Dummett 1975
Dummett 1975
INTUITIONISTIC LOGIC
Michael DUMMETT
University of Oxford, U.K .
sible to contrive such a justification which took meaning for granted, and
represented the question as turning on knowledge or certainty. We are
certain of the truth of a statement when we have conclusive grounds for it
and are certain that the grounds which we have are valid grounds for it
and are conclusive. If classical arguments for mathematical statements
are called in question, this cannot possibly be because it is thought that we
are, in general, unable to tell with certainty whether an argument is
classically valid, unless it is also intuitionistically valid: rather, it must be
that what is being put in doubt is whether arguments which are valid by
clas~icalbut not by intuitionistic criteria are absolutely valid, that is,
whether they really conclusively establish their conclusions as true. Even
if it were held that classical arguments, while not in general absolutely
valid, nevertheless always conferred a high probability on their conclu-
sions, it would be wrong to characterise the motive for employing only
intuitionistic arguments as lying in a desire to attain knowledge in place of
mere probable opinion in mathematics, since the very thesis that the use
of classical arguments did not lead to knowledge would represent the
crucial departure from the classical conception, beside which the question
of whether or not one continued to make use of classical arguments as
mere probabilistic reasoning is comparatively insignificant. (In any case,
within standard intuitionistic mathematics, there is no reason whatever
why the existence of a classical proof of it should render a statement
probable, since if, e.g., it is a statement of analysis, its being a classical
theorem does not prevent it from being intuitionistically disprovable.)
So far as I am able to see, there are just two lines of argument for
repudiating classical reasoning in mathematics in favour of intuitionistic
reasoning. The first runs along the following lines. The meaning of a
mathematical statement determines and is exhaustively determined by its
use. The meaning of such a statement cannot be, or contain as an
ingredient, anything which is not manifest in the use made of it, lying
solely in the mind of the individual who apprehends that meaning: if two
individuals agree completely about the use to be made of the statement,
then they agree about its meaning. The reason is that the meaning of a
statement consists solely in its role as an instrument of communication
between individuals, just as the powers of a chesspiece consist solely in
it5 role in the game according to the rules. An individual cannot
communicate what he cannot be observed to communicate: if one
individual associated with a mathematical symbol or formula some mental
content, where the association did not lie in the use he made of the symbol
T H E PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF lNTUITIONlSTIC LOGIC 7
or formula, then he could not convey that content by means of the symbol
or formula, for his audience would be unaware of the association and
would have no means of becoming aware of it.
The argument may be expressed in terms of the knowledge of meaning,
i,e. of understanding. A model of meaning is a model of understanding,
i.e. a representation of what it is that is known when an individual knowc
the meaning. Now knowledge of the meaning of a particular symbol or
expression is frequently verbalisable knowledge, that is, knowledge
which consists in the ability to state the rules in accordance with which
the expression or symbol is used or the way in which it may be replaced
by an equivalent expression or sequence of symbols. But to suppose that,
in general, a knowledge of meaning consisted in verbalisable knowledge
would involve an infinite regress: if a grasp of the meaning of an
expression consisted, in general, in the ability to state its meaning, then it
would be impossible for anyone to learn a language who was not already
equipped with a fairly extensive language. Hence that knowledge which,
in general, constitutes the understanding of the language of mathematics
must be implicit knowledge. Implicit knowledge cannot, however, mean-
ingfully be ascribed to someone unless it is possible to say in what the
manifestation of that knowledge consists: there must be an observable
difference between the behaviour or capacities of someone who is said to
have that knowledge and someone who is said to lack it. Hence it follows,
once more, that a grasp of the meaning of a mathematical statement m u 4 ,
in general, consist of a capacity to use that statement in a certain way, or
to respond in a certain way to its use by others.
Another approach is via the idea of learning mathematics. When we
learn a mathematical notation, or mathematical expressions, or, more
generally, the language of a mathematical theory, what we learn to do ic to
make use of the statements of that language: we learn when they may be
established by computation, and how to carry out the relevant computa-
tions, we learn from what they may be inferred and what may be inferred
from them, that is, what role they play in mathematical proofs and how
they can be applied in extra-mathematical contexts, and perhaps we learn
also what plausible arguments can render them probable. These things are
all that we are shown when we are learning the meanings of the
expressions of the language of the mathematical theory in qiiestion,
because they are all that we can be shown: and, likewise, our proficiency
in making the correct use of the statements and expressions of the
language is all that others have from which to judge whether or not we
8 M I<')+ A EL DUMME T I
significance: but their significance lies wholly in the role which they play
within the mathematical theories to which they belong, and which are
themselves significant precisely because they enable us to establish the
correctness of finitistic statements. Boole likewise distinguished, amongst
the formulas of his logical calculus, those which were interpretable from
those which were uninterpretable: a deduction might lead from some
interpretable formulae as premisses, via uninterpretable formulae as
intermediate steps, to a conclusion which was once more interpretable.
The immediately obvious difficulty about such a manner of construing a
mathematical, or any other, theory is to know how it can be justified. How
can we be sure that the statements or formulae to which we ascribe a
content, and which are derived by such a means, are true? The difference
between Hilbert and Boole, in this respect, was that Hilbert took the
demand for justification seriously, and saw the business of answering it as
the prime task for his philosophy of mathematics, while Boole simply
ignored the question. Of course, the most obvious way to find a
justification is to extend the interpretation to all the statements or
formulae with which we are concerned, and, in the case of Boole’s
calculus, this is very readily done, and indeed yields a great simplification
of the calculus. Even in Hilbert’s case, the consistency proof, once found,
does yield an interpretation of the infinitistic statements, though one
which is relative to the particular proof in which they occur, not one
uniform for all contexts. Without such a justification, the operation of the
mechanism of the theory or the language remains quite opaque to us; and
it is because the holist is oblivious of the demand for justification, or of
the unease which the lack of one causes us, that I said that he is to be
compared to Boole rather than to Hilbert. In his case, the question would
become: With what right do we feel an assurance that the observation
statements deduced with the help of the complex theories, mathematical,
scientific and otherwise, embedded in the interior of the total linguistic
structure, are true. when these observation statements are interpreted in
terms of their stimulus meanings? To this the holist attempts no answer,
save a generalised appeal to induction: these theories have ‘worked’ in the
past, in the sense of having for the most part yielded true observation
statements, and so we have confidence that they will continue to work in
the future.
The path of thought which leads from the thesis that use exhaustively
determines meaning to an acceptance of intuitionistic logic as the correct
THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF INTUITIONISTIC LOGIC 11
existing practice when it does not display the required harmony. Exactly
what the harmony is which is demanded depends upon the theory of
meaning accepted for the language, that is, the general model of that in
which the content of an individual sentence consists; that is why I
rendered the above remarks vague by the insertion of phrases like ‘in
some sense’. It will always be legitimate to demand, of any expression or
form of sentence belonging to the language, that its addition to the
language should yield a conservative extension; but, in order to make the
notion of a conservative extension precise, we need to appeal to some
concept such as that of truth or that of being assertible or capable in
principle of being established, or the like; and just which concept is to be
selected, and how it is to be explained, will depend upon the theory of
meaning that is adopted.
A theory of meaning, at least of the kind with which we are mostly
familiar, seizes upon some one general feature of sentences (at least of
assertoric sentences, which is all we need be concerned with when
considering the language of mathematics) as central: the notion of the
content of an individual sentence is then to be explained in terms of this
central feature. The selection of some one such feature of sentences as
central to the theory of meaning is what is registered by philosophical
dicta of the form, ‘Meaning is ...’- e.g. ‘The meaning of a sentence is the
method of its verification’, ‘The meaning of a sentence is determined by
its truth-conditions’, etc. (The slogan ‘Meaning is use’ is, however, of a
different character: the ‘use’ of a sentence is not, in this sense, a single
feature; the slogan simply restricts the kind of feature that may legiti-
mately be appealed to as constituting or determining meaning.) The
justification for thus selecting some one single feature of sentences as
central-as being that in which their individual meanings consist-is that it
is hoped that every other feature of the use of sentences can be derived,
in a uniform manner, from this central one. If, e.g., the notion of truth is
taken as central to the theory of meaning, then the meanings of individual
expressions will consist in the manner in which they contribute to
determining the truth-conditions of sentences in which they occur; but
this conception of meaning will be justified only if it is possible, for an
arbitrary assertoric sentence whose truth-conditions are taken as known,
to describe, in terms of the notion of truth, our actual practice in the use
of such a sentence; that is, to give a general characterisation of the
linguistic practice of making assertions, of the conditions under which
14 MICHAEL DUMMETT
they are made and the responses which they elicit. Obviously, we are very
far from being able to construct such a general theory of the use of
sentences, of the practice of speaking a language; equally obviously, it is
likely that, if we ever do attain such an account, it will involve a
considerable modification of the ideal pattern under which the account
will take a quite general form, irrespective of the individual content of the
sentence as given in terms of whatever is taken as the central notion of
the theory of meaning. But it is only to the extent that we shall eventually
be able to approximate to such a pattern that it is possible to give
substance to the claim that it is in terms of some one feature, such as truth
or verification, that the individual meanings of sentences and of their
component expressions are to be given.
It is the multiplicity of the different features of the use of sentences,
and the consequent legitimacy of the demand, given a molecular view of
language, for harmony between them, that makes it possible to criticise
existing practice, to call in question uses that are actually made of
sentences of the language. The thesis with which we started, that use
exhaustively determines meaning, does not, therefore, conflict with a
revisionary attitude to some aspect of language: what it does d o is to
restrict the selection of the feature of sentences which is to be treated as
central to the theory of meaning. On a platonistic interpretation of a
mathematical theory, the central notion is that of truth: a grasp of the
meaning of a sentence of the language of the theory consists in a
knowledge of what it is for that sentence to be true. Since, in general, the
sentences of the language will not be ones whose truth-value we are
capable of effectively deciding, the condition for the truth of such a
sentence will be one which we are not, in general, capable of recognising
as obtaining whenever it obtains, or of getting ourselves into a position in
which we can so recognise it. Nevertheless, on the theory of meaning
which underlies platonism, an individual’s grasp of the meaning of such a
sentence consists in his knowledge of what the condition is which has to
obtain for the sentence to be true, even though the condition is one which
he cannot, in general, recognise as obtaining when it does obtain.
Such a conception violates the principle that use exhaustively deter-
mines meaning; or, at least, if it does not, a strong case can be put up that
it does, and it is this case which constitutes the first type of ground which
appears to exist for repudiating classical in favour of intuitionistic logic
for mathematics. For, if the knowledge that constitutes a grasp of the
meaning of a sentence has to be capable of being manifested in actual
THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF INTUITIONISTIC LOGIC 15
tic one, on the basis of an argument of the first type, or a platonistic one,
on the basis of some rebuttal of it; and then one or other picture of the
metaphysical character of mathematical reality will force itself on us. If
we have decided upon a model of the meanings of mathematical state-
ments according to which we have to repudiate a notion of truth
considered as determinately attaching, or failing to attach, to such
statements independently of whether we can now, or ever will be able to,
prove or disprove them, then we shall be unable to use the picture of
mathematical reality as external to us and waiting to be discovered.
Instead, we shall inevitably adopt the picture of that reality as being the
product of our thought, or, at least, as coming into existence only as it is
thought. Conversely, if we admit a notion of truth as attaching objectively
to our mathematical statements independently of our knowledge, then,
likewise, the picture of mathematical reality as existing, like the galaxies,
independently of our observation of it will force itself on us in an equally
irresistible manner. But, when we approach the matter in this way, there
is no puzzle over the interpretation of these metaphors: psychologically
inescapable as they may be, their non-metaphorical content will consist
entirely in the two contrasting models of the meanings of mathematical
statements, and the issue between them will become simply the issue as to
which of these two models is correct. If, however, a view as to the
ontological status of mathematical objects is to be treated as a premiss for
deciding between the two models of meaning, then the metaphors cannot
without circularity be explained solely by reference to those models; and
it is obscure how else they are to be explained.
These considerations appear, at first sight, to be reinforced by reflection
upon Frege’s dictum, ‘Only in the context of a sentence does a name stand
for anything’. We cannot refer to an object save in the course of saying
something about it. Hence, any thesis concerning the ontological status of
objects of a given kind must be, at the same time, a thesis about what
makes a statement involving reference to such objects true, in other
words, a thesis about what properties an object of that kind can have.
Thus, to say that fictional characters are the creations of the imagination
is to say that a statement about a fictional character can be true only if it is
imagined as being true, that a fictional character can have only those
properties which it is part of the story that he has; to say that something is
an object of sense-that for it esse est percipi-is to say that it has only
those properties it is perceived as having: in both cases, the ontological
thesis is a ground for rejecting the law of excluding middle as applied to
22 MICHAEL DUMMETT
possible: whether one may consistently hold that natural numbers are the
creations of human thought, but yet believe that there is a notion of truth
under which each number-theoretic statement is determinately either
true or false, and that it is in terms of our grasp of their truth-conditions
that our understanding of number-theoretic statements is to be explained.
If such a combination is possible, then, it appears, there can be n o route
from the ontological thesis that mathematical objects are the creations of
our thought to the model of the meanings of mathematical statements
which underlies the adoption of an intuitionistic logic.
This is not the only question before us: for, even if these two views
cannot be consistently combined, it would not follow that the ontological
thesis could serve as a premiss for the constructivist view of the meanings
of mathematical statements; our difficulty was to understand how the
ontological thesis could have any substance if it were not merely a picture
encapsulating that conception of meaning. The answer is surely this: that,
while it is surely correct that a thesis about the ontological status of
objects of a given kind, e.g. natural numbers, must be understood as a
thesis about that in which the truth of certain statements about those
objects consists, it need not be taken as, in the first place, a thesis about
the entire class of such statements; it may, instead, be understood as a
thesis only about some restricted subclass of such statements, those
which are basic to the very possibility of making reference to those
objects. Thus, for example, the thesis that natural numbers are creations
of human thought may be taken as a thesis about the sort of thing which
makes a numerical equation or inequality true, or, more generally, a
statement formed from such equations by the sentential operators and
bounded quantification. To say that the only notion of truth we can have
for number-theoretic statements generally is that which equates truth
with our capacity to prove a statement is to prejudge the issue about the
correct model of meaning for such statements, and therefore cannot serve
as a premiss for the constructivist view of meaning. But to say that, for
decidable number-theoretic statements, truth consists in provability, is
not in itself to prejudge the question in what the truth of undecidable
statements, involving unbounded quantification, consists: and hence the
possibility is open that a view about the one might serve as a premiss for a
view about the other. Our problem is to discover whether it can do so in
fact: whether there is any legitimate route from the thesis that natural
numbers are creations of human thought, construed as a thesis about the
24 MICHAEL DUMMETT
(P 1 A ---f 3 n @,A) ?
Its double negation
(Y) A + 1 1 3 n (t,A)
we have
law
( K) (n = max (m,k ) & ( k m A )& ( k k ( A-+ B ) ) )+ (k,,B).
We should thus so have to construe the notion of proof that a proof of a
statement is taken as simultaneously constituting a proof of anything that
has already been recognised as a consequence of that statement. We can,
no doubt, escape having to say that it is simultaneously a proof of
whatever, in a platonistic sense, as a matter of fact is an intuitionistic
consequence of the statement: but when are we to be said to have
recognised that one statement is a consequence of another? If a proof of a
universally quantified statement is simultaneously a proof of all its
instances, it is difficult to see how we can avoid conceding that a
demonstration of the validity of a schema of first-order predicate logic is
simultaneously a demonstration of the truth of all its instances, or an
acceptance of the induction schema simultaneously an acceptance of all
cases of induction. The resulting notion of proof would be far removed
indeed from actual mathematical experience, and could not be explained
as no more than an idealisation of it.
The trouble with all this is that, as a representation of actual mathemati-
cal experience, we are operating with too simplified a notion of proof. The
axiom (7)is acceptable in the sense that, prescinding from the occasional
accident, once a theorem has been proved, it always remains uuuilahle to
be subsequently appealed to: but the idea that, having acknowledged the
two premisses of a modus ponens, we have thereby recognised the truth
of the conclusion, is plausible only in a case in which we are simultane-
ously bearing in mind the truth of the two premisses. To have once proved
a statement is not thereafter t o be continuously aware of its truth: if it
were, then we should indeed always know the logical consequences of
everything which we know, and should have no need of proof.
Acceptance of axiom (p)leads to the conclusion that we shall eventually
prove every logical consequence of everything we prove. This, as a
representation of the intuitionist notion of proof, is an improvement upon
Beth trees, as normally presented: for these are set up in such a way that, at
any stage (node), every logical consequence of statements true at that stage
is already true; the Beth trees are adapted only to situations, such as those
involving free choice sequences, where new information is coming in that
is not derived from the information we have at earlier stages. But the idea
that we shall eventually establish every logical consequence of everything
28 MICHAEL DUMMETT
(P) Vx A (x 1 + 3 n ( F A ( m I),
which appears, on the present interpretation of ‘I,,’, to say that we shall
explicitly prove every instance of every universally quantified statement
which we prove; so perhaps the error lies in the law ( A ) itself. A law such
as ( A ) is ordinarily justified by saying that, given a proof of Vx A(x), we
can, for each m, effectively find a proof of A ( m ) . If this is to remain a
sufficient justification of ( p ) , then ( p , ) must be construed as saying that,
given a proof of Vx A ( x ) , we can effectively find a proof that A ( m ) will
be proved at some stage. How can we do this, for given m ? Obviously, by
proving A ( m ) and noting the stage at which we do so. This means, then,
that the existentially quantified statement
(v) 3 n (k,,A(m))
is to be so understood that its assertion does not amount to a claim that we
shall, as a matter of fact, prove A ( m ) at some stage n, but only that we are
capable of bringing it about that A ( m ) is proved at some stage. Our
difficulties thus appear to have arisen from understanding the existential
quantifier in ( p ) in an excessively classical or realistic manner, namely as
THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF INTUITIONISTIC LOGIC 29
terms which are intelligible to a Platonist and do not beg any questions,
because they employ only notions which are not in dispute.
The obvious way to do this is to say that a mathematical statement is
intuitionistically true if there exists an (intuitionistic) proof of it, where
the existence of a proof does not consist in its platonic existence in a
realm outside space and time, but in our actual possession of it. Such a
notion of truth, obvious as it is, already departs at once from that supplied
by the analogue of the Tarski-type truth-definition, since the predicate ‘is
true’, thus explained, is significantly tensed: a statement not now true may
later become true. For this reason, when ‘true’ is so construed, the
schema (T) is incorrect: for the negation of the right-hand side of any
instance will be a mathematical statement, while the negation of the
left-hand side will be a non-mathematical statement, to the effect that we
do not as yet possess a proof of a certain mathematical statement, and
hence the two sides cannot be equivalent. We might, indeed, seek to
restore the equivalence by replacing ‘is true’ on the left-hand side by ‘is or
will be true’: but this would lead us back into the difficulties we
encountered with the theory of the creative subject, and I shall not further
explore it.
What does require exploration is the notion of proof being appealed to,
and that also of the existence of a proof. It has often, and, I think,
correctly been held that the notion of proof needs to be specialised if it is
to supply a non-circular account of the meanings of the intuitionistic
logical constants. It is possible to see this by considering disjunction and
existential quantification. The standard explanation of disjunction is that
a construction is a proof of A v B just in case it is a proof either of A or
of B. Despite this, it is not normally considered legitimate to assert a
disjunction, say in the course of a proof, only when we actually have a
proof of one or other disjunct. For instance, it would be quite in order to
assert that
1 is either prime or composite
without being able to say which alternative held good, and to derive some
theorem by means of an argument by cases. What makes this legitimate,
on the standard intuitionist view, is that we have a method which is in
principle effective for deciding which of the two alternatives is correct: if
we were to take the trouble to apply this method, the appeal to an
32 MICHAEI- DUMMETI
sign of disjunction and the existential quantifier were the only logical
constants whose explanation appeared to call for a distinction between
canonical proofs and demonstrations, the distinction might be avoided
altogether by modifying their explanations, to allow that a proof of a
disjunction consisted in any construction of which we could recognise
that it would effectively yield a proof of one or other disjunct, and
similarly for existential quantification: we should then be able to say that
a statement could be asserted only when it was (known to be) true.
However, the distinction is unavoidable if the explanations of universal
quantification, implication and negation are to escape circularity. The
standard explanation of implication is that a proof of A -+ B is a
construction of which we can recognise that, applied to any proof of A, it
would yield a proof of B. It is plain that the notion of proof being used
here cannot be one which admits unrestricted use of modus ponens: for, if
it did, the explanation would be quite empty. We could admit anything we
liked as constituting a proof of A -+ B, and it would remain the case that,
given such a proof, we had an effective method of converting any proof of
A into a proof of B, namely by adding the proof of A -+ B and
performing a single inference by modus ponens. Obviously, this is not
what is intended: what is intended is that the proof of A -+ B should
supply a means of converting a proof of A into a proof of B without
appeal to modus ponens, at least, without appeal to any modus ponens
containing A + B as a premiss. The kind of proof in terms of which the
explanation of implication is being given is, therefore, one of a restricted
kind. On the assumption that we have, or can effectively obtain, a proof of
A + B of this restricted kind, an inference from A -+ B by modus
ponens is justified, because it is in principle unnecessary. The same must,
by parity of reasoning, hold good for any other application of modus
ponens in the main (though not in any subordinate) deduction of any
proof. Thus, if the intuitionistic explanation of implication is to escape,
not merely circularity, but total vacuousness, there must be a restricted
type of proof-canonical proof-in terms of which the explanation is
given, and which does not admit modus ponens save in subordinate
deductions. Arguments employing modus ponens will be perfectly valid
and compelling, but they will, again, not be proofs in this restricted sense:
they will be demonstrations, related to canonical proofs as supplying a
means effective in principle for finding canonical proofs. Exactly simi!ar
remarks apply to universal quantification vis-8-vis universal instantiation
34 MICIiAHL DUMMETT
(A & Q > B,
-+
(A 1Q) + C,
but in which the subjunctive antecedent A neither implies nor presup-
poses either Q or its negation; in such a case, we cannot assert either
A + B or A -+ C. The other kind of counter-example is that in which we
do not consider the disjuncts to be determined by anything at all: no
supplementation of the antecedent would be sufficient to decide between
them in advance. If an electron were to pass through that screen, it would
have passed through one aperture or the other: but there is nothing at all
which will determine in advance through which it would pass. Similar
cases will arise, for those who believe in free will in the traditional sense,
in respect of human actions.
If we were to carry out the decision procedure for determining the
primality or otherwise of some specific large number N,we should either
obtain the result that N is prime or obtain the result that N is composite.
38 M I c ' H A E L D U MMET7