Zabeeh1968 Book WhatIsInAName
Zabeeh1968 Book WhatIsInAName
WHAT IS IN A NAME?
AN INQUIRY INTO THE SEMANTICS AND
PRAGMATICS OF PROPER NAMES
by
F ARHANG ZABEEH
Professor of Philosophy at Roosevelt University
"Nothing" ,
Said the logician.
"Change its sound and
You will change the name."
"Something" ,
Said Socrates.
"For see
What happened to me
When
The Pythian prophetess
Hung 'the wisest' on
My name."
F.Z.
CONTENTS
I. PRELIMINARIES I
"Words present to us little piCtures of things, lucid and normal, like the
pictures that are hung on the walls of schoolrooms to give children an
illustration of what is meant by a carpenter's bench, a bird, and an ant-
hill; things chosen as typical of everything else of the same sort," he
writes. "But names present to us - of persons and of towns which they
accustom us to regard as individual, as unique, like persons - a confused
picture, which draws from the names, from the brightness or darkness of
their sound, the colour in which it is uniformly painted, like one of those
posters, entirely blue or entirely red, in which, on account of the limi-
tations imposed by the process used in their reproduction, or by the whim
on the designer's part, are blue or red not only the sky and the sea, but the
ships and the church and the people in the streets."
1 Ibid., p. 296.
PRELIMIN ARIES 3
Yet that which nurtures joy, may too foster sorrow. Shakes-
peare makes use of the manysidedness of names, i.e., the dual
functions of personal names (label-connotation) to create a trage-
dy. In the Tragedy of Romeo and Juliet the two innocent lovers
attempt to shun the spell of their cursed clan-name - all in vain.
It was their names and not their deed which dragged them to
the abyss. For they cannot disentangle themselves from their
viscous clan-names which connote descriptions of vendetta
committed by the members of their clan - the guilt by association.
Juliet of Capulet laments that her lover Romeo of Montague is
called "Montague".
By a name
I know not how to tell thee who I am,
My name, dear saint, is hateful to myself,
Because it is an enemy to thee;
Had I it written, I would tear the word. 2
1 Church, A., Introduction to Mathematical Logic, Vol. I. Princeton, 1956 pp. 3-4, 9.
II. THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
I. Milt
Mill considers words to be names and "all names" according to
him. are "names of something, real or imaginary." 1 He regards
expressions as different as "John," "virtue," "old age," '"humani-
ty," "God," "man" or even definite descriptions such as "The
king who succeeded William the Conqueror," or "Caesar's army"
(his own examples) all as Names.
Names are then divided by him. into two classes ofIndividual
Name, i.e., "a name which is only capable of being truly affirmed,
in the same sense, of one thing" and General Name, i.e., "name
which is capable of being truly affirmed, in the same sense, of
each of an infinite number of things.'"
Names are again divided into two classes of Connotative Name,
i.e., "one which denotes a subject (anything which possesses
attributes), and implies an attribute" and Non-Connotative
Name, i.e., "names which signify a subject only or an attribute
only."
Once more names are divided into Concrete Name, i.e., "names
which stand for a thing," and Abstract Name, i.e., "names which
stand for an attribute of a thing."
Now proper-names (henceforth P-Ns) fall under the classes of
Individual, Non-Connotative, and Concrete names.
1 All references are to Mill's A System of Logic, loth ed. (first published in l843),
Book I, chaps. I and 2. Longmans, Greene Co., London, 1879.
10 THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
2. Frege
In philosophical literature references are given to Frege's semantic
theory which includes a discussion of PNs. It should be mention-
ed, however, that Frege was not concerned with explication of the
function of PNs in natural language. For this reason objections
which were brought forth against Frege's theory by some linguists
(like those directed against Russell's theories which were designed
primarily as solutions of some logical or epistomological puzzles)
on the ground that the theory is not true to the facts of language
or speech are otiose.
Nevertheless, since Frege's semantic theory in an oblique way
I.
expresses
Sense .....----I Genuine Proper Name I associates
- - - - + Images
(Objective) (Subjective)
11
Nominatum
1 Frege, all references are to "On Sense and Nominatum," Reading in Philosophical
Analysis, eds. Feigl and Sellars, Appleton-Century, I949.
16 THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
1 Thus Quine writes: "To rid language of redundant nomenclature of the simple
type, e.g., 'Tully' and 'Cicero,' would be no radial departure; but to eliminate
redundancies among complex names ..• would be to strike at the roots." Methods 0/
Logic, p. 209.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
are proper PNs which are never used (for example, some of the
first names listed in books which French citizens are legally
obligated to use when naming the 'newborn) and there are also
obsolete names, etc.
The contrast with Mill is instructive. Mill, as we observed, takes
PNs as if they are all listed in books waiting to be tagged on
things, hence his insistence upon the lack of meaning of PNs.
Frege, on the other hand, looks at PNs as if they have already
been used and thus his emphasis on their having a sense-deno-
tation or at least a sense (in case of apparent PNs).
Second: Even if we assume that all PNs have been used it is
still wrong to identify the meaning of a PN with its sense.
To talk about the "sense" of a PN is to talk about the various
properties of its bearer in case the name is a personal name; or
about the imaginary properties of an imaginary bearer in case the
PN is a fictional name. Now it is true that "Scott" is the name
among others of, "the author of Waverley," "Venus" is the name
of the morning star and "Bucephalus" is a name of the war horse
of Alexander the Great. However, all these expressions are used as
names and could be used to refer to various objects.
In each case, the meaning of a name should be distinguished
from the properties of its bearer.
Frege's theory is an attempt to explain why it is not always
trivial to assert identity statements by linking a PN with another
PN or with a unique property of its denotation. But it does not
help us much to "answer the question what is the meaning of a PN,
except negatively, by showing that the denotation of a name is
not its meaning.
3. Russell
Russell's interest in PNs has been always connected with his
logical and epistemological theories. However, some linguists
have taken Russell's statements to be intended as a description of
the linguistic facts and criticized him without realizing that
Russell's statements like Frege's are not intended to comprise a
linguistic theory - though Russell is not always explicit about his
undertaking.
Despite this, Russell's view deserves close attention and will
18 THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
1 Ibid., p. 4.
2Urmson, J. D., Philosophical Analysis, Oxford: Clarendon, I95I, p. 85.
a Russell, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, London: George Allen, I940, p. 3Z.
4 Russell, Human Knowledge, New York: Simon and Schuster, I948, p. 78. For the
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS 21
sundry bits of information but which does not itself point to any
one of them is a strange abuse of terms." 1
Another linguist, Le., N. Chomsky, criticizes Russell's proposal
about PNs as if it is made with the intention to describe a lin-
guistic fact.
Russell wrote in An Inquiry:
There is no logical necessity for names or other' object words" to meet any
condition of spatiotemporal contiguity or to have other Gestalt qualities,
and it is a nontrivial fact that they apparently do insofar as the designated
objects are of the type that can actually be perceived (for example, it is
not true of ' United States").
There is no a priori reason why a natural language could not contain a
word "HERD," like the collective "herd" except that it denotes a single
scattered object with cows as parts, so that' a cow lost a leg" implies "the
herd lost a leg," etc. 3
1 Ibid., p. 64.
2 Russell, Inquiry, pp. 33-34.
8 Chomsky, N., Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, The M.I.T. Press, 1965, p. 201.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS 23
3. Definite descriptions may be used in lieu of a PN. But they
are not logically equivalent.
4. Logically PNs are names of bare particulars which we are
directly acquainted with. They alone indicate an object with-
out ascribing characteristics to it.
Thus Russell disagrees with Mill that an ordinary PN is
without a connotation. We may sometimes use various de-
scriptions of a bearer of a PN in lieu of it. However, his invented
logically PN coincides with Mill's idea of PN.
(i) Zif/
In his book Semantic Analysis Ziff offers some opinions on PNs.
His remarks, however, are both illuminating and puzzling. He
begins with a necessary warning that, "it is not possible to state a
simple strong generalization about proper names. One can only
say what is so for the most part and that must be qualified." 1
Two problems seem to interest Ziff.
First: Whether there are semantic regularities, i.e., "regulari-
ties of some sort to be found in connection with the corpus
pertaining to both linguistic elements and then to other things,
e.g., the utterances and situations, or to phrases and persons, as
well as to utterances and utterance," 2 in connection with PNs
and if so, what kind.
1 Ziff, P., all references are to Semantic Analysis, Cornell University Press, New
York, 1960, p. 93.
S Ibid., p. 27.
24 THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
The fact that "Witchgren" (the names of his imaginary cat) in "Witchgren
is on the mat" does contrast with "he," "dust," • water," is I believe the
principal reason why so many philosophers are inclined to suppose that
proper names do have meaning in English. And if one adopts the slogan,
that "the meaning of a word is its use in the language," one can hardly
avoid supposing that proper names generally do have meaning in English. 3
The conclusion seems to be, "For the most part then, proper
names are not said to have meaning in English or to have a
meaning in English. But certain proper names are said to mean
something to someone and certain proper names are said to have
meaning." 5
1 Ibid., p. 89.
B Idem.
3 Ibid., p. I73.
4 Ibid., p. I75.
5 Ibid., pp. 93-94.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS 25
Nevertheless, Ziff admits that PNs have a connotation though
not meaning, i.e., some informative force.
Even though I want to deny that proper names are, for the most part, said
to have meaning in English ... I want to say that proper names do for the
most part if not invariably have a connotation ... one can say that a
proper name connotes something primarily to the hearer ... 1
It's neither meaningless nor senseless to call a female cat "Charile" yet
such a use of the name constitutes a deviation from a semantic regularity. 3
(To which we may respond quoting Mill that "we name a dog by
the name Ceaser").
I do not want here to question Ziff's account of semantic
regularity which is an important part of his book. However, the
following points have to be made.
First: The distinction between the meaning of an expression
and the connotation which an expression may carry with itself
1 Idem.
S Ibid., p. 102.
8 Ibid., p. 33.
26 THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
(ii) Strawson
Strawson has not been primarily concerned with the issue of
PNs but mostly with definite descriptions. However, since the
latter issue is closely connected with other referring expressions
such as PNs, some discussion of PN s appear in his work.
To begin with, in Introduction to Logical Theory, Strawson
rejects the view that the meaning of a genuine referring ex-
pression (such as definite descriptions which uniquely character-
ize some actual entities) is identical with the object to which it
applies.
He also denies that there are any referring expressions whose
use guarantees the existence of any object. Now PNs are typical
referring-expressions. They are also incapable of satisfying the
demand that their use require referents.
1Ibid., p. 94.
2For a rigorous criticism of this theory see "Review of Semantic Analysis," by J. J.
Katz, Journal Language, volume 38, no. I, pp. 52-69 (1962).
3 Strawson, P., Introduction to Logical Theory, London: Methuen, 1952, p. 189.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
When a man uses such an expression, he does not assert, nor does what he
says entail, a uniquely existential proposition. But one of the conventional
functions of the definite article is to act as a signal that a unique reference
is being made ... When we begin a sentence with "the such-and-such"
the use of "the" shows, but does not state, that we are intended to be,
referring to one particular individual of the species "such-and-such." 2
The same may be said of PNs. Thus, we may say, when a man
uses a PN, he does not assert, nor does what he says entail that
At one end of this scale stand the PNs we most commonly use in ordinary
discourse. The pure name has no descriptive meaning (except such as it
may acquire as a result of some one of its uses as a name). A word like "he"
has minimal descriptive meaning but has some. Substantial phrases like
"the round table" have the maximum descriptive force. An interesting
intermediate position is occupied by "impure" proper names like "The
Round Table" - substantial phrases which have grown capital letters.
Ignorance of a man's name is not ignorance of the language. That is why
we do Bot speak of the meaning of proper names. (But it won't do to say
they are meaningless.)
An ordinary personal name is, roughly, a word, used referringly, of
which the use is not dictated by any descriptive meaning the word may
have, and is not prescribed by any such general rule for use as a referring
expression (or a part of a referring expression) as we find in the case of
such words as "I," "this" and "the" but is governed by ad hoc conventions
for each particular set of applications of the word to a given person.
The important part is that the correctness of such applications does not
follow from any general rule or convention for the use of the word as such. 1
1 Idem. Here, in effect, Strawson comes close to secure meaning for PN. by ob-
serving "its referring use." However, in his earlier work, he criticizes Wittgenstein's
oblique statement that in the case of a PN, too, the meaning is the use. "Wittgenstein
attacks the notion of the word of which the meaning is the object it applies to: he
instances the ordinary proper name and distinguishes between its bearer and its
meaning (40); in this case, too, the meaning is the use (41-43). (Wittgenstein here
gives the wrong reason for objecting to the identification of the, or a, meaning of a
proper name with its bearer, or one of its bearers. If we speak at all of the meaning of
proper names, it is only in quite specialized ways, as when we say that 'Peter' means a
stone, or 'Giovanui' means 'John.' This is not an accident of usage, but reflects a
radical difference between proper names and other names. But here, as elsewhere,
Wittgenstein neglects the use of 'meaning')." "Review of Wittgenstein's Philosophical
Investigations," Mind, vol. LXIII, 1954.
30 THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
(iii) Ayer
In his recent article Names and Description Ayer raises the
question: "What then is their (proper-names) meaning?" and
answers, "This sounds a silly question - how cou1d one answer it
except by saying that as a ru1e different names have different
meaning? If you will tell me what proper names you have in
mind, then I will try to tell you what they severally mean." 1
Next, he rejects the suggestion that the meaning of a PN is the
1 Idem.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS 31
object which it denotes - and also a weaker assumption that "A
proper name may not be thought to mean what it denotes, but is
still held that it must denote something in order to be meaning-
ful." For he argues that "the distinctive feature of the fictitious
use of name (,Mr. Pickwick') is not that they have no reference,
for this may also be true of names which are used historically, but
that in what may be called their normal form the sentences in
which they occur are not truth-claiming." 1
Ayer comments on Strawson's statement that "a name is
worthless without a backing of descriptions which can be pro-
duced on demand to explain its application" by saying that "to
understand the use of a proper name one must know which
individual it is intended to refer to, but this knowledge need not
consist in the ability to furnish a verbal description of the indi-
vidual in question. It may be enough that one picks out the right
person or object, when the occasion arises." 2
I believe that none of these statements enlarge our under-
standing of PNs.
We do not have to know anything about the individual Smith
to be able to pick out the right person in order to know that
"Smith" is used as a personal name. A name is not worthless
without the backing of a description. But rather, as Wittgenstein
observes, "Naming is a preparation for description. Naming is so
far not amove in the language game any more than putting a piece
in its place on the board is a move in chess." 3
We do not bestow names on persons and places, artifacts, etc.,
if we are not interested to talk about them, i.e., to describe them
or evaluate them, in general, to say something about the bearer
of the name. Nonetheless, we should not assimilate the act of
referring to a thing by using its name with the act of describing
some facts about its bearer.
"Pickwick" is a fictitious name given by Dickens to one of his
characters, and we may make many true as well as false state-
ments about its bearer. Its bearer is not a historical figure, but a
fictional one. We make mistakes only if we assume that our
statements are descriptive of an historical figure. In each case, to
1 Idem.
2 Idem.
a Ibid., par. 49.
32 THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
Let us take a person with whom we are not acquainted, say Socrates. We
may define him as "the philosopher who drank the hemlock," but such a
definition does not assure us that Socrates existed, and if he did not exist,
•• Socrates" is not a name.
(iv) Searle
In his article on "Proper Names," 2 Searle makes the following
points.
I. PNs do not function as descriptions, but as pegs on which
to hang descriptions. Though descriptions could be used,
like PNs, to refer to an individual, they cannot perform the
same functions. Since every time we use a description in
place of a PN we have to specify identity conditions, i.e.,
that two or more descriptions refer to the same thing.
2. Following Strawson he writes that "We may say that
referring uses of both proper names and definite descriptions
1 Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, 2nd ed., London, 1926.
B Searle, J., "Proper Names," Mind, LXVII, no. 261, April, 1958.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS 33
presuppose the existence of one and only one object referred
to."
3. Finally to the question: "Does a proper name have a
sense?", he answers, "if this asks whether or not proper
names are used to describe or specify characteristics of
objects, the answer is 'No.' But if it asks whether or not
proper names are logically connected with characteristics of
the object to which they refer, the answer is 'Yes' in a loose
sort of way."
Searle's familiar criticism of the substitutability of PNs with a
definite description is correct. There may be many definite de-
scriptions of the same person, and two people may give different
descriptions of the same person. We need PNs if for no other
reason than to convey the identity of someone to whom more
than one definite description has been attributed. Thus as Searle
writes PNs are like pegs on which we hang descriptions. The same
point is made by Strawson. "It is proper names which tend to be
the resting-places of reference to particulars, the points on which
the descriptive phrases pivot." 1
Searle's statements, however, with regard to the presuppo-
sition of the referring use of PNs are misleading.
The referring use of PNs does not "presuppose the existence of
one and only one object referred to," but rather it purports to
individuate one object referred to. Whether the object referred to
exists spatiotemporally or in various ontological levels is not a
presupposition of the referring use of PNs.
Searle's last mentioned point concerning the logical connection
of a PN with properties of its bearer "in a loose sort of way" is
weak. It is a contingent fact that names are usually not given
without name-givers having an interest in the bearers of the
names. But there is no logical connection, even in a loose sort of
way, between a name and the bearer of that name. 2
(v) Shawayder
I would like now to consider some points which were made by
Shawayder concerning PNs in his Modes of Referring and The
Problem of Universals, and also in a review of a book of a Danish
linguist, Sf(Jrensen, titled The Meaning of Proper Names.
r. He argues negatively, on familiar grounds, against the
assimilation of a PN to description. Against Russell he writes,
But he should have concluded that a proper name, even in our usual sense
of the term, quite apart from what its use presumes, is not itself a definite
description at all. 1
chill is not mortal," or ambiguously (as some logicians say) e.g., "John Doe" without
being prepared to answer the question "who or what are you talking about?"
In using a PN what is necessary is to know that a sign is used as a name i.e., to
make a unique reference to the same entity. It is not necessary to know anything
about that entity. Note, for example how "John Smith" and "Mary Brown" are used
in this passage, "The idea of Edward's being a clergyman, and living in a small
parsonage house, diverted him beyond measure; and when to that was added the
fanciful imagery of Edward reading prayers in a white surplice, and publishing the
banns of marriage between John Smith and Mary Brown, he could conceive nothing
more rediculous." Jane Austen Sense and Sensibility.
1 Shawayder, D., Modes of Referring and the Problem of Universals, University of
California Press, p. 59.
B Shawayder, D., "Review of the Meaning of Proper Names by H. S. Sf1Irensen."
The Journal of Philosophy, LXI - No. 15. August 6, 1964.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS 35
of the name, i.e., when it is introduced in English, changes in
spelling, etc.) 1
(2) Some description of some of the bearers of the name, if they
are famous enough. (Thus under Cyrus (m) Gr . . . from Persian
Kuru, "throne," the name of the great king of Persia ... ) 2
None of these items constitute the meaning of a PN, since
neither the etymology of a PN (or etymology of a word) is a part
of the meaning of that word, nor is the description of some of its
bearers (if a PN has any bearer). Here is a place where one may
say that the etymological meaning of a word is not its use in
language. This would not be in conflict with Wittgenstein's
assertion that:
For a large class of cases - though not for all - in which we employ the
word "meaning" it can be defined thus: the meaning of a word is its use in
the language. 3
(vi) Kneale
Finally, I would like to report some observations made by
Kneale in his book The Development of Logic.
1 Withycombe, E. G., The Oxford Dictionary of English Christian Names, London:
Oxford Press, 1947, p. 25.
2 Ibid., p. 38.
3 Ibid., par. 43.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS
1 Kneale, William and Martha, The Development of Logic, Oxford: The Clarendon
Press, 1962, pp. 597-598.
2 Ibid., p. 597.
THEORIES OF LOGICIANS 37
that he could not pronounce his name. In each case, it is not
possible to dispense with the name by using the description.
Consider again that someone wants to deny that HShakespeare's
real name was 'Bacon'." He could not express his view by saying
merely that, "It is not the case that the real name of the author of
Hamlet was the name of the author of The Novum Organum."
Lastly consider the simple advertisement under lost dogs "answers
to the name 'Dash': had on a brass collar." Here again the name
is at least as important as any description of its bearer and
perhaps more so, in case "Dash" is the name of a dog closely
resembling many others.
The identification of the definite description with names
generates paradoxes.
Kneale himself quoted a paradox which I believe was generated
as a result of the assumption that the definite description of a
certain number is identical with the name of that number.
The paradox which is called Berry's paradox, is, to quote
Kneale:
concerns the least integer nat nameable in fewer than nineteen syllables.
Although it seems obvious that any name of this integer must contain at
least nineteen syllables, the words printed above in italics amount to a
name for it and they contain only eighteen syllables. 1
At this point I would like to leave the theories and the pro-
nouncements of logicians on PNs behind and provide at least a
few samples of what some recent grammarians and linguists have
written on this subject.
1 Ibid., p. 656.
III. THEORIES OF LINGUISTS
I. Gardiner
Gardiner, in his famous book The Theory of Speech and Language,l
makes some remarks about PNs. Later, in The Theory of Proper
Names: A Controversial Essay, he offers a theory. In both works,
however, his view presupposes the correctness of the Saussure's
Langue-Parole or Language - Speech dichotomy.
Gardiner defines "speech" as "a universally exerted activity,
having at first definitely utilitarian aims. In describing this
activity, we shall discover that it consists in the application of a
universally possessed science, namely the science which we call
language."
There are four elements in speech:
I. The speakier
2. The listener
3. The things referred to
4. The linguistic material
Now the speaker learns in a certain stage how to use the lin-
guistic material (words) in order to achieve certain ends, e.g., to
inform the listener that something is the case.
This theory is accepted by some philosophers. Thus Ryle, 2 in his
1 Idem.
B Ibid., p. 42.
S Gardiner, A. H., The Theory 0/ Proper Names, London: Oxford Press, 1954, p. 30.
THEORIES OF LINGUISTS
(r) "the star that is the central body of the solar system ... "
(2) "A self-luminous heavenly body ... " 1
Thus we may say that "sun" is used both as a PN, i.e., to refer
to our sun, and as a common name, i.e., to refer to any sun -
without using the questionable speech-language dichotomy.
Second, Gardiner correctly takes "the identification" and "the
individual application" of a PN as the silent feature of it. But
then he assumes wrongly that surnames are "common proper
names." Surnames, however, are not common names. A common
name like "Human" is applicable to any being which has a set of
specific properties. A surname is used to refer to any member of a
group not in virtue of a set of its specific properties. There are
specific properties belonging to humans, but there are no set of
specific properties belonging to the Kennedys in virtue of which
they are called by that name. In fact, neither the existence of
"individually applied names which are not proper names" nor
"commonly applied names which are" warrants rejection of his
early theory which maintained that PNs are individual names.
Only a slight modification is needed to save the theory against
these objections.
If we say, for example, that a PN qua PN is purported to be
used to refer to an individual and never to refer to more than one
individual, then we could argue that the use of a surname is not
inconsistent with this statement. For a surname is used as an aid
for the purpose of referring to an individual. If we call someone by
using his first name and more than one person answers to it, we
may add his surname (and if that won't help, a middle-name or a
definite description or a demonstrative pronoun, if we have to) in
order to make a correct identification possible.
Indeed surnames are invented in order to facilitate the unique
referring act and not to hinder it.
Third, Gardiner's assertion that the purpose of identification is
achieved by "distinctive sound alone, without regard to any
meaning possessed by the sound" is absurd.
In fact, it violates his earlier assertion that PNs are words, i.e.,
"meaning-bearing sound." One consequence of this assertion is his
naive epistemology that PNs "are recognizable not by the
intellect but by the sense." A mere sound does not tell us at all
1 The Random House Dictionary of the EngUsh Language. 1966 Random House, Inc.
THEORIES OF LINGUISTS 43
that it has a certain function, namely, it is designed to refer to a
particular entity. Obviously, unless we know its functions we do
not know that a sound is used as a PN;
Gardiner's motive is to defend a portion of Mill's theory that
PNs denote but do not connote. This could be done by pointing
out that we do not normally use a PN to convey information
about its bearer to the hearer but to prepare the hearer that some
information is forthcoming.
2.S(Jrensen
In his recent book The Meaning of Proper Names 1 the Danish
linguist, Holger Steen S0rensen offers a definiens formula for PNs.
He first rejects various theories offered (mostly by logicians)
about PNs.
He agrees with Gardiner that PNs are not mere noises, like the
sounds produced by a car engine; rather they are meaning-
bearing sounds, that is, words. And "Since we cannot know the
meaning of a sign unless it has meaning" he argues "it follows
that "Paris" has meaning. Similarly with other proper names ...
but many people might not know its meaning."
He rejects, for obvious reasons, the view that a PN must have a
denotation. Quoting Reichenbach's statement, viz., "A proper
name is a symbol coordinated by definition to an individual thing.
If a term is to be called a proper name it is necessary that there is
a corresponding thing." He comments that if this statement is
true "We must await the result of the investigation of the histori-
ans before we can class the sign S among proper names." But it is
absurd to assume that the works of the historians have any
bearing on linguistics or on logic.
S0rensen also tries to reject the assumption that PNs are
arbitrary (Mill). He argues that those who assume this would
probably believe also that "all signs, with the exception of ono-
matopoetic signs are arbitrary in the Saussurean Sense(s) of the
word."
His second argument is that there are some rules which govern
1 Sorensen, H. S., all references are to The Meaning 0/ Proper Names: With a
Definiens Formula For Proper Names in Modern English, Copenhagen: G.E.C. GAD
Publisher, 1963.
44 THEORIES OF LINGUISTS
naming, for example, "a child should have its father's surname."
S~rensen tries to provide a definition for PN after rejecting
various theories by making use of the Speech-Language dichoto-
my. Strangely enough, he tries to do so while asserting that" '1'
and 'you' are indefinable - they are semantic primitives of the
English language."
A definition of PN is given as follows:
Let "P" be a variable for a proper name. And let .eX" be a
+
variable for an appellative stem singular flexive. This, then,
is the partial definition formula - and what is on the right-hand
side of the equation mark the partial definiens formula-of
proper name:
"P" = "the X that ... "
It follows, S~rensen argues, that a PN cannot possibly denote
more than one entity.
He writes "From the fact that definiens of proper names
contain, and begin with, the definite article and an appellative
stem in the singular, it follows that proper names are individual
names."
Now if a PN is identified with some properties of its deno-
tation, then it could be argued that it is dispensible. S~rensen, in
fact, draws this conclusion. Thus he writes:
In the case of proper names: theoretically we could do without them, but
it is very inexpedient to have to say "the person that ... ," therefore we
say" Anderson," or whatever it may be.
1 Idem.
2 Strawson, P., "Review of SflJrensen 'The Meaning of Proper Names'," Mind,
volume LXXV, April, 1966, p. 298.
THEORIES OF LINGUISTS
3. Syntactic Regularities
The interest of logicians is concentrated on those aspects of PNs
which are supposed to be independent of the pecularities of any
specific language. Only by way of examples are there references to
PNs as they are used in English. Otherwise, their theories of PNs,
if true, are intended to account for PNs in any language, or at
least in languages having structural similarities.
On the other hand, linguists and descriptive grammarians, so
far as they are interested in PNs, are concerned with establishing
regularities which pertain to a specific language - in our case, the
English language.
Although the syntactic aspects of PNs are parasitic upon more
fundamental features, i.e., semantic and pragmatic, we shall not
ignore the observations of some grammarians and some linguists
even though they are only relevant to the English language.
Otto Jespersen, in his book Essentials of English Grammar,
writes, "As a rule proper names need no article, as they are
definite enough in themselves." He observes, however, that when
a plural is formed of a PN the article is required because it ceases
to be a PN "in the fullest sense," e.g., the Stuarts. "In accordance
with this rule we have the article with geographical names with
plural forms: the West Indies, the Netherlands, etc. Likewise, when
we refer to members of a family the article is used with plural: the
Carlyles." 1
This rule, however, breaks down when we consider that some
PNs are used with definite articles even though they are used in a
singular form, e.g., The Thames, The New York Times. Chomsky
suggests that such "Determiners" may be taken as part of the
name itself. He writes:
Proper nouns are nouns with no Determiner (or, as in the case of "The
Nile," with a fixed Determiner that may just as well be taken as part of
the noun itself, rather than as part of a freely and independently selected
Determiner system).2
1 Jespersen, 0., Essentials of English Gramma1', London: George Allen, 1960, p. 205.
2 Ibid., p. 100.
THEORIES OF LINGUISTS 47
If we accept this proposal we should also consider that there
are "Determiners" which accompany some expressions used as
PNs but could not be regarded as part of the expression itself.
For example, the definite article as used in the following ex-
pressions is not a meaningless or decorative sign:
"The United States"
"The British Common-Wealth"
"The East German Democratic Republic"
"The Round Table"
(Witness here Strawson's observation on descriptions growing
capital letters.)
S0rensen observes that, "'The United States,' must, no doubt,
be registered as an appellative construction: 'the' is a determi-
native; it is the definite article: 'The United States of America'
(The use of capital letters is a convention of speech enconomy
parallel to the use of capitallatters in 'the Channel')." 1
However, the distinction between PNs and definite descriptions
and common names used as PNs is not clear cut. A PN could be
used as a description and a definite description or a common
name could be used as a PN. Hence we should not take the
criterion of the absence of an article or a "Determiner" very
seriously.
Consider how proper names such as "Quisling," "Pegasus" or
"Chimaera" are now used as common nouns.
Partridge, in his book Proper Names That Have Become Common
Property, writes 2: "Quisling ... had shed his capital letters with
a speed unequalled by any of the several hundred other men ...
who have entered our dictionaries." Since Quisling was a famous
traitor during the Second World War, the phrase "he is a quisling"
meant "he is a traitor."
"The Chimaera" in Greek mythology was the name of a
dragon-tailed, lion-headed, goat-bodied animal slain by Bellero-
phon as aided by the winged horse Pegasus. We now use "chimae-
ra" to mean an idle fancy. In such cases PNs drop their definite
articles and their capitals and take their place among other words.
Consider also some contexts in which some typical PNs are used
as common names. "This is just like Joan," "Here comes another
Hitler," "This is not the Joan I married." In each case the PN is
used not to refer to an individual but to refer to some properties of
that individual.
On the other hand, we use some descriptions as PNs. Mill
observed that "Dartmouth" is used as a name of a city. We may
continue to use it as such, even if the river Dart changes its course.
Such surnames as ('Blond" (the fair), "Musard" (the dreamy),
"Roger Deus Salvet Dominas" (Roger God-save-the-Iadies) which
were originally personal nicknames and given simply as de-
scription or in admiration or fun were recorded in Domesday Book
(a sort of General Directory for I086).1
We may use and apply the designation "The United States" to
refer to our country even if the Federal Government absorbs all
the political powers of every state. The appelation "The East
German Democratic Republic" is used to refer to a part of
Germany despite the fact that politically that state is neither
democratic nor a republic.
In each case, if we need to indicate that we are using these
expressions only as a PN and not as a description we may use the
expression ('the so-called."
The expression "The East German Democratic Republic," in
fact, is often used by the West Germans with the prefix "soge-
nannte" to dispel the impression that the expression is a de-
scription. Lastly, consider Jesperson's observation with regard
to the presence of a plural: that when on some rare occasions a
plural is formed of a PN the article is required because it ceases to
be a PN "in the fullest sense." No reason is given for this con-
viction. Perhaps the reason is this, that when we use the Carlyles
(to announce the arrival of Mr. and Mrs.) or the Alps (to refer to
groups of mountains in France and Italy) we use each name as a
group name. However, this cannot be said about The Netherlands
or The United States, since The Netherlands or The United States is
not in number contrast with the Netherland or an United State.
To conclude, neither the absence of "the" nor the plural sign
("S") could be regarded as criteria for signs used as PNs.
1 Note, for example the following: "It is a mistake to think that 'referring ex-
pression' itself can secure and guarantee this uniqueness. This is obvious in the
case of proper names, for here we cannot appeal to meaning. 'Tommy Jones' does
not have a meaning, and many people share it. Proper names are usually (rather)
common names." Linskey, L., Referring, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1967,
p. 118.
A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE 51
I. On Dictionary Definition
Do not say: 'There must be something common' •••
but look and see • ••
PhilosOPhical Investigations
In the rest of this work I will try to bring out some positive
features of PNs. We may be able to find an answer to our
question if, instead of pursuing a semantic inquiry, i.e., search for
a supposed relation between words and things, or a syntactic
inquiry, i.e., inquiry into relations of expressions, we take a close
look at pragmatics, namely, an inquiry into the relations between
expressions and the users of expressions.
The inquiry into the pragmatic dimension should precede the
semantic and syntactic and not vice versa, as it is often done by
logicians and grammarians. That is, unless we find out first the
kinds of expressions which are used by speakers of a language for
achieving a certain end we should not cut out the speaker and his
needs from the picture and look at language as something
possessing, by itself, certain internal or external properties.
My suggestion that the inquiry into pragmatics should precede
that of other dimensions is not based alone on observing the
A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE 55
inadequacies of such alternative approaches, but is also grounded
on the fact that the use of this approach is conducive to clarity
and would create fewer problems.
Let us illustrate this point. Suppose we define "tool" as any
object possessing specified physical properties on the ground that
a "tool" does in fact denote various objects, each possessing
certain physical properties. We have now created for ourselves a
problem of redefining our definiendum each time we invent a new
tool. More seriously, in investigating a newly discovered civili-
zation or prehistoric cultures we would exclude from the list of
tools any object not resembling physically our tools.
On the other hand, if we consider the pragmatic dimension by
looking first at certain human needs, motives and goals, and then
finding that certain artifacts or even natural objects (no matter
what physical properties they may have) are instrumental in
fulfilling these needs, motives and goals, then we would not have
to face the aforementioned problems. Under the new definition,
any object, and it need not be a physical object, which is used in
order to satisfy certain needs, motives and goals, may be counted
as a "tool." We may say, taking a hint from Aristotle, that in
defining an artifact, such as a tool or a house or an artificial body,
such as a court or a corporation, the purpose for which each
artifact or each artificial body is made should be included in the
definiens, since an artifact or an artificial body is not a mere
assemblage but a purposeful configuration of objects, persons, etc.
Let us now make use of the tool analogy and look at language
as a kind of a tool used to satisfy primarily social needs. (Don't
balk at dissimilarities. An analogy is not a proof.)
Making allowances for some very primitive and pre-historic
societies, it may be said that primarily language is employed by
men to convey information, evaluations, and recommendations.
It is used secondarily also for numerous other ends, such as
counting, warning, contracting, swearing, singing and solilo-
quizing, etc.
Corresponding to each activity we make use of a certain type of
linguistic expression. For example, to convey information, we do
make statements (that is we make use of sentences which have
truth-value); for recommending we make use of prescriptive
utterances; for counting we make use of numerals.
A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE
7. The Referent
In exhibiting the various functions of a PN, we need not commit
ourselves to the ontological status which the referent of the PN
may have. The fact that the referents of some PNs are spatio-
temporal entities or characters in plays and novels or heroes and
gods in myths, is irrelevant. Indeed, "To give to airy nothing a
local habitation and a name" to quote Shakespeare, is the occu-
pational disease of the poets. However, preoccupation with the
status of the referent of some PNs led some logicians to fabricate
myths about PNs, rather than describe their nature.
For example Quine writes that:
There is a tendency to try to preserve some shadowy entity under the
word 'Cerberus,' for example, lest the word lose its meaning. If 'Cerbe-
rus' were meaningless, not only would poetry suffer, but even certain
blunt statements of fact, such as there is no such thing as Cerberus would
lapse into meaningless ... 'Cerberus' remains meaningful despite not
naming ... Some meaningful words which are proper names from a
grammatical point of view. notably 'Cerberus' do not name anything.l
1 Ibid., p. 199-202.
60 A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE
8. Overlapping Categories
Not every referring expression is used to individuate a unique
referent. If I say, "Have a coke," any liquid which falls under the
description of being a Coca-Cola will do. (In fact, legally speaking
nothing could be a Coca-Cola unless it has certain specific de-
scriptions - among them the fact that it is manufactured by that
company alone.)
Hence, it seems that such names which usually fall under the
categories of E and D, that is, some names of Artifacts, or Insti-
tutions, in virtue of the fact that many items may fall under
them qua palpable resemblances would be regarded, at least
sometimes, as common names. Since there are many copies of
"The Holy Bible," many renditions of "The Eroica," many copies
of "The New York Times," many cartoons of "Mickey Mouse"
(not to speak of mickey mouse democracies) and even many
A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE 61
interpretations of "Hamlet," the name of such objects may be
regarded as a common name.
On the other hand, we may say unless a perfect replica of the
Mona Lisa or Venus De Milo is produced, their names are used as
PNs.
However, if we say not "anything which does have instances"
but "anything which may have instances qua having certain
properties" is not a unique entity, but rather a type of thing, and
hence its name is a common name, then we would destroy the
traditional distinction between common names and proper names
which correspond to the metaphysical categories of universals and
particulars. There is nothing sacrosanct about traditional cate-
gories. We may look at any universal as a particular and at any
particular as a universal. The existence of such categories is to be
justified on pragmatic grounds.
But since, as a matter of fact, we are interested in identifying
uniquely persons and things, we need PNs. That is not to say that
a PN may not be used as a common name or a common name as a
PN. Only by observing how an expression is used may we de-
termine whether it is used as a PN or a common name.
The temptation, however, to reduce PNs to common names or
common names to PNs is very strong (or metaphysically speaking
to reduce particulars to universals or universals to particulars).
Kneale, in line with Frege, takes numerals to be PNs of
numbers. He writes, "When the word 'four' is used as a noun,
e.g., in the statement 'four is an even number,' it seems to behave
as Frege says, like a proper name."
For "2 + 2" and" 4" are both used to refer to numbers. They are indeed
proper names of a number, but names with different senses ... a proper
name (which may be a single word or sign or a combination of such)
expresses its sense, but stands tor or designates its reference. 1
1 Ibid., p. 495-496.
62 A CONSTRUCTIVE :MOVE
9. A Use-Mention Confusion
One possible explanation for taking a PN as a common name and
hence asking for its meaning is the way PNs find their way into
our dictionaries. In ordinary dictionaries the names of some
significant persons and places appear among other words. The
1 Frege, The Foundations of Arithmetic, translated by J. L. Austin, Basil Blackwell,
1950, p. 49.
A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE
1 Withycombe, Idem.
A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE
I2. SamePerson-SameName
Since a PN is mostly llsed for referring uniquely to an entity and
individuating it, it is necessary that it always be applied to the
same entity. There are, however, various criteria for establishing
whether a referent of a PN, e.g., a person, a city, a book, a portion
of time, or an institution is the same. Examples of such criteria are
spatio-temporal continuity, finger prints, answering to the name,
temporal properties. Consider various criteria we use in order to
establish that "He is the same man," "This is the same day,"
"This is the same army," "This is the same French Academy,"
"This is the same hurricane."
Without an appeal to a criterion we cannot know that a referent
of a PN is the same or not. The same is true about the name itself.
That is, in the absence of a criterion, we are unable to know
whether a certain configuration of letters should be construed as
the same name. According to some legal rules, the criterion that
"X is the same PN as Y" is having the same sound and not
necessarily the same spelling. This criterion is called "Idem
Sonans." In a case when the identity of the beneficiary is in
doubt, a name which sounds like another is considered to be the
same, despite variance in spelling. 1
The point is that in order to establish whether the bearers of a
name are the same or whether names are the same we need to
appeal to certain criteria.
Though a PN should always be applied to the same item, the
converse is not the case. For persons, places, artifacts, etc., may
1 Greene, L. G., Law ot Names, New York: Oceana Publications, I954.
66 A CONSTRUCTIVE MOV.E
have various names during their life span. Consider "Dr. Jekyll"
and "Mr. Hyde," the names of the same person or "Everest" and
"Gaurisanker," the names of the same mountain from opposite
points of view.
I3. Name-Givers
Using an expression as a PN presupposes that that expression
was bequeathed by someone - e.g., parents, states, or authors,
upon some bearer, e.g., infants, cities, books, ships, etc. - as a
name so that if we want, we could refer to its bearer.
In this we should agree with Mill that pointing to a man and
saying "Smith" or to a city and saying "London" we do not
c;ou-vey to the hearer any information p.xcept that these are their
names.
Now giving a PN to an item presupposes that the name-giver is
interested in the bearer cum individual and not necessarily cum its
type~.
Gardlller observes that "there is no human being so wretched
as to have no name of his own" which, if true, shows that at least
everyone has someone's interest.
It is reported that the Roman slaves originally were without
names. Only after being sold they took their master's praenomen
in the genitive case followed by the suffix - "por." (Boy), e.g.,
"Marcipor," which indicates that some men, so long as they were
regarded by others as cattle, did not need a name. However, as
soon as they became servants some designation was called forth.
1 Withycombe, Idem.
70 A CONSTRUCTIVE MOVE
anything else truly and universally, e.g. Cleon and Callias, i.e. the
individual and sensible, but other things may be predicated of
them (for each of these is both man and animal) ... for as a rule
each sensible thing is such that it cannot be predicated of any-
thing save incidentally: for we sometimes say that that white
object is Socrates, or that that which approaches is Callias."
(B.I.: ch. I. 27).
In a similar vein Plato was concerned with names, both proper
and common, even though in his dialogues one cannot find a clear
distinction between these two categories. Proper names both
denote uniquely the individual and at the same time function as a
predicate characterizing the individual (Theaetetus. 209).
However in one dialogue, i.e. Cratylus, Plato almost solves the
general problem concerning names and the particular problem of
proper names.
The problem in this dialogue is the relation between language
and the world. Socrates rejects both the realistic and the nominal-
istic theories of language represented respectively by Cratylus
and Hermogenes in favour of another theory which we called
Instrumentalism (see, Universals: A new look at an old Problem).
Socrates refutes on various grounds the alternatives either
Phuiss (nature) or Nomos (convention), that either words are
dictated by the nature of things or are imposed arbitrarily upon
things. The significant part of the dialogue, however is the
Socratic discovery of a way-out of the dilemma.
To appreciate the full force of the Socratic insight I will quote
part of the discussion between Socrates and Hermogens:
Soc. And speech is a kind of action?
Her. True.
Soc. And will a man speak correctly who speaks as he pleases?
Will not a successful speaker rather be he who speaks in the
natural way of speaking, and as things ought to spoken and
with the natural instrument? Any other mode of speaking
will result in error and failure.
Her. I quite agree with you.
Soc. And is not naming a part of speaking? For in giving
names men speak.
Her. That is true.
CONCLUSION 73
Soc. And if speaking is a sort of action and has a relation to
acts, is not naming also a sort of action?
Ayer, A., "Names and Descriptions," The Concept of a Person, St. Martin's
Press, 1963.
Chomsky, N., Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, The M.LT. Press, 1965.
Church, A., Introduction to Mathematical Logic, Vol. I, Princeton, 1959.
Frege, G., The Foundations of Arithmetic, translated by J. L. Austin, Basil
Blackwell, 1950.
- "On Sense and Nominatum," Readings in Philosophical Analysis, eds.
Feigl and Sellars, Appleton-Century, 1949.
Gardiner, A., The Theory of SPeech and Language, Oxford. Clarendon.,
1932.
- The Theory of Proper Names: A Controversial Essay. London; Oxford
Press, 1954.
Green, L., Law of Names, New York: Oceana Publications, 1954.
Jespersen, 0., The PhilosoPhy of Grammar, London: Allen and Unwin,
19 2 4.
- Essentials of English Grammar, London: George Allen, 1960.
Katz, J., "Review of Semantic Analysis," Language, Vol. 38, No. I.
Kneale, W. and M., The Development of Logic, Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1962.
Linsky, L., Referring, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1967.
Mathews, C., English Surnames, London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 1966.
Mill, J., A System of Logic, 10th ed., London: Longmans Green and Co.,
18 79.
Patridge, E., Name into Word: Proper Names That Have Become Common
Property, New York: Macmillan, 1950.
Quine, W., Methods of Logic, New York: Holt-Dryden, 1960.
Russell, B., Introduction to Mathematical PhilosoPhy, London, 1919.
- An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, London: George Allen, 1940.
- "Proper Names," Human Knowledge, New York, Simon and Schusler,
1948.
- "The Philosophy of Logical Atomism," Logic and Knowledge, ed. R. C.
Marsh, London: Allen and Unwin, 1951.
Searle, J.; "Proper Names," Mind, LXVII, No. 261, 1958.
- "Proper Names and Descriptions," The Encyclopedia of PhilosoPhy,
Vol. 6, New York: Collier-Macmillan, 1967.
Shawyder, D., Modes of Referring and the Problem of Universals, Uni-
versity of California Press, 1961.
- "Review of the Meaning of Proper Names by H. S. S0rensen," The
Journal of PhilosoPhy, LXI, No. 15, 1964.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 77
S0rensen, H., The Meaning of Proper Names: With a Definiens Formula
for Proper Names in Modern English, Copenhagen: Gad Publishers,
1963.
- Word-Classes in Modern English, Copenhagen: Gad Publishers, 1958.
Strawson, P., "On Referring," PhilosoPhy and Ordinary Language, ed.
C. G. Caton, University of Illinois Press, 1963.
- Introduction to Logical Theory, London: Methuen, 1952.
- "Review of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations," Mind, Vol.
LXIII, 1954.
- Individual, London: Methuen, 1959.
- "Review of S0rensen 'The Meaning of Proper Names' ", Mind, Vol.
LXXV, 1966.
Witycombe, E., The Oxford Dictionary of English Christian Names, Lon-
don: Oxford Press, 1947.
Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, translated by G. E. M.
Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1954.
Zabeeh, F., Universals: A New Look at an Old Problem, The Hague: Marti-
nus Nijhoff, 1966.
Ziff, P., Semantic Analysis, New York: Cornell University Press, 1960.
INDEX