States of Exception Law History Theory 2020
States of Exception Law History Theory 2020
This book addresses the relevance of the state of exception for the analysis of
law, while reflecting on the deeper symbolic and jurisprudential significance of
the coalescence between law and force.
The concept of the state of exception has become a central topos in poli-
tical and legal philosophy as well as in critical theory. The theoretical appa-
ratus of the state of exception sharply captures the uneasy relationship
between law, life and politics in the contemporary global setting, while also
challenging the comforting narratives that uncritically connect democracy
with the tradition of the rule of law. Drawing on critical legal theory, con-
tinental jurisprudence, political philosophy and history, this book explores the
genealogy of the concept of the state of exception and reflects on its legal
embodiment in past and present contexts – including Weimar and Nazi Ger-
many, contemporary Europe and Turkey. In doing so, it explores the dis-
ruptive force of the exception for legal and political thought, as it recuperates
its contemporary critical potential.
The book will be of interest to students and scholars in the field of jur-
isprudence, philosophy and critical legal theory.
series editors
for information about the series and details of previous and forthcoming
titles, see https://www.routledge.com/law/series/LPCP
States of Exception
Edited by
Cosmin Cercel, Gian Giacomo Fusco
and Simon Lavis
First published 2021
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
A Glasshouse book
© 2021 selection and editorial matter Cosmin Cercel, Gian Giacomo Fusco and
Simon Lavis; individual chapters, the contributors
The right of Cosmin Cercel, Gian Giacomo Fusco and Simon Lavis to be
identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their
individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of
the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any
information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the
publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent
to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record has been requested for this book
PART 1
Law, theory and the logic of the exception 13
1 Exception, fiction, performativity 15
GIAN GIACOMO FUSCO
PART 2
Histories of exception 117
6 ‘Norm’ and ‘exception’: From the Weimar Republic to the Nazi
state form 119
DIMITRIOS KIVOTIDIS
Index 212
Contributors
1.
State of exception is one of those concepts in the politico-juridical vocabulary
whose established popularity is not affected by their evident terminological uncer-
tainty. Since the beginning of the twenty-first century, with the emergence of what
has been defined as the war on terror, academic production on the subject has been
literally flooded by an imponent stream of contributions. However, at this historical
juncture, when exceptional measures have become a stable part of the seemingly
decadent life of liberal democracies, the problem of the state of exception seems to
have lost its appeal. Indeed, one of the reviewers of the early version of the proposal
for this book noted that interest in the state of exception is somehow declining.1
The thousands of pages on the legal and political reactions to emergencies that
have filled up books, academic journals and newspapers at the beginning of the new
millennium seem to have buried the state of exception under a blanket of obsoles-
cence. The interest in such an important doctrine of Western jurisprudence seems to
belong to the past, the remoteness of which, however, has not yet been fully deter-
mined. What is more, despite the debates fuelled by the implementation of the
legal-governmental measures that have created the global framework for the war
on terror, from the standpoint of liberal legalism emergencies remain a paradox.
In the face of the hyper-normalisation of emergencies, to sustain that the
question of the state of exception is not compelling or appealing anymore is,
for us, symptomatic of both a specific academic and legal myopia in the face
of blatant evidence, which we aim to challenge throughout this volume, and a
dependence of scientific focus on trends and fashion.
Yet, in this rather polemic introduction, there is a further and more disturbing
factor that must be taken into account to explain why the state of exception turns
out to be an obsolete question. It might be the case that the high tolerance of the
use of emergency powers and to the exuberance of executive powers, with the sub-
sequent erosion of basic rights as well as the emergence of authoritarian drives at
the core of liberal democracy, has become so normal as to make exceptions unin-
teresting. What makes the state of exception important is indeed its exceptionality,
and when this feature wanes, exceptions logically lose their appeal. Our considera-
tions, thus, can only be untimely: ‘that is to say, acting counter to our time and
thereby acting on our time and, let us hope, for the benefit of a time to come’.2
2.
The shock and awe that has engulfed the liberal legal establishment in the wake of
the authoritarian turn, the surge of nationalism and identarian politics, bewildering
as it may be, is indicative of the theoretical scarcity of the existing conceptual
paradigms that have fashioned the legal canon since the time of the fall of the
Berlin Wall, if not from the very early years of the post-war period. Faced with the
return of the repressed historical experience of authoritarianism, constitutional
theorists, jurisprudents, human rights lawyers and global governance theorists have
fallen prey to a moment of anxiety. In the presence of the repudiation of liberal
legality, the defenders of the existing ideological superstructure have sought com-
fort either in the core of legality or within models from political theory and political
science. As such, the ominous veer towards overt authoritarian practices – from
challenges to judicial independence3 and academic freedom4 to racism5 and the
questioning of legal certainty6 – has been read through the lens of populism.7
Concepts such as populist constitutionalism8, autocratic legalism9 and stealth
authoritarianism10 have become the new symbolic veil that covers a present
marked by conflict, tension, struggle and repression. What is left unchallenged is,
unsurprisingly, the place and function of legal normativity within this very
dynamic. As this strand of literature emphasises, even in the wake of all the current
devaluation of the democratic form: ‘liberalism is … a constitutive precondition for
democracy, which provides for the rule of law, checks and balances, and guaranteed
fundamental rights.’11
From this point on, we are brought back from where it all started,
namely the illusion surrounding law’s ability to institute democracy,12 if
not its necessary connection to the liberal form.13 As it has been observed
in a rather different context, ‘to each problem it appears to be a solution
and the solution is almost always law’.14 The models circulated so far in
an attempt to make sense of the present shift in politics and constitutional
practice within the legal field not only offer a limited and somewhat dis-
torted image of what the present crisis entails but function as a stop-gap,
positively preventing us from addressing the current status of legality and
inquiring into the features of authoritarianism in power. Authoritarian
rulers of the day, from Erdoǧan to Bolsonaro and Trump, from Putin to
Orbán and Kaczyński, are lumped together in a haphazard manner15 with
little attention being paid to their historical trajectories; as in a theatrics
of anti-legality, they are portrayed as omnipotent subjects cynically
manipulating the law to pursue their goals.16
For its part, the people, as the constitutional subject, is reduced to a silent
bystander of this profanation of legality, deprived of agency. In the background
the law is simply an inert instrument, subjected to reframing; insofar as the new
authoritarians ‘don’t destroy state institutions; they repurpose rather than abol-
ish the institutions they inherited’.17 At the antipodes, in celebrating the return of
the political,18 the critical field positively ignores the historical sources of the
present predicament19 while satisfying itself in forgetting the structural character
of the law, its resilient stickiness and its binding force in commanding and
detouring political trajectories. The common features of this quandary, shared
by both defenders and critics of the emerging regimes of legality, in approaching
the actual threat to the existing politico-legal order find their source in a shared
oblivion to law’s historical connivance with the authoritarian projects. What has
been forgotten in this process is law’s inscription and construction in relation to a
3.
In the last two decades, the succession of multiple and diversified emergencies
have had a decisive impact in Western governmental systems and societies, which
unsurprisingly reacted by strengthening their securitarian drives. In a rather dis-
turbing fashion, liberal democracies tended increasingly to challenge the pres-
sure brought by global crisis – from international terrorism to the current waves
of migration – through the hardening of police measures and the consequent
limitation of civil and political liberties. We are assisting an unprecedented pro-
liferation of non-ordinary legislative procedures, a growing role of executives and
of technocratic administrative bodies, to the detriment of the functioning of
legislative institutions that necessarily determines the restriction of areas of
political participation. Once more, emergencies are showing their fundamental
transformative potential. Indeed, the instruments and procedures, which are
typically activated to challenge periods of profound crisis, are gradually turned
into stable elements of government. Since the turn of the new millennium,
emergencies have triggered a drive towards a reactionary mutation of liberal
democratic institutions, disguised as a necessary response to tensions and threats,
whose reality is often spectacular rather than substantial.
Democratic regimes are traditionally equipped with emergency constitutional
measures, such as the state of siege (or war) and martial law, which maintain an
4.
The starting point of our work is the recognition that the theoretical apparatus of
the state of exception sharply captures the uneasy relationship between law, life and
politics while at the same time challenging the comforting narratives that uncriti-
cally connect democracy with the tradition of the rule of law. As such, the exception
exposes a caesura within the very structure of the law (understood as a system of
signification), which opposes the normative legal content to the unarticulated force
of law. The state of siege, uses of martial law, the recourse to expedient legal pro-
cedures during and beyond times of crises, the rise of military and administrative
powers, and the confusion between legal, administrative and military categories all
seem to document and embody the essential fracture between form and force fos-
tered by our legal systems functioning under the aegis of the exception. Yet the
exception is not reducible to these historical instantiations, but also arguably seizes
on an important, yet thoroughly overlooked, aspect of modern societies, namely
the fact that ‘confronted with an excess, the system interiorizes what exceeds it
through an interdiction and in this way “designates itself as exterior to itself”’.26
Embodied in the figure of a socio-political standoff – as stasis, or civil
war – or in the recurrent use of emergency decrees, the exception represents
an abnormal course of the law, a limit-experience emerging at the point of
encounter between the legal order and the contingency of the social and the
political. The liminality of the exception, its peculiar position (or place), as a
limit or threshold, renders such a concept a privileged heuristic sign for
approaching the normal functioning of law in its intimate relation with the
other spheres of social life. As Lon Fuller perspicuously observed:
When all goes well and established legal rules encompass neatly the social
life they are intended to regulate … the law … proceeds with a transparent
simplicity suggesting no need for reflective scrutiny. Only in illness, we are
told, does the body reveal its complexity. Only when legal reasoning falters
and reaches out clumsily for help do we realize what a complex undertaking
the law is.27
26 Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Daniel Heller-
Roazen transl. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998 [1995]), 18.
27 Lon Fuller, Legal Fictions (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1967), viii.
Introduction 7
5.
This volume contains nine essays and an afterword. The contributions pro-
vide a panoply of different perspectives on the question of the state of
exception in theory and practice. As editors, we did not pursue homogeneity
of vision or uniformity in the style of presentation of arguments. Rather
Introduction 9
but to perceive in this darkness a light that (…) infinitely distances itself
from us’.28 However, it is not only this temporal dimension, which imbues
our projects, but also a shared consciousness of the need to reflect on the
exception through local contexts, and historical settings that have shaped its
global articulation. While Weimar and Nazi Germany remain reference
points for such investigations, critical histories of the exception in Turkey,
socialist Poland and putatively liberal Italy are other starting points for
uncovering the operation of the exception.
Following this path, this book is as much an exercise in thinking the excep-
tion with, against and beyond the authors who have apposed their signature on
its contemporary theorisation, an act that takes on a perhaps sacrificial
dimension. Such a refusal of the ‘name of the Father’ is a reaction to the very
unfolding of the state of exception, which continues to grow before our eyes.
This brings us to a last element of commonality marking this collection, that is
its relative generational homogeneity: as critical lawyers and theorists socialised
and marked by the perpetual presence of the exception, we are wary both of its
conceptual limits in describing the antinomies of contemporary legality, as well
as its constant deployment in the politico-legal realm. The contributions are,
each in its own way, attempts at moving beyond the exception, either by unra-
velling its conceptual limits or by exposing its historical roots.
The essays are grouped in two parts. The first, ‘Law, theory and the logic of
the exception’, includes five essays focusing on some of the more thorny the-
oretical aspects raised by the state of exception as a jurisprudential object.
The second part, ‘histories of the exception’, instead, is composed of four
essays, which investigate the theory and practice of the administration of
emergency powers, with direct reference to historical events. In organising the
volume in such a way, we intended the first part as laying down the theore-
tical framework for the second part. And of course, in a dialectical fashion,
the more historical interpretations included in the second part are meant to
offer a confirmation of some of the hypotheses advanced in the first. However,
given the varied nature and the scope of the contributions constituting the
book, it is ultimately up to the readers to find connections and contrasts
between the two parts.
The volume opens with Gian Giacomo Fusco’s ‘Exception, fiction, perfor-
mativity’, which addresses in a genealogical fashion the state of exception as a
legal object. By looking to what has been defined as the ‘fictitious state of
exception’, this chapter argues that the modern legal provisions for the
administration of emergency powers should be considered as specific legal
techniques whose inner logic is akin to that of legal fictions. Therefore, the
state of exception, which is generally interpreted as a reaction to a given fac-
tual situation, should be better understood in terms of performativity.
28 Giorgio Agamben, Nudities, David Kishik and Stefan Pedatella transl. (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2011), 14–15.
Introduction 11
The second essay is Cosmin Cercel’s ‘“Through a glass, darkly”: Law, his-
tory and the frontispiece of the exception’, which tackles critically the state of
exception in its relation to the status of legal normativity and the legal form.
This chapter maintains that in order to understand the political confusion of
the present status of legality, perpetually used as a powerful tool to legitimise
a transformation of liberal democratic regimes into quasi-authoritarian
executive-driven government, it is necessary to enquire into the theory and
practice of the state of exception in its tension with legal form and practice.
Cercel’s study is followed by Przemysław Tacik’s ‘The other side of excep-
tion: Sovereignty, modernity and international law’. This chapter, by focusing
on Agamben’s theory of the exception, aims at exploring the relationship
between sovereignty, international law and modernity that is nearly absent in
Agamben’s writings due to the aforementioned interrelated omissions. The
concept of the state of exception, originally pertaining to the field reigned by
sovereignty, might be well adapted to international law, where they take up
the position of the obverse side of national sovereigns. In this view, the
notorious conflation of fact and law in the international order appears not as
a contingent flaw, but an immanent feature of this order, correlative to the
mechanism of exception under sovereign power. Finally, Agamben’s analyses
of the phenomenon of camps will be used to explore the link between sover-
eignty, bare life and international law.
In Tormod Otter Johansen ‘Minor law: Notes towards a revolutionary jur-
isprudence’, Agamben’s critique of the state of exception and of sovereign
violence is coupled with Pashukanis’ Marxian theory of law. By scrutinising
the basic assumption that sees the self-standing of legal orders as necessarily
connected to the force of coercive violence, this chapter tries to think law as a
form of non-coercive social organisation. However, this implies a radical shift
from the ‘traditional’ hegemonic conception of law as regulation based on
given forms of obligation, towards a ‘minor law’, which in normativity is
sustained without any form of authority.
The final essay of Part I is Simon Lavis’ ‘The exception of the norm in the
Third Reich: (Re)reading the Nazi constitutional state of exception’, which
focuses on the vexed question of the legal status of ‘Nazi Law’. Through a
close engagement with the ‘dual’ character of the state’s law under Hitler’s
regime, this chapter investigates how the theory of the state of exception could
be used to interrogate and understand the mobile limits of the two sides of the
law – the informal/authoritarian; and the use of formal rule of law-driven
regulation – in the Third Reich. More specifically, this contribution seeks to
establish Agamben’s work on the state of exception as a useful tool to read
critically the legal aporia of the Third Reich.
Part 2 commences with Dimitrios Kivotidis’ ‘“Norm” and “exception”:
From the Weimar Republic to the Nazi state form’. In this chapter, Kivotidis
examines the unity between ‘norm’ and ‘exception’ as different forms of
exercise of public power. According to this reading, both ‘norm’ and
12 Giacomo Fusco et al.
‘exception’ are essential forms for the reproduction of bourgeois rule and the
change from one form to the other is contingent upon the intensification of
socio-economic antagonisms. This argument is pursued on the basis of an
examination of the transition from the Weimar Republic to the Nazi state
form, as reflected in the work of Carl Schmitt.
This is followed by Rafał Mańko’s ‘“Our Fatherland has found itself on
the verge of an abyss”: Poland’s 1981 martial law, or the unexpected
appearance of the state of exception under actually existing socialism’,
which offers a unique in its genre interpretation of the uses and con-
sequences of the martial law implemented in Poland in early 1980s. Such
event represents a rare example of the use of exceptional power in a socialist
country, where the working class is nominally sovereign, and where legality
does not take the ‘liberal’ form of Western democracies. In this chapter,
Mańko, by retracing the legal foundation of the Polish martial law and
specific jurisprudential meaning of the General’s dictatorship, exposes how,
paradoxically, the state of exception in the context of really existing social-
ism served as an instrument to the transition to a more liberal democracy
and capitalism.
Ceylan Begum Yildiz’s chapter, ‘A state in anomie: An analysis of modern
Turkey’s states of exception’ considers the transformation of exceptional
measures from a historical perspective while exposing the pattern of states of
exceptions in Turkey. Her chapter follows Agamben’s lead in investigating
Turkey as an anomic state, while introducing a subject-oriented perspective to
unfold the particular pattern of states of exception upon which the Turkish
nation state was built and continues to exist.
In the final chapter of Part II, Sara Raimondi’s ‘Beyond “the most serious
suspension of rights” of Genoa: Violence, anomie and force (of law)’
demonstrates that the taxonomy of the exception stretches beyond the
instances commonly found in the existing literature and opens up the ques-
tion of the function of exceptional measures within the context of con-
temporary democracies. In this regard, the analysis highlights how, across
multiple contexts, the exception operates at the intersection and blurring
point of the juridical and the political, right and violence, inside and out-
side, legal and physical status of those who are victims of exceptional prac-
tices, and of citizenship and bare life. The case of abuses and law-suspension
in Genoa offers an example of exception beyond its factual declaring and
demonstrates that exceptional instances are used by states also in the con-
text of democratic life, and, potentially, against their own citizens whenever
state institutions feel threatened.
Part 1
Introduction
A few days after the terrorist attacks in Paris of 13 November 2015, the
French president François Hollande spoke before a joint session of parlia-
ment in this way:
France is at war. The acts committed in Paris and near the Stade de
France on Friday evening are acts of war. They left at least 129 dead and
many injured. They are an act of aggression against our country, against
its values, against its young people, and against its way of life. They were
carried out by a jihadist army, by Daesh, which is fighting us because
France is a country of freedom, because we are the birthplace of human
rights. At this exceptionally solemn moment, I wanted to address a joint
session of Parliament to demonstrate our national unity in the face of
such an abomination and to respond with the cool determination that
this vile attack against our country calls for […] I shall marshal the full
strength of the State to defend the safety of its people. I know I can count
on the dedication of police officers, gendarmes, service personnel, and
you yourselves, our national representatives.1
powers of the president in the case of severe crisis (regulated by art. 16 of the
constitution).
3 “Loi n° 2017–1510 du 30 octobre 2017 renforçant la sécurité intérieure et la lutte
contre le terrorism”, see: www.legifrance.gouv.fr/affichTexte.do?cidTexte=JORF
TEXT000035932811&dateTexte=&categorieLien=id
4 On the integration and normalisation of emergency laws into democratic regimes,
see: Jean-Claude Paye, Global War on Liberty, James H. Membrez transl. (New
York: Telos Press, 2007); Günter Frankenberg, Political Technology and the Ero-
sion of the Rule of Law: Normalizing the State of Exception, H. Bauer, G. Fran-
kenberg transl. (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2014); Ryan Patrick Alford,
Permanent State of Emergency: Unchecked Executive Power and the Demise of
the Rule of Law (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2017); Alan
Greene, Permanent States of Emergency and the Rule of Law: Constitutions in an
Age of Crisis (London: Bloomsbury, 2018).
5 President Hollande was fully aware of this. Indeed, he stated that ‘the law which
governs the state of emergency of 3 April 1955 cannot really match the kind of
technologies and threats we face today’ and ‘Our Constitution currently has two
specific schemes that are not appropriate for the situation we are in. The first
scheme involves Article 16 of the Constitution. It specifies that the regular func-
tioning of public authorities be suspended. The president will then take such
measures as warranted by the circumstances, overriding the distribution of the
constitutional powers. And then there’s Article 36 of the Constitution, which
relates to the state of siege. And this isn’t appropriate either. A state of siege is
decreed in situations of imminent peril resulting from a foreign war or an armed
insurrection. In this situation, various powers are then transferred from the civil
to the military authorities’. See ‘Speech by the President of the Republic before a
joint session of Parliament’.
Exception, fiction, performativity 17
which ‘a state of peace itself can at the same time be a state of emergency’,6
on the grounds of a decision of a legitimate authority.
In its canonical definition, the state of exception consists of a partial or
complete temporary suspension of a normative order to safeguard its sur-
vival in a critical situation, which usually entails the restriction of certain
rights and constitutional guarantees and a variable infringement of the
principle of separation of powers, through the delegation of special powers
to the executive. As such, the state of exception finds its (onto)logical
presupposition, and its only raison d’être, in the presence of determinate
exceptional facts constituting a threat for the state. As has been observed,
an ‘emergency is a state of fact; however, as the brocard fittingly says, e
facto oritur ius [law arises from fact]’.7 But the widespread use and abuse
of emergency powers that we are witnessing teaches us that the relation of
determination between the exception as a fact and the exception as a legal
response is not as strict as it might seem at a theoretical level. The use of
the state of emergency and more generally of exceptional laws is now so
common that their relation to a factual necessity seems lost. In this
regard, Kim Lane Scheppele maintains that emergency powers, in con-
temporary constitutional regimes when used, are ‘never the sort of total
emergencies […] as one might imagine from theory’8; they are imple-
mented partially, discreetly and pervasively, altering the substance of the
law but leaving a semblance of legality intact, often on the ground of
‘rhetorical’ threats.
When the exception becomes a regulated and normalised technique of
government, the verification of its legality or illegality – a central trope of
past and present jurisprudence9 – becomes a trivial enterprise. More
6 Slavoj Žižek, Welcome To The Desert of The Real! Five Essays on September 11
and Related Dates (London: Verso, 2002), 107.
7 Gaetano Arangio-Ruiz, Istituzioni di diritto costituzionale italiano (Milan: Bocca,
1972 [1913]), 528.
8 Kim Lan Scheppele, ‘Legal and Extra-Legal Emergencies’, in K. E. Whittington
and G. A. Caldeira (eds), Oxford Handbook of Law and Politics (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2008), 174.
9 From the first half of the twentieth century, with the so-called debate on con-
stitutional dictatorship, to the more recent legal analysis of the emergencies
within the war on terror, scholars in challenging the issues of exceptional powers
divided themselves into legalist and extra-legalist; those ‘who seek to include the
state of exception within the sphere of the juridical order and those who consider
it something external, that is, an essentially political, or in any case extra-jur-
idical, phenomenon’. These models are ‘defined via a spatial metaphor of law as a
container’, assuming the form of a discourse over the limits and the places of law
and exception. For the legalists, exceptional measures have to be considered as
part of the legal system, and emergencies must be met legally recurring to them.
The extra-legalists instead consider the state of exception as something irre-
ducible to the legal form, something that is and must remain outside the limits of
the law; thus, serious crisis must be challenged without the formal-procedural
18 Gian Giacomo Fusco
important, instead, would be calling into question the very nature of the
exception as a ‘legal object’, which ‘lies squarely within the field of public
law’.10 To this end, in this chapter, taking inspiration from some arguments
advanced by Carl Schmitt and Giorgio Agamben, I will examine what has
been termed as fictitious (or political) state of exception. Emerging in the
context of the French Revolution in relation to the doctrine of the state of
siege, the idea of a fictitious state of exception – as opposed to a real one –
represents a kind of prototype for all the contemporary forms of regulated
emergency powers. As we will see, a state of exception is ‘fictitious’ inasmuch
as it allows for a suspension of the normal course of the law on the base of a
‘subjective’ decision (usually made according to the loose criteria of emer-
gency, security, danger, imminent threat, etc.); for this reason, crucial to the
regulation of the state of emergency is who has the authority to decide it. And
because of its rather peculiar relation with facts, in what follows I will argue
that the state of exception should be considered as a specific legal technique
whose function and logic is akin to those of legal fictions. Consequently, the
possibility of abusing emergency powers simply to obtain a certain goal, and
not as a reaction to a chain of perilous events, will appear as inscribed in the
very nature of the exception as a legal object. But this raises a further crucial
philosophical and jurisprudential point. Generally, the state of exception has
been interpreted as a reaction to a given situation of danger; in this chapter, I
will argue instead that the exception must be better understood in terms of
performativity.
limits of the law. Moreover, for the extra-legalists, the inclusion of the exception
into the realm of law accounts for a proper contamination of law itself by per-
verting the central principles of the rule of law. See: G. Agamben, State of
Exception (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005); Scheppele, ‘Legal and
Extra-Legal Emergencies’; and William E. Scheuerman, ‘Survey Article: Emer-
gency Powers and the Rule of Law After 9/11’, (2006) 14(1) Journal of Political
Philosophy 61.
10 Martin Loughlin, Foundations of Public Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2010), 402.
11 Frankenberg, Political Technology and the Erosion of the Rule of Law: Normal-
izing the State of Exception, 12–13.
Exception, fiction, performativity 19
12 Ibid., 80.
13 Carl Schmitt, Dictatorship, Michael Hoelzl and Graham Ward transl. (Cam-
bridge: Polity, 2014 [1921]), 158.
20 Gian Giacomo Fusco
responsibility only over the army and military affairs; the ‘state of war’ [état
de guerre], in which policing responsibility remained in the hands of civilian
bodies but the military commanders were entitled to assume police powers
when necessary for the military security of the area; and the ‘state of siege’
[état de siege], where all the legal functions of civilian authorities concerning
the maintenance of order and police force passed to the military commander,
who exercised them personally.14
As Schmitt argued, the concept of the state of siege underwent a radical
mutation when ‘the actual state of siege was replaced by a declaration of
state of siege’.15 During the turmoil that preceded the birth of the Second
Republic, a decree of the Constituent Assembly issued on 24 June 1848
placed the city of Paris in a state of siege. The ‘commendable performance’
of the commissar, and the success of the measures taken, led to the con-
stitutionalising of the state of siege with the law of 9 August 1849.16 This
provision was updated and amended in 1878, in conformity with new con-
stitutional arrangements. With the reduction of the state of siege to a con-
stitutional doctrine, Schmitt maintains, the government acquired the power
to determine the ‘state of siege whenever it deemed it necessary. The formal
act of the government’s declaration supplanted the real state of emergency.
The concept gained a political meaning; the technical-military procedure
was employed in the service of domestic politics’.17 In this moment, the
state of siege has undergone a radical mutation: it has lost its factual char-
acter as reflecting an actual situation (état de siege), and has become a
formal act of a government (état de siege fictive), depending on a decision of
a governing (sovereign) agent.
It is worth looking at the words of the constitutional provisions for the state
of siege, as included in the law of 1878:
9. The military authority has the power, (1) to conduct searches by day
or night in the homes of citizens; (2) to deport liberated convicts and
persons who do not have residence in the areas placed in the state of
siege; (3) to direct the surrender of arms and munitions, and to proceed
to search for and remove them; (4) to forbid publications and meetings
which it judges to be of a nature to incite or sustain disorder. 11 Despite
the state of siege, citizens continue to exercise the rights guaranteed by
the Constitution whose enjoyment is not suspended by the preceding
articles.18
Essential to the fictional state of siege, Schmitt points out, is that ‘the
authorization to take an action that the given situation necessitates has been
replaced by a number of limited functions’.19 In the modern constitutional
state, he goes on, ‘the solid unity of the state had finally been secured.
Tumults and riots could disturb the security, but the homogeneity of the state
would not be seriously threatened by social factions within it’; and in a stable
situation ‘the execution can be regulated according to legal procedure, as long
as the enemy is not a power that throws into question this unity’.20 The state
of siege, in its fictional-political version, represents the general paradigmatic-
model for constitutional provision regulating emergency powers; as Rossiter
suggested, ‘the state of siege was the model for similar instruments […] in
almost all […] civil law countries, and even in Anthony Hope’s mythical
Ruritania’.21
The development of the doctrine of the state of siege, from a pure
military to a fictive-political form, represented a substantial turning point
for the legal conception of crisis management. As Schmitt noted, the fic-
tional state of siege became the nodal point of a legal fiction22 since the
‘siege’ was no longer dependent on the presence of factual conditions but
became determined by a decision. Indeed, the evolution of the doctrine of
the state of siege
Dictatorship, Iustitium
In his strenuous critique of liberal legality and of the pretence of the principle
of the ‘rule of law’, Schmitt defines as ‘fictitious’ a state of exception that is
regulated by law, with the scope of preserving some individual rights and
liberties. This is very briefly the conclusion he reaches in the last chapters of
the book on Dictatorship, where he suggests that with the regulation of ‘dic-
tatorial’ powers typical of modern constitutional regimes, what was deter-
mined de facto – as a logical reaction to a determined situation of danger –
has been transformed into something that must be ‘decided on’. It seems,
though, that for Schmitt the very transformation of dictatorial powers into a
legal doctrine makes of the exception something fictional.
The idea of the state of exception as essentially ‘fictitious’ (if not properly a
legal fiction) is a central tenet of Agamben’s State of Exception. In this book he
criticises Schmitt’s genealogy of the exception (while admittedly accepting its
substantial arguments). For Agamben, the ancestor of the modern state of
exception must not be identified in the figure of the ‘dictatorship’, but in another
institute of Roman law: the iustitium. Along with the more popular dictatorship,
in fact, the iustitium represented a further instrument for the administration and
solution of crisis. While the first envisaged a specific magistrate that assumed full
powers for no longer than six months, the latter did not concern the election of a
single figure and the definition of a specific mandate but materialised itself in a
generalised suspension and alteration of the legal system.
In the first centuries of the Roman Republican history, the iustitium was
declared in particularly serious situations. This was usually followed by a tempo-
rally limited suspension of judicial and legal activities, decreed by a magistrate to
respond to a particular need (usually the recruitment of soldiers). Confronted with
a situation that endangered the Republic, the Senate had the possibility of ema-
nating a senatus consultum ultimum [final decree of the senate] by which the con-
suls, the praetor and the tribunes of the people and in extreme cases, all citizens,
are called to take whatever measures they deem necessary for the salvation of the
state. This special ‘consultum’ was based upon a decree declaring a tumultus
[tumult] (an emergency resulting from a foreign war, insurrection or civil war),
which usually led to the proclamation of the iustitium.
The key element in this legal procedure is the tumultus, which is not a term
designating a war or a specific form of emergency but a general term desig-
nating the magna trepidatio, the general state of agitation. Agamben notes
that the tumult represents the key element, the necessary presupposition, for
the iustitium to be declared. Much like in a state of emergency, the tumult is
something that must be determined and defined before the necessary legal
consequences ensue. The senate had the authority to decide on the presence
of an emergency situation, such as the imminent threat of enemy aggression
or disorder or the danger of the rise of a civil war, and in all these situations it
can declare a tumultum to be in place; this procedure is already in itself a
system of alert for the population, necessary to speed up and streamline the
otherwise rigid formalities of the decision-making process.
But what exactly is a tumultus? In the Philippics, Cicero states the
‘canonic’ definition of tumult by distinguishing it from a war: ‘for there
can be war without a tumult, there can be no tumult without a war. For
what else is a tumult than a confusion so great that greater fear arises
from it?’ For Cicero, the tumult must be distinguished as different from
both war and all other specific states of crisis. Agamben in this regard
claims that a tumult is not a war, ‘but technically designates the state of
disorder and unrest’. Much like the modern idea of an emergency, the
term ‘tumult’ constitutes for Roman law ‘the caesura by means of which,
from the point of view of public law, exceptional measures may be taken’.
‘The relation between bellum and tumultus’, Agamben concludes, ‘is the
same one that exists between war and military state of siege on the one
hand and state of exception and political state of siege on the other’.25
Hence, Agamben concludes, the state of exception as a general alteration
of a normative order has its paradigmatic ancestor not in the dictator-
ship – as Schmitt seems to suggest – but in the iustitium.
Despite this divergence, Agamben agrees with Schmitt on a crucial point:
the modern state of exception, as a regulated technical form of government,
by definition involves what is to a certain extent a work of fiction. Given its
dependence on the decision of a sovereign authority, the state of exception
becomes an effective instrument to be turned on or off at will, even when a
threat has not yet materialised or its being a menace is not explicitly evident.
Indeed, already in imperial Rome the use of the state of exception – in the
form of the iustitium – had become ‘nothing other than the sovereign’s
attempt to appropriate the state of exception by transforming it into a family
affair’.26 For this reason, in Agamben, the legal production of the state of
exception assumes the guise of an instrument that allows a body to act legally
in derogation of the law; it is the specific fiction through which the law finds
the ‘special law’ has been enacted through the use of decree-law; and it was
starting from the experience of the 1970’s that in Italy the use of such a normative
tool became common practice. Some defined such misuse of executive emergency
power a pathology, others highlighted the blatant unconstitutionality of it; in any
case, law-decrees now constitute the normal form of legislation to such a degree
that they have been described as ‘bills strengthened by guaranteed emergency'.
This implies, however, that the democratic principle of the separation of powers
has been altered and that the executive power has in fact, at least partially,
absorbed the legislative power. See: Carlo Fresa, Provvisorietà con forza di legge e
gestione degli stati di crisi (Padova: CEDAM, 1981); Pietro Pinna, L’emergenza
nell’ordinamento costituzionale italiano (Milano: Giuffrè, 1988); Andrea Cardone,
La ‘normalizzazione’ dell’emergenza: Contributo allo studio del potere extra ordi-
nem del Governo (Torino: Giappichelli, 2011); Giovanna Pistorio, La Decreta-
zione d’urgenza (Roma:Tre-Press, 2016).
36 Schmitt, Dictatorship, 160.
37 Agamben, State of Exception, 59.
38 Annelise Riles, ‘Is the Law Hopeful?’, Cornell Law Faculty Working Papers, 2010, 68.
39 Yan Thomas, ‘FictioLegis’, in Les Opérations du droit (Paris: Le Seuil, 2011),
133.
Exception, fiction, performativity 27
The operative logic of legal fictions consists of the creation of specific fic-
titious facts that allow the law to apply to circumstances in which it could not
normally be applied. In this sense, fictions are a useful technical tool for the
adaptation of an order of norms to unforeseen circumstances while remaining
unchanged. As Maine puts it, a legal fiction ‘conceals, or affects to conceal,
the fact that a rule of law has undergone alteration, its letter remaining
unchanged, its operation being modified’.44 The implementation of legal fic-
tions involves an actual change in the law while maintaining the fiction that it
remained the same.45 The underlying logic of the state of exception, thus,
could be consider as analogous to the one of legal fiction: in both cases an
alteration of the normal rule of law is the outcome of a non-objective deter-
mination of facts, while supposedly keeping the text of the law intact in its
punctual suspension/modification. The early formulation of the fictitious state
of siege is in this respect particularly instructive. In this case, the suspension
of certain rights protected by the law is the outcome of the ‘fiction’, according
to which a specific area under threat as to be regarded in law as if besieged.
But this implies logically that the law remains unchanged while its application
is modified.
So, it might be argued that the doctrine of the exception shares with the
legal fiction the peculiarity of being an instrument for the modification or
alteration of the law with the pretence of maintaining its continuity.
Indeed, they are both considered in legal theory as techniques imple-
mented to preserve the letter of the law in the face of new, unpredicted
facts. Therefore, it might be argued that the state of exception and legal
fictions share the same nature: they are both technical instruments allow-
ing, in different ways, the preservation of the law through its substantial
modification. Both the state of exception and legal fictions involve a non-
objective determination of facts; however, for the latter, legal consequences
are decided on the base of false premises, while for the former the partial
or total suspension of a normative order could be the outcome of a ‘real’
emergency. Moreover, a further distinction must be made: if the legal fic-
tion is aimed to create specific (fictional and false) facts for the application
of a limited set of rules, the exception’s purpose is to create the concrete
possibility of the suspension and non-application of the law – with all the
risks this enterprise brings. In both cases, however, the law calls – legally –
to exceed its dictates in order to gain the condition of its possibility,
guaranteeing for itself the ability to act on the outside. Indeed, both legal
fictions and the exception are essentially illegal; but it is this illegality that
allows the law to preserve its integrity.
Performativity
In a compelling passage on the significance of emergency powers as a para-
digm of government, Agamben argues that ‘the state of exception appears as
the opening of a fictitious lacuna in the order for the purpose of safeguarding
the existence of the norm and its applicability to the normal situation’; this
lacuna, he continues, ‘is not within the law [la legge], but concerns its relation
to reality’.46 Indeed, the exception, according to what has been argued so far,
calls into question law’s relation to reality in a twofold way. First, being con-
figured as a reaction to a determined critical situation it exposes the rather
feeble link that ties law’s normative integrity to the contingency of events.
Second, as with all legal principles and categories, the state of exception is a
paradigm of the peculiar modality in which the language of law relates and
inform reality. For the law, facts are not simply things placed in the outside
world waiting to be discovered. On the contrary, as Geoffrey Samuels
explains:
The idea that legal science is a discourse that has its object in actual
factual situations is to misunderstand, fundamentally, legal thought. …
[Law] functions as much within the world of fact as within the world of
law and it is this dual role that endows it with its capacity to create vir-
tual facts. Lawyers, like scientists, do not work directly on reality but
construct rationalized models of this reality, and it is these models that
become the ‘objects’ of legal discourse. The models of fact upon which
the […] lawyers work are as ‘virtual’.47
In this sense, the concept of state of exception and the whole terminological
arsenal of emergency laws are the specific virtual facts (or legal patterns)
through which the law apprehends its relationship with the contingency of
social and political (but also economic) events. And as we have seen pre-
viously through the words of Alexander Hamilton, it is the difficulty for the
law to ‘grasp’ what will happen next that makes the legal language of emer-
gency powers necessarily indeterminate (or virtual).
But, as is always the case with the law, legal objects and decisions, no
matter how virtual or fictional, have ‘real’ consequences. To paraphrase Hans
Vaihinger, for the law ‘the world of the “unreal” is just as important as the
world of the so-called real or actual (in the ordinary sense of the word);
indeed it is far more important’.48 Its ritual formality and functional systemic
closure makes the law capable of creating ‘new worlds out of old ones in a
process which one could describe […] as fact from fiction’.49 However, legal
objects – the world the law concurs in creating – are not something the reality
of which must be doubted. It is difficult to deny the existence binding rela-
tions and subjectivities, created by law’s words. The law is indeed nothing
other than a linguistic practice capable of creating its own reference in the
outside world: or as Agamben maintains, the law is ‘the realm in which all
language tends to assume a performative value’.50
The idea of performativity has proven to be particularly instructive for
characterising the constructive link between law’s language and reality. To put
it bluntly, the paradigm of performativity in law, while addressing the una-
voidable bond that ties the spheres of legal normativity and the outside world,
presupposes the neat distinction between the plane of norms and command
and the reality they are called to regulate. In this light, legal objects can have
a real effect on the world as long as they are not facts. What constitutes law’s
performative essence is the capacity to produce a reality, which stands apart
from the factual world but at the same time has an effect on it. Indeed, it
could be argued that the law is a discursive practice in which dwells the same
creational potentiality of language. A fact, an event or a thing becomes part
of the (legal) world only when is translated into the language of law: ‘quod
non est in actis non est in mundo’.51
The poignancy of the paradigm of performativity for jurisprudence is
acknowledged by John L. Austin, the author who first developed it into a
theory. As he claimed, not without a certain sarcasm, the dismissal of the
question of performativity of legal utterances, and the ‘widespread obsession
that the utterances of the law … must somehow be statements true or false,
has prevented many lawyers from getting this whole matter much straigh-
ter’.52 Austin’s theory is as simple as it is enigmatic: there are some linguistic
elements, the speech acts, the meaning of which refers to a reality that their
own enunciation creates. The examples are well known (to declare, to pro-
mise, to command, etc.) and an explanation here is not required for the pur-
poses of this paper. What is important to take into account is that
performative speech acts require conditions that, if not met, make them to fail
in their function. A speech act takes place only when is uttered according to
precise circumstances, which authorise and guarantee its validity. Austin listed
four necessary conditions for a performative utterance to succeed:
This list of necessary conditions could be grouped in two sets: on the one
hand we have what might be termed procedural rules that must be followed
(accepted conventional procedure that must be executed correctly and com-
pletely); on the other hand we find the authoritative aspect of the act,
according to which a performative utterance will have the desired effect only
when pronounced by the ‘appropriate’ author-person. If the conditions are
not met, Austin claims, we are in presence of infelicities – that is, acts the
performativity of which ‘misfires’. When a person already married utters a
marriage vow – or when the marriage is celebrated without the necessary
ritual-normative procedure – the act proffered simply does not take place, and
no marriage occurs. And by the same token, anyone can shout in a public
square, ‘I declare the state of national emergency’, and ‘as it cannot be an act
because the requisite authority is lacking, such an utterance is no more than
words; it reduces itself to futile clamour, childishness, or lunacy’.54
As has been observed, the ‘necessary conditions’ that Austin placed as vital to
a speech act are rather close to the “validating conditions” of obligations, con-
tracts and covenants more generally.55 For the law, a statement assumes legal
force only when pronounced or validated by a person whose position gives her
the appropriate authority, as decreed by a certain accepted conventional proce-
dure. The coincidence between the law’s practice and the validating conditions of
a performative act is here glaring: the sentence of a judge – to legislate, to sti-
pulate a contract, etc. – needs, like a speech act, the presence of both a proce-
dural (formal-normative) and an authoritative (personal) element. These two
elements must work in synergy to make law’s statements legally valid.
From this point of view, the state of exception appears as a legal perfor-
mance (carried out according to an established ‘accepted conventional
53 Ibid., 14–15.
54 Émile Benveniste, Problems in General Linguistic (Miami: University of Miami
Press, 1971), 236.
55 Elaine Scarry, ‘The Declaration of War: Constitutional and Unconstitutional
Violence’, in Austin Sarat and Thomas R. Kearns (eds), Law’s Violence (Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2009), 29. See also: Howard Warrender,
The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: His Theory of Obligation (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1957).
32 Gian Giacomo Fusco
Conclusion
The modern doctrine of the state of exception as a fictitious or political
technique of government is rooted in the experience of being besieged, which
is in the most perilous situation for the survivorship of the integrity of the
state. And this is visible in the language of emergency laws. From a strictly
legal point of view, the state of exception consists of a crisis reaction
mechanism that delegates to a single body exceptional powers in order to
restore a condition of normality as quickly as possible. The state of exception
is thus intended as a tool to protect a given constituted order in times of
crisis. But by providing the authority to declare a ‘state’ of emergency as
being in place, the doctrine of the exception allows a legitimate authority to
make ‘real’ what it is not, or what it is not yet real. Such a decision, as has
been argued, must be considered a work of fiction – with, however, very real
consequences, the most important of which is the obfuscation of the classic
categories of ‘war’ and ‘peace’.
The recognition that the fictional state of exception, as a form of adminis-
tration of emergency regulated by law, might offer a vehicle for abusive state
action has always been clear. The risk is that the increased concentration of
governmental powers, along with an alteration of the constitutional checks and
balances, could foster the emergence of an authoritarian system out of a
democratic one. Already Rossiter in his seminal work on constitutional dicta-
torship maintained that emergencies tend to perpetuate themselves, despite all
the control mechanisms typically present in constitutions. As he claimed, the
impression that the delegation of legislative powers, the making of law by
Exception, fiction, performativity 33
decree and in general the state of emergency are purely transitory and tem-
porary solutions is just misleading. On the contrary, he goes on, ‘the instru-
ments of government depicted here as temporary “crisis” arrangements have in
some countries, and may eventually in all countries, become lasting peacetime
institutions’.56 And recent developments are further proof of this trend.
It thus seems as if the possibility of being abused is inscribed in the very
nature of the state of exception as a legal object – and this is a belief shared
by many.57 In order to improve our position in the struggle against an
exception that has become the rule and given the incessant failures of jur-
isprudence to find a way out of this, the task before us is to move towards
thinking of legal normality with no exceptions – even if this means going
beyond the law as we know it.
1 Research for this chapter was undertaken in the context of the research project enti-
tled ‘Heads of State (Princes, Kings and Presidents) and the Authoritarian Dynamic
of Political Power in Romanian Constitutional History’, funded by the Romanian
Research Funding Agency (UEFISCDI), PN-III-P4-ID-PCE-2016–0013.
‘Through a glass, darkly’ 35
projects of modernity9 that that era has fostered. In doing so, they reconstruct
the law according to new ideological lines and expose the ‘unworked
through’, resistant past within the contemporary imaginaries of the Western
legal traditions. This is not simply a case of reconnecting to past experience,
of mimicking or reproducing modes of political takeover in an attempt to
seizing power; rather it is an affirmation of what has always already been part
of the constitutional and political horizon of our polities. From the stand-
point of a longue durée history of the law, we are now witnessing yet another
moment in a process of increasing affirmation of the powers of the execu-
tive,10 sweeping constitutional guarantees and securing control over the legal
apparatus.11 It is from within this line of inquiry that the continuity with the
past politico-legal practices is not simply a rhetorical and ideological trope
raised in order to provoke, soothe or shock our political sensitivities but a
historical nexus that can be documented through an analysis of the regimes of
legality in place in Europe and beyond.12
ideological weight and semantic luggage. As Peter Sloterdijk aptly put it in his
scathing, yet misdirected criticism of German revolutionary communism, the
idea of ‘another state, once again a state’15 seems to have been the horizon
limiting the reconstruction of polities at the end of wars and in the wake of
major social reshuffling. Now, this reconstruction was both wanting in scope
and obscure in its ideology and structure – from the wilful and informed
limited prosecution of fascist executioners and collaborationists16 in both the
West17 and the East18 to the ambiguous preservation of ideological tropes
such as anticommunism in the West19 and nationalism clothed as patriotism
in the East.20 Beyond these trends affecting the ‘general’ ideology of the
polities lie also the minute history of constitutional reforms, transitional jus-
tice processes, as well as the daily life of academic production and legal
training which by and large continued to function on the continent as much
as in common law jurisdictions as if nothing had happened. And indeed, from
a legal standpoint, informed by the formalist paradigms, nothing had hap-
pened with the substance and practice of the law. ‘Law continued while six
million died’,21 and indeed law through its agents continued to entertain the
illusion of a unitary body of rules able to structure the life of the polities and
knit communities under its rule, unexposed to historical upheaval.
This trend was irrespective and at times contrary to the ideological pled-
ges of the regimes in place, and certainly irrespective of the contingent
ideological content of the particular norms at either constitutional or infra-
constitutional level. Law was there to stay, even in the midst of purportedly
revolutionary transformations, of political reforms and in its explicit or
implicit disapplication.22 Yet, the resilience and survival of the legal form is
not a matter of securing formally or substantially freedoms or rights in an
attempt to articulate and limit the foundational violence of the law. Rather,
the opposite seems to be true. Through its very operation, the legal form
secures the survival of the exercise of unlimited sovereign power. Let us rest
on this point further: since the end of the First World War, an unprece-
dented growth of expedient measures situated at the limits of the legal
system, yet within its boundaries, can be attested against the background of
(and against the) mechanisms meant to supplant and limit the arbitrary
exercise of power.23 This took the form of mechanisms such as the institu-
tion of martial law, of emergency measures of a military, security and
financial nature, of explicit suspensions of fundamental rights,24 as well as
diffuse powers that escape the scrutiny of courts. Sometimes these provisions
found a place even within the very texture of codified legislation, such as in
the case of criminal legislation, continuing to act at the level of principles
informing the legal grammar of polities.25 Last, but not least, it nested
within the very formulation of the mechanisms pledging protection of
human rights but at the same time the primacy of the protection of the legal
order and state sovereignty.26 However, this is not a mere case of a conflict
of values that can make the object a balancing of rights but a fundamental
limit of the normativity in grounding itself.
At this stage the peculiar historical context in which the affirmation of the
primacy of the legal form occurred as well as the subsequent paradoxes it
entails should be emphasised. If the most rigorous theory articulating the law
as a normative category pertaining to the realm of ought is indeed Kelsen’s
Pure Theory of Law,27 one of its often disregarded features in relation to its
intellectual and material origins is its inscription within the same historical
trajectory that has produced the growth of executive power and the series of
suspension of the law. Let us note not only that the pure theory is not only
implicitly connected to the debates related to the application of the infamous
article 48 in the Weimar constitution28 but written within a historical
sequence that starts with the fall of the Austro-Hungarian Empire and the
reconstruction of state sovereignty in both Western and Central European
polities. The Kelsenian affirmation of law as a system of norms, and of the
pure theory as a way of describing their relation from a standpoint that is
value-free and ‘clean’ from moral, sociological or historical taint,29 appears
thus as a theoretical attempt at preserving the status of legality outside the
interplay of historical forces and political struggles. The peculiar explanation
of the interplay between validity and efficacy of the Grundnorm30 within the
context of revolution is indicative of not only the limits of such a project but
also a specific regime of historicity that marks legal thought. To put it simply,
in a case of a revolution – and Central Europe had witnessed a few in the
wake of the Great War – the Grundnorm has to entertain at least a certain
relation to factual reality.31 As Kelsen writes,
the sovereign body through the operation of the law: ‘The exception reveals
most clearly the essence of state’s authority. The decision parts here from the
legal norm and (…) authority proves that to produce law it need not be based
on law’.38
As such, the apparent liminal character of the exception and of excep-
tional measures within the constitutional body of rules39 is brought to the
fore as the authentic site of sovereign power – that is, indissociably con-
nected to the law and state.40 Let us recall here the medial place of the state
within Schmitt’s initial writings – as the institution able to connect the ideal
realm of normativity to the moving social reality. Accordingly, the state is ‘a
formation within the legal sphere whose meaning nests exclusively in the
task of realizing the law’.41 In so far as the sovereign is the one who decides
over the exception, the sovereign is also the one who decides on the nor-
mality, insofar as ‘for a legal order to make sense, a normal situation must
exist and he is sovereign who decides whether this normal situation actually
exists’.42 The exception is thus the operation that is able to sustain the
normal ordering of society, as ‘the state suspends the law in the exception on
the basis of its right to self-preservation’.43
There should be no uncertainty with regard to the common intellectual
imaginary shared by both Schmitt and Kelsen, which goes beyond their per-
sonal socialisation within the German-language world of legal theory. Refer-
ences to Kelsen are not only a constant presence within the writings of the
Crownjurist but the neo-Kantian sources supporting an understanding of the
law as a normative category – that is, as a matter of form – are the back-
ground against which both the idea of the state as mediation44 and later on
the state of exception as the point of reference of sovereignty are built. As
Schmitt writes, echoing Kelsen’s unresolved nexus between validity and effi-
cacy: ‘there exists no norm that is applicable to chaos’.45
According to Schmitt, the legal form is the background and the map that
enables one to grasp the remnants of authentic sovereignty under the histor-
ical veils raised by the liberal misadventure. One should note at this point not
only the political and theological implications of Schmitt’s writings in the
early years of the interwar period but also their relation to the legal historical
thread followed within the pages of the Dictatorship. Indeed, it is useful to
emphasise how much the conceptualisation of the ‘exception’ owes not only
to a criticism of the liberal categories of legality but also to a historical thesis
38 Ibid.
39 Ibid., 5.
40 Ibid.
41 Schmitt, La valeur de l’Etat, 100.
42 Schmitt, Political Theology, 13.
43 Ibid., 12.
44 Schmitt, La valeur de l’Etat, 119.
45 Schmitt, Political Theology, 13.
‘Through a glass, darkly’ 41
not the place where legal relationships are produced, but the place where the
state is simply imagined as a legal superstructure.63 Accordingly, ‘[t]he state
apparatus actually realizes itself as an impersonal “general will”, as “the
authority of law” etc., to the extent that society appears as a market’.64 What
is indeed able to produce a significant change within the operation of the law,
is a radical transformation at the level of economy, and of the concepts sup-
porting the view of a society as a market and the individual as a legal person.
It is only such a reshuffling that would be able to finally depose the law and
bring about its withering away, thus fulfilling the dictatorship of the proletar-
iat: ‘Liberation (…) would only occur when the general withering away of the
legal superstructure begins’.65
What is important in these theoretical positions developed on the left side
of the political spectrum and within the path opened by the Russian Revo-
lution, is the insistence on law’s ability to taint the content of a revolu-
tionary transformation – that is, the resilience of the legal form as well as its
necessary relation to other spheres, such as economy and politics. In other
words, a mere ‘takeover’ of the sites of power is never enough in changing
the law, nor is it the final point of its deposition. More importantly, the legal
form emerges as being supported by a wider array of relations – moulded by
history and economy – that keep it articulated and alive within the structure
of the polities, regardless of, if not in opposition to, the figure or the body of
the sovereign.66
These theoretical interventions that provided the substance of the jur-
isprudential debates of the interwar period did not disappear either with
Hitler’s rise to power in Germany or with Stalin’s rise to the helm of the
Communist Party of the Soviet Union. To begin with, Schmitt’s state of
exception grounding the sovereign decision was redeemed by historical
experience, both in the eventual application of Article 48 and in the effective
suspension of the Weimar Constitution. His contribution to the legal drama
of the Reichstag fire as well as his theoretical insights from Political Theology
found echo in his damning The Führer Protects the Law.67 Yet this final con-
tribution to the theory of exception and authoritarianism was perhaps part of
a wider trend of exceptional measures and emergencies engulfing the world at
the time.68 For its part, Benjamin’s search for a revolutionary violence able to
depose the law would remain only a sublime objective – neither the reality of
63 Ibid., 73.
64 Ibid., 95.
65 Ibid., 125.
66 Cercel, Towards a Jurisprudence of State Communism, 96.
67 Carl Schmitt, ‘Der Führer schützt das Recht,’ Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung 39, 1
August 1934, 945–950.
68 For the reception of Carl Schmitt’s work in wartime Romania, see Marius Ciş-
migiu, Regimul constituţional român: constituţia de criză şi ordinea politică
(Bucharest: Curentul, 1943).
44 Cosmin Cercel
Soviet Russia nor the revolution and Civil War in Spain would be able to
break the deadlock between law, revolution and violence. On the contrary, the
fascist onslaught with its long thread of security measures, as well as the
Stalinist betrayal, indefinitely postponed both divine justice and the withering
away of law and state. Pashukanis’ death in the purges, as well as the purge of
his work from the theoretical legal canon,69 left no room for a different rela-
tion between law and sovereign power than the one already present in the
structure of imperial states. Last but not least, Kelsen’s Pure Theory might
not have had a great career in the final interwar years, yet it thoroughly
influenced the political theoretical stand of some of the postwar debates,
before becoming the default theoretical position for constitutional lawyers on
the continent. While indeed the conundrum between validity and efficacy
might not have been answered from the standpoint of a pure theory, Kelsen’s
embrace of a liberal democratic stand70 and his advocacy for a connection
between legal form and democracy continues to influence the understanding
of law and politics to this day, while his formalism found quarters in the work
of practical lawyers from both sides of the Iron Curtain.
69 Piers Beirne and Robert Sharlet, ‘Editors’ introduction’, in Beirne and Sharlet
(eds), Pashukanis 1.
70 See, for instance, Hans Kelsen, ‘Foundations of Democracy’, (1955) 66 Ethics 1.
71 Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Daniel Heller-
Roazen transl. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998 [1995]).
72 Jacques Derrida, Marges de la philosophie (Paris: Minuit, 1972), 254.
73 Ibid.
74 Jacques Derrida, Force de loi (Paris: Galilée, 1994).
‘Through a glass, darkly’ 45
The ‘sovereign’ structure of the law, its peculiar and original ‘force’, has
the form of a state of exception in which fact and law are indistinguish-
able (…). Life, which is thus obliged, can in the last instance be impli-
cated in the sphere of the law only through the presupposition of its
inclusive exclusion, only in an exceptio.80
By exploring the mysterious figure of the homo sacer, what the Agambenian
project aims at is to identify the secret quilting point between the juridico-poli-
tical institutional model of analysing sovereign power and the biopolitical one,
from which the normativity of the law has been evacuated. The homo sacer, an
ancient institution of Roman law defining those found guilty of crimes and
whose life could have been lawfully taken away, without being sacrificial, exposes
a long series of paradoxes inherent in the structure of the Roman law.81 It unveils
the nexus between crime, punishment and sovereign power as well as the obscure
connection between legal thought and the sphere of religion.82 The sacrality of
the homo sacer marks of a zone of indistinction between sacred and profane,
between politics, law and religion representing an originary political structure
through which sovereign power – in its dual religious and profane guises –
invests the individual body of the subjects. As Agamben writes, ‘[l]ife that cannot
be sacrificed and yet may be killed is sacred life’.83
This paradox is indeed structural, and it reveals law’s core feature – that
of being a system of signification – a langue.84 In its application, the law is
75 Ibid., 84–98.
76 Ibid., 95.
77 Agamben, Homo Sacer, 10.
78 Ibid., 11.
79 Ibid., 19.
80 Ibid., 22.
81 Ibid., 47.
82 Ibid., 47–51.
83 Ibid., 52.
84 Ibid., 22.
46 Cosmin Cercel
85 Ibid., 20.
86 Ibid.
87 Ibid., 68.
88 Ibid., 72–73.
89 Ibid.
90 Ibid., 75–79.
‘Through a glass, darkly’ 47
91 Ibid., 73–78.
92 Ibid., 68.
93 Giorgio Agamben, State of Exception, Kevin Attell transl. (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2005 [2003]).
94 Ibid., 4.
95 Ibid.
96 Ibid., 32–39; 52–64.
97 Ibid., 33–34.
98 Ibid., 63.
99 Ibid., 3–4.
100 Ibid., 4.
48 Cosmin Cercel
shipwrecked’,126 and the theory of the state and law was the blind spot of the
Marxist analysis, there is yet the very starting point in Agamben’s project
which has a historical grounding. In other words, it is not by chance that we
witness a proliferation of exception and exceptional measures in the wake of
the October revolution and the end of the Great War. This can and should
probably be read within the context of another Agambenian core concept –
that of stasis and civil war127 – but it does not necessarily warrant such a
conflation between revolution and exception as the paradigm developed by
the Italian philosopher would.
While indeed the exception unveils a structural tension within – of leg-
ality, that is – and it was historically theorised, it also operates as a par-
ticular mechanism within the sphere of politics by doing away with
constitutional protections. The sovereign power, unfettered in the excep-
tion, does more often than not seem tainted by a specific ideological
colour and does have a specific historical and memorial weight. While
indeed the exception unveils a limit of the law – and is structurally nested
within the operation of modern legality – it is hardly ahistorical. By
taking for granted the very premise of the possibility of articulation of law
as normativity – a necessary step needed for the functioning of the
exception – the Agambenian paradigm projects law’s inability to ground
itself at the level of human history. Such a step, on the path opened by
Schmitt, rightly points to the law’s limits, but it does so only by keeping
alive the necessarily formal dimension of law as a pure potency. Accord-
ingly, it displaces the Schmittian criticism of the neo-Kantian presupposi-
tions that gave Kelsen’s theory its standing, but it expands them to the
level of all Western legal history. To be sure, this is a necessary step – even
from within a post-Kantian position – but it needs to be supplanted by a
deeper historical analysis that goes beyond the construction of a paradigm.
Accordingly, the state of exception in Agamben’s rendition has the func-
tion of recalling, if not restating the obvious. As Georg Lukács noted in
his criticism of Schmitt, any legal problem ‘depends whether the compe-
tent legal authority decided it thus or otherwise; but the character, com-
position, etc., of that authority are pre-determined by politico-social and
ultimately economic factors’.128 Such a critique is not to be dismissed as a
mere restatement of crude econocentrism, but ultimately raises the ques-
tion of the outside-of-the-law that finds a place and is rendered visible
within the structure of the exception.
Read through such lenses, the state of exception is perhaps the esoteric veil that
covers the status of legality within modernity. As such, it is not only able to
capture the specific tension between validity and efficacy of the legal norm but
also opens the path for a whole series of intellectual attempts at grounding the
law within the unfolding of a time in which ‘all that is solid melts into air’.133
Through the frontispiece of the exception, as painted by Agamben in his gen-
ealogy of the concept, we are able to grasp as if through a glass, darkly, the
operation of the exception as well as its intellectual archè.
However, as is the case with any frontispiece, it is followed by a work that is
yet to be written. This is a work that would take the history of law’s self-erasure
seriously on several levels. First, at a jurisprudential level, by placing at its core
the formal status of legality, that of a structure that is always at wrest with itself
and which, as any symbolic structure, is haunted by a foundational erasure and
thus is never complete. From this point of view, Jacques Lacan’s concept of the
Real in its relation to the Symbolic offers an edifying insight into this operation:
in its initial construction, the Symbolic, as an order of signification that produces
meaning and reality, is carved out through a constant negation of the primeval
matter of the psyche which is the Real.134 This process is not dissimilar to the
ways in which law is historically separating itself from politics, sovereign power
and religion. Yet, in Seminar XI, Lacan veers from a description of the Real as a
primeval traumatic encounter that is not mediated by the Symbolic towards a
notion of the Real as by-product of the very institution of the Symbolic order.135
The analogy with the state of exception is striking: from within the stand-
point of the law, the exception stands for the remainder of the unarticulated
Real, of an outside-of-the-law that cannot be otherwise captured than by
law’s self-erasure. Positing the exception at the core of law’s formal under-
standing is crucial in order to grasp is never-completed, always ungrounded
status. First, then, this jurisprudential stand necessarily calls for an under-
standing of the law as a historical category, insofar as what stays outside of
the articulation of the law is the remainder of historical struggles in which
social forces collide in giving shape of the sphere of legality.
Second, as a matter of historiography, the state of exception forces us to
inscribe legality in a broader timeframe and to refine our uses of concepts that
historians and political theorists borrow from the arsenal of jurisprudence.
Questions such as legitimacy and legality thus become particularly complex and
demand a due analysis with a view to clarify both the agency and the limits of
historical subjects. For instance, if one is to take the paradigm of the exception
seriously, important questions related to the lawless character of authoritarian
regimes do indeed need to be evaluated, just as the very symbolic line between
liberal legality and its authoritarian other needs to be revisited.
But this refinement does not regard only our legal past. On the contrary, such
important questions related to law’s structural inability of grounding itself as a
system of signification does call for a need to revisit our present as a part of a
historical becoming. In simple words, the present effective erasure of legality –
from the proliferation of emergency measures to the minute rewriting of legality
and constitutional practices – should be understood as what it is: a moment in a
historical unfolding of the exception. It is not an attack on liberal legality as
such, but rather an unearthing of its inner limits and of the authoritarian
potential nested at its core. Documenting the history of this process through
which the law positively undermines itself is the work that stays beyond the eso-
teric veil of the exception.
134 Bruce Fink, The Lacanian Subject: Between Language and Jouissance (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), 24.
135 Charles Shepherdson, Lacan and the Limits of Language (New York: Fordham
University Press, 2008), 27.
Chapter 3
Introduction
Few philosophical books are remembered by the date of their first pub-
lication; even fewer jurisprudential works earn this honour. Giorgio
Agamben’s Homo Sacer – the founding volume of the project published
in 19951 – triumphed in both categories. It belongs to a highly exclusive
group of texts which do not provide a philosophical reformulation of
legal studies, but rather take both philosophy and jurisprudence to a new
common field in which the legal and the philosophical become indis-
tinguishable. The revolution inaugurated by Agamben’s work – although
in many respects aptly disguised by references to Carl Schmitt, Walter
Benjamin and Hannah Arendt – develops in a philosophical rather than
jurisprudential pace. Its real impact will have become assessable after
decades, not years. In this sense Agamben’s stunning popularity among
legal scholars – sometimes, admittedly, leading to banal application of his
concepts – is not yet representative for the historical meaning of his
thinking. The Agambenian breakthrough requires further development:
the philosopher himself recognises it in his attempts to complete the still
open-ended Homo sacer project.2 Sometimes, however, the conceptual
blow is too powerful to be exhaustively contained in one series and
3 Ibid., 17–18.
4 In this respect Agamben finds Kant to be ‘on a false track’. Agamben, State of
Exception (Homo sacer II, 1), Kevin Attell transl. (Chicago and London: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 2005), 39.
5 Saul A. Kripke, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary
Exposition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982).
The other side of the exception 57
The situation created in the exception has the peculiar characteristic that
it cannot be defined either as a situation of fact or as a situation of right,
but instead institutes a paradoxical threshold of indistinction between the
two [emphasis added]. It is not a fact, since it is only created through the
suspension of the rule. […] In this sense, the sovereign exception is the
fundamental localization (Ortung), which does not limit itself to distin-
guishing what is inside from what is outside but instead traces a threshold
(the state of exception) between the two, on the basis of which outside and
inside, the normal situation and chaos, enter into those complex topological
relations that make the validity of the juridical order possible [emphasis
added].6
The tension between the rule and the fact finds its resolution in a typical
Agambenian manoeuvre: no primacy is given to either poles of the opposi-
tion, but a third, more powerful category is introduced to defuse them. It is
not produced, but it has always been already there. Not accidentally,
Agamben theorises it as a kind of space that ‘precedes’ the elements which
enter it. Its boundaries are comparable to the event horizon in astrophysics.
Whatever two elements overstep them (‘crosses the threshold of indistinc-
tion’ in Agambenian parlance), they lose the very possibility of being dif-
ferentiated. Musing on what they truly are in this area is senseless –
ontology coincides here with epistemology and whatever cannot be attested,
does not exist. In the zone of indistinction the elements conflate. To add one
last twist to the paradox, the conflation functions like a contagious zone
that expands to suspend our knowledge: no question on the primacy
between the elements and the conflation itself might be asked because the
conflation consumes it as well.
I suggest that we understand Agamben’s conflation as a process in
which the difference between two terms or concepts is suspended. The
difference does not disappear; it rather continues itself as a trace that
becomes overwritten with its own insignificance. William Watkin brilliantly
identified the area emerging after conflation, listing synonyms that Agam-
ben uses for it:
6 Ibid., 18–19.
58 Przemysław Tacik
uses various terms to name the zone and various other terms to designate its
specific quality, but the structure is always the same.7
16 Ibid., 41.
17 Ibid., 83.
18 Ibid., 96.
19 Ibid., 105.
20 Agamben, State of Exception, 83.
21 Agamben, Il Regno e la Gloria, 10.
22 Giorgio Agamben, Il mistero del male. Benedetto XVI e la fine dei tempi (Roma e
Bari: Laterza, 2013), 32.
23 Giorgio Agamben, L’avventura (Roma: Nottetempo, 2015), 59–60.
24 Giorgio Agamben, Pilato e Gesù (Roma: Nottetempo, 2013), 63.
25 Giorgio Agamben, Autoritratto nello studio (Milano: Nottetempo, 2017), 166.
26 Giorgio Agamben, Creazione e anarchia. L’opera nell’età della religione capita-
lista (Vicenza: Neri Pozza, 2017), 132.
27 Agamben, The Sacrament, 46.
28 Agamben, Opus Dei, 96–97.
29 Agamben, L’uso dei corpi, 9.
60 Przemysław Tacik
Third, in one of his latest books, Karman, Agamben invents another syno-
nym for conflation. Investigating once again the murky zone between rules and
practice,30 this time embodied in the tension between act and imputability,
Agamben suggests a neutral term for what lies between them: ‘a pure gesture’
(un puro gesto).31 It eludes the opposition between means and ends, becoming
‘unjudgeable’ (ingiudicabile).32 This saving category is an obvious counterpart
to the earlier theorisation of conflation between trial and punishment,33 so well
fathomed by Kafka. This juxtaposition demonstrates that conflation is a uni-
versal and ambivalent category. It might be both recognised in its many incar-
nations as a dangerous process (for instance in blurring the line between law
and violence) and a saving notion. Symptomatically, Agamben seeks the anti-
dote to the evil in the very same conflation, which responds for it.34 In this line
of thinking, he is clearly indebted to the Heideggerian legacy. The chain of
concepts which embody Agambenian liberation: ‘the suspension of the sus-
pension’,35 the Sabbath, the messianic era, letting-be (manifestly borrowed from
Heidegger) is conflation transformed into a redeeming device. Paradoxically,
conflation engulfs itself in its both variations, bringing ultimate demise and
salvation into the zone of indistinction.
If so, the concept of conflation – contrary to its limited application in the
notion of exception – would be strictly modern. It either describes modern
phenomena or, when applied to pre-modern mechanisms, reconstructs them
within the modern field of knowledge. With this recognition the conspicuous
absence of international law in Agamben’s work might be recognised as part
and parcel of his misrepresentation of modernity by the misleading assump-
tion of historical continuity.
30 This tension, viewed through the lens of the opposition (and conflation) between
form and life, was extensively explored in: Giorgio Agamben, The Highest Pov-
erty. Monastic Rules and Form-of-Life, Adam Kotsko transl. (Stanford CA:
Stanford University Press, 2013), xi-xiii, 26, 62, 84–86, 115, 143–145.
31 Giorgio Agamben, Karman. Breve trattato sull’azione, la colpa e il gesto (Torino:
Bollati Boringhieri, 2017), 136.
32 Ibid.
33 Giorgio Agamben, Il fuoco e il raconto (Roma: Nottetempo, 2014), 18.
34 In this respect, Agamben’s concept of inoperativeness (inoperosità) is a ‘positive’
incarnation of conflation. Building politics and poetics on it (see Agamben,
Creazione e anarchia, 47) are equivalent to Lévinas’ gesture of ethical reversal of
Heideggerianism.
35 Giorgio Agamben, The Open: Man and Animal, Kevin Attell transl. (Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press, 2004), 92.
The other side of the exception 61
36 Whether this was successful is another matter. See William D. Blatner, Hei-
degger’s Temporal Idealism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) and
Marlène Zarader, The Unthought Debt. Heidegger and the Hebraic Heritage,
Bettina Bergo transl. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2006).
37 Agamben, State of Exception, 11–22.
38 Cf. Carl Schmitt, Political Theology. Four Chapters on the Concept of Sover-
eignty, George Schwab transl. (Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press, 1985),
16–35.
39 Cf. Giorgio Agamben, Stasis. Civil War as a Political Paradigm, Nicholas Heron
transl. (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2015), vi, 1–2.
62 Przemysław Tacik
International law in its proper sense was born in early modern Europe. In
the Middle Ages the theologico-political structure of the continent was based
on the imagined Christian community which had two pivotal positions at the
top of it. God was imagined as the absolute ruler and keystone of the sym-
bolic order. Between God and the level of state rulers, there was a mezzanine
position, a ruler pro tempore of Europe: this position was an object of com-
petition between the pope and the emperor. Despite its many incoherences
and internal tensions, the Christian community of Europe was imaginable in
terms of totality.
The onset of modernity, however, led to structural displacement in this
order. First, state rulers gradually began to arrogate themselves the role of
absolute sovereigns, which is best epitomised in Jean Bodin’s canonical
theory of early modern sovereignty. In Bodin’s view, the sovereign does not
recognise any power over his position except for God’s; he decrees laws, but
is not subjugated to them.52 In other words, the level of state rulers becomes
the epicentre of politico-legal power and a critical knot between violence
and power.
Second, modern sovereign’s demand for power is localised: it is limited to
the territory of their states. The two traditional aspects of sovereignty (par-
enthetically, criticised by Schmitt in his introduction of the exception-based
definition of the sovereign53) – internal (absolute power over the social life of
the state) and external (independence from external sources of power) –
revolve around the idea of a determined territory. Repelling external claims to
power over the territory and affairs of a modern state founds sovereignty on
the negative power that allows this state to found its legal system on its own
unfounded decision. For the same reason total jurisdiction over state popula-
tion must be exclusive. This negative power guarantees independence of
sovereigns. Modern sovereignty is therefore based on the concept of recog-
nising other sovereigns’ rights and mutual co-existence. As Schmitt noted,
international law constructs the border not in order to exclude, but to recog-
nise the sovereign neighbour.54 This negative aspect of sovereignty is not just
a by-product of the creation of modern states. On the contrary, it is a key
factor in their emergence, indissolubly linked to the positive aspect.
Third, mutual recognition between sovereigns is based on a set of para-
doxes. Each arrogates to himself/herself the total and supreme power, but at
the same time recognises other sovereigns’ equal right, if only spatially sepa-
rated. Recognition emerges in the emptiness that is produced in the space
above the sovereigns. Whereas the Christian community assumed it to be part
52 Jean Bodin, Les six livres de la république (Paris: Fayard, 1985), 191–228,
297–299.
53 Schmitt, Political Theology, 16–35.
54 Carl Schmitt, Der Nomos der Erde im Völkerrecht des Ius Publicum Europaeum
(Köln: Greven, 1950), 22.
The other side of the exception 65
55 Jean Bethke Elshtain, Sovereignty. God, State, and Self (New York: Basic Books,
2008), 77–158.
56 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, The Philosophy of Right, S. W. Dyde transl.
(Kitchener: Batoche Books, 2001), 262, 264.
57 Ibid., 262–263.
58 Ian Brownlie, Principles of Public International Law (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2008), 729–747.
66 Przemysław Tacik
62 See Eric J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism since 1780: Programme, Myth,
Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
63 Cf. Agamben, Stasis, 36–40.
68 Przemysław Tacik
nominal locus of power and its executive centre. But this rift is in fact the
basic paradox of the modern state in which the population is the nominal
sovereign, whereas everyday government is performed in its name, but with
full effectiveness.64 Claude Lefort convincingly demonstrated that modern
democracy is built upon the emptiness of the locus of power, which is always
occupied temporarily.65 Extrapolating Agamben allows us to conclude that
the paradox of sovereignty – and its split into nominal reign and factual
government – is built upon the negativity which rules the inter-sovereign
space, making it a domain of permanent conflation between law and fact.
70 Cf. Bülent Diken and Carsten Bagge Laustsen, ‘The Camp’, (2006) 88 (4) Geo-
grafiska Annaler. Series B, Human Geography 446.
71 Raul Hilberg, The Destruction of European Jews (New York and London:
Holmes & Meier, 1985), vol. II, 609–659.
72 ‘For it is evident that those who regard the whole earth as their future territory
will stress the organ of domestic violence and will rule conquered territory with
70 Przemysław Tacik
police methods and personnel rather than with the army. Thus, the Nazis used
their SS troops, essentially a police force, for the rule and even the conquest of
foreign territories, with the ultimate aim of an amalgamation of the army and the
police under the leadership of the SS.’ Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitar-
ianism (San Diego: A Harvest Book, 1979), xxxvi.
73 See also Agamben, The Open, 76.
74 Primo Levi noted the effect it produced: ‘The confusion of languages is a funda-
mental component of the manner of living here: one is surrounded by a perpetual
Babel, in which everyone shouts orders and threats in languages never heard
before, and woe betide whoever fails to grasp the meaning.’ Primo Levi, If This Is
a Man…, Stuart Woolf transl. (New York: Orion Press, 1959), 36.
75 To a certain degree, the Third Reich succeeded to export this model to other
countries, thereby undermining the basic principles of international law. As
Hannah Arendt noted, ‘the increasing groups of stateless in the nontotalitarian
countries led to a form of lawlessness, organized by the police, which practically
resulted in a co-ordination of the free world with the legislation of the totalitarian
countries. That concentration camps were ultimately provided for the same
groups in all countries, even though there were considerable differences in the
treatment of their inmates, was all the more characteristic as the selection of the
groups was left exclusively to the initiative of the totalitarian regimes: if the Nazis
put a person in a concentration camp and if he made a successful escape, say, to
Holland, the Dutch would put him in an internment camp.’ Arendt, The Origins
of Totalitarianism, 288.
The other side of the exception 71
Conclusion
The conspicuous absence of international law in Agamben’s work seems
strictly correlated with his misrecognition of the specificity of modernity.
Consequently, the Agambenian approach to jurisprudence combines pro-
found perspicacity with surprising blind spots. It is only with understanding
the paradoxical nature of international law that two zones of exception might
be discerned in their mutual entanglement.
Contemporary human rights law conceals a mystified biopolitical device,
which might easily dispel the universalism of protection and give way to re-
uniting the two zones of exception in one territory of the camp. The nation
state, based on a paradoxical difference between the nation and the state,
which will never overlap, will always be tempted to spiral into the definitive
attempt to identify them. In the post-war era nation states not only still exist
but the world population has been trapped in their cooperative exertion of
power. They carry out universal police, but neatly distributed into national
instances. Parallel coexistence of two principles of international law – of
sovereign states and of populations – constitutes a permanent biopolitical
device. A device which, pushed to the extreme in the camps, leaves as a
remainder and a reminder humanity itself. If an ideal nation state governs
over the nation in the name of the nation, the phenomenon of Nazi camps
reveals its hidden zone of exception. In the camp the sovereign governs not
over a nation, but over a remainder of humanity; and not on behalf of the
76 As famously stated by the ECtHR in the Ireland v. the UK case (judgment from
18 January 1978, app. no. 5310/71), ‘Unlike international treaties of the classic
kind, the Convention comprises more than mere reciprocal engagements between
contracting States. It creates, over and above a network of mutual, bilateral
undertakings, objective obligations, which, in the words of the Preamble, benefit
from a ‘collective enforcement’ (§ 239).
72 Przemysław Tacik
nation, but on no one’s behalf. This is the zone of exception, in which the
suspension of international law conflates with the suspension of domestic
legal norms.
Agamben’s seduction with the Heideggerian paradigm in which danger and
salvation conflate profoundly mystifies this complex relation.77 The remedy
for the modern zone of indistinction cannot reside in its reinterpretation as
the messianic era, in which law is suspended: this is nothing but extrapolation
of the paradigmatically modern device imprinted in the construction of the
nation state. If any remedy can be sought, it must be located outside moder-
nity. Therefore, Agamben’s propensity to universalise and de-historicise only
perpetuates what it denounces. The messianic era of suspension is nothing
that awaits the entire history, but a disastrous temptation at the crossroads
between international and domestic law. What can await us, however, is the
true end of modernity: an event whose scope and sense must elude every
modern eye.
Minor law
Notes towards a revolutionary
jurisprudence
Tormod Otter Johansen
Introduction
A characteristic specific to contemporary Western society is its autonomous
sphere of legal rules and the order set up to deal with those rules, which
includes legislators, courts, and the police. However, this social sphere of law
is no longer just a part of society. Instead it now seems to encroach upon and
act as the hegemonic structure for all parts of society. Juridical argumenta-
tion, legislation, and rights discourse is the dominant mode of political
thinking and acting today, from economic processes to the family, from reli-
gion to solidarity.
This chapter interrogates two of the most radical attempts at thinking
about law beyond the horizon of this hegemony. The first attempt is
made by Evgeny Pashukanis, who argues that law as such will be extin-
guished in a future society. The second is that of Giorgio Agamben, who
argues that law will continue, but that it will take on a radically different
role, emptied of force and no longer married to sovereign power.
Informed by their arguments, I attempt to sketch out a third path: that
law could shift from its hegemonic position and become what could be
called minor law. This minor law would not be non-violent, nor would it
be without coercive force, but it would exist in a qualitatively different
position than law does today.
If law is moved into a minor position it will also be put in an excep-
tional position. The trajectory of modern society is one where law has
increasingly become the dominant form of social organisation. It has
embedded itself in social life as the normal structure conflict resolution
and governing. Agamben’s claim is that law and the exception to law, in
declarations of state of exception, camps, etc., have reached an apex where
the norm and the exception are indistinguishable.1 Whether or not one
agrees that law and its exception are no longer possible to distinguish, it is
significant that even deviations from legal normality are stated in legal
language. When torture, camps, drone strikes, invasions and other acts
with specious legal basis are legitimised today, it is done through legal
argument.2 Nothing, even the violent actions of the most powerful actors
in the world, escapes legal language.
The wager in this chapter is that beyond the hegemony of the legal, and
beyond the permanent state of exception that Agamben has argued we live in,
lies the possibility of a world where law and legal processes again become true
exceptions. True exceptions in the sense that legal rules and procedures
become actually rare and, even more importantly, that most social interaction
will be conducted without laws and legal rules being relevant. When laws,
courts and jurists are engaged it will when absolutely necessary, similar to
how the state of exception in its original form was a rare and truly excep-
tional phenomena.
I claim that there exists a third alternative between the ontological
overcoming of law in the Benjaminian-Agambenian notion of a coming
world where law is no longer in force, or married with violence, but only
studied; and the irrelevance of law in communism that Pashukanis sees as
the end goal of revolution. The third alternative is that law might not be
overcome or left by the wayside of history, but that it can take on a new
minor position next to other social forms and cease to be the major form
of organising social relations it is today. This third way is not the reformist
socialist approach of gaining state power to use the state and its legal
order to effect a more just and egalitarian order.3 It is presupposed here
that the major shift a communist revolution entails, if possible and actu-
ally realised, would be an overall reduction in coercion. This is at the core
of communist thought and the promise that the Marxist tradition con-
tinuously reaffirms.4
Pashukanis’s main claim is that law and legal relations will disappear and
be replaced by technical regulations to coordinate human action and moral
rules that will be voluntarily followed, instead of criminal and other forms
of law.
In Agamben’s philosophy of a coming community, a world beyond the
present is sketched where law will still continue to exist,5 but it will be
released from all power and force and therefore, with the Judaic law of
Halacha as a template, only studied. For Agamben, following Benjamin,
2 Note the infamous ‘Torture memos’ by John Yoo, prepared in absolute secret to
give legal legitimation to CIA torture.
3 Whether such a path is open at all is debatable, but that is not the path I inves-
tigate in the following.
4 Cf. Michael Head, Marxism, Revolution and Law: The Lively Debates of Early
Soviet Russia (Saarbrücken, Germany: VDM Verlag Dr. Müller, 2010), 19.
5 Giorgio Agamben, The Coming Community (Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minnesota Press, 1993).
Minor law 75
law will still exist, yet it will not be entwined with violence and coercion,
and it will likely be followed voluntarily. While any straightforward com-
parison and critique of these two thinkers necessarily does violence to
their work and legacies, the reason for this study is not to disprove the
validity or value in their respective philosophical positions. Rather, it is
focused on sketching out the possibility of a third way between the dis-
appearance of law and the continuation of law without force. This is possi-
ble due to the value of Pashukanis’s and Agamben’s contributions. Even if
law and the juridical, both in theory and in praxis, have been amply stu-
died and critiqued in the Marxist tradition, these studies have mostly
focused on inquiring into, and critiquing the role of, legal norms and
institutions in the present social order, and the role of law in creating and
maintaining capitalism.6
This study’s purpose is to connect Agamben with Pashukanis, partly
through the idiosyncratic but still openly Marxist thinker, Benjamin. Agam-
ben might not be a Marxist, but he is a thinker working and writing in rela-
tion to this tradition. Not least his important positioning early in Homo
Sacer, where he criticizes keeping the state as the ‘fundamental horizon’ when
the ‘weakness of anarchist and Marxian critiques of the State’ was to not
have investigated the State as its originating structure as such. Agamben is
clearly situated in an antagonistic position vis-à-vis the state, and therefore on
the side of the anarchist and Marxian tradition:
But one ends up identifying with an enemy whose structure one does not
understand, and the theory of the State (and in particular of the state of
exception, which is to say, of the dictatorship of the proletariat as the
transitional phase leading to the stateless society) is the reef on which the
revolutions of our century have been shipwrecked.7
There is a general lack of studies on law and the juridical in relation to the
future aspect and goal of Marxist thought: revolution and suspension of the
current capitalist order. Here the singular contribution from Pashukanis
stands out, even though it is embedded in his specific Soviet context, and was
6 And here I place Agamben in this tradition as well. (See especially Daniel
McLoughlin, ‘Introduction: Agamben and Radical Politics’, in McLoughlin (ed.),
Agamben and Radical Politics (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2016), 5,
and the edited volume it introduces as a whole. McLoughlin points out that the
shift in Agamben’s work towards economy and government partly makes up for
the critique he has received in not adequately regarding the issues that are the
main focus of the Marxist tradition, Daniel McLoughlin, ‘Rethinking Agamben:
Ontology and the Coming Politics’, (2014) 25(3) Law and Critique 323.
7 Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer : Sovereign Power and Bare Life (Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press, 1998), 11.
76 Tormod Otter Johansen
later swept away in the catastrophe of the Stalinist era.8 Pashukanis is unique
in that he specifically addresses the question of law and revolution in relation
to communism from a juridical perspective. This gives this theme more depth
than it receives in the peripheral comments from Marx and Engels, as well as
compared to the sweeping fragments in Lenin’s work. The greatest lack is still
that this approach and Pashukanis’s theory was not picked up and developed
afterwards. Unfortunately, the questions of law in revolution, and after revo-
lution, fell silent for decades.
While this central theme of law and revolution from a legal theoretical
perspective is central to jurisprudential thought in a Marxist tradition, it is
still in its infancy.9 The notion that this is appropriate, since we shouldn’t
worry about questions regarding the organisation of social life beyond the
boundary of revolution, is here rejected. It might be that any attempt to
contribute to a field we may call revolutionary jurisprudence, with the aim of
studying the role of law in and beyond revolution, also necessarily consists
of speculation. But speculation is different from programmatism that
attempts to prescribe future action. The possible futility and harmfulness of
theories of future actions should not scare us away from proper speculation.
Speculation is an act of thinking beyond the present by way of looking at
what is already here.
On the path of minor law, many, perhaps even most, laws will wither away
because they will be unnecessary and able to be replaced with other forms of
social coordination that do not involve violence and coercion. This is a
result of the overall reduction in coercion necessary in a world without wage
labour, markets and private property. Some laws might still exist, concerning
violence against persons or for the protection of children. These can possi-
bly, but not necessarily, be coupled with coercive force, with violence. This
would still entail a radical shift from the contemporary situation where legal
regulation is a hegemonic type of social organisation and continues to
expand to encompass attempts to solve all problems in human life. To turn
this trend around would mean that law would not disappear, but would be
subordinate and put in a minority position vis-à-vis voluntary and non-
coercive forms of social organisation.
8 See Head, Marxism, Revolution and Law: The Lively Debates of Early Soviet
Russia, chapter 8. The rising interest in Pashukanis’s thought, not least in inter-
national law, during the latter decades should be noted: see China Miéville,
Between Equal Rights: A Marxist Theory of International Law (Leiden: Brill,
2005).
9 Cosmin Cercel, Towards a Jurisprudence of State Communism: Law and the
Failure of Revolution (Abingdon: Routledge, 2018), 50.
Minor law 77
worker and employer, the exchange is that of work against salary. This is the true
content of the legal relation according to Pashukanis:
Law in its general definitions, law as a form, does not exist in the heads
and the theories of learned jurists. It has a parallel, real history which
unfolds not as a set of ideas, but as a specific set of relations which men
enter into not by conscious choice, but because the relations of produc-
tion compel them to do so. Man becomes a legal subject by virtue of the
same necessity which transforms the product of nature into a commodity
complete with the enigmatic property of value.17
17 Evgeny Pashukanis, The General Theory of Law and Marxism, 1980, available at
www.marxists.org/archive/pashukanis/1924/law/.
18 Ibid., chap. 3.
19 Head, Evgeny Pashukanis: A Critical Reappraisal, 179.
20 Pashukanis, The General Theory of Law and Marxism, 1980, chap. 3.
21 ‘Far from being a natural or eternal institution of human society, law was a
peculiar form that arose from definite commodity exchange relations that had
arisen historically at a certain stage of economic and social development and
would die away once that stage had passed.’ Head, Evgeny Pashukanis: A Critical
Reappraisal, 173.
80 Tormod Otter Johansen
While this formed the end goal of revolution, the intervening period of soci-
alism might still need law because it would retain exchange in the sphere of
distribution— the buying and selling of goods would still prevail. These are at
the same time bourgeois and capitalist aspects of the socialist transition state,
under the dictatorship of the proletariat. Were class relations to be finally
abolished, laws and legal relations would no longer be needed or, perhaps,
even possible because private exchange would no longer take place.
Pashukanis imagines the end of law as a necessary outcome of the end of
bourgeois class society. Law as a form of social organisation has reached its
peak in capitalist society, where it has acquired its purest form. The demise of
bourgeoisie society also means the “withering away of law in general, i.e. the
gradual disappearance of the juridic element in human relationships”.22 The
Pashukanian path is therefore a promise of the realisation of communism as
an end of all law. This leaves law no role, not even as a nonviolent, non-
coercive form of organisation. In its place, there will still exist “regulation”,
but Pashukanis sharply distinguishes these technical rules from law.
Concerning other forms of social organisation, he simply rejects them as
being legal at all. Military units are subordinated to the will of the comman-
der; the Jesuit order is comprised of members fulfiling the will of the leader.
These forms of hierarchical social organisation therefore have “nothing in
common with the legal form”. Similarly, fully realised communism would be
a state of things where no private interests needed to assert their claims
against others. Therefore, the legal form would no longer be of any use. The
social organisation would then not be legal in nature. Instead of the govern-
ment of persons there would be the administration of things, as Engels for-
mulated it.23 In Pashukanis, this even amounts to a destruction of ethics,
since moral obligation only makes sense in a class society where the right of
one implies the obligation of another.24
It is an important discussion whether Pashukanis’s concept of law, or rather
the legal form, is too narrow. His dismissal of public law and state power as
more or less irrelevant for law as such, especially given the transitional Soviet
state, are problematic. An integral part of his law-transcending theory is a con-
ceptualization of the use that the proletariat must make of the legal form in a
transitional socialist phase. Law together with other aspects of bourgeois society,
such as morality and the state, will play a role before communism can be rea-
lised.25 The question of whether his conception of law or the legal form as
restricted to only those relations that are founded in exchange – and equally,
whether every form of law can be derived from such a concept of private law –
can definitely be discussed and critiqued.26 Further, whether the distinction
between the “law” of bourgeois society and the “regulation” of socialist society
holds water is key to interpreting the value of his theory. But for the purposes of
this text, it is not necessary to develop these aspects further. Pashukanis’s work
stands as a singular contribution in Marxist theory and in legal theory in general
in that it tries to account jurisprudentially for the argument that law could be
extinguished. It might be argued that the possibility, or in Pashukanis’s case the
promise, of the extinction of law is not more than a postulate in the theory. That
might be too harsh since there is a somewhat developed argument for why that
can and must be the case, at least inside the framework of Marxist thought. But
even if it mainly functions as a postulate of the theory, this still amounts to quite
a step compared to most theories of law that cannot even consider the end of law
as a possibility.27 We will now turn to a similarly radical theory, but one which
surprisingly combines a retained role for law in a coming society at the same
time as this role is completely transformed on an ontological level.
25 Pashukanis, chap. 6.
26 ‘Pashukanis’ derivation of the legal form from the commodity form barred the
possibility of grappling with pre-capitalist and even post-capitalist varieties of law
and right.’ Igor Shoikhedbrod, ‘Estranged Bedfellows: Why Pashukanis Still
Charms Legal Formalists’, Legal Form, 15 June 2018, available at https://lega
lform.blog/2018/06/15/estranged-bedfellows-why-pashukanis-still-charms-legal-for
malists-igor-shoikhedbrod/.
27 In another study, I aim to pick up the threads of the notion that law could end
and develop them in a philosophical enquiry into what such an idea might actu-
ally mean. I would hesitate to mention a work in progress in print on the chance
it doesn’t materialise. And is it worth the reader’s attention to mention it? Inside
the discipline of law, the Scandinavian legal realism of the Uppsala School, cer-
tain radical neoliberals and anarchists on both the right and the left seem to be
where thought connected to this idea might be found. The other great well of
thought on the end of law is of course the theology of the Abrahamic religions.
82 Tormod Otter Johansen
But the feast is defined not only by what in it is not done, but primarily
by the fact that what is done—which in itself is not unlike what one does
every day—becomes undone, is rendered inoperative, liberated and sus-
pended from its ‘economy’, from the reasons and purposes that define it
during the weekdays (and not doing, in this sense, is only an extreme case
of this suspension). If one eats, it is not done for the sake of being fed; if
one gets dressed, it is not done for the sake of being covered up or taking
shelter from the cold; if one wakes up, it is not done for the sake of
working; if one walks, it is not done for the sake of going someplace; if
one speaks, it is not done for the sake of communicating information; if
one exchanges objects, it is not done for the sake of selling or buying.30
Inoperativity, then, stands for the possibility of doing what we always do, rather
than something else, but released from the economy in which it is usually caught.
Agamben describes this potential for making things inoperative as a destitution.
And furthermore, that this destitution could “furnish a paradigm for thinking
inoperativity as a model of politics”. The feast also contains other examples of
inoperative activities that Agamben mentions here and in other places: dance as
the inoperative use of the body, masks as the neutralisation of the face, and, not
least, the poem as the deactivation of the communicative function of language in
order to put it to a new use. “What the poem accomplishes for the potentiality of
speaking, politics and philosophy must accomplish for the power of acting.”
Here we are closing in on the future for law and the juridical. In contrast to
the constituent power that tries to establish a new order, “a violence that
28 It might be noted that this concise text has the potential to function as a prole-
gomena to the Homo Sacer project and Agamben’s thought as a whole.
29 Giorgio Agamben, ‘What Is a Destituent Power?’, transl. Stephanie Wakefield,
(2014) 32(1) Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 69.
30 Giorgio Agamben, Nudities (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2010), 69.
Minor law 83
establishes and constitutes the new law”, Agamben suggests that we should aim
to think of a destituent power whose definition is the task of the coming politics.
Here Agamben chooses to develop the question of what destitution could mean
by grappling with the seminal text for the question of the future of law, Benja-
min’s “Critique of violence”.31 Benjamin interrogates what a breaking of the
sovereign law and its violence could mean, which is a new historical epoch based
“on the destitution (Entsetzung) of law with all the powers on which it depends,
and as they depend on it, therefore ultimately on the destitution of state vio-
lence”.32 Benjamin finds an example of such a destitution of law in the prole-
tarian general strike. This strike does not use the violence available in the legal
categories of the present relation between labourers and capitalists, but rather
inaugurates a new reality where law is completely transformed. This destitution
therefore would mean something close to the extinction of law that Pashukanis
suggests. Benjamin calls for a divine violence to end the mythical violence of the
sovereign power of the state and the current order.
But Agamben is even more aligned in his next example. Paul, in Cor-
inthians 15:24, argues that the relation between the messiah and the law is not
only that he will make law, together with all authority and power, inoperative.
The messiah will also conserve the law through this inoperative action. This
Aufhebung then preserves the law as much as it makes it inoperative by
‘deactivating its action with regard to sin’.33
In the remainder of his text Agamben connects this to his notion of a form-of-
life, “a life that can never be separated from its form, a life in which it is never
possible to isolate something like a bare life”, in other words, a life that is not
caught in the violent grip of law bound up in sovereign power.34 What might this
mean specifically for law and the juridical?35
31 This is also the central text for Loick, A Critique of Sovereignty. See also Loick,
‘Law without Violence’.
32 Agamben, ‘What Is a Destituent Power?’, 70. Translated as ‘suspension’ or ‘abo-
lition’ in other versions, see Walter Benjamin, ‘Critique of Violence’, in Peter
Demetz (ed.), Reflections: Essays, Aphorisms, Autobiographical Writings (New
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1978), 300. Also Walter Benjamin, ‘Critique of
Violence’, in Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings (eds), Walter Benjamin:
Selected Writings. Vol. 1, 1913–1926 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
2004), 251.
33 Agamben, ‘What Is a Destituent Power?’, 71.
34 This also forms the explicit and central theme of the final volume in the Homo
Sacer series, Giorgio Agamben, The Use of Bodies (Stanford, CA: Stanford Uni-
versity Press, 2015).
35 Even though these questions are by necessity intertwined, and concern a common core.
A clear example of this is the quote Steven DeCaroli has rescued from an impromptu
discussion in Greece, where Agamben connects the need of the form-of-life with the
need to avoid the constitution of a new law: ‘We have to stop thinking of any revolu-
tionary action as directed toward the constitution of a new juridical order. Benjamin
calls this pure violence, which is a violence that will never constitute a new juridical
order. You depose without restoring another. If you are really, strongly and clearly able
84 Tormod Otter Johansen
One day humanity will play with law just as children play with disused
objects, not in order to restore them to their canonical use but to free
them from it for good. What is found after the law is not a more proper
and original use value that precedes the law but a new use that is born
only after it. And use, which has been contaminated by law, must also be
freed from its own value. This liberation is the task of study, or of play.
And this studious play is the passage that allows us to arrive at that jus-
tice that one of Benjamin’s posthumous fragments defines as a state of the
world in which the world appears as a good that absolutely cannot be
appropriated or made juridical.37
The law is thereby rescued from extinction; it is retained and even bears the pro-
mise of justice. Agamben points out in his reading of Benjamin that it is not this
activity that gives justice, rather it opens the possibility that we might arrive at
justice through the opening of a gate, as Benjamin writes. “The law—no longer
practiced but studied—is not justice, but only the gate that leads to it. What
opens a passage toward justice is not the erasure of law, but its deactivation and
inactivity—that is, another use of law.”38 Catherine Mills argues that the specific
choice of play is a way for Agamben to choose a middle path between endless
deferral, as in deconstruction, and eschatology, which purports the end of time as
such.39 The other alternative, that of letting law become extinct, as Pashukanis
suggests, would for Agamben threaten the rise of a new violent and sovereign law.
Agamben’s project has a much grander objective than the specific aspect
of the future of juridical structures and law I focus on. His main theme
to demonstrate the illegitimacy of the political order, in a way you are deposing it.’
Agamben, quoted in Steven DeCaroli, ‘What Is a Form-of-Life?: Giorgio Agamben
and the Practice of Poverty’, in McGloughlin (ed.), Agamben and Radical Politics, 226.
36 Agamben, State of Exception, 63.
37 Ibid., 64.
38 Ibid.
39 Catherine Mills, ‘Playing with Law: Agamben and Derrida on Postjuridical Jus-
tice’, (2008) 107(1) South Atlantic Quarterly 30.
Minor law 85
concerns the consequences of our ontological status and the way we com-
port ourselves to existence as such, towards Being in the wake of Heidegger.
But the fact that both legal concepts, institutions and the often enigmatic
“law” itself plays such a recurring role in Agamben’s texts also points
towards the question of the future or end of law as fundamental in his phi-
losophical and ontological work.
I interpret Agamben’s account as a possible description of or argument
for the possibility of a change of the juridical through and beyond a revo-
lution, even if it would be of a different kind than the Marxist and anarchist
revolutionary programs and attempts from which he distances himself.40
The question of whether Agamben himself is a representative or adheres to
the possibility of a communist revolution is here in a way suspended. In that
sense, this text does not try to interpret his often enigmatic stance on issues
of political change in general and communism in particular. Instead, it tries
to use his post-juridical thought for the purposes of revolutionary
jurisprudence.
Agamben is, among other things, inspired by Benjamin’s formulations on
the “study of law” as a future use of law, the same template as Halacha, the
Judaic law that is the object of tradition and study. This activity of studying is
not described as primarily a practical tool for the communicative need of the
community to choose and legitimate collective action. Instead, law will still
exist in a sense similar to the Jewish example, in that it is studied, but without
any coercive power of other humans. As we have seen, Agamben even
describes this activity as playing, where the law is left as a discarded object
from a previous era, suitable for use as a toy. He likens law to many other
artifacts and activities from history that have been “profaned” – in other
words, put to a new use beyond their previous roles in religion, warfare or
law. This implies an even more extreme future for law than it being just non-
violent. It no longer fulfills any practical or utilitarian function, but is instead
released from any function beyond its use as an object of study, or play.
We now play with religious symbols, with left-over things and with pro-
faned rituals. Even these rituals in themselves contain elements of play at
their core.41 But what would it even mean to play with law as a disused
object? Aren’t law and the juridical anathema to playfulness or play? Perhaps,
this is conceivable because of the very possibility that law could be freed from
the apparatus of teleological action and become the object of study and play.
Even though the ontological shift that the coming community, the new forms-
of-life, or the inoperative destituent power must act on every apparatus that
our present world contains and is structured around, law is the most extreme
case. The catastrophe is, in Jessica Whyte’s terms, most acute in law and
therefore it harbours the greatest potential for redemption.42 If we can play
with law, or study it without it being applied, we can destitute anything and
everything.
The problem with Agamben’s suggestion that law could subsist after its
connection with sovereign violence is severed is perhaps simply that it seems
too hopeful, too messianic. This is not a strong argument against it, since the
structure of a messianic argument implies that not only major change but also
the most radical change thinkable is possible.
In any case, to develop the theme of law beyond revolution that I have
presented with the help of Pashukanis and Agamben, I will now sketch
another configuration of law in a post-revolutionary situation.
What our ancestors thought about [the state] and how they shaped it is
something we must understand at least in outline in order to decide what
it is we ourselves want to do in the state and with the state. If we decide
that we want to have as little as possible to do with the state and refuse to
become engaged on its behalf, we must answer the questions of who is to
protect us against violence; who is to be responsible for the services
necessary for living and for the conveniences we take for granted; who
will maintain transportation and communication systems; who will
finance universities, libraries, museums, and much else.43
The case of criminal law, but even more so the role of social law in the pro-
tection of children and other vulnerable persons, can function as a specific
focal point, since it seems to be one of the most problematic aspects of
thinking law beyond sovereign power. The case against all law has to face the
case of a child being severely mistreated. Even though this one case cannot be
a general argument for the legitimacy of juridical structures, it is challenging
to not see the need for societal responsibility of some sort. If the care of a
child needs to be taken on by the community through coercive force, it
necessarily implies the protection of rights, fair procedure and, in the end,
institutional violence as a necessary means. Leaving the same matter to a
simply moral organ, with no qualified recourse to force, does not seem more
appetising to most modern senses. This is Lenin’s position on the protection
of people in a nutshell:
We are not utopians, and do not in the least deny the possibility and
inevitability of excesses on the part of individual persons, or the need to
stop such excesses. In the first place, however, no special machine, no
special apparatus of suppression, is needed for this: this will be done by
the armed people themselves, as simply and as readily as any crowd of
civilized people, even in modern society, interferes to put a stop to a
scuffle or to prevent a woman from being assaulted.44
43 Michael Stolleis, Public Law in Germany: A Historical Introduction from the 16th to
the 21st Century, Thomas Dunlap transl. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), 9.
44 Vladimir Lenin, The State and Revolution, 1999 [1918], Lenin Internet Archive,
available at https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1917/staterev/, chap. 1.
88 Tormod Otter Johansen
45 ‘Despite the wide range of organizational forms which may be found in small-
scale societies, the mechanisms for maintaining continuity and handling disputes
tend almost universally to be directly embedded in everyday life, unsupported by
a differentiated legal system.’ Simon Roberts, Order and Dispute: An Introduction
to Legal Anthropology, 2nd ed. (New Orleans, LA: Quid Pro Books, 2013), 15.
Minor law 89
49 I have learned anecdotally that the Kurdish Rojavan government police force
Asayish has the aim that all citizens should be provided with police training, with
the ultimate goal of dissolving the police force and replacing it with self-managed
security by the citizens themselves. Dissolving the police by making everyone a
potential police officer.
50 The interconnected aspect of schooling to the reproduction of the work force and
the indoctrination of work ethic and societal ideology are still problematic and
critical factors. Compare to Ivan Illich, Deschooling Society (London: Marion
Boyars, 2002).
Chapter 5
between what constitutes valid law and what does not.4 The state of excep-
tion, as the juridical response to a state of emergency, involves crossing the
threshold between normal and exceptional legal situations, lawfulness and
lawlessness, and so its examination has potential to illuminate this proble-
matic zone in the history of Nazi legality. This chapter, therefore, is con-
cerned with how contemporary theories of the state of exception may be
used to interrogate and understand the boundary between the two sides of
law in the Third Reich. In particular, it seeks to revisit Giorgio Agamben’s
work on the state of exception to establish what of value it can offer histor-
ians and theorists of law in Nazi Germany; how it can help us to read the
juridical aporia of the Third Reich.
The Third Reich is intimately connected to Agamben’s Homo sacer project
and specifically his study of the state of exception.5 Agamben relies heavily on
the Nazi use of the state of exception to support his claims of a ‘zone of
indistinction’ between fact and law. He locates this zone spatially in the ‘camp’,
and specifically the Nazi concentration camp, reading Auschwitz as the para-
digmatic example: ‘precisely the place in which the state of exception coincides
perfectly with the rule and the extreme situation becomes the very paradigm of
everyday life’,6 and ‘the hidden paradigm of the political space of modernity’.7
Agamben is also heavily influenced by Carl Schmitt’s writing on the state of
exception, where Schmitt notoriously became a supporter of and implicated in
the Nazi regime from its takeover of power in 1933.8
These connections invite a re-examination of the role of the exception in
the Nazi legal system because of the history-theory nexus at play in both
historical and jurisprudential narratives of Nazi law and Agamben’s own
theory. First, prevailing narratives of rupture and exceptionalism within
scholarship about Nazi law, including the portrayal of the Third Reich as a
fundamentally lawless state,9 and difficulties with properly framing Nazi law
4 See the Hart-Fuller debate: H. L. A. Hart, ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law
and Morals’ (1958) 71(4) Harvard Law Review 593; and Lon Fuller, ‘Positivism
and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart’, (1958) 71(4) Harvard Law
Review 630.
5 See especially the initial trilogy: Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and
Bare Life, Daniel Heller-Roazan transl. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998);
Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the Archive, Daniel Heller-Roazan transl.
(New York: Zone Books, 1999); and State of Exception, Kevin Attell transl. (Chicago,
IL: University of Chicago Press, 2005).
6 Agamben, Remnants of Auschwitz, 113.
7 Richard Ek, ‘Giorgio Agamben and the Spatialities of the Camp: An Introduc-
tion’, (2006) 88 Geografiska Annaler: Series B, Human Geography 363, 368.
8 See, for example, Carl Schmitt, ‘The Führer Protects the Law: On Adolf Hitler’s
Reichstag Address of 13 July 1934’ in Anson Rabinach, Sander Gilman (eds),
The Third Reich Sourcebook (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2013).
9 See David Fraser, Law after Auschwitz: Towards a Jurisprudence of the Holo-
caust (Durham, NC: Carolina Academic Press, 2005); Simon Lavis, ‘Nazi Law
as Non-law in Academic Discourse’ in Stephen Skinner (ed.), Ideology and
94 Simon Lavis
achieve two things. First, to understand better how and why Nazi law
achieved contemporary legitimacy inside and outside of the Third Reich
taking into account the necessary degree of consensus now accepted by his-
torians to have been essential for the survival of the regime, alongside the
undeniable terror and coercion.13 Second, to explore further how to theorise
the relationship between Fraenkel’s observed normative and prerogative states
in the Third Reich within a legal schema – to try to understand the nature of
Nazi authority as law. This is not, as has been said, to lend Nazism any value
that might be associated with the law, or at least the rule of law (which the
Nazis certainly rejected), but to try to understand how law operates in the
transformation of regimes such as Nazi Germany.
Protection of the People and State of 28 February 1933) utilised the Article
48 emergency provisions to suspend indefinitely key basic rights enshrined in
the constitution. It also enabled the Reich government to override the powers
of the German states (Länder). This decree is considered foundational to the
constitution of the Third Reich. Michael Bazyler notes that it ‘was never
abolished during Nazi rule. In effect, Hitler ruled for the next twelve years
under what amounted to martial law’.16 In Ian Kershaw’s view, this ‘hastily
constructed emergency decree amounted to the charter of the Third Reich’.17
Subsequently, however, on 24 March 1933, the passage of the Law to
Remove the Distress of the People and the State (the Enabling Act) amen-
ded the Weimar Constitution to allow laws to be passed by the executive
government without engaging the legislature, including laws that deviated
from the constitution itself (within certain limits), thereby dissolving the
distinction between administrative measures and ordinary law.18 This was
not passed using the Article 48 emergency powers or previously enacted
emergency legislation, but pursuant to the otherwise ordinary Article 76
constitutional amendment powers, requiring a two-thirds majority of the
Reichstag to assent to amend the constitution. It was, therefore, not strictly
a formal part of the state of exception, but was made possible by the factual
consequences of previous emergency legislation; for example, the impact of
the 4 and 28 February decrees on the composition of the Reichstag follow-
ing the March 1933 election.
The Enabling Act explicitly left the powers of the Reich president untouched
(Article 2), but this obstacle to total power was removed on the event of Hin-
denburg’s death on 2 August 1934, with the passage of the Law Concerning the
Head of State of the German Reich, dated 1 August 1934. This combined the
offices of chancellor and president and made Hitler the Führer and Reich
chancellor, including supreme commander of the armed forces. This law, of
formally questionable constitutional status, was affirmed by plebiscite on 19
August 1934.19 It was an exception within the exception to the extent that it fell
outside of the provisions of both Article 48 and the Enabling Act. It was
16 Michael Bazyler, Holocaust, Genocide, and the Law: A Quest for Justice in a
Post-Holocaust World (Oxford: OUP, 2016), 6. [Emphasis added]. Martial law
generally refers to the control of the state by military – as opposed to civilian –
forces in an emergency; the suspension of the law to ensure a return to the law. In
English law, ‘neither more nor less than the will of the general who commands
the army. In fact, martial law meant no law at all’; Duke of Wellington, 1851,
quoted in Leon Radzinowicz, A History of English Criminal Law and its Admin-
istration from 1750. Volume 4: Grappling for Control (London: Stevens & Sons,
1968), 143–144.
17 Kershaw, Hubris, 459.
18 Peter Caldwell, ‘National Socialism and Constitutional Law: Carl Schmitt, Otto
Koellreutter, and the Debate over the Nature of the Nazi State, 1933–1937’,
(1994) 16 Cardozo L. Rev. 399, 413.
19 Kershaw, Hubris, 524–525.
98 Simon Lavis
although the commissarial dictator acts outside the law, their actions
retain a connection to the legal order in two ways: the existing constitu-
tion is not abolished but temporarily suspended; and the terms of its
suspension are regulated by ‘norms of the realisation of law’.26
In this form a connection to the juridical order persists because ‘the law exists
in the “minimal form” of an actually existent constituent power, which has
not yet achieved a formal existence as a constituted legal system’.30
The Article 48 provisions in the Weimar Constitution naturally make no
mention of using the emergency measures to reshape the constitution itself,
referring instead to the restoration of public safety and order and the temporary
suspension of selected fundamental rights. However, whatever the intentions of
President Hindenburg in invoking Article 48 in February 1933 (and on prior
occasions), Hitler made it clear that the Nazis intended to use constitutional
methods to obtain power, not to restore the constitution, but rather to achieve
the aim of entirely re-constituting the state to conform to the Nazi vision.31
32 See Neumann Behemoth. Cf. Simon Lavis, ‘Nazi Law as Pure Instrument: Nat-
ural Law, (Extra-) Legal Terror, and the Neglect of Ideology’ in Michał Gałȩdek
and Anna Klimaszewska (eds), Modernisation, National Identity, and Legal
Instrumentalism: Studies in Comparative Legal History. Volume II: Public Law
(Leiden: Brill, 2019).
33 See David Fraser, ‘Criminal Law in Auschwitz: Positivism, Natural Law and the
Career of SS Lawyer Konrad Morgen’ in Stephen Skinner (ed.), Ideology and
Criminal Law: Fascist, National Socialist and Authoritarian Regimes (London:
Hart, 2019).
102 Simon Lavis
between the norm and the exception and finds both the conventional and
Schmittian interpretations ultimately unsatisfactory for illuminating this
boundary. He questions how the legal order can contain a lacuna unrelated to
law, but also how the suspension of the law can be contained within it. This
leads to his determination that ‘the state of exception is neither external nor
internal to the juridical order, and the problem of defining it concerns pre-
cisely a threshold, or a zone of indifference, where inside and outside do not
exclude one another but rather blur with each other’.34
For Agamben it is the very case of Nazi Germany that illuminates the zone
of indifference between the inside and outside of the law and renders Schmitt’s
analysis of the exception inadequate because it confounds the categories of
commissarial and sovereign dictatorship and the way Schmitt conceptualises
the relationship between the rule and the exception. Agamben asserts that in
1933, ‘Germany found itself technically in a situation of sovereign dictator-
ship, which should have led to the definitive abolition of the Weimar Con-
stitution and the establishment of a new constitution’,35 but this did not
occur. Instead, the Nazi regime ‘allowed the existing constitution … to subsist
and … placed beside the legal constitution a second structure, often not leg-
ally formalized, that could exist alongside the other because of the state of
exception’,36 thereby conflating the rule and exception: ‘this confusion
between the exception and the rule was precisely what the Third Reich had
concretely brought about, and the obstinacy with which Hitler pursued the
organization of his “dual state” without promulgating a new constitution is
proof of it’.37
According to Agamben, Schmitt’s theory does not account for this situa-
tion; ‘the machine can no longer function … the rule, which now coincides
with what it lives by, devours itself ’38. As McLoughlin states:
In light of this, Agamben collapses the distinction between law and exception
and eschews the relationship between the legal and extra-legal in the
when they tend to coincide in a single person, when the state of excep-
tion, in which they are bound and blurred together, becomes the rule,
then the juridico-political system transforms itself into a killing
machine.44
Agamben, famously, makes a leap from the operation of the exception in the
mass killings in the camp system of the Holocaust to a claim that ‘the voluntary
creation of a permanent state of emergency … has become one of the essential
practices of contemporary states, including so-called democratic ones’.45 His-
torians and theorists, however, have questioned both Agamben’s elucidation of
the Nazi exception and his conceptualisation of modern state practice in this
way. Often, for scholars of the Third Reich, Agamben’s use of Auschwitz as
paradigmatic of the camp system and the ‘nomos of the modern’ is the focus of
criticism. He is accused, among other things, of using poetic, abstract and non-
concrete writing, adopting an unhistorical or ahistorical methodology focused
on etymology rather than evidence, fetishising law and sovereignty, and simul-
taneously exceptionalising and universalising the Holocaust. There is only scope
here to recapitulate briefly the most relevant of these criticisms.
A key framing of many of his detractors include that Agamben’s version of
the Nazi state and Auschwitz is both un-historical and un-legal. For the
former, in the two senses that it is meta-historical – it does not work in his-
torical time – and it is not an accurate description of the relevant history. For
the latter, in the two senses that it does not correctly capture how law works,
and it is not an accurate description of the relevant law. For example, Heike
Schotten argues that ‘Agamben indulges in a kind of “Holocaust exception-
alism” wherein the Holocaust is both the center and the apex of politics,
political events, and political history (if not also of political “evil,” a term
that proliferates in Holocaust exceptionalist discourses)’,46 thereby simulta-
neously exceptionalising and universalising the Holocaust in unhistorical
ways. Alison Ross has highlighted the extent to which Agamben appears to
focus on defending his ideas rather than explaining events: ‘as political theory
Agamben’s work founders because his core fidelity is not to explain complex
events but to defend concepts with dubious explanatory value’.47 This indi-
cates, for Ross, ‘perhaps that his theory is too speculative, too ready to forgo
the task of analyzing actual practices and institutions in its “philosophical”
attachment to articulate the “ultimate” or the “fundamental”’.48 Esther
Marion goes further down the same path, to claim that ‘Agamben’s
This was because ‘Hitler had an instinctive aversion to any legal constraints
on his freedom of action and thus showed no desire for “normalizing” the
49 Esther Marion, ‘The Nazi Genocide and the Writing of the Holocaust Aporia:
Ethics and Remnants of Auschwitz’, (2006) 121(4) MLN 1009, 1009.
50 Mark Mazower, ‘Foucault, Agamben: Theory and the Nazis’, (2008) 35(1)
Boundary 2, 23, 31.
51 Ibid., 29.
52 Ibid., 31
53 Ichiro Takayoshi, ‘Can Philosophy Explain Nazi Violence? Giorgio Agamben
and the Problem of the “Historico-Philosophical” Method’, (2011) 13(1–2) Jour-
nal of Genocide Research 47, 50–59.
54 Ibid., 56.
106 Simon Lavis
the Third Reich, in the state of exception, did not strip the incurably ill of
legal protection and kill them lawfully. A group of individuals possessing
no legal authority broke the domestic law and murdered at least five
thousand chronically ill children and over one hundred thousand adult
psychiatry patients … . Hitler could have issued a law, prescribing that
the mentally and physically disabled be put to death because they posed a
dead burden on the state (Ballastexistenzen). Instead of turning the
incurably ill into ‘homo sacer’, however, Hitler chose to launch a clan-
destine operation. Drawing on the work of Lothar Gruchmann, Ian
Kershaw notes that ‘Even according to the legal theories of the time,
Hitler’s mandate could not be regarded as a formal Führer decree and
did not, therefore, possess the character of law’. In this regard, there is an
illuminating contrast between the ‘euthanasia action’ and the forced
sterilization: the latter was a ‘public procedure based on expert tribunals’
and the former was a covert, illegal operation.59
In the case of the euthanasia programme, then, ‘Hitler took great care to sidestep
the normal administrative and legislative branches of the Reich government’, to
commit a crime that ‘violated the domestic law of the Third Reich, however
55 Ibid.
56 Ibid.
57 Ibid., 56.
58 Ibid., 59. Cf. Fraser, ‘Criminal Law in Auschwitz’ in terms of the legal con-
tinuities between ‘legalised’ terror and the Holocaust.
59 Takayoshi, ‘Can philosophy explain Nazi violence?’, 52.
The exception of the norm in the Third Reich 107
60 Ibid., 53.
61 Ibid., 59.
62 Ibid.
63 See, for example, Benjamin A. Schupmann, Carl Schmitt’s State and Constitu-
tional Theory: A Critical Analysis (Oxford: OUP, 2017).
108 Simon Lavis
64 See fn 9 above.
65 Michael Stolleis, ‘Law and Lawyers Preparing the Holocaust’, (2007) 3 Annual
Review of Law and Social Science 213. See also Simon Lavis, ‘The Conundrum of
Nazi Law: An Historiographical Challenge to the Anglo-American Jur-
isprudential Representation of the Nazi Past’ (PhD, University of Nottingham,
2015 [unpublished]), available at http://eprints.nottingham.ac.uk/29061/1/Thesis_
Final_April%202015_Hardbound%20Final_4118996.pdf
66 See Lavis, ‘Nazi Law as Pure Instrument’.
67 Fraenkel, The Dual State. For a compelling recent attempt to revive Fraenkel’s
dual state theory for legal and political theory in relation to the Third Reich and
beyond, see Jens Meierhenrich, The Remnants of the Rechtsstaat: An Ethno-
graphy of Nazi Law (Oxford: OUP, 2018).
The exception of the norm in the Third Reich 109
both the role of elements of Nazi ideology in Nazi legality and its pre-
sence within the overall system of the prerogative state – a sphere of gov-
ernance ostensibly outside the legal realm – but a distinction is drawn
across the boundary separating the two states, between law and politics:
The law itself is nothing other than the expression of the communal order
in which the people live and which derives from the Führer. The Führer
law makes concrete the unwritten principles of the völkisch communal
life. It is therefore impossible to measure the laws of the Führer against a
74 Ibid., 57.
75 Stolleis, ‘Law and Lawyers Preparing the Holocaust’, 216.
76 Thomas Schaarschmidt, ‘Mobilizing German Society for War: The National
Socialist Gaue’ in Martina Steber and Bernhard Gotto (eds), Visions of Commu-
nity in Nazi Germany: Social Engineering and Private Lives (Oxford: OUP, 2014),
102.
77 Fraser, ‘Criminal Law in Auschwitz’, 35.
The exception of the norm in the Third Reich 111
higher concept of the law because every Führer law is a direct expression
of this völkisch concept of the law.78
While the Nazi’s own legal justifications for the effectively absolute power of
the Führer should be treated with care, incorporating the regime’s ideology
helps us to move past a key obstacle presented by the parallel existence of
both old and new systems: did the Nazis found a new constitutional order or
act entirely within an (increasingly expansive) suspension of the existing
order? An argument for the latter is that the Nazis did not formally institute a
new constitution or sets of legal codes in their ideological image. However, as
Peter Caldwell has asserted, ‘Nazism was not a movement of opportunism
without coherent principles—rather, its very principle was a kind of constitu-
tional opportunism’,79 and so ‘Nazi anticonstitutionalism … was not merely
an example of “pragmatism” or a “lack of principles,” but rather an essential
part of the National Socialist world view, manifested in real institutions as
well as theory’.80
The result of this is perhaps better seen as a functionally hybrid – rather
than a dual – system with an at times thin, but significant, connection to law
across all of its façets. Decrees, orders, commands and other measures
implemented by the regime, including those which infringed some of the
basic principles of the rule of law such as non-retroactivity of criminal law,
are not, it may be argued, ordinary legal rules. Nevertheless, those decrees,
orders, commands and other measures were from early on the basic, ordin-
ary norms of the Nazi legal system; i.e. they had full legal force, were pos-
ited correctly according to the (formally sparse) rules of the system, and
persisted as commonplace rather than exceptional elements of the system.
By recognising the conflation of law and non-law in the wake of the Nazi
institution of the state of exception, and acknowledging it as a deliberate,
ideological position capable of constituting a juridical order, Agamben’s
‘zone of indistinction’ may paradoxically be treated as an invitation to study
further the legal-historical constitution of the Nazi order, even while he
attempts to escape from the jurisprudential hegemony over life that this
implies, and in spite of the flaws in his representation of Nazi history.
78 Ernst Rudolf Huber, quoted in Jeremy Noakes, Geoffrey Pridham, Nazism 1919–
1945, Volume 2: State, Economy and Society 1933–1939 (Exeter: University of
Exeter Press, 1998), 282.
79 Caldwell, ‘National Socialism and Constitutional Law’, fn 6, 400–401.
80 Ibid., 400.
112 Simon Lavis
81 Ian Kershaw ‘“Working Towards the Führer”’ in Kershaw, Hubris (see page 529
for the origin of the phrase).
82 See, for example, Anthony McElligott and Tim Kirk (eds), Working towards the
Führer: Essays in Honour of Sir Ian Kershaw (Manchester: Manchester Uni-
versity Press, 2004). See also Dan Stone, Histories of the Holocaust (Oxford:
OUP, 2010), at page 55.
83 Kershaw, Hubris, 530.
84 The other being ‘the principle of the essential unity of Artgleichheit (unity of
species, type, or race) of the German Volk’, Caldwell, ‘National Socialism and
Constitutional Law’, 408.
85 Joseph W. Bendersky, A Concise History of Nazi Germany, 4th ed. (Maryland:
Rowman & Littlefield, 2014), 39.
The exception of the norm in the Third Reich 113
Histories of exception
Chapter 6
Introduction
In this chapter, I aim to examine the unity between ‘norm’ and ‘exception’ as
different forms of exercise of public power. I argue that both ‘norm’ and
‘exception’ are essential forms for the reproduction of bourgeois rule and that
the change from one form to the other is contingent upon the intensification
of socio-economic antagonisms (which manifest themselves in both class and
intra-class conflicts). This argument is pursued based on an examination of
the transition from the Weimar Republic to the Nazi state form, as reflected
in the work of Carl Schmitt.
Schmitt’s work will be assessed as a unified whole in its socio-economic
and political context. This methodological choice will allow us to raise
another theoretical point on the succession of different forms of state.
During the interwar period in Germany, two major changes took place:
one relating to the structure of the state and the other to the theory of the
state. The bourgeois state underwent a process of deep crisis and trans-
formation as it had to confront the antagonism of the first workers’ state
and the internal threat of the revolutionary working-class movement, as
well as the socio-economic contradictions of capitalism that reached their
peak at the economic crisis of 1929. These processes were bound to be
reflected in the theory of the state, and the work of Carl Schmitt is a key
example of this phenomenon.
The fundamental differences and nuances between the ‘normal’ and the
‘exceptional’ forms of exercise of public power is the point of departure of
this analysis. The Weimar Republic is not the same as the Nazi state. This
is precisely the point: they correspond to different levels of intensification
of social antagonisms. The German Revolution of 1919 was defeated, but
the German working-class struggle won vital concessions in the form of
civil, political and social rights, which were enshrined in the Weimar
Constitution. These concessions were embodied in the form of the welfare
state and were abolished in the form of the Nazi state. However, in order
to comprehend why these concessions were so easily abolished we have to
120 Dimitrios Kivotidis
figure out what is common to the two forms. What relations were repro-
duced by both the Weimar and the Nazi state? What social movements
were prevented by both?
It is argued that Schmitt’s theory of the state, reflecting a specific state
form, responded to specific socio-economic conditions of intensified class and
intra-class struggle that necessitated the change in the form of exercise of
public power. To this end, the dualisms found in Schmitt’s work (i.e. ‘com-
missarial’ and ‘sovereign dictatorship’, the ‘quantitative’ and the ‘qualitative
total state’) will be examined alongside an analysis of the socio-economic
reasons that necessitated the transition from the ‘quantitative-Weimar’ form
to the ‘qualitative-Nazi’ form. These reasons include, but are not limited to,
the need to reproduce the capitalist relations in the face of socio-economic
and political crisis, as well as the need to facilitate the conditions for intensi-
fied exploitation, which would restore the profitability of German capital by
crushing the labour movement and organisations.
In pursuing these arguments, the chapter is structured as follows: the ana-
lysis of Schmitt’s theoretical framework begins with the conceptual pair of
‘sovereign’ and ‘commissarial’ dictatorship. Part I examines the commonal-
ities and differences between the two. A discussion of the common origin of
both normal and exceptional forms in the legitimating concept of the ‘people’
is followed by an examination of the difference between the two, i.e. the ‘effi-
ciency’ in making the political decision against the ‘enemy’. In Part II, the
principle of ‘efficiency’ is examined in a move from the ‘political’ to the
‘social’ and the ‘economic’. This is achieved by examining another one of
Schmitt’s dualisms, between the ‘quantitative’ and the ‘qualitative total state’.
A careful look at Schmitt’s economic model reveals the reasons behind the
transition from one form to the other: the reproduction of capitalist power,
property and productive relations, as well as the facilitation of conditions for
intensified exploitation of labour. The similarities and differences between the
‘quantitative-Weimar’ and ‘qualitative-Nazi’ forms are examined with refer-
ence to the class and intra-class antagonisms and contradictions of interwar
Germany. Furthering this line of reasoning, Part III examines the prominent
role of plebiscitary legitimacy in the ‘qualitative-Nazi state’, as well as the
‘leadership principle’ as it appeared not only in the field of public law but also
in that of labour relations.
The legislator is nothing but right that is not yet constituted; the dictator
is nothing but constituted power. When a relationship emerges that
makes it possible to give the legislator the power of a dictator, to create a
dictatorial legislator and constitutional dictator, then the commissary
dictatorship has become a sovereign dictatorship. This relationship will
come about through an idea that is, in its substance, a consequence of
Rousseau’s contrat social, although he does not name as a separate
power: le pouvoir constituant.1
Two issues follow directly from the above. First, the relationship between
dictatorship (i.e. exceptional use of power) and the law is always there and
never questioned in both dictatorial forms. On the one hand, in ‘commis-
sarial dictatorship’ it is the exercise of power unrestrained from law that
safeguards the law itself. On the other, ‘sovereign dictatorship’ does not
appeal to an existing constitution, but to one that is still to come. This is
why the concept of ‘constituent power of the people’ is crucial here; because
the ‘people’ as the carrier of this power relates it to the constitution-to-come
as foundational to it.
This brings us to the second issue, i.e. the ideological function of the ‘people’.
Both forms of dictatorship are based on the idea of the ‘sovereign people’. It is
the ‘people’ that institutes the state with its constitution-making power on the
basis of its ‘political unity’, we read in Schmitt’s Constitutional Theory.2 And it
is in the interest of the ‘people’, i.e. it is in the ‘general interest’, that this con-
stitutional order is suspended for exceptional power to safeguard it. However,
the ‘people’, this classless and metaphysical subject, is a fiction. The concept of
the ‘people’ is an illusory concept, albeit one with very actual effects in a social
formation, precisely because it impedes the conceptualisation of society in its
contradictory movement by obscuring the conflicting social interests behind the
‘oneness’ of ‘popular sovereignty’. The ‘people’ as a whole cannot be sovereign
because society is divided; the ‘people’ stands in for a whole, which consists of
classes with conflicting interests, which cancel the possibility of a ‘general
interest’, expressed in a ‘general will’. ‘Sovereign’ and ‘commissarial’ dictator-
ship, normal and exceptional forms, are based on the idea of the ‘people’ (and
the accompanying concepts of general will and general interest) as a legitimat-
ing fiction of class rule.
Where does this leave us concerning the nature of the Nazi state? Was it a
‘permanent state of exception’? Was it a sovereign or a commissarial dicta-
torship? In order to answer this question we have to look at Schmitt’s cele-
bratory essay on the Nazi state, his 1933 State, Movement, People. There,
Schmitt refutes the argument that
He argues instead that there are two issues to be taken into account with
regard to the Enabling Act (or ‘law of empowerment’, i.e. the enabled
amendment of the Weimar Constitution that gave the German executive the
power to enact laws without the involvement of the Reichstag) of 24 March
1933. The first one consists of the fact that the elections of March 1933 ‘were
in fact a popular referendum, a plebiscite, by which the German people has
acknowledged Adolf Hitler, the leader of the National-Socialist Movement, as
the political leader of the German people’.4 According to Schmitt, the
‘people’ appears here to give ordinary elections the character of plebiscite.
The ‘pouvoir constituent’ and the ‘will of the people’ are invoked here by
Schmitt to found the Nazi state. And this invocation points towards the con-
cept of sovereign dictatorship with regard to the emergence of the Nazi state.
On the other hand, Schmitt emphasises the importance of the fact that this
transition should take place legally.5 The Enabling Act came into legal exis-
tence in conformity with Article 76 of the Weimar Constitution, which
required a two-thirds majority for laws amending the Constitution, but that
does not mean that one may still nowadays consider the Weimar Con-
stitution as the foundation of the present-day State structure, but only
that the law represents a bridge from the old to the new State, from the
old base to the new base.6
3 Carl Schmitt, State, Movement, People: The Triadic Structure of the Political
Unity (Washington, DC: Plutarch Press, 2001), 5.
4 Ibid.
5 Ibid., 6.
6 Ibid.
‘Norm’ and ‘exception’ 123
9 The important ideological effect of Hitler being seen as coming to power by the
most strictly constitutional means, notwithstanding the coercion against and
immediate arrests of members of the Communist Party and trade-Unionists
between the Reichstag Fire Decree and the voting of the Enabling Act, is reflec-
ted in statements such as the one by Kautsky, that ‘the Dictatorship has the mass
of the population behind it’: see Rajani Palme Dutt, Fascism and Social Revolu-
tion (London: Martin Lawrence, 1934), 148–149.
‘Norm’ and ‘exception’ 125
One could not wait for the empowerment of a system, which by its own
weakness and neutrality was in no way capable of recognising even a
mortal enemy of the German people, in order to abolish the Communist
Party, the enemy of the State and of the people.10
It becomes clear that the political premium should not be exploited by the com-
munists, but only by the Nazi Party in order to safeguard the bourgeois state with
the passing of the Enabling Act. This provides us with the substantive content of
the – not so formal any more – decisionist theory of Carl Schmitt. The new form
of the Nazi state can make the political decision and crush the enemy which
threatens the reproduction of bourgeois rule; and this is what the old form of the
Rechtsstaat could not deal with efficiently.
The ‘legal state’ with its inherent contradictions and its functionalist neu-
trality cannot make the political decision and exclude the communists from
the equal chance of rising to power. It is only for this reason that the ‘legal
state’ is criticised by Schmitt; because it does not correspond as a form to the
needs of the ruling class in a situation of intensified exploitation and class
struggle. On the other hand, the Nazis made use of the two extra-ordinary
law-makers – both the extraordinary law-maker ratione materiae (Art. 76 of
the Weimar Constitution) and the extraordinary law-maker ratione necessita-
tis (Art. 48), as defined by Schmitt in his Legality and Legitimacy – so as to
change the organisational structure of the bourgeois German state, get rid of
its neutral functionalist character, and effectively crush the communist threat
after recognising it as the enemy.11
Besides crushing the ‘enemy’, the Nazi state and its corresponding legal
ideology performed the equally important function of unifying the ruling
class and consolidating the bourgeois rule. Therefore, the notion of ‘political
unity’, which in Schmitt’s 1928 work Constitutional Theory serves as the basis
of the constitution-making power of a unified ‘people’, gives its place to the
principles of ‘leadership’ and ‘ethnic identity’, which can accommodate more
efficiently the most aggressive form of reactionary policies of the capitalist
state. However, the ideological function served by both notions is the same:
the construction of an abstract people, of a unified whole which obscures the
fundamental division between exploiting and exploited classes, with the added
effect of ameliorating the intra-class contradictions within the exploiting class
itself; a vital need of interwar German bourgeoisie. As Schmitt writes, ‘The
Reich Chancellor is the political leader of the German people, politically
united in the German Reich. The primary importance of the political leader-
ship is a fundamental principle of the present-day public law.’12
13 Ibid., 10–11.
‘Norm’ and ‘exception’ 127
14 William Scheuerman, Carl Schmitt: The End of Law (London: Rowman & Lit-
tlefield, 1999), 101.
15 Ibid., 103–104.
16 Ibid.
17 Carl Schmitt, ‘Starker Staat und gesunde Wirtschaft: Ein Vortrag vor Wirt-
schaftsführern’, (1933) Volk und Reich, no. 2, 89–90; Carl Schmitt, ‘Machtposi-
tionen des modernen Staates’ [1933], in Carl Schmitt, Verfassungsrechtliche
Aufsätze aus den Jahren 1924–1954, 371. According to Franz Neumann, in his
1932 address, Schmitt invented a distinction between ‘two kinds of totality, the
Roman and the Germanic’. Roman totality was quantitative; the Germanic,
qualitative. The former regimented all spheres of life, interfering with every
human activity. In sharp contrast, the Germanic remained content with a strong
and powerful state that demanded full political control but left economic activ-
ities unrestricted. Schmitt’s doctrine is, of course, no more Germanic than its
opposite is Roman. In fact, it had been formulated much more clearly and rea-
listically by an Italian, Vilfredo Pareto, who espoused political authoritarianism
and economic liberalism simultaneously and who influenced the early economic
policies of Mussolini. See Franz Neumann, Behemoth: The Structure and Practice
of National Socialism (Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 2009).
18 See Schmitt’s (untitled) lecture in Max Schlenker (ed.) Mitteilungen des Vereins
zur Wahrung der gemeinsamen wirtschaftlichen Interessen in Rheinland und
128 Dimitrios Kivotidis
Langnamverein, when he called for a ‘rollback of the state [in the economy] to
a natural and correct amount’.19 The qualitative total state must replace its
quantitative counterpart, a weak, social-democratic inspired interventionist
state. The capitalist economy should be self-administered, meaning that the
economic leaders, owners and managers need to be given substantial auton-
omy in their industries and factories, and they need to be freed from social-
democratic forms of regulation.20
Schmitt’s argument here is still one of ‘efficiency’. Not only the ‘efficiency’
of the qualitative total state in making the political decision but also the
‘efficiency’ of the qualitative state with regards to economic planning: for
Schmitt, the economically dominant should plan and the state should provide
the legal and institutional preconditions, as opposed to a system in which a
pluralist party and welfare state reflects the working-class struggle in the form
of concessions and freedoms granted to the exploited class in order to avoid a
radical overthrow of the property regime. Therefore, the exceptional form
safeguards the bourgeois rule not only by eradicating the communist threat
but also by promoting and consolidating the interests of monopoly capital.
In both its program and its fact, the so-called ‘qualitative total state’
bases itself on the fundamental condition for the reproduction of capitalist
relations, i.e. private property. The exceptional form is thus essential for the
reproduction of normality, or to use Fraenkel’s terminology, the ‘prerogative
state’ and the ‘normative state’ have a symbiotic relation: exceptional
powers and arbitrariness are necessary in order to reproduce the conditions
of capitalist production and as long as they do not threaten the reproduction
of these conditions. In his first Reichstag speech on 25 March 1933, Adolf
Hitler said: ‘The government will on principle safeguard the interests of the
German Nation not by roundabout ways of bureaucracy organised by the
state but by encouraging private initiative and by recognising private prop-
erty.’21 This function the ‘qualitative total state’ shares with its predecessor,
i.e. the ‘quantitative total state’, which according to Schmitt was ‘a totality
of weaknesses’.22
It should not be forgotten that after the end of the First World War and
Germany’s defeat, an intensified economic and socio-political crisis broke out
in the country. In November 1918, many German cities were the locus of
armed insurgencies, which led to the overtaking of governmental buildings
and the declaration of soviet (workers’ councils) rule, while a revolutionary
government was formed, which ruled over a substantive part of the country.
After a series of conflicts, in January 1919 the armed militia of the workers
were defeated and Karl Liebknecht and Rosa Luxemburg, the leaders of the
Spartacists, were murdered by the Freikorps.
The Weimar Constitution must be assessed in this context as the constitu-
tion of a bourgeois state in the need to reproduce itself in the face of multi-
level threat.23 The public legal form is assessed in its unity with the socio-
economic and political context; and the Weimar form was assumed by a
bourgeois state in need of reproducing itself. The Weimar Constitution, which
crystallised a new form of bourgeois state, can be seen as the German ruling
class’s response to the proletarian revolution: a state not indifferent to the
movement of economy, a state that does not recognise as its subject only the
private citizen but also the members of the exploited classes, which it seeks to
include in its provisions.
Originating in the context of highly intensified contradictions, the Weimar
Constitution was an example of the move from an individualist to a more
corporate24 model of constitutionalism, performing two important and inter-
related functions, i.e. the constitutionalisation of labour law and the intro-
duction of measures of ‘economic democracy’. However, despite the declared
intentions of its authors to combat the imbalance between capital and labour,
inherent in capitalist relations, the roots of the imbalance, located in the pri-
vate ownership of the means of production, were reproduced. Therefore, in
spite of its progressive nature, the Weimar Constitution ultimately served to
reproduce the capitalist relations of production by performing (objectively,
even though not consciously at all times) three very important functions:
demobilising the labour movement; promoting policies of class collaboration;
and promoting an ideology of non-radicalism.
22 Carl Schmitt, ‘Sound Economy – Strong State’, Appendix to Cristi, Carl Schmitt
and Authoritarian Liberalism.
23 On this issue see Enzo Traverso, Fire and Blood: The European Civil War, 1914–
1945 (London: Verso, 2016) and Pierre Broué, The German Revolution, 1917–
1923 (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2006).
24 For the purposes of the following analysis corporatism refers to the state model
which is based on the one hand on the political principles of ‘national sover-
eignty’ and on the other on the socio-economic principles of collaboration of the
various classes engaged in production; see Fausto Pitigliani, The Italian Cor-
porative State (London: P. S. King, 1933).
130 Dimitrios Kivotidis
whose aims for realising the full productive potential of their plant could be
served only by a determined policy of re-armament.27
The process of concentration of the decisive elements of German monopoly
capital in a new grouping of interests is described by Alfred Sohn-Rethel.
According to his analysis, on the one hand the establishment of fascism in Ger-
many in January 1933 was a result of the political victory of the dysfunctional
groups of big and small businesses over the financially sound parts of the German
economy, since, by the end of 1932, the near entirety of German finance capital
had coalesced on a policy bent on violent expansion and war.28 Germany’s pro-
duction capacities were far too large for its own narrow market. Hence, the need
for a larger internal market arose. This was expressed in the Nazi theory of the
‘living space’, but also in the expansion of the armament policies.
On the other hand, the victory of one group of businesses over the other, as
expressed in the decision of the German investment industries to expand their
monopoly market by means of their Central European policy, was underlined
by and corresponded closely with the common interest in suppressing wages
and increasing the number of working hours. If wages were not curtailed as
soon as possible, capital would be. This is because the crisis had seen a large
section of industry caught between the variable costs of wages and the fixed
ones of capital. If losses were not compensated by wage cuts, many businesses
would be pushed over the brink.29 A reversion of the capitalist mode of pro-
duction from relative to absolute surplus value extraction (i.e. intensification
of exploitation through increase in the number of working hours and drop in
real wages) was necessary for the German capital not to spiral downwards
into inescapable crisis again, as it did in 1929.
Of course, the attack on workers’ rights and the implementation of policies
directed at the lowering of labour costs did not begin with Hitler’s rise to
power. Ever since September 1926, the German industrialists had showed that
they could no longer afford the gains won by the working class between 1918
and 1923 by issuing a statement attacking the so-called ‘too generous dis-
tribution of social benefits’ and calling for a ‘reduction of the burden of
taxation’ in order to ‘restore the profitability of the economy’.30 Just weeks
after the Wall Street crash, the League of German Industry called for the
welfare state to be ‘adapted to the limits of economic sustainability’ decrying
‘unjustified and immoral abuse’ of social security benefits because in their
eyes the economic crisis had been caused by a bloated welfare state, high
wages and short working hours.31
27 Ibid., 46.
28 Ibid., 89.
29 Ibid., 55.
30 Ibid., 8.
31 Marcel Bois, ‘Hitler Wasn’t Inevitable’, Jacobin, 25 November 2015, available at
www.jacobinmag.com/2015/11/nuremberg-trials-hitler-goebbels-himmler-germa
n-communist-social-democrats/
132 Dimitrios Kivotidis
What German finance capital needed above all was to break out of the
falling rate of profit by the only means in existence that depended neither on
other capitalist powers nor on the world market, i.e. a forced raising of the
rate of surplus value by the slashing of the workers’ wages.32 This economic
need was met by Hitler’s policies that consisted of a systematic lowering of
wages. The millions of unemployed were gradually re-employed at rates of
pay no higher, or hardly so, than their unemployment benefit. This was
vividly captured by the slogan ‘Work for all, not wealth for all’, as the Nazis
expressed it after they had smashed the trade unions. The great mass of
financially weak firms welcomed Hitler’s economic ‘revival’ methods insofar
as through them they could escape the more or less acute danger of
bankruptcy.33
But the aggressive policies necessary to achieve this systematic lowering of
wages involved a sustained attack on workers’ rights that were safeguarded by
the Weimar Constitution. The leaders of German industries were well aware
that the policies they were compelled to pursue in the economic crisis, with
the attacks on all sections of the workers, including those who had gained by
the previous social legislation, would inevitably result in the weakening of the
basis of Social Democracy. These policies could not be realised in conditions
of intensified class struggle and growing militancy of the workers, unless the
bourgeois elite was able to smash not only the proletarian political organisa-
tions but also the mass basis appropriate to the previous system of control
through relative surplus value production, namely the trade unions and social
democracy. The best analysis of the reasons that necessitated the change from
the Weimar to the Nazi form was made before the Reichstag on 21 May 1935
by Adolf Hitler himself:
As a former Nazi official, Albert Krebs described in his memoirs: ‘[n]ot all
capitalists were particularly enthusiastic about the Nazis, but their scepticism
was relative and ended as soon as it became clear that Hitler was the only
person capable of destroying the labour movement’.35 The Nazi state form
and the Nazi economic model formed a unified yet contradictory whole,
which is reflected in the concept of ‘qualitative total state’ in Schmitt’s theo-
retical framework. These new economic and political forms corresponded to
the intensified capitalist contradictions after the capitalist crisis and the
objective need to restore the profitability of German enterprises by advancing
a new political system that would crush the working-class movement.
The essence of National Socialist social policy consisted in the reproduc-
tion of the class character of the German social formation, in the attempted
consolidation of its ruling class, in the atomization of the subordinate strata
through the destruction of every autonomous group mediating between them
and the state, and in the creation of a system of autocratic bureaucracies
interfering in all human relations.36 The maintenance of capitalist ownership,
‘private enterprise’, and the recovery of ‘profits’ and ‘profitability’ accom-
panied with moderate state intervention in a regulatory role were character-
istics of the interwar corporatist state, and were reflected in Schmitt’s
economic model of the ‘qualitative total state’.
We conclude that the Nazi form of government, as well as the Nazi eco-
nomic model, was necessitated by the intensification of class and intra-class
conflicts. The deadlock in the economy and the contradictions between pro-
tectionism and inflation were manifestations of capitalist contradictions. But
the capitalists were unified against the main opponent, namely the working
class organised in workers’ unions and workers’ parties. The measures against
the workers had to be passed and for this the communist threat had to be
extinguished. This urgency for action on the part of the industrial capitalists
was reflected in the use of the extra-ordinary law-making provisions, of Arti-
cle 48, in the Reichstag Fire Decree, and of Article 76 in the passing of the
Enabling Act, which consolidated the Nazi rule.
35 Albert Krebs, The Infancy of Nazism: The Memoirs of Ex-Gauleiter Albert Krebs
(London: New Viewpoints, 1976).
36 Neumann, Behemoth, 365.
134 Dimitrios Kivotidis
acts of the ordinary police pursuant upon general orders of the Gestapo and
all acts of the ordinary police which fall within the jurisdiction of the
Gestapo.40 The classification of more and more actions as ‘political’, rather
than private, so that they would fall within the jurisdiction of the Gestapo,
whose actions were not subject to judicial review, was essential for the
exceptional Nazi state form.
Furthermore, this process of politicisation appears in the form of the ple-
biscite and the identification of rulers and ruled. In his early analysis of the
Weimar form, even before the Nazi form, the election of the Reichspraesident
was interpreted by Schmitt as something different from a democratic elec-
tion41; it was seen as a plebiscitarian acclamation. It is no wonder then that in
the Nazi form of the plebiscite, popular sovereignty reaches an extreme point
of hollowness. Only a decisionist president, a leader (Führer) could escape
civil society’s centrifugal pluralism, and ‘unify the people’ by holding its trust.
It could thus provide the perfect legitimating mechanism for a class-colla-
borative form of state to reproduce the conditions of intensified exploitation
necessary for the recovery and expansion of German capital.
The plebiscite, this new form of legitimation, was cohesive with (even
though different from) parliamentary elections, which it superseded. They
both share an abstract and class-less conception of the ‘people’. The people
appear on stage when they are asked to vote, and then recede in the back-
ground once they have ‘blessed’ and legitimised a new round of policies,
which they have supposedly chosen in an expression of the ‘general will’.
But whereas in liberal democracy an election provides an opportunity for
freewheeling debate about candidates and political parties, and the election
is seen as culminating in some ‘normativisation’ (i.e. a piece of general law
deriving its legitimacy from rational debate), the Schmittian plebiscite is
simply a ‘decision giving expression to an act of will’, a means by which the
popular masses can hope to approximate ‘a pure decision not based on
reason and discussion and not justifying itself ’.42 The plebiscite as a dis-
tinctive form has the advantage for the ruling class to present the voters with
only an extremely limited choice, a polarising and reductionist distortion of
the many-sided reality. Moreover, it deals in binaries and has the added
advantage of the voters’ utter dependence on the way the question is for-
mulated (as Schmitt himself points out in his ‘Legality and Legitimacy’).
Therefore, plebiscitary legitimacy and the leadership principle served a
double purpose: on the one hand they acted as a unifying force against cen-
trifugal tendencies, a form accommodating the reconsolidation of German
capital. On the other hand they provided the legitimating mechanism neces-
sary for the conditions of intensified exploitation. For this reason, the effect of
40 Ibid., 27.
41 Schmitt, Constitutional Theory.
42 Scheuerman, Carl Schmitt: The End of Law, 102.
136 Dimitrios Kivotidis
43 Norman Thomas, ‘Labour Under the Nazis’ (1936) 14(3) Foreign Affairs 424.
44 David Kettler, ‘Works Community and Workers’ Organization: A Central Pro-
blem in Weimar Labour Law’, (1984) 13 Economy and Society, 278, 296.
45 Ibid.
46 Ibid.
47 Scheuerman, Carl Schmitt: The End of Law, 122.
‘Norm’ and ‘exception’ 137
It follows from the above that changes in German constitutional law and
changes in German labour law were intertwined during the interwar period.
The reason for this was shown to have been the intensification of social and
economic contradictions. Abolishing the rights to strike and collective bar-
gaining and crushing the working-class movement while creating a new
social basis based on the principle of class collaboration could not have been
achieved unless the form of exercise of public power had changed. The
interwar model of the corporate state48 was based on the one hand on the
principles of ‘national sovereignty’ and ‘national unity’ and on the other
hand on a concept implicit in the state system, which Fascism desires to
build up – namely, the economic collaboration of the various categories
engaged in production.49 Schmitt’s theoretical framework accommodates
both these principles, as is evident in the above analysis.
We conclude that the normal and the exceptional forms of exercise of
public power are different but not separated. They are rather united in their
difference. A fundamental necessity underlies both norm and exception: the
necessity of a regime of power, property and productive relations. The ordin-
ary function of the rule of law, which safeguards this regime, is conditional
upon the non-occurrence of the always existent and imminent danger, which
Schmitt terms as the ‘ever-present possibility of conflict’.50 It has been argued
that this ‘ever-present possibility of conflict’ stands for the intensification of
social antagonisms. This concept includes a multiplicity of factors (intra-class
conflicts and class struggle) that might necessitate a change in the form of
exercise of public power.
48 Franz Neumann held that the Nazi state form was incompatible with the model
of the corporate state because for National Socialism the primacy of politics is
decisive. The reason he gives for this is that the Nazi Party never allowed itself to
put the economic questions into the foreground and to announce comprehensive
economic official party programs. It always insisted on the primacy of politics
over economics and therefore consciously remained a political party without any
basic economic orientation: see Neumann, Behemoth, 232. However, the struc-
tural role of a political party in a social formation is hardly restricted to its poli-
tical intentions and announcements through party programmes. It is, on the
contrary, assessed by the objective effect its policies have in the social formation.
Neumann himself acknowledges that the role played by the German Labour
Front was one of promoting ideas and practices of class collaboration, under the
influence of corporative ideas: see Neumann, Behemoth, 414. In this respect the
Front served five crucial functions: the indoctrination of labour with the National
Socialist ideology, the taxation of the German working class; the securing of
positions for reliable party members, the atomization of the German working
classes, and the exercise of certain inner trade-union functions: see Neumann,
Behemoth, 417.
49 Fausto Pitigliani, The Italian Corporative State.
50 Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political.
138 Dimitrios Kivotidis
Conclusion
The above analysis showed the indissoluble union between ‘norm’ and
‘exception’, as well as between all the other dualisms employed by Schmitt to
characterise the different forms of exercise of public power. Schmitt’s dualisms
were examined in their socio-political context to unearth the content that the
different forms corresponded to. This move from political theology to poli-
tical economy meant that we had to discuss not the state in the abstract, but
the capitalist state, not sovereignty in the abstract, but the economic and
political power of a dominant class, not the ‘decision’ in the abstract, but the
decision based on socially and historically conditioned interests, not the ‘ever-
present possibility of conflict’, but the ever-present possibility of suspending
the rule of law, in order to deal with the internal enemy, which is nothing else
than the threat to the capitalist state
Rather than being taken from outside (ex-capere), the exception emerges
from within the law – it is bound within law because it corresponds to the
foundational need of the bourgeois state to reproduce itself in the face of
threat. The ‘normal’ and the ‘exceptional’ forms correspond to different his-
torical situations, to different levels of intensification socio-economic contra-
dictions, but they both serve the ultimate function of ensuring the
reproduction of a regime of power, property and productive relations. The
above analysis did not reduce the liberal democratic form of government to
the authoritarian one. Rather, it stressed the differences and the reasons
behind the differences of the two forms by focusing on the commonalities
between them: on the capitalist relations that were reproduced by both as well
as on the working-class movement that was obstructed by both, albeit in dif-
ferent ways.
It is perhaps under this prism that Walter Benjamin’s 8th thesis on the
Concept of History can be better assessed. The ‘emergency situation’ should
be understood from the standpoint of the exploited and the oppressed. This,
according to Mark Neocleous, means that:
One could argue then that this ‘real state of emergency’ corresponds to the
‘right of necessity’, the ‘right of extreme need’ that is found in the Hegelian
52 Domenico Losurdo, Hegel and the Freedom of the Moderns (Durham: Duke
University Press, 2004), 87.
Chapter 7
Introduction
It is a horrible, monstrous shame for the Party that after 36 years in power it
has to be defended by the police. But there is nothing else left ahead of us.
General Wojciech Jaruzelski2
‘[L]aw … nourishes itself on [the] exception and is a dead letter without it,’3
Giorgio Agamben wrote. But does the signifier ‘law’ refer here to feudal and
capitalist law, or also to law in a state-socialist polity? Is the state of exception
limited to bourgeois legality and the efforts of its ruling classes to strip the
proletariat of the scant legal protections it had won, or is it also possible under
conditions of so-called ‘socialist legality’? The Polish state of emergency, tech-
nically known as ‘state of war’ (stan wojenny), proclaimed on the night of 12–
13 December 1981, ‘conventionally translated [into English] as ‘martial law’4
1 I would like to thank Cosmin Cercel, Przemysław Tacik, Gian Giacomo Fusco,
Mikhail Antonov and Tormod Otter Johanssen for reading and commenting on
earlier versions of this chapter and for sharing with me their insightful ideas. The
present chapter presents exclusively my personal views and should not be attrib-
uted to any institution.
2 ‘Protocol No. 18 of PUWP CC Politburo Meeting, December 5, 1981’ in Andrzej
Paczkowski and Malcolm Byrne (eds), From Solidarity to Martial Law: The
Polish Crisis 1980–1981 (Budapest, New York: Central European University
Press. 2007), 443.
3 Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Daniel Heller-
Roazen transl. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), 27.
4 Brian Porter-Szűcs, Poland in the Modern World: Beyond Martyrdom (Chichester:
John Wiley & Sons, 2014) 303. On the terminology, cf. Giorgio Agamben, State
of Exception, Kevin Attell transl. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005) 4.
Indeed, the translation ‘martial law’ correctly conveys the link with war present in
the Polish term.
Poland’s 1981 martial law 141
5 Cercel notes that wartime communism ‘is and can be regarded as a dictatorship
or even more as a state of exception’ of a ‘transitional character’ See Cosmin
Cercel, Towards a Jurisprudence of State Communism: Law and the Failure of
Communism (London: Routledge, 2018), 93.
6 On the other hand, Cercel argues that the Stalinist defence of legality ‘was his-
torically consubstantial with a normalised state of exception marked by extra-
judicial measures, deportations and killings, and (…) was itself a state of
exception insofar as it tended to protected both the existing posiitve law and the
form of legality’ (Cercel, Towards a Jurisprudence, 103). However, in the case of
Stalinism, the institution of the state of exception was not used as such. The state
of exception was, arguably, practised, but not as a question of legal form, but
rather actual functioning of the repressive apparatus of the Soviet state.
7 Article 1 of the Constitution of the Polish People’s Republic of 22 July 1952,
consolidated version of 16 February 1976, Dziennik Ustaw PRL 1976, no 7, item
36.
8 I will use the expression ‘Martial Law’ in capital letters to denote the Polish
martial law declared on 12/13 December 1981 as a unique historical event.
142 Rafał Mańko
9 Carl Schmitt, Political Theology, George Schwab transl. (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 1985), 3.
10 See especially Jan Sowa, Inna Rzeczpospolita jest możliwa! Widma przeszłości,
wizje przyszłości [Another Republic is Possible! Specters of the Past, Visions of
the Future] (Warszawa: WAB, 2015) 108–109. Cf. idem, ‘An Unexpected Twist of
Ideology: Neoliberalism and the collapse of the Soviet Bloc’ (2012) 5 Praktyka
Teoretyczna 153, 161–168.
11 Ken Jowitt, New World Disorder: The Leninist Extinction (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1992), 1–49.
12 Ibid., 11.
13 Tadeusz Kowalik, From Solidarity to Sellout: The Restoration of Capitalism in
Poland, transl Eliza Lewandowska (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2011) 26.
.
14 Cf. Lech Mazewski, Posttotalitarny autorytaryzm PRL 1956–1989. Analiza
ustrojowopolityczna [Post-Totalitarian Authoritarianism: The Polish People’s
Republic 1956–1989. An Analysis of the Political Constitution] (Warszawa-Biała
Podlaska: Arte, 2010).
15 Cf. Mikhail Antonov, ‘Legal Realism in Soviet and Russian Jurisprudence’,
(2018) 43 Review of Central and East European Law 483. My idea of con-
ceptualising the informal, yet empirically binding rules of the ius politicum as a
layer of the socialist legal system goes against Mikhail Anotonov’s understanding,
who limits the scope of the signifier ‘law’ only to what I call here the lex scripta.
My approach, which I could describe as radically realist, aims to underscore the
importance of the Party’s internal normative system for the constitutional setup
Poland’s 1981 martial law 143
of a state-socialist polity which, without taking into account the ius politicum,
cannot be properly described only on the basis of the lex scripta. For a different,
and highly originial conceptualisaton in terms of the ‘law of the hegemon’, see
Dawid Bunikowski, ‘Hegemoni i ich prawo w czasach polskiego komunizmu.
Próba analizy prawnoustrojowej i filozoficzno-prawnej’ [Hegemons and their Law
in the Times of Polish Communism: An Attempt at a Constitutional and Legal-
.
Philosophical Analysis] (2010) 9 Roczniki Naukowe Wyzszej Szkoły Bankowej w
Toruniu 95.
16 See e.g. Thomas Lowit, ‘Y a-t-il des États en Europe de l’Est?’ (1979) 20 Revue
française de la sociologie 431; idem, ‘Le Parti polimorphe en Europe de l’Est’
(1979) 29 (4–5) Revue française de science politique 812.
17 I would like to thank Przemysław Tacik for drawing my attention to this aspect.
.
18 Mazewski, Posttotalitarny 40.
19 Stefan Kisielewski, ‘Wywiad ze Stefanem Kisielewskim’ [An Interview with
Stefan Kisielewski] (1956) 6 Kultura 27, at 28 (who even calls the Central Com-
mittee a ‘parliament’).
144 Rafał Mańko
in the 1930s in the USSR.20 In short, socialist legality differed from Western
liberal rule of law in two fundamental aspects. First, it emphasised the duty of
strict observance of the law by citizens and state authorities alike.21 Hence, it was
not so much a shield protecting citizens from government, but rather a sword
allowing the government to control citizens. Second, its central tenet was its class
character: socialist legality was about the legal form of the will of the ruling
class, i.e. theoretically the working people,22 which, however, expressed its will
through the Leninist party.23 Thus, socialist legality was more about giving legal
form to the authoritarian rule of the Party than about protecting citizens from it.
If we look into the question of fundamental rights in a state-socialist polity,
it becomes immediately patent that, in contrast to liberal capitalist states, the
fundamental economic and social rights are placed at the forefront. They
open the constitutional bill of rights and, by and large, they were actually
enforced.24 The state provided heavily subsidised housing, free healthcare, free
education even at university level, heavily subsidised access to culture, paid
holidays and subsidised holiday facilities, etc. As from 1956, abortion was
legal and available for free.25 In contrast, LGBT rights were not recognised,
and in the 1980s members of the LGBT community were even subject to
persecutions as part of a project led by the Ministry of the Interior.26
As concerns political rights, however, their prima facie constitutional for-
mulation did not reflect the reality. One could conceptualise this phenomenon
either by a very broad abuse of rights doctrine, pointing out that political
rights could be exercised only within the framework of the telos of the Polish
people’s Republic and with respect to the hegemonic role of the Leninist
party, itself constitutionalised in 1976.27 Or, one could simply point to the
dualist character of the legal system and note that the rights guaranteed by
the lex scripta were actually trumped by the ius politicum. All in all, the
political monopoly of the Leninist party excluded the creation of opposition
parties (its subjected allies, the Polish People’s Faction and the Democratic
Faction were called ‘factions’, not ‘parties’, to avoid any misunderstanding),
or of independent trade unions. The only politically independent organisation
in state-socialist Poland was, effectively, the Catholic Church. All these
aspects of state-socialist normalcy, and especially the political hegemony of
the Leninist party and the command system of the economy, came under
unprecedented pressure in 1980/81.
27 See Article 3(1) of the Polish Constitution (as of 1976): ‘The Polish United
Workers’ Party is the leading political force of society in the construction of
socialism.’
28 MacDonald, ‘The Polish Vortex’, 9.
29 Janusz Szkodlarski, Zarys historii gospodarczej Polski [An Outline of Poland’s
Economic History] (Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN, 2007) 483–5;
.
Andrzej Dorosz, ‘Zadłuzenie. zagraniczne PRL’ [The Foreign Indebtedness of the
Polish People’s Republic] in Zółtkowski (ed.), Zrozumieć PRL 204–214.
30 Andrzej Leon Sowa, Historia polityczna Polski 1944–1991 [A Political History of
Poland 1944–1991] (Kraków: Wydawnictwo Literackie, 2011), 407–11.
146 Rafał Mańko
Edward Gierek and his Politburo were removed and replaced with a new
leadership under First Secretary Stanisław Kania. Any attempts by the new
government to retreat from the August Agreements met with strikes. Over
time, Solidarity was radicalising itself and gaining an ever-broader mem-
bership base, ultimately reaching ten million members, compared to three
million Party members, in a 35-million population. The movement was
definitely massive, and its political ambitions were growing every month. It
even sought to reach out to workers in other state-socialist countries, as
evidenced by its highly provocative ‘Address to the Working People of
Eastern Europe’, explicitly directed to ‘the workers of Albania, Bulgaria,
Czechoslovakia, German Democratic Republic, Hungary and of the all the
nations of the Soviet Union’, in which they wrote that ‘contrary to lies
propagated in your countries, we are an authentic, ten-million organisation
of employees’.36
In October 1981, Solidarity adopted its official programme during the 1st
Congress of Delegates.37 Characteristically, the content of this document
cannot be found today either on historical websites of Solidarity38 or on the
website of the infamous Institute of National Memory. This is no wonder, as
the fifty-page document did not propose to introduce capitalism or even
market mechanisms, but rather had an openly anarcho-syndicalist and radi-
cally democratic character, demanding the introduction of worker self-man-
agement and ‘socialised planning’ of the economy.39 Not only the enterprises
(thesis 20) but also the media (thesis 32) were to be owned and managed by
society, rather than by the state or by the capital.40 All this allows Jan Sowa
to claim that Solidarity ‘not only was not an anti-communist movement (…)
but also was, in itself, a communist event par excellence.’41 In his view, Soli-
darity’s programme was the embodiment of the ‘revolutionary imaginarium of
the society, which had internalised the ideals of equality and socialisation,
foundational to the order introduced in Poland after World War II.’42
In this sense, therefore, Solidarity was a part of the broad revisionist
current within the communist movement, questioning the practices of
state-socialism in the name of what they considered to be an authentic
socialisation of the economy and government. As such, Solidarity was a
direct and to a large extent ideologically internal threat to the concrete
order of the Polish People’s Republic, based on hegemony of the Party and
its domination over the state and of the state over the economy. Solidar-
ity’s demands went even beyond what was practised in socialist Yugoslavia
and aimed at a total constitutional overhaul. On the other hand, it must
be admitted that apart from typically socialist elements of the economic
programme, such as full employment (thesis 9), or the right to housing
(thesis 17), the Solidarity programme also contained elements inspired by
liberal political philosophy, such as political pluralism (thesis 19), judicial
and prosecutorial independence (thesis 24), academic freedom (thesis 30)
and autonomous local government (thesis 21). Solidarity experts even
proposed to introduce direct democracy – referenda as a means of settling
conflicts between Solidarity and the Party.43 Not unsurprisingly, this
admixture of anarcho-syndicalism, political liberalism and radical democ-
racy was extremely alarming to the hegemonic Leninist party in power
and to Poland’s allies in the Warsaw Pact.
In Schmittian terms we can safely say that Solidarity aimed to be a new
pouvoir constituant, aiming at the abolition of Leninist civilisation in Poland,
and its replacement with an anarcho-syndicalist workers’ self-government,
coupled with pluralism and the rule of law, as outlined in the movement’s
official programme (which, in itself, could also have been formulated some-
what more moderately and need not have reflected the demands of the more
radical activists within Solidarity).
On 3 December 1981 the Presidium of the National Coordination Com-
mission of Solidarity, gathered in the city of Radom, adopted a very tough
declaration, approved by the entire Coordination Commission on 12 Decem-
ber 1981. The language was very confrontational, and the Solidarity leader-
ship was wary of the forthcoming legislation on the state of emergency. In the
document we read inter alia that
42 Ibid., 179–180.
43 Stefan Kurowski, Grzegorz Palka, Wacław Adamczak and Zbigniew Karwowski,
‘Instytucjonalne zabezpieczenie Programu Ekonomicznego Związku’ [Institu-
tional Safeguards for the Economic Programme of the Union] in Dokumenty I
tury zjazdu 77.
Poland’s 1981 martial law 149
and restrict traveling, or only to annul the right to strike, it will not be
introduced in any other way than through terror. It would amount to an
attempt to subdue the society through force. Therefore, the Union will
respond to the Sejm’s potential passing of the law on extraordinary
powers for the government with a 24-hour long universal protest strike in
Poland. In case the government takes advantage of the power granted to
it by the Sejm to use extraordinary measures, the Union cells and all
[workers’] crews should inevitably initiate a general strike.44
Radical and very concrete demands were made in categorical language. Soli-
darity indicated that it was not open to compromise on a number of demands,
including a new trade union law following its version, pluralist elections to
local councils on all levels and subordination of state administration to such
councils, change of economic governance giving Solidarity more powers, and
finally access to the media for Solidarity and the Catholic Church.45 This was
the state of mind of Solidarity leadership on 12 December 1981, directly
before Martial Law.
Poland’s domestic situation was, as from the summer of 1980, a reason of
growing concern for its allies in the Warsaw Pact, especially the USSR, GDR
and Czechoslovakia.46 The Soviets created a special commission to oversee
Poland, headed by the orthodox Marxist-Leninist Suslov.47 Large-scale mili-
tary manoeuvres involving the Soviet Army and other Warsaw Pact armies
took place on Polish territory and in the neighbouring countries.48 A special
Soviet command centre was installed nearby Warsaw.49 Of course, we will
never know whether the Soviets were actually intending to repeat the 1953/
1956/1968 scenarios or whether it was all mere bluff. As Mark Kramer rightly
points out, ‘Polish leaders (…) may have genuinely believed that an invasion
would occur if a solution “from within” Poland (i.e., martial law) did not
materialize. Indeed, Soviet leaders themselves may have wanted to create that
impression—even if they did not intend to follow up on it (…).’50
What remains important from the point of view of the exceptionality of the
situation are two facts. First, that Solidarity intended to build an alternative
social and political force, competing with the Leninist party and aiming to
The Council of State may introduce martial law in a part or on the entire
territory of the Polish People’s Republic if this is required by reasons of
defence or security of the state.
The pre-1939 legislation on the state of exception and martial law, as based
on the 1935 constitution, although formally not repealed, was inapplicable
by virtue of the principle of desuetudo.52 Poland’s post-1944 legal continuity
with the pre-1939 legal order was not unconditional: only legislation that
was compatible with the new political and economic system was considered
to be binding. Therefore, in 1981 Poland found itself in the situation of a
legal vacuum53: there existed the competence norm of Article 33 of the
formally introduced67 (it was not a novelty). Individuals and NGOs were pro-
hibited from owning or using printing devices. Correspondence was to be cen-
sored and phone calls tapped. Police were authorised to uses emergency
measures, including ‘chemical incapacitating agents’, water cannons and even
combat weapons. It made it possible to introduce a duty to work for all above 15
years of age, unless pensioned. Workers could be moved between enterprises and
a six-day working week could be introduced. Rationing of foodstuffs and obli-
gatory supplies from farmers were introduced. Transport could be suspended,
including the closure of border crossings, and telecom services limited.68
Administrative detention of individuals was introduced for persons aged above
17, ‘in relation to which, for reasons of their hitherto conduct, there is a risk that
remaining in liberty they would not conform to the legal order or would under-
take an activity threatening the interests of security or defence of the state.’69
Internment decisions were taken by regional commanders of the police, with the
possibility of appealing the decision to the minister of the interior.70 The decree
provided for the creation of ‘isolation centres’ for those subject to internment,
and for the application mutatis mutandis on rules on pre-trial detention to those
centres.71,72 Ironically, therefore, state-socialist Poland returned to the author-
itarian traditions of pre-1939 capitalist Poland, where administrative detention
had been introduced in 1934, following the military coup of 1926.73
Finally, a set of new criminal acts was introduced, with penalties ranging
from a maximum of three to even ten years in prison.74 The criminalised acts
included inter alia the continuing the activity of a suspended organisation, the
organisation of strikes or protest actions, acting to the detriment of the
interests of state security, or the propagation of fake news. Apart from crim-
inal acts, the decree introduced a number of new misdemeanors,75 punishable
by arrest up to three months or a financial penalty up to 5,000 zlotys – almost
half the average monthly salary.76 These included inter alia such acts as par-
ticipation in a strike or protest action, change of residence without permis-
sion, violation of the curfew, presence in a public place without ID, or
abstaining from work.
The Decree on Martial Law was accompanied by a decree on special
proceedings in cases concerning crimes and petty offences,77 a decree
granting jurisdiction over civilians to military courts,78 and a decree on
amnesty for anti-government acts committed before the Martial Law.79
The decree on special proceedings allowed for summary trials in a number
of crimes already foreseen in the Criminal Code, as well as those intro-
duced in the Decree on Martial Law. The decrees were applied swiftly and
effectively with the participation of over 53,000 soldiers.80 As of 14
December, 3,437 individuals were interned,81 the figure rising to 3,926 on
16 December,82 4,450 on 18 December,83 4,612 on 20 December,84 5,540
[Decree of the President of the Republic of 17 June 1934 concerning persons threaten-
ing security, peace and the public order], Dziennik Ustaw no 50, item 473.
74 Decree on Martial Law, Articles 46–51.
75 Decree on Martial Law, Articles 50–51.
76 The average salary in 1981 amounted to 7,689 zlotys, and in 1982–11,631 zlotys.
See ‘Przeciȩtne miesiȩczne wynagrodzenie w latach 1950–2008’ available at www.
infor.pl/prawo/zarobki/zarobki-w-polsce/686166,Przecietne-miesieczne-wynagrod
zenie-w-latach-19502008.html, accessed 26 January 2020.
77 Dekret z dnia 12 grudnia 1981 r. o postępowaniach szczególnych w sprawach o
przestępstwa i wykroczenia w czasie obowiązywania stanu wojennego [Decree of
12 December 1981 on special proceedings for crimes and petty offences during
martial law] (Dz.U. no 29, item 156).
78 Dekret z dnia 12 grudnia 1981 r. o przekazaniu do właściwości sądów wojsko-
wych spraw o niektóre przestępstwa oraz o zmianie ustroju sądów wojskowych i
wojskowych jednostek organizacyjnych Prokuratury PRL w czasie obow-
iązywania stanu wojennego [Decree of 12 December 1981 on the transfer of jur-
isdiction concerning certain crimes to courts martial] (Dz.U no 29, item 157).
79 Dekret z dnia 12 grudnia 1981 r. o przebaczeniu i puszczeniu w niepamiȩć niek-
tórych przestȩpstw i wykroczeń [Decree of 12 December 1981 on amnesty con-
cerning certain crimes and petty offences], Dz.U. no 29, item 158.
80 Paczkowski, Revolution, 94.
81 Rakowski, Dzienniki, 136.
82 Ibid., 138.
83 Ibid., 141.
84 Ibid., 143
Poland’s 1981 martial law 155
85 Ibid., 146.
86 Ibid., 148.
87 Ibid., 183.
88 Ibid., 189.
89 Paczkowski, Revolution 104. See also detailed statistics as of 12 October 1982 in
Rakowski, Dzienniki polityczne 1981-1983, 371.
90 Paczkowski, Revolution, 109.
91 Ustawa z dnia 25 stycznia 1982 r. o szczególnej regulacji prawnej w okresie stanu
wojennego [Act of 25 January 1982 on the special legal regime during the period
of martial law], Dziennik Ustaw no 3, item 18
92 Ustawa z dnia 18 grudnia 1982 r. o zmianie ustawy o szczególnej regulacji
prawnej w okresie stanu wojennego [Act of 18 December 1982 modifying the act
on the special legal regime during the period of martial law], Dziennik Ustaw no
41, item 272.
93 Uchwała Rady Państwa z dnia 19 grudnia 1982 r. w sprawie zawieszenia stanu
wojennego [Resolution of the Council of State of 19 December 1982 regarding
the suspension of the martial law], Dziennik Ustaw no 42, item 275.
94 Uchwała Rady Państwa z dnia 20 lipca 1983 r. w sprawie zniesienia stanu
wojennego [Resolution of the Council of State of 20 July 1983 regarding the
abolition of Martial Law], Dziennik Ustaw no 39, item 178.
95 Mieczysław F Rakowski, Dzienniki polityczne 1984-1986 (Warszawa: Iskry, 2005),
106-108; Marceli Kosman, Wojciech Jaruzelski. Mąż stanu w czasach przełomu
[Wojciech Jaruzelski: Statesman in Times of Breakthrough] (Toruń: Wydaw-
nictwo Adam Marszałek, 2013), 86.
156 Rafał Mańko
96 One of the first academic publications challenging the legality of the Martial Law
was Janusz Kochanowski and Tadeusz de Virion, ‘Glosa do wyroku SN z 1
marca 1982 r., V KRN 50/82’ (1982) 9 Państwo i Prawo, 148.
97 See e.g. Bogumiła Lubera and Agnieszka Sikorska, ‘Retroaktywność dekretu o
stanie wojennym w świetle Konstytucji z 1952 i 1997 r.’ [Retroactivity of the
Martial Law Decree in the Light of the 1952 and 1997 Constitutions] (2010) 4
Przegląd Prawa Konstytucyjnego 125, 131–139; Mażewski, Problem legalności
39–65, 131–138.
98 Cf. ‘Protocol No. 18’ 443–444, where the general presents plans to introduce
Martial Law, presumably approved tacitly by the Politburo, as claimed by
.
Mazewski, Posttotalitarny autorytatyzm, 104.
Poland’s 1981 martial law 157
1981.99 Hence, all five acts adopted that night were antedated, as they
mention 12 December, and not 13 December, as their date of adoption.
Furthermore, the operation of introducing the state of exception started at
11.30 pm on 12 December, i.e. even before the session of the Council of
State had begun.100 The Journal of Laws where they were promulgated was
dated 14 December, although it became available only on 17 December
1981.101 However, as the Supreme Court underlined in its judgment of 1
March 1982, the decrees and resolution were well known to citizens as they
had been made public in the mass media.102 The national television
informed about the content of the decree, and a communication by the
president of the Council of State concerning martial law was made public in
poster form.103 Indeed, taking into account the exceptionality of a state of
emergency, it would have rendered the Martial Law inoperative if it had
been necessary to wait for its legal effects until the decrees and resolution
were correctly published, perhaps even with a vacatio legis. Finally, since
Poland was a party to the International Covenant of Civic and Political
Rights, the ambassador of the Polish People’s Republic to the UN informed
the secretary general, initially by telephone, and later during an audience.104
Thus, formal legality was preserved, even on an international level.
.
99 Rakowski, Dzienniki polityczne 1981-1982, 135; Mazewski, Problem legalności,
36.
100 Ibid., 35–36.
101 Ibid., 48–49.
102 Case V KRN 50/82, OSNKW 1982 no 6, item 39.
.
103 Mazewski, Problem legalności, 50.
104 Ibid., 54–55.
105 Ibid., 65–67.
158 Rafał Mańko
underlined: first, the competence to introduce martial law was expressly pro-
vided for by the Constitution (Article 33(2)) and, second, the limitation of
fundamental rights is, beyond doubt, the very essence of any state of excep-
tion even if Article 33 of the Constitution was silent on that issue.
Did General Jaruzelski intend to save state socialism, reform it or replace it?
The evaluation of General Jaruzelski’s dictatorship – in the precise Schmittian
sense of Diktatur – depends to a large extent on how one classifies the political
system existing before its introduction on the night of 12/13 December 1981. In
my depiction of state-socialist ‘normalcy’ I avoided classifying it – at least on
the eve of the Martial Law – as a form of dictatorship. However, if one adopts,
along Marxist-Leninist lines, the classification of the Polish People’s Republic
as a dictatorship of the proletariat,112 or, along right-wing and conservative
lines, as a ‘communist dictatorship’, then the passage from normal situation to
state of exception becomes more problematic. It could then be seen as a pas-
sage from dictatorship of the proletariat to military dictatorship, perhaps akin
to war communism, or, if the opposite perspective is adopted, a passage from
the ‘communist dictatorship’ of the Party to military dictatorship, executed by
a junta in the form of the Military Council of National Salvation (WRON).
Given the revolutionary origins of the state-socialist form of government, with
the sovereign dictatorship at its roots, one could also argue that the constitution
of People’s Poland was, in fact, an ‘ossified sovereign dictatorship’, and General
Jaruzelski returned to its roots.113
However, what needs to be kept in mind is that in its precise Roman
meaning later developed by Schmitt, a dictatorship is, by definition, an
exceptional political arrangement, rather than a permanent state of a given
polity. With this assumption in mind, I wish to enquire whether, in Schmittian
terms, General Jaruzelski’s dictatorship can be characterised as a commissary
or sovereign one.
According to Schmitt’s dichotomy, a commissary dictatorship ‘suspends the
constitution in order to protect it – the very same one – in its concrete
form.’114 A commissary dictatorship, therefore, ‘protects a specific constitu-
tion against an attack that threatens to abolish this constitution.’115 Of
course, this entails suspending the constitution which, however, does not cease
112 A characterisation adopted e.g. by law and state theorist Adam Łopatka as late
as 1969 – see Adam Łopatka, Wstęp do prawoznawstwa [An Introduction to
Jurisprudence] (Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, 1969), 73–74.
113 I would like to thank Dr Przemysław Tacik for suggesting this idea to me.
114 Carl Schmitt, Dictatorship, Michael Hoelzl and Graham Ward transl. (Cam-
bridge: Polity, 2014), 118.
115 Ibid. [Emphasis added].
160 Rafał Mańko
116 Ibid.
117 Ibid. 119 [Emphasis added].
118 Ibid.
119 Carl Schmitt, Constitutional Theory, Jeffrey Seitzer transl. (Durham, London:
Duke University Press, 2008), 128.
120 Wojciech Jaruzelski, televised address to the nation, broadcast on 13 December
1981, full recording available at www.youtube.com/watch?v=4yUKFzYEFSg,
accessed 15 January 2020.
121 Ibid.
Poland’s 1981 martial law 161
‘[i]ts only task is the protection of the legal order in the State, the creation of
executive guarantees that will enable to restore order and discipline.’122
Jaruzelski underscored the temporary nature of the dictatorship, promising
that the Military Council ‘shall be dissolved once rule of law prevails in the
country, once conditions appear for the normal functioning of the civil
administration and representative bodies.’123 What is worth underlining in
these passages is the absence of Marxist-Leninist ideological tropes and the
domination of a state-centrist, rule-of-law rhetoric, quite distant from a
revolutionary communist spirit. As a matter of fact, although the General
initially wanted to call the emergency body the ‘Military Revolutionary
Council for the Salvation of the Fatherland’ (Wojskowo-Rewolucyjna Rada
Ocalenia Ojczyzny)124 – a name consciously evoking the Revvoyensoviet125 –
he eventually dropped any allusions to the Revolution, preferring the some-
what nationalist rhetoric of ‘national salvation’. As historian Andrzej Pacz-
kowski comments, ‘the word “revolution” vanished almost at the last
minute, probably because it was reminiscent of the system’s roots and
ideology, which could have had limited the number of supporters of martial
law. It was deemed better to allude to patriotic sentiment and loyalty to the
state, embodied by the army (…).’126
Concerning the key element of state-socialist constitutionalism – the
hegemony of the Leninist party – the general was not so outspoken. In fact,
he mentioned the party only in the 13th minute of his televised address,
noting that ‘[d]espite the errors that have been committed and bitter failures,
within the process of historical transitions the Party retains an active and
creative role.’127 He even mentioned the party’s ‘leadership mission’, and did
not overlook the ‘Polish-Soviet alliance’ which ‘shall remain the cornerstone
of the raison d’état, the guarantee of the inviolability of our borders’,
122 Ibid.
123 Ibid.
124 The name was mentioned by General Florian Siwicki in his talks with the Soviets
on 11 December 1981 – see ‘Zeszyt roboczy gen. Wiktora Anoszkina’ [General
Victor Anoshkin’s Working Notebook] in Łukasz Kamiński (ed.), 2 Przed i po 13
grudnia: Państwa bloku wschodniego wobec kryzysu w prl 1980–1982 [Before and
After 13 December: States of the East Block Towards the Crisis in the Polish
People’s Republic 1980–1982] (Warszawa: Instytut Pamięci Narodowej, 2007)
403. See also Stanisław Kwiatkowski, W stanie wyższej konieczności. Wojsko w
sytuacji konfliktu społecznego w Polsce 1981–1983 (Toruń: Wydawnictwo Adam
Marszałek, 2011) 120 (who mentions that the adjective ‘revolutionary’ was to be
part of the name of the new body) and Rakowski, Dzienniki polityczne 1981-1982
127 (who notes that Jaruzelski mentioned the name ‘Military Revolutionary
Council’ on 7 December 1981).
125 Russian full name: ‘Революционный Boeнный Совет’, the supreme military
command body of Soviet Russia, existing between 1918 and 1934.
126 Paczkowski, Revolution, 51.
127 Ibid.
162 Rafał Mańko
128 ‘Protocol no 18’ 443. Cf. Rakowski, Dzienniki polityczne 1981-1983, 125-126.
129 ‘Protocol no 40 of the CPSU CC Politburo Meeting’ (13 December 1981), in
Paczkowski and Byrne (eds), From Solidarity, 473.
130 Wojciech Jaruzelski Stan wojenny, 412.
131 Jaruzelski, Stan wojenny, 276.
.
132 Lech Mazewski, ‘O sposobie prawniczej interpretacji stanu wojennego z 13
grudnia 1981 r. i jego następstw. Nie Carl Schmitt, a Jerzy Stembrowicz’ [On the
Method of Juristic Interpretation of the Martial Law of 13 December 1981 and
Its Consequences: Not Carl Schmitt but Jerzy Stembrowicz] (2013) 21 Przegląd
Sejmowy (4) 103, 108.
Poland’s 1981 martial law 163
government.’133 Paweł Bała, in turn, claimed that Jaruzelski’s initial intent was
to protect the existing order (i.e. to introduce a commissary dictatorship), but
that nonetheless he abolished it and ended up being a sovereign dictator.134
.
Indeed, Bała’s claim resonates with Mazewski’s view that the Martial Law
effectively ended the leading role of the Party, reducing it to an ‘empty shell’.135
Following this line of reasoning, the Martial Law would be a sovereign dicta-
torship which replaced the original state-socialist constitution providing for the
hegemony of the Leninist party, with an interim constitution based on the power
of the formal governmental bodies and backed by the political police, which,
towards the end of the decade, opened the process of transformation towards
capitalism.136 This interpretation finds some corroboration from the construc-
tion of the rule of law, which I discuss in the next section.
.
133 Mazewski, Posttotalitarny, 105.
134 Paweł Bała ‘Stan wojenny 13 grudnia 1981 r. jako zagadnienie prawa ustrojo-
wego. Interpretacja decyzjonistyczna’ [The Martial Law of 13 December 1981 as
a Question of Constitutional Law: A Decisionist Interpretation], (2013) 21 Prze-
gląd Sejmowy, (4) 83, 99.
.
135 Mazewski, Posttotalitarny, 108.
136 In ideological terms, one can speak of a depletion of the Marxist-Leninist ideol-
ogy already progressing from the 1970s, when it came under pressure of con-
sumerism and technocratism, before being replaced with nationalist rhetoric in
the early 1980s. This paved the way towards the neoliberal and nationalist ideo-
logical hegemony after 1989.
.
137 Lech Mazewski, ‘O sposobie’, 108.
138 Poznański, Poland’s Protracted, 144.
139 Ibid. 144–145.
140 Ibid. 148.
164 Rafał Mańko
Conclusions
In 1980, the fundamental pillars of the Leninist model of Poland’s state-
socialist constitution came under direct challenge from the Solidarność
movement, which emerged in the midst of the country’s deepest economic
crisis since World War II. Solidarność increasingly openly challenged the
Leninist party’s leadership position and Poland’s strategic alliance with the
Soviet Union – to the dismay of Poland’s allies in the Warsaw Pact, who
created a commonly perceived impression of their readiness to intervene in
order do defend the authoritarian state-socialist system, just as they had done
in 1953, 1956 and 1968 in other countries of the bloc. The decision to intro-
duce martial law on 12/13 December 1981 was aimed, in particular, at
blocking the further activity of Solidarność, subjecting its chief activists to
administrative detention without trial, outlawing strikes and introducing a
temporary military control of the state apparatus and the economy. On an
ideological level, the Martial Law was yet a further step in the decomposition
of Marxist-Leninist ideological hegemony in Poland. While in the 1970s,
under the rule of Edward Gierek, a rhetoric of technocracy and consumerism
had been introduced,144 the Martial Law signalled a language of ‘national
salvation’ even in the most basic, biological sense. The presence of the mili-
tary in many positions of responsibility, starting from the first secretary and
prime minister, certainly contributed to the ideological shift.
.
141 Mazewski, Posttotalitarny, 115.
142 On the origins of the Court see e.g. Adam Sulikowski, ‘Government of Judges
and Neoliberal Ideology: the Polish Case’ in Rafał Mańko, Cosmin Cercel and
Adam Sulikowski (eds), Law and Critique in Central Europe: Questioning the
Past, Resisting the Present (Oxford: Counterpress, 2016).
143 Poznański, Poland’s Protracted, 85.
144 Cf. Sulikowski, ‘Government of Judges’, 35.
Poland’s 1981 martial law 165
From its inception, the formal legality of the Martial Law has been subject
to debate. The main arguments of its opponents include the lack of a sub-
stantive legal basis for its introduction (lack of security threat), the alleged
retroactivity of the legislative decrees on the emergent legal regime and of the
introduction of martial law, and finally the fact that the decrees were adopted
without first closing the session of the Sejm (the Council of State was allowed
to issue decrees only between sessions). Against the backdrop of this critique,
I have argued that the act of introduction of martial law was beyond doubt
formally legal, keeping in mind that the decision that an exceptional situation
is at stake is, in its very essence, a political decision and is not susceptible to
juridical evaluation.145 Concerning the legislative decrees, issued despite the
formally ongoing session of Parliament, I noted that any prior debate on the
emergency legislation would have undermined the effectiveness of the state of
exception, voiding this constitutional institution of its purpose. In any event,
in January 1982 Parliament ratified the decrees in the form of an act of
parliament.146
Looking at General Jaruzelski’s dictatorship through the lens of Schmitt’s
dichotomy of sovereign vs. commissary dictatorship, one should keep in mind
that the state-socialist order, revolutionary in its origin, preserved, to a certain
extent, the essence of a sovereign dictatorship, even if ossified.147 The gen-
eral’s act of introducing the Martial Law, however, was presented at the time
as a commissary dictatorship, aimed at protecting the status quo threatened
by Solidarność. Nonetheless, objective factors indicate that already in 1982
the General commenced the construction of elements of the liberal rule of
law, as well as implemented far-reaching economic reforms which, on the one
hand, created an effective workers’ self-government in state enterprises but on
the other hand also broadened capitalist elements in the economy. However,
despite a temporary transfer of power to the military, as early as 1985 the
general withdrew from the position of prime minister, and retained the role of
first secretary. The party-state system of dualist governance, based on the
nomenklatura system, was once again in place. Despite the Party’s relatively
weakened position, the general refused to dissolve it, prolonging its existence
up to January 1990, even if as an ‘empty shell’.148 My radically realist
approach to state-socialist constitutionalism, taking into account not only
what was presented as ‘law’ (the lex scripta) but also what de facto operated
qua law (the ius politicum) has been instrumental to conceptualising the real
significance of General Jaruzelski’s act of introducing the Martial Law: on the
level of the lex scripta it was merely commissary, but if we take the
.
145 Mazewski, Problem legalności, 71.
146 Ibid., 57–63.
147 I would like to thank Przemysław Tacik for suggesting this idea to me.
.
148 Mazewski, Posttotalitarny, 108.
166 Rafał Mańko
constitution as a whole, in its substantive and not only formal sense, it had
clear elements of a sovereign dictatorship.
A final question that begs for an answer is the place and role of the working class
in the historical process. After all, in a state-socialist polity the working class
is, in a constitutional sense, the sovereign, even if organised and expressing its
will through the channels of the Party. The emergence of Solidarity as a
working-class movement with a generous social programme and more or less
concealed political ambitions challenged the Party’s role as the porte-parole of
the working class. The direct effects of the Martial Law were the outlawing
of strikes and protest actions, the suspension of Solidarity and the internment
of its chief activists, many of them workers. In that sense, the Polish state of
exception is no exception: it was directed against the working class. On the
other hand, however, reforms introduced under Martial Law created, for the
first time in Polish history, an effective workers’ self-government in state
enterprises (though many were exempt from it), making an unprecedented
move towards the Yugoslav model of socialisation of the economy, rather than
its etatisation.149 But in the long run workers were the losers as it was them
who were asked to pay the bill of transformation to capitalism in 1989.150 The
21 proposals of August 1980 or the 1981 programme of a ‘Self-Governing
Republic’ were deliberately forgotten.151 The Party elites joined the opposi-
tion elites, leaving the working class behind.152 The Martial Law was a success
in preserving the role of the nomenklatura and allowing it survive until more
favourable geopolitical circumstances, when they could engage in the infa-
mous ‘nomenklatura privatisation’.153 It destroyed Solidarity as a workers’
movement which would have most probably fiercely opposed the later neo-
liberal transformation.154 The working class, the de nomine sovereign in the
Polish People’s Republic, was the ultimate loser.155
A state in anomie
An analysis of modern Turkey’s states of
exception
Ceylan Begüm Yıldız
Introduction
[T]he norm functions precisely by way of managing the prospect of its undoing,
an undoing that inheres in its doings.1
least two more basements in Cizre around the same time,5 with at least 130
people losing their lives.6
The story of those who were trapped and died in that basement is just a
drop in the ocean of Turkey’s juridico-political history of deadly exceptional
measures. After the demise of the one-party regime in 1945, Turkey experi-
enced a series of military coups in 1960, 1971 and 1980. In 1982, after the
1980 coup, Turkey’s military regime drafted a new constitution, under the
authority of the ruling military group. The 1980 coup was followed by a dual
regime of state of emergency rule and counter-terror law that dominated
political, as well social and economic, life in the 1990s. Since the summer of
2015, the infamous tight control seen in the 1990s has been extended further
still to include round-the-clock curfews and a nationwide state of emergency.
During the final state of emergency in 2016–2018,7 Turkey went through a
parliamentary regime change after a constitutional referendum. The state-
form change – from a parliamentary system to a strong presidential one –
took place de facto through executive decrees (KHK –Kanun Hükmünde
Kararname) issued during the state of emergency, which were later formalised
via the constitutional referendum of April 2017.8 The new system was pre-
sented by the ruling Justice and Development Party (AKP) as a Turkish-style
presidency.9 While some scholars referred to it as hyper-presidentialism,
emphasising the ‘strong single executive power with very little or no
5 The Human Rights Foundation of Turkey’s Cizre field report located three shel-
ter basements, which had been destroyed by military forces. Although some of the
bodies were identified and buried hastily, either by the families or by local gov-
ernment authorities, the whereabouts of the other bodies is still unknown. The
field report mentions human remains scattered all over the city and witness testi-
monies mention some human remains thrown in the Tigris River. Human Rights
Foundation of Turkey, 76-Day Curfew: Cizre Field Report, 2016, available at
http://en.tihv.org.tr/79-day-curfew-cizre-field-report/, accessed 26 February 2019.
6 Amnesty International reports that the number of people who sought shelter in
various other basements in Cizre amounts to 130. Amnesty International,
Amnesty International Report 2016/17: The state of the world’s human rights
(2017), available at www.amnesty.org/download/Documents/POL1048002017E
NGLISH.PDF, accessed 26 February 2019.
7 A nationwide state of emergency was declared on 21 July 2016 after the failed coup
attempt by the followers of Fetullah Gülen. The AKP government used this
opportunity to eliminate all opposition with mass purges in governmental posts
including civil service and the military. For an overview of events, see (Amnesty
International 2017:. 367–371). For figures of two years of emergency measures, see
‘OHAL sona erdi: lki yıllık sürecin bilançosu’, BBC Türkçe, 19 July 2018, available
at www.bbc.com/turkce/haberler-turkiye-44799489, accessed 26 February 2019.
8 Sinan Erensü and Ayça Alemdaroǧlu, ‘Dialectics of reform and repression: Unpack-
ing Turkey’s authoritarian “turn”’, (2018) 52(1) Review of Middle East Studies 16.
9 For political context on this Turkish style of presidency, see Ersin Kalaycioǧlu,
‘The challenge of à la Turca presidentialism in Turkey’, Global Turkey in Europe,
2014, available at www.iai.it/sites/default/files/gte_c_18.pdf, accessed 23 July 2019.
A state in anomie 169
10 Şule Özsoy Boyunsuz, ‘The AKP’s proposal for a “Turkish type of pre-
sidentialism” in comparative context’, (2016) 17(1) Turkish Studies.
11 Canan Aslan Akman and Pınar Akçalı, ‘Changing the system through instru-
mentalising weak political institutions: The quest for a presidential system in
Turkey in historical and comparative perspective’, (2017) 18(4) Turkish Studies
577.
12 In addition to those cited within the text, there are special issue journals focusing
on the matter of authoritarian turn in Turkey, see: Kerem Öktem and Karabekir
Akkoyunlu (eds.), ‘Exit from Democracy: Illiberal governance in Turkey and
beyond’, (2016) 16(4) Southeast European and Black Sea Studies 469. Cemal
Burak Tansel, ‘Decoding the Repertoires of Authoritarian Neoliberalism in
Turkey’, (2018) 23(2) South European Society and Politics 197. Kumru F. Tokta-
miş, and Isabel David, eds. ‘Critical Crossroads: Erdogan and the transformation
of Turkey’ (2018) 29(3) Mediterranean Quarterly 1.
13 Ziya Öniş, ‘Monopolising the Centre: The AKP and the uncertain path of Turk-
ish democracy’, (2015) 50(2) International Spectator.
14 Kumru F. Toktamiş and Isabel David, ‘Introduction: Democratization betrayed:
Erdogan’s New Turkey’ (2018) 29(3) Mediterranean Quarterly.
15 Özlem Kaygusuz, ‘Authoritarian neoliberalism and regime security in Turkey:
Moving to an ‘exceptional state’ under AKP’, (2018) 23(2) South European
Society and Politics 281.
16 Giorgio Agamben, State of Exception. Kevin Attell transl. (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2005).
170 Ceylan Begüm Yıldız
17 Ibid., 23.
18 Judith Butler and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, Who Sings the Nation-State?
(London, New York and Calcutta: Seagull Books, 2010).
19 Ibid., 3.
A state in anomie 171
defending the country between the years 1918 and 1923.29 It appears that
this decree was enacted in response to the Ottoman war criminals tribunal,
which aimed to prosecute the military elites of the independence war – such
as Enver, Cemal and Talaat Pashas, who later became political leaders of
the Turkish Republic – for offenses against Greeks and Armenians.30 As
Taner Akçam’s detailed account of crimes committed within those years
discloses, ‘Christians were to be eliminated by expulsion or massacre. Non-
Turkish Muslims, such as the Kurds, Arabs, and Balkan migrants (refugees
from Christian persecution), were relocated and dispersed among the Turk-
ish majority to be assimilated into the dominant culture.’31 In other words,
the Izale-i Şekavet (no. 356) and the decree no. 372 pardoned any criminal
acts carried out in supressing Greek, Armenian and Kurdish minorities to
prevent their possible alliance with the occupying forces.32 These two legal
measures cannot be dismissed as exceptional measures taken during excep-
tional times of crisis; rather, they indicate the pattern of exceptional norms
in which modern Turkey’s juridico-political system operates. Even in this
brief history of exceptional measures taken during the foundation of the
Republic of Turkey, it is possible to spot the difference in terms of ‘who was
left in what state’, which serves as a pattern for upcoming states of emer-
gency.33 The answer lies in what type of state of exception was granted to
different subjects; in other words, who was killed and who was granted
amnesty for their killings.
In his inquest on the state of exception, Agamben unearths an interesting
relationship between mourning, feast and anomie.34 He considers mourning
in terms of public mourning, and specifically in the case of a sovereign’s
29 Esen, 146.
30 The offences subject to the war crimes tribunals were the expulsion of Greeks and
Armenian Genocide. The articles 2216–230 of the Treaty of Sévres, which is a
peace treaty signed between the Ottoman state and the Allied forces (the Eur-
opean opponents in the First World War) in 1920 but later on replaced by the
Lausanne Peace Treaty with the foundation of the Turkish Republic in 1923, were
concerned with prosecution of Ottoman war criminals. Taner Akçam, From
Empire to Republic: Turkish Nationalism and The Armenian Genocide (London:
Zeb Books, 2004), 180–207.
31 Taner Akçam, The Young Turks’ Crime Against Humanity: The Armenian Gen-
ocide and Ethnic Cleansing in the Ottoman Empire (Princeton: Princeton Uni-
versity Press, 2012), xv–xvi.
32 The Treaty of Sévres aimed to partition Anatolia to establish Armenian and
Kurdish nation states and included partitioning Thrace to Greeks (ibid.).
33 It is hard to spot such an obvious pattern in the late Ottoman period, which
suggests that the pattern has to do with the foundation of Turkey as a nation
state. For an analysis of exceptional measures taken during the Ottoman period,
see: Noémi Lévy-Aksu, ‘An Ottoman variation on the state of siege: The inven-
tion of the idare-i örfiyye during the first constitutıonal period’, (2016) 54 New
Perspectives on Turkey 1.
34 Agamben, State of Exception, 65–73.
A state in anomie 173
funeral and its potential to create public chaos. He writes: ‘[t]he correspon-
dence between anomie and mourning becomes comprehensible only in the
light of the correspondence between the death of the sovereign and the state
of exception’.35 Agamben considers public mourning a ritualised form of the
state of exception that is declared to prevent chaos. The other point he makes
is related to the periodic feasts ‘that are characterised by unbridled license
and the suspension and overturning of normal legal and social hierarchies
[when] criminal behaviour is considered licit or, in any case, not punishable’.36
Although Agamben’s reading of mourning and feast are quite specific, I
believe his exposure of the relationship between mourning, feast and anomie
enables us to comprehend the workings of two parallel regimes of states of
exception embedded within the foundation of the Republic of Turkey.
At this point I would like to bring a contemporary account of mourning in
relation to a state of exception to the discussion. Just after the 2015 bombings
in Paris, which were followed by a two-year state of emergency,37 Judith
Butler wrote a short commentary unpacking this intrinsic relationship
between public mourning and exception.38 Referencing Gillian Rose, Butler
titles her commentary ‘Mourning Becomes the Law’. Although Butler does
not openly refer to Agamben’s work, she elaborates in a similar vein:
35 Ibid., 68.
36 Ibid., 71.
37 A state of emergency was declared in France following the November 2015
attacks, which expired in November 2017. The state of emergency served as
grounds for legitimising the AKP government’s grip on power through the emer-
gency measures. Similar to the executive power grab of AKP through a refer-
endum, France ended its state of emergency by introducing a counter terrorism
bill, which was criticised for normalising the state of emergency. ‘France declares
end to state of emergency almost two years after Paris terror attacks’, Indepen-
dent, 31 October 2017, available at www.independent.co.uk/news/world/europe/fra
nce-state-of-emergency-end-terror-attacks-paris-isis-terrorism-alerts-warnin
g-risk-reduced-a8029311.html, accessed 26 February 2019.
38 Judith Butler, ‘Mourning becomes the law: Judith Butler from Paris’, Verso, 2015,
available at www.versobooks.com/blogs/2337-mourning-becomes-the-law-judith-
butler-from-paris. The text appears to be taken down from the website, however it
can be reached from: Judith Butler, ‘Mourning becomes the law: Judith Butler
from Paris’, Instituro 25 de Mayo para la Democracia, 2015, available at https://
instituto25m.info/mourning-becomes-the-law-judith-butler-from-paris/, accessed
28 February 2019.
39 Ibid., 2.
174 Ceylan Begüm Yıldız
What Butler suggests is that the state of public mourning had become an
excuse for the state of exception. This contemporary example can help us
relate Agamben’s analysis on mourning and exception to today, and to see
that their relationship is not only a casual one, but rather, they overlap
and blur into one another. In other words, the state of mourning is not
only a part of the apparatus of exception but at times it appears as a form
of a state of exception that paralyses and captures subjects in a constant
state of mourning.
These two parallel states of exception operated within the foundational
years of modern Turkey – one issuing a state of mourning (Takrîr-i Sükûn
Kânunu) and the other a state of feast (Izale-i Şekavet and decree no. 372).
They constitute a frame for what is inside and what is outside of the Turkish
nation state. Here I am referring to the Butlerian concept of ‘frame’ which is
defined as follows: ‘to call the frame into question is to show that the frame
never quite contained the scene it was meant to limn, that something was
already outside, which made the very sense of the inside possible, recogni-
sable’.40 Considering the framing of the Turkish nation state enables us to
approach its inside/outside features, free from the limitations of territorial
nation state borders. The last point is crucial to help us unpack Turkey’s
anomic state characterised by the territorial nation state borders of Turkey
(known as misak-i milli) containing both those left in the state of mourning
and those granted the state of feast (or amnesty). The exceptional measure
of issuing an amnesty for criminal acts only makes sense if there is an
exceptional criminal activity that would not be accepted in normal times on
recognised subjects. Hence, the double form of states of exception, mourn-
ing and feast, sets the frame of the Turkish nation state, which indicates a
group of subjects placed out of the frame regardless of their citizenship
status. However, there is a catch; it is this outside that makes the inside
possible and recognisable.
Regardless of its ethnic diversity, the Republic of Turkey is commonly
referred to as the Turkish state (Türk milleti) rather than the state of Turkey.
This choice of words is not random; it refers back to the nation state building
process in Turkey.41 Since its foundation, all other ethnicities, other than those
recognised non-Muslim minorities, have been forced to unite under one
national identity.42 In other words, the Turkish state is the ‘frame’ of the
as minorities and granted only non-Muslims with minority rights. The rest of the
population is recognised as Turkish by the allied forces. ‘Lausanne Peace Treaty’,
24 July 1923, Republic of Turkey Ministry of Foreign Affairs, available at www.
mfa.gov.tr/lausanne-peace-treaty.en.mfa, accessed 28 February 2019.
43 Butler, Frames of War, 31.
44 Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Daniel Heller-
Roazen transl. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998) 72.
176 Ceylan Begüm Yıldız
45 Amendments to Article 141 and 142 of Turkish Penal Code, 3 December 1951,
No. 5844.
46 OHAL (Olağanüstü Hal Kanunu), 25 October 1983, No. 2935.
47 The state of exception (OHAL) was split from the state of siege by the 1982
Constitution. The Constitution, amended after the Constitutional Referendum of
April 2017, combined the two back again under the responsibilities of the
National Security Council, although the president alone can declare a state of
emergency. As article 119 says: ‘In the event of war, the emergence of a situation
necessitating war, mobilization, an uprising, strong rebellious actions against the
motherland and the Republic, widespread acts of violence of internal or external
origin threatening the indivisibility of the country and the nation, emergence of
widespread acts of violence aimed at the destruction of the Constitutional order
or of fundamental rights and freedoms, serious deterioration of public order
because of acts of violence, occurrence of natural disasters, outbreak of danger-
ous epidemic diseases or emergence of a serious economic crisis; the President of
the Republic may declare state of emergency in one region or nationwide for a
period not exceeding six months’. Amendments to the Constitution of the
Republic of Turkey, 16 April 2017, No. 6771.
A state in anomie 177
48 Provincial Administration Law (İl İdaresi Kanunu), 10 June 1949, no. 5442.
49 Erkan Şenses, ‘OHAL’siz OHAL Sokaǧa Çıkma Yasakları!’ (2016) 145 Güncel
Hukuk Dergisi.
50 Article 11(a) and (c) of Provincial Administration Law.
51 European Commission for Democracy through Law, Opinion on the Legal Fra-
mework Governing Curfews, 2016, available at www.venice.coe.int/webforms/
documents/?pdf=CDL-AD(2016)010-e, accessed 25 November 2019.
52 Ibid., 20.
178 Ceylan Begüm Yıldız
[i]t is no coincidence that the ‘terror’ should coincide with the moment in
which life as such – the nation (which is to say, birth) – became the
principle of sovereignty. The sole form in which life as such can be poli-
ticised is its unconditioned exposure to death – that is, bare life’.54
By taking this note as a point of departure, I suggest that Turkey has been in
a never-ending state of civil war since its foundational war of independence in
1923, which served as a condition for the continuity of the Turkish nation
state and, hence, for its sovereignty.
As argued above, throughout its history the Turkish state has governed the
Kurdish region through exceptional measures while legitimising those mea-
sures through the rhetoric of the ‘war on terror’, nearly a decade prior to its
global use. Those exceptional measures against the Kurdish population were
legitimised with the historic accusation of terrorism, and they enabled the
threshold to be pushed further still and the anomie to be extended even fur-
ther. Today’s post-referendum question of ‘what went wrong’55 concerning
Turkey’s de jure dictatorship has its answers in this gradual expansion of
anomie through the ultra-exceptional measures issued on the Kurdish popu-
lation. During the most violent times of the curfews, this point was raised by
a large group of Turkey-affiliated academics, known by the name Academics
for Peace, who wrote in a statement that Turkey has been systematically kill-
ing its own Kurdish citizens.56 This is civil war and the current situation of de
argued above, this has its roots in the foundational war of the Republic of Turkey
and its nation state framing process.63 The exceptional measures that followed,
and which had been implemented within the Kurdish regions since the founda-
tion of the republic, demonstrate the evolution of the founding war of the
Turkish state into a continuous state of civil war that has been kept as a possi-
bility within the anomic state of Turkey from the start. Thus, the Kurdish
population have always been perceived by the Turkish state as potential terror-
ists, and the Kurdish majority provinces have always been considered the head-
quarters of terrorism to keep stasis a waiting possibility. Indeed, as Agamben
claims, stasis ‘must remain always possible in the city, yet … nonetheless must
not be remembered through trials and resentments’.64
For stasis to remain a possibility in a state, the times of feast and mourning
should be left unpunished. This has been the case in Turkey since the first amnesty
of 1923. The Turkish state neither accepted responsibility for the systematic vio-
lence imposed on the Kurdish region nor punished those responsible for the extra-
judicial killings, which took place during the double regime of OHAL and the
counter-terror law of the 1990s.65 Relatives of those who were forcibly disappeared
during those times, known as the Saturday Mothers (Cumartesi Anneleri), have
been gathering in Istanbul at Galatasaray Square every Saturday since 27 March
1995. The Saturday Mothers not only demonstrate the transitiveness of kinship
and citizenship but also contribute to the argument raised above regarding Turkey’s
anomic state, leaving the Kurdish subjects in a constant state of public mourning.
Finally, the last aspect that is exposed by the round-the clock curfews is the
economy of Turkey’s anomic state, which is yet to be explored in the literature.
Agamben briefly mentions the economic aspect of stasis when he writes; ‘civil
war marks the threshold through which the unpolitical is politicised and the
political is “economised”’.66 The Turkish government issued ‘emergency expro-
priation’ orders in the areas under the curfew. According to Amnesty Interna-
tional’s report on displacements during the curfews, ‘in the city of Cizre, a total
of 22 plots of land were expropriated across three neighbourhoods’,67 and this
number goes up to 60% of land in the historical Sur district of Diyarbakır. The
report concludes that this was a systematic plan to displace its Kurdish
residents.68
At this point, I would like to recall Agamben’s critique of Michel Fou-
cault’s genealogy of biopolitics in which Foucault suggests that the sovereign
power’s interest in the economy of life began with liberalism.69 In Kingdom
and the Glory, Agamben argues that every primary target of the sovereign
power requires calculation, writing: ‘[e]very act of government aims at a pri-
mary target, yet, precisely for this reason, it can lead to “collateral damage”
which can be expected or unexpected in their specifics, but are in any case
taken for granted’.70 Surely, Agamben has a point here, that the Turkish
forces consider the people trapped and killed in the basement as no more
than collateral damage, and their deaths require no further investigation or
punishment. However, I believe the economy of emergency can be considered
in broader terms, either in the Foucauldian sense of homo economicus (bio-
politics in the sense of economy of life) or in terms of neoliberal war econo-
mies.71 Over the last decade, Turkey’s economic growth has been heavily
based on the construction sector.72 In this sense, curfews reveal the economic
aspect of the state of exception; that the destruction of cities and the deaths of
their inhabitants were coordinated in order to facilitate rebuilding – to gen-
erate growth not only through rebuilding infrastructure but also through the
rebuilding, or rather re-branding, of Kurdish cities that are to be consumed
by ‘the other’; such as for tourism.73 In other words, in neoliberal times of
crises, economic projections become the driving force behind the imple-
mentation of states of exception.
Conclusion
Although Agamben exposes the crucial placement of stasis within the modern
juridico-political systems, he provides little explanation as to how the active
state of stasis is calmed or concluded only to be evoked again in the future.
Surely, this is partly due to Agamben’s general argument of exception being
an everyday paradigm of government; hence, stasis never calms down. How-
ever, as the case of Turkey demonstrates, it changes form; and at this point it
is possible to direct a criticism at Agamben’s lack of differentiation between
different forms of states of exception.74 As the case of Turkey exhibits,
although exception is the norm, there are different forms of exception, which
leave targeted subjects in different, and at times opposing, states. Further-
more, target-oriented exceptional measures, such as granting one group an
amnesty while another is left in mourning, are the motor that keeps stasis as a
constant possibility within the state. Hence, in order to keep an active state of
stasis as a possibility, there must be passive form(s) of stasis when the active
state of civil war seems to be concluded. As a way of conclusion, I would like
to recall the state of those trapped in the basement.
On 26 January 2015, one of the trapped people in Cizre lost his life while
waiting for an ambulance to arrive, and while waiting for the European Court
of Human Rights’ (ECtHR) decision on the request for an interlocutory
injunction due to interim measures.75 He was the sixth person to die in that
basement. The next day three MPs began a hunger strike to raise awareness
of those trapped, calling for ambulances not to be stopped at military check-
points.76 This should have created a commotion in parliament, but the hunger
strikers were MPs from the People’s Democratic Party (Halkların Demokra-
tik Partisi – HDP), the Kurdish Party-led leftist coalition party which was
accused of conspiring against the Turkish government. They were quickly
labelled as terrorists by the government,77 and on the third day of their
hunger strike, the Turkish Constitutional Court denied their application for
Introduction
The language of the exception has increasingly been used in academic litera-
ture to denote a wide range of phenomena proliferating globally in the last
decades, particularly in the wake of the global war on terror and the recent
migration ‘crises’. Prisons and refugee camps, extraordinary renditions,
counter-terrorist legislation and the increased focus on border controls are
just some of the examples that are often listed as instances of exception.
Much less attention, however, tends to be paid to the weight that similar cir-
cumstances play at the domestic level and in the putatively liberal-democratic
life of states. The chapter intervenes in this debate by offering a novel analysis
of the case of acute violence and police brutality that occurred in the context
of the 2001 Genoa G8 summit, which for gravity and scope has been descri-
bed as the ‘most serious suspension of democratic rights in a Western
Democracy after WWII’.1 The analysis departs from existent attempts to
investigate the case through the lens of studies of popular protests or brutal
police behaviour. It argues that the framework drawn from Carl Schmitt,
Walter Benjamin and Giorgio Agamben, which defines the exception as an
anomie produced by a specific triangulation of power, law and life, provides
an original and unexplored reading of the case. By applying the framework of
the exception to the case of Genoa, the aim of the enquiry is twofold. First, it
demonstrates that the taxonomy of the exception stretches beyond the
instances commonly found in the literature on the topic and to which the
term is often reduced. Second, it opens up the question as to the function of
exceptional measures within the context of contemporary democracies.
In this regard, the analysis highlights how, across multiple contexts, excep-
tion operates at the intersection and blurring point of the juridical and the
political, right and violence, inside and outside, legal and physical status of
those who are victims of exceptional practices, of citizenship and bare life. In
5 Carl Schmitt, Political Theology, George Schwab transl. (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 1985 [1933]), 5.
6 Carl Schmitt, Political Theology, 7; also in Georg Schwab, The Challenge of the
Exception: An Introduction to the Political Ideas of Carl Schmitt between 1921
and 1936 (Westport: Greenwood Press, 1989).
7 Alessandro Fontana, ‘Du Droit de Résistance au Devoir d’Insurrection’, in Jean-
Claude Zancarini (ed.) Le Droit de Résistance, XIIe-XXe Siècle, 15–33, (Paris:
ENS, 2001), 16.
8 William Rasch, ‘Conflict as a Vocation: Carl Schmitt and the Possibility of Poli-
tics’, (2000) 17(1) Theory, Culture and Society 8.
9 Walter Benjamin, ‘Critique of Violence’ in Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jen-
nings (eds.), Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings. Vol. 1, 1913–1926 (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1996 [1921]).
Beyond ‘the most serious suspension of rights’ 187
for violence in relation to the law. In this regard, the author distinguishes
between forms of institutionalised violence that can either create the law (law-
making) or maintain it (law-preserving) and that are part of the functioning
of the modern state.10 In this classification, he defines the function of the
police in particular as a ‘spectral mixture’ that sits astride the two forms of
institutional (legal) violence and but is emancipated from both: in the author’s
words, ‘this (of the police) is violence for legal ends, but with the simultaneous
authority to decide these ends itself within wide limits (in the right to
decree)’.11 While operating within the mythical function of the law, the police,
as an authority of the modern state, also have the power to decide their own
ends, thus enabling a hybrid and, for Benjamin, ignominious, form of vio-
lence. To continue with the author: ‘the police intervenes “for security rea-
sons” in countless cases where no legal situation exists’,12 thus creating a
mismatch between their own ends and the ends of the general law. For Ben-
jamin, therefore, the figure of the police is chiefly well positioned to perform a
type of violence where no clear legal situation exists, by acting in a factual
legal void where decision-making institutions are able to define their own
ends. The result is a contingent action by the police that can act simulta-
neously within and beyond the law. I maintain that, although not openly
defined as such, the role of the police reproduces a configuration analogous to
an exception by filling a situation of legal anomie with an action that bears
no essential relation to the law. Therefore, it can potentially transgress and
transcend the ordinary legal order in its actual conduct.
In addition, the analysis of Benjamin’s work allows us to shift attention
beyond the moment of the suspension of the law onto the dynamics produced
within the legal vacuum: the factual bracketing of the law – produced by the
police’s deciding upon their own ends – questions the nature of the acts
committed under the anomie, which escape any legal classification. For Ben-
jamin, an authority like the police, or, in fact, following Rasch, any decision-
making agency of the modern state, can enact a form of violence whose aims
are not identical to and, potentially, even disconnected from, those of the
general law. By doing so, they create a potential source of exceptional
Closing the circle of what has been presented above, the action of institutions
like the police can thus be defined as sovereign, since, by acting beyond the
law, they are produced in such a capacity. As Benjamin also specifies,15 this is
more true (and, in fact, for him, more devastating) in regimes like democ-
racies, where the modern conditions of rule of law and separation between
legislative and executive are active, than in cases like an absolute monarchy,
where the two powers are already united in the figure of the king. It is thus
democracies that can bear witness ‘to the greatest conceivable degeneration of
violence.’16
The unfettered power enabled by the situation of legal indefiniteness,
therefore, discloses the arbitrariness with which sovereign power can be exer-
cised: the exception effects the possibility of a sovereign action, which is not
accountable to the regulations, or constraints of the general law. Any ruling
or executive act can be performed without justification of the reasons that
13 Jacques Rancière, ‘Who is the Subject of the Rights of Man?’, (2004) 103(2/3)
The South Atlantic Quarterly 306.
14 Judith Butler, Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence (London:
Verso, 2004), 66 [emphasis added].
15 Benjamin, Critique of Violence, 286.
16 Ibid.
Beyond ‘the most serious suspension of rights’ 189
make the action possible, and that bear nothing essential in their ends and
aims, if not renewing their position of sovereignty. Agamben describes this
dynamic when he notices that
the state of exception is the device that must ultimately articulate and
hold together the two aspects of the juridical-political machine by insti-
tuting a threshold of undecidability between anomie and nomos, between
life and law […]. It is founded on the essential fiction according to which
anomie in the form of auctoritas, living law or force of law, is still related
to the juridical order, and the power to suspend the norm has an
immediate hold on life.18
Besides the legal dimension, the exception enables a direct reach to the lives
of the subjects involved. In particular, the challenge of the exception consists
in opening an area of ‘undecidability’, where a pure decision disconnected
from the regular legal ends (and the violence ensuing from it) may occur. The
divide between law and sovereign decision, between norm and fact in the
19 Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Daniel Heller-
Roazen transl. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998 [1995]).
20 Hannah Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harvest Books & Har-
court, 1985 [1951]).
21 Jacques Rancière, ‘Who is the Subject of the Rights of Man?’.
22 Ibid., 306.
Beyond ‘the most serious suspension of rights’ 191
23 Thanos Zartaloudis, Giorgio Agamben: Power, Law and the Uses of Criticism
(Abingdon, UK; New York: Routledge, 2010), 160.
24 See for instance Mitchell Dean, Governmentality: Power and Rule in Modern
Society (London: Sage, 1999); Vivienne Jabri, Discourses on Violence (Manche-
ster; New York: Manchester University Press, 1996); Andrew Neal, ‘Foucault in
Guantanamo: Towards an Archeology of Exception’, (2006) 37(1) Security Dia-
logue 31, 46; Jef Huysmans, ‘The Jargon of Exception’ 183.
192 Sara Raimondi
brought to the attention of public opinion, media and scholars. The diverse
literature on the topic tends to point out the extraordinary intensity of the
violence deployed in the policing operations surrounding the event. The per-
vasiveness of repressive tactics by police and security forces resulted from a
pre-emptive regime of control which, according to Naomi Klein, was
enforced around the city even a month before the summit took place.25
Nevertheless, the peculiarity of the circumstances witnessed in Genoa was a
use of force beyond the limited situations of protests, which was manifested in
moments exceeding regular policing tasks on the streets.26
The spread layer of abusive facts perpetrated by law enforcement autho-
rities emerges clearly in a study conducted by Michael Boyle27: his analysis of
the experience of groups of activists during the protests shows how Genoa
was characterised by a set of incidents of patrolling all the areas of the event,
culminating in degrading treatment and curtailment of rights against the
subjects involved. I maintain that the events witnessed in Genoa were not
only a case of accidental brutality in enforcing policing duties. Rather, the
exceptionality of facts turned into systematic conduct that can be classified as
an instance of exception according to the criteria highlighted above: there, a
police body acting as sovereign created a legal anomie where the law was de
facto suspended and subjects’ rights were downgraded to the point of dehu-
manisation. These dynamics ascribe a particular interest to the events occur-
red and distinguish them from a simple case of deployment of brutal force by
the police. Before approaching the analysis, it is useful to briefly describe the
episodes in more detail.
Among the widespread examples of ill-treatment and excessive measures
deployed across the whole set of events in Genoa, two specific cases stand out
as relevant for the analysis. On the night of the 21 July 2001, the second day
of the protests, a squad of police national forces attacked the Diaz-Pertini
25 Naomi Klein, ‘Getting Used to Violence: How Years of Police Brutality Culmi-
nated in the Death of the Italian Protester Carlo Giuliani’ in Klein, Fences and
Windows: The Front Lines of the Globalization Debate (New York: Flamingo,
2002), 149.
26 Notably, the protests culminated with the killing of one of the demonstrators (see
Klein, ‘Getting Used to Violence: How Years of Police Brutality Culminated in
the Death of the Italian Protester Carlo Giuliani’, or Rory Carroll, ‘Italian Police
Framed G8 Protesters’, The Guardian, 22 June 2002. For the International reg-
ulation around the use of force by enforcement officers in situations of protest, see
the UN legislation around protest policing; in particular, the UN Code of Con-
duct for Law Enforcement Officials (Art. 3) and the UN Basic Principles on the
Use of Force and Firearms by Law Enforcements Officials (Pt. 4–10, 14; also in
Amnesty International Annual Report, ‘Italy: G8 Genoa Policing Operation of
July 2001. A Summary of Concerns’).
27 Michael Boyle, ‘The Criminalization of Dissent: Protest Violence, Activist Per-
formance, and the Curious Case of the VolxTheaterKarawane in Genoa’, (2011)
55(4) The Drama Review 113, 127.
Beyond ‘the most serious suspension of rights’ 193
High School building in one of the town districts. It had been transformed
into a temporary centre for the Genoa Social Forum28 and the broadcast
organisation Indymedia, both collecting national and non-national demon-
strators, journalists and lawyers involved in the event. The raid by the police,
initially explained as a check against the carrying of weapons and damaging
acts allegedly carried out by the group of 93 activists, turned later into a
prolonged assault, with systematic beatings, ill-treatment and injuring of the
provisional detainees. The subjects’ status within the detention has been
described in the statements of the victims, which denounced the ‘special kind
of discipline’ that the police performed by incarcerating victims in ‘a deten-
tion centre that became a place of dark terror’.29 Beatings were accompanied
by further abuses, mutilations, physical violations and the enforced simulation
of animal behaviours.
A similar situation was later replicated at the police point of the nearby
Bolzaneto facility, which had been reassigned as a detention structure for
protesters before they were moved to formal imprisonment. Here, the same
regime of cruel and inhuman tactics was deployed against the over two
hundred detainees, with repeated beatings, verbal abuse, needs deprivation
and humiliating physical and psychological mistreatment by both law
enforcement officers and medical staff during the days of confinement.
Again in reports: ‘Prisoners described their feeling of being cut off from the
rest of the world, in a place where there were no laws and no rules. Indeed,
the police forced their captives to sign statements waiving all their legal
rights.’30 The downgrading of political and human rights was therefore a
remarkable feature pertaining to the whole experience and imposed by the
officers involved in the event.31
The incommensurability of violence deployed has been significantly cap-
tured by the words of one of the policemen involved, who later defined the
beating at the Diaz as a ‘Mexican butcher’s shop’,32 signalling the inhuman
and degrading character of the abuse. What is relevant for the argument,
however, is primarily the judgment that came from the international commu-
nity, which intervened to define the event as ‘the most serious suspension of
democratic rights in a Western country after the Second World War’, stressing
were able to create a space for an action independent from and unconnected
to the regular functioning of the law. The police thus became the vehicle
through which the exception was realised, acting as a sovereign power with
the ultimate decision-making authority in the situation.
The dual role of the police and the fine line between policing duties and
arbitrariness of behaviour may not only be contingent to the case, but rather
a feature substantially embedded in the figure of the police. As seen in Ben-
jamin, in the function of enforcing public order, police authority is con-
stitutively placed on the threshold between the legitimacy of the action and
the discretionary application of legal measures. Agamben further restates this
point when, in an essay titled ‘Sovereign Police’, he notes that ‘contrary to
public opinion’, in performing their task the police are
38 Giorgio Agamben, Means without Ends: Notes on Politics, Vincenzo Binetti and
Cesare Cesarino transl. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000
[1996]), 103.
196 Sara Raimondi
42 Monica Jansen, ‘Narrare le Forze dell’Ordine dopo Genova 2001’, (2010) 65(3)
Italian Studies 418.
43 Donatella della Porta and Lorenzo Zamponi, ‘Protest and Policing on October
15th, Global Day of Action: The Italian Case’, (2013) 23(1) Policing and Society:
An International Journal of Research and Policy 65, 80.
44 Boyle, ‘The Criminalization of Dissent: Protest Violence, Activist Performance,
and the Curious Case of the VolxTheaterKarawane in Genoa’, 114.
45 Agamben, State of Exception, 4.
46 See for instance Donatella della Porta and Herbert Reiter, La Protesta e il Con-
trollo: Movimenti e Forze dell’Ordinenell’Era della Globalizzazione (Milano:
Altraeconomia/Piacenza: Berti, 2004); Luis Fernandez, Policing Dissent: Social
Control and the Anti-Globalization Movement (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers
University Press, 2008); John Noakes and Patrick Gillham, ‘Aspects of the “New
Penology” in the Police Response to Major Political Protests in the United States,
1999–2000’, in Donatella della Porta, Abby Peterson and Herbert Reiter (eds),
198 Sara Raimondi
camp represents the space where law and fact blur and sovereignty accesses
bare life, then the case of torture and abuses of Genoa provides an example of
the same form of ‘camp’: legal norms are totally abandoned and the situation
is left in the hands of authorities that exercise an unfettered power over sub-
jects’ lives. As expressively explicated by Agamben:
The already known areas where German authorities gathered ‘illegal’ subjects
under the Nazi regime, the prisons for suspects where police deploy counter-
terrorist measures, the structures for immigrants along the borders of Western
countries and, we can now add, the temporary facilities where officers keep
demonstrators before an official trial can all be considered camps: they all
provide the material condition to locate an exception and degrade individuals
to the level of an unqualified existence. Reading the exception as a juridical-
political category realised empirically by the camp helps us connect the case
of Genoa to the comprehensive range of modern exceptions and reconsider
the pervasiveness of the measure in the political life of current modern states:
all cases open a space of juridical anomie wherein any sorts of behaviour,
even violent and inhuman, become possible.
Moreover, with the extension just reached, the case that was presented may
even go further than previous examples: if, so far, the concept has been
ascribed to subjects with uncertain legal status – refugees, immigrants or
individuals placed at the margins of the juridical order – Genoa shows that it
is possible to direct such mechanisms towards the same citizens that the state
is responsible for protecting. The measure of the exception, then, gives con-
sistency to a single comprehensive process: if restricted to well-defined situa-
tions in the past, the exception gradually turns into a targeted measure and,
finally, appears possible in episodes addressed potentially to any subject. In all
cases, a degrading, abusive and dehumanising action is performed, indepen-
dently of the specific circumstances and context of application. The argument
thus achieves a double result: on the one hand it suggests that Genoa is not
an accidental occurrence but partakes to a precise analytical category; on the
other, it tests that practices of exception are more pervasive than their stan-
dard definition and are present within current democracies.
A final clarification may be added: in discussing the exception in today’s
domestic contexts, many authors, and Agamben himself, critically extend the
measure to an encompassing reading of the modern political condition. They
draw from Foucault’s biopolitical approach57 and take life as the core objec-
tive of politics. In these readings, the aim of state power is to achieve a tota-
lising control over its citizens by also disciplining the natural, (apparently)
non-political existence. The practice of the exception is thus seen as over-
whelming, up to the point of interpreting the camp as the ‘fundamental bio-
political paradigm of the West’.58 Moreover, today’s use of Foucauldian
governmentality59 tends to connect the topic to the ‘exceptional’ measures
adopted in discourses of security in the West after 9/11: provisions such as
monitoring communications, borders checks and all the operations enforced
as internal defence are included in the same range of exceptional practices.
The analysis of the case of Genoa using the framework of the state of
exception can be seen as opening up an additional dimension that cuts across
the trends and mainstream approaches identified in the literature. On the one
hand it distances itself from the language of security studies that tend to
mainly apply the analysis of the exception to the societal trends supported by
the discourse of the ‘war on terror’ and the structuring of the social field with
exceptional practices. On the other hand it also moves beyond the more easily
recognisable cases of dehumanisation and ill-treatment. If cases like Guanta-
namo Bay or Abu Ghraib have become emblematic of the application of the
‘no man’s land’ that the exception produces, and of the ‘inclusive exclusion’60
through which bare life is incorporated in the very order and legitimation of
modern politics, Genoa demonstrates that cases of exception are even more
pervasive and hidden in the context of democratic life and can also be
enforced by states against their own citizens. More than as a paradigmatic
example, therefore, the analysis of the case provided here wishes to open up
an additional avenue of enquiry to the approaches usually emphasised in the
literature in relation to the exception. Even more, the case examined here
invites treating the concept of the exception as more blurred and ‘messier’
than many categorisations in the literature would have it. The analysis per-
formed highlights how, across multiple contexts, exceptions require the co-
presence of only apparently opposite terms of analysis: the juridical and the
political; right and violence; the legal status and the physicality of those who
57 Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish (London: Penguin, 1977); Michel Fou-
cault, Society Must be Defended: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975–76
(London: Penguin, 2004).
58 Agamben, Homo Sacer, 181.
59 Jabri, ‘War, Security and the Liberal State’; Neal, ‘Foucault in Guantanamo:
Towards an Archeology of Exception’.
60 Agamben, Homo Sacer, 22.
202 Sara Raimondi
are victims of exceptional practices; citizens and bare life. Beyond the cases
usually analysed, then, the exception can become a privileged point of obser-
vation for a reflective diagnosis of the life of modern states. More than inter-
rogating the changing nature of politics in the age of globalisation that the
literature on exceptionalism often tends to highlight,61 the analysis conducted
here opens up new questions around the function of exceptional measures
within the context of contemporary democracies, their historical continuity
and geographical circulation, and asks what exception reveals about the
complex relationship between the legal, political and social dimension (also)
of domestic state life.
I write this afterword in the middle of the Covid-19 pandemic. We live day
to day in compulsory social isolation. We are citizens and subjects of the
state of emergency and of states of exception. While some have argued
that the pandemic is exaggerated and being deployed for nefarious pur-
poses, the death tolls are not fictional.1 The legal and political possibilities
of the virus, its potential to serve as a fundamental disruption to the
constituted order remain real, but are perhaps overwrought in relation to
other ‘normal’ states of legal exception.2 The chapters of this book are
now more than theoretical, jurisprudential, historical, socio-legal inter-
rogations of the state of exception; they are part of the explanation of our
quotidian reality and an examination of our existential and jurisprudential
state of being.3 The law and politics of the state of exception are no
longer the outliers of our existence.
Of course, as the contributors make clear, governments do not need a
pandemic to institute emergencies or states of exception. Before Covid-19,
Myanmar committed genocide against the Rohingya, whose very juridical
existence they deny.4 China placed tens of thousands of Uighers in re-educa-
tion camps to teach them authentic Chinese values, before, during, and no
1 Lukas van den Berge, ‘Biopolitics and the coronavirus: Foucault, Agamben,
Žižek’, (2020) 49(1) Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 3-6. Available at
SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3566072 SSRN 3566072.
2 Cristiano Paixão and Juliano Zaiden Benvindo, ‘”Constitutional dismember-
ment” and strategic deconstitutionalization in times of crisis: Beyond emergency
powers,” Int’l J. Const. l. Blog, 24 April 2020, available at http://iconnectblog.
com/2020/04/constitutional-dismemberment-and-strategic-deconstitutionaliza-
tion-in-times-of-crisis-betond-emergency-powers/.
3 Simon Western, “Covid-19: An intrusion of the Real. The unconscious unleashes its
truth”, Academia.edu, available at https://birkbeck.academia.edu/SimonWestern.
4 Application of the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime
of Genocide (The Gambia v. Myanmar), Order, 23 January 2020, International
Court of Justice, General List, no. 178.
204 David Fraser
doubt after the coronavirus.5 India attempted to reconfigure its laws to exclude
citizenship for many Muslims.6 Dingong Duterte in the Philippines cured himself
of being gay by being surrounded by beautiful women, urges regulatory simplifi-
cation to aid his economic supporters and allies, and gives official approval to the
killing of drug dealers as enemies of the state.7 In Brazil, Bolsonaro destroys indi-
genous populations in the name of economic progress and allows the coronavirus
free reign in the favelas.8 In the United States, Trump used the invasion of “bad
hombres” from the south to take military funding to build his wall.9 He asserted
ordinary executive powers to exclude travellers from Muslim countries.10 Detention
camps for migrants from Australia to the Balkans to Italy are a commonplace of
normal governmental practice.11 The camp is no longer, if it ever was, a place of
exception or emergency. Attacks on Roma in every country in the European
Union, where their status as gens du voyage poses a threat to sovereignty of the
nation state and the pan-European polity at one and the same time, continue
unabated.12
The pandemic simply gives an excuse, and a broader power and authority to
governments who wish to use it, to institute long-term anti-democratic reforms
that will persist after the exception. This is the fear, and the reality, of Orban’s
Hungary, but that country is perhaps only the exception to the exception.13
History teaches us that the processes of states of emergency and exception are
constituted by complex matrices of power and resistance. The most effective
tools of ideology, politics, and law have always involved the invocation of the
need to protect, to immunize, the body politic from a foreign threat. The pan-
demic has merely allowed the invocation of these signifiers in a blatant and overt
way, bringing to light already present prejudices and hatreds. The figurative virus
of history has become the literal virus of the present.
For Donald Trump, Covid-19 is a new “Yellow Peril,” a Chinese virus.14
Exceptional measures inside and at the border continue in a slightly mag-
nified, and more legally plausible, form. In India, anti-Muslim violence,
already widespread under Modi’s proto-fascist attempts to change the
citizenship laws, has morphed into the creation of a Muslim virus, spread
perniciously by the Other among true (Hindu) Indians.15 In Israel, ultra-
Orthodox Jews protest against the secular authorities of the Jewish state
and their attempt to identify and isolate them for what they experience, or
classify for their own political ends, as discriminatory, anti-religious pur-
poses.16 In the United States, Canada, and throughout Europe there has
been a rise in anti-Asian violence against the Chinese virus and its embo-
died enemy carriers.17 At the same time, the Jew as virus, the signifying
apparatus of law and politics so popular among the Nazis, has simply
been reconstituted by today’s antisemites.18 Historical “fact” gives way to
a reconstituted historical present as new/old tropes and signifiers are
deployed by the opponents of the “deep state” and “fake news.” Anti-
lockdown demonstrators invoke Holocaust imagery, introduce tropes sig-
nifying and constructing modern liberal government as a Nazi regime in
disguise, controlled by the Jews Soros and the Rothschilds. The idea of a
Nazi Jewish regime is deployed with no apparent ironic, and certainly no
historical, self-understanding. The protesters create a self-signification as
the real victims of Hiterlite/Jewish oppression.19 They demand a return to
normal constitutional order, an order which for many requires the decon-
struction of the state itself. Those on the far right have found a danger to
true democracy in the invocation of the state of exception by authorities
they consider antithetical to “authentic” values. As Elie Mystal has con-
cluded, this is a new embodied form of constitutional unpatriotism.
14 “‘Not racist at all’: Donald Trump defends calling coronavirus the ‘Chinese
virus’”, Guardian, 18 March 2020.
15 “Coronavirus conspiracy theories targeting Muslims spread in India”, Guardian,
13 April 2020.
16 Loewenthal, Adv. et al v. Prime Minister, HCJ 2435/20.
17 “Targeting Asians and Asian Americans will make it harder to stop Covid-19”,
Washington Post, 2 April 2020.
18 Marcy Oster, “Anti-lockdown protests spawn more anti-Semitic conspiracy the-
ories, Holocaust imagery”, The Forward, 20 April 2020; Lev Topor, “Covid-19:
Blaming the Jews for the Plague, again”, Fathom, March 2020.
19 Frank Hornstein, “Holocaust trivialization at protests isn’t just offensive. It
threatens democracy”, The Forward, 20 April 2020; “Dutch-Muslim politician
tweets Jewish yellow star to protest coronavirus surveillance plan”, Jewish Tele-
graphic Agency, 20 April 2020.
206 David Fraser
Solidarity is for them a demand from the deep state that must be resisted
in the name of liberty.20 The battles of resistance to the power of the state
of exception can and do take on forms sometimes as dangerous as the
emergency itself.
In the anti-lockdown protests against public health measures we can
uncover the real nature of the exception and its juridical apparatus. When
those on the left voice their fears of a surreptitious attack on civil liberties and
on broad understandings of the appropriate place for social solidarity in
modern democracies, when Orban and Modi use the virus to deepen their
power and authorise violence against the enemy, and far-right protesters
invoke a Jewish plot to control true citizens and profit from the cure for the
“fake” or manufactured pandemic, the law and politics of emergencies come
into the light in a much clearer fashion. The state of exception is never simply
about the “state” in the exception, but more centrally focuses on deeper
iterations of the nation and its others. Everywhere the idea of the nation, of
an authentic identity combatting pretenders, including the state, the “deep
state,” and real Other, becomes the true ideological, political, and legal point
of contention in the different, but always recognizable, states of exception.
Before Covid-19, as Fusco (chapter 1) and Cercel (chapter 2) highlight,
France lived under a state of emergency for significant periods of Fifth
Republic democracy. From “Muslim terrorism” to the gilets jaunes and pen-
sion reform protests, the constitution and a supplementary legislative frame-
work establish the legal context for the exception that is not one.21 Before the
pandemic, in eastern and central Europe, conservative, populist, nationalist
governments turned back democratic reforms and reconfigured institutional
arrangements in the name of national identity and sovereignty, with gutless
non-reactions from their neighbours and the European Union.22 All that was
and is needed in each of these cases, and others studied by the contributors to
this volume, is an identified enemy and law.
As Fusco (chapter 1) argues, the creation of the enemy, of the threat to
the state, or the nation, of the war that demands and indeed creates the
exception, is largely an ideological device. Rhetoric and propaganda,
assertions by executive and legislative branches of a public emergency,
demanding exceptional measures, are left unchallenged or merely con-
firmed by the judicial branch of liberal democracies. The “historical”
State.”26 Law and the Nazi state were in a constant position of self-contented
juxtaposition and mutual reflection throughout the 1933–1945 period. Any
argument that this was not the case must confront the historical and con-
stitutional realities set out and analyzed by Lavis. As Kivotidis (chapter 6)
also makes clear, the insights of Schmitt and Agamben into the core law/
exception nexus are not marginal to our endeavors. We have known, or
should have known, for some time that “law is politics.” To dismiss Schmitt is
to dismiss the central reality of law as a political phenomenon in either its
“normal” or its “exceptional” manifestations. There is never, nor can there be,
any kind of fundamental normative or taxonomical change from the Schmit-
tian consolidating conflict between friend and foe within a state of exception.
The politics of the exception are always political, and the law of the exception
is always law.
Kai Ambos in his recent work has established and carefully analysed the
close and intractable links and continuities between Nazi criminal law, the
immediate pre-Nazi period, the 1933–1945 “caesura,” and the post-Nazi
period.27 The time has come to move beyond any debate that Nazi law was
not law, or that the National Socialist period was marked by some kind of
pure exceptionality devoid of law. An appropriately nuanced “rediscovery” of
Schmitt is a step in the right direction. The normativity and legality of the
exception are core elements of any confrontation with the emergencies that
constitute our lived realities. This does not mean, as the writers in this volume
make clear in a variety of historical and geo-political contexts, that we must
resign ourselves politically to a Schmittian right-wing political dictatorship.
The dynamics and outcomes of power/resistance are not written in jur-
isprudential or political stone. We simply need to become comfortable with a
legal philosophical place where the actual nature of the form and content of
Nazi law, the position of exceptionality within its normative structures, and
the ideas of a truly constitutive “exceptionalism” are placed at the centre of
our historical and philosophical inquiries. When, as a jurisprudential matter,
the Nazi state is understood as a legal state, the exception as a lawful con-
stitutional moment, true critical engagement can begin. When we arrive at
this constitutional and constitutive realization, Trump, Orban, Modi, Bolso-
naro, Duterte, et al., for all the necessary contextual differences, occupy a
similar and comparable jurisprudential space.
The political and philosophical critique of our current legal/political
regimes and the place of the “exception” within that social and juridical order
are at the heart of all the contributions to this volume. From French con-
stitutional normativity to the historical events and jurisprudential
state”—the identity of the enemy matters little. Every state, every nation
concretized inside or outside, or even in opposition to, formal nation state
structures has complex or crude mechanisms for identifying the internal or
external enemy and for dealing with the threat through the state of the
exception. The taxonomies deployed are always, despite local, national parti-
cularities and specificities, reducible to a juridified enemy who must be elimi-
nated. As Raimondi (chapter 9) sets out, liberal democracy, the rule of law,
the Rechtsstaat, are no shield. In Italy, this enemy, foreign and domestic, in
the form of G8 protesters, can be identified, singled out, “exceptionalized,”
and as the Homo sacer, beaten and killed by the forces of a legitimate demo-
cratic European legality. The new European order, the Europe of human
rights, a Europe allegedly constructed on the premise of a post-1933–1945
legalized “never again,” confirms the state’s right to kill within some regime
of undefined, but apparently murderous, legal proportionality.28 There is, as
there has always been, a legal frame in which the state of exception permits
the execution of its will through the execution of its enemy.
Johansen (chapter 4) offers a somewhat more optimistic (but still always
realistic) argument that the condition of law/emergency is perhaps not per-
manent. He seeks to place law in a minor key, reduced in power and sig-
nificance, by social and political actions of reorganization and re-ordering.
The dynamics and possibilities of resistance to emergency power can be
identified. The process of a new, diminished legality and the questions of
social practices as moments of resistance to law, of the reconfiguration of a
knowledge/power juridical and political dynamic, of norm and exception, are
however still decided within a legalized frame that appears to be dominated
by law and lawful exceptions. The identification of spaces available for a
Johansenian resistance appears from this perspective to be one of practising
deconstructive politics, of identifying the necessary lacuna, the signifying
break in the chain of social meaning through political endeavor. The decon-
struction occurs in a moment or in a place, in a spatio-temporal site, a point
of weakness into which a new politics might make some form of disruptive
incursion. The problem, the legalized exception as resistance to counter-
power, may or indeed must always nonetheless remain. Writing law under
some form of political erasure still requires both the original writing of law
and the irreducibility of the law that remains, even when deconstructed. The
dynamic relationship between that which is written (law) and that which is
erased (law) must still, as Johansen recognizes, as do the other contributors to
the volume, operate in the new relationship and dynamic of the written that is
resistance. Law has yet to wither away or to be replaced in any meaningful
fashion by some still ill-defined and barely recognizable set of social practices
that would eliminate, or even significantly reduce, the omnipresence of a
28 Stephen Skinner, Lethal Force: The Right to Life and the ECHR (Oxford: Hart,
2019), 92, 139.
Afterword 211
Lacan, J. 52–53, 143 nation state 12, 71–72, 170, 174, 176,
language (philosophy) 46, 55, 59, 63, 178–80, 204, 210
67, 70, 74, 82, 89; legal language National Socialism (ideology) 36, 92,
25, 29, 74; legal performance 31; 97–99, 111–12, 127, 137, 209,
performativity 10, 18, 30–31; speech Nationalism 2, 4, 35, 37
act 30–31; system of signification 6, Nazi law 11, 92–96, 101, 103, 105, 109,
45, 53 see also Austin, J. L. 115–16, 209; Nazi legal system 93, 94,
legal fiction 10, 18, 21–22, 26–28, 207 111; Nazi legality 93–94, 108, 110;
legal form 4, 5, 11, 37, 38, 40–43, 50, Nuremberg laws 69
80–81, 88, 90, 96? 129, 144, 156, 175; Nazi state 92, 95, 97–98, 100, 104,
legal relations 42–43, 74, 79–80, 86; 107–109, 112, 114, 119, 122–26, 130,
legal superstructure 43 see also 133, 135–37, 207–208; Enabling Act
Pashukanis, E. 97, 100–101, 122–25, 133; Führer 43,
legal theory 28, 40, 46–47, 81, 115, 207, 209 94–97, 101, 103, 106, 108, 110–115,
legal certainty 2–3; legal proportionality 126, 135–36; führerprinzip 94, 101,
56, 210 108, 111–15, 126, 136; führerstaat 110;
legitimation 123, 135, 201, 207 Nazi ideology 107, 110, 112, 115;
Lenin, I. V. 76, 87, 142 National-Socialist Party 102, 123, 125,
Leninism 141–145, 148–49, 159, 137; Reichstag Fire Decree 96, 98,
161–64, 209 100, 123, 133
Łȩtowska, E. 164 Neocleous, M. 5, 138
lex scripta 142–43, 145, 156, 163, neoliberalism 81, 166, 181,
liberal democracy 1, 4, 12, 34, 135, 198, neutralisation 41, 82
210; liberal legality 2, 22, 53 Nietzsche, F. 2, 66
liberalism 2, 36, 41, 148, 181 nomenklatura 143, 146, 165–66
Liebknecht, K. 129 Northern Ireland 44
Loick, D. 77–78, 88, 90 Notrecht 139 see also Hegel, G. W. F.
Loraux, N. 179
Löwith, K. 62 Orbán, V. 3, 204; 206, 208
Lukács, G. 51
Luxemburg, R. 129 Paczkowski, A. 151, 161
Pandemic 203–206
Maine, H. 27–28 Pashukanis, E. 11, 42–44, 47,
Mandelstam, O. 9–10 73–88, 91
Marion, E. 104–105 Pasquino, P. 21
martial courts 171 Paul, St. 83
martial law 4, 34, 38, 97–98, 110, Philippines 204
140–43, 149–66, 209 Pilate 59
Marx, K. 76, 142 plebiscite 97, 122, 126, 135
Marxism 41–43, 49, 51, 74–76, 78, 81, Poland 10, 12, 140–66; Commissioner for
84–85, 149, 159, 161, 164 Citizens’ Rights 164; Gdańsk 146,
.
Mazewski, L. 143 160; Institute of National Memory
Mazower, M. 105 147; Military Council of National
McLoughlin, D. 102 Salvation 151, 159–60; Ministry of the
minor law 73, 76 Interior 144, 153; Patriotic Movement
minorities 172, 174 of National Regeneration 152; Polish
modernity 11, 36, 46, 48, 52, 55, 59–67, People’s Republic 156–59; Presidium
71–72, 93, 188 of the National Coordination
Modi, N. 205 Commission of Solidarity 148;
mourning 172–75, 180, 182–83 Round Table agreements 157,
Myanmar 203 162; Sejm 149, 165; Solidarity
Mystal, E. 205 157–62, 166
216 Index
Third Reich 8, 11, 69–70, 93–98, violence 3, 11, 38, 41–44, 46–47, 49–50,
100–109, 114–15 see also Nazi state 57, 60, 64, 74–78, 82–83, 86–91, 100,
threshold 6, 49, 52, 57–58, 93, 102, 170, 103, 106, 180, 184, 186–89, 191–93,
176–80, 189–90, 195, 200 see also zone 195–98, 201, 205–206; divine violence
of indistinction 42, 49, 83; mythical violence 42, 83;
torture 74, 194, 197, 200 pure violence 49, 187–89; see also
totalitarianism 7, 47, 70, 113, 175, 198 Benjamin W.
transitional justice 37, 157, 209 Volk 69, 101, 106, 110–111
Trump, D. 3, 35, 204–205, 208
tumultus 22–23, 49 Warsaw Pact 141, 148–49, 158, 162, 164
Turkey 10, 12, 167–83, 209; Cizre Warsaw 35
167–68, 180, 182–83, Gezi protests 169, Watkin, W. 57
OHAL (Olağanüstü Hal Kanunu) Weimar Constitution 38, 43, 92, 96–99,
176–77, 180; People’s Democratic Party 101–102, 105, 119, 122–26, 129–32;
182, Provincial Administration Law Reich chancellor 96–97, 125, Reich
177; Turkish Penal Code 176–77; president 96–97,
Turkish Republic 170, 172 welfare state 119, 126–28, 130–31
white mythology 44 see also Derrida J.
United Nations 157, Whyte, J. 86
United States of America 35, 113, Willikens, W. 111
204–205 Wittgenstein, L. 56
USSR 144, 149, 207 workers’ rights 131–32
validity 31, 39–40, 44, 50, 52, 57, 75, 95, zone of indistinction 45, 47–48, 57–58, 60,
109, 123–24, 151, 195 72, 93–95, 108, 111, 114–16, 169, 191