe-
cies, the evolutionary emergence of cognitive capacities for unleashed expression, as a core
part of the human cognitive phenotype (§6), allows those proclivities to be expressed in
overtly intentional ways, thus differentiating art from other forms of aesthetic experience.
The emergence of art institutions can further reinforce these effects . Contemporary
art galleries in particular use white walls, open spaces and other features of curation to
present artworks as items to be considered and appreciated, hence triggering, we claim, the
These and other institutional effects, which can generate highly personal, even idiosyncratic
interpretations, are well established in art theory. What cognitive pragmatic perspectives
help to provide is description of how these effects exploit and otherwise build on the way au-
page 36 of 51
diences spontaneously interpret ostensive behaviour in more ordinary forms of social inter-
8.5. Languages
Language use is quintessentially ostensive. Unlike some of the other means of expression
described above, language use involves making informative intentions wholly manifest. We
are arguing, in other words, that cognitive capacities for ostensive communication are
foundational to language use: there could not be any languages or linguistic communication
without the prior existence of cognitive capacities for ostensive communication (see also e.g.
Levinson, 2006; Tomasello, 2008; Scott-Phillips, 2015). As we put it in §1, natural languages
Languages have, of course, their own particular features that collectively distinguish
words, grammars and so on, which function to associate particular behaviours (speech, ges-
ture) with particular inferences that the communicator intends to trigger in the audience.
This ‘pragmatics-first’ perspective on the nature of languages aligns with usage- and con-
used as a means to provide evidence of speaker meaning (e.g. Tomasello, 2003; Goldberg &
Suttle, 2010, 2003; Bybee & Beckner, 2010; Schmid, 2020; Hartmann & Player, 2021).
and stabilization of communicative conventions has been documented in several real world
case studies (e.g. Kegl et al., 1999; Meir et al., 2010; Brentari & Goldin-Meadow, 2017; inter
alia), and studied experimentally in the laboratory (e.g. Fay et al., 2013; Schouwstra & de
Swart, 2014; Granito et al., 2019; Motamedi et al., 2019; Raviv et al., 2019; inter alia). What
is commonly observed in these literatures is how behaviour that is sufficiently similar to pre-
token of the same type as previously used, even after just one interaction; and also how fur-
page 37 of 51
ther repetition causes the focal behaviours to become increasingly conventional. How and
In answering this question, what is not often recognised is that the very same cogni-
tive capacities that make ostensive communication possible in the first place, also play a piv-
otal role here. In particular, without audience presumptions of optimal relevance (§4.3), be-
haviour that resembles past communicative behaviour is mysterious and strange. Why re-
peat a past behaviour, and bring attention to it? Such behaviour is worth doing only if the
attention grabbing repetition of a past behaviour triggers in audiences the interpretation that
the behaviour is being used for the same or similar purposes as previously. So past events
have a role in communication not simply because of statistical learning of associations, but
because alluding to past events is typically the most efficient way to trigger, in the target au-
dience, interpretative inferences that are the same or similar to those triggered previously.
Furthermore, this allusion to past events will often mean that a given behaviour can
afford to be slightly less complex or less elaborate than the previous version, so long as the
allusion is still made. Communicative success becomes increasingly governed by the simple
fact that echoing how behaviours have been successfully used in the past is the most efficient
means of prompting the intended inferences in the audience. Repeated many times over, this
leads to gradual simplification of the stimuli; and in time shapes many of the features that
levels of resemblance between form and use (‘symbolism’), statistical relationships between
word length and frequency of use (e.g. ‘Zipf’s law’), and so on. These processes can, we be-
lieve, be fruitfully analysed within an epidemiological framework (e.g. Enfield, 2003; 2014;
Finally, we note that linguistic stimuli are processed by some dedicated cognitive ca-
pacities (see e.g. Hagoort, 2017 for one recent summary). Crucially, these capacities appear
the comprehension side in particular, inference of what is said and inference of what is
meant are not serial, with one following the other, but instead seem to impact on each other
in a dynamic process of parallel ‘mutual adjustment’ (see e.g. Carston, 2002; Wilson, 2004;
page 38 of 51
Sperber & Wilson, 2005 for post-Gricean description of this process; and e.g. Spotorno et al.,
2012; Vanlangendonck et al., 2018; Paunov et al., 2019 for neuroscientific evidence). Further
and deeper integration of findings in psycholinguistics and cognitive pragmatics are import-
ant future research goals (Noveck, 2018); but in any case, the evolutionary emergence of
these dedicated capacities must have followed, rather than preceded, the evolutionary emer-
Historically speaking, pragmatics has been situated on the periphery of the language sci-
ences, appearing in textbooks usually only as a fringe topic. We have argued, in contrast, that
cognitive capacities for ostensive communication are foundational, because they unleash ex-
pression on a grand scale. This in turn redefines the domain of pragmatics itself. Rather than
being narrowly conceived as the study of how context influences the interpretation of utter-
terised as the study of how, and the many means by which, informative intentions are sat-
isfied. The core questions for pragmatics are how informative intentions are made manifest,
and to what effect. Language use and other conventionalised means of expression are the
most salient specific instances, and are clearly central to human sociality, but there are many
others too.
cognitive context. Human communication has long posed a challenge to evolutionary biology
and signalling theory, due to its versatility, diversity, and clear proneness to deception (§2).
We have described how this problem is resolved in humans, allowing truly unleashed expres-
sion (§5); described key graded differences between the specialised capacity of mind that
drives human communication and other means of social cognition (§3 & §4), some of which
are shared with other great apes (§7); and provided a crucial proof of evolvability, by relating
these graded differences to specific and distinctive aspects of the human social ecology (§6).
We also described how several different means of human expression each employ the relev-
ant cognitive capacities in interestingly different ways (§8). If we are right about this, then
page 39 of 51
the evolutionary emergence of specialised, cognitive means of manipulation and social vigil-
ance is a root cause of many of the most distinctive aspects of human behaviour and societ-
ies.
An essential future goal is to establish a formal foundation for this reconceived prag-
description of the phenomenon of interest, recognising its full complexity while simultan-
eously providing some provisional order and generality. We hope to have contributed to that
goal here, which is too often neglected in contemporary cognitive psychology and cognate
disciplines (Rozin, 2001; Rai & Fiske, 2010; Doliński, 2018; inter alia). Formal models build
others’ mental states, are a particularly promising direction (e.g. Shafto et al., 2014; Good-
man & Frank, 2016; Ho et al., 2019). Different specific models differ in the detail and we do
not subscribe to all of the assumptions made. 11 Moreover, we do not believe that any existing
model is sufficiently general to cover the full range of prototypical cases of communication
(pointing, gesture, inter alia), let alone the broader diversity we highlighted in §8. Nonethe-
less, we do believe that modelling human interaction in these terms is an important and
promising research direction. We hope that our description of the evolutionary and cognitive
foundations of human expression, in all its diversity, will aid this agenda.
More broadly, we agree with recent arguments that the human evolutionary sciences
are presently too ‘cognition blind’ (e.g. Morin, 2016; Heyes, 2019), and that greater theoret-
ical unity will be achieved by deeper consideration of the cognitive processes that underpin
otherwise diverse human behaviours. The case of communication and expression is, we be-
lieve, a clear case in point. Quite commonly, particular types of expressive behaviour (lan-
guage use, teaching, punishment, art, inter alia) are considered each in isolation, without
11Consider, for instance, the Rational Speech Act framework (Goodman & Frank, 2016). Here, com-
municative behaviours are assumed to have ‘literal’ meanings, independent of use, from which speak-
ers might deviate. We do not share this assumption; that is, we do not believe that there is any such
thing as ‘literal meaning’ so conceived. Indeed, this is one of the key points of difference between neo-
Gricean approaches and the post-Gricean approach we have adopted in this article (Sperber & Wilson,
2005; see also citations in §8.5, on the process of parallel mutual adjustment, which undermines the
notion of literal meaning).
page 40 of 51
much consideration of the possibility that they might in fact derive from the same underlying
biological trait: as if the evolution of running was considered in isolation from the evolution
of walking, when in fact both are derived sub-functions of the unified capacity for bipedal
locomotion. We have argued that the same applies here. Different types of human ‘expressive
Acknowledgements
For comments on previous drafts, we thank Josep Call, György Gergely, Günther Knoblich,
Dan Sperber, Cordula Vesper, and members of the Smash, Oscar and Aces research groups
at Central European University. For extensive discussions on the cognitive and evolutionary
basis of human expression, we thank the ‘Relevance Researchers Network’, and all members
of the Somics project, ‘Constructing social minds: Coordination, communication, & cultural
transmission’.
Conflicts of interest
None
page 41 of 51
References
page 42 of 51
Bray, E. E., Gnanadesikan, G. E., Horschler, D. J., Levy, K. M., Kennedy, B. S., Famula, T. R.,
& MacLean, E. L. (in press). Early-emerging and highly-heritable sensitivity to hu-
man communication in dogs. Current Biology.
Bugnyar, T., Reber, S. A., & Buckner, C. (2016). Ravens attribute visual access to unseen
competitors. Nature Communications, 7, 10506.
Bybee, J. L., & Beckner, C. (2010). Usage-based theory. In: B. Heine & H. Narrog (Eds.), The
Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Analysis (2nd ed.). OUP.
Calcott, B. (2009). Lineage explanations: Explaining how biological mechanisms change.
The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(1), 51-78.
Call, J. (2011). How artificial communication affects the communication and cognition of the
great apes. Mind & Language, 26(1), 1-20.
Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(5), 187-192.
Carey, S. (2009). The Origin Of Concepts. OUP.
Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts & Utterances. Blackwell.
Carston, R. (2004). Review of S. Levinson, ‘Presumptive Meanings: The theory of general-
ized conversational implicature’. Journal of Linguistics, 40(1), 181-186.
Cartmill, E. A., & Byrne, R. W. (2010). Semantics of primate gestures: intentional meanings
of orangutan gestures. Animal Cognition, 13(6), 793-804.
Chudek, M., & Henrich, J. (2011). Culture-gene coevolution, norm-psychology and the emer-
gence of human prosociality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(5), 218-226.
Clark, B. (2013). Relevance Theory. CUP.
Clark, H. H. (1996). Using Language. CUP.
Clark, H., Elsherif, M. M., & Leavens, D. A. (2019). Ontogeny vs. phylogeny in primate/canid
comparisons: A meta-analysis of the object choice task. Neuroscience & Biobehavi-
oral Reviews, 105, 178-189.
Clay, Z., & Tennie, C. (2018). Is overimitation a uniquely human phenomenon? Insights
from human children as compared to bonobos. Child Development, 89(5), 1535-1544.
Cornell, L. & Wharton, T. (in press). Before meaning: Creature construction, sea-sponges,
lizards and Humean projection. In: E. Ifantidou, L. de Saussure & T. Wharton (Eds.)
Beyond Meaning. John Benjamins.
Csibra, G. (2010). Recognizing communicative intentions in infancy. Mind & Language,
25(2), 141-168.
Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 148-
153.
Curioni, A., Vesper, C., Knoblich, G., & Sebanz, N. (2019). Reciprocal information flow and
role distribution support joint action coordination. Cognition, 187, 21-31.
Curry, O. S., Mullins, D. A., & Whitehouse, H. (2019). Is it good to cooperate? Testing the
theory of morality-as-cooperation in 60 societies. Current Anthropology, 60, 47-69.
Cushman, F., Sarin, A., & Ho., M. (in press). Punishment as communication. In: J. Doris &
M. Vargas (Eds.) Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology.
Danto, A. (1964). The Artworld. Journal of Philosophy, 61(19), 571–584.
page 43 of 51
Dawkins R., & Krebs J. R. (1978). Animal signals: Information or manipulation? In: J. Krebs
& N. Davies (Eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach (pp. 282-309).
Blackwell.
Debove, S., André, J. B., & Baumard, N. (2015). Partner choice creates fairness in humans.
Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 282(1808), 20150392.
Delton, A. W., & Robertson, T. E. (2012). The social cognition of social foraging: Partner se-
lection by underlying valuation. Evolution & Human Behavior, 33(6), 715-725.
Dessalles, J.-L. (1998). Altruism, status, & the origin of relevance. In: J. R. Hurford, M.
Studdert-Kennedy & C. Knight (Eds.), Approaches to the Evolution of Language (pp.
130-147). CUP.
Dickie, G. (1987). The art circle. Philosophical Review, 96, 141–146.
Diggle, S. P., Gardner, A., West, S. A., & Griffin, A. S. (2007). Evolutionary theory of bacterial
quorum sensing: when is a signal not a signal? Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 362(1483), 1241-1249.
Dissanayake, E. (1988). What is Art For? UWP.
Dissanayake, E. (2003). The core of art-Making special. Journal of the Canadian Associ-
ation for Curriculum studies, 1(2), 13-38.
Doliński, D. (2018). Is psychology still a science of behaviour? Social Psychological Bulletin,
13(2), 1-14.
Downey, G. (2008). Scaffolding imitation in Capoeira: Physical education & enculturation in
an Afro‐Brazilian art. American Anthropologist, 110(2), 204-213.
Duff, R. A. (2001). Punishment, Communication & Community. OUP.
Duranti, A. (2015). The Anthropology Of Intentions. CUP.
Emery, N. J., & Clayton, N. S. (2009). Comparative social cognition. Annual Review of Psy-
chology, 60, 87-113.
Enfield, N. J. (2003). Linguistic Epidemiology: Semantics & grammar of language contact
in mainland Southeast Asia. Routledge.
Enfield, N. J. (2014). Natural Causes Of Language. Language Science Press.
Engelmann, J. M., & Tomasello, M. (2019). Children’s sense of fairness as equal respect.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 23(6), 454-463.
Fay, N., Arbib, M., & Garrod, S. (2013). How to bootstrap a human communication system.
Cognitive Science, 37(7), 1356-1367.
Feinberg, J. (1965). The expressive function of punishment. The Monist, 49(3), 397-423.
Ferreira, F., & Patson, N. D. (2007). The ‘good enough’ approach to language comprehen-
sion. Language & Linguistics Compass, 1(1-2), 71-83.
Ferriere, R., Bronstein, J. L., Rinaldi, S., Law, R., & Gauduchon, M. (2002). Cheating and the
evolutionary stability of mutualisms. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B,
269(1493), 773-780.
Fitch, W. T., Huber, L., & Bugnyar, T. (2010). Social cognition and the evolution of language:
constructing cognitive phylogenies. Neuron, 65(6), 795-814.
Fodor, J. A. (2012). Déjà vu all over again: How Danto's aesthetics recapitulates the philo-
sophy of mind. In: M. Rollins (Ed.), Danto & His Critics (pp. 55–68). Wiley Black-
well.
page 44 of 51
Frank, R. H. (1988). Passions Within Reason. WW Norton & Co.
Frith, U., & Frith, C. (2010). The social brain: Allowing humans to boldly go where no other
species has been. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sci-
ences, 365(1537), 165-176.
Fröhlich, M., & Hobaiter, C. (2018). The development of gestural communication in great
apes. Behavioral Ecology & Sociobiology, 72(12), 194.
Genty, E., & Zuberbühler, K. (2014). Spatial reference in a bonobo gesture. Current Biology,
24(14), 1601-1605.
Gergely G. (2013). Ostensive communication and cultural learning: The natural pedagogy
hypothesis. In: J. Metcalfe & H. S. Terrace (Eds.). Agency & Joint Attention (pp. 139-
151). OUP.
Gergely, G. & Csibra, G. (2006). Sylvia's recipe: Human culture, imitation, and pedagogy. In:
N. Enfield & S. Levinson (Eds.), Roots of Human Sociality: Culture, Cognition &
Human Interaction (pp. 229-255). Berg Press.
Gibbs Jr, R. W., & Bryant, G. A. (2008). Striving for optimal relevance when answering ques-
tions. Cognition, 106(1), 345-369.
Goldberg, A. E. (2003). Constructions: A new theoretical approach to language. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 7(5), 219-224.
Goldberg, A., & Suttle, L. (2010). Construction grammar. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews:
Cognitive Science, 1(4), 468-477.
Goldin-Meadow, S. (2005). The Resilience Of Language. Psychology Press.
Goodman, N. D., & Frank, M. C. (2016). Pragmatic language interpretation as probabilistic
inference. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(11), 818-829.
Gómez, J. C. (1996). Ostensive behavior in great apes: The role of eye contact. In: A. Russon
et al. (Eds.), Reaching Into Thought (pp. 131-151). CUP.
Graham, K. E., Hobaiter, C., Ounsley, J., Furuichi, T., & Byrne, R. W. (2018). Bonobo and
chimpanzee gestures overlap extensively in meaning. PLoS Biology 16, e2004825.
Granito, C., Tehrani, J., Kendal, J., & Scott-Phillips, T. (2019). Style of pictorial representa-
tion is shaped by intergroup contact. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 1, e8.
Green, M. (2007). Self-Expression. OUP.
Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. The Philosophical Review, 66(3), 377-388.
Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic & conversation. In: P. Cole & J. Morgan, Syntax & Semantics III:
Speech Acts (pp. 41-58). Academic Press.
Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies In The Way Of Words. HUP.
Grosse, G., Scott-Phillips, T. & Tomasello, M. (2013). Three-year-olds hide their communic-
ative intentions in appropriate contexts. Developmental Psychology, 49(11),
2095-2101.
Guilford, T., & Dawkins, M. S. (1991). Receiver psychology and the evolution of animal sig-
nals. Animal Behaviour, 42(1), 1-14.
Hagoort, P. (2017). The core and beyond in the language-ready brain. Neuroscience &
Biobehavioral Reviews, 81, 194-204.
Hampton, J. (1992). An expressive theory of punishment. In: W. Cragg (Ed.), Retributivism
& Its Critics (pp. 1-21). Franz Steiner Verlag.
page 45 of 51
Hartmann, S., & Pleyer, M. (2021). Constructing a protolanguage: Reconstructing prehistoric
languages in a usage-based construction grammar framework. Philosophical Trans-
actions of the Royal Society B, 376(1824), 20200200.
Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., & Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics
do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59(4), 771-785.
Heintz, C. (2011). Presuming placeholders are relevant enables conceptual change (com-
mentary on S. Carey, ‘Précis of The Origin of Concepts’). Behavioral & Brain Sci-
ences, 34(3), 131.
Heintz, C., Karabegovic, M., & Molnar, A. (2016). The co-evolution of honesty and strategic
vigilance. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 1503.
Heintz, C., & Scott-Phillips, T. (2020). Gradualism in the evolution of ostensive communica-
tion. In: A. Ravignani et al. (Eds.), The Evolution of Language: Proceedings of the
12th International Conference (pp. 144-154).
Heyes, C. (2019) Cognition blindness and cognitive gadgets. Behavioral & Brain Sciences,
42, e187.
Ho, M. K., Cushman, F., Littman, M. L., & Austerweil, J. L. (2019). People teach with re-
wards and punishments as communication, not reinforcements. Journal of Experi-
mental Psychology: General, 148(3), 520-549.
Hoehl, S., Keupp, S., Schleihauf, H., McGuigan, N., Buttelmann, D., & Whiten, A. (2019).
‘Over-imitation’: A review and appraisal of a decade of research. Developmental Re-
view, 51, 90-108.
Hoffman, M., Yoeli, E., & Nowak, M. A. (2015). Cooperate without looking: Why we care
what people think and not just what they do. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, 112(6), 1727-1732.
Hoppitt, W. J., Brown, G. R., Kendal, R., Rendell, L., Thornton, A., Webster, M. M., & La-
land, K. N. (2008). Lessons from animal teaching. Trends in Ecology & Evolution,
23(9), 486-493.
Horner, V., & Whiten, A. (2005). Causal knowledge and imitation/emulation switching in
chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) and children (Homo sapiens). Animal Cognition,
8(3), 164-181.
Hrdy, S. B., & Burkart, J. M. (2020). The emergence of emotionally modern humans: Im-
plications for language and learning. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society
B, 375(1803), 20190499.
Hurford, J. R. (2007). Origins Of Meaning. OUP.
Jacob, P., & Scott-Phillips, T. (2020). Is mindreading a gadget? Synthese.
Jaeggi, A. V., Burkart, J. M., & van Schaik, C. P. (2010). On the psychology of cooperation in
humans and other primates: Combining the natural history and experimental evid-
ence of prosociality. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological
Sciences, 365(1553), 2723-2735.
Johansson, S. (2021). The Dawn of Language. MacLehose Press.
Johnston, A. M., Holden, P. C., & Santos, L. R. (2017). Exploring the evolutionary origins of
overimitation: A comparison across domesticated and non-domesticated canids. De-
velopmental Science, 20(4), e12460.
page 46 of 51
Karabegovic, M., & Heintz, C. (under review). Changing the mind, not the heart: Credible
evidence in prosocial displays.
Kegl, J., Senghas, A., & Coppola, M. (1999). Creation through contact: Sign language emer-
gence & sign language change in Nicaragua. In: M. DeGraff (Ed.), Language Creation
& Language Change: Creolization, diachrony & development (pp. 179-237). MIT
Press.
Király, I., Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2013). Beyond rational imitation: Learning arbitrary
means actions from communicative demonstrations. Journal of Experimental Child
Psychology, 116(2), 471-486.
Kline, M. A. (2015). How to learn about teaching: An evolutionary framework for the study of
teaching behavior in humans and other animals. Behavioral & Brain Sciences, 38.
Krebs, J. R., & Dawkins, R. (1984). Animal signals: Mindreading and manipulation. In: J.
Krebs & N. Davies (Eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach (2nd
ed.) (pp. 380-402). OUP.
Krems, J. A., Williams, K. E. G., Aktipis, A., & Kenrick, D. T. (2021). Friendship jealousy:
One tool for maintaining friendships in the face of third-party threats? Journal of
Personality & Social Psychology, 120(4), 977-1012.
Lachmann, M., Szamado, S., & Bergstrom, C. T. (2001). Cost and conflict in animal signals
and human language. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98(23),
13189-13194.
Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated Learning: Legitimate peripheral participation. CUP.
Leaver, L. A., Hopewell, L., Caldwell, C., & Mallarky, L. (2007). Audience effects on food
caching in grey squirrels (Sciurus carolinensis): Evidence for pilferage avoidance
strategies. Animal Cognition, 10(1), 23-27.
Legare, C. H., & Nielsen, M. (2015). Imitation and innovation: The dual engines of cultural
learning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 19(11), 688-699.
Leroux, M., & Townsend, S. W. (2020). Call combinations in great apes and the evolution of
syntax. Animal Behavior & Cognition, 7(2), 131-139.
Levinson, S. C. (2006). On the human ‘interactional engine’. In: Wenner-Gren International
Symposium Series (pp. 39-69). Berg Publishers.
Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive Meanings. MIT Press.
Levinson, S. C., & Holler, J. (2014). The origin of human multi-modal communication.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 369(1651),
20130302.
Lyons, D. E., Young, A. G., & Keil, F. C. (2007). The hidden structure of overimitation. Pro-
ceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104, 19751-19756.
Marchand, T. H. (2010). Embodied cognition and communication: Studies with British fine
woodworkers. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 16, S100-S120.
Maynard Smith, J., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal Signals. OUP.
McCallum, K., Mitchell, S., & Scott-Phillips, T. (2020). The art experience. Review of Philo-
sophy & Psychology, 11, 21-35.
McEllin, L., Sebanz, N., & Knoblich, G. (2018a). Identifying others’ informative intentions
from movement kinematics. Cognition, 180, 246-258.
page 47 of 51
McEllin, L., Knoblich, G., & Sebanz, N. (2018b). Distinct kinematic markers of demonstra-
tion and joint action coordination? Evidence from virtual xylophone playing. Journal
of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance, 44(6), 885-897.
Meir, I., Sandler, W., Padden, C., and Aronoff, M. (2010). Emerging sign languages. In: M.
Marschark & P. E. Spencer (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Deaf Studies, Language
& Education, Volume 2 (pp.267-280). OUP.
Mercier, H. (2017). How gullible are we? A review of the evidence from psychology and social
science. Review of General Psychology, 21(2), 103-122.
Mercier, H. & Sperber, D. (2009) Intuitive and reflective inferences. In: J. Evans & K. Frank-
ish (Eds.), In Two Minds: Dual Processes & Beyond (pp. 149-170). Oxford University
Press.
Moll, H., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Cooperation and human cognition: The Vygotskian intel-
ligence hypothesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological
Sciences, 362(1480), 639-648.
Moore, R. (2017). Convergent minds: Ostension, inference and Grice’s third clause. Interface
Focus, 7, 20160107.
Morin, O. (2016). How Traditions Live & Die. OUP.
Motamedi, Y., Schouwstra, M., Smith, K., Culbertson, J., & Kirby, S. (2019). Evolving artifi-
cial sign languages in the lab: From improvised gesture to systematic sign. Cognition,
192, 103964.
Nielsen, M., & Tomaselli, K. (2010). Overimitation in Kalahari Bushman children and the
origins of human cultural cognition. Psychological Science, 21(5), 729-736.
Newman-Norlund, S. E., Noordzij, M. L., Newman-Norlund, R. D., Volman, I. A., De Ruiter,
J. P., Hagoort, P., & Toni, I. (2009). Recipient design in tacit communication. Cogni-
tion, 111(1), 46-54.
Noë, R., & Hammerstein, P. (1995). Biological markets. Trends in Ecology & Evolution,
10(8), 336-339.
Noveck, I. (2018). Experimental Pragmatics: The making of a cognitive science. CUP.
Nowak, M. A., & Sigmund, K. (2005). Evolution of indirect reciprocity. Nature, 437(7063),
1291-1298.
Origgi, G. (2004). Is trust an epistemological notion? Episteme, 1(1), 61-72.
Origgi, G. (2005). A stance of trust. In: 9th International Pragmatics Conference (IPRA).
Padilla Cruz, M. (Ed.). (2016). Relevance Theory: Recent developments, current challenges
& future directions. John Benjamins.
Paunov, A. M., Blank, I. A., & Fedorenko, E. (2019). Functionally distinct language and The-
ory of Mind networks are synchronized at rest and during language comprehension.
Journal of Neurophysiology, 121(4), 1244-1265.
Pezzulo, G., Donnarumma, F., Dindo, H., D’Ausilio, A., Konvalinka, I., & Castelfranchi, C.
(2019). The body talks: Sensorimotor communication and its brain and kinematic
signatures. Physics of Life Reviews, 28, 1-21.
Pignocchi, A. (2019) The continuity between art and everyday communication. In: F. Cova &
S. Rehault (Eds), Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Aesthetics (pp. 241–266).
Bloomsbury.
Primoratz, I. (1989). Punishment as language. Philosophy, 64(248), 187-205.
page 48 of 51
Progovac, L. (2015). Evolutionary Syntax. OUP.
Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. (2010). ODD (observation-and description-deprived) psychological re-
search (commentary on Henrich et al., ‘The weirdest people in the world?’). Behavi-
oral & Brain Sciences, 33(2-3), 106.
Royka, A., Aboody, R., & Jara-Ettinger, J. (2018). Movement as a message: inferring com-
municative intent from actions. In: Proceedings of the 40th Annual Conference of the
Cognitive Science Society.
Rozin, P. (2001). Social psychology and science: Some lessons from Solomon Asch. Person-
ality & Social Psychology Review, 5(1), 2-14.
Raviv, L., Meyer, A., & Lev-Ari, S. (2019). Larger communities create more systematic lan-
guages. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 286(1907), 20191262.
Schmid, H.-J. (2020). The Dynamics Of The Linguistic System: Usage, conventionalization,
& entrenchment. OUP.
Schmitz, L., Vesper, C., Sebanz, N., & Knoblich, G. (2018). When height carries weight:
Communicating hidden object properties for joint action. Cognitive Science, 42(6),
2021-2059.
Scott-Phillips, T. (2008). Defining biological communication. Journal of Evolutionary Bio-
logy, 21(2), 387-395.
Scott-Phillips, T. (2010). The evolution of relevance. Cognitive Science, 34(4), 583-601.
Scott-Phillips, T. (2015). Speaking Our Minds. Palgrave Macmillan.
Scott-Phillips, T. (2017). Pragmatics and the aims of language evolution. Psychonomic Bul-
letin & Review, 24(1), 186-189.
Scott-Phillips, T., Blythe, R., Gardner, A. & West, S. (2012). How do communication systems
emerge? Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B, 279, 1943-1949.
Scott-Phillips, T. C., Dickins, T. E., & West, S. A. (2011). Evolutionary theory and the ulti-
mate-proximate distinction in the human behavioral sciences. Perspectives on Psy-
chological Science, 6(1), 38-47.
Scott-Phillips, T., Diggle, S., Gurney, J., Ivens, A. & Popat, R. (2014). Combinatorial commu-
nication in bacteria: Implications for the origins of linguistic generativity. PLoS One,
9(4), e95929.
Scott-Phillips, T., Kirby, S., & Ritchie, G. R. S. (2009). Signalling signalhood and the emer-
gence of communication. Cognition, 113(2), 226-233.
Schouwstra, M., & de Swart, H. (2014). The semantic origins of word order. Cognition,
131(3), 431-436.
Searcy, W. A., & Nowicki, S. (2005). The Evolution Of Animal Communication. PUP.
Sebanz, N., Bekkering, H., & Knoblich, G. (2006). Joint action: Bodies and minds moving
together. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(2), 70-76.
Seyfarth, R. M., & Cheney, D. L. (2018). The Social Origins Of Language. PUP.
Shafto, P., Goodman, N. D., & Griffiths, T. L. (2014). A rational account of pedagogical reas-
oning: Teaching by, and learning from, examples. Cognitive Psychology, 71, 55-89.
Sommers, R. (2021). Experimental jurisprudence. Science, 373(6553), 394-395.
Spelke, E. S. (1990). Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science, 14(1), 29-56.
page 49 of 51
Spelke, E. S., & Kinzler, K. D. (2007). Core knowledge. Developmental Science, 10(1), 89-96.
Sperber. D. (2000). Metarepresentations in an evolutionary perspective. In D. Sperber (Ed.),
Metarepresentations: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 117-137). OUP.
Sperber, D. (2013) Speakers are honest because hearers are vigilant: Reply to Kourken Mi-
chaelian. Episteme 10(1), 61-71.
Sperber, D. (2019). Personal notes on a shared trajectory. In: K. Scott et al. (Eds.), Relev-
ance, Pragmatics & Interpretation (pp. 13-20). CUP.
Sperber, D., & Baumard, N. (2012). Moral reputation: An evolutionary and cognitive per-
spective. Mind & Language, 27(5), 495-518.
Sperber, D., Clément, F., Heintz, C., Mascaro, O., Mercier, H., Origgi, G., & Wilson, D.
(2010). Epistemic vigilance. Mind & Language, 25(4), 359-393.
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1986/1995). Relevance: Communication & cognition. Blackwell.
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (2002) Pragmatics, modularity & mind-reading. Mind &
Language 17, 3-23.
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (2005) Pragmatics. In: F. Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), Oxford
Handbook of Philosophy of Language. OUP.
Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (2015) Beyond speaker’s meaning. Croatian Journal of Philo-
sophy, 15(44), 117-149.
Spotorno, N., Koun, E., Prado, J., van der Henst, J. B., & Noveck, I. A. (2012). Neural evid-
ence that utterance-processing entails mentalizing: The case of irony. NeuroImage,
63(1), 25-39.
Sripada, C. S. (2005). Punishment and the strategic structure of moral systems. Biology &
Philosophy, 20(4), 767-789.
Sterelny, K. (2012). Language, gesture, skill: The co-evolutionary foundations of language.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367(1599), 2141-2151.
Sterelny, K. (2017). From code to speaker meaning. Biology & Philosophy, 32(6), 819-838.
Sugiyama, M. S. (in press). Co-occurrence of ostensive communication and generalizable
knowledge in forager storytelling. Human Nature.
Tauzin, T., & Gergely, G. (2018). Communicative mind-reading in preverbal infants. Scientif-
ic Reports, 8(1), 1-9.
Thornton, A., & Raihani, N. J. (2008). The evolution of teaching. Animal Behaviour, 75(6),
1823-1836.
Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing A Language. HUP.
Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins Of Human Communication. MIT Press.
Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., & Liszkowski, U. (2007). A new look at infant pointing. Child
Development, 78(3), 705-722.
Topál, J., Kis, A., & Oláh, K. (2014). Dogs’ sensitivity to human ostensive cues: A unique ad-
aptation? In: J. Kaminski & S. Marshall-Pescini (Eds.), The Social Dog: Behaviour &
cognition (pp.319-346). Academic Press.
Townsend, S. W., Engesser, S., Stoll, S., Zuberbühler, K., & Bickel, B. (2018). Compositional-
ity in animals and humans. PLoS Biology, 16(8), e2006425.
page 50 of 51
Townsend, S. W., Koski, S. E., Byrne, R. W., Slocombe, K. E., Bickel, B., Boeckle, M., Braga
Goncalves, I., Burkart, J. M., Flower, T., Gaunet, F., Glock, H. J., Gruber, T., Jansen,
D. A. W. A. M., Liebal, K., Linke, A., Miklósi, Á., Moore, R., van Schaik, C. P., Stoll, S.,
Vail, A., Waller, B. M., Wild, M., Zuberbühler, K., Manser, M. B. (2017). Exorcising
Grice’s ghost: An empirical approach to studying intentional communication in an-
imals. Biological Reviews, 92(3), 1427-1433.
Vanlangendonck, F., Willems, R. M., & Hagoort, P. (2018). Taking common ground into ac-
count: Specifying the role of the mentalizing network in communicative language
production. PLoS One, 13(10), e0202943.
van der Henst, J.-B., Carles, L., & Sperber, D. (2002). Truthfulness and relevance in telling
the time. Mind & Language, 17, 457-466.
Vesper, C., Abramova, E., Bütepage, J., Ciardo, F., Crossey, B., Effenberg, A., Hristova., D.,
Karlinsky., A., McEllin, L., Nijssen, S. R. R., Schmitz, L., & Wahn, B. (2017). Joint ac-
tion: Mental representations, shared information and general mechanisms for co-
ordinating with others. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 2039.
Vesper, C., Butterfill, S., Knoblich, G., & Sebanz, N. (2010). A minimal architecture for joint
action. Neural Networks, 23(8-9), 998-1003.
Völter, C. J., Rossano, F., & Call, J. (2015). From exploitation to cooperation: Social tool use
in orang-utan mother–offspring dyads. Animal Behaviour, 100, 126-134.
Wharton, T. (2006). The evolution of pragmatics. The Elsevier Encyclopaedia of Language
& Linguistics (pp. 338-345).
Wharton, T. (2009). Pragmatics & Non-Verbal Communication. CUP.
Wilson, D. (2004). Relevance and lexical pragmatics. UCL Working Papers In Linguistics,
16, 343-360.
Wilson, D., & Sperber, D. (2012). Meaning & Relevance. CUP.
Wynne, C. D. (2016). What is special about dog cognition? Current Directions in Psycholo-
gical Science, 25(5), 345-350.
Zuberbühler, K. (2018). Intentional communication in primates. Revue Tranel, 68, 69-75.
page 51 of 51