Defining Determinism
Defining Determinism
69 (2018), 215–252
Defining Determinism
Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
1 Introduction
2 Determinism in Philosophy of Science: Three Approaches
2.1 Determinism: The core idea and how to spell it out
2.2 The three approaches in more detail
2.3 Representing indeterminism
3 Orthodoxy: DMAP, with Invocations of DEQN
4 Branching-Style Determinism (DBRN)
4.1 Models and realizations
4.2 Faithfulness
4.3 Two types of branching topologies
5 Comparing the Approaches
5.1 Case studies
5.2 Formal comparison of the DMAP and DBRN frameworks
6 Conclusions
ß The Author 2016. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of British Society for the Philosophy of Science.
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Non-Commercial License
(http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium,
doi:10.1093/bjps/axv049 provided the original work is properly cited. For commercial re-use, please contact journals.permissions@oup.com
Advance Access published on May 5, 2016
216 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
1 Introduction
In this article we describe how a definition of determinism based on branch-
ing models supplements and improves current treatments of determinism of
scientific theories in physics. Our focus is on a definition of determinism that
takes a scientific theory as input, and delivers a verdict as to the theory’s
determinism as output, providing one bit of information. This may seem to
be a simple matter, but in practice a number of subtle issues are involved: In
THEORY:
Deterministic?
topology. In Section 5, which comprises the bulk of the article, we compare the
three approaches to defining determinism, with a view to making good our
claim of the usefulness of DBRN. We proceed in two steps: First (Section 5.1),
we give three examples of the application of the three approaches to physical
theories, referring to Newtonian mechanics, quantum mechanics, and general
relativity (GR). We show in which ways the DBRN definition comes natu-
rally, including the construction of an explicit mathematical model. A perhaps
surprising result from our case studies is that the DMAP definition, despite its
status as official orthodoxy, is hardly ever used, and that the DEQN definition
218 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
1
It is possible to express this core idea without tensed notions, by saying that each event permits
at most one possible subsequent course of events. We will stick to the tensed version in terms of
present state and future development in what follows.
2
Thanks to Balázs Gyenis for discussion of this point.
220 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
the resources needed for assessing the theory’s determinism: a theory’s defining
differential equations assume the role of laws of nature, and solutions to these
equations stand in for physically possible worlds. On the assumption that different
solutions to a theory’s defining equations represent different physically possible
worlds, determinism then boils down to the existence of a unique solution for each
appropriate initial value—this is the essence of the DEQN approach.
2.2.1 DEQN
The equation-based definition of determinism represents the mathematical per-
spective of present physicists, focusing on a theory’s defining (differential) equa-
tions. The leading question is whether for each initial condition there exists a
unique solution for these equations. It turns out that the answer depends on
what kind of differential equations one considers. For ordinary differential
equations (ODEs), there are general methods that allow for a conditional state-
ment of the existence and uniqueness of solutions. In contrast to the tractable
landscape of ODEs, there are no useful general results concerning the existence
and uniqueness of solutions to partial differential equations.
It is important to distinguish here between global existence and local exis-
tence of solutions, where ‘global’ refers to the full range of the time parameter,
and ‘local’ indicates a neighbourhood (possibly arbitrarily small) of a given
moment of time. The question of the existence and uniqueness of solutions
thus splits into two problems. First, is there a unique local solution for each
moment of time? And if the answer to that question is positive, are such local
solutions uniquely extendible to the full, global range of the time parameter?
Now, for an ODE dx dt ¼ f ðx; tÞ, the Peano theorem establishes that for every
initial condition there is at least one local solution of the equation—provided
that the function, f, is bounded and continuous. Further, the Picard–Lindelöf
theorem states that, provided the function f satisfies the so-called Lipschitz
condition, for every initial condition an ODE has at most one local solution.
3
As Wilson ([1989]) remarks, this picture may be unjustified when it comes to assessing, for
example, the determinism or indeterminism of classical mechanics: breakdowns of the determin-
ism of the theory will normally lead to the incorporation of additional assumptions or additional
bits of theory, rather than a flat-out admission of indeterminism. The point remains, however,
that at any stage of practical assessment, one can consider ‘what’s currently on the table’, and a
definition of determinism has to apply at any such stage.
Defining Determinism 221
These results extend to ODEs of arbitrary order and carry over to sets of
ODEs as well.4 As to the extendibility of local solutions to an ODE to a
global solution, in general, the answer is in the negative, though for some
classes of ODEs, under certain conditions, extendibility holds. This is highly
pertinent to the assessment of determinism, as it is global uniqueness that
naturally corresponds to determinism, whereas the mentioned theorems con-
ditionally assure the existence and uniqueness of merely local solutions. Non-
2.2.2 DMAP
The mapping-based approach to defining determinism amounts to current
orthodoxy in philosophy of science (see Section 3). This approach takes deter-
minism to be a matter of the existence of suitable mappings in the whole space
of a theory’s temporal realizations. The approach is grounded in Montague’s
([1974]) pioneering formal investigations of deterministic theories from a logi-
cal point of view. Speaking abstractly, the diagnosis of determinism according
to DMAP is a two-stage affair. In a first step, all of the individual realizations
of the linear temporal development of systems falling under the theory are put
side by side. These are the separate possible ways a world could be that are
admitted by the theory. Depending on the theory in question, these could be
all the solutions to the theory’s defining equations, or a class of temporal
realizations that is given in some other, perhaps more complex manner
(quantum mechanics in a consistent histories formulation would be a case
in point here; see Section 5.1.2). In a second step, this class of temporal
developments is checked for instances of indeterminism, in the following
way: If there are two realizations that can be identified at one time,5 but
whose future segments after that time cannot be identified, this signals
4
For a rigorous statement of the mentioned theorems and some useful discussions, see (Arnol’d
[1992]).
5
Instead of identification at a time, for some theories it is necessary to consider identification over
an arbitrarily short interval of time, or over initial segments of temporal developments.
222 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
indeterminism. If the test fails, that is, if all realizations that can be identified
at one time can also be identified at all future times, then the theory is deter-
ministic. The type of mapping that is used to identify different realizations at
different times plays a subtle but crucial role for this definition (see Section 3).
The DMAP definition corresponds to a divergence analysis of future pos-
sibilities, which is popular in current metaphysics (Lewis [1986]). Individual
realizations (ways a world could be) are ‘modally thin’, in that they harbour
2.2.3 DBRN
An alternative understanding of future possibilities underlies the branching-
based DBRN characterization of the determinism of theories. Doing justice to
the philosophical idea of alternative future possibilities, in a branching con-
ception a single model is so construed such that it can contain multiple pos-
sibilities. The existence of possibilities is intrinsic to a model, and a model can
thus be modally thick. Rather than opting for linearly ordered temporal rea-
lizations as in DMAP, a branching model is generally only partially ordered in
a tree-like manner; the individual realizations form linear chains (histories)
within that partial ordering. Within one partial ordering, these histories are
bound together by overlapping up to a certain time, so that there is no need to
look for the identifying mappings needed for DMAP. The diagnosis of inde-
terminism is very simple: if there is a model that is not linearly ordered (such a
model contains more than one history), then the theory is indeterministic. A
deterministic theory is one all models of which are linear.
THEORY:
Indeterministic
Linear Partially
6
For affirmations of a similar general outlook, see, for example, (Bishop [2006]; Hoefer [2010]).
7
In this section we stick to Butterfield’s use of ‘model’ for what we generally call ‘realization’ or
‘history’, that is, for a single, linear temporal time-course of the development of a system.
224 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
we say that a theory is deterministic if, and only if: for any two of its
models, if they have instantaneous slices that are isomorphic, then the
corresponding final segments are also isomorphic.
8
Note that a defining feature of manifolds, local Euclidicity, together with the Hausdorff prop-
erty (typically assumed for manifolds in physics applications) implies that there is no branching
in M. As a consequence, there is no way for M to represent alternative possible events; M is
only interpretable as a totality of spatiotemporal events. One might worry that to account for
alternative possible events via branching, either local Euclidicity or the Hausdorff property for
space-times must be sacrificed. We will return to this worry and dismiss it in Section 4.3.
9
See (Halvorson [2012]) for similar issues that arise for attempts to specify a theory in language-
independent terms.
10
For GR, the promissory note is repaid (although not in a strictly logical sense, as no language is
specified) in (Butterfield [1989]). ‘Isomorphism’ is used there in the sense applicable to mani-
folds. A diffeomorphism is a smooth bijection between two manifolds M and M0 . Two models,
hM; Oi i and hM0 ; O0i i, are called isomorphic if and only if there is a diffeomorphism, d, between
the manifolds M and M0 , and for the objects Oi, we have d ðOi Þ ¼ O0i (where d ðOi Þ is the object
Oi dragged along by the diffeomorphism d). The definition of determinism is then as follows:
Here, the correspondence between the set O and the set of genuine physical
states is crucial. Since elements of O may have mathematical surplus structure,
the failure of the requirement that ‘if H1 ðtÞ ¼ H2 ðtÞ for some t, then H1 ðtÞ
¼ H2 ðtÞ for all t’ need not signal indeterminism. It is a typical situation in
physics, and not some mere philosophical possibility of theoretical under-
determination, that a theory’s mathematical descriptions correspond many-
to-one to physical states, so that the identity in the above quotation needs to
be replaced by a broader notion of agreement. Consider classical electromag-
netism, where the electric field, E, and the magnetic field, B, are derived from a
scalar potential, ’, and a vector potential, A. The relation between A; and
E; B is many-to-one: for any smooth function , the potentials A; ’, and the
potentials
qc
A0 ¼ A þ rc; ’0 ¼ ’ ;
qt
represent the same physical situation, and the same E and B fields. The trans-
formation A ° A0 ; ’ ° ’0 is called a gauge transformation. The arbitrariness
of the choice of means that the theory has surplus mathematical structure
(‘gauge freedom’). For a theory with gauge freedom, the fact that two realiza-
tions have the same mathematical state at a certain t, but different states at
some later t0 , is not of itself indicative of indeterminism; it could also be that
the states at t0 represent the same physical state by different mathematical
means. It will not do to demand that only theories without gauge degrees of
freedom are considered, since there are good scientific reasons for allowing
that kind of freedom in our physical theories.12 Thus, to decide the question of
determinism of a theory requires us to decide whether the divergence of reali-
zations results from gauge freedom or not. This is conceptually difficult, as
11
Although Earman focuses on future- and past-oriented determinism, whereas Butterfield ana-
lyses future-oriented determinism, each explication can be readily extended to accommodate
both versions of determinism.
12
As Earman ([2006], p. 1381) points out, attempts at treating gauge degrees of freedom as
physical quantities subject to dynamical laws are generally not fruitful.
226 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
So far, this is just passing the buck. To see in what way branching is
involved, we need to specify a sense of ‘model’, ‘faithful’, and ‘indeterministic’
such that a model of a theory can be both faithful and indeterministic.
A chain in hM; <i is a linear subset; by virtue of Zorn’s lemma, there are
maximal chains in M. A tree-like order hM; <i can contain more than one
maximal chain, as in the lower right of Figure 2 (see also Figure 3).16 It is
usually sensible to require that all maximal chains in M be order-isomorphic,
for example, all isomorphic to hR; <R i.
Based on this notion of a model, the following definition of determinism is
adequate:
The existence of more than one maximal chain in hM; <i means that there is
more than one realization in the model hM; <; S; f i, since each maximal chain
h M in the model specifies a realization hh; <jh ; S; fjh i, simply by restricting
f to h, as hh; <jh i is a linear order. Accordingly, a deterministic model of a
theory contains just one realization, whereas an indeterministic model bundles
15
See also (Belnap et al. [2001], Chapter 7A) and, for the related framework of branching space-
times, (Belnap [1992], [2012]).
16
Provably, M contains more than one maximal chain if and only if it contains at least one upward
fork, that is, three moments, x, y, and z, for which x < y, x < z, but there is no common upper
bound for y and z, which holds if and only if neither y z nor z < y.
Defining Determinism 229
4.2 Faithfulness
There is one loose end left to tie up: So far, we have seen that it would be
possible to produce an indeterministic model from a linearly ordered, deter-
ministic model hM; <; S; f i simply by adding a disjoint copy of a final segment
of M to create a forward-branching structure, and extending f on the new
branch by copying. This would be indeterminism on the cheap. We will require
a faithful branching model that contains no difference in the ordering without
a corresponding difference in states.17 On a strict reading, faithfulness requires
a difference in states at, or immediately after, the splitting of any two histories.
In the case of what we will call case (b) branching (such that branching
histories have a first moment of disagreement, see Section 4.3), this boils
down to the requirement that the first moments of difference in two histories
have different states assigned.18 In case (a) branching, where there is a max-
imal moment in the intersection of two histories, faithfulness means that states
should be different immediately after such a maximal moment. This can be
made more precise by adding a further structure that identifies moments
occurring at the same time in different histories.19
In Section 5.2, where we construct a DBRN representation of a system out
of a DMAP representation of a system, we will use a weaker concept of
faithfulness that simply requires that two branching histories must be different
state-wise. We will also discuss how to formally represent sameness of physical
states, given that physical states might have non-unique mathematical repre-
sentations resulting from gauge freedom or from the symmetries of a theory.
17
In some cases we may want to drop the requirement of faithfulness. For example, if we know
that a process is indeterministic and thus has to be modelled by a branching model, but the
assigned states agree on two different maximal chains, this may signal that the theory is incom-
plete. In the present context, however, our aim is to diagnose (in)determinism, and so we are
methodologically required to assume completeness.
18
In the case of Figure 3(b), we thus want f ð01 Þ 6¼ f ð02 Þ.
19
See (Belnap et al. [2001], pp. 194–6) on instants as partitions of the set of moments. In the case of
Figure 3(a), if these instants have the plausible form ht1 ; t2 i for t 2 Rþ , so that we can identify
the time of moment t1 on the upper track with the time of t2 on the lower track, we thus want that
for any t > 0 there is some t0 < t; t0 > 0, such that f ðt01 Þ 6¼ f ðt02 Þ.
230 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
(a) 11
-1 0
12
(b) 01 11
-1
Figure 3. Two types of branching. Both (a) and (b) depict two continuous histories
branching at point 0. In (a), point 0 is the shared maximum in the intersection. In
(b), the intersection of the histories has no maximum, and points 01 and 02 are
different minimal upper bounds of the intersection.
and the resulting space should be connected, one sees that case (a) fails to be
locally Euclidean (any open set containing 0 has to contain some initial
segment of both tracks), whereas case (b) is a generalized manifold
(a locally Euclidean space, in which, however, the Hausdorff condition fails
for 01 and 02).
In terms of the behaviour of differential equations—that is, taking the
function, f, to be provided by solutions to such equations—case (a) represents
21
The same paper voices the worry that branching implies a failure of the Hausdorff property.
232 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
Given the initial data rð0Þ ¼ 0 and dr=dtð0Þ ¼ 0, Equation (1) has a station-
ary solution r1 ðtÞ ¼ 0, as well as a family of solutions rb, parametrized by the
real-valued parameter b 0:
22
We stick to this simple choice of S here in order to keep the exposition simple. Nothing of
substance is changed if we take the system’s state at a moment to specify not just the particle’s
radial distance from the apex (S ¼ R), but that radial distance together with the particle’s
instantaneous momentum (S ¼ R2 ).
Defining Determinism 233
8
<0 if t b
rb ðtÞ ¼ ðt bÞ4 ð2Þ
: if t > b:
144
½t; b l ½t ; b if and only if t < t0 and ½t; b ¼ ½t; b0 . It can be proved that hM; li
0 0
satisfies the postulates for a tree-like partial ordering. hM; li has a family
þ
fhb gb2Rþ of maximal chains, where Rþ 0;1 ¼ R [ f0g [ f1g. We will associ-
0;1
ate h1 with the stationary solution, and hb, for 0 b < 1, with a solution in
which the mass point begins to move immediately after time t ¼ b.
23
It is important that the particle has been at the apex for all t < 0. If there is some first time t0 < 0
at which the particle is placed on the apex, the solutions have to satisfy rb ðtÞ ¼ 0 only for
t0 t b, and will not be time-translation symmetric. This would speak against counting
them as just one possibility.
234 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
We now construct the actual branching model. The function, f, for the
model is
8
<0 if t < b
(iii) f ð½t; bÞ ¼ ðt bÞ4 ð3Þ
: if t b:
144
Note that the model has a ‘stationary’ history, hh1 ; l; R; fjh1 i, representing
the mass point remaining stationary on the dome’s apex, as well as a family of
‘dynamic’ histories of the form hhb ; l; R; fjhb i (0 b < 1), representing the
mass point remaining on the apex until time b, and then moving in accordance
with Equation 2.24 The model exhibits (a)-type branching, since every inter-
section hb \ hb0 (with b 6¼ b0 ) has a maximum ½c; c (where c ¼ minfb; b0 g).
Finally, the model constructed above is faithful in our sense: if two maximal
chains hb and hb0 branch at a moment, then there is a difference in states
assigned to elements of hb and of hb0 immediately after that moment. The
verdict thus is that Norton’s dome is indeterministic.
We draw some morals from the application of DEQN, DMAP, and DBRN
to Norton’s dome in Section 5.1.4—after discussing two more cases.
problem or any other grand thing, we will sketch how determinism of quan-
tum mechanics is to be analysed through the lens of each of the three
approaches, focusing in particular on a branching-style representation of
that theory.
For the DEQN approach, the main fact is the form of the Schrödinger
equation,
qc
25
A good introduction to this field is (Earman [1986]). For a more mathematically advanced
treatment, see (Earman [2006]).
26
Those that admit multiple self-adjoint extensions; cf. (Earman [2006], p. 1401).
236 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
where at each chosen time ti, i ¼ 1; . . . ; m, the family contains projectors Phi
from an exhaustive set of ni mutually exclusive projectors P1i ; . . . ; Pni i ,
X
ni
Theorems similar to this hold for the Einstein equations with other data.32
From our perspective, the interesting point is that these theorems do not
prohibit a maximal Cauchy development of an initial data set from having
more than one non-isometric extension—the theorems only prohibit these
extensions from being globally hyperbolic. A case in point is provided by
the so-called polarized Gowdy space-time. This is a globally hyperbolic
space-time, defined for a restricted set of values of one coordinate, a
vacuum solution to the Einstein equations, and an MVCD of an appropriate
initial data set. When this space-time is extended for the full range of the
coordinate, some of its maximal extensions turn out not to be isometric
(Chruściel and Isenberg [1993], pp. 1623ff). These non-isometric extensions
might be viewed as possible histories of a faithful indeterministic model, yield-
ing the verdict that GR is indeterministic.33
The issue is, however, complicated. The mentioned non-isometric maximal
extensions of the polarized Gowdy space-time do not admit global time func-
tions and contain closed time-like curves (CTCs). This spells trouble for any
definition of determinism based on partial orderings, since there is no natural
antisymmetric ordering on a CTC. Accordingly, the notion of alternatives for
the future, which is basic to the core idea of indeterminism, makes sense only
locally, but not globally any more.34
32
Notably, (Ringström [2009], p. 147, Theorem 16.6) proves the existence of a maximal globally
hyperbolic development of the data for a specific model with matter, the so-called non-linear
scalar field model. In this case, the initial data sets are different from their counterparts in the
vacuum solution case, and embeddability applies to the matter field as well.
33
Non-isometric extensions of a maximal Cauchy development are deemed non-generic by the
strong cosmic censorship conjecture. In this spirit, (Chruściel and Isenberg [1993]) prove that
non-isometric extensions of a polarized Gowdy space-time are rare, in a measure-theoretical
sense, in the set of all extensions of that space-time. As there is little ground to equate ‘rare’ with
‘non-physical’, the example cannot be discounted easily. For a discussion of the strong cosmic
censorship conjecture in the context of polarized Gowdy space-times, see (Chruściel et al.
[1990]).
34
This calls for spelling out our Definition 2 of indeterminism in terms of modal forks: ‘A model is
indeterministic if and only if it contains at least one modal fork’; for the definition of modal
forks, see (Placek et al. [2014], p. 423). The two formulations coincide in the context of branch-
ing time, as any two histories in branching time form such a fork. The formulation in terms of
modal forks is, however, also applicable in the context of more complex branching theories in
which histories are not linearly ordered.
Defining Determinism 239
Certainly more work is needed to fully develop the core idea of indetermin-
ism with respect to space-times admitting CTCs. With respect to our approach
laid out in Section 4, we note the following: The main definition of the DBRN
approach, Definition 1, is still adequate due to its abstract nature. It will,
however, be necessary to extend the definition of an indeterministic model
(Definition 2) such that space-times admitting CTCs are covered as well, by
taking local alternatives into account.35 In parallel to this development, it will
with J some index set. Here, the Mj are the realizations characterizing the
system; any hTj ; <j i is a linear ordering of times (typically, hR; <R i); and
fj : Tj ° S is a specification of system states for times t 2 Tj . Furthermore,
A is a class of isomorphisms between realizations, allowing for the fact that
different mathematical structures may represent the same physics (see our
discussion of gauge transformations in Section 3 above.). Technically,
each 2 A is a mapping between realizations that preserves their structure,
which means that it specifies an order-preserving bijection identifying the
times across different realizations, and it maps corresponding system states
onto physically equivalent system states. In line with typical considerations in
physics, we will assume that the set of isomorphisms, A, has the structure of a
group, that is, elements of A can be combined such that (i) there is a neutral
element (the identity mapping, id), (ii) each element 2 A has an inverse
1 2 A for which 1 ¼ 1 ¼ id, and (iii) composition of elements is
associative, that is, ðgÞ ¼ ðÞg. As we will see, for the DMAP approach
36
Given an assessment of single systems as deterministic or indeterministic, the verdict transfers
immediately to the theory itself: a theory is indeterministic if and only if there is at least one
indeterministic system falling under it.
Defining Determinism 241
with I some index set. The Bi are the faithful branching models of the system’s
where hi are maximal chains in hBi ; <i i. We will say that an isomorphism, h,
restricted to a maximal chain, h, of some branching model is a linearization of
. There is a certain subtlety concerning the issue of where the linearizations
come from. Clearly, the set A contains automorphisms among branching
models (minimally, the identity), and these give rise to linearizations (one
takes B1 ¼ B2 in the formula above.) But the linearizations can also be
derived from isomorphisms reaching across different branching models
(take B1 6¼ B2 , above). (These linear mapping are partial automorphisms
within a branching model, but they are not derived from an automorphism,
but from an isomorphism between different models.) Faithfulness of a branch-
ing model is assessed by both sorts of isomorphisms between linear realiza-
tions. A branching model, Bi , will be declared unfaithful if it has two maximal
chains, h1 and h2, such that jh1 ðhh1 ; <jh1 ; S; fjh1 iÞ ¼ hh2 ; <jh2 ; S; fjh2 i for some
2 A. Observe that this isomorphism-based assessment uses a weaker notion
of faithfulness, which does not require a difference immediately after branch-
ing—it only requires absence of total isomorphism of linear realizations (com-
pare with Section 4.2, above). This weaker constraint will make it easier to
meet the demand of deriving a branching representation from a mapping
representation (see below).
242 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
5.2.1 DBRN
A system with faithful branching representation B is indeterministic if and
5.2.2 DMAP
In terms of the DMAP approach, the core idea of determinism translates into
the thought that agreement of two realizations up to some time implies their
total agreement.37 Thus, indeterminism means that there are two realizations
that agree up to some time, but disagree later on. Here, ‘agreement’—both
with respect to states and with respect to times—has to be spelled out in terms
of isomorphisms. In line with (Butterfield [2005]), the definition is as follows:
A system with mapping representation M is indeterministic if and only if there
are realizations Mk ¼ hTk ; <k ; fk i; Ml ¼ hTl ; <l ; fl i; k; l 2 J, for which there
is some t0 2 Tk and some 2 A such that
. for all t t0 ; fk ðtÞ ¼ ðfl ÞðtÞ, that is, the states on an initial segment can
be identified, but
. there is no 2 A mapping Mk wholly onto Ml , that is, no isomorphism
2 A for which fk ¼ fl .38
It should be clear from the form of the definition that the choice of A matters
greatly. Minimally, the set of isomorphisms has to contain the identity, but it is
a difficult matter to decide which other mappings are to be included for a given
system. The verdict about determinism can depend on that choice.
37
This idea is somewhat more general than the idea that agreement at some time, or in some small
region around some time, should imply global agreement. Our choice makes the DMAP/
DBRN comparison somewhat more transparent.
38
Our notation, fl or fl , indicates that an isomorphism 2 A maps function fl to function fl ,
thereby taking care of two things in accordance with our discussion above: mapping of times
and mapping of states.
Defining Determinism 243
Finally, we collect all the linear realizations in one set [i2I Ci , arriving at the
mapping structure
M ¼ h[i2I Ci ; AM i:
since that would contradict the faithfulness of the original branching repre-
sentation B.
If B is deterministic, the verdict as to the derived M need not coincide,
depending on how much information about isomorphisms is given through
A. As stated above, for branching structures the set A plays a double role.
On the one hand, A can provide information about the global fact that
two different branching models picture the same physical situation, because
turns out that the construction is somewhat involved and not unique, but the
verdicts agree.
We will derive a branching representation from a mapping representation
by successively constructing branching models from appropriate sets of reali-
zations. In such a set, any two realizations must be partially isomorphic, but
not globally isomorphic. More formally, let us call a subset fMk jk 2 Kg of the
set of realizations ‘good’ if and only if for any two k; l 2 K; k 6¼ l, there is
39
This is connected to the fact that the relation of being partially, but not globally, isomorphic is
not transitive, that is, it is not an equivalence relation.
40
The following construction is not unique, and it is not guaranteed to deliver branching models
that are intuitively satisfying. The construction does, however, fulfil all formal requirements.
246 Thomas Müller and Tomasz Placek
f 0n ðt0 Þ ¼ f 0m ðt0 Þ:
Next, our set of moments (the base set for the partial branching order) is
~
B :¼ B=&;
Note that the definition of & guarantees well-definedness, meaning that for
hs; mi 2 ½ht; ni, we have f 0n ðtÞ ¼ f 0m ðsÞ. It remains to define the partial ordering
< on the set of moments B:
½ht; ni < ½hs; mi
f 0n ðt0 Þ ¼ f 0m ðt0 Þ:
Pulling things together, adding all these branching models for all the good sets
into which the given set of realizations was partitioned, will give a full branching
representation for the system in question. It remains to specify the set AB of
isomorphisms. For the verdict of determinism or indeterminism, this subtle issue
is, however, not important, so that we can set AB to contain just the identity.
It is easy to see that by the given construction, a verdict as to determinism or
indeterminism of the mapping structure is retained in the branching structure.
In the case of determinism, all good sets are singletons, giving rise to only
linear, deterministic branching models. In the case of indeterminism, there will
be at least one non-trivial good set, giving rise to a faithful branching model
with at least two histories. Such a non-linear structure triggers the verdict of
indeterminism.
5.2.6 Summing up
As we saw, the relations between two representations of determinism, as
offered by DMAP and DBRN, are somewhat intricate. Their verdicts with
respect to a system’s determinism usually agree, but not always. That is, if
DBRN diagnoses a system as indeterministic, DMAP will concur. However, if
DBRN’s verdict is ‘determinism’, a DMAP analysis might disagree. In the
opposite direction verdicts agree, that is, if DMAP deems a system as deter-
ministic/indeterministic, DBRN will come with the same diagnosis. Although
the two approaches agree on the verdict in such cases, they might view the
underlying details differently, as the DMAP representation of determinism (or
Defining Determinism 247
6 Conclusions
Our aim in this article was to elaborate formally the core idea of determinism,
Acknowledgments
Thomas Müller
Fachbereich Philosophie
Universität Konstanz
Konstanz, Germany
Thomas.Mueller@uni-konstanz.de
Tomasz Placek
Department of Philosophy
Jagiellonian University
Krakow, Poland
Tomasz.Placek@uj.edu.pl
References
Arnol’d, V. I. [1992]: Ordinary Differential Equations, Berlin: Springer.
Belnap, N. [1992]: ‘Branching Space-Time’, Synthese, 92, pp. 385–434.
Belnap, N. [2012]: ‘Newtonian Determinism to Branching Space-Times Indeterminism
in Two Moves’, Synthese, 188, pp. 5–21.
Belnap, N., Perloff, M. and Xu, M. [2001]: Facing the Future, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Bishop, R. [2006]: ‘Determinism and Indeterminism’, in D. Borchert (ed.), Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, Volume 3, Farmington Hills: Thompson Gale, pp. 29–35.
Butterfield, J. [1989]: ‘The Hole Truth’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 40,
pp. 1–28.
Butterfield, J. [2005]: ‘Determinism and Indeterminism’, in E. Craig (ed.), Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 3, London: Routledge.
Choquet-Bruhat, Y. and Geroch, R. [1969]: ‘Global Aspects of the Cauchy Problem in
General Relativity’, Communications in Mathematical Physics, 14, pp. 329–35.
Chruściel, P. and Isenberg, J. [1993]: ‘Nonisometric Vacuum Extensions of Vacuum
Maximal Globally Hyperbolic Spacetimes’, Physical Review D, 48, pp. 1616–28.
Defining Determinism 251
Chruściel, P., Isenberg, J. and Moncrief, V. [1990]: ‘Strong Cosmic Censorship in
Polarized Gowdy Spacetimes’, Classical and Quantum Gravity, 7, pp. 1671–80.
Earman, J. [1986]: A Primer on Determinism, Reidel: Dordrecht.
Earman, J. [2006]: ‘Aspects of Determinism in Modern Physics’, in J. N. Butterfield and
J. Earman (eds), Philosophy of Physics, Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 1369–434.
Earman, J. [2008]: ‘Pruning Some Branches from Branching Spacetimes’, in D. Dieks
(ed.), The Ontology of Spacetime II, Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 187–206.
Earman, J. and Norton, J. [1987]: ‘What Price Spacetime Substantivalism? The Hole
Thomason, R. [1970]: ‘Indeterminist Time and Truth-Value Gaps’, Theoria, 36, pp.
264–81.
van Kampen, N. G. [2007]: Stochastic Processes in Physics and Chemistry, Amsterdam:
Elsevier.
Wald, R. M. [1984]: General Relativity, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Wilson, M. [1989]: ‘Critical Notice: John Earman’s A Primer on Determinism’,
Philosophy of Science, 56, pp. 502–32.