Polanyi 1970
Polanyi 1970
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Phi Beta Kappa Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to The American Scholar
655
б5б
658
But at this juncture, just when all seems neatly settled, new
problems arise owing to the modern rejection of the traditional
conception of painting. Remember the kind of statements that in-
augurated modern painting toward the end of the last century?
Whistler described his own paintings as the arrangement of colors
and tones on canvas. In France, Maurice Denis declared some
years later that a painting is "essentially a plane surface covered
with paint in a certain arrangement. " The twentieth century
opened with a series of novel works in Italy and Switzerland, in
France, Germany and Russia, all showing paintings that radically
rejected any aim of resembling nature. Pirenne's theory affirming
that we are invariably aware of the canvas might appear to side
with this modern movement, which would identify all painting
with brushstrokes on a canvas.
659
"I would start from as far away as I could, when the illusion w
plete, and come gradually nearer, until suddenly, what had
hand, and a ribbon, and a piece of velvet dissolved into a frica
beautiful brushstrokes. "*
* Sir Kenneth Clark, "Six Great Pictures," The Sunday Times (London), June 2, 1957.
This quotation was drawn to my attention by E. H. Gombrich in Art and Illusion.
660
focal awareness of: subsidiary no awarene88 of. Focally ' seen results:
awareness of: '
3) Between these tw
ing, and the upper
meaning - we find th
subsidiary awarenes
quality of these two.
We can now see wha
nature of a painting
plus brushstrokes" i
these two, but right i
To say (with Gombr
a painting misses the
blobs but subsidiarily,
perspectivai depth of
two contradictories b
• Canvas plus paint seen fo
representative painting to ab
part of flatness in the painti
661
662
beyond all that exists in nature or human affairs: for what we see
is a flat surface having a deep perspective. This quality of flat
depth, which is the hallmark of a normal painting, may be said to
be transnatural.
It has been frequently npticed that the colors and tones avail-
able to the painter cannot equal the variety we meet in nature;
but to possess a flat depth goes far beyond nature. We are facing
here no mere deficiency of a painting, which reduces its imitation
of nature, but its possession of a peculiar quality that is altogether
lacking in nature. And thus we realize that the painter must aim
from the very start at producing an image essentially different
from nature.
663
664
ticipation in its utterance. And again, it is for poetry that this action
of the arts has been first identified. I. A. Richards has contrasted
the vagueness and incoherence of our own experiences with the
severely circumscribed statements of a poem. And T. S. Eliot
spoke likewise of the ordering powers of poetry: ". . . the ordinary
man's experience/' he wrote, "is chaotic, irregular, fragmentary.
The latter falls in love, or reads Spinoza, and these two experiences
have nothing to do with each other, or with the noise of the type*
writer or the smell of cooking; in the mind of the poet these ex-
periences are already forming new wholes."*
From our lives ever meandering, and from things we pass by,
poems and plays and paintings call up vague memories and cast
them into structures firmly woven and well organized. And as the
artist draws on his own rambling experience for subjects to be
shaped by his art, so do we, his public, turn to his works in order
that their aspect may make sense of our own fugitive experiences.
By means of its artificial framework, which is sharply incom-
patible with its subject, a work of art takes us into an expérience
beyond the realm both of nature and of practical affairs, and our
understanding and acceptance of art consists in letting it thus carry
us into its own transnatural domain. Art does not inform us about
its subject, but makes us live in it, as its maker first lived in it -
sometimes many centuries before.
So now, since eighteen months ago the dawn, three months ago the
proper light of day, and indeed a very few days ago the most marvellous
# Quoted by Philip Wheelright in Metaphor and Reality (1963).
665
666
667
668
# Richard Wollheim, "Art and Illusion," The British Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 3,
No. 1, 1963; On Drawing an Object (1964); Art and Its Objects (1968).
t H. Osborne, "On Artistic Illusion," The British Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 9, Nos. 2
and 3, 1969.
t Science, Faith and Society (1946).
669