Nico Krisch (Eds) - Entangled Legalities Beyond The State
Nico Krisch (Eds) - Entangled Legalities Beyond The State
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
GLOBAL LAW SERIES
Edited by
NICO KRISCH
Graduate Institute of International and Development Studies, Geneva
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781108843065
DOI: 10.1017/9781108914642
© Cambridge University Press 2022
This work is in copyright. It is subject to statutory exceptions
and to the provisions of relevant licensing agreements;
with the exception of the Creative Commons version the link for which is provided below,
no reproduction of any part of this work may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
An online version of this work is published at doi.org/10.1017/9781108914642 under a Creative Commons
Open Access license CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 which permits re-use, distribution and reproduction in any medium
for non-commercial purposes providing appropriate credit to the original work is given. You may not distribute
derivative works without permission. To view a copy of this license, visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/
by-nc-nd/4.0.
All versions of this work may contain content reproduced under license from third parties. Permission to
reproduce this third-party content must be obtained from these third-parties directly.
When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781108914642.
First published 2022
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Krisch, Nico, editor.
Title: Entangled legalities beyond the state / edited by Nico Krisch, Graduate Institute of International and
Development Studies, Geneva.
Description: Cambridge, United Kingdom ; New York, NY : Cambridge University Press, 2022. |
Series: Global law series | Includes papers “presented . . . the Hong Kong annual conference
of the International Society of Public Law, and also at a conference on ‘Multiple Legalities:
Conflict and Entanglement in the Global Legal Order’ which I convened with
Hannah Birkenkӧtter from Humboldt University as part of the OSAIC group”–ECIP preface. |
Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2021019498 (print) | LCCN 2021019499 (ebook) |
ISBN 9781108843065 (hardback) | ISBN 9781108823791 (paperback) |
ISBN 9781108914642 (epub)
Subjects: LCSH: Legal polycentricity–Congresses. | Law and globalization–Congresses. |
International and municipal law–Congresses. | Conflict of laws–Congresses.
Classification: LCC K236 .E58 2022 (print) | LCC K236 (ebook) | DDC 340.9–dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2021019498
LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2021019499
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
vi
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
vii
Index 478
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
CONTRIBUTORS
viii
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
ix
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
x
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
PREFACE
Entanglement may appear a strange term for an inquiry in law. Many will
think it does not have anything to do with law at all, but rather with
threads, nets or wire. Some may think it has to do with relationships –
especially complicated ones – but not the kinds of relationships that help
us to make sense of legal structures. Both views have a point, and
paradoxically pursuing legal entanglements is attractive in part because
they have a point. What we try to do with this volume is to take us away
from the familiar, to break with some traditional frames, and thus to pave
the way for thinking afresh about law, especially law beyond the confines
of the state.
In this endeavour, ‘entanglement’ helps not only to unsettle but also to
reconstruct. By pointing us towards relationships, it helps to shift our
gaze to the ways in which legal norms and legal systems are not self-
standing entities but are instead tied up in relationships with others
(other norms and legal systems) that often are crucial to understanding
the identity of each part as well as the character of the whole. In many
contexts of legal practice, litigants draw on norms from a wide variety of
origins – domestic and international, sub-state and transnational, public
and private – to persuade courts of their cases. Law, whether in finance,
environment, human rights, trade, sports or corporate accountability, is
not one law but is pieced together out of a great many layers by skilled
attorneys, civil society actors, business representatives and government
lawyers. In the end, law is the product of the ways in which the relation-
ships of its different parts are construed.
Using the notion of entanglement is a way of highlighting the inter-
woven character of much of law, and it urges us to understand better on
which terms such an entanglement takes place. This is what the present
volume hopes to achieve. Bringing together a stellar group of scholars –
from law, political science, sociology, anthropology and history – it
shows us how actors entangle and disentangle law in a variety of con-
texts, and how this forces us to change the way we should think about law
xi
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
xii
and legal order more broadly. It takes into view a highly diverse set of
issues – ranging from family law disputes in Bangladesh to the Chinese
Belt and Road Initiative and the making of global standards by the
Financial Stability Board – and it uses insights about legal practices in
these contexts to advance our theorization of law. In all of this, law
appears neither as one nor as many, but as somewhere in-between.
Entanglement points to this in-between character and highlights the
challenge we face when trying to square such practices into the frame
of unitary, well-ordered legal systems we are accustomed to as a result of
the legal theories of the twentieth century.
The volume has been a long time in the making. The idea of entangle-
ments was born in the discussions Francesco Corradini, Lucy Lu Reimers
and I had on our ‘Interface Law’ project – a project that was itself part of
a broader, interdisciplinary research group in which we were trying to
understand ‘Overlapping Spheres of Authority and Interface Conflicts in
the Global Order’ (OSAIC, because everything these days needs an
acronym). In our project, we were trying to reconstruct the norms actors
use to structure the relations between different legal orders, but we soon
realized that we could not capture much of what we were seeing with the
typical vocabulary of conflict and reception norms. We thus needed to
look elsewhere and began to draw more widely from legal anthropology
and sociology, from historical studies and from legal theories long out-
side the mainstream. Students of legal pluralism, of postmodern inter-
legalities or of historical legal entanglements had begun to describe
aspects of the phenomenon we were interested in, and we built on their
findings in order to generate a broader account of how law was shaped by
interactions between norms from different contexts beyond the typical
frame of legal systems.
In the spring of 2018, we gathered a group of colleagues in Geneva for
a workshop exploring further the entanglements we began to see. Many
of these colleagues, and a few new members of the group, have taken our
discussions further and contributed to this volume. We presented some
of our work collectively at the Hong Kong annual conference of the
International Society of Public Law, and also at a conference on ‘Multiple
Legalities: Conflict and Entanglement in the Global Legal Order’, which
I convened with Hannah Birkenkötter from Humboldt University of
Berlin as part of the OSAIC group. I am grateful to the participants in
these different events for their intense engagement with our ideas
and papers.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
xiii
Entangled Legalities is the product of many minds and hands – most
obviously the minds and hands of the contributors to whom I owe much
gratitude. My special thanks go to our Interface Law team – Lucy and
Francesco from the beginning, and later also Tomáš Morochovič, who
not only moved us forward in substance but also handled many of the
practical aspects of editing the volume with great professionalism and
efficiency. The Graduate Institute of International and Development
Studies, and especially Camila Morais Silva, provided excellent practical
and logistical support throughout. And all this was rendered possible
by generous funding from the Swiss National Science Foundation
through project grant 100011E-170996, as well as the Deutsche
Forschungsgemeinschaft which supported the overall OSAIC research
group with project grant no. 277531170.
We hope the volume will inspire many to new explorations of law –
and help them to look at the law in a different way. We believe that many
of our insights are true not only for today’s globalized world but reflect
relatively common features of law throughout history – perhaps with the
(limited) exception of the twentieth-century modern state. That law is
characterized by multiplicity, and by interconnections between its mul-
tiple parts, is neither good nor bad; it is just normal. Focusing on this
normality, and tracing how law is created out of entanglement, should
open up many fruitful avenues for future work. With this volume we
have tried to make a beginning.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
ABBREVIATIONS
xiv
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
xv
CSR corporate social responsibility
DPRK Democratic People’s Republic of Korea
DSU Dispute Settlement Understanding
EC European Communities
ECHR European Convention on Human Rights
ECtHR European Court of Human Rights
EIA Environmental Impact Assessment
EO Executive Order
ESIA environmental and social impact assessment
ETP Eastern Tropical Pacific
FATF Financial Action Task Force
FET fair and equitable treatment
FIFA Fédération Internationale de Football Association
FIFA RSTP FIFA Regulations on the Status and Transfer of Players
FNLMA First Nations Land Management Act
FPIC free, prior and informed consent
FRF Romanian Football Federation
FSAP Financial Sector Assessment Program
FSB Financial Stability Board
FSF Financial Stability Forum
FTA Free Trade Agreement
G7 Group of Seven
G10 Group of Ten
G20 Group of Twenty
G2G government-to-government
GATT General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade
GMOs genetically modified organisms
HRC UN Human Rights Committee
IACrtHR Inter-American Court of Human Rights
IAEA the International Atomic Energy Agency
IAIS International Association of Insurance Supervisors
IASC International Accounting Standards Committee
IBS international banking standard
ICCPR International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights
ICJ International Court of Justice
ICSID International Centre for Settlement of Investment Disputes
IFC International Finance Corporation
IIA international investment agreement
ILA International Law Association
ILC International Law Commission
ILO International Labour Organization
IMF International Monetary Fund
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
xvi
IOSCO International Organization of Securities Commission
ISDS investor–state dispute settlement
ISEAL International Social and Environmental Accreditation and
Labelling
ISO International Organization for Standardization
JCPOA the Joint Comprehensive Plan of Action
MEAs multilateral environmental agreements
MFLO Muslim Family Law Ordinance
MOFCOM China’s Ministry of Commerce
MOU memorandum of understanding
NAFTA North American Free Trade Agreement
NCPs National Contact Points
NGO non-governmental organization
OBOR One Belt One Road
OECD Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development
OFAC Office of Foreign Assets Control
OHCHR Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human
Rights
OIC The Agreement on Promotion, Protection and Guarantee of
Agreement Investments among member States of the Organization of the
Islamic Conference
PCA Permanent Court of Arbitration
PoE panel of experts
PPMs processing and production methods
PRC People’s Republic of China
RSPO Roundtable for Sustainable Palm Oil
SASF semi-autonomous social field
SFT Swiss Federal Tribunal
SGBs sports governing bodies
SPS Agreement on Sanitary and Phytosanitary Measures
Agreement
SR Special Representative
SWIFT Society for Worldwide Interbank Financial Telecommunication
TBT Agreement on Technical Barriers to Trade
Agreement
TEDs turtle excluder devices
TPP Trans-Pacific Partnership
TTIP Transatlantic Trade and Investment Partnership
UDHR Universal Declaration of Human Rights
UEFA Union Européenne de Football Association
UEFA FFP UEFA Club Licensing and Financial Fair Play Regulations
UN United Nations
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
xvii
UNCED United Nations Conference on Environment and Development
UNCITRAL United Nations Commission on International Trade Law
UNCTAD United Nations Conference on Trade and Development
UNDRIP United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples
UNFCCC United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change
UNGPs United Nations Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights
UNSC United Nations Security Council
UNSCR United Nations Security Council Resolution
VCLT Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties
WADA World Anti-Doping Agency
WADC World Anti-Doping Code
WTO World Trade Organization
WTO DSB WTO Dispute Settlement Body
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
1
1.1 Introduction
Law tends to make its appearance in the singular. We think of a legal
order as a relatively integrated whole, as a system in which the different
parts play a defined role and display a certain amount of coherence, if
only because there are rules that regulate what happens when different
norms conflict and because there are judges to decide unclear cases. We
also expect law to be coherent and orderly as a matter of normative
judgement – under the rule of law, we need to be able to know what the
law requires from us. The unitary legal system then appears as both an
analytical frame and an evolutionary achievement.
Yet in many contexts, law does not actually appear in the singular but
in the plural. Norms from different origins become relevant in the same
situation, and they often come with divergent prescriptions or at least
orientations. Their relations are not predefined but remain to be deter-
mined through the social interplay of actors. State law interacts with
local, Indigenous and religious law; norms from international and trans-
national law are used alongside domestic law and national regulation.
These norms are not limited to neatly separated spheres but instead often
address, directly or indirectly, the same set of actors and the same kind of
behaviour. Yet they do not form part of a common legal order – they are
entangled rather than integrated.
Such entanglement is the focus of the present volume. We regard
entanglement as a common state of affairs in law – and likely a more
common one than legal ‘systems’ with aspirations of hierarchy, order and
coherence, as depicted in the standard image of law in the context of the
modern, Western nation state. Legal entanglement was typical before the
modern state arose, has been present within many states throughout, and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
has arguably increased with the rise in importance of transnational and
international rules.
In this volume, we focus primarily on contemporary forms of
entanglement, with a particular eye on encounters ‘beyond’ the state,
both in the relation of state law with non-state law (especially of an
Indigenous or religious kind) as well as the relation of different legalities
in the transnational sphere. We inquire into the contexts in which
entanglement occurs: the different bodies of norms, institutions and
actors involved, as well as the dynamics they create. We also inquire into
the legal forms it generates: the ways in which actors construe the
relations between different norms, which are increasingly central to
defining the shape of the overall order. And we are interested in the
consequences entanglement has for conceptions of legal order more
broadly – how do we need to adjust our understanding of ‘law’ if it is
entangled rather than systemic?
This framing chapter sets the scene for the volume by defining key
concepts, developing the theoretical frame and setting out the questions
and problématiques animating the volume while highlighting the contri-
butions of the different chapters. It begins by clarifying the concept of
‘entanglement’ in law (Section 1.2) and then explores some historical
instantiations to generate a backdrop against which to theorize its con-
temporary forms (Section 1.3). The chapter then develops expectations as
to where we can observe entanglement and what the actors and dynamics
behind it are (Section 1.4). It outlines a typology of the legal forms in
which we can expect entanglement to be reflected (Section 1.5), and then
lays out some implications of entangled legalities for our conceptualiza-
tion of legal order (Section 1.6).
1
See Wikipedia entry on ‘quantum entanglement’, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Quantum_
entanglement.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
by the insight that the histories of European and extra-European societies
cannot be understood without taking into account the continuous con-
nections between them.2 Unlike comparative approaches which inquire
into similarities and differences, entangled histories are interested ‘in
processes of mutual influencing, in reciprocal or asymmetric perceptions,
in entangled processes of constituting one another’,3 and especially in
‘the constitutive role which the interaction between Europe and the
extra-European world has played for the specificities of modernity in
the different societies’.4
Similarly, the idea of histoire croisée focuses on intercrossings between
different objects of inquiry – intercrossings that potentially transform
these objects themselves.5 In cultural studies more broadly (and well
beyond the particular focus on postcoloniality), the notion of cultural
entanglements has been used to highlight ‘the aspects of agency, proces-
suality and the creation of something new which is more than just an
addition of its origins’ from different contexts, and the importance of
liminal spaces in which different cultures come into particularly close
encounters.6
In the study of law, proponents of legal pluralism have done most to
trace ‘entanglements’ between different legal orders, even if they have not
always called them thus.7 The first phase of legal pluralism often focused
on the simultaneous, parallel existence of different legal systems in the
same social field, often with an eye on the relationship of formal and
informal law, state law and custom, particularly in traditional societies.
This gave way over time to a broader appreciation of similar phenomena
in other contexts, including states in the Global North. Later pluralist
scholarship also moved away from an image of separate legalities and
2
S. Randeria, ‘Geteilte Geschichte und verwobene Moderne’, in N. Jegelka, H. Leitgeb, and
J. Rüsen (eds), Zukunftsentwürfe: Ideen für eine Kultur der Veränderung (Campus Verlag,
1999), pp. 87–96.
3
J. Kocka, ‘Comparison and Beyond’ (2003) 42 History and Theory 39–44, at 42.
4
S. Conrad and S. Randeria, ‘Einleitung: Geteilte Geschichten - Europa in einer postkolo-
nialen Welt’, in S. Conrad, S. Randeria and R. Roemhild (eds), Jenseits des Eurozentrismus
(Campus Verlag, 2013), pp. 32–70, at p. 40.
5
M. Werner and B. Zimmermann, ‘Beyond Comparison: Histoire Croisée and the Challenge
of Reflexivity’ (2006) 45 History and Theory 30–50, at 38.
6
P. W. Stockhammer, ‘Conceptualizing Cultural Hybridization in Archaeology’, in P. W.
Stockhammer (ed.), Conceptualizing Cultural Hybridization: A Transdisciplinary
Approach (Springer, 2011), pp. 43–58, at pp. 47–8.
7
K. Günther and S. Randeria, Recht, Kultur und Gesellschaft im Prozess der Globalisierung
(Programmbeirat der Werner Reimers Konferenzen, 2001), p. 85.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
came to stress the ‘complex and interactive relationship’ between
different forms of ordering and their intertwined nature.8 Some authors
have found intersecting legalities, or ‘interlegality’, to be the condition of
postmodern law.9
In recent years, in a ‘third phase’ of legal pluralism, these approaches
have found broader application to law under conditions of globalization,
taking into more direct view relations between domestic, international
and transnational law.10 The connections between these three phases, or
approaches, are not always clear-cut, and in Chapter 17 Brian
Z. Tamanaha highlights the discontinuities as well as the problems in
borrowing from the two former to inform the latter approach. Legal
historians, too, have begun to inquire more closely into legal entangle-
ments. Inspired by frames from the study of history, the emphasis of this
historical work is on openness, entanglement being seen as characterized
by ‘complex intertwined networks, with no beginning and no end, and a
difficulty to fix the own point of departure’.11
This passage suggests, as in much of legal pluralist writing and works
on interlegality, that the entanglements that come into focus here are
primarily about mutual de facto influences and the travelling content of
legal norms. Legal transplants and the substantive reception of legal
forms and institutions are recurring themes,12 in a somewhat similar
way to archaeologists studying the material entanglement of objects that
are created in imitation of, and borrowing from, foreign examples.13 The
perspective tends to be that of an outside observer tracing such influ-
ences, even if the participants in legal discourse (or the different legal
8
S. E. Merry, ‘Legal Pluralism’ (1988) 22 Law & Society Review 869–96, at 873; J. Griffiths,
‘What Is Legal Pluralism?’ (1986) 18 The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law
1–55, at 17–18.
9
B. de Sousa Santos, ‘Law: A Map of Misreading – Toward a Postmodern Conception of
Law’ (1987) 14 Journal of Law and Society 1279–302; B. de Sousa Santos, Toward a New
Legal Common Sense: Law, Globalization, and Emancipation (Cambridge University
Press, 2002).
10
Günther and Randeria, Recht, Kultur und Gesellschaft im Prozess der Globalisierung; R.
Michaels, ‘Global Legal Pluralism’ (2009) 5 Annual Review of Law & Social Science 1–35;
P. Zumbansen, ‘Transnational Legal Pluralism’ (2010) 1 Transnational Legal Theory
141–89; P. S. Berman, Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law Beyond Borders
(Cambridge University Press, 2012).
11
T. Duve, ‘Entanglements in Legal History: Introductory Remarks’, in T. Duve (ed.),
Entanglements in Legal History: Conceptual Approaches (Max Planck Institute for
European Legal History, 2014), pp. 3–25, at p. 8.
12
Duve (ed.), Entanglements in Legal History.
13
Stockhammer, ‘Conceptualizing Cultural Hybridization in Archaeology’, p. 50.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
discourses intersecting here) continue to emphasize traditional frames.14
Many pluralists have long lamented the fact that legal discourse ignored
such growing mutual influences and remained wedded to ideas of closed,
unitary legal orders.15
Yet also from the perspective of the actors involved in them, legal
orders have always had aspects defining their relations with other bodies
of norms. Conflict-of-law norms for foreign law and norms about the
reception of international law in domestic legal orders are the most
prominent examples.16 If anything, globalization has enhanced the pres-
sure on defining and developing these interface norms further – the
global universe of norms is ever more populated, with overlapping norms
and authority spheres in many, if not most, issue areas. Participants in
legal discourses can choose to ignore this multiplicity and merely focus
on their own legal order, but when other norms have strong social
backing ignoring them can be costly in terms of legitimacy and often
also compliance. In a context of multiplicity, defining relations becomes
central for actors to stake out their positions.17
As a result, bodies of norms become ‘entangled’ not only as a matter of
fact, but also in discursive construction. It is such connections which we,
unlike much of the classical pluralist literature, take into focus in this
volume. Actors – litigants, judges, dispute settlers, observers, addressees –
make claims about the relation of norms from different backgrounds,
and they thus define and redefine the relative weights and interconnec-
tion between the norms at play. They also define the extent to which
norms are perceived to form part of broader assemblages – in the
relatively stable and firm mode of modern state legal orders, or in
more porous ways, with a more open interplay of norms and character-
ized more through their linkages across boundaries than any strong
form of belonging to an order as such.18 The production of tertiary
14
Günther and Randeria, Recht, Kultur und Gesellschaft im Prozess der Globalisierung.
15
See, e.g., G. Teubner, ‘The King’s Many Bodies: The Self-Deconstruction of Law’s
Hierarchy’ (1997) 31 Law & Society Review 763–88.
16
See Chapter 16 by Michaels.
17
See also M. Delmas-Marty, Ordering Pluralism: A Conceptual Framework for
Understanding the Transnational Legal World (Bloomsbury, 2009); N. Krisch, Beyond
Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law (Oxford University Press,
2010), chapter 8.
18
The notion of ‘bodies of norms’ is meant to capture this possibility of looser assemblages,
the boundaries and strength of which are themselves produced through discourses in and
around law. It is also meant to capture that norms tend to come in clusters or patterns,
especially when they are institutionally produced.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
norms – norms about the recognition of one legal order by another, as in
Ralf Michaels’ chapter – is one example here. The different contributions
to the volume trace the ways in which relations between norms from
different origins are construed in social practice – thus taking a primarily
external perspective, though interested in the forms participants in legal
discourses have at their disposal.
When we focus on legal entanglement here, we mean such discursive
entanglement: the universe of statements that link different bodies of
norms with one another. This is similar to the ‘relational’ (as opposed to
‘material’) entanglement in cultural studies: an entanglement in which
the difference in origin remains visible even if the object is embedded in a
different practice.19 In a context of growing multiplicity, this entangle-
ment becomes stronger – where various norms are seen to apply to the
same situation, actors will often be forced to clarify the relation they see
between them, and we move towards a greater ‘centrality of the
margins’.20 As actors engage in this practice, they also redefine the overall
order as such: they construe the weight of different norms in that order,
the relative strength of their claims over behaviour or institutions. And
through this, they remake the law. If we understand law as ultimately
socially constructed,21 a shift in the ways in which actors relate different
parts of the legal order to one another reshapes the law itself.
Where entanglement is particularly pronounced, we might even end
up in a situation in which – just as in quantum physics – ‘the state of each
[body of norms] cannot be described independently of the state of the
other(s)’;22 a situation of enmeshment, or even the creation of a new,
hybrid form. But entanglement, in the way we use it here, remains
distinct from full integration into a new form. Where norms are widely
accepted as part of a common legal order, they are integrated rather than
entangled. Likewise, when one body of norms is not linked with another
by relevant actors, they remain separate. Entanglement comes in different
degrees, but it sits between, and is distinct from, both separation and
integration.
19
Stockhammer, ‘Conceptualizing Cultural Hybridization in Archaeology’, p. 50.
20
N. Walker, ‘Beyond Boundary Disputes and Basic Grids: Mapping the Global Disorder of
Normative Orders’ (2008) 6 International Journal of Constitutional Law 373–96.
21
See, e.g., B. Z. Tamanaha, A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society (Oxford University
Press, 2001).
22
See Wikipedia entry on ‘quantum entanglement’, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
Quantum_entanglement.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
1.3 Entanglement before and around the State
Entanglement was, by all accounts, a defining feature of many legal
orders before the emergence and consolidation of the modern state.
Even Roman law, often associated with system and coherence, is an
impressive example of multiple fora, rules and practices, between which
litigants and dispute settlers navigated their way. In Chapter 13, Caroline
Humfress gives a vivid account of this complex interplay, tracing how
actors reasoned out the application of different norms and, especially at
the margins of the late Roman Empire, generated connected, but not
integrated, legal orderings of their own.
Yet perhaps the most prominent expression of entangled legalities is to
be found in medieval Europe. From the eleventh century onwards, law
became increasingly systematized through legislation and codification,
but the corpus iuris of much secular law was still made up of rules drawn
(‘received’) from a wide variety of sources, including Roman law and
customary usages. These rules retained their character as Roman law, ius
commune, etc., but they were transformed through the reception process
in a way that made them more compatible than they might have other-
wise been.23 Codifications, reflections of the law applied on the ground,
consequently contained elements from many different bodies of norms.
The eleventh-century Usatges de Barcelona used rules of Visigoth and
Roman origin just as well as secular and ecclesiastical ones; the German
Sachsenspiegel of the early thirteenth century meshed an account of local
custom with rules from imperial legislation and some from canon law. In
the French law of the period, multiple local customs stood alongside
royal law, with royal courts applying only those customs they deemed
‘reasonable’, often taking as guidance canon law or the learned Roman
law taught at universities.24
Scholars have described the resulting structure as a ‘patchwork of
accommodations’, in stark contrast with the idea of an integrated order
or system.25 Judges in this structure could not merely rely on one set of
rules but had to navigate between norms from a wide variety of contexts,
23
H. J. Berman, Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western Legal Tradition
(Harvard University Press, 1983), p. 2.
24
Ibid., pp. 470–1, 504, 511.
25
S. P. Donlan and D. Heirbaut, ‘“A Patchwork of Accommodations”: Reflections on
European Legal Hybridity and Jurisdictional Complexity’, in S. P. Donlan and
D. Heirbaut (eds), The Laws’ Many Bodies: Studies in Legal Hybridity and Jurisdictional
Complexity, c1600–1900 (Duncker & Humblot, 2015), p. 9.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
with greater emphasis on the substantive appropriateness of the rule
finally chosen than on its pedigree.26 In their pragmatic ways, these
judges inevitably entangled the multiple bodies of norms at play. This
structure slowly gave way, with the emergence and consolidation of the
modern nation state, to a focus on one, national law and the attempt to
shape it through binding codifications. But the transition was winding
and protracted, with many pockets of entanglement persisting for a long
time.27 In Germany, for example, legal plurality continued to be promin-
ent until the late nineteenth century. Judges based their decisions on a
confluence of local laws, ius commune and various other sets of norms
until the legislative and judicial unification of many areas of law after the
creation of the German state.28
Entanglements remained particularly strong in borderlands in which
different authorities and legal traditions intersected. French Flanders and
the Roussillon, acquired by France from the Netherlands and Spain in the
seventeenth century, experienced long periods of interwoven application
of French laws, local customs and previously governing rules, thereby
pursuing accommodation and avoiding clashes of authority.29 Yet more
pronounced was multiplicity in imperial structures, inside and outside
Europe.30 In the Holy Roman Empire, a prime example of jurisdictional
complexity, the law applied was ‘a mixture’ of a variety of legal sources,
meshing Roman and canon law with imperial prescriptions and
26
Donlan and Heirbaut, ‘“A Patchwork of Accommodations”’, p. 21.
27
See the contributions in Donlan and Heirbaut (eds), The Laws’ Many Bodies.
28
See N. Jansen, ‘Law and Political Domination: Historical Observations, Conceptual
Reflections, and Some Questions for Discussion’ (2018) 16 International Journal of
Constitutional Law 1176–85; M. Löhnig, ‘Killing Legal Complexity: The Jurisprudence
of the German Reichsgericht in the First Years of its Existence’, in S. P. Donlan and
D. Heirbaut (eds), The Laws’ Many Bodies: Studies in Legal Hybridity and Jurisdictional
Complexity, c1600–1900 (Duncker & Humblot, 2015), pp. 249–70.
29
A. Wijffels, ‘Ancien Régime France: Legal Particularism under the Absolute Monarchy’,
in S. P. Donlan and D. Heirbaut (eds), The Laws’ Many Bodies: Studies in Legal Hybridity
and Jurisdictional Complexity, c1600–1900 (Duncker & Humblot, 2015), pp. 81–108; B.
Durand, ‘Pluralism in France in the Modern Era – Between the “Quest for Justice” and
“Uniformity Through the Law”: The Case of Roussillon’, in S. P. Donlan and D. Heirbaut
(eds), The Laws’ Many Bodies: Studies in Legal Hybridity and Jurisdictional Complexity,
c1600–1900 (Duncker & Humblot, 2015), pp. 169–92.
30
See L. Benton and R. J. Ross (eds), Legal Pluralism and Empires, 1500–1850 (New York
University Press, 2013); J. Duindam, J. D. Harries, C. Humfress and H. Nimrod (eds),
Law and Empire: Ideas, Practices, Actors (Brill, 2013).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
territorial and local rules.31 In the British Empire, jurists in England and
abroad ‘liberally mixed sources of common, civil, and natural law, prin-
ciples of equity, and the law of nations’ when grappling with colonial
situations.32 Here and elsewhere, imperial and local legalities overlapped,
and imperial subjects navigated the different bodies of norms and juris-
dictions, often choosing sites and norms beneficial for them individually
and creating ‘relational fields’ of law along the way.33
With the consolidation of the modern state, complexity and entangle-
ment were reduced but not entirely suppressed. The ‘cuts’ between
different elements of modern, liberal law, highlighted by Julia Eckert in
Chapter 15, have also always been contested. ‘Negotiations’ between state
and non-state law, traced in pluralist scholarship, persisted both in
Europe and elsewhere, albeit with major variations.34 In recent decades,
increasing societal diversity has sparked renewed interest in the relation
of state and religious jurisdictions, especially on issues of family law.35
Such issues are often dealt with in a conflict-of-laws frame, with special
attention to public policy exceptions, but they evoke larger issues of
primacy between state law, human rights and religious precepts, as
reflected in Tobias Berger’s chapter on Bangladesh. The greater salience
of these issues, especially in Western countries, stems in part from the
rise of multicultural claims over the past decades. These claims have also
directed renewed attention to the relation between state and Indigenous
legal orders.36 In this collection, the contributions by Kirsten Anker
31
P. Oestmann, ‘The Law of the Holy Roman Empire of the German Nation’, in
H. Pihlajamäki, M.D. Dubber, and M. Godfrey (eds), The Oxford Handbook of
European Legal History (2018), pp. 731–59.
32
R. J. Ross and P. J. Stern, ‘Reconstructing Early Modern Notions of Legal Pluralism’, in
L. Benton and R. J. Ross (eds), Legal Pluralism and Empires, 1500–1850 (New York
University Press, 2013), pp. 109–42, at p. 130.
33
K. Barkey, ‘Aspects of Legal Pluralism in the Ottoman Empire’, in L. Benton and R. J.
Ross (eds), Legal Pluralism and Empires, 1500–1850 (New York University Press, 2013),
pp. 83–107, at pp. 94–103. See also S. E. Merry, ‘Colonial Law and Its Uncertainties
Forum: Maneuvering the Personal Law System in Colonial India: Comment’ (2010) 28
Law and History Review 1067–72, at 1068.
34
Merry, ‘Legal Pluralism’; M. A. Helfand (ed.), Negotiating State and Non-state Law: The
Challenge of Global and Local Legal Pluralism (Cambridge University Press, 2015).
35
See, e.g., M. A. Helfand, ‘Religious Arbitration and the New Multiculturalism:
Negotiating Conflicting Legal Orders’ (2011) 86 NYU Law Review 1231; M. Maclean
and J. Eekelaar (eds), Managing Family Justice in Diverse Societies (Bloomsbury, 2013).
36
See, e.g., J. Tully, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity
(Cambridge University Press, 1995); K. Gover, Tribal Constitutionalism: States, Tribes,
and the Governance of Membership (Oxford University Press, 2010).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
(Chapter 3) and by Keith Culver and Michael Giudice (Chapter 14) draw
on this latter debate. They use the example of relations between the
Canadian state and First Nations and trace how traditional, hierarchical
legal conceptualizations can be, and are being, transformed into ones
of entanglement.
The rise of transnational and international legalities over the past few
decades has exacerbated the perceived multiplicity of legal orders and has
helped to remove legal pluralism from the obscurity it long suffered in
many mainstream accounts of law.37 One important driver for this
development, especially for European scholars, has been the constitu-
tional indeterminacy of the European Union. Protracted conflict between
national constitutional courts and the European Court of Justice led
many to diagnose a form of (constitutional) pluralism in Europe.38 For
international lawyers, the long debate on fragmentation within the inter-
national legal order as well as the increasingly dense relations between
domestic and international layers of law generated greater interest in the
construction of these relations.39 Both as concerns the EU and inter-
national law, ‘entanglement’ is probably a better descriptor of complex
realities than (integrated or separate) legal systems.
One important aspect of the new ‘global legal pluralism’ has been the
broader focus on different kinds of legalities – formal and informal,
public and private.40 The concept of law used in this debate typically
goes beyond a traditional, Hartian frame and borrows from understand-
ings used by legal pluralists with more anthropological backgrounds.
The boundaries of the concept remain contested, and are often blurred,41
but they tend to include as a minimum ‘institutional normative
37
See, e.g., Berman, Global Legal Pluralism.
38
N. MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation in the European
Commonwealth (Oxford University Press, 1999); N. Krisch, ‘Europe’s Constitutional
Monstrosity’ (2005) 25 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 321–34; G. De Búrca and J. H.
Weiler (eds), The Worlds of European Constitutionalism (Cambridge University Press,
2011).
39
M. Koskenniemi, ‘The Fate of Public International Law: Between Technique and Politics’
(2007) 70 The Modern Law Review 1–30; J. E. Nijman and A. Nollkaemper (eds), New
Perspectives on the Divide between National and International Law (Oxford University
Press, 2007); Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism.
40
See, e.g., Berman, Global Legal Pluralism; N. Krisch, ‘Pluralism in International Law and
Beyond’, in J. d’Aspremont and S. Singh (eds), Concepts for International Law:
Contributions to Disciplinary Thought (Edward Elgar, 2019), pp. 691–707.
41
See B. Z. Tamanaha, ‘Understanding Legal Pluralism: Past to Present, Local to Global’
(2008) 30 Sydney Law Review 375–411.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
orders’ – bodies of norms associated with certain institutions, formal or
informal, for their interpretation or enforcement.42 Customary and reli-
gious law form part of the ‘law’ on this account, just as many of the
informal norms – soft law, standards, etc. – that are institutionally
produced and monitored, accepted by actors in the respective fields as
carrying significant weight, and are often more consequential than
formal rules.43 It is such a broader understanding of law that underlies
the present volume. Not all chapters necessarily employ the same
approach – some have a focus on more formal norms, others stretch
the notion of law well into non-normative forms of governance.44
Chapters 14 and 17 by Culver and Giudice and by Tamanaha are most
explicit in theorizing the concept of law as such, and in many of the other
chapters we can witness how the most consequential entanglements
straddle the boundaries of formal law and create linkages with, and
among, less formal legalities.
42
See K. Culver and M. Giudice, Legality’s Borders: An Essay in General Jurisprudence
(Oxford University Press, 2010); M. Del Mar, ‘Legality as Relative Institutionalisation:
MacCormick’s Diffusionism and Transnational Legal Theory’ (2014) 5 Transnational
Legal Theory 177–217.
43
N. Krisch, ‘The Decay of Consent: International Law in an Age of Global Public Goods’
(2014) 108 American Journal of International Law 1–40; J. Pauwelyn, R. Wessel and J.
Wouters (eds), Informal International Lawmaking (Oxford University Press, 2012).
44
Contrast, for example, Chapters 4 and 6 by Backer and Kanetake.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
been deeply entangled since the 1960s, with the Andean Community
where, despite a similarly strong central court and formal setup, national
and community rules have remained far more distant.45 Or compare the
differences across countries in the ways global women’s rights relate to
national legal discourses – sometimes kept at a distance, sometimes
leading to mutual influences of a transformative kind.46 In all these cases,
encounters would be possible in the liminal space of overlapping norms,
but actual encounters do not always happen, and if they do they do so in
widely varying forms and intensities.
Understanding such variation would require a detailed contextual
analysis in each case, and it is bound to be impossible to generalize
broadly across historical and institutional contexts. Tamanaha, for
example, emphasizes in Chapter 17 the contrast between relations among
legalities that reflect diversity in modes and visions of life – as between
state law and customary law in many, especially postcolonial societies –
and legal multiplicity fostered by a proliferation of regulatory or adjudi-
catory institutions of more or less the same kind. But based on existing
studies and the analyses in this volume, we can develop some observa-
tions and conjectures about the actors, pathways and dynamics through
which legal entanglement comes about and develops.
1.4.1 Actors
On which path entanglement comes about (and whether it does) will
always depend on the actors present and relevant in a given context – it
is through them that entanglement is ‘brought to life’.47 Relations
between bodies of norms are often construed by judges and other
dispute settlers, but not only or perhaps not even primarily. They are
also built by lawmakers, such as governments formulating legislation
and treaties defining the relation with other rules; by regulators devising
common norms and drawing on them in their regulatory practice; by
international organizations producing statements about the weight of
one body of norms vis-à-vis another. This volume contains many
45
See, e.g., K. J. Alter and L. R. Helfer, ‘Nature or Nurture? Judicial Lawmaking in the
European Court of Justice and the Andean Tribunal of Justice’ (2010) 64 International
Organization 563–92.
46
P. Levitt and S. E. Merry, ‘Vernacularization on the Ground: Local Uses of Global
Women’s Rights in Peru, China, India and the United States’ (2009) 9 Global Networks
441–61.
47
See especially Chapters 2 and 13 by Berger and Humfress.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
examples of this type, such as attempts by the Chinese government to
entangle different legalities, transnationally through the Belt and Road
Initiative and domestically through the social credit system, explored in
Chapters 4 and 5 by Larry Catá Backer and Tomer Broude. International
bodies are the focus of other contributions, as in Machiko Kanetake’s
account of the UN Human Rights Committee’s efforts to create linkages
with domestic courts in Chapter 6, or Grégoire Mallard and Aurel
Niederberger’s inquiry in Chapter 9 into the way in which norms on
counter-proliferation finance are circulating between regulators and
institutions such as the UN Security Council or the Financial Action
Task Force.
Yet the scope of relevant actors goes well beyond the governmental
sphere. As already noted in the imperial context, individual litigants often
play key roles in determining by whom legal claims are decided, and they
present arguments about which norms ought to apply and how.48
Lawyers advising clients generate understandings of how different laws
relate; international law firms, in particular, are important producers of
legal knowledge in this respect.49 Civil society groups, business associ-
ations and private norm addressees are often active in fostering views on
how one body of norms interacts with another – they need to navigate a
pluralist order, and their statements will have a particular weight in areas
where more authoritative actors are absent. For example, as emerges
from Eckert’s chapter on struggles over rights violations in the context
of global value chains, entanglement will often be driven by a ‘mobilisa-
tion of law from below’. More generally, if we think of law as a social
practice, it is a broad range of societal and official actors whose practices
constitute legal orders and the relations of norms among them.50 Actors
are situated, and this situation shapes their way of regarding the multiple
norms at play. Where actors – for example dispute settlers – are closely
tied to one body of norms, we can expect them to be more reticent
bridge-builders than actors with a self-understanding that is less clearly
defined. This is most obvious in the context of national courts. Where
judges understand themselves as part of a state’s authority structure,
tasked first and foremost with applying that state’s law, they are unlikely
48
See Chapter 13 by Humfress.
49
See also Günther and Randeria, Recht, Kultur und Gesellschaft im Prozess der
Globalisierung, pp. 52–9.
50
See generally Chapter 17 by Tamanaha; and the emphasis on a ‘user theory of jurisdic-
tion’ in Chapter 13 by Humfress.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
to draw openly on norms from other origins.51 However, not all national
judges are alike. Common law judges, for example, might be more open
than their civil law colleagues to creating linkages with norms from
various sources out of an understanding of law that is encompassing
rather than tied to a particular political authority.52 Which actors are
tasked with resolving a particular conflict – and what background they
have – will then often have strong repercussions for the kind and
strength of resulting connections. Humfress’ chapter, with its focus on
the different engagements with Roman law by military officials, clerics
and tribal leaders in the resolution of an individual dispute, brings this
point out nicely.
Variations in situatedness might also help to explain, for example, the
relative unwillingness of courts tasked with the interpretation of a par-
ticular instrument to consider norms from other origins, compared with
the attempts of, say, the International Court of Justice to provide a
(somewhat) more ecumenical reading of international law.53 A body
tasked with the interpretation of less well-defined areas of law, such as
the Court of Arbitration for Sport, is likely to sense greater freedom in
creating linkages with norms from different origins.54 And dispute set-
tlers who, like arbitrators appointed ad hoc, are not beholden to a
particular political or legal order, can be expected to draw on a broader
range of norms than their more directly committed counterparts.
Non-governmental actors – and especially those that are not tasked
with enforcing a particular legal order – are more generally less commit-
ted in principle, and they are likely to be more flexible in using and
drawing upon different legalities: they may perhaps be seen to inhabit the
‘liminal spaces’ in which entanglements tend to flourish.55 This is prob-
ably also true for actors who, like regulators, understand themselves as
lawmakers rather than law-appliers and therefore may feel less
51
See J. Resnik, ‘Law as Affiliation: “Foreign” Law, Democratic Federalism, and the
Sovereigntism of the Nation-State’ (2008) 6 International Journal of Constitutional Law
33–66.
52
See Chapter 6 by Kanetake; also H. P. Glenn, ‘Transnational Common Laws’ (2005) 29
Fordham International Law Journal 457–71.
53
Y. Shany, ‘International Courts as Inter-Legality Hubs’, in J. Klabbers and G. Palombella
(eds), The Challenge of Inter-Legality (Cambridge University Press, 2019), pp. 319–38. See
also Corradini, Chapter 7, on investment tribunals.
54
See Chapter 10 by Duval.
55
On those liminal spaces, see Stockhammer, ‘Conceptualizing Cultural Hybridization in
Archaeology’, pp. 45–51.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
constrained by considerations of what the law in force is on a given issue.
Yet, as Broude highlights in Chapter 5, individual actors tend to
approach the multiple legalities potentially relevant in a given situation
from a particular, and highly bounded, perspective – their situatedness
will often make them see, or prioritize, certain norms rather than others,
and it is crucial to understand these perspectives for an account of how
and why legalities become entangled (or not).
1.4.2 Pathways
There are many paths to entanglement, and the discussion so far has
already suggested some important ones. The ideational context of actors –
most clearly in the case of judges – is bound to condition whether they
construe legal orders as one or as separate, and whether they see them as
open or closed. The space for and possibilities of entanglement are likely
to vary historically and geographically as a result. For a judge in
seventeenth-century Germany, entangling may have been the norm,
whereas his late twentieth-century counterpart will have approached
the plurality of norms through a prism of clearly separated (and intern-
ally integrated) legal spheres. Likewise, actors in many developing coun-
tries may be more used to navigating different normative orders than
their colleagues in the Global North, even if there remains important
variation. On the other hand, actors with a firm international law back-
ground applying formal international legal rules may be less open to
applying norms from other sources than those engaged in the application
of informal or transnational norms. The intense practice of linking
norms from different origins by bodies such as the National Contact
Points under the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and
Development (OECD) Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises, traced
by Tomáš Morochovič and Lucy Lu Reimers in Chapter 12, reflects a very
open imagination of the law to be applied. At the same time, inter-
national lawyers will tend to regard different issue-specific regimes as
part of one international legal order and seek to construe harmonious
relations between them.56 That said, the communities of practice actors
form part of will often shape the way they construe linkages; this comes
out particularly clearly in Chapter 11 in Francesco Corradini’s portrayal
56
H. Birkenkötter, ‘International Law as a Common Language across Spheres of Authority?’
(2020) 9 Global Constitutionalism 318–42.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of how investment and human rights communities differ in their con-
struction of the nexus between norms from these areas.57
A second ideational pathway works through resonance. Norms from
other origins may be appealing for their substantive content but also for
the aura of progress they come with, the Zeitgeist they represent or the fit
they produce with existing commitments. Likewise, the actors creating
such norms may appear as appealing – as embodying the right values, as
culturally superior, etc., sometimes as a result of hegemonic scripts.58
Linkage on this basis is, however, likely primarily when the norms in
question resonate with norms and values in the target context.59 Such
resonance does not only have to do with the ‘actual’ content of the
respective norms but also, and perhaps primarily, with the ways in which
those norms are framed and construed in societal and political dis-
courses. If such construction allows enhancing beliefs and values that
are already widely held, linkages succeed more easily, but they may come
at the cost of greater distance from the way in which those norms are
understood in the contexts they originate from.
Other pathways relate more directly to rational choices. Relevant
actors often stand to gain from linkages between different bodies of
norms – litigants, for example, may see the mobilization of law from a
variety of sources as beneficial to their cause, as detailed in Eckert’s
chapter. They may also use them to relativize or circumvent unfavourable
local norms or obtain advantageous remedies.60 Sometimes, they will be
led to draw freely on relevant norms from different origins – state law,
religious law, or international norms.61 In Berger’s chapter on the
entanglement of state and non-state law in Bangladesh, activists make
liberal use of multiple normative registers, including religious and inter-
national law, to carve out space for marginalized actors.
57
See also S. Taekema, ‘Between or beyond Legal Orders: Questioning the Concept of Legal
Order in Light of Interlegality’, in J. Klabbers and G. Palombella (eds), The Challenge of
Inter-Legality (Cambridge University Press, 2019), pp. 69–88, at pp. 78, 84.
58
See Chapter 15 by Eckert.
59
Levitt and Merry, ‘Vernacularization on the Ground’; T. Berger, Global Norms and Local
Courts: Translating the Rule of Law in Bangladesh (Oxford University Press, 2017).
60
L. Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–1900
(Cambridge University Press, 2002) p. 137; Barkey, ‘Aspects of Legal Pluralism in the
Ottoman Empire’, p. 100.
61
See J. Eckert, ‘What Is the Context in “Law in Context”?’, in S. P. Donlan and
L. Heckendorn Urscheler (eds), Concepts of Law: Comparative, Jurisprudential, and
Social Science Perspectives (Routledge, 2016), pp. 225–36.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Linkages with different bodies of norms can create space, but they
can also serve to strengthen authority. For example, transnational regu-
lators may enhance their own position by linking up with bodies of
norms produced by other, reputed institutions, as detailed in
Corradini’s chapter on global financial regulation, and in particular the
efforts of the Financial Stability Board, to weave a common set of norms.
Another prominent example are national courts who, by linking their
domestic legal order to European Community law, created space for
themselves vis-à-vis political branches and hierarchically superior
courts.62 In Antoine Duval’s chapter on the making of a transnational
lex sportiva, it is the Court of Arbitration for Sport that bolsters its
authority – and wards off potential challenges by other courts – by
drawing together rules and laws of very different pedigree.
In this picture, stronger, more autonomous actors would likely be
more resistant to closer entanglement, while weaker, more vulnerable
ones would seek it to bolster their own position and authority.63
Corradini’s chapter on investment and human rights law suggests that
increasing legitimacy challenges for investment law might push actors,
including arbitrators, to seek stronger entanglements, at least rhetorically.
In contrast, Lucy Lu Reimers’ chapter on international trade law shows
how a relatively strong institution – the World Trade Organization
(WTO) – has been able to use linkages strategically and selectively, while
avoiding unfavourable entanglements. In Backer’s chapter, algorithmic
techniques of governance can subsume other legalities, but typically on
their own terms and potentially dominating them as a consequence of
technological change. Taking the different, competing norms into
account may appear as the path of least resistance, but it may also help
to create space to come to a preferred conclusion.
A further major pathway, too often neglected, is coercion, broadly
conceived. Metropolitan law in imperial settings may have at times held
some appeal or benefits, but in many cases local actors have woven it into
their legal arguments because of a relation of domination – expressed, for
example, through imperial judges who needed to relate ‘their’ law to the
norms operative on the ground, or through local judges who thereby
62
K. J. Alter, Establishing the Supremacy of European Law: The Making of an International
Rule of Law in Europe (Oxford University Press, 2001).
63
This may help to explain patterns in judicial borrowing by international courts; see E.
Voeten, ‘Borrowing and Nonborrowing among International Courts’ (2010) 39 The
Journal of Legal Studies 547–76.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
reaffirmed loyalty and obedience to imperial rulers.64 But coercion is not
confined to the distant past. Today, for example, the adoption of World
Bank rules on resettlement in the context of infrastructure programmes
on the part of borrowing states is often a matter of conditionality and
necessity rather than persuasion or attraction.65 In Chapter 11, Corradini
points to the coercive aspects of conditionality in the implementation of
international financial standards by the International Monetary Fund.
Backer’s chapter highlights hierarchical forms of entanglement in the
Chinese social credit system as well as transnational credit rating agen-
cies. Broude’s chapter traces the imperial character of entanglements
brought about by the Chinese Belt and Road Initiative. Mallard and
Niederberger’s contribution to this volume also stresses the coercive
aspect as it traces the hegemonic origins of intertextual entanglements
in the new legal order of counter-proliferation finance. In their compel-
ling reading, the circulating references between different kinds of rules –
formal and informal, international and national – reinforce each other’s
authority but also serve to hide their origins in US policies.
1.4.3 Dynamics
Entanglements may be gradual and smooth, but often they are charac-
terized by a dialectical dynamic – one in which actors favour proximity
between different bodies of norms but they also seek a certain distance,
and they thus construe the relation as neither strict separation nor full
integration into one order. Just as processes of globalization are charac-
terized by the dual tendencies of assimilation and fragmentation,
entanglement is an in-between state which often oscillates between these
poles.66
This is perhaps most obvious when entanglement comes about, at least
in part, through coercion. Pressure to adopt certain norms is then likely
to be countered by attempts to create distance at the same time, as in the
case of local law faced with metropolitan legislation in (post)colonial
64
See, e.g., Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures, chapter 4.
65
See S. Randeria, ‘The State of Globalization: Legal Plurality, Overlapping Sovereignties
and Ambiguous Alliances between Civil Society and the Cunning State in India’ (2007) 24
Theory, Culture & Society 1–33.
66
See Z. Bauman, ‘On Glocalization: Or Globalization for some, Localization for some
Others’ (1998) 54 Thesis Eleven 37–49; Conrad and Randeria, ‘Einleitung: Geteilte
Geschichten’, pp. 41–2.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
contexts.67 This is visible today, for example, in the continuing struggle of
Indigenous peoples against the supremacy claims of (settler) state law or
in attempts to counter state law demands by emphasizing the autonomy
of Sharia law.68 But the tension between proximity and distance can be
observed more widely. In the postnational context, it will often reflect a
tension between factors militating for closer linkage – for example the
harmonization of markets, or universal human rights claims – and an
insistence on autonomy and the freedom to decide differently. The latter
is relatively obvious in ‘vertical’ relations when actors insist on the
autonomy of smaller units, for example national institutions vis-à-vis
international rules.69 Kanetake’s chapter shows how UN human rights
bodies accommodate potential resistance by leaving national actors sig-
nificant flexibility when it comes to giving international decisions domes-
tic legal weight, and how national courts use (and sometimes extend) this
space in a variety of ways. Approaching the question from the local angle,
Berger’s chapter traces the complex interplay between proximity and
distancing in the approaches of different actors to multiple available
norms, from Islamic to state and international human rights law, in
debates over a ban on Islamic fatwas in Bangladesh.
Yet we can also observe an insistence on autonomy in other, more
‘horizontal’ contexts, for example when actors seek to defend the values
driving international human rights law or international economic law
from being contaminated by the respective other.70 Reimers’ chapter on
the interaction between international trade and environmental law pro-
vides a vivid account of this dynamic. The more particular bodies of
norms are linked with distinct values, institutions and constituencies, the
more linkages may create concerns about heteronomy and provoke calls
for greater distance. In the end, the portrayal of certain relations as
‘vertical’ or ‘horizontal’ is also a product of how an entanglement is
socially construed – as we can see, for example, in Culver and
67
On the latter, see e.g. Barkey, ‘Aspects of Legal Pluralism in the Ottoman Empire’,
pp. 101–3.
68
See Chapters 3, 14 and 17 by Anker, Culver and Giudice, and Tamanaha.
69
The ‘vertical’ and ‘horizontal’ dimensions of entanglement are helpful as heuristic tools to
structure the inquiry, but it should be noted that they are themselves products of how the
relation between different bodies of norms are related. Indigenous and state law, for
example, can be understood as standing in either the one or the other relation; the politics
of this choice are reflected in Chapter 14 by Culver and Giudice.
70
P. Alston, ‘Resisting the Merger and Acquisition of Human Rights by Trade Law: A Reply
to Petersmann’ (2002) 13 European Journal of International Law 815–44.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Giudice’s discussion of the relation of Canadian state and indigenous
laws in Chapter 14, the question of whether a relation should be seen as
one or the other can be highly contested and consequential. Attempts at
linkage can make entanglements appear as more vertical, attempts at
distancing can make them more horizontal.
The need to create, or insist on, distance is likely to be, in part, a
function of the character of the entangled norms. Where these are
informal and soft, actors retain space and autonomy even in the face of
close linkages. The examples of corporate social responsibility norms, in
Morochovič and Reimers’ chapter, or global financial standards, in
Corradini’s contribution, are cases in point here – as Corradini empha-
sizes, the creation of unified financial standards has long been hampered
by an insistence on autonomy on the part of both national governments
and various international bodies. In hard law contexts, for example in
domestic courts, the stakes of entanglement will often be higher and a
clear definition of relations more consequential.
The dialectic of proximity and distancing also has a temporal dimen-
sion. Linkages often have long-term effects, especially when they concern
not only individual norms but whole sets of norms or legal orders.
A norm defining the status of international law in the domestic legal
order, for example, has relevance for an unlimited number of interactions
between both legal orders in the future. The effects of such linkage,
however, are often difficult to predict for the actors involved, and atten-
tion may well be drawn to them only when problems arise and a
particular issue becomes politicized.71 As tighter forms of coupling
emerge and come to apply to increasingly consequential and salient
issues, they can be expected to provoke political contestation and resist-
ance which will often seek to disrupt more routinized forms of inter-
action and may result in mechanisms for reclaiming distance. Even if
issue-specific, this politicization may lead to calls for redefining the
linkage more broadly. In this vein, contestation around issues of terror-
ism and voting rights for prisoners has engendered a general movement
in the UK for greater distance from judgements of the European Court of
Human Rights.72
71
M. Zürn, M. Binder and M. Ecker-Ehrhardt, ‘International Authority and Its
Politicization’ (2012) 4 International Theory 69–106.
72
See M. Madsen, ‘The Challenging Authority of the European Court of Human Rights:
From Cold War Legal Diplomacy to the Brighton Declaration and Backlash’ (2016) 79
Law and Contemporary Problems 141–78, at 170–1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
1.5 A Variety of Forms
If we can indeed expect a push towards greater proximity, accompanied
by certain forms of distancing that prevent full integration, the result is
likely to be the emergence of new types of norms at the interfaces
between different parts of the legal order – norms that, instead of
governing behaviour directly, define the relation and applicability of
primary norms (on behaviour) as well as secondary norms (on powers
to make and interpret the law).73 With this volume, we aim at gaining a
clearer picture of the shape of these norms – ‘tertiary norms’, as Michaels
describes them in Chapter 16.
In a context of entanglement, interface norms are likely to reflect the
dialectic dynamics in Section 1.4 – strengthening ties between different
bodies of norms but preserving discretion or safety valves that help to
recalibrate relations in times of tension.74 Yet how these norms are
construed will often differ across actors. This is most obvious in the
jurisprudence of different courts, for example in differences in interpret-
ation of the proper relationship of human rights and international
humanitarian law.75 But it is at least equally observable outside the
courtroom, for example in the conflict over the relationship of the
TRIPS (Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights)
Agreement with international human rights and world health law as
regards access to essential medicines. Here, the World Health Assembly
and the (then) UN Human Rights Commission urged an interpretative
coupling of the different areas, while neither the WTO’s eventual Doha
Declaration on the TRIPS Agreement and Public Health nor the imple-
menting decision mention other bodies of law at all – despite the fact
that, as a political matter, these other bodies were obviously important
for the eventual rapprochement of the WTO.76 Corradini’s chapter on
investment and human rights, and Reimers’ on trade and environment,
73
See Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism, pp. 285–96.
74
In a similar vein, Kjaer highlights the proliferation of ‘connectivity norms’ in the global
order; see P. F. Kjaer, ‘Global Law as Inter-contextuality and as Inter-legality’, in
J. Klabbers and G. Palombella (eds), The Challenge of Inter-legality (Cambridge
University Press, 2019), pp. 302–18, at p. 304.
75
See, e.g., A. E. Cassimatis, ‘International Humanitarian Law, International Human Rights
Law, and Fragmentation of International Law’ (2007) 56 International & Comparative
Law Quarterly 623–39.
76
See on the contest L. R. Helfer, ‘Regime Shifting: The TRIPS Agreement and New
Dynamics of International Intellectual Property Lawmaking’ (2004) 29 Yale Journal of
International Law 1, at 42–5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
trace other cases of actors’ diverging views over the relationship between
two bodies of norms, and they highlight especially the interactive
and temporal dimension of the construction of the relationship.
Interface norms themselves are contingent: claims about them vary
across actors and times. Stable relations between bodies of norms may
emerge from convergence among concerned actors on the substance or
on the norms governing the interfaces, but such convergence may well
prove elusive.
Getting closer to these interfaces means that we cannot limit ourselves
to considering the formal rules that govern these relations or the occa-
sional pronouncement of a court – too much of the postnational legal
order only has loose connections with courts or other formal dispute
settlers. Instead, we need to take into view the ways in which different
kinds of actors – norm-makers, addressees, dispute settlers and other
concerned societal actors – construe these relations and resolve (poten-
tial) conflicts between different norms. We thus need to get closer to the
‘social life’ of postnational law in order to understand the way it works.77
This is brought out in this volume by, for example, Eckert’s account of
the construction of entanglements ‘from below’ which zooms in on
societal actors and their struggles behind the legal façade, or in
Humfress’ insistence on a user theory of jurisdiction that starts from
the ways in which litigants draw on particular authorities to navigate
different layers of law.
The relations brought about through societal action can be a mere
matter of fact and influence between different bodies of norms. But
they will also often be the result of, and reflected in, discursive
statements – in the overlapping bodies of norms themselves or in
statements about them from relevant actors. The production of inter-
face norms is then the result not so much of a one-off determination,
but of a process of law – a process whose analysis will often benefit
from sociological and anthropological methods to complement the
work of lawyers, as evident from the multidisciplinary contributions
to this volume.78
77
See also Taekema’s suggestion that a practice orientation is key to understanding inter-
legality in Taekema, ‘Between or Beyond Legal Orders’.
78
See generally S. F. Moore, Law as Process: An Anthropological Approach (Routledge &
Kegan Paul, 1978).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
1.5.1 Towards a Typology
What then are the norms and practices that structure the relations
between different bodies of norms? Practice has generated a host of tools
and approaches in this respect,79 and we can distinguish three main
types: reception norms, overarching norms and – situated between
them – straddling practices. The two former form part of the common
repertoire of inter- and intra-systemic norms – they reflect the dichot-
omy between the (external) conflict of laws and the (internal) conflict of
norms80 – while the latter blur system boundaries and suggest an alter-
native structure, characterized by looser couplings.
Reception norms. Reception norms are the typical form through which
a legal system deals with norms from the outside; they reproduce the
inside/outside distinction and define the ways in which outside norms
enter a given body of norms. Michaels’ tertiary norms, as developed in
Chapter 16, fall into this category as they are designed to regulate the
relations of one legal system with others. Reception norms include norms
performing an accommodating function in the regulation of the inter-
action between bodies of norms.81 They can reflect closer as well as more
distanced relations, though they remain short of actual integration. They
can thus range from the exclusion of outside norms to fixed references,
potentially coupled with conditions of a procedural or substantive kind.
Examples of the latter are conflict-of-law norms that specify in which
circumstances foreign norms are applied by national courts; norms about
the effect and hierarchical status of outside norms in the domestic legal
order; or norms of the Solange kind that recognize the direct effect of
(regional or international) norms if these fulfil certain – procedural or
substantive – conditions, for example equivalent protection. More flex-
ible reception norms embody greater discretion, for example in require-
ments of taking norms from other authority spheres ‘into account’, or in
practices granting them ‘persuasive authority’, thus giving them weight
79
See, e.g., Delmas-Marty, Ordering Pluralism; D. Pulkowski, The Law and Politics of
International Regime Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2014); A. Peters, ‘The
Refinement of International Law: From Fragmentation to Regime Interaction and
Politicization’ (2017) 15 International Journal of Constitutional Law 671–704.
80
R. Michaels and J. Pauwelyn, ‘Conflict of Norms or Conflict of Laws? Different
Techniques in the Fragmentation of Public International Law’ (2012) 22 Duke Journal
of Comparative & International Law 349–76.
81
See R. Michaels, ‘On Liberalism and Legal Pluralism’, in M. Maduro, K. Tuori and
S. Sankari (eds), Transnational Law: Rethinking European Law and Legal Thinking
(Cambridge University Press, 2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
but no conclusive effect.82 Kanetake’s chapter traces the many such forms
the United Nations treaty bodies and domestic courts use to calibrate
their relations, providing for both linkage and flexibility by using open
criteria, such as ‘due consideration’.
Overarching norms. Typical for the intra-systemic dimension, over-
arching norms regulate relations centrally and with binding character for
the different bodies of norms involved. This can involve classical conflict
norms, such as lex specialis or lex posterior. It can also involve norms
about hierarchies, as between constitutions and ordinary statutes or
secondary legislation, between federal and state law in federal orders,
between ius cogens and other international rules or between obligations
under the United Nations Charter and other international obligations
under Article 103 of the Charter. Overarching norms can also be con-
strued as substantive integrating rules or principles, such as human
rights, sustainable development or democracy/good governance, which
create normative expectations throughout the entire system – often
expressed, in international law, as rules of ‘customary’ or ‘general’ inter-
national law.83 Equally more flexible are interpretative connections that
allow actors space to define relations, such as principles of harmonizing
interpretation or requirements not to interpret certain rules ‘in isolation’
from other parts of the legal order.84 On the other hand, overarching
rules can also be seen to protect the autonomy of certain parts of the
order, through constitutional limits on interference, the recognition of
the self-contained character of certain suborders, lex specialis claims or
rules which delimit regulatory spheres, as between agreements with
different sets of parties.
Straddling practices. The third (and perhaps most interesting) category
comprises norms and practices that straddle different bodies of norms
without being seen to belong to either, thus blurring the boundaries
between them. Given the prevailing systemic imagery, such practices
have found less attention so far, even if – as we have seen in the brief
historical survey in Section 1.3 – they seem to have formed an important
part of the entangled legalities of the past. Such norms and practices will
also tend to be less clearly developed and are likely to appear in more
inchoate forms. We can observe them, for example, in courts weaving
82
See also Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism, pp. 286–96.
83
See Chapters 7 and 8 by Corradini and Reimers.
84
See, e.g., C. McLachlan, ‘The Principle of Systemic Integration and Article 31(3)(C) of the
Vienna Convention’ (2005) 54 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 279–320.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
together different bodies of norms in order to come to a solution in a
given case. For example, the Court of Appeal of England and Wales, in a
case concerning the implementation of UN sanctions, used the notion of
‘conciliation’ to bring together UK primary and secondary legislation, the
European Convention on Human Rights as well as obligations deriving
from UN Security Council resolutions in a harmonious fashion, rather
than stipulating rules of hierarchy or re-enacting the boundaries between
legal systems.85 Other boundary-blurring norms may be hybrid norms,
multi-sourced equivalent norms86 or open concepts used to provide a
pathway between different bodies of norms. Examples here include due
diligence principles that allow for connections between the national and
transnational regulation of multinational companies, or the notion of
‘core labour rights’ developed by the International Labour Organization
and allowing for flexible references in a multitude of other codes, public
and private. These forms mirror the ‘intertextuality’ traced by Mallard
and Niederberger in counter-proliferation finance.87 Open concepts are
also visible in Berger’s account of the Bangladeshi Supreme Court’s
navigation of the boundary between state and religious law (and inter-
national human rights).
Such straddling practices are particularly visible in contexts less struc-
tured by ideational frames of modern state law. Humfress emphasizes the
importance of jurisgenerative practices of actors, rather than formalized
norms and relations between them, in the making of law in Chapter 13
on the Eastern Roman Empire. Similar observations pertain to
contemporary contexts with a lesser degree of formalization and weaker
boundaries than typically found in the state context. Some of the
National Contact Points under the OECD Guidelines for Multinational
Enterprises, for example, have emerged as quasi-judicial dispute settle-
ment bodies and have drawn on various bodies of norms to ground their
findings, as Morochovič and Reimers detail in Chapter 12. Some of the
norms they use – such as the requirement of ‘free, prior and informed
consent’ – are drawn from other bodies of norms but used as if they were
free-floating principles applicable throughout. Similarly, Duval traces
how the Court of Arbitration for Sport uses both publicly and privately
85
England and Wales Court of Appeal, Judgment of 30 October 2008, A, K, M, Q & G
v. HM Treasury [2008] EWCA Civ 1187.
86
T. Broude and Y. Shany (eds), Multi-sourced Equivalent Norms in International Law
(Bloomsbury, 2011).
87
See also Kjaer, ‘Global Law as Inter-contextuality and as Inter-legality’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
produced norms in its effort at weaving together lex sportiva’s ‘tapestry’.
Such references build lasting connections between different norms, even
in the absence of (systemic) reception norms. We can observe similar
phenomena on the regulatory side, as Corradini shows in Chapter 7. The
Financial Stability Board (FSB), for example, has sought to connect
standards from various transnational and international standard-setters,
public and private, formal and informal, through its Compendium of
Standards, with fifteen ‘key standards’ singled out as requiring particular
attention. Through the Compendium, the FSB seeks to build a more
integrated order out of the existing multiplicity, though one that func-
tions not in the form of a system but through a web with less stable
linkages and hierarchies. Other bodies in global financial governance play
their part in weaving this web. The resulting structure is not sustained
through firm general rules about relations, but rather through contin-
gent, sometimes ad hoc, acts of linking, referencing and distancing, with
a potential consolidation occurring only over time.88
Another intriguing yet highly challenging form of entanglement is
highlighted in Backer’s chapter on algorithmic techniques of governance.
With the rise of such forms of governance, the linkages between different
bodies of norms created through algorithms and ratings become a central
concern, and one so far hardly understood. This is especially so as
algorithmic governance – just as the many indicators and rankings in
contemporary governance in and beyond the state – operationalizes, but
typically does not lay open, the normative choices and preferences that
go into the weighing of different types of norms and expectations.89
88
See also N. Krisch, F. Corradini and L. L. Reimers, ‘Order at the Margins: The Legal
Construction of Interface Conflicts over Time’ (2020) 9 Global Constitutionalism 343–63.
89
See also K. E. Davis, A. Fisher, B. Kingsbury and S. E. Merry (eds), Governance by
Indicators: Global Power through Classification and Rankings (Oxford University Press,
2012).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
1.6.1 Conflict and Consolidation
Legal entanglement will often be seen as prone to conflict – more clearly
defined relations, either the separation or the integration of different
bodies of norms, seem to promise greater stability. Stanley Hoffmann’s
famous dictum about the European Community, which he saw as occu-
pying an unstable middle ground between international cooperation and
the creation of a new state, exemplifies this widespread view.90 Today,
similar assessments often accompany the diagnosis of regime complexity
and interface conflicts between different institutions and norms in the
global order.91
Whether this assumption of conflictivity is empirically justified is not
obvious,92 however, and how it applies to different forms and degrees of
entanglement even less so. Entangled relations do not have to be unstable
at all; they can display a high degree of consolidation around the norms
that govern interactions. This is especially so if addressees as well as
dispute settlers adopt a conciliatory rather than confrontational atti-
tude.93 Even if underlying tensions persist, the relative openness of such
entanglements, and the frequent accommodation of both linkage and
distancing just mentioned, may actually help to provide flexibility and
the necessary safety valves to adjust to changing or unforeseen
circumstances.94
In fact, in several of the chapters in this volume, closer entanglements
are construed precisely to respond to, and ward off, challenges to the
legitimacy of a certain body of norms. These challenges stem from, for
example, human rights (as in Duval’s story of the Court of Arbitration
for Sport or Corradini’s of international investment law) or environ-
mental concerns (as in Reimer’s chapter on trade law). On the other
hand, more distant entanglement is sometimes sought to defuse conflicts
that would be caused by too integrated a relation – as in the move
90
S. Hoffmann, ‘Obstinate or Obsolete? The Fate of the Nation-State and the Case of
Western Europe’ (1966) 95 Daedalus 862–915.
91
See, e.g., D. W. Drezner, ‘The Tragedy of the Global Institutional Commons’, in
M. Finnemore and J. Goldstein (eds), Back to Basics: State Power in a Contemporary
World (Oxford University Press, 2013), pp. 280–310.
92
See C. Kreuder-Sonnen and M. Zürn, ‘After Fragmentation: Institutional Density, Regime
Complexes and Interface Conflicts’ (2020) 9 Global Constitutionalism 241–67.
93
See Peters, ‘The Refinement of International Law’; T. Megiddo, ‘Beyond Fragmentation:
On International Law’s Integrationist Forces’ (2019) 44 Yale Journal of International Law
115–48.
94
See Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism, chapter 7.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
towards a more equal status for Indigenous groups (Chapters 3 and 14 by
Anker and Culver and Giudice), or towards greater leeway for national
courts vis-à-vis international human rights adjudication (Chapter 6 by
Kanetake). Legal entanglement, on the evidence presented here, does not
eliminate conflict, but it might help to reduce problems associated with
stronger integration or a strict separation of norms that express different,
sometimes competing values. It might also, as in Berger’s chapter on the
struggle over the prohibition of fatwas in Bangladesh, simply help to
delay a more principled, clear-cut response to a societal conflict, creating
time and space for other processes to do their work.
Once open and contested, interactions between different bodies of
norms will also often develop into more settled relations over time.
This can be observed, for example, in the evolution of human rights-
based contestation in international economic law which we have traced
in an earlier article. What initially appeared as destabilizing challenges –
of World Bank authority, or earlier corporate social responsibility rules –
led to an adjustment and transformation which, despite some continuing
uncertainties, has led to new consolidation.95
95
Krisch, Corradini and Reimers, ‘Order at the Margins’.
96
See only H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Clarendon Press, 1994); J. Raz, The Concept
of a Legal System: An Introduction to the Theory of Legal System (Clarendon Press, 1980).
97
See R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Harvard University Press, 1986); S. Shapiro, Legality
(Harvard University Press, 2011).
98
See also Tamanaha, ‘Understanding Legal Pluralism’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
norms and overarching norms – here, entanglement is integrated into the
legal system through the system’s own rules about identity and boundar-
ies. Yet even here, the particular rules required to deal with the relations
with others have not been overly well theorized. Reception norms,
traditionally seen as relatively marginal, pose theoretical problems
because, as a matter of fact, they do not operate solely within the system
but depend on accommodating rules and practices in other systems.
Where interactions between different bodies of norms are intense, the
potential for divergences and substantial incoherence grows, posing a
challenge for the rule of law aspirations often associated with law, and
especially with the systemic image of law. And while a description of law
that operates with closure and hierarchies may still have some formal
validity (within each of the interacting systems), it captures less of the
social reality of a legal order.99 In Chapter 16, Michaels draws our
attention to the challenge of plurality for a Hartian legal theory and
begins to develop a response by introducing ‘tertiary’ norms and clarify-
ing their scope and functioning. He highlights in particular that such
tertiary norms need to reflect a recognition not just from the officials or
addressees of the particular legal system concerned but also from other
legal systems with which it stands in relations.
The theoretical challenge grows further when we turn to the straddling
practices mentioned in Section 1.5. The more these blur the boundaries
of different legal systems, the less they can be integrated into a systemic
image of the law, even one relying on a multiplicity of systems. The idea
of a ‘web’ – in which different norms, and bodies of norms, form
connections with one another, with the whole only emerging from these
connections – then becomes yet more attractive.100 As Culver and
Giudice demonstrate in Chapter 14, such a web may rest on a conceptu-
alization that builds upon but modifies a Hartian approach, by empha-
sizing mutual references between legal institutions.101 This might also
provide a frame in which systemic and non-systemic expressions of law
can coexist, distinguished primarily by the strength and stability of the
connections between particular norms and bodies of norms. Culver and
99
See also the discussion in Taekema, ‘Between or Beyond Legal Orders’; G. Palombella,
‘Theory, Realities, and Promises of Inter-Legality’, in J. Klabbers and G. Palombella
(eds), The Challenge of Inter-Legality (Cambridge University Press, 2019), pp. 363–90, at
pp. 374–8.
100
F. Ost and M. Van de Kerchove, De la pyramide au réseau?: pour une théorie dialectique
du droit (Publications Fac St Louis, 2002).
101
See also Culver and Giudice, Legality’s Borders.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Giudice demonstrate the analytical but also the normative appeal of
entanglement over more systemic, hierarchical models by using the
example of state–First Nations relations in Canada.
Much theorizing about networks in law, often inspired by Niklas
Luhmann’s systems theory, has taken the perspective of an external
observer, seeking to bring to light the real workings of a social system
represented otherwise by the actors involved in it – to reveal ‘the hard-
core reality of a trompe d’oeil’.102 Yet, as our volume shows, a networked
reality may well be visible also in the legal discourses themselves.
Linkages and entanglements are processed and produced internally to
legal practice, through various kinds of norms and practices connecting
and straddling different bodies of norms. Often enough, these linkages
may connect individual norms, rather than ‘bodies’ of norms as such,
thus taking us yet further away from the notion of closed systems.103
A pluralist jurisprudence will then have to give an account of not only the
inter-systemic dimension,104 but also the trans-systemic, networked
character of law, as in Boaventura de Sousa Santos’ interlegality.105
This is bound to have repercussions on the nature of legal reasoning,
well beyond the particular forms of interface norms constructed to deal
with the margins. Where actors understand law as a web rather than a
hierarchical system, we can expect them to turn away from the ambition
of principled solutions – valid throughout the system – and shift towards
forms of practical, localized and perhaps provisional accommodation.
Inconsistencies within the law are then not so much elements to be
eliminated, but instead normal occurrences in an order of multiplicity
that need to be processed and navigated.106 As indicated by Broude’s
chapter on the many attitudes of actors towards the entangled legalities
they are confronted with, ‘navigating’ may in any event be a more
accurate description of the approach to legal reasoning appropriate in
this context. However, as Eckert astutely highlights in her contribution,
102
Teubner, ‘The King’s Many Bodies’, 765.
103
See D. Burchardt, ‘Intertwinement of Legal Spaces in the Transnational Legal Sphere’
(2017) 30 Leiden Journal of International Law 305–26.
104
This is the dominant perspective in, for example, N. Roughan and A. Halpin (eds), In
Pursuit of Pluralist Jurisprudence (Cambridge University Press, 2017).
105
See, e.g., de Sousa Santos, Toward a New Legal Common Sense.
106
See, e.g., H. P. Glenn, The Cosmopolitan State (Oxford University Press, 2013),
chapter 14; M. Del Mar, ‘Legal Reasoning in Pluralist Jurisprudence’, in N. Roughan
and A. Halpin (eds), In Pursuit of Pluralist Jurisprudence (Cambridge University Press,
2017), pp. 40–63; Taekema, ‘Between or beyond Legal Orders’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
such a ‘navigating’ stance (and the turn away from systematicity) may
well undermine one of the core sources of hope associated with the law –
the hope for coherence and universality.
This image suggests a deeper inquiry into the theoretical foundations
underlying competing imaginations of law. The contrast between ‘post-
modern’ (complex and multivalent) and ‘modern’ (orderly and systemic)
approaches to law is useful here,107 but other directions need to be
equally included. Anker’s chapter pursues one of these by showing how
Indigenous approaches to law have a more natural affinity to entangle-
ment, based on an ontology in which law is merely part of the relations
that already exist in symbiotic ecosystems. Taking into view such con-
ceptions of law, and more broadly those animating the historically
widespread forms of legal entanglement around the world, should help
to situate the image of law in the modern state that most of our
jurisprudence has been built around. This image – the systemic, hier-
archical and exclusive one – may well constitute the exception rather
than the rule.
1.7 Conclusion
If law is typically understood in the singular, our focus on entangled
legalities traces the implications of its appearance in the plural. Legal
multiplicity can, of course, just mean that different legal orders exist side
by side, with occasional contact, as in the traditional conflict-of-laws
paradigm between national legal orders. But where interactions are more
frequent and intense, the relations between different legal orders (and
more broadly, different bodies of norms) move to the centre of attention.
The legal order as such can then no longer be understood without an
account of the ways in which its different parts are entangled.108 In this
volume, we try to understand the contours of such entanglement better.
We ask what entanglement may mean in law and whether it can give a
useful account of the relations between different norms, especially in the
context of law beyond the state. We try to understand the forms through
which actors produce entanglement and what kind of order results from
their efforts at weaving norms from different origins together – or at
keeping them apart. Entanglement, in our approach, does not denote
107
See also D. Burchardt, ‘The Twilight of Legal Order? On the Current Challenges Faced
by the Concept of a Legal System’ (2018) 9 Transnational Legal Theory 110–46.
108
See also Chapters 14 and 16 by Culver and Giudice and Michaels.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
merely any form of de facto interaction; it seeks to capture linkages
expressed in discursive statements about the relation of multiple norms,
namely legal statements about the relations of different norms and
legal orders.
We conjecture that in today’s globalized world, the burgeoning multi-
plicity of norms has engendered more entanglement than was the norm
in the heyday of consolidated legal orders within nation states. In this
respect it may present greater similarities with pre-national legal orders
(and continuities with lesser-studied aspects of law in and around
modern states) and connect with a neo-medievalist interpretation of
the postnational constellation.109 Yet this volume is not intended to
present a comprehensive empirical picture of legal entanglements in
the past or present. It primarily seeks to draw attention to a phenomenon
that helps us to observe law differently, and to develop a better under-
standing of the causes, forms and consequences of this phenomenon.
With this, we hope to shift the focus, to begin to see entanglement as a
normal state of law, and initiate broader enquiries into entangled
legal orders.
109
See J. Friedrichs, ‘The Meaning of New Medievalism’ (2001) 7 European Journal of
International Relations 475–501.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
PART I
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
2
2.1 Introduction
Legal entanglements unfold in a curious space. They emerge in-between
different sets of norms, which are neither fully integrated nor kept
entirely apart.1 This position in-between various sets of norms is inher-
ently unstable, so that legal entanglements need ardent work of creation,
maintenance and constant renewal. Entanglements thus need to be made
and unmade by specific actors who are situated in historically shaped yet
malleable contexts where different sets of norms overlap and coincide.
This chapter focuses on the ways in which different actors entangle
international, state and non-state law in postcolonial societies. While
undoubtedly a very heterogeneous category that unavoidably escapes
reductionist attempts at homogenization, I argue that those places where
colonial powers institutionalized plural legal orders as explicit strategies
for the consolidation of their rule constitute a privileged site for the
investigation of entangled legalities. It is from these sites that systemic
images of law, as they have been problematized in Chapter 1, have been
forcefully attacked. As Renisa Mawani argues, ‘Law, in all of its plurality –
including Western, customary, and personal law – is conventionally
viewed as geographically situated and territorially bound to national
and imperial polities. What the comparative and transnational turn
has revealed is that law was also itinerant, moving with imperial author-
ities and colonial subjects, and connecting imperial jurisdictions in the
process.’2 Itinerant laws have thus produced historically grown legal
1
See the definitional discussion in Chapter 1.
2
R. Mawani, ‘Law and Colonialism’, in A. Sarat and P. Ewick (eds), The Handbook of Law
and Society (Wiley-Blackwell, 2015), pp. 417–32, at p. 426.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
entanglements affecting socio-legal dynamics in most of the world today.
Yet laws hardly ever travel by themselves.
This chapter consequently analyses (some of ) the actors that make law
move and the dynamics in which they seek to make and unmake certain
legal connections. Focusing on judges and activists of non-governmental
organizations (NGOs), it identifies three modes in which dynamics of
distancing and approximation between different sets of norms can unfold:
denial, deferral and translation. Whereas denial refers to a state where
empirically existing entanglements are acknowledged but their legal as well
as normative validity is denied, deferral denotes a situation of precarious
balance in which a given relationship between interwoven sets of norms
cannot be altered, as this would leave one or more of the involved parties
deeply dissatisfied. Thriving on imprecision and ambiguity, the politics of
deferral thus denotes a strategy of leaving the final arrangements between
different bodies of norms open and unsettled. Finally, rather than aiming
to unmake entanglements, as in the case of denial, or postponing conclu-
sive settlements between competing sets of norms, as in the case of
deferral, translation refers to the proactive transformation of norms that
occurs as they move back and forth between different contexts. In all three
modes – denial, deferral and translation – multiple normativities do not
merely coexist but are brought to life and are related to each other through
the ardent work of individual actors. They are the main protagonists of this
chapter.
After having discussed the ways in which colonial legacies have his-
torically shaped and continue to strongly affect entanglements between
international, state and non-state law in postcolonial spaces (Section 2.2),
I turn to the discussion of denial, deferral and translation as three distinct
modes through which actors seek to navigate highly complex entangled
legal landscapes (Section 2.3). The remainder of the chapter then turns to
the analysis of the dynamics in which legalities become entangled in
Bangladesh as a postcolonial space par excellence (Section 2.4). More
precisely, I focus on three instances to illustrate these dynamics: first, the
Supreme Court’s attempt to ban Islamic fatwas in 2001 (denial); second,
the violent protests this has triggered and the subsequent decision of the
Appellate Division of the Supreme Court to stay the verdict for over a
decade (deferral); and third, the work of local activists who, regardless of
constitutional developments, seek to carve out emancipatory spaces for
marginalized people by simultaneously drawing on multiple normative
registers, including Islamic and international human rights norms
(translation).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
2.2 Colonial Entanglements
Today’s legal entanglements unfold in long historical trajectories in
which colonial encounters have played a decisive role.3 On the one hand,
law was a key instrument of colonial rule. It was, in the words of Martin
Chanock, ‘the cutting edge of colonialism, an instrument of the power of
an alien state and part of the process of coercion’.4 As an instrument of
coercion, law was crucial for the facilitation of the extraction of land,
labour and mineral resources from the colonized as well as for the
organization of highly unequal trade networks and market exchanges.5
Yet beyond its function as a tool for domination, Sally Engle Marry has
argued that law also had constitutive effects; it not only enabled extrac-
tion but also ‘transformed conceptions of time, space, property, work,
marriage, and the state’.6 Embedded in broader systems of domination,
colonial laws thus significantly altered not only the material infrastruc-
tures of colonized societies but also deeply transformed diverse systems
of knowledge deployed to navigate various aspects of everyday life. While
colonial projects varied significantly across time and space, as well as
between different colonizing empires, most, if not all, European colonial
projects operated through the making and unmaking of legal entangle-
ments whose shape and direction were frequently the subjects of intense
debate in both the colonies and the metropoles. In these debates, argu-
ments ranged from the wholesale transfer of metropolitan laws to the
wide-ranging reliance on seemingly indigenous laws in systems of indir-
ect rule. Yet even in the latter case, colonialism’s legal entanglements had
far-reaching effects on colonized societies. Rather than simply relying on
pre-existing ‘traditional’ or ‘customary’ authority, colonial projects oper-
ating through various forms of indirect rule strongly altered Indigenous
legal forums. Importantly, the kind of legal pluralism that emerged and
continues to significantly shape legal dynamics in most of the world
today was thus not a factual state of affairs but a project to be realized.
As Lauren Benton argues, ‘colonial powers sought simultaneously to
3
For an extended version of this argument, see also T. Berger, ‘The “Global South” as a
Relational Category: Global Hierarchies in the Production of Law and Legal Pluralism’
(forthcoming) Third World Quarterly.
4
M. Chanock, Law, Custom, and Social Order: The Colonial Experience in Malawi and
Zambia (Cambridge University Press, 1985), p. 4.
5
J. L. Comaroff, ‘Reflections on the Colonial State, in South Africa and Elsewhere: Factions,
Fragments, Facts and Fictions’ (1998) 4 Social Identities 321–61, at 325.
6
S. E. Merry, ‘Law and Colonialism’ (1991) 25 Law & Society Review 889–922, at 890–1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
establish limited jurisdiction and to reinforce – and in some cases create –
Indigenous legal forums. As with indirect rule, legal pluralism as a
colonial project often required the creation of “traditional” authority
and the reification of legal practices and sources of law that had existed
formerly only as fluid elements of a flexible legal process.’7
While the constitutive effects of colonial laws on colonized societies
have been carefully documented, recursive effects on the colonizing
societies have received less attention. In the legal histories of Western
Europe and North America, narratives of autonomous legal evolutions
still predominate. Yet the constitutive effects of colonial encounters cut
both ways. Although highly unequal, these encounters did not merely
constitute the unilateral imposition of legal templates. Instead, recent
scholarship has shown how even core aspects of European legal systems
remain poorly understood if conceptualized without the transnational
entanglements in which they emerged. Rather than being only peripheral
to legal developments in Europe, colonies frequently had to serve as
laboratories for legal innovation and new regulatory techniques. As
John Comaroff has argued, ‘the terrain of the colonized became a testing
ground from which emanated new lawfare, new technologies of order
and regulation. These sometimes confined themselves to the colonial
frontier itself. But sometimes they were taken back to the metropole,
there to alter its social lineaments.’8 At times, the alterations that resulted
from the retransfer of legal innovation to the metropole were far-
reaching. One example is the legal institution of property as a corner-
stone of liberal social and political orders developing in Western Europe.
As Brenna Bhandar has shown, the emergence and current shape of
modern property laws in the United Kingdom are inseparable from
colonial expansions since the eighteenth century.9 In her account, the
validation of formal ownership via the registration of land titles in state-
regulated regimes institutionally emerged in the colonies of South
Australia and British Colombia, long before a similar regime became
implemented in the United Kingdom on a national scale.10 Perhaps
7
L. Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–1900
(Cambridge University Press, 2002), p. 128.
8
J. L. Comaroff, ‘Colonialism, Culture, and the Law: A Foreword’ (2001) 26 Law & Social
Inquiry 305–14, at 311.
9
B. Bhandar, Colonial Lives of Property: Law, Land, and Racial Regimes of Ownership
(Duke University Press, 2018).
10
Ibid., pp. 77–114.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
ironically, the subsequent prevalence of private property as a formally
sanctioned, state-recognized institution became a key marker of civiliza-
tional achievements while, conversely, its absence turned into a key
justificatory trope for colonial settlements.11 The ensuing ‘racial regimes
of ownership’, as Bhandar aptly calls them, fundamentally shaped pro-
cesses of social and political transformation in both the colonies and the
metropoles. At an equally fundamental level, Nasser Hussain has shown
how notions of the rule of law, and exceptions to this rule of law in terms
of emergency powers, were at the heart of nineteenth-century colonial
governance in India and Jamaica, which, in turn, decisively ‘affected the
development of Western legality’.12 These accounts of the entangled
legalities in which modern notions of property as well as ‘the rule of
law’ as cornerstones of legal systems emerged powerfully undermine
inward-looking narratives of teleological (legal) development in either
the Global North or the Global South.
11
C. W. Mills, The Racial Contract (Cornell University Press, 1997).
12
N. Hussain, The Jurisprudence of Emergency: Colonialism and the Rule of Law (University
of Michigan Press, 2003), p. 3.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
provided, buildings erected’.13 Second, transnational entanglements
also continue shaping the operation of non-state legal systems. These
entanglements stem from various sources, including (again) inter-
national donor organizations that have recently rediscovered non-state
justice institutions as seemingly ‘local’ and ‘authentic’ avenues for the
promotion of human rights and the rule of law.14 Yet diaspora commu-
nities also entangle non-state justice institutions in broader webs of
conflict resolution beyond the confines of the nation state, thus embed-
ding seemingly local courts in wider networks of normative and legal
reasoning.15 Finally, state and non-state law in postcolonial contexts are
not only transnationally embedded but also interact with each other.
The ensuing entanglements can take various forms. They can surface as
formal legal integration, for example, when non-state justice institu-
tions are recognized by state authorities under conditions of adherence
to certain substantive and/or procedural requirements. In addition,
entanglements can also emerge through officials performing functions
across different systems. Marlies Bouman provides a powerful example
of such entanglement in her analysis of the complicity of police officers
in the facilitation of non-state justice in Botswana, where ‘chiefly courts
are in fact tolerated, or even supported, by the official police forces,
although their adjudication activities are in violation of various national
laws’.16 Beyond formal integration, state and non-state law thus also
become entangled in quotidian practices of conflict resolution.
What emerges in these entanglements is a dynamic movement of
approximation and distancing, as actors navigate the complex space
in-between state and non-state law. As argued in Chapter 1, this
space in-between emerges as entanglements ‘[are often] characterized
by a dialectical dynamic – one in which actors favour proximity between
different bodies of norms but they also seek a certain distance, and they
13
D. Desai and M. Woolcock, ‘Experimental Justice Reform: Justice for the Poor: Lessons
from the World Bank and Beyond’ (2015) 11 Annual Review of Law and Social Science
155–74, at 163.
14
T. Berger, ‘Global Village Courts: The United Nations and the Bureaucratization of Non-
state Justice in the Global South’, in R. Niezen and M. Sapignoli (eds), Palaces of Hope:
The Anthropology of International Organizations (Cambridge University Press, 2017),
pp. 198–219.
15
A. Hoque, ‘Land, Development and the Political Class: In a Translocal “Londoni” Village’
(2020) 54 Contributions to Indian Sociology 215–35.
16
M. Bouman, ‘A Note on Chiefly and National Policing in Botswana’ (1987) 19 Journal of
Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law 275–300, at 291.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
thus construe the relation as neither strict separation nor full integration
into one order’. In what follows, I introduce three distinct modes in
which the dynamics of entangling (and disentangling) legalities can
unfold: denial, deferral and translation. Denial constitutes a radical form
of distancing. It does not concern so much the repudiation of the actual
existence of the entanglements of different sets of norms as empirical
phenomena but denies their legal validity as much as their normative
desirability. Entangled legalities are thus portrayed as pathologies to be
overcome by the actors involved. In the case of entanglements between
state and non-state law, denial as a way of (almost) unmaking entangle-
ments frequently relies on teleological narratives reproducing rather than
challenging idealized notions of law as a unitary and coherent system.
Interestingly, the denial of one set of entanglements might well coincide
with simultaneous demands for new but different entanglements. Liberal
critics of the pathologies of non-state institutions, for example, often rely
on international norms concerning human rights to make their case for
severing the ties between state law and its local non-state counterparts. In
these cases, entangled legalities are evaluated against the backdrop of a
spatial imagination in which ‘the international’ is seen as the reservoir of
normatively desirable order, whereas ‘the local’ becomes the source of
backwardness, poverty and strife.17 State law is sought to be entangled
with the former, also to distance it from the latter.
In contrast to the denial of legal entanglements, deferral aims at
keeping a precarious balance between different forces in place. Often this
involves undermining aspirations to unity and coherence usually associ-
ated with state law. Instead of producing certainty, the politics of deferral
flourishes in the realm of the uncertain and undecided. It enables cohab-
itation precisely because it does not conclusively settle issues or conflicts,
which cannot be settled, or cannot be settled in a way acceptable to all
parties involved. Noah Salomon provides a striking example of the
politics of deferral in his analysis of ‘The Ruse of Law’ in Sudan.
Analysing the politics of religious diversity in the 1990s, he shows how,
in the run-up to the 2005 Comprehensive Peace Agreement, only the
suspension of the questions of applicability of Islamic religious principles
to non-Muslims enabled progress in otherwise stalled negotiations
between the north and the south. In Salomon’s words, in the negotiations
it seemed ‘that the consensus was that the building of a state that respects
17
R. Rao, Third World Protest: Between Home and the World (Oxford University Press,
2010), p. 45.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
religious diversity was only possible in spite of the law – that is, when the
law was unequally or inconsistently applied – and not by crafting a law
that would be acceptable to all’.18 Here, a unitary and consistent legal
system is deliberately eschewed for inconsistency and a status of deferred
legal certainty. Interestingly, the resulting uncertainty is often a source of
stability rather than chaos. While scholars operating within the kind
of unitary images of law outlined in Chapter 1 unavoidably understand
uncertainty as a source of trouble and strife, the notion of legal entangle-
ments opens the analytical space to appreciate the stabilizing function of
uncertainty. Precisely because the conflictual relationship between differ-
ent sets of norms is not brought into hierarchical order but is kept
open and thus dynamic (or ‘uncertain’), entangled legalities can have
de-escalating effects in situations where seemingly irreconcilable differ-
ences coincide.
The third mode through which actors navigate entangled legalities is
translation. Rather than aiming to unmake entanglements, as in the case
of denial, or postponing specific settlements between competing sets of
norms (as with deferral), translation refers to the proactive transform-
ation of norms that occurs as they move back and forth between different
contexts. Its focus is less on conceptualizing the ways in which different
sets of norms are temporarily coupled or decoupled but rather on the
myriad ways in which external ideas enter specific sets of norms.
Translations usually involve two kinds of change that occur simultan-
eously.19 On the one hand, the content of norms changes, at times quite
considerably. As Walter Benjamin argued in his seminal reflection of
‘The Task of the Translator’, translations are inherently creative as much
as productive processes. Instead of simply transferring ideas from one
language (or one context) into another, translations constitute proactive
innovations of new meanings. This, in turn, challenges the idea of ‘the
original’ as an authoritative reference point to which any translation
would need to seek as close a proximity as possible. Instead, proximity
in meaning might well arise from a seeming distance to the original. In
the beautifully poetic words of Benjamin, ‘no translation would be
possible if, in accord with its ultimate essence, it were to strive for
18
N. Salomon, ‘The Ruse of Law: Legal Equality and the Problem of Citizenship in a
Multireligious Sudan’, in W. F. Sullivan, R. A. Yelle and M. Taussig-Rubbo (eds), After
Secular Law (Stanford University Press, 2011), pp. 200–20, at p. 203.
19
T. Berger, Global Norms and Local Courts: Translating the Rule of Law in Bangladesh
(Oxford University Press, 2017).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
similarity to the original. For in its continuing life, which could not be so
called if it were not the transformation and renewal of a living thing, the
original is changed.’20 On the other hand, as the content of norms
changes, the contexts in which they are translated are also altered. In
processes of translation as well as in instances of denial and deferral, the
boundaries of Razian legal systems, both inwards and outwards, become
rather fuzzy. To illustrate the modes of denial, deferral and translation,
the remainder of this chapter turns to the analysis of entangled legalities
in contemporary Bangladesh.
20
W. Benjamin, ‘The Translator’s Task’ (1997) 10 TTR: traduction, terminologie, rédaction
151–65, at 155.
21
C. Bell, ‘Kissinger in Retrospect: The Diplomacy of Power-Concert?’ (1977) 53
International Affairs 202–16.
22
D. Lewis, Bangladesh: Politics, Economics, and Civil Society (Cambridge University Press,
2011).
23
S. White, ‘NGOs, Civil Society, and the State in Bangladesh: The Politics of Representing
the Poor’ (1999) 30 Development and Change 307–26.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
assertion that Hindus and Muslims constituted two different nations and
consequently ought to inhabit distinct nation states, Pakistan emerged as
a bifurcated state with two geographically disconnected wings, separated
by more than 1,000 kilometres of Indian territory. In many ways an
unviable political project from the outset, tensions in Pakistan quickly
rose, especially between the eastern and western wings. Escalating over
questions of political representation, the distribution of resources and –
above all – national language, these tensions resulted in a short but
bloody war of independence in 1970–1, leaving between one and three
million dead and more than ten million refugees in neighbouring India.
Based on an ethnolinguistic nationalism built around the Bengali lan-
guage as the most decisive marker of identity for the inhabitants of what
was then still East Pakistan, the independence movement sought to
undermine Pakistan’s raison d’être as the homeland for all Muslims on
the subcontinent by advocating a secular rather than religious identity for
the future state-to-be. After the surrender of the Pakistani troops,
following Indian aerial intervention in December 1971, Sheikh Mujibur
Rahman and the Awami League as leaders of the independence move-
ment consequently established secularism, together with socialism,
nationalism and democracy, as constitutive principles of the newly born
state of Bangladesh.24
Since its inception the state of Bangladesh has existed in a web of
multiple, at times overlapping, entangled legalities. From the British
colonial state in India, it inherited a bifurcation between secular Civil
and Criminal Codes and a set of religious personal laws governing
questions of marriage, divorce, inheritance and the custody of children.
While based on religious precepts, the colonial state heavily intervened in
the interpretation of religion. Relying on orientalist scholarship and
excessively scripture-based understandings of religion, the colonial state
codified religious laws whose content diverged significantly from the
quotidian practices of (religious) legal interpretation in India. As
Michael Anderson has argued, ‘colonial administrators may never have
changed Islamic legal arrangements quite so profoundly as when they
were trying to preserve them’.25 Departing from the colonial interpret-
ation of religious law, the Pakistani state also engaged in substantial
24
W. van Schendel, A History of Bangladesh (Cambridge University Press, 2009).
25
M. R. Anderson, ‘Islamic Law and the Colonial Encounter in British India’, in D. Arnold
and P. Robb (eds), Institutions and Ideologies: A SOAS South Asia Reader (Curzon Press,
1993), pp. 165–85, at p. 169.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
religious law reform. From the Pakistani period, the postcolonial state in
Bangladesh inherited the 1961 Muslim Family Laws Ordinance (MFLO).
In many ways a radical piece of legislation, the MFLO altered inheritance
patterns for orphaned grandchildren in ways considered by many reli-
gious authorities in direct contravention of Shar’ia law.26 Until today, this
provision of the MFLO is subject to vocal protest, most recently during
large-scale rallies of the Hefazat-e-Islami movement in Dhaka in 2013,
demanding (in addition to twelve further points) the ‘abolishment of
anti-Islamic inheritance laws’. Besides altering the law of inheritance, the
MFLO also established a central role for the state in the administration of
Muslim family law.
It prohibits the practice of so-called ‘verbal divorce’ (effected by a
husband uttering the word ‘talaq’ three consecutive times). Under the
MFLO, all Muslim marriages have to be registered with the state, and
any divorce of such marriage can only take effect if submitted in
writing to the chairman of the local administrative council and
subject to a ninety-day mediation phase aimed at the restoration of
marital life. While welcomed by women’s rights organizations, the
MFLO provoked severe resistance among the community of religious
scholars in Pakistan who understood it to be a direct attack on their
authority.27
From the liberation movement, the state inherited the initial emphasis
on secularism as a foundation of the state. Yet this notion of secularism
was always subject to interpretation and contestation. Between 1975 and
1991, Bangladesh was governed by two military dictatorships, both of
which deployed religious language as a legitimating device.28 The first
dictator, General Ziaur Rahman, changed the principle of secularism to
an emphasis on ‘absolute trust and faith in the Almighty Allah’ in the
preamble as well as a new subclause (1A) of the Bangladeshi constitution.
The second one, General Husain Md. Ershad, altered the constitution in
1988 by introducing the Eighth Amendment that declared Islam to be the
26
M. J. Nelson, In the Shadow of Shari’ah: Islam, Islamic Law, and Democracy in Pakistan
(Columbia University Press, 2011); M. J. Nelson, ‘Inheritance Unbound: The Politics of
Personal Law Reform in Pakistan and India’, in S. Khilnani, V. Raghavan and A. K.
Thiruvengadam (eds), Comparative Constitutionalism in South Asia (Oxford University
Press, 2012), pp. 219–46.
27
M. Ahmad, ‘The MFLO of Pakistan’ (1993) 10 International Journal on World Peace
37–46, at 42–3.
28
A. Riaz, ‘“God Willing”: The Politics and Ideology of Islamism in Bangladesh’ (2003) 23
Comparative Studies of South Asia, Africa and the Middle East 301–20.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
state religion.29 Ershad’s amendment encountered strong resistance from
both secular and religious forces within the country, as the strongest
Islamic political party, the Jamaat-e-Islami, denounced Ershad’s move as
‘hypocritical’ and ‘not genuinely Islamic’.30 A 2010 Supreme Court
verdict reinstated secularism as a cornerstone of the constitution and
banned Islamic parties.31 Through the following Fifteenth Amendment
of the Constitution in 2011, Article 1A was deleted and replaced by
Article 8 (1) stating that ‘[t]he principles of nationalism, socialism,
democracy, and secularism [. . .] shall constitute the fundamental prin-
ciples of state policy’. At the same time, however, Article 2A was left
intact, declaring that ‘[t]he state religion of the Republic is Islam, but the
State shall ensure equal status and equal right in the practice of the
Hindu, Buddhist, Christian and other religions’.32
Finally, the complex constitutional history also encompasses ongoing
transnational entanglements in the form of obligations under inter-
national treaties. Bangladesh has signed the Convention on the
Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW,
signed in 1984), the Convention on the Rights of the Child (signed in
1990), the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural
Rights (signed in 1998) and the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (signed in 2000), all of which have become powerful tools
in the hands of Bangladeshi human rights organizations in their struggles
against myriad forms of discrimination. In these struggles, local organ-
izations need to navigate a complex web of entangled legalities, compris-
ing a discrete set of state laws, often still exhibiting the imprint of colonial
authorship, various forms of local non-state law, including religious
29
Ershad’s amendment also further ‘indigenized’ national identify by changing the spelling
of ‘Bengali’ to ‘Bangla’ and ‘Dacca’ to ‘Dhaka’.
30
Riaz, ‘God Willing’, 308–11.
31
This decision currently seems highly controversial as in the run-up to the national
elections in January 2014, the Election Commission has withdrawn the registration of
the Jamaat-e-Islami. A High Court verdict from November 2013 confirmed the deregis-
tration of the Jamaat-e-Islami. The judges argued that although Islam is the state religion
under article (2A), ‘the Jamaat had misinterpreted Islam from its inception’ (quoted in
The Dhaka Tribune, 4 November 2013).
32
Constitution of the People’s Republic of Bangladesh, P.O. No. 76 of 1972, 4 November
1972, website of the Bangladeshi Ministry of Law, http://bdlaws.minlaw.gov.bd/sections_
detail.php?id=367§ions_id=24549, accessed 7 November 2013. This is the slightly
altered version of 2011. The earlier version from 1988 read: ‘[t]he state religion of the
Republic is Islam, but other religions may be practiced in peace and harmony in the
republic’. Quote taken from www.law.emory.edu/ifl/legal/bangladesh.htm, accessed on
7 November 2013.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
precepts and customary conventions, and a liberal international archi-
tecture at least partially anchored in state law.
In what follows, I analyse denial, deferral and translation as three
modes in which human rights organizations seek to navigate these
entanglements. To scrutinize these processes of entangling and disentan-
gling legalities, I focus in particular on the question of the legal status of
fatwa. While the precise definition of fatwa is itself subject to ongoing
debates, at its most basic fatwa refers to a non-binding decision issued by
a learned religious authority on a point of Islamic law or practice.33 Yet
who exactly qualifies as a learned scholar authorized to issue fatwa, the
weight of fatwa in light of competing legal precepts and the precise scope
of which kinds of questions are actually governed and governable under
Islamic law remain subjects of contention, and not only in Bangladesh.34
In Bangladesh, these questions gained judicial salience with a High Court
judgement issued in 2001.
2.5 Denial
On 1 January 2001, a Division Bench of the High Court Division of the
Supreme Court of Bangladesh delivered what many national and inter-
national observers at the time considered to be a landmark judgement.
On its own initiative and without having been approached by any party,
the court has issued a suo moto ruling in reaction to a news item reported
in the Bangladeshi newspaper Daily Bangla Bazar Patrika on 2 December
2000. The ruling questioned local authorities of Naogaon district
regarding their failure to act against an illegal fatwa. The fatwa had
directed a young woman of Naogaon to undertake an intervening mar-
riage after an alleged verbal divorce to restore marital life with her
previous husband. According to the news report, Saiful Chunnu of
Naogaon village had pronounced ‘talaq’ (‘divorce’) to his wife Shahid
more than a year ago, yet the couple had reconciled and continued
marital life. As Saiful Chunnu spent a few days away from their village
on family business, a neighbour claimed to have heard the pronounce-
ment of ‘talaq’ and issued a fatwa directing Shahid to undergo a so-called
33
D. Siddiqi, ‘Islam, Gender, and the Nation: The Social Life of Bangladeshi Fatwas’, in
D. Heath and C. Mathur (eds), Communalism and Globalization in South Asia and Its
Diaspora (Routledge, 2011), pp. 181–203, at pp. 200–1.
34
W. B. Hallaq, The Impossible State: Islam, Politics, and Modernity’s Moral Predicament
(Columbia University Press, 2013).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
hilla (intervening) marriage with another man from the village. Upon his
return and learning about the forced hilla marriage, Saiful Chunnu
refused to continue their marriage and sent Shahid back to her father’s
house. While highlighting the persistence of patriarchal power relations,
the case is rather unambiguous in the legal terms of the state. Both
intervening hilla marriages and verbal divorce (whether by uttering
‘talaq’ once or thrice) are in violation of Section 7 of the MFLO; in
addition, causing people to believe that they will become objects of
Divine displeasure is punishable under Section 508 of the Penal
Code.35 The court’s condemnation of the local authorities’ failure to act
is thus neither surprising nor controversial.
While singling out the fatwa case from Naogaon, the court’s verdict
unfolds against the backdrop of deeper societal controversies over fatwa
practices. As Dina Siddiqui has shown, since the early 1990s approxi-
mately thirty-five to sixty fatwa cases have annually gained attention in
the national press.36 This does not mean that fatwa are a recent phenom-
enon; it only indicates the increased visibility of certain kinds of fatwa
verdicts after the return to electoral democracy in 1990 and the correla-
tive improvements in freedom of speech. The fatwa cases that attract the
attention of a larger audience often involve extreme displays of violent
enforcement, frequently targeted against women’s bodies. One of the first
fatwa cases discussed at the national level was the case of Nurjahan in
1993. After having obtained a divorce from her first husband, Nurjahan
rejected the proposal of an influential member of the village community
and decided, instead, to marry a landless youth of her choice. Enraged by
the refusal, the influential village elder initiated a shalish court and
prompted a local religious figure to issue a fatwa against Nurjahan and
her second husband for adultery. Although the same figure had previ-
ously verified the state-sanctioned divorce of Nurjahan and her first
husband, he subsequently disputed the validity of the divorce papers
produced in the shalish session, in which Nurjahan, her husband and
the guests attending their wedding party were condemned to acts of
severe public humiliation. Based on her meticulous reconstruction of
the complexity of local power structures, Dina Siddiqui has shown how
35
F. Pereira, ‘Introduction’ (2002) 4 Interventions 212–14; S. Hossain, ‘High Court Nails
Fatwa’ (2002) 4 Interventions 220–3; A.-U. Zaman, ‘Fatwa and the High Court’ (2002) 4
Interventions 233–6.
36
D. Siddiqi, ‘Crime and Punishment: Laws of Seduction, Consent, and Rape in Bangladesh’
(2011) 1 Social Difference Online 46–54, at 47.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
Nurjahan’s case cannot be read exclusively through the lens of seeming
adherence to religious moral precepts. Instead, she shows how the fatwa
aims to reaffirm intersecting power structures, including patriarchal
control and class domination.37 Yet these complexities are frequently
lost in both liberal international and secular-nationalist narratives of
fatwa violence. As Siddiqui argues, in Bangladesh:
Understandings of the ‘fatwa-frenzy’ were also overdetermined by the
specific trajectory of secular nationalism [. . .], in which Islam had always
been the Other of the nation. Within this context, fatwas came to signify
the contamination of secular national space by the backwardness of
religious law. Accordingly, fatwas could be read as antinational phenom-
ena attached to Islam, rather than one located in the complex conditions
of modernity.38
37
Siddiqi, ‘Islam, Gender, and the Nation’, p. 189.
38
D. Siddiqi, ‘Transnational Feminism and “Local” Realities: The Imperiled Muslim
Woman and the Production of (In)Justice’ (2011) 9 Hawwa 76–96, at 81.
39
Quoted in the Daily Star Law Report, 7 January 2001. Reproduced in ‘The Fatwa in
Question Is Wrong’ (2002) 4 Interventions 228–32, at 231.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Before parting with this matter, we find it necessary to answer a question
as to why a particular group of men, upon either getting education from
maddrasah or forming a religious group, are becoming fanatics with
wrong views. There must be defect in their education and their attitude.
As a short measure, we recommend that study of Muslim Family Laws
Ordinance must be introduced in all schools and that the Khatibs in all
the mosques must be directed to discuss the Ordinance in their Friday
sermons. As a long-term measure, we recommend an unified education
system and an enactment to control the freedom of religion subject to law,
public order and morality within the scope of Article 4 (1) of the
Constitution. The State must define and enforce public morality. It must
educate society.40
40
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
2.6 Deferral
After the Supreme Court had stayed the verdict in January 2001, initially
for a mere six weeks, it took more than a decade before the legal status of
fatwa was to reappear at the court. Confronted with hardened positions
between secular-nationalist and religious camps, the court decided not to
pursue the case further. Instead of aiming for legal clarity, the court
settled for a politics of deferral where the legal status of fatwa remained
undecided. Initially, the deferral coincided with a change in political
climate. While the original judgement was passed during the last days
of the Awami League-led government, in October 2001 the Bangladesh
Nationalist Party (BNP), in coalition with three smaller parties, including
religious ones, won the elections. Although recent scholarship has shown
how the ideological differences between the Awami League and the BNP
seem exaggerated in both public imagination and scholarly discourse,41
the BNP’s return to power in 2001 did amplify the voice of small yet
highly organized Islamic political parties. Operating in a precarious
balance of different political forces, the erstwhile very vocal defendants
of the so-called ‘fatwa ban’ settled for a strategy of deferral, especially at
the constitutional level. While the case seemed to be lingering and almost
forgotten, its deferral was actually not caused by inaction but hard work,
requiring myriad interventions to make sure that no judgement was
forthcoming. One close observer and longstanding participant in the
judicial contestation over the status of fatwa summarized the politics of
deferral that emerged as follows:
And then [after the Supreme Court had stayed the verdict in 2001], we
ran a ten-year job to make sure that this case did not get heard too early,
because at various points there were very worrying constructions of the
bench and so on – and we were worried that if the case got heard that we
would end up with a Supreme Court finding [. . .] saying that there is a
fundamental right to issue fatwa.42
41
M. Hassan and S. Nazneen, ‘Violence and the Breakdown of the Political Settlement: An
Uncertain Future for Bangladesh?’ (2017) 17 Conflict, Security & Development 205–23.
42
Interview by author with senior legal counsel, Dhaka, January 2012.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Court judgement, it declared fatwa legal, but only if it was (1) passed by a
‘learned person’, and (2) only applied to ‘religious matters’. Yet on both
of these important qualifications the judgement remained conspicuously
vague. It neither defined the ingredients necessary to qualify as a ‘learned
person’ nor delineated what precisely constituted a ‘religious matter’. The
ambiguity surrounding the judgement further increased as the Supreme
Court did not publish the full judgement until 2015, forty-four months
after the verdict had been actually passed and communicated as a brief
statement.43 When the full judgement was eventually published, it still
refrained from these crucial specifications of what qualifies ‘properly
educated persons’ to issue fatwa in ‘religious maters’, and what exactly
these religious matters comprised. Even as the Supreme Court formerly
settled the case, the politics of deferral thus continued, as the precise
status of fatwa within the complex legal architecture of Bangladesh
remained an unsettled question and open to competing interpretations.
While deferring the conclusive settlement on the constitutional status
of fatwa required the continuous work by the parties involved in the
case, it also allowed human right’s activists to disentangle the legal
condemnation of violence against women from broader questions
about the status of religious law. While these broader questions
remained deferred, the judgement nonetheless explicitly stated that
‘no punishment including physical violence or mental torture in any
form can be imposed or implicated on anybody in pursuance of [a]
fatwa’.44 The Supreme Court’s judgement thus overturned the High
Court’s decision to ban fatwa in 2001 but upheld another High Court
decision from 2010 on the illegality of extrajudicial punishment. This
2010 High Court decision, in turn, came in response to three writ
petitions filed by five prominent human rights organizations in
Bangladesh, the Bangladesh Legal Aid and Services Trust, Ain-o-
Shalish Kendro, Bangladesh Mahila Parishad, BRAC and Nijera Kori.
These organizations are exceptionally skilful socio-legal actors, and
their strategic choices have paved a distinct pathway to legal entangle-
ment. Most of the organizations had already been at the forefront of the
judicial process leading to the fatwa ban in 2001. A decade later, their
43
A. Sarkar, ‘Fatwa Must Not Violate Laws, SC Says in Full Verdict’, Daily Star, 26 January
2015, www.thedailystar.net/fatwa-must-not-violate-laws-61702.
44
Quoted in T. Huda, ‘Zero Tolerance for Fatwas that Violate Human Rights’, Daily Star,
23 December 2017, www.thedailystar.net/opinion/human-rights/zero-tolerance-fatwas-
violate-human-rights-1509055.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
writ petitions constitute an attempt at disentangling the inflection of
violence, often against women, from questions of Islam and Islamic law.
Starting from the observation that the first judgement declaring fatwa
illegal was ‘very poorly reasoned’, one human rights activist describes
how these five organizations at the time ‘thought that somehow we had
to clarify this whole question: what is a fatwa, what is not a fatwa, and
what is the nature of this violence? And to bring the conversation, the
discussion, the judicial exercise back to a discussion about the consti-
tution and law, rather than religion and religious rights. We had to take
it out of that space.’45 Taking the violence perpetrated against women
out of the space of contestations over religious-cum-legal authority is
an act of disentanglement. It aims to dissociate the pathologies of
patriarchal power structures in Bangladesh from questions of religious
rights within a constitutional framework. At the same time, while
disentangling questions of violence and questions of fatwa, the argu-
mentative architecture built carefully by the five human rights organ-
izations did include new entanglements with international norms. As
the activist already cited argues, in the final court hearing the organiza-
tions were very careful to advance the following argument:
we as Bangladeshi organisations working in Bangladesh within the frame-
work of the Bangladesh constitution, but also within the framework of
International Human Rights obligation that pertain on our government,
have this interpretation. Our interpretation is that we want to have a very
clear condemnation of the violence perpetrated in the name of fatwa. We
do not want a debate what is and is not fatwa under religious law, we are
not before a religious court, but before a constitutional court, so we want a
constitutional interpretation. Our constitution clearly says: all forms of
cruel and degrading punishment are prohibited.46
45
Interview by author with senior legal counsel, Dhaka, January 2012.
46
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
2.7 Translation
The processes of distancing and approximation analysed as ‘denial’ and
‘deferral’ in Sections 2.5 and 2.6 play out in a context of confrontation
between secular-nationalist and Islamic narratives deployed by different
actors to lay claims upon the state and its constitutional order. At times,
these claims have been laid quite violently, for example, in the repeated
physical attacks on secular women’s rights NGOs by seemingly religious
actors throughout the 1990s or in the equally violent crackdown on
members of the Jamaat-e-Islami by the seemingly secular Awami
League government in the run-up to the 2014 election. While the divid-
ing line between the religious and the secular is frequently staged in
exceedingly violent spectacles in Bangladesh, recent scholarship has cast
serious doubts on the social embeddedness of this divide. Analysing the
confrontation between religious actors and secular NGOs over questions
of women’s economic empowerment in rural areas throughout the 1990s,
Sarah White has shown how ‘the substance of the NGO–“Mullah”
confrontation lay indeed in the symbolic, or political, capital that each
side could derive from it, rather than this signifying any more structural
antagonism between “Islam” and the expansion of women’s economic
activity’.47 Analysing the multifaceted dynamics of entangled legalities in
rural Bangladesh thus requires moving beyond the confines of both
secular and religious elite discourses as they circulate in Dhaka’s higher
judicial institutions and national media outlets. In contrast to urban
elites, the grassroots-level fieldworker and activists in rural Bangladesh
often need to navigate significantly more complex legal landscapes that
eschew dichotomous confrontations between Islam and secular
nationalism.48
To carve out emancipatory spaces for poor and marginalized people,
and women in particular, activists in rural Bangladesh simultaneously
draw on multiple, often quite different, normative registers. While the
upper echelons of Bangladesh’s vibrant NGO sector frequently disregard
piety and religious registers as tools for local struggles, Elora
Shehabuddin has shown how grassroots-level staff of these organizations
regularly draw on religious arguments in their everyday work. The
47
S. C. White, ‘Beyond the Paradox: Religion, Family and Modernity in Contemporary
Bangladesh’ (2012) 46 Modern Asian Studies 1429–58, at 1441.
48
E. Shehabuddin, Reshaping the Holy: Democracy, Development, and Muslim Women in
Bangladesh (Columbia University Press, 2008), p. 30.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
examples she cites range from Islamic condemnations of violence against
women (for example by invoking the example of the Prophet
Mohammed) to religious sanctions for girls’ education and the use of
contraception.49 Often materially dependent on international funding,
this kind of grassroots-level activism in rural Bangladesh thus needs to
straddle the normative expectations of very different audiences.
Elsewhere, I have argued that the notion of translation offers a productive
way to capture the work local activists do in their attempts to straddle
these different normative expectations as well as the different legal
systems in which these expectations are embedded.50 Rather than distan-
cing or approximation, the notion of translation refers to the transform-
ation of legalities that occurs as norms move back and forth between
different contexts where they become embedded in deep webs of pre-
existing institutions, practices and normative aspirations. In what
follows, I use this notion of translation to illustrate a third mechanism
by which different legalities become entangled.
I analysed a series of such translations between 2011 and 2012
throughout my field research on the recursive interactions between
transnational liberal norms and local non-state justice institutions in
Bangladesh.51 Responding to a growing fatigue with conventional rule
of law reform programmes that exclusively target state institutions,
mostly in the Global South, non-state justice institutions have recently
reappeared on the agenda of international donor organizations as one
possible avenue for the promotion of human rights and the rule of law.
One of the largest projects this recent interest in non-state justice insti-
tutions has given rise to aims at ‘activating’ the village courts in
Bangladesh. The village court is a quasi-formal institution whose setup
and operational logic closely resembles the non-state institution of the
shalish. Yet, in contrast to the shalish, the state does recognize the village
courts as legitimate sites for the trial of minor civil and criminal cases if
they adhere to certain procedural requirements laid down in the
2006 Village Court Act. This focus on civil and criminal cases renders
the village courts a seemingly secular institution, as in Bangladesh (like in
India and Pakistan) the respective Civil and Criminal Codes are based on
secular law, whereas Family Law is based on religious sources codified by
the state, for example, in the MFLO discussed in Section 2.4. As several
49
Ibid., p. 102.
50
Berger, Global Norms and Local Courts.
51
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
representatives of international donor agencies confirmed throughout
my fieldwork, one key attraction of the village courts as sites for
interventions was precisely their seeming ability to bypass the
entire ‘fatwa problematique’ discussed in Sections 2.5 and 2.6.52 As they
understood the village courts as quasi-formal institutions dealing with
conflicts governed by secular law, they simply did not expect religious
arguments or religious authorities to figure prominently in their project
activities.
Contra their expectations, religion did figure prominently as the field-
workers and court assistants employed by local NGOs at grassroots levels
for the implementation of the project regularly engaged in vivid religious
argumentations. Many of these argumentations involved women’s stand-
ing in processes of conflict resolution, which – in turn – frequently
escaped neat distinctions between civil, criminal and family disputes.
Often, questions of physical insult or disputes over land ownership are
intimately tied to family conflicts, rendering distinctions between differ-
ent sets of state law difficult in practice. In reality, religious lines of
argument played important roles as the resolution of conflicts falling
under civil or criminal law repeatedly required the simultaneous inter-
vention in disputes within the realm of family law. In these interventions,
religious arguments were drawn upon. In the case of fatwa, for example,
many fieldworkers and court assistants argued that local religious author-
ities lacked the training to give binding interpretations of Islamic law.
Similarly, they emphasized the religious obligation of husbands to issue
security payments before marrying their wives (morhana) and main-
tained that verbal divorces without the state-prescribed ninety-days
mediation phase were, in fact, ‘Un-Islamic’. Ironically, while inter-
national donor agencies sought to strengthen quasi-formal institutions
for the resolution of civil and criminal conflicts, the fieldworkers and
court assistants implementing the project argued, in many ways, that
only the state had both the authority and the legitimacy to interpret
Islamic family law. These acts of translation entangle international and
local legalities in novel ways, thus allowing grassroots-level employees of
Bangladeshi NGOs to carve out participatory spaces for women in a
discursive environment otherwise characterized by a dichotomous con-
frontation between Islam and secular nationalism.
52
Interview by author with representative of the United Nations Development Program,
Dhaka, March 2012.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
,
2.8 Conclusions
As a paradigmatic developing country, Bangladesh exemplifies the com-
plexities of legal entanglements as they unfold in most of the world.
Indeed, as argued in Chapter 1, the ideal type of closed, coherent and
unitary legal systems that carefully guard their boundaries with clearly
defined reception norms while ordering internal plurality hierarchically
and unambiguously has been historically the exception rather than the
rule. Navigating complex and contradictory legal landscapes often
requires the mastery of ‘straddling practices’, in which the boundaries
between different sets of norms loosen at the edges and become more
fuzzy. As I have argued in this chapter, the conditions of postcolonial
statehood are highly conducive to zooming in on these fuzzy rather than
clearly demarcated boundaries between different legal systems.
Theorizing legal entanglements from the postcolonial space of
Bangladesh, I have identified three distinct modes in which actors seek
to forge specific entanglements between different sets of norms. In the
case of denial, empirically existing entanglements are acknowledged
while their normative and legal validity is denied. Deferral as a mode of
entanglement eschews fixity and, instead, thrives on ambiguity and
imprecision. Here, the precise relationship between different sets of
norms is deliberately left open by postponing a conclusive verdict on
their hierarchical order. In contrast to legal theorists who equate impre-
cision with disorder and instability, the empirical excavation of processes
of continued deferral as a mode of entanglement in Bangladesh has
shown how it actually can become a source of stability in situations
where a given relationship between different sets of norms should not
be altered without leaving at least one party deeply dissatisfied. Yet, as
I have shown, also keeping the final arrangements between competing
sets of norms unsettled requires continued and ardent work; the mere
fact that nothing seems to change is no indication of inaction but is
instead the product of continued legal labour by multiple actors, in the
case at hand primarily NGOs and representatives of religious institutions.
Like denial and deferral, translation as a mode of entangling legalities
also depends on the proactive work of individual actors. In translations,
the content of norms is transformed as they move back and forth
between different contexts. While resonating in the receiving context,
translations nonetheless retain the mark of the foreign, thus constituting
a particular kind of entanglement in which norms are neither fully
integrated nor wholly kept apart but made recognizable across different
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
contexts. Denial, deferral and translation constitute different pathways to
legal entanglements. As I have shown in this chapter, social and legal
conflicts do not, as frequently assumed in legal scholarship, unfold as
disputes over the precise meaning and interpretation of individual legal
norms. Instead, they also, and often even primarily, unfold as contesta-
tions over which of these pathways to take.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
3
To Be Is to Be Entangled
Indigenous Treaty-Making, Relational Legalities
and the Ecological Grounds of Law
3.1 Introduction
How are we entangled? I invite you to breathe in. Can you feel the air
enter your nostrils and lungs, and then be expelled? Try it again. With
some practice you may no longer feel ‘you’ and ‘the air’, but simply a
sensation that appears in consciousness. From this and a multitude of
other metabolic processes, your body is literally constructed and decon-
structed daily through exchanges – the activities of breathing, eating,
shedding – with your environment. At an atomic level, it is not even easy
to tell where the boundary between the self and the environment lies.
Between the electrons and the nucleus that make up the apparent solidity
of your skin is a distance the equivalent of something like that between
the Sun and Jupiter. Electrons that are ‘part of’ your skin can be dis-
charged in a current, and, indeed, have no distinct location (or other
definite properties) but exist as a set of probable states expressed as a
wave function (indeed, as energy).1
The human minds that find these aspects of quantum mechanics
counterintuitive have evolved, slowly and over millennia, a form of
intuition matched to the mechanics of what is visible and touchable,2
a musculoskeletal system adapted to gravity on earth, and a nervous
system capable of responding to prevalent threats and resources in
furtherance of survival. Generalized throughout ecosystems, this
1
M. Humphrey, P. Pancella and N. Berrah, Quantum Physics (Alpha Books, 2015),
chapter 9.
2
This may correspond to Newtownian physics or even earlier theories: see B. Sherrin,
‘Common Sense Clarified: The Role of Intuitive Knowledge in Physics Problem Solving’
(2006) 43 Journal of Research in Science Teaching 535–55.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
physical, chemical and biological interconnectivity entangles everything
from whales to weather patterns.3 The way things appear to us is a
product of an interaction of the properties of matter and motion with
our sensory-motor system (although we can play around with those
perceptions, as in the breathing meditation above). This ‘life of the body’
then proves integral to the development of even the most abstract of
conceptual schemas, whether because reasoning relies metaphorically on
basic physical properties like shape, size, distance, motion, up/down,
now/later, inside/outside and containment, or because, as a neuroscien-
tist might put it, ‘imagining and doing use a shared neural substrate’.4
That is, we learn to think together with human and non-human others;
through them, we humans co-constitute our ‘selves’. Forms – selves,
types, categories, concepts – are neither mind nor thing, say ecologists
of mind, but a process of pattern production and propagation in which
we participate with the rest of the world, both present and absent.5
Following the first order of physical interdependence, this second
order of semantic emergence from the material is also related to the
inseparability of observer and observed. For example, were we to measure
or observe the location of those electrons above, we would find that our
choice of apparatus affects the phenomenon that is observed, such as in
the famous wave–particle experiment for light.6 Interaction with labora-
tory equipment causes the wave function to collapse into a definite state.7
Further, to understand what an electron is, we would first need to
examine the material conditions that provide it with meaning and
some definite sense of existence; doing so, we would inevitably find a
network of humans and non-humans – scientists and lab technicians,
microscopes and particle accelerators, but also funding agencies,
3
K. Balaramen, ‘Whales Keep Carbon Out of the Atmosphere’, Scientific American,
11 April 2017, www.scientificamerican.com/article/whales-keep-carbon-out-of-the-atmos
phere/.
4
V. Gallese and G. Lakoff, ‘The Brain’s Concepts: The Role of the Sensory-Motor System in
Conceptual Knowledge’ (2005) 22 Cognitive Neuropsychology 455–79, at 456.
5
E. Kohn, How Forests Think: Towards an Anthropology beyond the Human (University of
California Press, 2013), pp. 20, 37. On constitutive absences, see T. W. Deacon, Incomplete
Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter (Norton, 2006), p. 3.
6
See R. Feynman, R. Leighton and M. Sands, The Feynman Lectures on Physics (Addison-
Wesley, 1965), Vol. 3, §1-4–§1-6, www.feynmanlectures.caltech.edu.
7
And once one aspect of that state is measured – its location, for instance – other of its
properties can no longer be determined, as per Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle: see
ibid., §1-8.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
manufacturers and policy-makers, as well as a shared system of signs and
representations.8
I have begun with the lessons of (to take them in rough order)
mindfulness, dialectics, quantum mechanics, ecology, phenomenology,
cognitive psychology, evolutionary semiotics, anthropological post-
humanism and actor-network theory to make the point that you and
I have multiple ways of grasping entanglement. However, my purpose in
this chapter is not to then notice that law is yet another ‘thing’ that
becomes entangled or is made by entanglement, although I hold this to
be sometimes a useful way of seeing the world. Socio-legal theory, for
example, has embraced the dialectic idea that ‘law’ and ‘society’ are co-
constituted through processes of argumentation, proof, naming and
claiming, record-keeping, monitoring and all forms of performance,
discipline, enactment, representation and discourse. Intersecting legal
orders may produce particular formulations of one another through
processes of ‘recognition’, on which social actors act, so that those actors
then become in some measure part of the changing reality of each of
those orders.9 Rather than entangled legalities, though, in this text I am
interested in legalities of entanglement – forms of legality adapted to the
ontological entanglement in which we find ourselves. It has been noted
that one reason for the various ecological crises we face is that dominant
forms of law have become dysfunctionally oblivious to human interde-
pendence with the living world.10 Seeking to understand or develop
legalities of entanglement engages with the normative project of develop-
ing what has been labelled ‘Earth jurisprudence’ or law imagined in
ecological terms.11
In this chapter, I would like to suggest ways in which many Indigenous
legalities provide examples of law borne out of entangled ways of being.
From where I am writing, in Canada, invoking Indigenous legalities also
engages with the normative project of settler-colonial reconciliation and
8
K. Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of
Matter and Meaning (Duke University Press, 2007), p. 22.
9
See K. Anker, Declarations of Interdependence: A Pluralist Approach to Indigenous Rights
(Ashgate, 2014).
10
F. Capra and U. Mattei, The Ecology of Law: Toward a Legal System in Tune with Nature
and Community (Berrett-Koehler Publications, 2015); K. Bosselman, The Principle of
Sustainability: Transforming Law and Governance, 2nd ed. (Routledge, 2016); F. Ost, La
Nature Hors la Loi, l’Ecologie à l’Épreuve du Droit (La Découverte, 1995).
11
P. Burdon (ed.), Exploring Wild Law: The Philosophy of Earth Jurisprudence (Wakefield
Press, 2011).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the call for the recognition of Indigenous law as law.12 Indeed, political
philosopher James Tully’s recent work on sustainable constitutionalism
would have us see that the ‘ecological problem’ and the ‘reconciliation
problem’ are intricately connected.13 The disembedding of European
peoples from their environments – produced by phenomena like the
enclosure of the commons and industrialization – and the colonizing
dispossession of Indigenous peoples were driven by similar forces and
ideologies.14 Indeed, some would go further and describe plantation
colonies as the historical engine for industrial capitalism and its eco-
logical fallout.15 In the present, efforts towards Indigenous reconciliation
are continually thwarted by the pressures of extractive economics, as well
as the assumption of state dominion over land through its monopoly
over sovereignty and the rule of law.16 So, on the one hand, reconciliation
cannot occur without a reckoning with the ecological pathologies of the
reigning legal, economic and political systems. On the other hand,
solutions to ecological crises that do not address the colonial suppression
of Indigenous law and knowledge, Tully argues, will ‘fail to discern and
realize a good, sustainable relationship [with the Earth] because such a
relationship is discovered and learned through practice. [. . .] Indigenous
peoples and their practical knowledge systems have co-evolved with the
ecosystems in which they have co-inhabited, learned from, shaped and
been shaped.’17
As state institutions and citizens grapple with the issue of how to
‘make space for’ and recognize Indigenous legal orders, a reverse formu-
lation of the question of coexistence appears that is much more deeply
challenging both to state sovereignty and its form of legality: how can
12
V. Napoleon and H. Friedland, ‘Gathering the Threads: Developing a Methodology for
Researching and Rebuilding Indigenous Legal Traditions’ (2015–16) 1 Lakehead Law
Journal 16–44, at 20.
13
J. Tully, ‘Reconciliation Here on Earth’, in J. Tully, J. Borrows and M. Asch
(eds), Resurgence and Reconciliation: Indigenous–Settler Relations and Earth Teachings
(University of Toronto Press, 2018).
14
See K. Polanyi, The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our
Times (Beacon Press, 2001) on the market society or V. Plumwood on a form of gendered
rationality in Feminism and the Mastery of Nature (Routledge, 1993) and Environmental
Culture: The Ecological Crisis of Reason (Routledge, 2002).
15
D. Haraway, ‘Anthropocene, Capitalocene, Plantationocene, Chthulucene: Making Kin’
(2015) 6 Environmental Humanities 159–65.
16
See H. King and S. Pasternak, Canada’s Emerging Indigenous Rights Framework:
A Critical Analysis (Special Report of the Yellowhead Institute, 2018), https://
yellowheadinstitute.org/rightsframework/.
17
Tully, ‘Reconciliation Here on Earth’, p. 84.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
newcomers find a place for themselves in Indigenous legal orders?18 It is
my argument that attempting to find such a place leads us to a different
take on both the reconciliation and the Earth jurisprudence project. First,
tentative answers to the question of coexistence require not simply trying
to understand the competitive overlap of Indigenous and non-
Indigenous legal orders, for example, as they vie for jurisdiction over
forestry or child protection matters, nor the mutual normative or ideo-
logical influences that may historically have created ‘intersocietal law’19
or now lead to entanglement in the nature of mutual impacts, transplants
and borrowings between legal traditions.20 Rather, these questions
require looking to the way Indigenous law speaks to the deeper onto-
logical entanglement in which all things – including Indigenous peoples,
newcomers and their legal orders – are implicated in each other. For the
Earth jurisprudence project, this engagement with Indigenous legalities
leads us away from mere intellectual recognition of symbiosis and plan-
etary limits and towards embodied practices of entanglement.
Beginning with a brief overview of Canadian history through the lens
of pluralist legal encounters, the centrepiece of which is the conclusion of
treaties between European colonial (and, post-1867, Canadian federal)
authorities and Indigenous peoples, I argue, borrowing a framework
developed by Anishinaabe legal scholar Aaron Mills, that such a view
largely relies on a contractual, and thus liberal, understanding of
legality.21 I then shift to exploring the legalities out of which
Indigenous practices of treaty-making emerged. As Robert Williams
Jr. puts it, treaties are ‘a way of imagining a world of human solidarity
18
See for instance, L. S. G. Finch, ‘The Duty to Learn: Taking Account of Indigenous Legal
Orders in Practice’, paper presented at the ‘Indigenous Legal Orders and the Common Law’
British Columbia Continuing Legal Education Conference (Vancouver, November 2012),
www.cerp.gouv.qc.ca/fileadmin/Fichiers_clients/Documents_deposes_a_la_Commission/P-
253.pdf, 20.
19
B. Slattery, ‘The Generative Structure of Aboriginal Rights’ (2007) 38 Supreme Court Law
Review 595–628; J. Webber, ‘Relations of Force, Relations of Justice’ (1995) 33 Osgoode
Hall Law Journal 623–60.
20
B. Miller, ‘An Ethnographic View of Legal Entanglements on the Salish Sea Borderlands’
(2014) 47 UBC Law Review 991–1023.
21
A. Mills, ‘What Is a Treaty? On Contract and Mutual Aid’, in J. Borrows and M. Coyle
(eds), The Right Relationship: Reimagining the Implementation of Historical Treaties
(University of Toronto Press, 2017). My objective is to bring that work to bear on the
theme of this volume, so that the difference between ‘entangled legalities’ and ‘legalities of
entanglement’ comes more sharply into focus.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
where we regard others as our relatives’.22 Following the lead of Williams
and a number of other Indigenous scholars, I understand treaty jurispru-
dence as growing out of a deep appreciation for entanglement as consti-
tutive of our being. Human treaties, if you like, are the reiteration of
similar patterns of interdependence beyond the human. Further, I have
learned that treaties were – and are – extended as invitations to new-
comers to enter into relations with the peoples of Turtle Island23 and the
broader webs of their connections with local ecologies. Responding to an
invitation confounds the colonial dynamics of recognition, in which
Indigenous law is rendered legible to state institutions or individuals;24
it is also different to simply stepping back or carving out a space for
Indigenous law so as to avoid appropriating what is not mine, because it
is about law as the practice of relationships rather than as an object of
knowledge or appropriation. Finally, the invitation to invigorate onto-
logical interdependence also has critical consequences not just for
rethinking the liberal monad of the contractual conception of treaties,
but for several other separations foundational to modern legal theory,
such as the division between culture and nature, mind and matter, and
subject and object. It gives me a way of drawing the lessons of entangle-
ment from above into a relational mode for law generally.
22
R. Williams, Linking Arms Together: Indian Treaty Visions of Law and Peace 1600–1800
(Routledge, 1999), p. 113.
23
A common name for North America deriving from widespread creation stories that
recount the emergence of the land from the back of a turtle.
24
See G. Coulthard, Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition
(University of Minnesota Press, 2014) and A. Simpson, Mohawk Interruptus: Political Life
across the Borders of Settler States (Duke University Press, 2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
early times, of Indigenous protocols by colonists as a strategic pathway to
mutual benefit. In conducting trade and diplomatic business, colonial
officials would give gifts, exchange wampum belts and perform abbrevi-
ated parts of the Haudenosaunee condolence ceremony for greeting
allies:25 these norms were likely adopted to ‘create space to come to a
preferred conclusion’.26 Conciliatory approaches led in some places to ad
hoc forms of criminal and civil justice that represented compromises
between differing conceptions of crime and punishment. For instance, in
New France, the individual responsibility for French habitants con-
fronted the Innu practice of compensating crimes like murder with goods
or human substitution.27 The emergent norm for intercultural murder in
New France for 150 years – that Aboriginal culprits would be delivered to
French authorities, who would then pardon them with the exchange of
ceremonial gifts – could be a connecting norm, ‘weaving together differ-
ent bodies of norms in order to come to a solution in a given case’.28
Again, in Krisch’s terms, we can see interface norms providing
for varying degrees of engagement. The Treaty of Albany from
1701 describes complimentary, but distinct, areas of jurisdiction in which
wrongs or injuries committed by the English or Dutch against Indians
would be punished by the governor at New York, and, conversely,
wrongs committed by ‘Indians belonging to the Sachims’ against the
English or Dutch would be punished by the Sachims.29 American law
similarly recognized limited tribal sovereignty and treated it as foreign
law subject to private international law rules.30 Elsewhere, the common
law ‘doctrine of continuity’ promoted the recognition of local Indigenous
‘customs’ within colonial legal categories and incorporated them as
25
M. Pomedli, ‘Eighteenth-Century Treaties: Amended Iroquois Condolence Rituals’
(1995) 19 American Indian Quarterly 319–39; A. Wallace and T. Powell, ‘How to Buy
a Continent: The Protocol of Indian Treaties as Developed by Benjamin Franklin and
Other Members of the American Philosophical Society’ (2015) 159 Proceedings of the
American Philosophical Society 251–81; J. R. Miller, Compact, Contract, Covenant:
Aboriginal Treaty-Making in Canada (University of Toronto Press, 2009), pp. 11–32.
26
See Chapter 1.
27
Webber, ‘Relations of Force and Relations of Justice’; R. White, The Middle Ground:
Indians, Empires, and Republics in the Great Lakes Region, 1650–1815 (Cambridge
University Press, 1991).
28
See Chapter 1.
29
J. Borrows and L. Rotman, Aboriginal Legal Issues: Cases, Materials and Commentary, 4th
ed. (LexisNexis, 2012), pp. 14–16.
30
M. Walters, ‘The “Golden Thread” of Continuity: Aboriginal Customs at Common Law
and Under the Constitution Act, 1982’ (1999) 44 McGill Law Journal 711–52.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
British law.31 The longstanding practice of making trade and diplomatic
agreements formalized into an official British treaty-making policy with
the Royal Proclamation of 1763, which provided for an ‘interface norm’
of consent for the settlement of lands occupied by Indigenous ‘nations’ –
such lands would only be settled if ‘ceded to or purchased by’ the Crown
at ‘some public Meeting or Assembly of the said Indians’.32 These so-
called ‘cession’ treaties extended from Ontario in the east to parts of
British Columbia in the west from the 1780s to 1921; their written texts
read as a transaction in which Indigenous parties promise to ‘cede,
release and surrender’ their lands to the Crown in exchange for small
reserves, contingent hunting and fishing rights over the remainder of
their territories, payments and other promises like the provision of
education or medicine. An earlier era of treaties secured ‘friendship’
between the British and their Indigenous allies.33 The undertakings of
the Royal Proclamation itself were the subject of the Treaty of Niagara in
1764, at which 2,000 representatives of twenty-four Indigenous Nations
from the eastern regions of North America gathered to ‘join hands’ in the
Covenant Chain of friendship and alliance, in continuity of such treaties
with European colonists dating back to the 1600s.34
Treaty-making thus constituted the central ‘interface norm’ for
Indigenous and colonial polities for an extended period. Later, the
balance of power shifted in favour of the Europeans. Following confeder-
ation in 1867 the Canadian state assumed jurisdiction over Indigenous
peoples as subjects, and instigated a policy of assimilation.35 After a
century or more of official state denial of the existence or relevance of
Indigenous law, the constitutional recognition of ‘Aboriginal and treaty
rights’ with the promulgation of s. 35 of the Canadian Constitution Act
in 1982 opened the door to wider consideration of the place of
Indigenous legal orders, jurisdiction and sovereignty in modern
Canada. For historic treaties, constitutional recognition has meant
31
J. Borrows, ‘With or Without You: First Nations Law (in Canada)’ (1996) 41 McGill Law
Journal 629–65.
32
King George III of England, Royal Proclamation issued 7 October 1763, https://exhibits
.library.utoronto.ca/items/show/2470.
33
Such as the ‘Covenant Chain’ treaties in the seventeenth century, and the ‘Peace and
Friendship’ treaties in the eighteenth century: see Miller, Compact, Contract, Covenant,
chapter 2.
34
Ibid., pp. 70–3.
35
For a comprehensive history, see J. R. Miller, Skyscrapers Hide the Heavens: A History of
Native-Newcomer Relations in Canada, 4th ed. (University of Toronto Press, 2018).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
reversing the prevailing judicial stance that they were unenforceable
either because First Nations lacked the capacity of an ‘independent
power’, or because treaties were understood simply as gestures of political
good will and not as binding legal obligations.36 Further, courts now
undertake to interpret the written treaties as manifesting the parties’
common intention in light of their distinct motivations and understand-
ings, and the cultural and linguistic differences between the parties.37
While the written text remains the core of treaty interpretation for the
courts, research on the transcripts of treaty negotiations, as well as oral
histories passed through generations, has led to an academic consensus
that the Indigenous signatory parties to the ‘cession’ treaties could not
have intended to surrender their land; that an understanding of their
relationships to land – and of their constitutional orders more generally –
supports only that the treaty parties were agreeing to share the land and
enter into ongoing relationships with the newcomers.38
36
R. v. Syliboy [1929] 1 DLR 30.
37
R. v. Sioui [1990] 1 SCR 1025, pp. 1068–9; R. v. Badger [1996] 1 SCR 771, pp. 52–4.
38
See, for example, M. Asch, On Being Here to Stay: Treaties and Aboriginal Rights in
Canada (University of Toronto Press, 2014); A. Craft, Breathing Life into the Stone Fort
Treaty: An Anishinabe Understanding of Treaty One (Purich Publishing, 2013); J. S. Long,
Treaty No. 9: Making the Agreement to Share the Land in Far Northern Ontario (McGill-
Queen’s University Press, 2010); R. T. Price (ed.), The Spirit of the Alberta Indian
Treaties, 3rd ed. (University of Alberta Press, 1999); Treaty 7 Elders and Tribal Council
with W. Hildebrandt, D. First Rider and S. Carter, The True Spirit and Original Intent of
Treaty 7 (McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1996).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
ways in which norms become entangled. Indeed, it is significant for what
we see as being entangled.
One of the ‘strategic pathways’ taken up by the French, Dutch and
British was the adoption of the metaphors and tropes of Indigenous
diplomatic language. Kinship terms in treaty formalities abounded: the
Haudenosaunee were addressed as ‘brethren’ in the eighteenth-century
treaties collected by Benjamin Franklin, and the British were invited,
through rituals of care and concern between parties (‘wiping tears’ and
‘clearing the ground’), to eschew purely mercantile concerns in favour of
human solidarity.39 These treaties invoked the bodily gesture of ‘linking
arms’ or the linkage metaphor of the Covenant Chain that had to be
polished regularly, lest it tarnish.40 In treaty negotiations following the
Royal Proclamation, Kings George III and George IV were referred to as
‘our Great Father’, Queen Victoria the ‘Great Mother’,41 while the new-
comers were greeted as Kiciwamanawak or cousin by the Cree: elder
Harold Johnson writes of the treaty his forebears signed as an adoption
ceremony under Cree law.42
These kinship tropes are not mere flourish, but speak to an underlying
‘worldview’ or, as I have been taught, a legality. Kinship extended beyond
the human, to animals, plants, water, rocks and spirits, which are
often linguistically marked as ‘animate’ and attributed agency in North
American Indigenous languages.43 For Anishinaabe peoples, Nindoodem
(totem) animals – representations of which were placed as signatures on
the Great Peace of Montreal in 1701 – were not only symbolic ways to
organize human groups and to structure identity but, as explained by
Anishinaabe of the period, were taken as their apical ancestors in the
Creation period.44 Harold Johnson puts the connection of humans to
non-humans in prosaic terms:
39
Pomedli, ‘Eighteenth-Century Treaties’, 319.
40
Williams Jr, ‘Linking Arms Together’.
41
M. Walters, ‘“Your Sovereign and Our Father”: The Imperial Crown and the Idea of
Legal-Ethnohistory’, in S. Dorsett and I. Hunter (eds), Law and Politics in British Colonial
Thought: Transpositions of Empire (Palgrave Macmillan, 2010).
42
H. Johnson, Two Families: Treaties and Government (Purich Publishing, 2007), p. 82.
43
R. W. Kimmerer, ‘Learning the Grammar of Animacy’ (2017) 28 Anthropology of
Consciousness 128–34; J. Cruikshank, Do Glaciers Listen? Local Knowledge, Colonial
Encounters, and Social Imagination (University of British Columbia Press, 2005).
44
H. Bohaker, ‘“Nindoodemag”: The Significance of Algonquian Kinship Networks in the
Eastern Great Lakes Region, 1600–1701’ (2006) 63 The William and Mary Quarterly
23–52.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
This is where my ancestors are buried, where their atoms are carried up
by insects to become part of the forest, where the animals eat the plants of
the forest, and where my ancestors’ atoms are in the animals that I eat, in
my turn. I am part of this place.45
45
Johnson, Two Families: Treaties and Government, p. 13.
46
P. Nadasdy, ‘The Gift in the Animal: The Ontology of Hunting and Human–Animal
Sociality’ (2007) 34 American Ethnologist 25–43.
47
Craft, Breathing Life into the Stone Fort Treaty, p. 94.
48
H. Stark, ‘Respect, Responsibility and Renewal: The Foundations of Anishinaabe Treaty
Making with the United States and Canada’ (2010) 34 American Indian Culture and
Research Journal 145–64, at 146. See also Borrows, ‘With or Without You’.
49
Mills, ‘What Is a Treaty?’ and Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin: All That Has Been Given for Living
Well Together – One Vision of Anishinaabe Constitutionalism’, PhD thesis, University of
Victoria (2019), http://dspace.library.uvic.ca/handle/1828/10985.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Further, the somethings are not just in the material realm: Sákéj Henderson
stresses that Indigenous law also emerges out of experiences with the spiritual
realm – that is, with the affective forces of the ecosystem for which he borrows
quantum physicist David Peat’s term, the ‘implicate order’.50
50
J. Y. Henderson, ‘Ayukpachi: Empowering Aboriginal Thought’, in M. Battiste,
Reclaiming Indigenous Voice and Vision (University of British Columbia Press, 2000),
p. 262. See also G. Cajete, Native Science: Natural Laws of Interdependence (Clear Light
Publishers, 2000).
51
Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, p. 24.
52
R. Macdonald, ‘Everyday Lessons of Law Teaching – Le quotidien de l’enseignement
juridique’ (2012) 3 Canadian Legal Education Annual Review 3–37, at 12.
53
Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, p. 24.
54
B. Mann, ‘Afterward: The Death and Transfiguration of Early American Legal History’, in
C. Tomlins and B. Mann (eds), The Many Legalities of Early America (University of
North Carolina Press, 2001), p. 447.
55
See examples in Miller, Compact, Contract, Covenant, p. 13.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
with the British,56 grant that the King may ‘hold, occupy, possess and
enjoy’ the land in question ‘irrevocably’ for ‘consideration’ or in light of
‘presents’,57 or ‘cede, release, surrender and yield up’ territories in
exchange for cash annuities and other benefits, for example.58 We have
already looked fleetingly at two ways in which these texts have come into
question as being representative of the nature of the agreements reached
between the parties. First, the wealth of research in the past few decades
on the oral negotiations shows that Indigenous parties did not cede title
to land (much less sovereignty) but were negotiating on the basis of
consensual coexistence and the sharing of land and resources.59 Second,
images like the Covenant Chain emphasize that, from the perspective of
Indigenous parties, treaties were relational – and thus involving a need
for ‘polishing’ or renewal as parties revisit their commitments to one
another and attend to evolving situations – rather than transactional,
constituted by a discrete moment in time that fixed parties’ rights with
respect to one another.60 These two points capture something of
the contrast between Indigenous treaty jurisprudence and contract.
However, the legality of interdependence that I introduced above allows
us to see that the transactional character of contract is just the tip of the
iceberg.
In exploring the broader ways of being that lie underneath contrac-
tarian logic, I am indebted to Mills’ comparative analysis of constitu-
tional logics in Canada/Turtle Island, one of the most thorough and
clearheaded that I have yet seen.61 Contracts, as we know, create obliga-
tions when two parties exercise their free will to make and accept binding
promises, in a ‘meeting of the minds’. Aside from these privately created
bonds, we are subject to other obligations created by legitimate political
authority – again, justified by the consent of the governed through the
putative ‘social contract’. The autonomous selves at the heart of this story
56
Such as the Peace and Friendship Treaties from 1752 and 1760–1, www.rcaanc-cirnac.gc
.ca/eng/1370373165583/1581292088522.
57
The language typical of the Upper Canada Land Surrenders from the 1780s to 1862, ibid.
58
The formula frequently used in the ‘numbered’ treaties of 1871–1921, ibid.
59
See references cited at n. 38.
60
J. Y. Henderson, ‘Empowering Treaty Federalism’ (1994) 58 Saskatchewan Law Review
241–329; M. Walters, ‘Brightening the Covenant Chain: Aboriginal Treaty Meanings in
Law and History After Marshall’ (2001) 24 Dalhousie Law Journal 75–138.
61
Mills, ‘What Is a Treaty?’ and Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’; A. Mills, ‘The Lifeworlds of Law:
On Revitilizing Indigenous Legal Orders Today’ (2016) 61 McGill Law Journal 847–84; A.
Mills, ‘Driving the Gift Home’ (2016) 33 Windsor Yearbook of Access to Justice 167–86.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of obligations are of course deeply liberal ones, with capacities for self-
direction and rational choice. The relationship between humans set up by
the pattern of offer and acceptance is one of direct and strictly defined
reciprocity. Without contract, in the liberal story, we are disconnected,
even antagonistic, individuals;62 only the social contract and its appoint-
ment of a sovereign stop us from descending into Hobbes’ ‘war of all
against all’. Rights underwritten by the sovereign are also oppositional, a
power over things or others because their compliance is compelled;63
they secure negative liberty and freedom from our fellow humans; rights
and obligations, and the autonomy and self-interest they protect, square
up bilaterally in a zero-sum game.64 The disconnection extends to
humans’ ecological contexts as liberal legality collaborates with the
extractive ‘mastery’ of nature, and in turn underwrites the physical
alienation of peoples from land through commodification of the com-
mons and colonization.
In the logics of gift and mutual aid, Mills writes, treaty is not the means
to bring into relation atomistic persons in order to secure their liberty,
that is, their capacity to exercise their autonomy. Instead, persons are
always and already interdependent – the sum of their relations – and
treaties deepen their intentional participation in a complex circulation of
gifts through specific kinship forms.65 In place of the contractual struc-
ture offer/acceptance/consideration, where what is offered in response
corresponds directly to the initial offer, the response to gift is gratitude
that then moves us to reciprocate, although likely not directly, to the gift
giver.66 Alternatively, and this is a formulation seen often in treaty
records, Mills explains that mutual aid might be initiated through the
presentation of a need to one’s relatives that then inculcates a sense of
responsibility and initiates beneficent action: hence the language of peti-
tioning the King for ‘pity’ or protection in treaties.67 In this way, and
whether they are initiated as gifts or petitions, treaties are offered not as a
way for Indigenous peoples and non-Indigenous peoples to bind
62
Mills notes that even communitarian theorists hold that our social embeddedness is
simply a factor in how we are able to exercise individual autonomy rather than see it as
grounding a different understanding of the self: see Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, p. 52.
63
Brian Tierney, The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law and
Church Law 1150–1625 (William B. Eerdmans, 2001), p. 16.
64
Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, p. 101.
65
Mills, ‘What Is a Treaty?’
66
Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, p. 102.
67
Ibid., p. 104.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
themselves to their promises, but as an invitation to specific forms of
kinship, a relationship governed by Indigenous legality.
This understanding of treaty has implications for Canada’s reconcili-
ation project. If, as the aphorism now goes, ‘we are all treaty people’ here
in Canada, the possibility of reconciliation and respect for Indigenous
law is undermined if contract – and the baggage of its legality – is taken
as the framing device. It would constitute what Mills calls ‘constitutional
capture’, that is, that Indigenous claims are worked out through common
and civil law categories, and within the presumptive structure of
Canada’s liberal constitution.68 Further, the logic of gifts and mutual
aid does not presume, as does liberal legality, that human political and
legal relational structures can be severed from those of the Earth. In the
logic of mutual aid, the reconciliation question is not about securing
space for Indigenous legal traditions and the exercise of autonomy for
different legal orders, but about sustaining healthy relationships in our
ecosystems.69 The treaty invitation to non-Indigenous peoples is to root
themselves in Canadian soil, quite literally.
Learning, as an outsider, about the legal traditions specific to par-
ticular places in Canada, and the life-worlds that inform them, is part of
68
Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, pp. 35–7, 212. This is a particular instance of a larger problem
with political ‘recognition’: see P. Markell, Bound by Recognition (Princeton University
Press, 2003); D. Turner, This Is Not a Peace Pipe: Towards a Critical Indigenous
Philosophy (University of Toronto Press, 2006); Coulthard, Red Skin, White Masks.
69
The Two-Row Wampum (Kaswenta), a beaded belt with two parallel purple lines on a
white background and closely associated with colonial-era treaty-making, is often said to
represent a principle of non-interference – the European ship and the Haudenosaunee
canoe sail separately in the shared river. It thus looks at first glance like an Indigenous (or
intercultural) endorsement of something akin to negative liberty. This wampum may well
have emerged in an era during which the original covenant had been forgotten by British
authorities (see D. Bonaparte, ‘The Disputed Myth, Metaphor and Reality of Two Row
Wampum’ (8 September 2013), http://indiancountrytodaymedianetwork.com/2013/08/
09/disputed-myth-metaphor-and-reality-two-row-wampum; and K. Muller, ‘The Two
“Mystery” Belts of Grand River: A Biography of the Two Row Wampum and the
Friendship Belt’ (2007) 31 American Indian Quarterly 129–64). Stepping back from
efforts to quash and undermine Indigenous legal orders is a necessary redress of imperial
relations. However, it is only an initial remedial step, and it would be a mistake to assume
that non-interference as a liberal value of negative liberty is an end goal of treaty. A more
fulsome reading of the Two-Row, which includes the three alternating white lines
representing peace, friendship and respect (J. Borrows, Recovering Canada: The
Resurgence of Indigenous Law (University of Toronto Press, 2002), p. 149), is consistent
with the ethos of relationality found throughout Haudenosaunee thinking (see generally
K. P. Williams, Kayenerenkó:wa: The Great Law of Peace (University of Manitoba Press,
2018)).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
a process of decolonization. Supreme Court jurisprudence has under-
lined that the goal of reconciliation in s. 35 of the Canadian
Constitution requires the inclusion of the ‘Aboriginal perspective’ on
rights under s. 35,70 and the Indian Residential School Truth and
Reconciliation Commission report of 2015 calls on law schools to
include courses on Indigenous legal traditions so that future judges
and lawyers may be equipped to go beyond paying lip service to ‘the
Aboriginal perspective’.71 Such cross-cultural projects inevitably raise
issues of translation – who can do it and how, the problems of
rendering living and highly contextualized traditions legible to out-
siders and their institutions, and the risk of appropriating what little
remains after centuries of destructive colonial policies. These dynamics
are reconfigured by the framing of Mills and others of the issue as one
of relatedness rather than recognition. Mills writes that Anishinaabe
constitutionalism is not about ethnic identity but about a way of being
in political community on Earth: ‘Though your stories may be different
and you and I may not read the earth the same way, this is a consti-
tutional framework available to all.’72 This is why my approach here
and elsewhere is to explore ways in which the messages of Anishinaabe
and Haudenosaunee jurisprudence (the two rooted traditions growing
out of the place where I live) resonate with the knowledge from my own
inherited traditions.73
This understanding of treaties also has consequences for expanding
our consideration of the heuristic of entangled legalities itself. Conceiving
of entangled legalities in terms of normative pluralism – borrowing or
transplanting rules and principles, developing hybrids, instituting struc-
tures that deal with conflicting norms – presupposes the form that law
takes and constitutes its own kind of capture. If an actor – like a judge or
other decision-maker – can select from a range of norms, we would have
to think about law as dismembered pieces, as abstract propositions to be
70
R v. Van Der Peet [1996] 2 SCR 507, [49].
71
Call to Action 28 in Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Canada, Honouring the
Truth, Reconciling for the Future: Summary of the Final Report of the Truth and
Reconciliation Commission of Canada (Truth and Reconciliation Commission of
Canada, 2015), www.trc.ca/res-trc-finding.html. See K. Drake, ‘Finding a Path to
Reconciliation: Mandatory Indigenous Law, Anishinaabe Pedagogy, and Academic
Freedom’ (2017) 95 Canadian Bar Review 9–46.
72
Mills, ‘What Is a Treaty?’, p. 245.
73
See K. Anker, ‘Law as Forest: Eco-Logics, Stories and Spirits in Indigenous Jurisprudence’
(2017) 21 Law Text Culture 191–213.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘applied’ rather than an integral part of the way we live.74 In the case of
Indigenous law, such a floating rule or principle would, as Gordon
Christie argues, be disembedded from the landscape.75 Sákéj
Henderson’s vivid metaphor is that understanding Indigenous law as
rules would be trying to appreciate an opera by reading the flute score.76
In fact, Mills argues that rooted legalities do not find their usual or
ultimate expression as rules at all.77 This is partly because rules require
abstraction – the disembedding from relationships – and partly because
the agency of beings is suppressed if they are subject to (even provision-
ally) determinate rules.78 Our entanglements, our giving and receiving of
gifts, are continually co-constituting the world and, if I have understood
well, the law is learned as a way of being in those relationships, producing
not generalizable rules but rather a capacity to exercise judgement in situ
to foster those relationships.79
Many scholars working on law in the Anthropocene have noticed the
dysfunctionality of the conventional notion of law as rules faced with
the dynamic and integrated nature of ecological crises, largely because
the rule of law is based on predictability and resistance to change.80 Law
needs, consequently, to mirror ecological systems, to become dynamic
and adaptive.81 It may be that models of adaptive management, in which
decisions and regulations are provisional and adjustable in light of
environmental feedback, have something in common with the indeter-
minacy of law-as-judgement of rooted legalities. This short foray into the
74
See M. Constable’s retelling of the Norman conquest as the origin of positive law in the
move from implicit knowledge about how to act to the articulation of rules in propos-
itional language: The Law of the Other: The Mixed Jury and Changing Perceptions of
Citizenship, Law, and Knowledge (University of Chicago Press, 1994), chapter 4.
75
G. Christie, ‘Indigenous Legal Orders, Canadian Law and UNDRIP’, in UNDRIP
Implementation: Braiding International, Domestic and Indigenous Laws (Centre for
International Governance Innovation, 2017), p. 49.
76
J. S. Henderson, ‘Comprehending First Nations Jurisprudence’, unpublished paper,
Indigenous Law and Legal Systems Conference (University of Toronto Faculty of Law,
27 January 2007).
77
Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, p. 135.
78
See the story of Wiisakejak and the ducks discussed by Mills, ‘Miinigowiziwin’, p. 137.
79
Ibid., t pp. 137–45.
80
J. Stacey, The Constitution of the Environmental Emergency (Hart, 2018); C. Voigt, Rule of
Law for Nature: New Dimensions and Ideas in Environmental Law (Cambridge
University Press, 2013); J. Ebbesson, ‘The Rule of Law in Governance of Complex
Socio-ecological Changes’ (2010) 20 Global Environmental Change 414–22.
81
J. Ellis, ‘Crisis, Resilience, and the Time of Law’ (2019) 32 Canadian Journal of Law and
Jurisprudence 305–20.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
legalities of entanglement that inform treaty-making in North America
gives insight into the ways in which the premises of ecological law – a
rule of law grounded in the Earth, in which each of us has an ‘ecological
citizenship’ calling on us to ‘respect the workings of the Earth’s life
systems’82 – can be more than just the means to the end of sustainability;
those workings are more than simply a model to copy or calculate with,
they are a set of relationships to live in.
3.5 Conclusion
But wait. How are we separate? This can also be enumerated. Being an
individual and distinct organism is a dominant and recurring part of my
existence. When I touch a boiling kettle, it is only my hand that recoils.
My body mostly feels like a bounded unit with my ‘self’ located some-
where in my head. Although individualism is often decried as a mytho-
logical foundation for liberalism, it has a phenomenological and
pragmatic reality – alongside entanglement, it is also part of the way
the world thinks. Human symbolic thought has the property of permit-
ting the experience of an interior or virtual world that can seem separate
from the domain of the concrete, material world. This separation
between mind and matter, and between culture and nature, has in part
been actualized – and amplified – through agricultural practices, the
construction of cities and states, and empirical science. As anthropologist
Eduardo Kohn comments, the phenomenon we are calling the
Anthropocene seems to be the apotheosis of the mind–matter dualism
inherent in symbolic thinking.83
There is now a multitude of disciplines seeking to critique or
find solutions to the ways in which the current legal and political
paradigm ignores our ontology of entanglement, among them
ecological jurisprudence, ecology of mind,84 new materialisms85 and
82
UN GA, ‘Sustainable Development: Harmony with Nature – Report of the Secretary
General’ (17 August 2012) UN Doc A/67/.
83
E. Kohn, ‘Anthropology as Cosmic Diplomacy: Toward an Ecological Ethic for the
Anthropocene’, unpublished paper, Yale Ethnography and Social Theory Colloquium
Series (Yale University, 5 February 2018), https://fore.yale.edu/files/Kohn.pdf, p. 6.
84
G. Bateson, Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unity (E. P. Dutton, 1979).
85
J. Bennett, Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things (Duke University Press, 2010); A.
Grear, ‘Toward New Legal Futures? In Search of Renewing Foundations’, in A. Grear and
E. Grant (eds), Thought, Law, Rights and Action in an Age of Environmental Crisis
(Edward Elgar, 2015).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
cosmopolitics.86 Many of their insights, like those I related in Section 3.1,
may be useful, in the reconciliation project, for taking Indigenous law
seriously, particularly in engaging elements – like spirits or animals as
persons – that can sound fanciful because the idiom used to express them
has become denigrated within a modern disenchanted approach to
knowledge.87
But these disciplines addressing the ecological project also have much
to learn from engaging with Indigenous perspectives. Zoe Todd, Kyle
Powys Whyte and others have pointed out that discourses of the
Anthropocene have tended to both overstate the extent to which the
problem is a merely recent or impending dystopia, instead of the con-
tinuity of an apocalypse that for Indigenous peoples began with coloniza-
tion, and ignore or erase the contributions of Indigenous activists and
thinkers to our framing.88 Many factors in anthropogenic climate change
and ecocide relate to the genocides, land transformations, migrations and
global trade wrought by colonialism, but the Anthropocene as a discur-
sive trope also ‘continues a logic of the universal which is structured to
sever the relations between mind, body and land’.89 What this study of
treaty shows is that the exchange on entanglement cannot be simply an
intellectual one, as Indigenous ontologies are part of legal orders through
which those who share their territories are, like it or not, related.90 And as
we have seen, that legality – manifest in treaty – is centred on grounded
practices of creating and sustaining kin.
Given that entanglement and separation are both ‘in’ the world, we
desperately need to choose to amplify those aspects of the way the world
thinks that foster connection and care. As philosopher of science Donna
Haraway puts it in her book for these troubled times, Staying with the
86
B. Latour, ‘Whose Cosmos? Which Cosmopolitics? A Comment on Ulrich Beck’s Peace
Proposal’ (2004) 10 Common Knowledge 450–62; I. Stengers, Cosmopolitics I (University
of Minnesota Press, 2011).
87
M. Berman, The Reenchantment of the World (Cornell University Press, 1981).
88
Z. Todd, ‘An Indigenous Feminist’s Take on the Ontological Turn: “Ontology” Is Just
Another Word for Colonialism’ (2016) 24 Journal of Historical Sociology 4–22; K. P.
White, ‘Our Ancestors’ Dystopia Now: Indigenous Conservation and the Anthropocene’,
in U. Heise, J. Christensen and M. Niemann (eds), The Routledge Companion to the
Environmental Humanities (Routledge, 2017).
89
H. Davis and Z. Todd, ‘On the Importance of a Date, or Decolonizing the Anthropocene’
(2017) 16 ACME: An International Journal for Critical Geographies 761–80, at 761.
90
Todd, ‘An Indigenous Feminist’s Take on the Ontological Turn’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Trouble, given the irreversible losses that we are facing, any renewed
generative flourishing will need the kind of refuge spaces that are made
by a mesh of symbiotic, sympoetic, collaborators.91 The answer that both
she and Indigenous treaty jurisprudence give to the question ‘how are we
related, how are we entangled’? Let us multiply the ways.
91
D. Haraway, Staying with the Trouble: Making Kin in the Cthulucene (Duke University
Press, 2016).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
4
In the sixth month, Gabriel the angel was sent from God to a town in Galilee
called Nazareth, to a virgin engaged to a man called Joseph, from the family
of David. [. . .] ‘Don’t be afraid, Mary’, said the angel to her. ‘You’re in favour
with God. Listen: you will conceive in your womb and will have a son; and
you shall call his name Jesus [. . .] The Lord God will give him the throne of
David his father, and he shall reign over the house of Jacob for ever. His
kingdom will never come to an end.’1
4.1 Introduction
The annunciation by Jessup2 of the birth of what would become trans-
national law conceived within the womb of Western (and then global)
jurisprudence imagined a transformed juridical order in which the
notion of law was broadened beyond the state (at least with respect
to a definable set of activities). These legalities, in turn, were to be
entangled3 to solve what before had been issues the resolution of which
could be undertaken solely by reference to the law of a state.4 But this
1
Luke 26:31.
2
P. C. Jessup, Transnational Law (Yale University Press, 1956).
3
E.g., N. Krisch, ‘The Open Architecture of European Human Rights Law’ (2008) 71
Modern Law Review 183–216 (‘we find different norms and actors competing for ultimate
authority; and since they lack a common legal frame of reference, they compete, to a large
extent, through politics rather than legal argument’).
4
L. C. Backer, ‘The Cri de Jessup Sixty Years Later: Transnational Law’s Intangible Objects
and Abstracted Frameworks Beyond Nation, Enterprise, and Law’, in P. Zumbansen (ed.),
The Many Lives of Transnational Law: Critical Engagements with Jessup’s Bold Proposal
(Cambridge University Press, 2019), pp. 386–418.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘good news’ did not immediately produce transformations in the halls of
the priestly castes charged with the preservation of the jurisprudential
order carefully nurtured in recognizable form from the time of Martin
Luther and centred on the state as the principal expression of regulatory
power through law.5 For this caste and the states they served, the solution
was, is and remains the law of conflicts and traditional private inter-
national law.6 However, the twenty-first century has seen a reluctant
acceptance in theory of the decentring of the state, and consequentially,
of the recognition of the rise of multiple centres of governance with
multiple forms of law.7 That conceptual recognition comes at least a
century behind early modern studies of its realities in some states.8 The
reluctance arises from the ideological consequences of such a conceptual
acceptance. At its limit, the fear produces a modernist panic9 about the
state of the state, and of law as its official language. Despite the need
expressed by some,10 there remains a reluctance to give up ‘the ultimately
law-focused epistemological mechanism still at work’,11 and thus to forgo
the post-1945 ambitions for a transformation of global politics based on
the self-reflexive state as the highest legitimate form of communal polit-
ical expression,12 the expression of which could be made legitimate only
when undertaken through the language of law.13 Indeed, ‘[t]he main
5
United Nations, Guiding Principles for Business and Human Rights: Implementing the
United Nations ‘Protect, Respect and Remedy’ Framework (United Nations, 2011), p. 7
(‘States individually are the primary duty-bearers under international human rights law,
and collectively they are the trustees of the international human rights regime’).
6
C. A. Whytock, ‘Conflict of Laws, Global Governance, and Transnational Legal Order’ (2016) 1
UC Irvine Journal of International, Transnational, and Comparative Law 117–40.
7
P. Zumbansen, ‘Transnational Legal Pluralism’ (2010) 1 Transnational Legal Theory
141–189; L. C. Backer, ‘Governance without Government: An Overview’, in G. Handl,
J. Zekoll and P. Zumbansen (eds), Beyond Territoriality: Transnational Legal Authority in
an Age of Globalization (Martinus Nijhoff, 2012), pp. 87–123.
8
E. Patrignani, ‘Legal Pluralism as a Theoretical Programme’ (2016) 6 Oñati Socio-legal
Series 707–25, at 711.
9
A. D. Smith, Nationalism and Modernism: A Critical Survey of Recent Theories of Nations
and Nationalism (Routledge, 1998), pp. 8–23, 221–8.
10
G. Teubner, ‘The Two Faces of Janus: Rethinking Legal Pluralism’ (1991) 13 Cardozo Law
Review 1443–62.
11
T. Duve, ‘European Legal History: Concepts, Methods, Challenges’, in T. Duve (ed.),
Entanglements in Legal History: Conceptual Approaches (Max Planck Institute for
European Legal History, 2014), pp. 29–66, at p. 58.
12
L. C. Backer, ‘God(s) Over Constitutions: International and Religious Transnational
Constitutionalism in the 21st Century’ (2008) 27 Mississippi College Law Review 11–65.
13
D. Dyzenhaus, ‘Hobbes and the Legitimacy of Law’ (2001) 20 Law and Philosophy
461–98.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
shortcoming of the extended conception of law advocated by anthropo-
logical and sociological approaches is the one pointed at by the so-called
pan-legalist objection: the problem of the distinctiveness of law from
other social normative orderings has been haunting the theorists of legal
pluralism until today’.14 In short, what factions of the leader class feared
most in the twenty-first century was precisely the consequences of legal
entanglements that might bring down their tightly woven conceptual
house.15
Yet that very rejection provides strong evidence not merely of its
existence but also of its effects, principal of which are the ruptures that
entanglement produces between these emerging centres of law/norms/
governance,16 both within and among the conventional nation state.17
It is within these spaces that one might seek both the meaning and
manner in which what Luhmann once described as structural coupling
might occur.18 These spaces without a space, these in-between spaces of
law (and governance), these fragmented but entangled legalities, have
assumed a spatial dimension.19 It is now understood as both a connector
(the trames20 through which spaces connect and communicate) but also
as its own normative territory within which those communications and
connections are not merely mediated but managed through complex
entanglements,21 or dynamic processes of communicative irritations.22
14
Patrignani, ‘Legal Pluralism as a Theoretical Programme’, 713; M. Croce, ‘All Law Is
Plural: Legal Pluralism and the Distinctiveness of Law’ (2012) 65 Journal of Legal
Pluralism and Unofficial Law 1–30.
15
J. Crowe, ‘The Limits of Legal Pluralism’ (2015) 24 Griffith Law Review 314–31.
16
N. Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law (Oxford
University Press, 2010); P. S. Berman, Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law
beyond Borders (Cambridge University Press, 2012).
17
M. Davies, ‘Legal Pluralism’, in P. Cane and H. M. Kritzer (eds), The Oxford Handbook of
Empirical Legal Research (Oxford University Press, 2010).
18
N. Luhmann, The Differentiation of Society (Columbia University Press, 1982).
19
A. Bianchi, International Law Theories: An Inquiry into Different Ways of Thinking
(Oxford University Press, 2016), pp. 227–31.
20
Here understood both as a side path (e.g. and ironically here, Sallust (c.40 BC) C. 57, 1:
‘uti per tramites occulte perfugeret in Galliam Transalpinam’; J. 48: ‘per tramites occultos
Metelli antevenit’) but also as a way of life or course or manner of engagement (e.g.
Lucretius. (c.55 B.C.) 6, 27: ‘ab aequitatis recto tramite deviare’).
21
G.-P. Calliess and P. Zumbansen, Rough Consensus and Running Code: A Theory of
Transnational Private Law (Hart Publishing, 2010).
22
G. Teubner, ‘Legal Irritants: Good Faith in British Law or How Unifying Law Ends Up in
New Differences’ (1998) 61 Modern Law Review 11–32.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The budding focus on the interspatial carries with it both promise and
challenge. The promise: an interspatial gap filling in all of its complexities
and theoretical possibilities. This has been the central exploration of
entanglements among law, norms, rules and habits with coercive effect.23
The challenge is centred on the risk of boundaries without end: of the
permanent and quite dynamic cacophony of borders that is produced by
the obsession with the interfaces between bodies of norms that them-
selves create borders within the space between norm systems for which
other interfaces are necessary.24 The problem of the never-ending spaces
between spaces, where every law system defines its own inter-spaces,
becomes self-entangling, and might itself be undergoing an extra-spatial
transformation. That extra-spatial form of governance – in which space
loses its centrality and law changes its forms and function – is the object
of the exploration here.
More specifically, the chapter considers the emergence of data-driven
analytics and the algorithmic techniques of imposing consequences
(some of it machine driven, on the basis of artificial intelligence (AI))25
as defining not just new modalities of governance but also reshaping the
conception of spatiality within which entangled governance happens,
national and transnational, public and private. So reshaped, these data-
driven governance legalities entangle with traditional modes of govern-
ance through law in what may be new and interesting ways. These
‘social credit’ ratings, risk management, assessment, accountability or
compliance systems have been established as a means to aid traditional
governance;26 yet they have the potential to displace the structures of
governance they are meant to serve. But more than that, they may well
change the landscape and language in which one encounters legal
entanglements and its operational effects. The thesis of this chapter is
simple: legal entanglement has moved beyond the two-dimensional space
23
Berman, Global Legal Pluralism; G. Teubner, ‘“Global Bukowina”: Legal Pluralism in the
World Society’, in G. Teubner (ed.), Global Law without a State (Ashgate, 1997).
24
Cf. H. Nagendra and E. Ostrom, ‘Polycentric Governance of Multifunctional Forested
Landscapes’ (2012) 6 International Journal of the Commons 104–33.
25
People’s Republic of China, ‘Chinese State Council released the New Generation AI
Development Plan (新一代人工智能发展规划的通知)’ (July 2017), www.gov.cn/
zhengce/content/2017-07/20/content_5211996.htm; see European Commission website
on Digital Single Market, Policy, Artificial Intelligence (2019), https://ec.europa.eu/
digital-single-market/en/artificial-intelligence.
26
See, e.g., essays in K. E. Davis, A. Fisher, B. Kingsbury and S. E. Merry (eds), Governance
by Indicators: Global Power through Quantification and Rankings (Oxford University
Press, 2012).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
for engagement envisioned by Jessup and his successor. Entanglement
was once confined to states, other governance institutions and between
them all. That engagement was built around and with the traditional
language of law and jurisprudence. Increasingly, the emerging quantita-
tive legalities built around AI and big data management systems (e.g.
social credit initiatives) that are neither dependent on the forms and
techniques of law nor on the bureaucratic apparatus of state entangle
more decisively with conventional and plural law and norm systems.
These add an additional layer of actor (the ‘market’, the analyst, the
modeller, the systems engineer, the coder) and seek to displace the
language of law and jurisprudence with the language of data-based
analytics applied towards a comprehensive management of behaviour.
The resulting entanglement may reshape the meaning and making of
entanglement itself. At its limit, this reshaping will have a particular
effect on the way in which conventional plural legalities, until now the
singular feature of globalized law frameworks, may be assembled through
dynamic and sometimes unstable entangled linkages and rationalized by
a regulatory algorithm that may come to manage them all.27
This contribution, then, considers governance entanglement between
the entangled legalities of law-norm systems and the legalities emerging
from data-driven systems of behaviour management. The realities of
emerging legalities that exceed the capacity of law to express their form
require a three-dimensional analysis of entanglement and a broader view
of legality, one that reconsiders data-driven, machine-administered regu-
latory systems more than an enhanced form of property.28 One deals
here not just with the flattened inter-legalities of the traditional structures
of ordering power by rules. Instead, one must now understand the way
those clusters of entanglement themselves are entangled with emerging
modalities of law/regulation/norms which have come to form the centre
of what is understood as plural legalities.
27
J. R. R. Tolkien, The Fellowship of the Ring (Random House, 1954), chapter 2. That extra-
spatiality is nicely captured through what is now a sadly hackneyed and often quoted
passage from a well-known book which provides a rich metaphor for multidimensional
entanglement, rings of power for all communities to each bind themselves and ‘One Ring
to rule them all, . . . to find them, . . . to . . . bind them.’
28
E.g., OECD, ‘OECD Council Recommendation on Artificial Intelligence’ (adopted
21 May 2019) OECD/LEGAL/0449, https://legalinstruments.oecd.org/en/instruments/
OECD-LEGAL-0449.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Section 4.2 briefly sketches the characteristics of emerging legalities
that neither embrace the form nor the language of law. The two sections
that follow examine the nature of inter-systemic entanglements which
occur when data-driven governance legal orders29 are thrown into the
already plural mix of legalities. Two principal forms of data-driven
governance have emerged that are increasingly linking to traditional
legalities.30 The first is the Chinese ‘social credit’ initiative, which
emerged in its current form in 2014, and is an undertaking by the present
administration of the Chinese government that is meant to produce an
all-around approach to ensuring compliance with law and social respon-
sibility under the guidance of the state. The second are US and Western
private initiatives around emerging markets for data. These are framed
around principles of governance, risk management and compliance.
With respect to each, the nature and textures of entanglement that
encounters between traditional plural legalities and data-driven govern-
ance systems produce is considered. These entanglements present a
distinct challenge, the challenge of linguistic disjunction, for the man-
agement of human organization. While law- and norm-based systems
speak the same language, data-driven governance does not.
Communicative disjunction may have profound effects on the nature
and quality of entanglement, producing a competition for the lingua
franca that may affect the way in which law is expressed, and may
threaten the plurality of law.31 Each also exhibits quite distinct charac-
teristics and therefore quite different forms and qualities of entangle-
ment, suggesting a more complex fracture and interaction among ever
more different systems of legalities that are emerging in fractured polit-
ical systems arranged around global trade regimes.
29
T. C. Halliday and G. Shaffer (eds), Transnational Legal Orders (Cambridge University
Press, 2015).
30
At greater length in L. C. Backer, ‘Next Generation Law: Data-Driven Governance and
Accountability Based Regulatory Systems in the West and Social Credit Regimes in
China’ (2018) 28 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal 123–72.
31
E.g., J. House, ‘English as Lingua Franca: A Threat to Multilingualism?’ (2003) 7 Journal
of Sociolinguistics 556–78.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
and others.32 What started as an effort to rationalize the emerging
techniques of indicators,33 as a means of governance, quickly became a
study of these techniques, increasingly systematized, as governance.34
The recognition of algorithmic governance appeared like a direct and
hidden threat to the carefully constructed public structures of law and
governance systems.35 Just as it seemed that theory could come to grips
with the possibility of law (governance) systems beyond the state, the
entire framework of law systems themselves seemed to be sidelined by
data-based algorithmic systems to which law and norms appeared to be a
stranger. And these challenges have come to the West in forms that
appear to conflate the operations of Marxist-Leninist government with
Western democratic markets-driven polycentric (plural) governance.36
Yet these judgements ought not to deter from considering the (inevitable
it seems) rise of these systems in both China and the West, and the
additional layer of entanglement they add to the emerging formal and
public systems of governance that constitute global legal polycentric
(pluralist) governance.37 To that end, a brief exploration of the shape
of social credit initiatives fuelled by AI and machine learning-enabled
algorithms is worth considering.
The rise of social credit initiatives (ratings and data-driven governance
in the West) and big data management systems (as a means to imple-
ment these governance frameworks) appears to further entangle legalities
in perhaps unexpected ways. It takes as its starting point the significant
drive towards accountability and measurement in governance incarnated
through rankings and ratings. Administration of rankings and ratings
then devolves to the institutions that administer and along with that
devolution goes the power to determine what behaviours will be valued,
and in what amount, to rank and rate. In effect, the indicator acquires
32
F. Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and
Information (Harvard University Press, 2016).
33
S. E. Merry, The Seductions of Quantification: Measuring Human Rights, Gender Violence,
and Sex Trafficking (University of Chicago Press, 2016) (measurement systems constitute
a form of power).
34
Backer, ‘Next Generation Law’.
35
Pasquale, The Black Box Society.
36
M. Harris, ‘The Moral Hazard of Big Data’, New Republic (6 February 2015), https://
newrepublic.com/article/120987/pasquales-black-box-challenges-digital-sphere-run-
algorithms.
37
E. Ostrom, ‘Beyond Markets and States: Polycentric Governance of Complex Economic
Systems’ (2010) 100 American Economic Review 641–72.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
regulatory autonomy. Thus characterized as a regulatory system, it is
then entangled with traditional law-norm systems.38 If law and norms –
traditional governance – are grounded in the supremacy of space, of
territory, then how is one to approach governance orders that might
themselves be detached from traditional spatial limitations? That is the
principal focus of this chapter. It considers the emergence of what might
eventually be understood as a legal/normative order that has arisen not
from the need to organize a territory, within which people and things are
corralled, but generated from and centred on the objects of regulation
themselves. The emerging systems that have been referenced in this
chapter as ‘social credit’ initiatives offer a glimpse at a governance
operating system quite distinct from the legal/normative systems that
have served as the building blocks first of the Westphalian state system
(in its domestic and international elements), and thereafter the poly-
centric systems that mark this transnational age.39
In place of legal/normative systems driven through the construction of
an apparatus of government within territories (physical or abstract) it
fashions a system driven through data generated by people and things.40
38
Consider the example of corruption, one well examined in the essays in S. E. Merry, K. E.
Davis and B. Kingsbury (eds), The Quiet Power of Indicators: Measuring Governance,
Corruption, and Rule of Law (Cambridge University Press, 2015). In this case trans-
national measures inform international instruments that then inform national transpos-
ition of corruption measures. These, in turn, are substantially affected by systems of
analytics of performance built around proprietary assessments of corruption compliance
that are framed around these legal principles and rules, but which are interpreted and
quantified in ways that reflect the values and objectives of the analysts and coders
preparing the analytical framework (and providing quantifiable values to identified
actions). See, e.g., D. Kaufmann, A. Kraay and M. Mastruzzi, ‘Measuring Corruption:
Myths and Realities’, World Bank (April 2007); Transparency International, ‘Corruption
Perceptions Index’ (2019), www.transparency.org/research/cpi/overview; O. E.
Hawthorne, ‘Do International Corruption Metrics Matter? Assessing the Impact of
Transparency International’s Corruption Perceptions Index’, PhD thesis, Old
Dominion University (2012), https://digitalcommons.odu.edu/gpis_etds/50.
39
M. Zürn, A. Nollkaemper and R, Peerenboom, ‘Introduction: Rule of Law Dynamics in an
Era of International and Transnational Governance’, in M. Zürn, A. Nollkaemper and R,
Peerenboom (eds), Rule of Law Dynamics in an Era of International and Transnational
Governance (Cambridge University Press, 2012) pp. 1–18.
40
L. C. Backer, ‘Global Panopticism: Surveillance Lawmaking by Corporations, States, and
Other Entities’ (2008) 15 Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 101–48. These data-
driven systems can be aligned with and enhance control over a territory/population in the
manner of Foucault’s bio-politics. See T. Lemke, ‘“The Birth of Bio-Politics”: Michel
Foucault’s Lecture at the College de France on Neo-Liberal Governmentality’ (2010) 30
Economy and Society 190–207; M. Foucault, Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the
Collège de France, 1975–1976, trans. D. Macey (St. Martin’s Press, 1997). The notion of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
Data substitute for custom and tradition; data-driven governance substi-
tutes the language of counting for the more qualitative descriptive lan-
guage of practice. Governing organs substitute, in place of custom and
tradition, the quite precise data warehouse, one with a vocabulary and
rule of normativity all of its own.41 It can be filled constantly with the
detritus of daily activity – at the market, on the web, in the car, on the
street, in the store, etc.42 These can be used for a variety of ends, some of
them public, but in the process entangling the normative decisions about
character of data for the content of norms.43 In the place of policy and
principle one encounters data analytics. Choice ceases to be politically
potent only within the electoral field; all choices become political as they
point behaviour managers to desires and habits of the masses producing
data. In lieu of debate there is analytics. The framing of that analysis, that
is the judgements and principles embedded in those analytics, is not
subsumed within the algorithm. The algorithm itself is the expression of
the sum of the objectives and perspectives of those for whose objectives
the algorithm is deployed. In lieu of principles, then, there are presump-
tions and the self-created limitations of data fields that create the
population, however, has long breached the political borders of territorial states (see
Backer, ‘The Cri de Jessup Sixty Years Later’). Consider in this case the entanglements of
public, private and data-driven systems in the operation of social media platforms like
Facebook. Facebook’s rules with respect to posts on its platform represent the uneasy and
unstable product of collisions between public law (e.g. the EU General Data Protection
Regulation (O. Solon, ‘How Europe’s “Breakthrough” Privacy Law Takes on Facebook
and Google’, The Guardian, 19 April 2018)), private regulation (Facebook’s normative
rules for acceptable content and procedural rules for content removal (J. C. Wong and O.
Solon, ‘Facebook Releases Content Moderation Guidelines—Rules Long Kept Secret’, The
Guardian, 24 April 2018)), Facebook’s algorithms (how Facebook determines post views
on newsfeeds, for example), and in 2020 a private quasi-judicial Oversight Board consti-
tuted by Facebook as its own internal judicial-administrative body, ‘a 20-member inde-
pendent panel that will rule on which posts can be blocked as false or as hate speech or
harassment’ (New York Post Editorial Board, ‘Facebook’s New “Supreme Court” Looks
Like a License to Censor’, New York Post, 7 May 2020).
41
R. Kimball et al., The Data Warehouse Lifecycle Toolkit, 2nd ed. (Wiley, 2008); H.
Edelstein and R. C. Barquin, Planning and Designing the Data Warehouse (Simon &
Schuster, 1996).
42
Cf., essays in J. Wang (ed.), Data Warehousing and Mining: Concepts, Methodologies,
Tools, and Applications (IGI Global, 2008).
43
This is particularly true in the West in the context of cyber criminality. Cf. I.-Y. Song
et al., ‘Designing a Data Warehouse for Cyber Crimes’ (2006) 1 Journal of Digital
Forensics, Security and Law 5–22; L. C. Backer, ‘Chinese Strategies to Combat
Corporate Corruption: From a “Two Thrust Approach” to a “Two Swords One Thrust
Strategy” of Compliance, Prosecutorial Discretion, and Sovereign Investor Oversight in
China’ (2019) 152 International Lawyer 1–45.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
boundaries within which choices are cabined. These are the structures of
conventional governance, but now deployed in a quite different space.
But these are not normative orders in the traditional sense. That
fundamental characteristic suggests the opportunities and challenges that
these emerging systems represent. Social credit initiatives – data and
algorithmic orders – change the relation among governance actors,
decentring the judge, the regulator and the social actors, in favour of
those who can manage, organize and apply metrics to some end or other
(that is to the same ends of law). Yet they do not mediate relations among
norms so much as absorb them all in furtherance of extra-spatial object-
ives – to focus on behaviours in a self-reflexive loop founded on
behaviour-generated data, the vectors of which may be modified through
systems of real-time rewards and punishments (of individuals and insti-
tutions, including governmental and economic institutions). These
orders, then, are not so much enmeshed as they are ubiquitous – serving
both as techniques of management, and as the primary structures of
regulation themselves. Absorption does not mean elimination; it posits
an entanglement of a different order – between conventional govern-
mental orders, the entanglements of which continue to produce norms,
but their interpretation and application, that is the way these norms are
given meaning, entangle conventional legalities with the analytic legal-
ities of the algorithm and the entanglement of choices made between
techno-experts, coders and public or private officials. These characteris-
tics became much more visible in the context of the Covid-19 pandemic
where the entanglement of simulation and conventional political legal-
ities became the central regulatory element of institutional responses to
the virus.44
It follows then that the anticipated entanglements become more con-
fused where one set of systems (law/regulation) continues to posit that
metrics-based governance is merely technique, rather than a regulatory
system in its own right. The interspatial, and its data-driven forms,
produces a quite distinctive template for the conceptual construction of
law/norms between law/norm systems; and it emerges with its own
language and sensibilities in ways that are not yet completely clear.
Every political culture approaches the emerging realities of ‘artificial
44
L. C. Backer, ‘Simulating Politics in the Shadow of COVID-19: “Like the School Nurse
Trying to Tell the Principal How to Run the School”’, Law at the End of the Day blog
(4 May 2020), https://lcbackerblog.blogspot.com/2020/05/simulating-politics-in-shadow-
of-covid.html.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
intelligence’, machine learning and the data-driven governance that is
sometimes its object, in ways that tend to affirm cultural expectations and
points of view. Where cultures are obsessed with particular conceptions
of privacy and property, the result is an engagement that is centred on
political constraints against states and enterprises, on the management of
markets for data and at the same time on an enhanced methodology of
data-driven analytics to deepen cultures of compliance, assessment and
accountability.
In liberal democratic states, that focus also has constitutional and
political dimensions.45 Thus, the regulatory machinery of the European
Union has lately been tasked to manage data under the presumption of a
hierarchy of authority that further presumes the normative nature of law
and the mechanical nature of data and their analytics. Data and data
processing ‘should be designed to serve mankind. The right to the
protection of personal data is not an absolute right; it must be considered
in relation to its function in society and be balanced against other
fundamental rights, in accordance with the principle of proportional-
ity.’46 There is a particular aversion to the forms of data-driven intrusions
from the economic sector (the ‘for hire’ fields) on the formalities and
rituals of exogenous democratic expression.47 And, of course, there is an
equal obsession with theft of information48 and its misuse.49 And yet,
even as its elites offer the protection of law, it manages that data which
itself manages behaviour.
A tiny microchip inserted under the skin can replace the need to carry
keys, credit cards and train tickets. [. . .] The small implants were first
used in 2015 in Sweden – initially confidentially – and several other
45
P. N. Howard, S. Woolley and R. Calo, ‘Algorithms, Bots, and Political Communication
in the US 2016 Election: The Challenge of Automated Political Communication for
Election Law and Administration’ (2018) 15 Journal of Information Technology &
Politics 81–93.
46
Regulation 2016/679 of 27 April 2016 on the protection of natural persons with regard to
the processing of personal data and on the free movement of such data, and repealing
Directive 95/46/EC (General Data Protection Regulation), OJ 2016 No L119, 4 May 2016
(‘GDPR’), preamble, section 4.
47
N. Statt, ‘The Justice Department and FBI Are Reportedly Investigating Cambridge
Analytica over Facebook Scandal’, The Verge (15 May 2018), www.theverge.com/2018/
5/15/17358802/facebook-cambridge-analytica-justice-department-fbi-investigation.
48
A. Narayanan and V. Shmatkov, ‘Robust De-anonymization of Large Sparse Datasets’,
Proceedings of the 2008 IEEE Symposium on Security and Privacy (2008), www.cs.utexas
.edu/~shmat/shmat_oak08netflix.pdf, pp. 111–25.
49
General Data Protection Regulation.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
countries. Swedes have gone on to be very active in microchipping, with
scant debate about issues surrounding its use, in a country keen on new
technology and where the sharing of personal information is held up as a
sign of a transparent society.50
50
AFP, ‘Thousands of People in Sweden get Microchip Implants for a New Way of Life’,
South China Morning Post, 13 May 2015.
51
UN CESCR, ‘Statement on the Coronavirus Disease (COVID-19) Pandemic and
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’ (adopted 17 April 2020) UN Doc. E/C.12/2020/1.
52
D. Zhang, H. Peng, Y. Haibin and Y. Lu, ‘Crowd Abnormal Behavior Detection based on
Machine Learning’ (2013) 12 Information Technology Journal 1199–205.
53
F. Xiang, ‘AI Will spell the End of Capitalism’, Washington Post, 25 April 2018.
54
L. C. Backer, ‘The Algorithms of Ideology in Economic Planning: A Critical Look at
Cuba’s National Economic and Social Development Plan 2030’ (2017) 27 Cuba in
Transition 115–36.
55
S. Leng, ‘Big Data to Give China Edge over the West’, South China Morning Post,
21 January 2018.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
values of property and rights-based legal orderings.56 And yet, even as
there is a movement towards the overt management of behaviour
through data, there is as well an obsession to ground that regulatory
approach within the structures of regulation – in this case a regulation
that protects the integrity of data and its use by the state and its delegees.
Data and consequence (accountability for business, incentive to encour-
age preferred behaviours and punish violations of behaviour norms) thus
combined, focus on stability and order in social development.
56
L. Fan, V. Das, N. Kostyuk and M. M. Hussain, ‘Constructing a Data-Driven Society:
China’s Social Credit System as a State Surveillance Infrastructure’ (2018) 10 Policy &
Internet 415–53.
57
Fan et al., ‘Constructing a Data-Driven Society’.
58
The Covid-19 pandemic has provided a powerful if simple illustration of how this works
in China. In order to better manage responses to the Covid-19 pandemic, Chinese
residents were each assigned a colour code representing a rating of contagion risk. That
risk rating is administered through Alibaba, a private enterprise. It has developed the
Alipay Health Code which adds a health colour code to each person’s Alipay account
(held by the vast majority of individuals). To access the rating each account holder
downloads an app. The system of data-driven colour coding (the analytics of which
remain opaque) are then used by other actors (state and private) to determine whether
the individual will be required to quarantine, and whether the individual will be granted
access to places of business or public spaces. The ranking data are shared with state
authorities and aligned with the state’s regulations and policies respecting Covid-19
mitigation measures. P. Mozur, R. Zhong and A. Krolik, ‘In Coronavirus Fight, China
Gives Citizens a Color Code, with Red Flags’, New York Times, 1 March 2020; X. Wǎng,
‘Zhīfùbǎo jiànkāng mǎ 7 tiān luòdì chāo 100 chéng shùzìhuà fángyì pǎo chū “zhōngguó
sùdù’ (‘Alipay Health Code Implemented in 100 Cities in 7 Days: Digital Epidemic
Prevention at China Speed’), Xinhuanet, 19 February 2020, www.xinhuanet.com/tech/
2020–02/19/c_1125596647.htm.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Communist Party of China (CPC).59 Its autonomous and systemic char-
acter was emphasized from the beginning:
It is founded on laws, regulations, standards and charters, it is based on a
complete network covering the credit records of members of society and
credit infrastructure, it is supported by the lawful application of credit
information and a credit services system, its inherent requirements are
establishing the idea of an sincerity culture, and carrying forward sincerity
and traditional virtues, it uses encouragement to keep trust and con-
straints against breaking trust as incentive mechanisms, and its objective
is raising the honest mentality and credit levels of the entire society.60
Yet one notes the entanglement – the system is constituted through law,
but is established as autonomous from the law system around which it
operates. The object is to establish a structure for managed entanglement
within the state. Each, in turn, requires the production of a self-reflexive
legality whose operation is entangled with those of the normative polit-
ical, societal and economic order. Its mechanism, machine learning and
AI, the entanglement of a rule system for AI and AI as law itself was also
elaborated by the State Council in 2017.61 ‘Social credit systems are
centered on ratings. Ratings are derived, in turn, from data generated
by what is being rated—individuals, businesses, public and private insti-
tutions, and eventually even [CPC] members. To that end, it is necessary
to manage data production as it is to manage the analytics and conse-
quences drawn from the data.’62
Social credit initiatives have as their object the development of a
national reputation system, assigning a rating that reflects a qualitative
judgement of relevant data gathered about the subject. Reputation, itself,
embraces notions of sincerity, and of integrity and compliance, in
accordance with the standards and objectives overseen by the state.
Four areas are identified: ‘sincerity in government affairs’ (政务诚信),
‘commercial sincerity’ (商务诚信), ‘societal sincerity’ (社会诚信) and
‘judicial credibility’ (司法公信). AI and machine learning focus on the
59
L. C. Backer, ‘China’s Social Credit System: Data-Driven Governance for a “New Era”’
(2019) 118 Current History: A Journal of Contemporary World Affairs 209–14.
60
People’s Republic of China, ‘State Council Notice Concerning Issuance of the Planning
Outline for the Construction of a Social Credit System (2014–2020)’ (2014), https://
chinacopyrightandmedia.wordpress.com/2014/06/14/planning-outline-for-the-construc
tion-of-a-social-credit-system-2014–2020/, p. 1.
61
People’s Republic of China, ‘Chinese State Council Released the New Generation AI
Development Plan’.
62
Backer, ‘China’s Social Credit System’, 211.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
generation of mechanisms for the management and integrity of data and
for its marketization.63
The objectives of both are grounded in economic and social develop-
ment and support for national security.64 The project of a comprehensive
and nationally integrated programme of credit ratings of virtually all
aspects of organized life in China, built pursuant to rules and laws,
administered by public and private bodies and overseen by the CPC
remains a work in progress, though one increasingly structured by the
highest Chinese state organs.65 It is self-consciously constructed as an
alternative legality, both within China and against the forms of plural
legalities in the West that the Chinese leadership increasingly find diffi-
cult to enmesh with their own.66
Nearly from its inception, social credit was understood as a new kind
of law, separate from but entangled with traditional law systems, which
had been themselves the product of the fusion of traditional approaches
to law and Western concepts of law, rule of law and legal mechanics.67 At
the same time, social credit expressed a form of governance that also
deeply entangled systems of social ordering through rules (laws) and the
paramount authority of the CPC to guide such lawmaking and its
application through its own political-economic model.68 The determin-
ation to adopt a social credit initiative (and its operationalization through
AI-enhanced algorithmic governance techniques) was itself a function of
63
E. Kania, ‘China’s AI Agenda Advances: As China Throws State Support behind AI
Development, Major Chinese Technology Companies Will Remain Integral Players’, The
Diplomat (14 February 2018), https://thediplomat.com/2018/02/chinas-ai-agenda-
advances/.
64
Kania, ‘China’s AI Agenda Advances’.
65
People’s Republic of China, ‘State Council 关于加快推进社会信用体系建设构建以信
用为基础的新型监管机制的指导意见’ (‘Guiding Opinion on Accelerating the
Advancement of the Establishment of the Social Credit System with New Forms of
Credit-Based Regulatory Mechanisms’), translated by Jeremy Daum, China Law
Translate (17 July 2019), www.chinalawtranslate.com. This document issued by the
General Office of the State Council provided guiding opinions on the acceleration of
the construction of the system. The document emphasized the centrality and importance
of the social credit system as a separable form of legality, and served as a reminder of the
determination of the current political leaders to move from a primary dependence on law
to data-driven management of behaviour as a central element of ordering society. Backer,
‘China’s Social Credit System’, 209.
66
Backer, ‘China’s Social Credit System’, 210.
67
X. Dai, ‘Toward a Reputation State: The Social Credit System Project of China’ (10 June
2018), https://ssrn.com/abstract=3193577.
68
S. Jiang, ‘Written and Unwritten Constitutions: A New Approach to the Study of
Constitutional Government in China’ (2010) 36 Modern China 12–46.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the determination that such data-driven governance would enhance the
long-term Chinese political-economic objectives embedded in their con-
cept of socialist modernization, a core policy of the Chinese state since
the era of Deng Xiaoping. Social credit was to evidence the transform-
ation of techniques that marked a new phase of the socialist market
economy system and of the social governance system, one which received
its more definitive political form after the announcement of the ‘New Era’
political line of the CPC in the wake of the 19th CPC Congress of
October 2017.69
But its genesis also represented a practical response to a long-term
problem that both state and private elements of society found increas-
ingly burdensome.70 These included a number of issues that threatened
not merely the orderly progress of socialist modernization, but also
inhibited the progressive advancement of social and cultural objectives.
These included grave production safety accidents, food and drug security
incidents, commercial swindles, the manufacture and sale of counterfeit
products, tax evasion, fraudulent financial claims, academic impropriety
and gaps between the extent of integrity in government affairs and
judicial credibility and the expectations of the popular masses. If neither
law nor regulation appeared to produce conformity, and if the transac-
tion costs of deploying a vast enforcement network was counterproduc-
tive to the long-term goal of a self-regulating society that was efficient
and productive in socially approved ways, then a different approach to
the management of societal factors was necessary.
This ambitious set of objectives was to be guided by a set of core
premises and constraints. Social credit initiatives must conform to and
advance the objectives of the CPC Basic Line, including the development
of economic forces for policy ends.71 The Chinese social credit system
also has a moral dimension, which deeply informs its regulatory and
enforcement dimensions. Its object is to steer the culture and practices of
people in virtually every aspect of their lives. To those ends, the Twelve
69
J. Xi, ‘Secure a Decisive Victory in Building a Moderately Prosperous Society in All
Respects and Strive for the Great Success of Socialism with Chinese Characteristics for a
New Era: Report Delivered to the 19th National Congress of the Communist Party of
China’, Xinhuanet, 18 October 2017, www.xinhuanet.com/english/download/Xi_
Jinping’s_report_at_19th_CPC_National_Congress.pdf.
70
People’s Republic of China, ‘State Council Notice Concerning Issuance of the
Planning Outline’.
71
Constitution of the Communist Party of the People’s Republic of China (General
Program).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
Core Socialist Values unveiled in 2012 play an important role.72
Entanglement is meant to be conscious and coordinated rather than
organic and serendipitous73 – highlighting the difference between a
central-planning (public and administrative) versus a markets-based
(private and demand driven) political order.
The social credit initiative was comprehensive. It was envisioned that
when completed, social credit systems would manage key operations in
four sectors: government, commercial activities, social integrity and
judicial credibility.74 With respect to the role of social credit in govern-
ment, the focus was on the use of data-driven analytics tied to algorithms
that produced the basis for accountability to result in rewards or punish-
ments around a variety of governmental actions. These included: admin-
istrative permissions, government procurement, tendering and bidding,
labour and employment, social security, scientific research management,
cadre promotion and appointment, management and supervision, appli-
cation for government financial support and other such areas and
fostering the development of a credit services market. Clearly, data-
driven analytics and its resulting assessment system would produce an
immediate effect on those whose conduct triggers measured responses.
For those who met credit minima, access to benefits would be enhanced.
Those assessed at a low enough level would be placed on an effective
blacklist that would make functioning in a modern society substantially
more difficult and costly, absent readjustment. Moreover, social credit
was also to be used as a tool for intra-governmental accountability, and to
monitor civil servants.
Social credit mechanisms were also directed towards a very broad
range of commercial activities – whether by state-owned enterprises or
the private sector. Private behaviour by individuals was also to be man-
aged through social credit systems under the umbrella of enhancing
‘Social Integrity’. An area of particular note for the application of data-
driven analytics was that of the judicial system. The specific focus was on
judicial creditability and on the integrity of the judicial function and the
performance (and accountability) of judges for their work. The State
72
L. C. Backer, ‘Blacklists and Social Credit Regimes in China’, interdisciplinary symposium
Super-Scoring? Data-Driven Societal Technologies in China and Western-Style
Democracies as a New Challenge for Education (Cologne, Germany, 11 October 2019),
www.superscoring.de/2019/08/28/blacklists-and-social-credit-regimes-in-china/.
73
Ibid.
74
People’s Republic of China, ‘State Council Notice Concerning Issuance of the Planning
Outline’, II(1)–(4).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Council identified a number of areas: proceedings transparency, prosecu-
torial and public security services conduct, the operation of judicial
administrative systems and law enforcement standardization. Here one
notes the likelihood of a vertical entanglement. Judges are the objects of
law and the agents of procedures reflected in the legalities of law and
regulation. Yet the content of the way those functions are assessed (and
consequentially the way that the implementation of legal duties is under-
stood and measured, and thus interpreted) become a function of a
distinct legality – that of the social credit system applied to the judge.
Data-driven projects might well include the production of data-driven
algorithms to guide judicial decision-making or to develop guidelines for
charging and prosecution. Here one encounters an entanglement in
which the discretionary scope of one system is constrained by the
operation of the other.
The societal effects of social credit programmes were to be enhanced
through the application of these mechanisms on education and culture
projects. Social credit in the development of education system reform was
to be tied to the construction of the socialist core value system. Education
was to be a means for the socialization of social credit mentalities and its
general acceptance.75 Assessment would be built around parameters for
judging the development and operation of ‘moral’ classrooms. These are
to be built around the establishment of models of appropriate conduct.76
Appropriate conduct, in turn, is to be assessed against the twelve socialist
values that have been established after the CPC’s 18th Congress: ‘Core
socialist values comprise a set of moral principles summarized by central
authorities as prosperity, democracy, civility, harmony, freedom,
75
People’s Republic of China, ‘State Council Notice Concerning Issuance of the
Planning Outline’.
76
See L. C. Backer, ‘What Is the Fundamental Task of Education? Xi Jinping’s Concept of
立德树人 [Cultivating People of Moral Character] and Its Implementation through
Undergraduate University Reform in 教育部关于一流本科课程建设的实施意见
[Implementation Opinions of the Ministry of Education on the Construction of First-
Class Undergraduate Courses]’, Law at the End of the Day (1 November 2019), https://
lcbpsusenate.blogspot.com/2019/11/what-s-fundamental-task-of-education-xi.html. The
Ministry of Education’s draft Measures for the Appointment and Management of
Foreign Teachers [外籍教师聘任和管理办法] (www.moj.gov.cn/news/content/
2020–07/21/zlk_3252777.html) establishes the parameters by which the Chinese social
credit system is extended to foreign teachers including assessments relating to the foreign
teacher’s compliance with law, ethics and quality of teaching be included in a national
foreign teacher comprehensive information service platform. Article 31 includes the list
of activities that will permit dismissal and require listing on a social credit blacklist.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
equality, justice, the rule of law, patriotism, dedication, integrity and
friendliness.’77 To that end, state organs are encouraged to oversee special
campaigns in focus sectors, and to ‘persist in correcting unhealthy trends
and evil practices of abusing power for personal gain, lying and cheating,
forgetting integrity when tempted by gains, benefiting oneself at others’
expense, etc., and establish trends of sectoral sincerity and integrity’.78
All of this is to be accomplished by building social credit baseline
systems79 and their mechanisms.80 These systems were then to be oper-
ationalized through blacklists. Blacklists – made up of the names of
people whose social credit scores fall below certain thresholds – have
already begun to have a substantial effect in everyday life. The system is
manifested through ratings, and more importantly from the collection of
blacklists produced as a function of ratings. Blacklists then affect the
availability of goods and services.81
These, then, will serve as the systems through which entanglement will
be coordinated. Baseline systems were identified as (1) sectoral credit
information systems; (2) local information systems; (3) credit investi-
gation systems; and (4) uniform credit investigation platforms in the
financial sector. In addition, government in cooperation with the private
sector were to develop credit information exchange and sharing. These
shall provide the regulatory structures for the operationalization of data-
driven assessment and punishment/reward systems. The forms of
entanglement are also identified as (1) incentive structures and punish-
ments for deviations; and (2) legal, regulatory and standards systems for
credit.
The entanglements of social credit within the Chinese context are as
comprehensive as its ambitions. Social credit is meant to provide a new
language for law, at least as it is meant to serve to control behaviour. At
the same time, the constitution of social credit is driven by law. That is,
law serves as a constituting element of regulatory systems that themselves
77
China Daily, ‘Core Socialist Values’ (2017), www.chinadaily.com.cn/china/19thcpcnatio
nalcongress/2017–10/12/content_33160115.htm.
78
People’s Republic of China, ‘State Council Notice Concerning Issuance of the
Planning Outline’.
79
Ibid., part IV.
80
Ibid., part V.
81
T. F. Chan, ‘China’s Social Credit System Has Blocked People from Taking 11 Million
Flights and 4 Million Train Trips’, Business Insider (21 May 2018), www.businessinsider
.com/china-social-credit-system-blocked-people-taking-flights-train-trips-2018–5?r=
UK&IR=T.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
are grounded in forms and practices that are not law. At the same time,
those forms and practices of social credit then drive law as it is applied.
They do so by giving meaning to the objectives and expectations written
into law by the way that social credit is administered through the process
of identifying behaviour, analysing its meaning and attaching conse-
quences. At the same time, social credit provides a bridge between law,
compliance and assessment systems. In the process it also helps shape the
cultures within which expectations are shaped and cultural habits
formed, which then lend themselves to expression in the normative
content of law. Here social credit moves entanglement into an ecology
of interrelated subsystems all deployed to move forward the political
project of the CPC.
82
L. C. Backer, ‘Theorizing Regulatory Governance within Its Ecology: The Structure of
Management in an Age of Globalization’ (2018) 24 Contemporary Politics 607–30.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
actors.83 These actors also exercise governance authority in traditional
ways (through rules, laws and the exercise of political and economic
power). But for them, increasingly, assessment and accountability
regimes, born of compliance objectives within the spaces and inter-
spaces of conventional law/normative systems,84 provide incentives to
manage populations above the multiple governance spaces to which they
might have to account.
What emerges in the West are systems of ‘governance, risk manage-
ment, and compliance’.85 Where in China the government (under the
guidance of the CPC) pushes data-driven governance, in the West it is
the market, and the delegation of managerial authority (compliance),
that tends to drive these oversight and control systems – the literature
highlighting this dynamic is by now well developed.86 Anyone can rate
and assess – but there are markets for rating as well; the most successful
producers of rating enhance their profitability in markets for ratings.
They focus on creating everything from hierarchies of value to assess-
ment of conformity to a variety of corporate social responsibility obliga-
tions.87 Less well developed is the conception of data, and the ratings that
draw on them, as a system with regulatory effect. ‘Simply put, because of
big data, managers can measure, and hence know, radically more about
their businesses, and directly translate that knowledge into improved
decision making and performance.’88 Data-driven governance is essential
for a variety of private sphere activities, and has become a business in its
own right.89
For both, data-driven analytics and the algorithms through which
data-based judgements can be formed and consequences processed have
83
L. C. Backer, ‘The Structural Characteristics of Global Law for the 21st Century: Fracture,
Fluidity, Permeability, and Polycentricity’ (2017) 17 Tilburg Law Review 177–99.
84
American Law Institute, Principles of the Law: Compliance, Risk Management, and
Enforcement, Tentative Draft No. 1 (American Law Institute, 2019).
85
Cf. R. M. Steinberg, Governance, Risk Management, and Compliance: It Can’t Happen to
Us; Avoiding Corporate Disaster While Driving Success (John Wiley & Sons, 2011).
86
T. J. Sinclair, The New Masters of Capital: American Bond Rating Agencies and the Politics
of Creditworthiness (Cornell University Press, 2014); L. J. White, ‘Markets: The Credit
Rating Agencies’ (2010) 24 Journal of Economic Perspectives 211–26; E. I. Altman and H.
A. Rijken, ‘How Rating Agencies Achieve Rating Stability’ (2004) 28 Journal of Banking &
Finance 2679–714; see also essays in Davis et al., Governance by Indicators.
87
Backer, ‘Next Generation Law’.
88
A. McAfee and E. Brynjolffon, ‘Big Data: The Management Revolution’, Harvard Business
Review (October 2012), https://hbr.org/2012/10/big-data-the-management-revolution.
89
C. Tang, The Data Industry: The Business and Economics of Information and Big Data
(Wiley, 2016).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
become important elements of risk and compliance systems in five
critical areas. The first is law enforcement (state entities) and compliance
(private entities). Data-driven analytics here is presented as a method for
complying with legal duty or responsibility. Administrative regulation
and law provide the objectives, but the implementation occurs within
automized data-driven systems. Examples include regimes for the distri-
bution of governmental funds through revenue sharing and other pro-
grammes.90 The second is transparency regimes: ‘It is used within an
organization or community to enhance its operation and discipline its
members; it is used externally to enhance legitimacy (norm) and
accountability (technique) among stakeholders who have an interest in
but not a direct participation in the operation of the enterprise.’91 The
third is in controlling behaviour. For economic enterprises this was
driven in part by law,92 and in part by changes in the way that adminis-
trative officials exercised authority.93 Data-based analytics may be essen-
tial in the exercise of prosecutorial discretion in the USA94 and the UK.95
Businesses are increasingly using data-driven analytics to control behav-
iours through health and wellness programmes. The fourth, shaping
cultures, is possible when monitoring (micro-surveillance) is tied to
transparency and enforcement. Smoking campaigns are a well-known
example.96 Here one entangles moral value systems (about smoking) into
political action (anti-smoking regulation) which is then entangled within
medical and quantitative measures of harm which contribute to health
90
Department of Commerce v. New York, Supreme Court No. 18–966, 588 US (2019).
91
L. C. Backer, ‘Transparency between Norm, Technique and Property in International Law
and Governance: The Example of Corporate Disclosure Regimes and Environmental
Impacts’ (2013) 22 Minnesota Journal of International Law 1–70.
92
Under the Delaware fiduciary duty law, Stone v. Ritter, 911 A.2d 362 (Del. 2006).
93
J. Nassikas, J. Tan and L. Carson, ‘New DOJ Compliance Program Guidance’, Harvard
Law School Forum on Corporate Governance (10 June 2019), https://corpgov.law
.harvard.edu/2019/06/10/new-doj-compliance-program-guidance/ (‘Compliance pro-
gram effectiveness is a key variable DOJ takes into consideration when (1) making
charging decisions and exercising prosecutorial discretion, (2) making sentencing recom-
mendations, including calculating recommended fines, and (3) deciding whether to
impose reporting requirements or appoint an outside compliance monitor as part of a
corporate resolution’).
94
US Department of Justice, ‘The Fraud Section’s Foreign Corrupt Practices Act
Enforcement Plan and Guidance’ (5 April 2016), www.justice.gov/criminal-fraud/file/
838416/download.
95
See UK Criminal Finances Act 2017, chapter 22.
96
T. Hu et al., ‘The Impact of California Proposition 99, a Major Anti-smoking Law, on
Cigarette Consumption’ (1994) 15 Journal of Public Health Policy 26–36.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
rankings that affect private markets for insurance, and rankings that may
affect individual access to credit or education.97 Fifth is accountability as
assessment, self-assessment and accountability regimes at the individual
and entity levels.98 These entangle both legal systems through compli-
ance regimes and markets-based systems through data-driven ratings
systems.
Entanglements between data and conventional governance orders have
only recently emerged more clearly. The recent controversy over the
inclusion of questions about citizenship on the US census provides a
case in point.99 Inclusion of the question would generate data, a core
operational principle of census taking. That generation is coupled with a
host of conventional law which relied on the governance of census data
generation for its own operation. But the generation of data has signifi-
cant consequences precisely because the system of regulation into which
those data are injected is itself based on the way data are curated. Here is
the point of entanglement between census as a system of data generation,
census as the jurisdiction of compiling a quantitative narrative image of
the American population, and census as a necessary predicate for the
operationalization of a number of conflicting political objectives
expressed though the law of states and the federal government. It’s no
surprise to see census questions shifting with the times: ‘Lots of questions
go off the census when they’re not very important anymore.’100 The
conflict within data governance became famously entangled with the
legal regulation of the administrative state in a US Supreme Court
opinion most notable for its recognition of conflict expressed in rules
governing the exercise of political discretion within a web of legislation
where the interests of secondary sovereigns are affected.101
97
C. P. Guzalian, M. A. Stein and H. S. Akiskal, ‘Credit Scores, Lending, and Psychological
Disability’ (2015) 95 Boston University Law Review 1807.
98
L. C. Backer, ‘Unpacking Accountability in Business and Human Rights: The
Multinational Enterprise, the State, and the International Community’, in L. Enneking,
I. Giesen, A.-J. Schaap, C. Ryngaert, F. Kristen and L. Roorda (eds), Accountability and
International Business Operations: Providing Justice for Corporate Violations of Human
Rights, Labor and Environmental Standards (Routledge, 2019).
99
Department of Commerce v. New York (2019).
100
C. E. Shoichet, ‘Why Putting a Citizenship Question on the Census Is a Big Deal’, CNN
(28 March 2018), https://edition.cnn.com/2018/03/27/politics/census-citizenship-ques
tion-explainer/index.html (quoting University of Wisconsin Professor Margo
Anderson).
101
Department of Commerce v. New York (2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Another important point of entanglement between data-driven and
traditional legalities centres on the scope and principles through which
data may be harvested. Most aggressive – again voluntary and on a
bargained for basis – are chip implants for employees102 by merchants
(including the state). This is a system grounded in consent, in value
added as an inducement for participation. Increasingly, however, states
have sought to use their legislative authority to restrict, or at least
manage, this essential feature of data-based rule systems, by legislating
the legal effects (and limits) of consent, especially within an employment
relationship.103 More passive are the seamless systems of cameras, credit
card transactions, turnstiles, passes for highway tolls, key stroke and
internet tracking systems and the like that can effectively track individ-
uals and record their activities on a continuous basis. Their regulatory
effect is now well known.104 Yet their entanglements with plural legal
systems have only just invaded the consciousness of regulatory stake-
holders. Emerging issues include privacy rights;105 and rights to be
forgotten.106 But the focus has also turned to the application of issues
of race, gender and other non-discrimination law and policy to the
structures of data-driven governance bound up in the extraction of
information for behaviour management ends.107 Conversely, data-driven
systems themselves have entangled with law systems in the area of
discrimination law by providing a complementary system, the products
102
M. Fox, ‘Installing Microchips in Employees Is “the Right Thing to Do,” CEO says’,
CNBC (24 July 2017), www.cnbc.com/2017/07/24/installing-microchips-in-employees-
is-the-right-thing-to-do-ceo-says.html.
103
A. Keshner, ‘States Are Cracking Down on Companies Microchipping their Employees’
MarketWatch (4 February 2020), www.marketwatch.com/story/states-are-cracking-
down-on-companies-microchipping-their-employees-how-common-is-it-and-why-
does-it-happen-2020-02-03.
104
N. Just and M. Latzer, ‘Governance by Algorithms: Reality Construction by Algorithmic
Selection on the Internet’ (2017) 39 Media, Culture & Society 238–58; P. Bergevin,
‘Addicted to Ratings: The Case for Reducing Governments’ Reliance on Credit
Ratings’ (May 2010) 130 C. D. How Institute Backgrounder; F. Partnoy, ‘The Siskel
and Ebert of Financial Markets: Two Thumbs Down for the Credit Rating Agencies’
(1999) 77 Washington University Law Quarterly 619–712.
105
W. Kerber, ‘Digital Markets, Data, and Privacy: Competition Law, Consumer Law and
Data Protection’ (2016) 11 Journal of Intellectual Property Law & Practice 856–66; S.
Spiekermann, A. Acquisti, R. Böhme and L. Hui, ‘The Challenges of Data Markets and
Privacy’ (2015) 25 Electronic Markets 161–7.
106
J. Rosen, ‘The Right to Be Forgotten’ (2012) 64 Stanford Law Review 88.
107
E.g., S. U. Noble, Algorithms of Oppression: How Search Engines Reinforce Racism (New
York University Press, 2018); V. Eubanks, Automating Inequality: How High-Tech Tools
Profile, Police, and Punish the Poor (St Martin’s Press, 2018).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
of which are used by law systems as techniques of proof of discriminatory
intent or in forming or assessing policy and regulations.108
Compliance itself is a data-driven exercise, but one in which the
parameters are set by legal systems, administered through the actors
onto which compliance is imposed, and assessed and disciplined either
by the state or private actors.109 Compliance is expressed as the private
law internal governance systems that implement the delegation of
responsibility (in part) from the state effected through law or regulatory
directive. These include implementing administrative guidance,110 to
compliance systems built around disclosure and reporting systems, for
example, the French Supply Chain Due Diligence Law111 or the
Australian Modern Slavery Law.112 The second is crafted through data-
driven assessment systems that take their objectives from the policies of
private law internal governance and which rely heavily on markets for
external disciplining.113 These entanglements are clearest in the context
of corporate governance.114
Of all of the forms of data-driven governance, perhaps the closest the
West has to the emerging Chinese social credit initiative are credit rating
agencies. Financial credit rating agencies, for example, become actors in
the governance of financial markets through their production of a stand-
ardized rating of risk (creditworthiness), which is then used for making
investment decisions, and consequently to make the regulation of financial
markets dependent on the risk assessed.115 These operate within a market
108
E.g., J. Ringelheim, ‘Collecting Racial or Ethnic Data for Anti-discrimination Policies:
A U.S.–Europe Comparison’ (2008) 10 Rutgers Race and Law Review 39; P. Simon, ‘The
Measurement of Racial Discrimination: The Policy Use of Statistics’ (2005) 57
International Social Science Journal 9–25; M. Chamallas, ‘Questioning the Use of
Race-Specific and Gender-Specific Economic Data in Tort Litigation: A Constitutional
Argument’ (1994) 63 Fordham Law Review 73.
109
American Law Institute, Principles of the Law.
110
US Department of Justice, ‘The Fraud Section’s Foreign Corrupt Practices Act
Enforcement Plan and Guidance’.
111
F. Baddache, ‘What to Learn from France’s and UK’s Human Rights Due Diligence
Laws?’, KSAPA (15 June 2019), https://ksapa.org/what-to-learn-from-france-and-uks-
human-rights-due-diligence-laws/.
112
See Australian Modern Slavery Act 2018, Act No. 153 of 2018.
113
Backer, ‘Theorizing Regulatory Governance Within Its Ecology’.
114
P. Baxter, ‘Corporate Governance Ratings and Financial Performance: Evidence from
Australia’ (2014) 5 International Journal of Corporate Governance 178–96.
115
D. Kerwer, ‘Standardizing as Governance: The Case of Credit Ratings Agencies’, in A.
Heritier (ed.), Reinventing European and International Governance (Rowman &
Littlefield, 2002), pp. 293–316, at p. 294.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
for services with a few big players rating business and public credit. Their
profit derives from subscriptions or issuer-pays models of income. This
produces a markets-driven model that mimics the effects of Chinese
centralizing and public control models. These credit agencies’ businesses
are grounded in data-based analytics applied to objectives and their effect
is to discipline behaviours through reward–punishment systems derived
from their analytics. Their systems are functionally differentiated, and they
exhibit only a necessary unification even within the same field. At the same
time, their activities serve as the basis for regulation, and are, to some
extent, regulated by the state whose finances they in turn rate.
4.5 Conclusion
The relationship between traditional governance orders, in a context of
spatially distinct but intermeshed legal/normative orders, remains to be
fully explored. This chapter suggested some points of entry and on
fundamental approaches. First, the use of metrics and the quantification
of accountability has moved beyond an increasingly sophisticated palette
of rankings and inducement to become a regulatory space in its own
right. Second, that regulatory space embeds politics and law within the
construction of its analytics and the determination of the meaning of
rankings. China is building a centralized system tied to its political
organization. Most of the elements of social credit have already been
developed in the West. But the unification of the various elements, and
their seamless operation, would be a great innovation. While the West
approaches data-driven governance entanglements through the lens of
privatization and markets,116 China inverts the trajectories of entangle-
ment, focusing instead on recreating within the state the universe of data-
driven governance in which law becomes the instruction manual for the
operation of social ordering through data-driven analytics. Third, these
systems pose a challenge for the conventional understanding of entangle-
ment among systems all characterized by qualitative approaches to
regulation. Perhaps most interesting of all the consequences of these
social credit systems may be their ability to absorb traditional systems,
and in that process of absorption to reduce the centrality of borderlands
between systems.
116
C. Cutler, ‘The Privatization of Global Governance and the Modern Law Merchant’, in
A. Heritier (ed.), Reinventing European and International Governance (Rowman &
Littlefield, 2002), pp. 127–58.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
Hints of this trajectory are evident in the movement towards compli-
ance and accountability. These increasingly data-driven exercises turn
traditional governance systems, and the governance systems arising
between and within them (conventional spatiality of governance), into
the generators of data that themselves can be subject to management in
accordance with principles and objectives. These objectives may them-
selves be drawn from the political-cultural assumptions of society or
themselves may be dynamic expressions monitored through the aggre-
gate conduct of data generators themselves. The multiplicity of legal
regimes, then, is itself a source of data useful for data-driven analytics
that can manage these as well as aid in the management of systems.117
This suggests entanglement of a different order, between qualitative and
quantitative regulatory measures which increasingly fold one into the
other while retaining an element of autonomy based on the different
regulatory spaces from which they are sourced.
What is clear is that entanglement can no longer ignore the legalities of
data-driven governance even as it seeks to embed its language and
structure its communication across systems that do not speak the same
language. The entanglements of a law after modernity118 become more
complicated – not merely as between distinct and polycentric rule
systems sharing common characteristics (the forms and functions of
rules), but now between systems that do not speak the same language
(words versus metrics, compliance versus assessment, etc.). Governance
evolves from the language and conceptual universe of politics and prin-
ciples to the language of the operating system grounded in systemic
objectives. In a world of algorithms, those who would devise them will
be king. And those who would be kings in Western democratic republics
may well soon be scientists and not lawyers.119 ‘When you look at the
most important issues facing our country, it is climate change or health-
care policy or cyber security, the integrity of our elections. Who better to
address these issues than a scientist?’120 Who better indeed, when the
117
E. Finn, What Algorithms Want: Imagination in the Age of Computing (MIT Press,
2017).
118
S. Douglas-Scott, Law after Modernity (Hart Publishing, 2013).
119
M. Dhar, ‘Hey, Congress: Scientists Are Coming for Your Seats’, LiveScience (26 April
2018), www.livescience.com/62411-scientists-running-for-congress.html.
120
K. Karson, ‘“The Year that Science Strikes Back”: Historic Number of Scientists
Taking Over Ballots in 2018’, ABC News (9 February 2018), https://abcnews.go.com/
Politics/year-science-strikes-back-historic-number-scientists-taking/story?id=52959780
(quoting Shaughnessy Naughton president of 314 Action organization).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
state is a container for accountability systems through data-driven algo-
rithms? That, ultimately, suggests the great challenge for legalities and
their entanglements where society continues to move beyond the prob-
lems of entangling legal systems to those for which the econometrician,
the statistician and the moralist121 may have as great a voice as the lawyer
or the judge, and the politician or administrator.122
121
F. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals: A Polemic, trans. W. Kaufmann and R. J.
Hollindale (Vintage Books, 1967), pp. 58–9.
122
J. Cheney-Lippold, We Are Data: Algorithms and the Making of Our Digital Selves
(New York University Press, 2017).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
5
5.1 Introduction
This chapter aims to make three main descriptive and implicitly critical
points of varying importance regarding the phenomenon of ‘entangled
legalities’,1 using China’s ‘Belt and Road Initiative’ (BRI) as a platform
for discussion.
The first point, deceptively the simplest, is that legal entanglement is
not necessarily an outcome of chance, anarchy or disorder, but can rather
be produced and augmented by centralized (albeit not necessarily struc-
turally hierarchical) political aims and ideas, that create legal and regula-
tory ripple effects, in ways both intended and unintended. Thus, for
example, BRI, also previously known as the ‘One Belt, One Road’
(OBOR) and more romantically as the ‘New Silk Road’, is a central
controlling idea in the People’s Republic of China’s (PRC) thirteenth
five-year plan (2016–20) and beyond,2 clearly guided from above within
Thanks to Yael Berda, Marcia Harpaz, Nico Krisch and Heng Wang for comments on earlier
drafts, and to the participants in the May, 2018 workshop on ‘Entangled Legalities’ at the
Graduate Institute Geneva. The cut-off date for factual discussion in this chapter is
15 September 2019, and all websites referred to were accessible then.
1
As identified in this project’s framing piece, see Chapter 1.
2
See Chapter 51, ‘The 13th Five-Year Plan for Economic and Social Development of the
People’s Republic of China’ (official translation https://en.ndrc.gov.cn/newsrelease_8232/
201612/P020191101481868235378.pdf); and National Development and Reform
Commission, Ministry of Foreign Affairs and Ministry of Commerce of the People’s
Republic of China, ‘Vision and Actions on Jointly Building Silk Road Economic Belt
and 21st-Century Maritime Silk Road’ (March 2015), https://en.ndrc.gov.cn/newsrelease_
8232/201612/P020191101481868235378.pdf. For comprehensive analysis, see J. Chaisse
and J. Górski (eds), The Belt and Road Initiative: Law Economics and Politics (Brill Nijhoff,
2018); and H. Wang, ‘China’s Approach to the Belt and Road Initiative: Scope, Character
and Sustainability’ (2019) 22(1) Journal of International Economic Law 29–55.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
PRC political hierarchies.3 Nevertheless, its local and international legal
implications are in many respects non-hierarchical, diffuse and decen-
tralized, touching upon a very broad and diverse range of distinctive,
though not entirely discrete, norms, systems and especially actors. The
interaction between the presumptively hierarchical and the miscellany of
interacting parts, so to speak, produces a high level of legal entanglement.
In other words, legal entanglement, or entangled legalities, can be the
outcome of strategic thinking and intent, a type of deliberate order of
governance, applied to a diversity of actors that serve as nodes or bridges
of entanglement between otherwise disparate legal systems. These ideas
are expanded on in Section 5.2, using BRI as a case study.
The second point is that, a priori, entangled legalities cannot exist
without high degrees of separateness or compartmentalization between
norms, systems and actors, even as they constantly interact with each
other. This is not merely a trite dialectical observation – that is, just like
threads in a ball of string, there must be separate strands of legality for
them to become entangled – but a statement related to the structures of
legal and law-relevant practice. A global or multi-regional governance
project – if that is indeed what it is4 – as massive and largely opaque but
increasingly familiar as BRI, is obviously overwhelming in its scope and
implications to individuals and indeed to organizations (both public and
private, governmental and non-governmental). Arguably, most legal
practitioners and/or private/public economic operators and government
officials in the multitude of relevant jurisdictions do not consider their
everyday work to be part of the overall project of BRI or related to it, or at
least it’s not the primary way in which they understand their work. Many
3
On BRI/OBOR as a global geopolitical and economic strategy, see U. W. Chohan, ‘The
Political Economy of OBOR and the Global Economic Center of Gravity’, in J. Chaisse and
J. Górski (eds), The Belt and Road Initiative: Law Economics and Politics (Brill Nijhoff,
2018), pp. 59–82, at p. 59. A much harder line, that envisions China’s strategy for global
supremacy, is taken in M. Pillsbury, The Hundred-Year Marathon: China’s Secret to
Replace America as the Global Superpower (St. Martin’s Griffin, 2015), p. 244, mentioning
BRI/OBOR only as a means to an end.
4
Many contend that it is, and China does not seem to conceal this; see W. Zhou and
M. Esteban, ‘Beyond Balancing: China’s Approach towards the Belt and Road Initiative’
(2018) 27 Journal of Contemporary China 487–501; W. A. Callahan, ‘China’s “Asia Dream”:
The Belt Road Initiative and the New Regional Order’ (2016) 1 Asian Journal of
Comparative Politics 226–43. A fascinating though clearly propagandist exposé of BRI as a
global governance project, including rhetoric on ‘the construction of a community with a
shared future for mankind’, can be found in H. Liang and Y. Zhang, The Theoretical System
of Belt and Road Initiative (People’s Publishing House and Springer Nature, 2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
might not even know what BRI actually is, if only because it does not
conform to more standardized international economic legal structures
and conventions. They are just ‘doing their job’ within much more
limited, object specific, cognitively manageable and often jurisdictionally
divided (ratione loci or ratione materiae), a.k.a. ‘siloed’, strands of an
overarching legal entanglement to which they might be largely oblivious
in practice. This is demonstrated through a stylized and imagined eth-
nography (which is nevertheless well grounded in realistic scenarios),
undertaken in Section 5.3, the heart of this chapter, in which I trace the
different legal practices and local perspectives of particular individual
actors, legal and other,5 engaging in this era, in different ways, with BRI.
These actors are the contact points of entanglement, each of them
representing a normative and/or legal system that is entangled with
BRI and with other systems. These actors include, for example, an
investment protection lawyer at MOFCOM6 in Beijing, a public procure-
ment regulator in Greece, an associate or partner at (insert big law firm
name) in Kazakhstan, insurgents in Balochistan and judges in national
constitutional courts and indeed regional courts such as the Court of
Justice of the European Union and the European Court of Human
Rights.
Taking note of their separateness, the distinctive and representative
existence of these individual narratives should not be taken to imply
5
The focus here is deliberately on individual actors and agents engaged with different levels
and dimensions of law; the role of the individual in international legality is increasingly
acknowledged, from a variety of perspectives. See, e.g., A. Peters, Beyond Human Rights:
The Legal Status of the Individual in International Law (Cambridge University Press,
2016); T. Megiddo, ‘Methodological Individualism’ (2019) 60 Harvard Journal of
International Law 219–80; and T. Broude and I. Levy, ‘Outcome Bias and Expertise in
Investigations under International Humanitarian Law’ (2020) 30(4) European Journal of
International Law, 1303–18.
6
MOFCOM is China’s Ministry of Commerce. As international trade and governance
scholars Gao and Shaffer have recently put it, ‘MOFCOM has a Janus-faced role of looking
inward and outward’, in the sense that it regulates both domestic and international
commercial affairs – see G. Shaffer and H. Gao, ‘China’s Rise: How it took on the U.S.
at the WTO’ (2018) 1 University of Illinois Law Review 115–84, at 138. As in trade, the
MOFCOM mandate covers both outgoing and incoming foreign investment, including
International Investment Agreements; see K. P. Sauvant and V. Z. Chen, ‘China’s
Regulatory Framework for Outward Foreign Direct Investment’ (2014) 7 China
Economic Journal 141–63; and A. C. Dai, ‘The International Investment Agreement
Network under the “Belt and Road” Initiative’, in J. Chaisse and J. Górski (eds), The
Belt and Road Initiative: Law Economics and Politics (Brill Nijhoff, 2018), pp. 220–49, at
p. 220.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
disentanglement in any way. Rather, the opposite is true; this separate-
ness establishes a pattern of a set of different systems, approaches and
perspectives that coexist with normative entanglement. Put differently,
this is not simple, straightforward self-containment or ‘fragmentation’ of
international law.7 Rather, to my mind the main contribution of the
concept of international or transnational legal entanglement is its
emphasis on querying how different legal norms and systems, with
heterogeneous yet often shared legal foundations, engage with each other
in unanticipated circumstances. Thus, Section 5.4 demonstrates how the
seemingly separate worlds of law and practice can come together, and
indeed are already conjoined in an actual case – the Belgrade–Budapest
railway project – emphasizing their interdependencies, some of them
unexpected and counterintuitive, but in any case, deeply legally
entangled.
The third point, discussed in the concluding Section 5.5, builds on the
first two, and is well demonstrated by BRI, namely that entangled
legalities may be strongly and positively associated with the gradual,
messy and piecemeal process of empire-building, or at least empire-
bidding. The combination of top-down and bottom-up forces of legal
entanglement create flexibilities and benefits for hegemonic contenders,
such as in the present case, China, that well acknowledge their own
political constraints.
7
The fragmentation of international law has been a central feature in both the practice and
theorization of international law since the rise of distinct regimes and institutions in the
1990s, exacerbating the decentralized and anarchic nature of international law (see, e.g.,
M. Koskenniemi and P. Leino, ‘Fragmentation of International Law? Postmodern
Anxieties’ (2002) 15 Leiden Journal of International Law 553–79; Report of the Study
Group of the International Law Commission, ‘Fragmentation of International Law:
Difficulties Arising from the Diversification and Expansion of International Law’ (13
April 2006) UN Doc A/CN.4/L.682, as corrected (11 August 2006) UN Doc A/CN.4/
L.682/Corr.1 (finalized by Martti Koskenniemi). It remains a fixture of international legal
debate to this day (e.g. T. Megiddo, ‘Beyond Fragmentation: On International Law’s
Integrationist Forces’ (2019) 44 Yale Journal of International Law 115–48).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
the neat analytics of the Kelsenian idea of a ‘hierarchical structure’ or
stufenbau8 – in the absence of any clear pyramid between the enmeshed
norms involved – or any pretence of distinguishing, in a Hohfeldian
sense, between rights, liberties, powers and immunities.9 Entangled legal-
ities plainly lie in the theoretical and practical realms of legal pluralism,10
characterized as ‘complex intertwined networks’.11 Add to these the
substantively contested but formally accepted public and private law
distinction,12 and further dimensions of entanglement emerge. It is not,
however, always that difficult to ‘fix the own point of departure’ of
entanglement,13 if one accepts that entangled legalities can actually be a
preference, ‘from above’. They may express a preference for legal plural-
ity that serves centralized and powerful interests and ideas – even
hegemonic aspirations – better and more flexibly than a clearly defined
hierarchy. This is to say that entanglement can be an established mode of
legal and regulatory governance, at both macro (centralized) and micro
(localized) levels. Regarding public (and private) international law it is
not merely a phenomenon of the famous international ‘anarchical soci-
ety’14 – it is not necessarily a form of anarchy at all, even if it defies the
suffix ‘-archy’. Thus, in terms of ‘pathways’ to its emergence, there is a
type of legal entanglement that is inevitably a combination of mutual
benefit, appeal and coercion,15 or alternatively, imperfectly close to
8
H. Kelsen, ‘The Concept of the Legal Order’ (1982) 27 The American Journal of
Jurisprudence 64–84.
9
W. N. Hohfeld, ‘Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning’ (1917)
26 The Yale Law Journal 710–70.
10
See Section 1.1 in Chapter 1.
11
T. Duve, ‘Entanglements in Legal History: Introductory Remarks’, in T. Duve (ed.),
Entanglements in Legal History: Conceptual Approaches (Max Planck Institute for Legal
History, 2014), pp. 3–25, at p. 8.
12
M. Rosenfeld, ‘Rethinking the Boundaries between Public Law and Private Law for the
Twenty First Century: An Introduction’ (2013) 11 International Journal of Constitutional
Law 125–28 and subsequent contributions in the same issue of the journal: A. Supiot,
‘The Public–Private Relation in the Context of Today’s Refeudalization’ (2013) 11
International Journal of Constitutional Law 129–45; P. Goodrich, ‘The Political
Theology of Private Law’ (2013) 11 International Journal of Constitutional Law 146–61;
and J. Resnik, ‘Globalization(s), Privatization(s), Constitutionalization, and Statization:
Icons and Experiences of Sovereignty in the 21st Century’ (2013) 11 International Journal
of Constitutional Law 162–99.
13
Duve, ‘Entanglements in Legal History’, p. 8.
14
H. Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics (Macmillan, 1977).
15
Krisch identifies these three ‘pathways’ to entanglement, see Section 1.4.2 in Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
coercion, the outcome of a fourth pathway – through implicit dominance
or disguised hegemony.
In other words, whether by default or by design, a central actor, which
has the authority and perhaps even the real power to create a structured,
hierarchical legal system, may refrain from doing so or even prefer not to
if this conduct better serves its goals, and if the costs of hierarchical
regulation outweigh its benefits. Moreover, grand ideas can be both
centralized as guiding elements – telos or teloi – and in this respect can
be very effective in creating localized effects through legal entanglement.
The BRI is, arguably, a case in point. I return to this, in brief, in
Section 5.5.
But what is BRI or the ‘New Silk Road’, actually? BRI defies definition,
yet cannot be ignored. At its rawest, it can be understood straightfor-
wardly as an ambitious programme of infrastructure project finance
within China (primarily in the less developed western provinces)16 and
in dozens of other countries, spreading to the south and mainly outward
to the west of China, all to the tune of US$1 trillion to be invested over
twenty years. BRI, which has been often been analogized to the post-
World War II ‘Marshall Plan’,17 can transform the living conditions of
hundreds of millions throughout the nether lands of South and Central
Asia, reaching into Africa and, more discreetly, into Europe.
Indeed, Europe seems to be very much a crucial economic objective of
BRI, presenting a ‘pivot to Europe’ in response to the Obama adminis-
tration’s now all but forgotten ‘Pivot to Asia’ which included US leader-
ship in negotiations over the Trans-Pacific Partnership (TPP),18 a policy
16
See A. Chatzky and J. McBride, ‘China’s Massive Belt and Road Initiative’, Council on
Foreign Relations Backgrounder (21 May 2019), www.cfr.org/backgrounder/chinas-mas
sive-belt-and-road-initiative.
17
Quite recently: ‘Will China’s Belt and Road Initiative Outdo the Marshall Plan?’, The
Economist (8 March 2018), www.economist.com/finance-and-economics/2018/03/08/
will-chinas-belt-and-road-initiative-outdo-the-marshall-plan.
18
The TPP was envisioned as a ‘mega-regional’ trade and investment agreement encom-
passing most of the economies of the Pacific Rim. One of President Trump’s first
decisions upon entering office was to withdraw from the TPP, with significant regional
implications (see S. Narine, ‘US Domestic Politics and America’s Withdrawal from the
Trans-Pacific Partnership: Implications for Southeast Asia’ (2018) 40 Contemporary
Southeast Asia 50–76). All other parties to the negotiations continued to discuss a revised
regional trade agreement without the USA, the Comprehensive and Progressive
Agreement for Trans-Pacific Partnership, which entered into force for the first six
ratifying states in December 2018; for comparison, see H. Wang, ‘The Future of Deep
Trade Agreements: The Convergence of TPP (and CPTPP) and CETA)?’ (2019) 53
Journal of World Trade 317–42.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
obliterated by President Trump but not considered a great success even
beforehand.19 Chinese investments in European ports and rail systems
are transforming market access and distribution in the EU much more
positively than the legal conundrums of Brexit will.20 Reportedly, China
now controls – in current terms – one-tenth of all European port
capacity, with gateways in Piraeus, Zeebrugge and elsewhere.21 This can
only be expected to expand, as China invests in rail infrastructures
through the Balkans to central Europe.22 Thus, BRI is not only important
in simple economic terms. The historical Silk Road had two sides; from a
Eurocentric perspective, it was a road to China, from a Chinese perspec-
tive it was a road to Europe. BRI is more of the latter than the former.
Europeans have only recently started to grasp this,23 as more states in the
EU sign on to the programme (e.g. Greece, Hungary, Italy) – literally
through ‘non-binding’ BRI Memoranda;24 attend BRI diplomatic forums;
and grant Chinese firms infrastructure projects and accept their loans.
This has created an intra-EU tension between member states and the
EU Commission, which is explicitly more reserved regarding China
and BRI,25 due to concerns about foreign investment approval and
19
M. J. Green, ‘The Legacy of Obama’s ‘Pivot’ to Asia’, Foreign Policy (3 September 2016),
https://foreignpolicy.com/2016/09/03/the-legacy-of-obamas-pivot-to-asia/.
20
Indeed, some see the possible strengthening of the United Kingdom’s bilateral economic
relations with China as a remedy to problems arising from Brexit, while others see it as a
threat to the UK’s sovereignty; see K. Brown, ‘How Brexit Britain Can Gain from China’s
Belt and Road’, This Week in Asia (12 May 2017), www.scmp.com/week-asia/opinion/
article/2094166/what-brexit-britain-has-gain-chinas-belt-and-road; and M. Auslin,
‘Brexit Britain Is Eager for a Sweet Deal with Beijing: But at What Price?’, The
Spectator (4 August 2018), www.spectator.co.uk/2018/08/making-china-great-again/. As
of the time of this writing, there is no United Kingdom–China trade arrangement outside
of the WTO.
21
See K. Johnson, ‘Why Is China Buying up Europe’s Ports?’, Foreign Policy (2 February
2018).
22
‘Serbia Starts Construction of Chinese-Funded Railway to Budapest’, Reuters
(28 November 2017), www.reuters.com/article/serbia-china-railway/serbia-starts-con
struction-of-chinese-funded-railway-to-budapest-idUSL8N1NY4RR.
23
AFP, ‘Europe Casts a Wary Eye on China’s Silk Road Plans’, Straits Times (7 January
2018), www.straitstimes.com/world/europe/europe-casts-a-wary-eye-on-chinas-silk-
road-plans.
24
See Memorandum of Understanding between the Government of the Republic of Italy and
the Government of the People’s Republic of China on Cooperation within the Framework of
the Silk Road Economic Belt and the 21st Century Maritime Silk Road Initiative (March
2019), www.governo.it/sites/governo.it/files/Memorandum_Italia-Cina_EN.pdf.
25
See European Commission and High Representative of the Union for Foreign Affairs and
Security Policy, ‘Joint Communication to the European Parliament, the European
Council and the Council, EU-China – A Strategic Outlook’ (12 March 2019) JOIN
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
debt-entrapment,26 and prompted the EU Commission to develop closer
economic relations with Japan, including a very recent bilateral agree-
ment on infrastructure connectivity, depicted as a counter to BRI.27
Moreover, it would be naïve to think that BRI is not indeed also a
governance project, potentially the greatest geopolitical transformation
since the end of the first Cold War, aiming to create a Eurasian economic
and political space under Chinese dominance. It brings to mind George
Kennan’s ‘Long Telegram’ regarding Soviet influence after World War II,
in that it ‘involves questions so intricate, so delicate, so strange to our
form of thought, and so important to analysis of our international
environment that I cannot compress answers into single brief message
without yielding to what I feel would be a dangerous degree of oversim-
plification’.28 The EU Commission EU-China: Strategic Outlook docu-
ment from 2019,29 is of course a public document and hence much more
cautious in its drafting; notably, however, it does not mention BRI by any
of its names, while the word security appears, in a variety of contexts,
much more than the words trade or investment. In other words, the EU
has become acutely aware of the geopolitical/economic gauntlet that
China has thrown down through BRI.
But again, what is BRI, in legal governance terms? It has been noted
that locating the ‘formal legal sources, either domestic or international’ of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
BRI is a difficult task.30 Heng Wang has called the Chinese approach to
BRI ‘less institutional’, presumably in comparison with Western
approaches that have relied on institutions in the architecture of inter-
national law and regimes. Within this Chinese approach he notes two
layers or categories of non-domestic law relevant to BRI: first, ‘BRI-
specific’ documents, such as the increasing number of non-binding or
binding Memoranda of Understanding (MOUs) between China and
states and international organizations;31 and second, ‘BRI-related’ rules
that can apply to BRI economic activity, such as World Trade
Organization (WTO) law, regional trade agreements and international
investment agreements.32 To these one might add a variety of inter-
national legal rules and norms that are also BRI-related, such as human
rights instruments, and environmental, maritime and other standards
and private law. Seeking further for historical and institutional analogies,
one can clutch on to the Asian Infrastructure Investment Bank, estab-
lished by China supposedly as an alternative to longstanding multilateral
development banks, a competitor to the World Bank Group and an
essential political and economic instrument for BRI.33 One can also look
to the Silk Road Fund, a multi-million dollar investment fund, wholly
controlled by China.34 But as China scholar Maria Adele Carrai has
written, these financial branches do not provide BRI with a rigid legal
structure.35 BRI does not have a ‘membership’, an ‘institution’, a ‘deci-
sion-making’ process. It does not fit easily into any boxes of conventional
international legal order. This does not mean, however, that it does not
have many significant implications for law in its spheres of influence,
creating entangled legalities at many levels, down to the most localized.
30
L. Zeng, ‘Conceptual Analysis of China’s Belt and Road Initiative: A Road towards a
Regional Community of Common Destiny’ (2016) 15 Chinese Journal of International
Law 517–41, at 539.
31
Such as the 2017 MOU between China’s National Development and Reform Commission
(NDRC) and the United Nations Economic Commission for Europe (UNECE) (UNECE-
NDRC MOU), www.unece.org/fileadmin/DAM/MoU_between_UNECE___the_NDRC_
in_China_2017–05–14.pdf; and AFP, ‘Europe Casts a Wary Eye on China’s Silk
Road Plans’.
32
Wang, ‘China’s Approach to the Belt and Road Initiative’, section II.
33
M. Callaghan and P. Hubbard, ‘The Asian Infrastructure Investment Bank:
Multilateralism on the Silk Road’ (2016) 9 China Economic Journal 116–39.
34
See www.silkroadfund.com.cn/.
35
M. A. Carrai, ‘It Is Not the End of History: The Financing Institutions of the Belt and
Road Initiative and the Bretton Woods System’ (2017) 14 Transnational Dispute
Management 1–14, at 2–3.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
To be sure, the present section of this chapter does not aspire to
provide a comprehensive descriptive analysis of BRI. Indeed, the nature
of the beast, as already stylized above, as well as the current flux in
international ‘geoeconomics’,36 would seem to preclude this.37 Rather,
the point to be made is that while BRI evidently constitutes a complex
system of entangled legalities, it would appear to have been deliberately
conceived as such, ‘top down’, by its initiator, not by chance or oversight,
and in lieu of attempting to establish a less entangled, more structured (if
not hierarchical) form of governance.
One possible point of departure towards understanding this and its
implications for entangled legalities, is the top-down definition of the BRI
goals, as set out quite innocuously in Chapter 51 of the PRC’s thirteenth
five-year plan,38 which reads as follows:
We will uphold amity, sincerity, mutual benefit, and inclusiveness as well
as the principle of joint discussion, common development, and shared
growth as we look to undertake practical and mutually-beneficial cooper-
ation in multiple sectors with countries and regions involved in the Belt
and Road Initiative, with the aim of developing a new picture of all-
around opening up in which China is opened to the world through
eastward and westward links and across land and sea [emphases added].39
These passages are fascinating, when read side by side, in both their
similarities and their differences. The similarities of mutual benefit,
36
See A. Roberts, H. C. Moraes and V. Ferguson, ‘The Geoeconomic World Order’, Lawfare
(19 November 2018), www.lawfareblog.com/geoeconomic-world-order, arguing that at
this time ‘We appear to be entering into a new geoeconomic world order, characterized
by great power rivalry between the United States and China and the clear use of economic
tools to achieve strategic goals’.
37
The sources in n. 2 provide the most comprehensive surveys to date, especially Wang.
38
Ibid.
39
See n. 2.
40
See Art. 2 of EEC, ‘Treaty of Rome: Treaty Establishing the European Economic
Community’ (25 March 1957) 298 U.N.T.S. 3, 4 Eur. Y.B. 412.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
economic development amity and harmony are clear (although also
worthy of deeper theoretical analysis in other contexts). The differences
relate to the conceptual mindset of governance. ‘The Community’ con-
trasts with ‘We’, ‘task’ may be opposed to ‘aim’. China’s five-year plan
sets out goals and aspirations for BRI, leaving open the institutional
technology for their achievement, while placing China firmly as primus
inter pares in a decentralized project. Elsewhere one can find that BRI has
a driving concept of a ‘community of common destiny’,41 but the terms
in which it is couched only enhance the difference in institutional (or
non-institutional) design – China at the centre of a decentralized system
(oxymoron intended). In contrast, the corollary in the Treaty of Rome
sought to establish an orderly structure of institutional governance,
which will have as its task the achievement of its common goals.
We know how dramatic the Treaty of Rome has been for the peoples
of Europe over the last six decades, for its governance and for its
legalities, which are often entangled but nevertheless structured upon
formal principles such as direct effect, supremacy and subsidiarity. We
do not know how dramatic the vision of BRI, posed in its own terms, will
be over the next decades. But it can be said that it is a politically
centralized vision that can have manifold unintended consequences in
many established legal systems – in any state or territory that BRI relates
to, directly or indirectly, in any international legal system that it relates
to, and indeed in any issue area of regulation or legal domain. Perhaps
the key phrase in the paragraph quoted from the five-year plan is ‘a new
picture’. Let us try to hypothesize what this picture could be – indeed,
already is – for a variety of entangled legal actors.
41
D. Zhang, ‘The Concept of “Community of Common Destiny” in China’s Diplomacy:
Meaning, Motives and Implications’, Asia and the Pacific Policy Studies (16 April 2018).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
legal systems in recent history, from variegated legal and geographical
perspectives. The reader can consider this as a narrative or as an
imagined or hypothetical ethnography,42 but the section does not aspire
to methodological insight, rather aiming at illustrating one end of the
spectrum of legal entanglement, namely, the relative separateness of legal
actors, actions and environments and their interconnections. The names,
characters and incidents portrayed can be thought of as fiction, but they
are all based on or derived from real situations. Thankfully, there are
social scientists and legal scholars conducting actual field research in this
area. The contribution here is aimed towards the theory of entangled
legalities, not to legal sociology or anthropology or to the empirical study
of BRI, at least not directly.
The main point to be made here is that entangled legalities exist on a
regular basis, first and foremost because of separateness and compart-
mentalization derived from structures of legal and law-relevant practice,
as well as overarching cognitive limits, that constrain these actors to a
focus on their particular environments, backgrounds and objectives. In
Section 5.4 I show, through a more detailed real-life example, how this
separateness is only part of the story of legal entanglement, as the distinct
fields of legal practice inevitably, though sometimes unexpectedly, have
points of contact and interdependence.
Let us start where it all begins, in China itself, with an initial ethno-
graphical vignette. A is a very senior lawyer at the investment law division
of MOFCOM, the PRC’s Ministry of Commerce.43 A, in his late thirties,
works in Beijing, which is no less than the centre of the real-world universe
for him (forget about Manhattan or Berlin, unless you are thinking of
Leonard Cohen). Born in a prefecture-level city in Hubei province in
central China, he has been predominantly trained and groomed in the
PRC, from a very young age, for public service, through its system of
42
Ethnography is a (not uncontroversial) anthropological/sociological qualitative method-
ology of describing people or cultures through observation; it has become accepted also in
socio-legal studies (see, e.g., J. Starr and M. Goodale (eds), Practicing Ethnography in Law:
New Dialogues, Enduring Methods (Palgrave Macmillan, 2002)) entailing interviews, field
research and other qualitative social science methods. An excellent example of ethno-
graphical research in the field of international economic law is G. A. Sarfaty, Values in
Translation: Human Rights and the Culture of the World Bank (Stanford University Press,
2012). The vignettes in this section are not based on such systematic research, so they
cannot claim to be a true ethnography, and don’t wish to be, hence the qualifiers
‘imagined’ or ‘hypothetical’.
43
See references in n. 6.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
‘meritocracy’.44 He is, however, distinctly a ‘man of the world’. He holds an
LLM degree from a leading law school in the USA, speaks excellent
English, and has travelled – in his professional capacity, of course, primar-
ily as an advisor to trade and investment agreement negotiations, perish
the thought of corruption – several times to Brussels, Singapore, Kuala
Lumpur, Johannesburg, Dubai and Canberra, and has previously worked
at a junior level in the Chinese delegation in Geneva. Despite his worldli-
ness, his sights are always set on promotion within the Chinese system. He
cautiously hopes to hold high office in the Party and government some-
day.45 To him, BRI is very significant. It will project and extend China’s
economic and political power and prowess to the world, and A is both
confident and proud that he is part of this project, in particular because it
will, on balance, bring wealth, welfare and Chinese values to other cul-
tures.46 Law is an important instrument to this end, utilizing formats
developed by Western powers (such as International Investment
Agreements (IIAs), which he negotiates)47 that are now fundamental for
facilitating and establishing China’s trade and investment policies, which
can promote BRI as a significant global public good.48 Entangled legality is
de rigueur, it comes naturally, so long as the overarching goals are
promoted and ideally achieved. A is not concerned at all with the formal
problem posed by parallel or even contradictory legal systems, such as
international investment agreements and commercial obligations,49 so
long as they serve the greater purposes of BRI.
44
For a survey on competing views regarding Chinese meritocracy, and a comparison with
promotion systems in Western democracies (at the ministerial level), see D. S. Lee and P. J.
Schuler, ‘Testing the “China Model” of Meritocratic Promotions: Do Democracies Reward
Less Competent Ministers than Autocracies?’ (2020) 53 Comparative Political Studies 531–66.
45
The Communist Party plays a crucial role in Chinese governance, and according to some
analysis, over the last few years, administrative power is shifting in the direction of the
Party; see L. L. P. Gore, ‘The Communist Party-Dominated Governance Model of China:
Legitimacy, Accountability, and Meritocracy’ (2019) 51 Polity 161–94.
46
In line with Part 16 of the five-year plan (see n. 2), which addresses socialist values and
ethics as well as Chinese cultural heritage.
47
On China’s BRI IIA policy, see Dai, ‘The International Investment Agreement Network
under the “Belt and Road” Initiative’; and Sauvant and Chen, ‘China’s Regulatory
Framework for Outward Foreign Direct Investment’.
48
Similarly, see C. He, ‘The Belt and Road Initiative as Global Public Good: Implications for
International Law’, in W. Shan, K. Nuotio and K. Zhang (eds), Normative Readings of the
Belt and Road Initiative: Road to New Paradigms (Springer, 2018), pp. 85–104.
49
As an example, China has at least two co-existing agreements with South Korea, which
include investment protection provisions – a Bilateral Investment Agreement from
2007 and a Trade Agreement from 2012.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
For A, ‘law’ is technically public international law, that needs to be
upheld as an overarching order that serves China’s interests in general
and BRI in particular; but in practice much of it is commercial law. This
need not be enforced through traditional Western dispute settlement
systems, but through combinations of legal argumentation and diplo-
macy, and alternative dispute resolution procedures, such as mediation.50
Moving on to another entangled and entangling actor at the European
portal representing the other end of BRI, B is a mid-level legal counsel in
the Greek Ministry of Infrastructure, Transport and Networks in the
Athens suburb of Cholargos. At the age of thirty-two, B’s worldview is
inevitably coloured by the financial and government debt crises of the
2000s that began when she was a law student at the Kapodistrian
University of Athens, and the scepticism that it has brought in Greece
towards international institutions, both at the EU level51 and beyond.
B aspires to attain an internationally recognized graduate law degree,
perhaps in the UK (though this is becoming less attractive because of
Brexit, making the Netherlands her new first choice), but she first needs to
establish herself economically and in her professional career, and perhaps
start a family. B is a formalist, she follows the book, even when the book is
blurred. But she also patriotically understands her state’s strengths and
weaknesses, and that an opportunity for foreign investment and increased
employment should not be passed up. In her eyes, austerity, imposed by
international neoliberal forces, pales in the face of the riches offered by a
powerful and trustworthy economic good faith partner from China. The
Chinese state-operated enterprises that offer lucrative terms for infra-
structure projects that place Greece at a crucial juncture between China
and the rest of Europe are a breath of fresh air. Yes, the Chinese can be
50
China has been involved in only a handful of disputes under its IIAs. There is a trend
towards constructing and viewing BRI projects and potential disputes related to them as
private, commercial law issues, and within that framing to encourage resolution through
mediation; see, e.g., the MOU reportedly signed by the Singapore International Mediation
Centre and the China Council for the Promotion of International Trade in January 2019,
setting up a BRI-focused panel of mediators (T. D. Wei, ‘Singapore, China to Set Up
Mediators’ Panel for Belt and Road Projects’, Straits Times (25 January 2019), www
.straitstimes.com/asia/east-asia/singapore-china-to-set-up-mediators-panel-for-belt-and-
road-projects).
51
Greece was traditionally a Europeanist state, but public opinion towards the EU and its
major member states has declined, although not to the level of ‘Grexit’; see B. Clements,
K. Nanou and S. Verney, ‘“We No Longer Love You, But We Don’t Want to Leave You”:
The Eurozone Crisis and Popular Euroscepticism in Greece’ (2014) 36 Journal of
European Integration 247–65.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
difficult to deal with, but they don’t have the arrogance of the Western
Europeans or Americans.52 They know what civil law means and are
willing to negotiate flexibly and pragmatically. B is not really sure what
BRI is – she’s heard of it, after all she reads the Greek economic press and
The Economist from time to time. Over the last few years, however, she
has been much more focused on settling the terms of the corporate
franchise of a shipping container terminal in the port of Piraeus, and
the sale of a majority share in the port authority, with a huge Chinese
state-owned shipping company. As time goes by, she takes pride in her
small professional contribution to the major increase in shipping con-
tainer traffic through Piraeus (about ten times the 2008 volume),53 as well
as the increase in the number of Chinese tourists visiting Greece, all of
which have helped the Greek economy. She was delighted when, in
August 2018, the Tsipras government signed a BRI MOU with China,
and is pleased that the current government is continuing to expand the
relationship, while cognizant of US and EU concerns.54
For B, law is mainly Greek administrative and corporate law, in the
shadow of EU law; A’s world of law is entirely foreign to her.
In-between A and B, C is a partner in the Almaty office of X, Y and Z
LLP, a global ‘big law’ firm. He is only aged twenty-eight, actually born
on the day that Kazakhstan declared sovereignty on its territory just
before the dissolution of the Soviet Union. He is considered something
of a maverick in the Kazakh energy and infrastructure law scene. Fluent
in Kazakh, Russian and English, his legal education is exclusively from
law schools in Kazakhstan. He is a deal-maker, building on his excellent
family connections. His legal specialty is project finance, and he sees BRI
as the future – breaking away from Russia, disengaging from the USA
(with which he has become personally disillusioned), China is the way
forward to Kazakhstan’s prosperity and international recognition.55
52
According to public opinion polls (2017), between 50 and 60 per cent of the Greek
population considers China favourably; see P. Le Corre, ‘China’s Rise as a Geoeconomic
Influencer: Four European Case Studies’, Carnegie Endowment for International Peace
Working Paper (2018), p. 20, https://carnegieendowment.org/files/WP_LeCorre_China_
Final_Web.pdf.
53
For more details of COSCO’s Piraeus deals, see ibid. at 15.
54
See S. Lau, ‘Amid Headwinds, Greece Gives Cosco Green Light for Partial Piraeus Port
Upgrade’, South China Morning Post (11 October 2019), www.scmp.com/news/china/diplo
macy/article/3032618/amid-headwinds-greece-gives-cosco-green-light-partial-piraeus.
55
See N. Kassenova, ‘China’s Silk Road and Kazakhstan’s Bright Path: Linking Dreams of
Prosperity’ (2017) 24 Asia Policy 110–16.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
He has worked with US and EU companies on energy projects, but
prefers to work with China – far less red-tape, no social and environ-
mental risk assessments through the Equator Principles or Global
Compact,56 no EU regulations. This is not to say that he is not concerned
with these issues, but they can be addressed through Kazakhstan’s laws
and regulations. He is particularly proud of his involvement with the
massive Khorgos ‘Dry Port’ project, with its potential for regional
transformation.57
To C, law is a somewhat blurry (if not shady) area of Kazakhstani
business and corporate law,58 transnational financial law and energy law.
From the perspective of legal practice, his work is quite similar to that of
B, but the legal environment is very, very different. As an ambitious
young commercial lawyer, he is driven not only by his clients’ interests
but also by his own – knowing that he and his partners stand to gain a lot
from the Chinese presence in Kazakhstan.59 He considers himself no less
a businessman than a lawyer, and is contemplating entering politics. He
is happy to take Chinese dictates and stay within the bounds of Kazakh
legality, so long as the project gets done.
D is a Baloch nationalist and insurgent separatist in Balochistan, the
most destitute province in Pakistan, despite being extremely rich in
natural gas and minerals – and hence, of great interest to the PRC.
Balochistan is also a key building block in BRI, in the form of the
‘China–Pakistan Economic Corridor’, in which reportedly some US$60
billion have been invested or pledged by China, not least in the port of
Gwadar on the Arabian Sea, now wholly run by a Chinese corporation,
56
See http://equator-principles.com/ and www.unglobalcompact.org/ respectively.
57
A. Higgins, ‘China’s Ambitious New “Port”: Landlocked Kazakhstan’, New York Times (1
January 2018), www.nytimes.com/2018/01/01/world/asia/china-kazakhstan-silk-road
.html; and H. Ruehl, ‘The Khorgos Hype on the Belt and Road’, The Diplomat
(27 September 2019), https://thediplomat.com/2019/09/the-khorgos-hype-on-the-belt-
and-road/.
58
Kazakhstan is highly ranked in the World Bank’s ‘Ease of Doing Business’ index (see
https://data.worldbank.org/indicator/IC.BUS.EASE.XQ), but its business and corporate
law is a patchwork of different legal foundations and practices, itself a legal entanglement;
see F. Karagussov, ‘Development of Company Law in Kazakhstan: Main Issues and
Trends’ (2016) 24 Juridica International 84–95; and Baker and McKenzie, ‘Doing
Business in Kazakhstan 2019’ (2019), www.bakermckenzie.com/-/media/files/insight/
guides/2019/doing-business-in-kazakhstan-2019.pdf?la=en.
59
Consider T. Yu, ‘China’s “One Belt, One Road Initiative”: What’s in It for Law Firms and
Lawyers?’ (2017) 5 The Chinese Journal of Comparative Law 1–21. The article deals
primarily with gains to lawyers in China, but clearly the same question is asked by lawyers
around the world.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
with a lease until 2059. At twenty-four, he was extremely disappointed
with the 2018 surrender of the leadership of the Baloch Liberation Army
(BLA), which seems to him connected to China’s increased involvement
in the region.60 He is very concerned that Chinese control in his home-
land will benefit elites and not trickle down to his people. Weighing his
steps carefully, he is not excluding the possibility of joining militant
factions and insurgents that advocate taking armed action against the
Chinese presence and have even attacked Chinese engineers under the
name of the BLA, if only to gain more political traction, even independ-
ence, by raising political risk to BRI operations.61
For D, law, in general, is not very relevant. There is tribal law, there are
social norms, but he is not concerned with Pakistani law or with con-
tracts beyond a handshake (that is to say, legality can be entangled with
an absence of legality too). A’s, B’s and C’s worlds of legality are as distant
from him as are their air-conditioned offices.
Even more distant, occupying her own tempered chambers, E is a
western European Judge in the European Court of Human Rights.
Trained in the best law schools of Europe, a well-respected professor
of law in her country and with several honorary doctorates around the
world, for her, Strasbourg is no less than the centre of the normative
universe (forget about Geneva, Washington, DC or Karlsruhe,
let alone San Jose or Beijing), and the European Convention for the
Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms is her moral
compass. It is of course the law, and even more so, it is a constitution.
Yes, it can get messy sometimes with the overburdened caseload, and
the unclear effectiveness and the constitutional orders of the Council
of Europe members, such as Georgia and Azerbaijan. These are BRI
states, but now also Greece, Italy, Hungary, Serbia and fourteen
other Central and Eastern European states are. BRI is not remotely
on her judicial radar, though if something relevant comes up in the
60
F. Bokhari and K. Stacey, ‘China Woos Pakistan Militants to Secure Belt and Road
Projects’, Financial Times (19 February 2018), www.ft.com/content/063ce350-1099-
11e8-8cb6-b9ccc4c4dbbb.
61
See D. R. Chaudhury, ‘Baloch Liberation Army Attacks Chinese Assets for 3rd Time
Since Aug 2018’, Economic Times (1 April 2019), https://economictimes.indiatimes.com/
news/defence/baloch-liberation-army-attacks-chinese-assets-for-3rd-time-since-aug-
2018/articleshow/68664144.cms?from=mdr; and M. A. Notezai, ‘Will Balochistan Blow
up China’s Belt and Road?’, Foreign Policy (30 May 2019), https://foreignpolicy.com/
2019/05/30/will-balochistan-blow-up-chinas-belt-and-road/.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Caucasus, or anywhere in Europe for that matter, the European
Convention and Court will surely kick in.
For E, law is Western, European human rights law, and her legal
practice, originally one of scholarship and court-watching, is now firmly
the practice of judging.
The list, this cast of characters, can easily go on, but the point should
be clear. Each and every one of these legal actors is a constitutive part of
BRI, even if they are barely aware of it. They seem to occupy separate
universes in which each of their representative narratives does not imply
disentanglement, but rather separateness, a separateness that is both
necessary for entanglement and coexists with it. They occupy legal silos
across national and substantive lines. They are entangled without really
knowing it, as they are cognitively limited and object oriented and, above
all, practice focused. In Section 5.4 I briefly relate one recent, actual case
in which both the separateness and connectedness dimensions of
entanglement have been brought to bear.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
Hungary respectively, and the entanglement of BRI project-related law
with EU law. The project, which will include high-speed trains, fits in
with the broader vision of modernized train lines from Piraeus/Athens
into the heart of central Europe,62 and indeed with its engagement
strategy with Central and Eastern European countries, which preceded
BRI – the so-called ‘16+1 initiative’ informally launched in 2011,63 now
often referred to as ‘17+1’, including Greece. Our focus here is on the
segment that lies in Hungarian territory and the project’s interaction with
EU law (Serbia not being an EU member state). Hungary was the first EU
member state to sign a BRI MOU with China, in 2015.64 In November of
the same year, China, Hungary and Serbia signed a US$1.9 billion
government-to-government (G2G) agreement regarding the Belgrade–
Budapest line, and the project’s main contractor was named – a consor-
tium between the Hungarian State Railways corporation and two Chinese
railway companies. This legal relationship – the China–Hungary MOU
and the infrastructure construction and financing agreement – constitute
one strand in this story of entangled legality. The second strand emerged
and entangled with the first once the EU launched a preliminary
infringement procedure against Hungary in May 2017, based on con-
cerns that the absence of a competitive tender for the huge contract
violated EU competition and procurement law; and that the role of the
Hungarian corporation, with only 15 per cent of the deal (and 85 per cent
of the project to be funded through twenty-year loans from China) was
unclear. Reportedly, the Hungarian government was of the position that
since the infrastructure agreement was not within the commercial com-
petence of the EU, it was ‘none of Brussels’ business’.65
Even at this early stage of the story – the plot is soon to thicken,
though the general setup is the same – one can think of the sources of
both separateness and interdependence in this case of entangled legality,
at least on a speculative basis. If one is charitable, at least regarding intent
62
For external analysis, see ‘The Potential for Growth through Chinese Infrastructure
Investments in Central and South-Eastern Europe along the “Balkan Silk Road”’, report
prepared by Dr Jens Bastian for the European Bank for Reconstruction and Development
(July 2017), www.ebrd.com/documents/policy/the-balkan-silk-road.pdf.
63
See T. Matura, ‘The Belt and Road Initiative Depicted in Hungary and Slovakia’ (2018) 7
(2) Journal of Contemporary East Asia Studies 174–89, section 4.
64
Ibid., section 5.1.2.
65
J. Spike, ‘EC Launches Infringement Proceeding Concerning Budapest–Belgrade Railway
Project’, Budapest Beacon (16 September 2016), https://budapestbeacon.com/ec-
launches-infringement-proceeding-concerning-budapest-belgrade-railway-project/.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
rather than legal capacity, perhaps the Hungarian public and most likely
also private lawyers (think of variations of B and C) involved in the rail
infrastructure agreement truly thought that it had nothing to do with EU
law, having been signed between three governments in an area that
generally is (so Hungary claims) not within EU competence. Perhaps
they just didn’t think of it, being so cognitively focused on making the
deal on the legal separateness of this kind of agreement. Or, less charit-
ably, maybe they were aware of possible problems, but took the chance in
order to make progress with China, and with the hope that the EU would
back down for political reasons. Least charitably, they had other incen-
tives that perhaps justified EU scrutiny.
China’s lawyers – A’s colleagues in a different department of a different
ministry and their counterparts in the Chinese corporations – were either
oblivious to EU law and/or did not consider the possibility that a govern-
mental party to a G2G agreement would make representations of this
nature with any real legal (or political) risk, or perhaps thought that if there
were a problem it would be handled as it would have been in China, or
were so self-motivated that they chose to ignore all of these issues, or
deliberately took this chance in order to signal to the EU their determin-
ation to engage with EU member states and corporations directly.
What about the EU Commission lawyers, whom we can to some
extent analogize to E? For them, there is no question that EU law on
competition, procurement, corporations and more are applicable,
answerable and supreme. To them, the infrastructure agreement is no
different than any of the multitude of structurally similar agreements that
are subject to EU law. Maybe this one required additional scrutiny due to
its size and mainly because of its role in bringing Chinese influence into
the heart of Europe.66
Apparently, conceding interdependence, Hungary issued a tender for
the project later in 2017,67 and a new one in late 2018, which was won in
April 2019 by a similar Chinese–Hungarian consortium, with a similar
financial structure,68 but for the fact that the Hungarian partner would be
66
See J. Kynge, A. Beesley and A. Byrne, ‘EU Sets Collision Course with China over “Silk
Road” Rail Project’, Financial Times (20 February 2017), www.ft.com/content/003bad14-
f52f-11e6–95ee-f14e55513608.
67
‘Hungary to Launch Tender on Budapest–Belgrade Rail Project’, RailPro (5 October
2017), www.railwaypro.com/wp/hungary-launch-tender-budapest-belgrade-rail-project/.
68
‘Hungarian–Chinese Consortium Wins Budapest–Belgrade Rail Contract’, IE – Industry
Europe (29 April 2019), https://industryeurope.com/hungarian-chinese-consortium-
wins-budapest-belgrade-rail-contract/.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
a company controlled by Lőrinc Mészáros, reportedly ‘a key ally’ of
Prime Minister Viktor Orbán,69 a strong proponent of the project and
of strong relations with China – among his many other well-known
political views.
This is not the place to reflect in-depth on either the economic and
political undercurrents of this episode, or on its actual outcomes, or on
the effectiveness of the different legal actors and legalities involved. What
can be said is that in this case, separate strands of legality – international
law in the form of the Hungary–China BRI MOU, international G2G
commercial law and EU law – started off as separate, with actors even in
denial of their entanglement, and ended up in a state that may be called
‘interdependent accommodation’. At least for now, EU law and insti-
tutions have been placated, and the Belgrade–Budapest project is pro-
jected to go ahead.
69
See ‘Talks on Budapest–Belgrade Rail Financing to be Accelerated’, Budapest Business
Journal (24 September 2019), https://bbj.hu/economy/talks-on-budapest-belgrade-rail-
financing-to-be-accelerated_171667.
70
E. Benvenisti and G. W. Downs, ‘The Empire’s New Clothes: Political Economy and the
Fragmentation of International Law’ (2010) 60 Stanford Law Review 595–631.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
slow-moving, temporally based, entrenched, yet also changing political
formations that need to be studied to understand how they change, adapt
and move on to maintain themselves, partly through reproduction and
partly through innovation of their institutional structures’.71 Histories of
the British and other European empires,72 and of the American ‘non-
empire’,73 confirm the relationship between legal pluralism and the creation
of imperial domination over extended periods of time. It is no coincidence
that Queen Elizabeth included the statement that ‘Rome was not built in a
day’, albeit in different circumstances, in an address at the University of
Cambridge in 1564.74 No empire, new or old, is so built.
This ‘set of slow moving [. . .] political formations’ would seem to inevit-
ably lead to ‘entangled legalities’, or in other words, to a set of separate, but
enmeshed, legal and governance constructs. Although these constructs may
seem to lack a hierarchy or ‘centre’, they nevertheless constitute a system of
non-national power allocation, however vague it may be, for example
globalization as empire, selon Hardt and Negri.75 Alternatively, in a more
historified manner, empires may be built on entangled legalities as ‘trans-
national organizations that aim[ed] to mobilize the resources available not
only within their areas, but outside them as well’ that ‘[w]hatever their
origins, [. . .] ow[ed] their existence and their unity to the broad network of
connections that they manage[d] to establish’.76
These understandings of empire are not, of course, without contro-
versy or critique, as fitting to the topic itself.77 They are brought out here
to accentuate – once again, descriptively but implicitly critically – that
BRI, with its attributes and character of entangled legalities, shares
similarities with other imperialist projects, representing a shift ‘beyond
the state’ and perhaps postnational or transnational trends, at a time that
71
K. Barkey, Empire of Difference: The Ottomans in Comparative Perspective (Cambridge
University Press, 2008), p. 5.
72
L. Benton and R. J. Ross (eds), Legal Pluralism and Empires, 1500–1850 (New York
University Press, 2013).
73
D. Immerwahr, How to Hide an Empire: A History of the Greater United States (Farrar,
Straus and Giroux, 2019).
74
J. Nichols, The Progresses and Public Processions of Queen Elizabeth, Vol. 1 (John Nichols
and Son, 1823), p. 176.
75
M. Hardt and A. Negri, Empire (Harvard University Press, 2000).
76
H. Kamen, Empire: How Spain Became a World Power, 1492–1763 (Harper Collins,
2003).
77
F. Cooper, ‘Empire Multiplied: A Review Essay’ (2004) 46 Comparative Studies in Society
and History 247–72.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
, ()
seems to be marked by heightened statism, nationalism and perceived
disrespect for international law.
All of this is manifested in BRI, which combines both a non-national,
ultimately global vision with localized segments that can be recognized
and comprehended along national, territorial and object-oriented lines.
Pre-national, postnational – perhaps the only way to understand entan-
gled legalities is through the lens of empire: ‘a new and all-pervasive
system of power, based on networks and amorphous connections, rooted
nowhere in particular’.78 ‘Nowhere in particular’ is not necessarily a
geographical statement. Communism was ‘rooted’ in Moscow, ‘global-
ization’ in Washington; both were empires by this definition, both built
upon nationalism and created and encouraged ‘entangled legalities’ (with
separateness) in multiple ways. BRI might be thought of in a similar
fashion.
78
Ibid., 248, describing Hardt and Negri.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
PART II
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
6
6.1 Introduction
Human rights law is one of the fields of law that creates the subject
matter overlap between international and domestic law. Human rights
treaties purport to regulate the governmental authority exercised over
individuals, which is, in parallel, regulated by domestic constitutional and
administrative law. This overlap creates the deliberative space between
human rights treaty-monitoring bodies and national authorities, includ-
ing domestic courts. In fact, judicial decisions can be at times ‘entangled’
with the findings of UN human rights treaty-monitoring bodies.
Domestic courts take note, discuss, accept or resist decisions, comments
or observations of UN human rights treaty-monitoring bodies. The
quality of such a deliberative space is crucial for the effectiveness of the
treaty-monitoring bodies, whose findings ultimately aim at bringing
about change to domestic legal frameworks and practices, including
those of the judiciary.
Against this background, this chapter engages in the analysis of path-
ways that guide the deliberative space involving UN human rights treaty-
monitoring bodies and domestic courts. Such pathways can be pragmatic
or sociological in nature. For instance, the unavailability of treaty body
findings in local languages significantly limits public knowledge about
them and the likelihood that litigant parties rely on general comments
and other treaty body findings. Interactions can be facilitated if judges
periodically receive training regarding the work of the monitoring bodies.
At the same time, domestic judges’ interactions with treaty body findings
have also been guided by normative pathways. They can originate in both
international and national law. In limited circumstances, such pathways
exhibit a formalistic character that Views, one of the categories of the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
documents produced by treaty bodies, have legal binding force. Yet it is
usually the case that normative pathways are much less dichotomous.
This chapter examines one of such normative pathways, namely that
state parties ought to give due consideration to the findings of UN
human rights treaty-monitoring bodies. The legal basis of such a duty
to consider remains contested. Furthermore, the duty to consider is
necessarily precarious, inasmuch as its effectiveness depends on how
precisely consideration is given by judges in a particular case.
Nevertheless, the duty to consider – and its normative variations, as will
be discussed in this chapter – occasionally appears in the reasoning of
domestic courts whose narrative is entangled with treaty interpretation
by UN human rights-monitoring bodies.
The chapter starts by outlining the different types of the findings of the
monitoring bodies (Section 6.2). Domestic courts’ engagement varies
depending on states, courts and judges. The limited research I have con-
ducted1 demonstrates a great deal of variance with regard to domestic
courts’ explicit engagement with the monitoring bodies. Domestic judges
may not be aware of the relevant documents; and even if they are, they
may reject the judicial relevance of such documents (Section 6.3). At the
same time, there are a number of domestic court decisions that have
explicitly invoked treaty body findings (Section 6.4). What matters for
the sake of this chapter is that judicial engagement can be guided by the
duty to consider and its variations (Sections 6.4 and 6.5). These pathways
serve as ‘interface norms’ that facilitate ties yet preserve discretion on the
part of domestic courts.2 Under limited circumstances, the duty to con-
sider may even be understood as entailing an obligation to give effect to
Views (Section 6.6). The duty to consider may not be a robust normative
path. Yet it can still pave the way for a sustainable and forward-looking
deliberative space, by creating the opportunities for learning and self-
reflection for domestic courts and the international guardians.
1
The chapter’s analysis is based on my previous publication: M. Kanetake, ‘UN Human
Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies before Domestic Courts’ (2018) 67 International &
Comparative Law Quarterly 201–32. For the sake of the previous publication, I have
collected and analysed 150 domestic court decisions (decided from 1982 to 2016) across
forty-one jurisdictions. For the sake of the present chapter, I have additionally collected
and analysed forty other domestic court decisions (decided between 1992 and 2018) across
twenty-one jurisdictions, based on my own research, existing literature, the Oxford
Reports on International Law in Domestic Courts (ILDC) and the International Law
Reports (ILR).
2
See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
6.2 Measuring the Domestic Relevance of the ‘Jurisprudence’
of the Monitoring Bodies
UN human rights treaty-monitoring bodies are part of the institutional
arrangements at the international level that assist states’ implementation
of nine core human rights treaties. There are ten bodies tasked with
monitoring the implementation of the treaties, namely: (1) Human
Rights Committee (HRC), (2) Committee on Economic, Social and
Cultural Rights (CESCR), (3) Committee on the Elimination of Racial
Discrimination (CERD), (4) Committee on the Elimination of
Discrimination against Women (CEDAW), (5) Committee Against
Torture (CAT), (6) Subcommittee on Prevention of Torture, (7)
Committee on the Rights of the Child (CRC), (8) Committee on
Migrant Workers (CMW), (9) Committee on the Rights of Persons with
Disabilities (CRPD), and (10) Committee on Enforced Disappearances
(CED). These committees have been adjusting their working methods
towards better harmonization, particularly in response to the UN
General Assembly’s resolution 68/268 of 2014.3
The ten bodies issue a wide range of documents (which are generally
termed ‘findings’ in this chapter). They can be categorized into three
types:4 (1) General Comments and Recommendations, which are
addressed to all state parties; (2) Concluding Observations and
Concluding Comments, which are addressed to a particular state party;
and (3) Views (or Decisions) and Suggestions and Recommendations,
which pertain to individual communications or petitions.5 There are
eight treaty bodies that are competent to receive and consider petitions
from individuals.6 By mobilizing the limited staff resources, the commit-
tees adopted 250 decisions on individual communications per year
during 2018–19, for instance.7 In some of those decisions, the commit-
tees found breaches of treaty obligations. Between 1977 and March 2019,
3
UN General Assembly, ‘Strengthening and Enhancing the Effective Functioning of the
Human Rights Treaty Body System’ (21 April 2014) UN Doc. A/RES/68/268, para. 38.
4
See N. Ando, ‘General Comments/Recommendations’, in R. Wolfrum (ed.), The Max
Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law (Oxford University Press, 2008), para. 2.
5
This chapter consistently uses the term ‘Views’ to describe the types of findings regarding
individual communications or petitions, even if the findings can also be entitled as
‘Decisions’, etc.
6
These eight bodies are: HRC, CESCR, CERD, CEDAW, CAT, CRC, CRPD, and CED. The
CMW also anticipates the petition mechanism.
7
Report of the Secretary-General, ‘Status of the Human Rights Treaty Body System’ (10
January 2020) UN Doc. A/74/643, para. 18.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the HRC found violations of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (ICCPR) in 1,157 Views.8 The adoption of Views is in
addition to thirty-six General Comments adopted by the HRC between
1981 and 2018, accompanied by numerous state-specific observations.
The crux is that these different types of findings are cross-referenced
with one another, which internally strengthens each body’s treaty inter-
pretation.9 Just to provide one specific example, in its Concluding
Observations addressed to the Netherlands in 2016, the CEDAW urged
the state party to implement its earlier Views, by further indicating
that the state’s non-implementation of the Views is inconsistent with
the CEDAW’s General Recommendation No. 33 on women’s access to
justice.10 By cross-referencing its own documents, each treaty body
creates what the International Court of Justice (ICJ) termed ‘jurispru-
dence’ in para. 66 of the Diallo case (2010)11 – although, I must add, the
use of such a juridical vocabulary depends on how one appreciates the
functions of the treaty-monitoring bodies.
Para. 66 of the Diallo case is crucial in that the ICJ commented on the
normative relevance of the HRC’s treaty interpretation. The court
observed that the HRC has ‘built up a considerable body of interpretive
case law’ through Views and General Comments.12 Having reiterated the
formalistic starting point that the court is ‘in no way obliged’ to follow
the interpretation of the HRC, the court continued by saying that it
‘should ascribe great weight to the interpretation’ of the HRC.13 The
Diallo case was not the first occasion on which the ICJ had resorted to
the position of the HRC.14 Yet the remark of the court in Diallo was
noteworthy, in that the court elucidated the normative ‘weight’ to be
8
UNHRC, ‘Report of the Human Rights Committee, 123rd Session (2–27 July 2018), 124th
Session (8 October–2 November 2018), 125th Session (4–29 March 2019)’ (2019) UN
Doc. A/74/40, para. 25.
9
See, on the CERD’s work, R. Wolfrum, ‘The Committee on the Elimination of Racial
Discrimination’ (1999) 3 Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law Online 489–519, at
509.
10
CEDAW, ‘Concluding Observations on the Sixth Periodic Report of the Netherlands’
(24 November 2016) CEDAW/C/NLD/CO/6, para. 14.
11
Ahmadou Sadio Diallo (Republic of Guinea v. Democratic Republic of the Congo), Merits,
Judgment of 30 November 2010, [2010] ICJ Reports 639, para. 66.
12
Ibid., para. 66.
13
Ibid., para. 66 (emphasis added).
14
E.g., Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied Palestinian
Territory, Advisory Opinion of 9 July 2004, [2004] ICJ Reports 136, paras 109–10. See
L. Crema, ‘The Interpretive Work of Treaty Bodies: How They Look at Evolutionary
Interpretation, and How Other Courts Look at Them’, in G. Abi-Saab et al. (eds),
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
given to the HRC’s interpretation. This does not mean that the ICJ is
consistent in terms of its willingness to substantively engage with UN
human rights treaty-monitoring bodies. In the Obligation to Prosecute or
Extradite (Belgium v. Senegal) case (2012), the ICJ took a rather dismis-
sive attitude towards the CAT’s treaty interpretation.15
Methodologically, it is hard to assess the extent to which treaty body
findings alter domestic legal practices. The international bodies’ inter-
pretation can influence legal discourse indirectly and over a long period
of time. That said, one form of assessment is to measure the level of
compliance. Some treaty-monitoring bodies indicate the level of satis-
factory follow-up by states parties to the outcomes of individual com-
munications. For example, the CAT’s report of May 2017 shows that
42 per cent of its communications (55 out of 131), in which the CAT
found violations, resulted in satisfactory or partially satisfactory
outcomes.16
Yet this chapter’s focus is not on assessing general rates of compliance.
Instead, the chapter analyses the explicit reference to treaty body findings
in judicial reasoning. The cases I examine are therefore inclusive of, but
not limited to, the case-specific responses to Views. This wider coverage
is appropriate and necessary, precisely because the chapter’s focus is on
the judiciary, as opposed to other branches of the government. As
I further explain in Section 6.3, domestic courts play a relatively limited
role in providing case-specific responses to Views. The principle of res
judicata often prevents judges from reopening cases at the domestic level.
National courts may be able to give effect to Views if there are any
relevant pieces of domestic law that allow judges to reopen a case.17
Illustrative in this regard is a Norwegian example. By the Act of 15 June
2001 No. 63 which amended the Criminal Procedure and the Civil
Procedure Acts, Norway allowed the reopening of cases following the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
findings of the monitoring body.18 While the Norwegian initiatives have
been welcomed by the HRC,19 few countries seem to have followed the
same path that systematically allows the reopening of proceedings. This
means that the case-specific responses to Views primarily depend on the
willingness of the executive and legislative branches of the government.20
18
UNHRC, ‘Consideration of Reports Submitted by States Parties under the Covenant,
Fifth Periodic Report, Norway’ (3 December 2004) CPR/C/NOR/2004/5, para. 157. See
also para. 158 (establishment of the Criminal Cases Review Commission to assist
petitioners).
19
UNHRC, ‘Concluding Observation of the Human Rights Committee, Norway’ (25 April
2006) CCPR/C/NOR/CO/5, para. 3(b) (establishment of the Commission to assist
petitioners).
20
See, e.g., X v. Council of Ministers, Appeal judgment ILDC 2520 (ES 2015), ROJ: STS 507/
2015, ECLI: ES:TS:2015:507 (Spain, Supreme Court, Administrative Chamber, 6 February
2015) paras 41–5 (OUP page numbers).
21
See n. 1 above.
22
See nn. 17–19 and accompanying text on the principle of res judicata and the need for
specific pieces of legislation.
23
Kavanagh v. Governor of Mountjoy Prison [2002] 3 IR 97; 132 ILR 380 (Ireland, Supreme
Court, 1 March 2002) 404.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the ICCPR on equality before the law.24 While the Irish Supreme Court’s
rejection was based on the constitutional ground that justice ought to be
administered by properly constituted courts,25 the court also commented
on the absence of international legal grounds. According to the Irish
court, ‘[n]either the Covenant nor the Protocol at any point purports to
give any binding effect to the views expressed by the Committee’ which,
as the Supreme Court reiterated, ‘does not formulate any form of judg-
ment or declare any entitlement to relief’.26
In a similar vein, another noteworthy case is Wilson v. Ermita (2016)
before the Supreme Court of the Philippines.27 In 1998, Wilson, a British
national, was convicted of the crime of rape and sentenced to death. Before
his conviction was set aside by the Supreme Court in 1999,28 Wilson
submitted the communication to the HRC, which eventually rendered its
Views in 2003.29 According to the HRC, the conditions under which
Wilson was arrested, detained and imprisoned infringed several provisions
of the ICCPR, including Article 7 on the prohibition of torture, or other
cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment.30 The HRC
observed that the Philippines should provide compensation for Wilson.31
He then filed a petition for mandamus before the Supreme Court of the
Philippines, arguing that the government is obliged to enforce the Views as
part of its duties under international law.32 The Supreme Court dismissed
Wilson’s claim. While the court’s rejection was based primarily on the lack
of domestic effect of treaties,33 the Supreme Court made remarks on the
characteristics of Views. According to the court, nowhere in the ICCPR
does it state that Views formed part of the treaty.34
24
UNHRC, Kavanagh v. Ireland (No.1), Views, Communication No. 819/1998, CCPR/C/
71/D/819/1998, adopted 4 April 2001, paras 10.3 and 11.
25
Kavanagh v. Governor of Mountjoy Prison, 404 (referring to Article 34.1 of the Irish
Constitution).
26
Ibid.
27
Wilson v. Ermita and ors, Petition for mandamus, GR No 189220, ILDC 3005 (PH 2016)
(Philippines, Supreme Court, 7 December 2016).
28
Ibid., paras 3–6 (paragraph numbers added by Oxford University Press (OUP)).
29
UNHRC, Albert Wilson v. The Philippines, Views, Communication No. 868/1999, CCPR/
C/79/D/868/1999 (11 November 2003).
30
Ibid., paras 7.3–8 (violations of Articles 7, 9(1)–(3), 10(1)–(2)).
31
Ibid., para. 9.
32
Wilson v. Ermita, para. 17 (OUP numbers).
33
Ibid., paras 32–3 (OUP numbers). The Court’s view on the domestic effect of the ICCPR
seems inconsistent with the Court’s own jurisprudence: see E. K. P. Aguilan, ‘Analysis:
ILDC 3005 (PH 2016)’ (2019), para. A3.
34
Wilson v. Ermita, para. 34 (OUP numbers).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The court’s conclusion in Wilson v. Ermita is nothing new.
Noteworthy still, however, is that the Supreme Court of the Philippines
invoked the HRC’s General Comment No. 33 in the course of denying
the applicability of Views to case-specific judicial responses. In General
Comment No. 33 (advanced unedited version of November 2008), the
HRC regarded its Views as exhibiting ‘some important characteristics of
a judicial decision’.35 The Supreme Court quoted this phrase, observing
that the HRC’s Views ‘only displays “important characteristics of a
judicial decision”’.36 According to the court, the Views are thus ‘mere
recommendations to guide the State it is issued against’.37 While the
Supreme Court of the Philippines at least engaged with the narrative of
General Comment No. 33, the court’s use of the finding was rather ironic.
Judges used it in order to dismiss, as opposed to augment, the judicial
relevance of the Views of the HRC.
These examples again remind us of the structurally limited role of the
judiciary in providing case-specific follow-up.38 Yet even outside case-
specific circumstances, some domestic courts have much more ‘distanced
relations’39 with UN treaty-monitoring bodies and have taken a dismissive
attitude towards the relevance of their treaty interpretation.40 In some
countries, judicial narrative accommodates little or no reference to treaty
body findings. While the International Law Association’s (ILA) Committee
on International Human Rights Law and Practice (1997–2008) conducted
extensive studies on judicial practices, the study could not specifically
identify judicial references to the monitoring bodies in, among others,
the countries of Francophone Africa or the Arab region. According to
the 2004 Berlin report of the ILA Committee, there were no identifiable
judicial practices in Bulgaria, Jordan, Egypt, Saudi Arabia, Colombia,
Ecuador, Chile, Argentina, Malaysia, Singapore or Brunei.41 The absence
35
UNHRC, ‘General Comment No. 33: The Obligations of States Parties under the
Optional Protocol’ (Advance unedited version, 5 November 2008) CCPR/C/GC/33,
para. 11.
36
Wilson v. Ermita, para. 35 (OUP numbers) (emphasis added).
37
Ibid. Any responses to such recommendations are a matter to be determined by the
legislative and executive branches of the government, the Supreme Court added – see
para. 36 (OUP numbers).
38
See nn. 17–19 and accompanying text.
39
See Chapter 1.
40
Kanetake, ‘UN Human Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies before Domestic Courts’, 226–7.
41
ILA, Committee on International Human Rights Law and Practice, ‘Final Report on the
Impact of Findings of the United Nations Human Rights Treaty Bodies’ (2004) para. 29,
ft 28.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of explicit reference is also evident in French courts. A study of
French courts’ practices suggests that not only judges, but also
the litigants themselves rarely refer to the monitoring bodies’
findings.42
42
S. El Boudouhi and G. Dannenberg, ‘France: Implementation of International Human
Rights Decisions in France’, in S. Kadelbach, T. Rensmann and E. Rieter (eds), Judging
International Human Rights (Springer International Publishing, 2019) pp. 453–70, at
p. 466.
43
Kanetake, ‘UN Human Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies before Domestic Courts’,
228–30.
44
Ibid., 229–30.
45
See, e.g., ‘Report of the International Law Commission, Seventieth Session (30 April–1
June and 2 July–10 August 2018)’ (2018) UN GAOR, 73rd Sess., Supp. No. 10, UN Doc.
A/73/10, 109, para. 7, fn 614; C. Tomuschat, ‘Human Rights Committee’, in R. Wolfrum
(ed.), The Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law (Oxford University Press,
2010), para. 14.
46
See van Alebeek and Nollkaemper, ‘The Legal Status of Decisions by Human Rights
Treaty Bodies’, pp. 372–3, pp. 385–90.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
parties regarding its interpretation’.47 While, in principle, ‘subsequent
practice’ is not equated with the institutional practices of the monitoring
bodies themselves, the monitoring bodies’ findings can facilitate an
interpretation accepted by states parties which may support or acquiesce
to the observations of the monitoring bodies,48 even though caution
should be exercised.
Despite the content-based obligation on the part of states parties, the
rule of treaty interpretation is so flexible that domestic courts can readily
argue that the monitoring bodies’ interpretation does not reflect ‘subse-
quent practice’. The flexibility is preserved by the International Law
Commission (ILC), which adopted, in 2018, a set of draft conclusions
on ‘subsequent agreements and subsequent practice in relation to the
interpretation of treaties’.49 In the draft conclusions, the ILC reiterated
that a pronouncement of ‘expert treaty bodies’, such as UN human rights
treaty-monitoring bodies,50 ‘may’ give rise to, or refer to, a ‘subsequent
agreement or subsequent practice by parties’ under Article 31(3) of the
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties.51 The draft conclusions,
however, warned that ‘[s]ilence by a party shall not be presumed to
constitute subsequent practice’ under Article 31(3)(b) of the Vienna
Convention.52 As the ILC acknowledges, ‘it cannot usually be expected
that States parties take a position with respect to every pronouncement
by an expert treaty body, be it addressed to another State or to all States
generally’.53 While this caution against the misinterpretation of silence by
states parties makes pragmatic sense, the ILC’s work did not elaborate
upon possible indicators with which to assess whether the pronounce-
ment of UN human rights treaty-monitoring bodies reflects
established treaty interpretation. Overall, the ILC’s work preserved the
47
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, 23 May 1969, in force 27 January 1980,
1155 UNTS 311, Article 31(3)(b).
48
ILA, ‘Final Report on the Impact of Findings’ (2004), para. 21; G. Ulfstein, ‘Individual
Complaints’, in H. Keller, G. Ulfstein and L. Grover (eds), UN Human Rights Treaty
Bodies: Law and Legitimacy (Cambridge University Press, 2012) pp. 73–115, at
pp. 97–100.
49
‘Text of the Draft Conclusions on Subsequent Agreements and Subsequent Practice in
Relation to the Interpretation of Treaties’, see ‘Report of the International Law
Commission, Seventieth Session’, 12–16.
50
‘Report of the International Law Commission, Seventieth Session’ above, 106
(Conclusion 13).
51
Ibid., 106 (Conclusion 13.3).
52
Ibid., 106 (Conclusion 13.2).
53
Ibid., 113, para. 19 (commentary regarding Conclusion 13.3).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
flexibility – and associated uncertainty – inherent in Article 31(3)(b) of
the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, which, in the context of
the theme of this chapter, effectively leaves ample space for domestic
courts to reject the obligatory nature of the specific content of the
findings.
54
Kanetake, ‘UN Human Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies before Domestic Courts’, 226.
55
Ibid.
56
‘Kav LaOved’ – Worker’s Hotline and ors v. Ministry of Interior and ors, Original petition
to the High Court of Justice, HCJ 11437/05, ILDC 2181 (IL 2011) (13 April 2011) (Israel,
Supreme Court as High Court of Justice), paras H3–H4 (ILDC paragraph numbers). See
CEDAW, ‘General Recommendation No. 21: Equality in Marriage and Family Relations’
(1994) UN Doc. A/49/38; CEDAW, ‘General Recommendation No. 26 on Women
Migrant Workers’ (5 December 2008) CEDAW/C/2009/WP.1/R; CERD, ‘General
Recommendation 30 on Discrimination against Non-citizens’ (2004) UN Doc. A/59/
18, 93.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
interpret the scope of arbitrary arrest and detention under the ICCPR,
which served ultimately to decide upon the constitutionality of
domestic legislation.57
In a similar vein, the Federal Court of Australia in Iliafi v. The
Church of Jesus Christ and the Latter-Day Saints Australia (2014)
resorted to several findings of the monitoring bodies: General
Recommendation No. 20 of the CERD,58 the HRC’s General
Comments Nos. 22 (on the right to freedom of thought, conscience
and religion) and 23 (on the rights of minorities),59 and the jurispru-
dence of the HRC formulated through its Views.60 These documents
were mentioned by the Australian court in order to interpret the Racial
Discrimination Convention and the ICCPR,61 and, ultimately, to con-
strue the Racial Discrimination Act 1975 of Australia.62 Interestingly,
the Federal Court of Australia cited para. 66 of the ICJ’s decision in
Diallo, as well as Article 38(1)(d) of the ICJ Statute, in consulting the
CERD’s General Recommendation No. 20.63 Yet the court did not
specify whether it intended to ascribe, as the ICJ did in paragraph
66 of Diallo, ‘great weight’ to the interpretation of the monitoring
bodies.64
While there are abundant examples of judicial reference, the extent of
substantive engagement varies depending on courts and judges. Illustrative
in this regard is the comparison between UK and Canadian courts in a
series of decisions concerning the interpretation of Article 14(1) of the
57
HCJ Infiltrators Case, Adam and Ors v. The Knesset and Ors, Original petition to the High
Court of Justice, HCJ 7146/12, ILDC 2078 (IL 2013), 16 September 2013 (Israel, Supreme
Court), paras H5–H6 (ILDC report by Nita Benoliel); Y. Shany, ‘Israel’, in F. M.
Palombino (ed.), Duelling for Supremacy: International Law vs. National Fundamental
Principles (Cambridge University Press, 2019) p. 167–83, at pp. 177–8.
58
Iliafi and Others v. The Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-Day Saints Australia [2014]
FCAFC 26 (19 March 2014) (Federal Court of Australia), paras 62–4; CERD, ‘General
Recommendation 20: The Guarantee of Human Rights Free from Racial Discrimination’
(1996) UN Doc. A/51/18 (1996), annex VIII, 124.
59
Iliafi, paras 66–7, 85, 96–9, 103; HRC, ‘General Comment No. 22 (Art. 18)’ (27 September
1993) CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.4; HRC, ‘General Comment No. 23: The Rights of
Minorities (Article 27)’ (26 April 1994) CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.5.
60
E.g., Iliafi, paras 100–1.
61
International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination,
21 December 1965, 660 UNTS 195, Art 5; International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights, 16 December 1966, 999 UNTS 171, Articles 18, 27.
62
Racial Discrimination Act 1975 (Australia), Act No. 52 of 1975 (11 June 1975), section 9.
63
Iliafi, para. 62.
64
Diallo, para. 66.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Torture Convention.65 Both UK and Canadian courts disagreed with the
CAT’s interpretation of the provision that a civil remedy ought to be made
available for all acts of torture, including those committed outside the
forum state,66 by limiting the scope of state immunity.67
While both UK and Canadian courts disagreed with the CAT’s treaty
interpretation, there were differences in terms of the extent to which
courts substantively engaged with the CAT’s position. In the House of
Lords, judges rather summarily dismissed the relevance the CAT in Jones
v. Saudi Arabia (2006).68 Lord Bingham noted that ‘[w]hatever its value
in influencing the trend of international thinking, the legal authority of
the Committee’s recommendation is slight’.69 In a similar vein, Lord
Hoffmann found ‘no value’ in the Committee’s position.70 The disagree-
ment of UK judges in Jones was referred to by the Canadian Supreme
Court in Kazemi (Estate) v. Iran (2014).71 The Canadian court, however,
while disagreeing with the CAT’s interpretation, took a few more steps to
provide substantive explanations as to why judges did not agree with the
CAT’s interpretation.
In Kazemi, the Canadian Supreme Court admitted that ‘the
Committee’s comments may be helpful for purposes of interpret-
ation’,72 by referring to its earlier decision in Suresh (2002) where
the Supreme Court had consulted the CAT’s position.73 Yet the
majority of the Canadian Supreme Court noted that the Committee’s
65
Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or
Punishment, 10 December 1984, 1465 UNTS 85, Art. 14(1). See Kanetake, ‘UN Human
Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies before Domestic Courts’, 212–13.
66
See, e.g., CAT, ‘General Comment No. 3 (2012): Implementation of Article 14 by States
Parties’ (13 December 2012) CAT/C/GC/3, para. 22.
67
The CAT made it clear in its Concluding Observations addressed to Canada: CAT,
‘Concluding Observations of the Committee against Torture: Canada’ (25 June 2012)
CAT/C/CAN/CO/6, para. 15; CAT, ‘Concluding Observations on the Seventh Periodic
Report of Canada’ (21 December 2018) CAT/C/CAN/CO/7, para. 41.
68
Jones v. Saudi Arabia [2006] UKHL 26; (2007) 1 AC 270 (UK, House of Lords,
14 June 2006).
69
Ibid., para. 23 (Lord Bingham).
70
Ibid., para. 57 (Lord Hoffmann). See also Jones and Others v. The United Kingdom, App.
Nos. 34356/06 and 40528/06, Judgment of 14 January 2014, para. 208 (disagreeing with
the CAT’s interpretation).
71
Kazemi (Estate) v. Islamic Republic of Iran 2014 SCC 62, [2014] 3 S.C.R. 176 (Canada,
Supreme Court, Judgment of 10 October 2014), para. 148.
72
Ibid., para. 148.
73
Suresh v. Canada, (2002) 208 DLR (4th) 1 (2002) 124 ILR 343 (Canada, Supreme Court,
11 January 2002), para. 73; Kanetake, ‘UN Human Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies
before Domestic Courts’, 211.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
comments, ‘despite their importance’, ‘should not be given greater
weight than the pronouncements of states parties and judicial
authorities’.74 The court observed that the CAT’s comments ‘do not
override adjudicative interpretations’, such as those seen in Jones.75
‘At best’, according to the highest court of Canada, the CAT’s com-
ments ‘form part of a dialogue within the international community
where no consensus has yet developed’ on treaty interpretation.76 The
majority’s treatment of the CAT’s remarks is contrasted with the
narrative of Justice Abella in dissent. She observed that the CAT’s
‘expertise lends support to the weight of its interpretation’,77 referring
to the fact that the Committee had made critical remarks on Canadian
legal practices.78 The narrative of the Canadian court was noteworthy
in that the court explained how much weight it should give to the
CAT’s treaty interpretation. While judges in the majority substan-
tively engaged with the CAT’s position, the Supreme Court, at least
in this specific case, regarded it as merely one of the opinions that the
court may take into account.
74
Kazemi (2014), para. 147.
75
Ibid., para. 148.
76
Ibid.
77
Ibid., para. 224 (Justice Abella in dissent, agreeing with the Canadian Bar Association’s
remark).
78
Ibid., para. 226 (Justice Abella in dissent).
79
E.g., Y. Iwasawa, ‘Domestic Application of International Law’ (2016) 378 Recueil des
Cours 236–7 (regarding Japanese courts’ practices); Kanetake, ‘UN Human Rights Treaty
Monitoring Bodies Before Domestic Courts’, 220–1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
(2012)80 before the Federal Court of Australia, the judge consulted the
HRC’s Views and General Comments Nos. 15 (on the position of aliens)
and 31 (on the nature of the general obligation)81 in the process of
interpreting Australia’s non-refoulement obligations. The Federal Court
explicitly elaborated upon the question of what materials the court may
consult in interpreting the ICCPR.82 The judge accepted, ‘upon reflec-
tion’, that ‘the Committee’s interpretation of the ICCPR is admissible’ in
court for the interpretation of the treaty.83 The Federal Court suggested
that its recourse to the HRC’s interpretation was justified by Article 40(4)
of the ICCPR and Article 1 of the Optional Protocol.84 Article 40(4)
serves as a legal basis for the HRC to issue General Comments,85 while
Article 1 of the Optional Protocol empowers the Committee to receive
and consider individual communications.86 On this basis, according to
the Federal Court, the Committee’s Views and General Comments form
part of ‘supplementary means of interpretation’ (under Article 32 of the
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties).87 Equally, the Views and
General Comments serve as ‘subsidiary means for the determination of
rules of law’ (under Article 38(1)(d) of the Statute of the International
Court of Justice).88
The characterization of treaty body findings as part of supplementary
means leaves states (and their courts) to decide whether to consider a
particular finding of the committees and how much weight states give to
80
Minister for Immigration and Citizenship v. Anochie and Another [2012] FCA 1440,
(2012) 209 FCR 497 (Australia, Federal Court, 18 December 2012). The subsequent
decision did not refer to the Committee’s findings: Anochie v. Minister for Immigration
and Citizenship [2013] AATA 391 (Australia, Administrative Appeals Tribunal,
12 June 2013).
81
UNHRC, ‘General Comment No. 15: The Position of Aliens under the Covenant’ (11
April 1986) HRI/GEN/1/Rev.9 (Vol. I); HRC, ‘General Comment No. 31: Nature of the
General Legal Obligation Imposed on States Parties to the Covenant’ (29 March 2004)
CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.13.
82
Anochie, paras 40–50.
83
Ibid., para. 45.
84
Ibid., paras 45–6.
85
ICCPR, Article 40(4).
86
Optional Protocol to the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
16 December 1966, 999 UNTS 302, Article 1. The Federal Court also noted the fact that
the HRC’s Views are forwarded to the individual and the state party concerned, according
to Article 5(4) of the Optional Protocol.
87
Anochie, para. 48. This is based on the Federal Court’s earlier case: Minister for
Immigration and Multicultural and Indigenous Affairs v. Al Masri (2003) 126 FCR 54,
para. 148.
88
Ibid., para. 49.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the committees’ interpretation. In the aforementioned Anochie, the
Australian court noted that, given that the members of the HRC were
supposed to be ‘persons of high moral character and recognized
competence in the field of human rights’,89 the HRC’s output may
form part of the ‘teachings of the most highly qualified publicists’ under
Article 38(1)(d) of the ICJ Statute.90 On this basis, the Federal Court
quoted para. 66 of the ICJ’s judgement in Diallo, in which the ICJ found
that it ‘should ascribe great weight’ to the interpretation of the
Committee.91
89
ICCPR, Article 28(2).
90
Anochie, para. 49.
91
Ibid. See n. 64 and accompanying text.
92
See n. 1 on the scope of the research on which the chapter is based.
93
Lewis v. Attorney General of Jamaica (2000) 134 ILR 615 (Jamaica, Judicial Committee of
the Privy Council, 12 September 2000).
94
Ibid., 635.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the Views of the HRC as non-binding, yet still ‘authoritative’, and noted
that national courts could only deviate from the Views if justified by
‘compelling reasons’.95
These instances of judicial respect for Views do not alter the fact that
domestic courts have a limited role in taking case-specific follow-up
measures.96 In this sense, it is much more relevant to see how domestic
courts navigate their pathways to the monitoring bodies outside case-
specific contexts. Some judges were willing to indicate the existence of
normative expectations – if not a strict obligation – for domestic courts
to engage with the monitoring bodies’ interpretation when the courts
interpret relevant treaty provisions. For instance, the Colombian
Constitutional Court in 2004 characterized the CESCR as an ‘authorized
interpreter’ of the Covenant.97 In the Test Trial Fund Clara Wichmann
case of 2005, the Dutch court noted that the CEDAW is empowered to
issue General Recommendations and that such Recommendations
should be taken into account in the context of interpreting the
Convention.98 In 2007, the Belize Supreme Court in the case of Cal noted
that, given Belize’s commitments under the Racial Discrimination
Convention, the government ‘should take this communication
[country-specific Correspondence] seriously and respond accordingly’.99
Another noteworthy example is the German Federal Constitutional
Court’s engagement with the CRPD’s Concluding Observations and
General Comments in the Order of 26 July 2016.100 The case involved
the provision of medical treatment to a woman against her natural will in
circumstances where she suffered from mental and physical illnesses and
was deemed unable to provide consent. The Federal Constitutional Court
95
Appellante v. de Raad van Bestuur van de Sociale Verzekeringsbank, 21 July 2006, LJN:
AY5560 (the Netherlands, Central Appeals Tribunal); cited in van Alebeek and
Nollkaemper, ‘The Legal Status of Decisions by Human Rights Treaty Bodies’, p. 402,
fn 199.
96
See nn. 17–19 and accompanying text on the principle of res judicata. In this vein, see,
e.g., X v. Council of Ministers, paras 41, 43 (OUP numbers).
97
Decision No T-025 of 2004 (2004) (Constitutional Court, Colombia, 22 January 2004,
English translation www.brookings.edu), para. 8.3.2 (‘como intérprete autorizado del
Pacto sobre la materia’).
98
Test Trial Fund Clara Wichmann (Stichting Proefprocessenfonds Clara Wichmann) and
Ors v. Netherlands, First instance decision (2005) HA ZA 03/3395, LJN: AU2088, ILDC
221 (NL 2005) (the Netherlands, District Court, 7 September 2005), para. 3.18.
99
Cal v. Attorney-General (2007) 71 WIR 110; 135 ILR 77 (Belize, Supreme Court,
18 October 2007), para. 125.
100
German Federal Constitutional Court (BVerfG), Order of the First Senate of 26 July 2016,
1 BvL 8/15 (English translation www.bverfg.de/e/ls20160726_1bvl000815en.html).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
obliged the legislature to enact laws to allow coercive medical treatment
in such cases. In holding that coercive treatment was compatible with the
Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, the German court
effectively disagreed with the CRPD’s General Comment No. 1,
Concluding Observations on Germany, and Guidelines on Article 14,
in which the CRPD had criticized the practices of custodianship and
forced treatment for failing to respect disabled persons’ autonomy and
will.101 According to the Constitutional Court, these CRPD documents
do not address the critical scenario involving persons who cannot form a
free will.102 While the German Federal Constitutional Court took a
critical look at the CRPD’s observations, the court substantively engaged
with the Committee’s position. Furthermore, the court notably observed
that a national court, although it is not obliged to follow the CRPD,103
should deal with the CRPD’s opinions ‘in an argumentative way and in
good faith’104 – as the German court seems to have done in this specific
instance.
101
CRPD, ‘General Comment No. 1 (2014), Article 12: Equal Recognition Before the Law’
(19 May 2014) CRPD/C/GC/1, para. 26; CRPD, ‘Concluding Observations on the Initial
Report of Germany’ (13 May 2015) CRPD/C/DEU/CO/1, paras 25–6; CRPD,
‘Guidelines on Article 14 of the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities:
The Right to Liberty and Security of Persons with Disabilities’ (September 2015), paras
11–12.
102
German Federal Constitutional Court, 1 BvL 8/15, para. 91.
103
Ibid., para. 90.
104
Ibid., para. 90.
105
See nn. 17–19 and accompanying text.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
6.5.2.1 Case-Specific Responses to Views
With regard to the case-specific responses to Views, it is hard to deny the
existence, under international law, of such an obligation to consider. In
fact, some treaties explicitly provide such an obligation. With regard to
the CEDAW, Article 7(4) of the Optional Protocol obliges a state party to
‘give due consideration to the views of the Committee’ and to submit
within six months the state’s follow-up action.106 These dual obligations
(to give due consideration and to provide information on follow-up
action) are also explicitly laid down in regard to the Views of the
CESCR107 and the CRC.108
The language is less explicit when it comes to the HRC. Yet the
ICCPR’s Optional Protocol, adopted in 1966, at least obliges a state party
to submit information in response to the Views.109 On top of the explicit
requirement, there is an obligation to cooperate with a committee, which
is applicable to all the monitoring bodies, including the HRC. Such an
obligation is based on the general obligation to perform a treaty in good
faith, under Article 26 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of
Treaties,110 accompanied by states parties’ recognition of the competence
of the committees under relevant human rights treaties. While the
meaning of ‘good faith’ is no doubt contextual,111 the good faith obliga-
tion has been understood as an obligation to cooperate with the commit-
tees, as the HRC remarked in General Comment No. 33.112 Cooperation
does not amount to require compliance; yet a state party may be acting in
bad faith towards its treaty commitment if frequent non-compliance is
combined with the failure to attempt to seriously engage with Views.113
106
Optional Protocol to the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination
against Women, 6 October 1999, 2131 UNTS 83, Article 7(4).
107
Optional Protocol to the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural
Rights, 10 December 2008, UN Doc. A/63/435, Article 9(2).
108
Optional Protocol to the Convention on the Rights of the Child on a communications
procedure, 19 December 2011, UN Doc. A/RES/66/138, Article 11(1).
109
Optional Protocol to the ICCPR (n 86).
110
VCLT, Article 26.
111
See R. Kolb, Good Faith in International Law (Hart Publishing, 2017), pp. 166–9.
112
UNHRC, ‘General Comment No. 33: The Obligations of States Parties under the
Optional Protocol’ (25 June 2009) CCPR/C/GC/33, para. 15. Cf. UNHRC, ‘Draft
General Comment No 33 (Second Revised Version as of 18 August 2008)’ (25 August
2008) CCPR/C/GC/33/CRP.3, para. 16.
113
S. Joseph, ‘Committees: Human Rights Bodies’, in R. Wolfrum (ed.), The Max Planck
Encyclopedia of Public International Law (Oxford University Press, 2010), para. 9.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
It is readily possible to find statements by states parties that they owe
an obligation to take into account the Views addressed to them.114
Iceland, for instance, expressed its position in a series of actions following
the HRC’s Views in Haraldsson et al. v. Iceland in October 2007 regarding
the fisheries management system.115 According to the Icelandic govern-
ment, Iceland ‘elected to become a party’ to the Optional Protocol to the
ICCPR, ‘thereby recognising the competence of the Human Rights
Committee to decide whether there has been a violation of the provisions
of the Covenant or not’.116 On this basis, Iceland noted that it is
‘therefore required by international law to address the conclusions of
the Committee’.117 Not surprisingly, the government still preserved the
space for discretion, adding that the Views in question were not detailed
enough. According to Iceland, the Views ‘do not include a summarized
conclusion in the form of an adjudication, but a general discussion’
without ‘detailed guidance as to the precise measures required’.118 In
short, Iceland is acknowledging an obligation to consider and respond to
Views, while, at the same time, characterizing them as ‘a general
discussion’.119
There are also some influential academic writings that support the
existence of the obligation to consider with regard to states parties’ case-
specific responses to Views. Tomuschat articulated that ‘States Parties
cannot simply ignore’ the Views of the HRC, despite the fact that they
114
See van Alebeek and Nollkaemper, ‘The Legal Status of Decisions by Human Rights
Treaty Bodies’, p. 386.
115
UNHRC, Erlingur Sveinn Haraldsson and Örn Snævar Sveinsson v. Iceland,
Communication No. 1306/2004, CCPR/C/91/D/1306/2004 (14 December 2007). The
communication concerned discrimination in the business of commercial fishing quotas.
See G. Gauksdottir and T. Ingadottir, ‘Compliance with the Views of the UN Human
Rights Committee and the Judgments of the European Court of Human Rights in
Iceland’, in A. Eide, J. T. Möller and I. Ziemele (eds), Making Peoples Heard: Essays
on Human Rights in Honour of Gudmundur Alfredsson (Nijhoff, 2011) pp. 511–36, at
pp. 526–9.
116
Letter from the government of Iceland concerning the Views adopted by the Human
Rights Committee on 24 October 2007, cited in Gauksdottir and Ingadottir, ‘Compliance
with the Views of the UN Human Rights Committee’, pp. 530–1.
117
Ibid., p. 531.
118
Ibid., p. 531.
119
Ibid. Iceland’s readiness to review its system has led the HRC to close the follow-up
examination of the case: ‘Report of the Human Rights Committee, Volume I, 103rd
Session (17 October–4 November 2011), 104th Session (12–30 March 2012)’, (2012) UN
Doc. A/67/40 (Vol. I), at 114–15 (with a finding of a partly satisfactory implementation
of the recommendation).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
lack legally binding force.120 States parties ‘have to consider’ the Views ‘in
good faith (bona fide)’.121 Tomuschat observes that states’ lack of reac-
tion ‘would appear to amount to a violation of the obligations under the
ICCPR’.122 By quoting Tomuschat’s remarks, the Venice Commission
reiterated that ‘member states are under the obligation to take the HRC’s
final views into consideration in good faith’.123
A main point of contestation remains the extent to which the obligation
to consider in good faith requires states parties, and indirectly their courts,
to favour the monitoring bodies’ treaty interpretation. According to
Tomuschat, states parties have to ‘carefully examine’ the Views addressed
to them, and that ‘there exists a presumption in favour of substantive
correctness of such views’.124 In case of disagreement, a state party ‘must
present detailed observations specifying its counter-arguments’.125 An
observation of a similar nature to the one by Tomuschat was relied upon
by the Privy Council, in the New Zealand case of Tangiora in 1999, which
found the HRC’s Views hard to dismiss despite the lack of binding
force.126 According to the Privy Council, the Views of the HRC acquire
‘authority from the standing of its members and their judicial qualities of
impartiality, objectivity and restraint’.127 Moreover, the Privy Council
suggested that the functions of the Committee are ‘adjudicative’, as it
makes a definitive and final ruling which is determinative of an issue that
has been referred to it.128 Despite these statements, however, the basis of
the presumption of substantive correctness remains unclear.
120
Tomuschat, ‘Human Rights Committee’, para. 14.
121
Ibid.
122
Ibid.
123
European Commission for Democracy through Law (Venice Commission), ‘Report on
the Implementation of International Human Rights Treaties in Domestic Law and the
Role of Courts’ adopted by the Venice Commission at its 100th plenary session (Rome,
10–11 October 2014), CDL-AD(2014)036 (8 December 2014), para. 78.
124
Christian Tomuschat, Human Rights: Between Idealism and Realism (Oxford University
Press, 2014), p. 267.
125
Ibid.
126
Tangiora v. Wellington District Legal Services Committee (1999) [2000] 1 WLR 240;
124 ILR 570 (New Zealand, Judicial Committee of the Privy Council, 4 October 1999).
127
Ibid., 575.
128
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
commentary to its draft conclusions adopted in 2018, the ILC acknow-
ledge that ‘State parties may have an obligation, under a duty to cooper-
ate under certain treaties, to take into account and to react to a
pronouncement of an expert treaty body’129 where the pronouncement
is ‘specifically addressed to them or to individual communications
regarding their own conduct’.130 The ILC’s commentary signals that
the dual obligations to consider and react may be applicable, not only
to Views, but also to Concluding Observations addressed to a specific
state party. The 2016 Final Report of the ILA International Human
Rights Law Committee may have even gone beyond the ILC’s suggestion.
According to the Final Report, the ‘jurisprudence’ developed by human
rights bodies ‘constitutes res interpretata within the treaty system
accepted by the state’.131 On this basis, the ILA’s Final Report observed
that domestic courts implement the good faith obligation by ‘giving
serious consideration’ to the decisions of human rights bodies.132 The
ILA’s Final Report indicated that the treaty bodies’ ‘jurisprudence’ – and
not necessarily limited to Views in case-specific follow-up – ought to be
considered seriously.
It seems plausible to argue that states parties’ obligation to cooperate
with the committees, based on the obligation to perform a treaty in good
faith,133 is applicable to Concluding Observations as they are addressed
to specific states. One cannot be certain, however, whether this obligation
is applicable to General Comments. Further contested is whether the
presumption of substantive correctness applies to findings outside case-
specific follow-up to Views. In para. 66 of Diallo, the ICJ was prepared to
accord ‘great weight’ to the HRC’s ‘interpretation’ or ‘jurisprudence’ in
general.134 Interestingly, the ICJ’s justification for doing so was not only
because the Committee is the ‘independent body that was established
specifically to supervise the application of that treaty [i.e. the ICCPR]’.135
129
‘Report of the International Law Commission, Seventieth Session’ above, p. 113, para. 19
(commentary regarding Conclusion 13.3) (emphasis added).
130
Ibid. (emphasis added).
131
S. Kadelbach, ‘The Domestic Implementation of Judgments/Decisions of Courts and
Other International Bodies That Involve International Human Rights Law: Final Report
of the ILA International Human Rights Law Committee (Part 2)’, in S. Kadelbach, T.
Rensmann and E. Rieter (eds), Judging International Human Rights (Springer
International Publishing, 2019) pp. 51–100, at pp. 70–1.
132
Ibid., p. 71.
133
See nn. 110–113 and accompanying text.
134
See Diallo, para. 66.
135
See ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The ICJ ascribed great weight to the HRC’s interpretation, also because of
the wider interests at stake in achieving ‘the necessary clarity and the
essential consistency of international law, as well as legal security’ neces-
sary for the rights holders and duty bearers.136 The reasoning of the ICJ
shows that the degree of normative weight to be given to treaty body
findings relies not only on one’s understanding of the characteristics of
the monitoring bodies, but also the wider role that one wishes to ascribe
to the bodies within the international legal order.
136
See ibid.
137
Judgment No. 1263/2018 of 17 July 2018, ROJ: STS 2747/2018, ECLI: ES:TS:2018:2747
(Tribunal Supremo [Supreme Court], Sala de lo Contencioso-Administrativo
[Contentious-Administrative Chamber]) (Spain). For detailed analysis, see M.
Kanetake, ‘María de los Ángeles González Carreño v. Ministry of Justice’ (2019) 113
American Journal of International Law 586–92.
138
For facts, see CEDAW, Angela González Carreño v. Spain, Communication No. 47/2012
(16 July 2014), paras 2.1–2.21.
139
Ibid., para. 2.5.
140
See, e.g., ibid., para. 2.12.
141
Ibid., para. 2.13.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
After the tragic incident, González Carreño went through a series of
domestic court proceedings, trying to prove the pecuniary liability of the
state which failed to protect her and her late daughter. From April
2004 to October 2010, her liability claims met rejection four times before
Spanish courts.142 Her constitutional claim was likewise rejected by the
Constitutional Court in April 2011.143 Having exhausted domestic rem-
edies, on 19 September 2012, González Carreño brought her petition to
the CEDAW. The Committee rendered its Views on 16 July 2014, finding
the Spanish government in violation of her Conventional rights.144
Having found a violation of the state’s obligations under the
Convention,145 the Committee recommended Spain to provide compen-
sation and conduct an exhaustive and impartial investigation.146 At the
domestic level, however, the CEDAW’s recommendations in July
2014 did not result in any changes to the situation of the appellant.
A year later, in July 2015, the CEDAW still expressed its concern about
the ‘lack of follow-up to the Committee’s views’ on the part of the state
party regarding González Carreño.147 Meanwhile, she launched a series
of new administrative and judicial proceedings, ultimately before the
Supreme Court, requesting the government to give effect to the
CEDAW’s Views.148
In its judgement of 17 July 2018, the Spanish Supreme Court regarded
the Views of the CEDAW as binding at the domestic level, ordering the
government to pay €600,000 for moral damages suffered by the appel-
lant.149 The Supreme Court reached such a conclusion on the basis of
both international and domestic laws. With regard to the international
legal basis, the Spanish court held that the Views of the CEDAW have a
‘binding/obligatory’ character.150 The court ascribed such a character to
Views, despite its acknowledgement that the CEDAW Convention does
not oblige states parties to adopt any specific procedures in order to give
142
Ibid., paras 2.18–2.20.
143
Ibid., para. 2.21.
144
Ibid., para. 10.
145
CEDAW, Angela González Carreño, para. 10 (Articles 2(a–f ), 5(a) and 16(1)(d) of the
CEDAW Convention).
146
Ibid., para. 11(a).
147
CEDAW, ‘Concluding Observations on the Combined Seventh and Eighth Periodic
Reports of Spain’ (29 July 2015) CEDAW/C/ESP/CO/7–8, paras 10–11.
148
See further Kanetake, ‘María de los Ángeles González Carreño’, 588–9.
149
Judgment No. 1263/2018 of 17 July 2018, 14.
150
Ibid., 12.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
effect to Views.151 The court derived the ‘binding/obligatory’ character
on the basis of Article 24 of the CEDAW Convention and Articles 7(4)
and 1 of the Optional Protocol.152
The Supreme Court’s reasoning was further supported by domestic
law. The court reiterated that the CEDAW Convention, on which the
Committee and its Views are based, forms part of the domestic legal
order under Article 96 of the Spanish Constitution.153 Pursuant to Article
10(2) of the Constitution, fundamental rights shall be interpreted in
accordance with human rights treaties ratified by Spain.154 An important
aspect of the court’s reasoning was the manner in which the court
invoked Article 9(3) of the Spanish Constitution. The provision guaran-
tees ‘the principle of legality and the normative hierarchy’, according to
which international obligations relating to the execution of the decisions
of the CEDAW form part of the Spanish internal order and enjoy a
hierarchical position above ordinary domestic law.155 On this basis, the
Supreme Court observed that the Convention and the Views ‘can and
should be a decisive element’ in proving the possible infringement of the
fundamental rights of the appellant.156 While the Supreme Court empha-
sized the particularities of the appellant’s case, the court took the position
that the CEDAW’s Views must be considered as a ‘valid basis’ for
bringing a claim concerning the pecuniary liability of the state.157
Otherwise, as articulated by the Supreme Court, the ‘absence of a specific
procedure for executing’ the Views of the Committee constitutes ‘in itself
a breach of a legal and constitutional mandate by Spain’.158
The Spanish Supreme Court’s reasoning pertains only to the
CEDAW’s Views on individual communications, and not to other
types of findings. Yet it would be good to reiterate once again that
each monitoring body engages with its own previous findings. In the
CEDAW’s Views in Angela González Carreño v. Spain, the Committee’s
151
Ibid., 12.
152
Ibid., 12.
153
See ibid., 12.
154
Ibid., 12.
155
Ibid., 12. It must be noted that international obligations are superior to ordinary
domestic law – but not above the Constitution – based on Articles 95 and 96 of the
Constitution, instead of Article 9(3) itself.
156
Ibid., 12.
157
Judgment No. 1263/2018 of 17 July 2018., 13.
158
Ibid., 13.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
reasoning built on its General Recommendation No. 19 (1992),159
in which the CEDAW had made it clear that states ought to act with
due diligence to prevent violations involving the acts of private per-
sons.160 In Angela González Carreño v. Spain, the Committee found the
violations of the Convention, ‘read jointly with . . . general recommenda-
tion No. 19 of the Committee’.161 In other words, by according legal
binding effect to Views, the Spanish Supreme Court in the judgement of
July 2018 augmented the normative relevance of other CEDAW findings
at the domestic level.
159
CEDAW, ‘General Recommendation No. 19: Violence against Women’ (1992).
160
Ibid., para. 9.
161
CEDAW, Angela González Carreño, para. 10.
162
UNHRC, ‘Draft General Comment No 33’, para. 14 (‘the [an] authentic interpreter’).
See, further, Kanetake, ‘UN Human Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies Before Domestic
Courts’, 205–6.
163
UNHRC, ‘Draft General Comment No 33’, para. 11. On differences between the
adoption of Views and judicial decision making, see, e.g., L. S. Borlini and L. Crema,
‘The Legal Status of Decisions by Human Rights Treaty Bodies: International
Supervision, Authoritative Interpretations or Mission Éducatrice?’ (2019) 18 Global
Community Yearbook of International Law and Jurisprudence, section III C.
164
Ibid., ‘Draft General Comment No 33’, para. 16.
165
CAT, ‘Thirty-Sixth Session, Summary Record of the 717th Meeting’ (1 June 2006) CAT/
C/SR.717, para. 65 (Mr. Mariño Menéndez, emphasis added). The remarks were also
endorsed by the chairperson: see para. 66 (Mr. Mavrommatis).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The imperative vocabularies used in the draft version of General
Comment No. 33 met with criticisms from several states parties.166
In the end, the wording of the final version of General Comment
No. 33 was revised, including the critical phrase ‘authentic interpreter’.167
The draft version of General Comment No. 33 was an attempt to
creatively translate a procedural duty to cooperate with the Committee,
based on the good faith obligation, into the substantive obligation to
respect the Views of the HRC.168 Such an attempt was not successful in
2008, at least in the context of the HRC.
In the judgement of July 2018, the Spanish Supreme Court by no
means characterized the CEDAW as an authentic interpreter. In fact,
the Spanish Constitutional Court reiterated in 2002 that the HRC was
not a judicial organ and that the Views of the HRC could not represent
the ‘authentic interpretation’ of the ICCPR.169 The crux, however, is that
the Spanish Supreme Court’s reasoning in 2018 was in part based on the
state party’s obligation to take Views seriously. The Spanish court
referred to not only Article 24 of the Convention, according to which
states parties ‘undertake to adopt all necessary measures at the national
level aimed at achieving the full realization of the rights recognized in the
present Convention’.170 The Court also relied on Article 7(4) of the
Optional Protocol, according to which the state party has dual obliga-
tions. Namely, the party ‘shall give due consideration to the views of the
Committee, together with its recommendations’ and ‘shall submit to the
Committee, within six months, a written response’.171 As noted in
Section 6.5.2.1, these dual obligations are enunciated for the CESCR
and the CRC as well.172 Overall, the reasoning of the Spanish highest
166
Kanetake, ‘UN Human Rights Treaty Monitoring Bodies before Domestic Courts’,
205–6.
167
UNHRC, ‘Draft General Comment No 33’, para. 14; UNHRC, ‘General Comment
No. 33’, para. 13. Regarding the distinction between authentic and authoritative inter-
pretation, see Iwasawa, ‘Domestic Application of International Law’, 239–41.
168
UNHRC, ‘Draft General Comment No 33’, para. 16.
169
PM v. Criminal Chamber of the Supreme Court, Constitutional Appeal (recurso de
amparo), ILDC 1794 (ES 2002), STC 70/2002, para. 7 of the section on legal foundations
(Spain, Constitutional Court, 3 April 2002) (‘Dictámenes no pueden constituir la
interpretación auténtica del Pacto’). The Constitutional Court’s narrative was repro-
duced by the Spanish Supreme Court in its judgment of 8 June 2015: Judgment of the
Supreme Court of 8 June 2015 (Spain, Supreme Court, Third Chamber, Contentious-
Administrative), https://supremo.vlex.es/vid/575807258.
170
Judgment No. 1263/2018 of 17 July 2018, 12; CEDAW Convention, Article 24.
171
Optional Protocol CEDAW, Article 7(4).
172
See nn. 107–108.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
court demonstrates the breadth of what can be offered through the
obligation to consider. After the lengthy administrative and judicial
proceedings involving the victim of the state’s neglect, the obligation to
consider has reached the point where no further deliberation may be
welcome.
6.7 Conclusion
The shortcomings of human rights protection at the domestic level have
sustained the need for institutional mechanisms at the international level
that monitor and assist states’ implementation of human rights treaties.
The ten human rights treaty-monitoring bodies, within their significantly
limited resources, actively adopt general and specific findings. Each
treaty-monitoring body generates and reiterates its own interpretation
of relevant treaty obligations by cross-referencing previous findings.
Despite the accumulation of instruments adopted, the effectiveness of
treaty body findings ultimately relies on the degree to which their treaty
interpretation becomes entangled with the practice of states parties,
including their judiciary.
As illustrated by some examples discussed in this chapter, the treaty
interpretation built by UN human rights treaty-monitoring bodies has
been intertwined with the discourse of domestic court decisions. Various
courts have shown their willingness to take into account General
Comments, Concluding Observations and Views in the course of inter-
preting applicable human rights treaties and relevant domestic legal
provisions. Judges’ proximity to the international monitoring bodies
varies, depending on sociological contexts in which judges have been
situated. If UN treaty-monitoring bodies are not integrated in judges’
legal training, it may be unrealistic to expect them to see the relevance of
treaty body findings.
At the same time, a connecting point between UN treaty-monitoring
bodies and domestic courts can also be normative, at least in part. One
such normative pathway which generates ‘discursive entanglement’173 is
the obligation to consider. As illustrated in the present chapter, there are
a number of variations surrounding such an obligation, from mere
encouragement to take into account to an obligation to implement.
While normative expectations may be limited to certain types of treaty
173
See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
body findings, the monitoring bodies regularly refer back to General
Comments in drafting Concluding Observations or Views, reminding a
state party of the monitoring bodies’ earlier remarks on which specific
observations are built. In other words, the consideration of Views would
substantively involve a state party’s reflection of General Comments or
Concluding Observations.
Pathways built around the obligation to consider are not single routes.
There are multiple normative variations: ranging from a cursory look, to
substantive and reasoned engagement, to legally obliged acceptance. Due
to the fact that there are multiple possibilities, judges’ willingness to
substantively engage with the treaty body’s interpretation can be altered,
for instance, by the initiatives to better ensure independence and impar-
tiality of UN treaty-monitoring bodies.174 Substantive engagement on the
part of domestic courts creates further opportunities for the treaty bodies
to tailor their approaches to states parties. Deliberative space involving
domestic courts and the monitoring bodies may be multifaceted and
changeable, in that it allows various degrees of entanglement on the part
of domestic courts. Yet it is precisely because of its precariousness that
there arises the need for constant attempts to augment the quality of
engagement, both on the part of domestic courts and UN treaty-
monitoring bodies.
174
E.g., ‘Guidelines on the Independence and Impartiality of Members of the Human
Rights Treaty Bodies (“the Addis Ababa Guidelines”)’ (2 August 2012) UN Doc. A/67/
222 Annex I.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
7
7.1 Introduction
Metaphors may be helpful tools to think about law. They may also help
us to imagine what happens when law makes its actual appearance in the
plural rather than in the singular. Consider the following statement:
[W]estbrook’s intriguing metaphor of cream poured into coffee, swirling
and billowing before blending into a homogenized liquid, is suggestive.
But this only captures part of what we should be concerned with. The
cream comes from a single outside source, it is poured from above, the
flow is in one direction, and the blending is relatively harmonious; but
many of our stories of diffusion of law are more complex often involving
two or more reciprocally interacting change agents, crossing of levels, and
repression, resistance, or avoidance.1
I am grateful to Nico Krisch for his constructive comments and criticism on earlier versions
of this work. I also thank Tomáš Morochovič for his careful editing and helpful suggestions
on this text. I gratefully acknowledge financial support by the Swiss National Science
Foundation, which made this research possible.
1
W. Twining, ‘Diffusion and Globalization Discourse Symposium: Diffusion of Law in the
21st Century: Interaction and Influence’ (2006) 47 Harvard International Law Journal
507–16.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
and industry employ some sort of mediators between the water and the oil
(so-called ‘emulgators’) to achieve this.2
2
B. Simma, ‘Foreign Investment Arbitration: A Place for Human Rights?’ (2011) 60
International & Comparative Law Quarterly 573–96.
3
See Chapter 1.
4
P. Alston, ‘Resisting the Merger and Acquisition of Human Rights by Trade Law: A Reply
to Petersman’ (2002) 13 European Journal of International Law 815–44; see also, in the
context of the interface between trade and environment, Chapter 8.
5
OEIGWG Chairmanship, ‘Second Revised Draft, Legally Binding Instrument to Regulate,
in International Human Rights Law, the Activities of Transnational Corporations and
Other Business Enterprises’ (6 August 2020) www.ohchr.org/Documents/HRBodies/
HRCouncil/WGTransCorp/Session6/OEIGWG_Chair-Rapporteur_second_revised_
draft_LBI_on_TNCs_and_OBEs_with_respect_to_Human_Rights.pdf.
6
N. Krisch, F. Corradini and L. Lu Reimers, ‘Order at the Margins: The Legal Construction
of Interface Conflicts Over Time’ (2020) 9 Global Constitutionalism 343–63.
7
See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
that are likely to affect whether and how ‘forms of entanglement’8 in
international investment law have come about and developed. On the
one hand, these forms may be an effect of competing interests of actors
with unequal access to resources and knowledge to shape and organize
them. Rational actors’ attitudes towards what they represent as ‘other’
legalities may depend upon the potential gains involved in that deter-
mination. On the other hand, actors’ mindsets and the cultural setting
of investment arbitration are bound to have repercussions on how the
boundaries of international investment law and its relations with com-
peting legalities are shaped. Against this background, Section 7.3 exam-
ines how actors have actually dealt with multiple legalities, in particular
with human rights norms, in the context of investor–state dispute
settlement (ISDS) and analyses the various forms that they have gener-
ated there. As actors’ responses to multiplicity have varied considerably
in practice, the emerging picture is not coherent. When interpreting
investment treaty standards, investment adjudicators have disregarded
human rights norms in some cases, while in other cases they accorded
them some weight, but always doing so from the perspective of their
own legality. Actors’ strategic interests and ideational context may
partly account for the diversity of interpretive practices observed.
As the institutions of international investment protection face
growing challenges from national governments, academics and non-
governmental actors, linkages with human rights may be beneficial to
their cause.
Section 7.4 examines similar dynamics of convergence and divergence
between legalities in contexts of international investment law reform,
where the norm of ISDS itself has become the object of acute contest-
ation. Human rights experts have articulated a mode of ordering multi-
plicity that is similar to the dominant forms of relationing observed in
foreign investment litigation. Associated as they are to a systemic vision
of order, human rights lawyers have also relied on norms of internal
hierarchy according to which different legalities have to be ‘consistent’
with human rights and the rule of law. Some of these experts went so far
as to claim that human rights norms have priority over conflicting
legalities.
8
See Chapter 1. For the purpose of this chapter, I use ‘entanglement’ and
‘enmeshment’ interchangeably.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
7.2 Pathways to Entanglement in International Investment
Governance Sites
Legal scholars have emphasized the pluralist, decentralized and incremen-
tally evolving character of international investment law.9 Indeed, in con-
texts of investment treaty disputes, often this law makes its appearance
more in the plural than in the singular.10 For example, bilateral investment
treaties (BITs), multilateral or regional trade and investment agreements
often interplay with domestic laws, contractual frameworks and other
rules of international law and therefore it becomes crucial to define their
relations.11 At sites of foreign investment governance, entanglements do
not build themselves but are defined by the interplay of situated actors
with competing stakes and normative orientations.12 Such diversity of
actors and ‘bodies of norms’13 makes this arena of global economic
governance, and investment treaty arbitration in particular,14 an ideal
setting to analyse how entangled legalities are formed and operate. The
purpose of this chapter is to get closer to the social life of relations built in
and around this law. To do so, I consider how actors’ attitudes towards
human rights norms in investor–state arbitration may respond to com-
peting interests and the ideational background in which they are formed.
9
J. Pauwelyn, ‘Rational Design or Accidental Evolution? The Emergence of International
Investment Law’, in Z. Douglas, J. Pauwelyn and J. E. Viñuales (eds), The Foundations of
International Investment Law: Bringing Theory into Practice (Oxford University Press,
2014), pp. 11–43; A. Roberts, ‘Clash of Paradigms: Actors and Analogies Shaping the
Investment Treaty System’ (2013) 107 The American Journal of International Law 45–94.
10
Z. Douglas, ‘The Hybrid Foundations of Investment Treaty Arbitration’ (2003) 74 British
Yearbook of International Law 151–289, referring to the ‘laws applicable to an investment
dispute’ at 194.
11
J. Viñuales, ‘Sources of International Investment Law: Conceptual Foundations of Unruly
Practices’, in S. Besson and J. d’Aspremont (eds), Oxford Handbook on the Sources of
International Law (Oxford University Press, 2017).
12
See Chapter 1, Section 1.4.1.
13
On this notion, see Chapter 1, Section 1.2.
14
On ISDS as a mechanism and form of global governance, see S. Schill, ‘W(h)ither
Fragmentation? On the Literature and Sociology of International Investment Law’
(2011) 22 European Journal of International Law 875–908.
15
See Chapter 1, Section 1.4.1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
arbitration participants – foreign investors, host governments,
investment arbitrators, lawyers and non-governmental organizations
(NGOs) – act rationally to maximize their self-interest.16 Given the
competition of interests and concerns involved, conflicting demands
and priorities are bound to condition whether and how norms will be
brought together or kept apart.17 This outcome may depend on actors’
‘prudential reasons-for-action’ – different actors will shape forms of
relation depending on their own expected gains.18
Since ‘states, investors, and NGOs often favour different paradigms in
light of their divergent normative interests and agendas’,19 these interests
and agendas will also determine what weight they will give to the
legalities at play. I assume that the interest of the two disputing parties –
foreign investor and responding state – is to win the dispute. As investors
argue ‘for broad investor rights’,20 we can expect them to defend their
own interests from the potentially disruptive effects of human rights
protecting the interests of other individuals or groups. Empirical findings
suggest that foreign investors have benefited from investment litigation.
Particularly since the second half of 1990s, they have gained from using
investment claims against poor and rich governments.21 The stability and
predictability of international investment protection – legally sanctioned
through international arbitration – has been economically beneficial to
international investors. It seems that the status quo has protected foreign
investors’ interests against the preferences of other societal actors.22
Given the beneficial environment in which investors bring their claims,
couplings with bodies of norms of different origin may open unpredict-
able scenarios. As rational actors, foreign investors will seek to resist this
16
J. Bonnitcha, L. N. S. Poulsen and M. Waibel, The Political Economy of the Investment
Treaty Regime (Oxford University Press, 2017), at 127.
17
On the competition of interests involved, see M. Sornarajah, The International Law on
Foreign Investment (Cambridge University Press, 2017), ‘Introduction’.
18
T. Schultz, Transnational Legality: Stateless Law and International Arbitration (Oxford
University Press, 2014), pp. 26–30.
19
Roberts, ‘Clash of Paradigms’, 48.
20
J. Pauwelyn, ‘The Rule of Law without the Rule of Lawyers? Why Investment Arbitrators
Are from Mars, Trade Adjudicators from Venus’ (2015) 109 American Journal of
International Law 761–805, at 782.
21
T. Schultz and C. Dupont, ‘Investment Arbitration: Promoting the Rule of Law or Over-
empowering Investors? A Quantitative Empirical Study’ (2015) 25 European Journal of
International Law 1147–68.
22
N. Tzouvala, ‘The Academic Debate about Mega-Regionals and International Lawyers:
Legalism as Critique?’ (2018) 6 London Review of International Law 189–209, at 200.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
outcome.23 However, in cases in which it is convenient to them, they may
also entangle their rights with human rights norms, perhaps to enhance
the persuasiveness of their claims against the host government.24 States,
too, may expect gains from these types of connections. Frequently, and
especially in times of economic crises, linkages with human rights might
strengthen their defences against investor’s claims. Countries with
limited financial resources may use these linkages as a rhetorical strategy
to expand their ‘regulatory authority’25 and avoid costly liability or
reduce the amount of compensation due to the investor. Finally, NGOs
(other than business associations) and human rights experts may entan-
gle international investment and human rights law to advance the inter-
ests of affected outsiders like local communities and human rights
holders.
Investment arbitration insiders’ decision-making may also respond to
constraints and incentives.26 Previous empirical analysis has concluded
that arbitrators of the International Centre for Settlement of Investment
Disputes (ICSID) form a ‘network’ that ‘reinforces prevailing norms and
behaviours and insulates its most important members from outside
influence’.27 Beyond international arbitrators, legal counsel, expert wit-
nesses and tribunal secretaries have also become particularly influential
actors.28 In conditions of professional competition, the members of the
investment arbitration industry may have professional incentives to
distance human rights. As co-operators of the system, they will have
material incentives to defend their legal specialization and their role as
the masters of its law. From their perspective, investment arbitration may
be a specialized profession with its own ‘ethos’ and associated relevant
23
‘[I]nvestors will not invoke the kind of international law that may weaken their legal
position’, A. van Aaken, ‘Fragmentation of International Law: The Case of International
Investment Protection’ (2008) 17 Finnish Yearbook of International Law 91–130, at 93.
24
On the ‘strategic function of human rights references in investment arbitration’, see S.
Steininger, ‘What’s Human Rights Got To Do With It? An Empirical Analysis of Human
Rights References in Investment Arbitration’ (2018) 31 Leiden Journal of International
Law 33–58, at 45–9.
25
Pauwelyn, ‘The Rule of Law’, at 782.
26
T. Schultz, ‘Arbitral Decision-Making: Legal Realism and Law and Economics’ (2015) 6
Journal of International Dispute Settlement 231–51.
27
S. Puig, ‘Social Capital in the Arbitration Market’ (2014) 25 European Journal of
International Law 387–424, at 390.
28
M. Langford, D. Behn and R. H. Lie, ‘The Revolving Door in International Investment
Arbitration’ (2017) 20 Journal of International Economic Law 301–32.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
frameworks and practices.29 Therefore, distancing human rights may be
needed to secure reputation from other members of their community of
practice and to continue their practice as usual.30 Yet empirical work has
found that over time there have been incentives for these legal experts to
be reflexively open to societal demands. As investor–state arbitration
faces a legitimacy crisis, some arbitrators may act strategically to ‘manage
consciously or unconsciously the legitimacy of arbitration’ by showing
‘greater deference to respondent states’.31 To do so, they might seek to
adjust their decision-making in response to the claims and interests of
dominant states like the European Union, the United States and China,
but also to those of some Latin America countries that have been vocal
against investment arbitration. In this context, investment arbitration
officials might benefit from linkages with norms with strong social
backing like human rights law to strengthen their own legitimacy.32
29
T. Schultz, ‘The Ethos of Arbitration’, in T. Schultz and F. Ortino (eds), Oxford Handbook
of International Arbitration (Oxford University Press, 2020).
30
Schultz, ‘Arbitral Decision-Making’.
31
M. Langford and D. Behn, ‘Managing Backlash: The Evolving Investment Treaty
Arbitrator?’ (2018) 29 European Journal of International Law 551–80.
32
See Chapter 1, Section 1.2. See also Steininger, ‘What’s Human Rights’, at 49–50.
33
See Chapter 1, Section 1.2. On the concepts of ‘shared understanding’ and ‘communities
of practice’, see J. Brunnée and S. Toope, ‘Interactional International Law: An
Introduction’ (2011) 3 International Theory 307–18.
34
A. Bianchi, ‘Epistemic Communities in International Arbitration’, in T. Schultz and
F. Ortino (eds), The Oxford Handbook of International Arbitration (Oxford University
Press, 2020).
35
Roberts, ‘Clash of Paradigms’; E. Gaillard, ‘Sociology of International Arbitration’ (2015)
1 Arbitration International 1–17.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
be driven by how different actors regard international investment law, for
example by adopting primarily an international public law, commercial
arbitration or public law approach.36
Investment tribunals will often understand their role as strictly con-
fined to the determination of whether foreign investors’ rights have been
violated or not. In that determination, arbitrators will see themselves
primarily as interpreters of the legal basis creating those rights (e.g. a
treaty), with implications for their room for manoeuvre to create rela-
tions with bodies of norms perceived as external. ISDS participants’
choice of ‘conceptual maps’37 is likely to impact whether and how
legalities are brought together or kept apart and with which effects.
This choice may depend upon actors’ background and projects. For
instance, investment arbitrators with knowledge in public international
law have drawn on the judgements of the ICJ, while others with experi-
ence in trade law have relied on the World Trade Organization (WTO)
jurisprudence.38 The same holds true for arbitrators emphasizing a
‘universalistic’ versus ‘particularistic’ perspective of the interaction
between ‘general international law’ and other ‘special regimes’. For
example, a former ICJ judge has situated ‘international investment law’
within ‘general international law’ in keeping with his vision about the
relationship between ‘special regimes’ within the wider ‘universe of
international law’.39 Similarly, lawyers believing in a unified ‘inter-
national legal system’ as opposed to a ‘fragmented’ one will consider
linkages between international investment and human rights law with
less hesitancy.40
However, previous sociological analysis of the ‘investment arbitration
culture’ has concluded that lawyers with a strong background in public
international law are the minority in investment arbitration settings
while the ‘commercial arbitration paradigm’ appears as the dominant
36
Roberts, ‘Clash of Paradigms’.
37
Ibid.
38
Ibid., at 55.
39
Simma, ‘Foreign Investment Arbitration’. B. Simma and J. Kill, ‘Harmonizing Investment
Protection and International Human Rights: First Steps Towards a Methodology’, in C.
Binder, U. Kriebaum, A. Reinisch and S. Wittich (eds), International Investment Law for
the 21st Century: Essays in Honour of Christoph Schreurer (Oxford University Press,
2009), pp. 679–707.
40
P.-M. Dupuy, ‘Unification Rather than Fragmentation of International Law? The Case of
International Investment Law and Human Rights Law’, in P.-M. Dupuy, E.-U.
Petersmann and F. Francioni (eds), Human Rights in International Investment Law and
Arbitration (Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 45–62.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
one.41 Empirical work on the composition of investor–state arbitral
tribunals at ICSID has found that these tribunals comprise individuals –
mostly men from the USA and Europe – whose conception of law reflects
their particular training and professional background.42 Here, inter-
national ‘business lawyers’ with competence in ‘commerce, industry or
finance’ appear as the dominant players.43 The investment arbitration
community seems to have little knowledge of human rights law due to
the particular ‘sociocultural features’ and processes of socialization of
that community.44 Indeed, ‘culture influences how people think, com-
municate, behave’,45 including how they situate themselves in relation to
different constituencies and their legalities. However, legal culture and
socio-psychological influences46 are not the only elements of the idea-
tional context in which arbitrators’ decision-making is situated.
Empirical work has found that arbitrators’ ‘policy preferences’, including
their ideology, also shape their decisions.47 As a consequence of the ‘set
of values and beliefs’48 that seem dominant in investment arbitration we
might expect resistance to tight linkages with human rights,49 although it
is possible that investment arbitrators’ ‘background preferences’50 might
begin to change.
41
M. Hirsch, ‘The Sociological Dimension of International Arbitration: The Investment
Arbitration Culture’, in T. Schultz and F. Ortino (eds), Oxford Handbook of International
Arbitration (Oxford University Press, 2020).
42
Pauwelyn, ‘The Rule of Law’.
43
Puig, ‘Social Capital’, 402.
44
M. Hirsch, Invitation to the Sociology of International Law (Oxford University Press,
2015), pp. 129–55.
45
Ibid., p. 131.
46
M. Gicquello, ‘The Reform of Investor–State Dispute Settlement: Bringing the Findings of
Social Psychology into the Debate’ (2019) 10 Journal of International Dispute Settlement
561–81.
47
M. Waibel and Y. Wu, ‘Are Arbitrators Political? Evidence from International Investment
Arbitration?’ (2017) www.yanhuiwu.com/documents/arbitrator.pdf.
48
Gaillard, ‘Sociology of International Arbitration’.
49
Hirsch, Invitation to the Sociology.
50
Langford and Behn, ‘Managing Backlash’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
between multiple bodies of norms.51 Influenced by the discourse of
institutions like the World Bank-based ICSID, the Permanent Court of
Arbitration (PCA) or the United Nations Commission on International
Trade Law (UNCITRAL), ISDS has become one among many govern-
ance sites where ‘horizontal’ and ‘vertical’ interactions between legal
orders have been articulated over time. At this site, ad hoc investment
arbitrators have become key decision-makers in setting the boundaries of
‘international investment law’.52 While scholars have observed an
increase in the number of actors’ statements referring to human rights
norms in investment litigation,53 we know less about the forms of rela-
tion constructed through those claims. In Section 7.3.2, I draw on a
selection of statements to analyse the ways in which different actors have
brought bodies of norms in relation in ISDS.
51
See Chapter 1.
52
J. E. Alvarez, Boundaries of Investment Arbitration: The Use of Trade and European
Human Rights Law in Investor-State Disputes (Juris, 2018). Already in 1990, the AAPL
tribunal stated that an investment treaty ‘is not a self-contained closed legal system
limited to provide for substantive material rules of direct applicability, but it has to be
envisaged within a wider juridical context in which rules from other sources are inte-
grated through implied incorporation methods, or by direct reference to certain supple-
mentary rules, whether of international character or of domestic law nature’. Asian
Agricultural Products Ltd v. Republic of Sri Lanka, ICSID Case No ARB/87//3, Award,
27 June 1990, 21.
53
Steininger, ‘What’s Human Rights’; Alvarez, Boundaries of Investment Arbitration.
54
CMS Gas Transmission Co v. Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/01/8, Award,
12 May 2005.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
was the question of the ‘applicable law’.55 While the investor regarded the
BIT and international law as lex specialis, Argentina not only considered
its constitutional order relevant but also superior to the BIT. Drawing on
its constitution, public law and international customary rules on state of
necessity, Argentina said that obligations to safeguard constitutional
rights prevailed over its BIT commitments, including investor’s fair and
equitable treatment (FET) claims.56 Argentina situated and construed the
relation between the legalities at play within an order where constitu-
tional public law and human rights had primacy over investment treaties.
Drawing on a ‘more pragmatic and less doctrinaire’ approach and
‘taking the facts of the case and the arguments of the parties into
account’,57 the tribunal concurred with Argentina that both the inter-
national and the domestic legal orders applied to the dispute. It found ‘a
close interaction between the legislation and the regulations governing
the gas privatization, the Licence and international law, as embodied
both in the Treaty and in customary international law’.58 While the
tribunal emphasized that the multiple legalities were ‘inseparable’, it also
specified that they were to be applied ‘to the extent justified’.59 As a
consequence, the tribunal decided against Argentina that ‘while treaties
in theory could collide with the Constitution, in practice this is not very
likely’60 and ‘in this case, the tribunal does not find any such collision’
partly because ‘there is no question of affecting fundamental human
rights when considering the issues disputed by the parties’.61 The tribunal
highlighted that ‘the specific domestic legislation of Argentina and rules
of international law applied by the Tribunal will be discussed in connec-
tion with the issues contended’.62 By assigning a specific ‘role’ to domes-
tic and international law in relation to the ‘facts’ of the dispute, the
tribunal created distance between these legal orders. It insisted on
regarding the two laws as separate legal orders that could simultaneously
apply in the circumstances of the case, rather than creating a hierarchical
55
Ibid., para. 109.
56
Ibid., para. 114.
57
‘It is no longer the case of one prevailing over the other and excluding it altogether.
Rather both sources have a role to play’. Ibid., para. 116–18.
58
CMS Gas Transmission., above, para. 117.
59
Ibid., para. 117.
60
Ibid., para. 120.
61
Ibid., para. 121.
62
Ibid., para. 122.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
relation between them, as if the obligations owed to the investor and to
the Argentinian population could run in parallel.
63
Glamis Gold, Ltd. v. United States of America, ICSID, Award, 8 June 2009.
64
Ibid., para. 353.
65
Glamis Gold, Ltd. v. United States of America, ICSID, Non-party supplemental submis-
sion of the Quechan Indian Nation, 16 October 2006.
66
Glamis Gold, Ltd. v. United States of America, ICSID, Non-party supplemental
submission.
67
On the implications of this interpretative practice for the construction of relations with
human rights norms, see Hirsch, Invitation to the Sociology, p. 148.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Chapter 11 system’,68 the tribunal refused to ‘decide many of the most
controversial issues raised in this proceeding’69 and therefore did not
consider the multiplicity of laws that the Quechan people invoked.
Eventually, the tribunal dismissed the claims of the investor but also
disregarded the claims by the Quechan people by placing emphasis on its
‘case-specific mandate’ and on the ‘issues presented’ by the parties to the
dispute.70 The interpretation of investment treaty standards in the ‘con-
text’ of human rights norms was on display in the Suez case,71 in which
foreign investors brought claims against Argentina under three BITs.72 In
this case, investors’ rights to ‘full protection and security’ and ‘fair and
equitable treatment’ were pitched against Argentina’s human rights
obligations. While the investors deemed human rights ‘irrelevant’ to
the determination of whether the obligations under the BITs had been
breached,73 five NGOs brought the right to water and to life to bear in the
definition of the ‘applicable law’ for the ‘proper adjudication of the
dispute’ and for the ‘proper application’ of fair and equitable treatment
and indirect expropriation.74 They maintained that the case involved a
conflict between the state’s duty to protect the right to water and its
obligations to the investor75 and that the former norm prevailed over the
latter.76 They ordered the conflicting norms by invoking the requirement
‘not to interpret certain rules in isolation from other parts of the legal
order’.77 According to the NGOs, the interpretation of the BIT had to
take human rights law ‘into account’. Similarly, Argentina framed human
rights law as the ‘context’ in which the BIT standards had to be inter-
preted.78 The tribunal’s determination of the relative weight of the bodies
68
Glamis Gold, Ltd., Award, para. 3.
69
Ibid., para. 8.
70
Ibid., para. 8.
71
Suez, Sociedad General de Aguas de Barcelona S.A., and Vivendi Universal S.A. v. The
Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/03/19, Decision on Liability, 30 July 2010.
72
These were the Argentine–France BIT, the Argentine–Spain BIT and the Argentine–
UK BIT.
73
Suez, Decision on Liability, para. 255.
74
Centro de Estudios Legales y Sociales (‘CELS’) et al., ‘Amicus Curiae Submission in ICSID
Case No. ARB/03/19’ (2007).
75
On the background of the dispute see J. Calvert, ‘Civil Society and Investor–State Dispute
Settlement: Assessing the Social Dimensions of Investment Disputes in Latin America’
(2018) 23 New Political Economy 46–65.
76
Centro de Estudios Legales y Sociales (‘CELS’) et al., ‘Amicus Curiae’.
77
On this requirement as a type of overarching norm, see Chapter 1.
78
‘[I]n order to judge whether a treaty provision has been violated, for example the
provision on fair and equitable treatment’, the ‘Tribunal must take account of the context
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of norms at play was different from that of Argentina and the NGO. In
contrast to the Glamis tribunal, which had chosen to ignore the multipli-
city of laws, the Suez tribunal interpreted them as separate layers moving
in parallel directions and simultaneously applicable to the factual cir-
cumstances of the case.79 As a result, it insisted on keeping a great
distance between bodies of norms, which it perceived as separate and
independent legal units. This particular way of ordering bodies of norms
may indeed be read as a ‘general reluctance [. . .] to openly decide
potential conflicts between investment protection and public policy
objectives’.80
in which Argentina acted and that the human right to water informs that context’. See
Suez, Decision on Liability, para. 252.
79
‘[A]rgentina is subject to both international obligations, i.e. human rights and treaty
obligation, and must respect both of them equally’. Suez, Decision on Liability, para. 262.
80
J. E. Viñuales, Foreign Investment and the Environment in International Law (Cambridge
University Press, 2012), p. 155.
81
Hesham T. M. Al Warraq v. Republic of Indonesia, ICSID, Award, 15 December 2014. For
a commentary, see L. Cotula, ‘Human Rights and Investor Obligations in Investor-State
Arbitration: Hesham Talaat M. Al-Warraq v The Republic of Indonesia, UNCITRAL
Arbitration, Final Award, 15 December 2014 (Bernardo M. Cremades, Michael Hwang,
Fali S. Nariman)’ (2016) 17 The Journal of World Investment & Trade 148–57.
82
Agreement for the Promotion, Protection and Guarantee of Investment among Member
States of The Organization of the Islamic Conference.
83
Al-Warraq, Award, para. 519.
84
The European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR), the African Commission on
Human and People’s Rights and the Inter-American Court of Human Rights.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘basic rights’ and the fair and equitable treatment standard under the
OIC Agreement into relation.85
The tribunal concurred with the investor that certain civil and political
rights were part of investment protection norms, but it distanced the
notion of ‘basic rights’ under the OIC Agreement from human rights
norms by highlighting the particular ‘object and purpose’ of the former
(i.e. investment promotion and protection).86 However, the tribunal
construed greater proximity between the FET standard and the norm
against ‘denial of justice’ under various human rights instruments, in
particular article 14(3) of the ICCPR. Eventually, the tribunal decided
that ‘denial of justice constitutes a clear violation of the FET standard’.87
The tribunal brought ICCPR norms and the FET standard in relation
after claiming that ‘the ICCPR is now regarded as a part of “general
international law”’, which suggests that ‘general international law’ was
used as an ‘overarching norm’ to connect ICCPR norms to the invest-
ment legal order.88 The Urbaser dispute89 between foreign investors and
Argentina, related to a concession for water and sewage services under
the terms of the Spain–Argentina BIT, partly redefined the openness of
ISDS to human rights. The question of the relation between international
investment agreements and human rights emerged in the context of a
counterclaim by Argentina seeking compensation for damages from the
investor, which affected basic human rights.90 In contrast to the Suez
dispute, investors did not consider human rights ‘irrelevant’ but dis-
tanced them through interpretive practices. The investors claimed that
human rights were duties of the state rather than of private companies
and said that Argentina was under the ‘obligations regarding the
population’s right to water, and its obligations towards international
investors’, which ought to be fulfilled ‘simultaneously’,91 reflecting the
approach of the CMS and Suez awards. The investors also drew on the
precedent of the Biloune v. Ghana dispute, in which the tribunal decided
that ‘a ruling on human rights violations is outside the scope of its
85
Al-Warraq, Award, paras 177–82.
86
Ibid., paras 519–22.
87
Ibid., para. 621.
88
On this type of interface norm, see Chapter 1. For a similar observation in the context of
international trade law, see Chapter 8.
89
Urbaser S.A. and Consorcio de Aguas Bilbao Bizkaia, Bilbao Biskaia Ur Partzuergoa
v. The Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/07/26, Award, 8 December 2016.
90
Ibid., para. 1156.
91
Ibid., para. 694.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
jurisdiction’.92 While the investors emphasized the BIT, claiming that its
‘provisions, principles and rights’ were ‘essential to resolve the dispute’,
Argentina maintained that the ‘applicable law’ consisted of the ‘BIT,
Argentine law and general international law’ and that they ought to be
applied ‘jointly and harmoniously’.93 According to Argentina, the BIT
was not ‘a set of self-contained rules’ and therefore ‘international law in
general’ had to be applied, including ‘imperative international law’, which
trumped standards of investment protection.94 The Urbaser tribunal
responded to this situation of multiplicity by situating the legalities at
play within an overarching structure. It found that ‘the BIT does not
represent, in the view of the Contracting Parties and its clear text, a set of
rules defined in isolation without consideration given to rules of inter-
national law external to its own rules’.95 Drawing on the Tulip annulment
decision,96 the tribunal listed various international human rights instru-
ments followed by article 31(3)(c) of the VCLT and decided that ‘the BIT
cannot be interpreted and applied in a vacuum’ and that, while it ought
to be ‘mindful of the BIT’s special purpose as a Treaty promoting foreign
investments’, ‘it cannot do so without taking the relevant rules of inter-
national law into account. The BIT has to be construed in harmony with
other rules of international law of which it forms part, including those
relating to human rights’.97 Reliance on ‘overarching norms’, which the
tribunal implicitly construed by interpreting the provisions on applicable
92
‘[W]hile the acts alleged to violate the international human rights of Mr Biloune may be
relevant in considering the investment dispute under arbitration, this Tribunal lacks
jurisdiction to address, as an independent cause of action, a claim of violation of human
rights’. Antoine Biloune and Marine Drive Complex Ltd. v. Ghana Investment Centre and
the Government of Ghana, Awards of 27 October 1989 and 30 June 1990, Yearbook
Commercial Arbitration XIX (1994) p.11 (CUL-207). Cited in Urbaser., Award,
para. 1129.
93
Urbaser., Award, para. 548.
94
Ibid., para. 555.
95
Ibid., para. 1192.
96
In the Tulip case, the investor invoked art. 6 of the ECHR on the right to a fair trial.
Turkey, the respondent state, argued that the invoked provision was irrelevant in the
context of the dispute as the ECHR and the ICSID Convention belonged to two ‘different
regimes’. In the view of the Annulment Committee, human rights were relevant and ‘shall
be taken into account’ in light of Article 31(3)(c) of the ‘VCLT’. Tulip Real Estate and
Development Netherlands B.V. v. Republic of Turkey, ICSID Case no. ARB/11/28,
Decisions on Annulment, 30 December 2015, paras 86–92, where the ad hoc
Committee refers to the ‘principle of systemic integration’, stating that resort to author-
ities stemming from the field of human rights is a ‘legitimate method of
treaty interpretation’.
97
Urbaser, Award, para. 1200.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
law under article X(5) of the BIT and article 42 of ICSID Convention,
enabled the tribunal to place the BIT in ‘the overall system of inter-
national law’.98 Conflicting statements about the relation between inter-
national investment and human rights norms were brought forward in
the Bear Creek dispute,99 involving claims by a Canadian mining com-
pany investing in a mining project in Peru under the investment chapter
of the Canada–Peru Free Trade Agreement (FTA). The investment
project generated acute protests by affected Indigenous communities,
including the Aymara population, inhabiting the surrounding area and
demanding respect for their human rights. With regard to the applicable
law to the dispute, the investor and the state focused on the FTA and
applicable rules of international law.100 However, two civil society organ-
izations presented a description of the facts and of the law which
highlighted connections between the Aymara population’s Indigenous
rights and the FTA provisions.101 The two organizations argued that
Indigenous rights had to be taken into account when interpreting the
FTA.102 In his dissenting opinion, co-arbitrator Sands drew on the
Urbaser award to argue that consultation requirements in article 15 of
the International Labour Organization (ILO) Convention 169 were
part of the ‘applicable rules of international law’ which the tribunal
could ‘take into account’.103 By failing to carry out its obligations vis-à-
vis the Aymara peoples’ ‘rights under international law’, the investor
contributed to the demise of the investment. Consequently, the amount
of damages to be awarded was to be reduced by half.104 Although co-
arbitrator Sands’ dissenting opinion in Bear Creek and the award
in Urbaser placed a different degree of emphasis on human rights,105
98
Ibid., para. 1201.
99
Bear Creek Mining Corporation v. Republic of Peru, ICSID Case No. ARB/14/2, Award,
30 November 2017.
100
Ibid., paras 267–9.
101
The two organizations were the Association of Human Rights and the Environment-
Puno together with Mr. Carlos Lopez, and the Columbia Center on Sustainable
Investment (CCSI). Eventually, only the former organization was allowed to participate
as ‘other persons’ under the FTA whereas the latter’s application was rejected by the
tribunal.
102
The CCSI placed strong emphasis on legal relationships and on the relevance of the legal
context to the interpretation of the FTA. See CCSI, ‘Application to File a Written
Submission as an “Other Person” Pursuant to Article 836 and Annex 836’.
103
Bear Creek Mining Corporation v. Republic of Peru, ICSID Case No. ARB/14/2, Partial
Dissenting Opinion of Professor P. Sands, 30 November 2017, at 11.
104
Ibid., pp. 38–40.
105
I am indebted to Tomáš Morochovič for this observation.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
both statements strengthened the expectation that international
investment agreements cannot be interpreted in isolation from other
parts of the legal order.106 Claims about the primacy of human rights
over investment protection norms were formulated by the state in the
South American Silver dispute, related to an investment in mining activ-
ities in Bolivia under the terms of the United Kingdom–Bolivia BIT. The
dispute stemmed from measures adopted by Bolivia to protect
Indigenous communities inhabiting the areas surrounding the invest-
ment project. The parties to the dispute disagreed over the relation
between the BIT and international law and between the BIT and the
Bolivian national legal system. The investor deemed the BIT to be the
‘primary source of law and lex specialis, as supplemented by general
principles of law, as needed’.107 It distanced domestic law, arguing that
it did not form part of the ‘law applicable to the merits of the arbitration
proceeding’108 and contended that recourse to supplementary means to
interpret the BIT was ‘unnecessary’.109 By contrast, Bolivia demanded
that a wider body of norms be taken ‘in consideration’ when interpreting
the applicable law.110 The state said that its constitution and inter-
national norms on the protection of Indigenous rights111 were ‘supple-
mentary’ to the BIT and prevailed over norms in investment treaties in
case of conflict.112 The investor contested this representation, arguing
that the invoked rights could not be taken into consideration by the
tribunal since they were not binding on the United Kingdom and did not
constitute customary international law or general principles of law.113
Having identified the BIT as ‘the principal instrument’114 for resolving
the dispute, the tribunal found that the tool of ‘systemic interpretation’
under article 31(3)(c) of the VCLT is not limitless and must be applied
106
On this type of overarching norm, see Chapter 1.
107
South American Silver Limited v. Plurinational State of Bolivia, PCA Case No. 2013–15,
Award, 22 November 2018, para. 187.
108
Ibid., para.193.
109
Ibid., para. 261.
110
Ibid., para. 200.
111
Bolivia referred to the 1969 American Convention on Human Rights, the 1994 Inter-
American Convention on the Prevention, Punishment and Eradication of Violence
against Women, ILO Convention No.169, the 2007 United Nations Declaration on the
Rights of Indigenous Peoples and the Political Constitution of the Plurinational State of
Bolivia. Ibid., para. 199.
112
Ibid., para. 196.
113
Ibid., para. 190.
114
Ibid., para. 208.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
with caution.115 According to the tribunal, ‘this principle must be applied
in harmony with the rest of the provisions of the same article and
cautiously, in order to prevent the tribunal from exceeding its jurisdiction
and applying rules to the dispute which the Parties have not agreed to’.116
Eventually, the tribunal concluded that Bolivia had to pay compensation
and compound interests to the investor but dismissed all other claims of
the investor.
115
Ibid., para. 212.
116
Ibid., para. 216.
117
See Chapter 1, Section 1.4.
118
Langford and Behn, ‘Managing Backlash’.
119
E. Benvenisti, ‘Democracy Captured: The Mega-Regional Agreements and the Future of
Global Public Law’ (2016) 23 Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and
Democratic Theory 58–70.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
may lead to a greater variety of claims and forms of relation than the
status quo allows. Yet this is unlikely to lead to entanglements that would
be independent from the institutional and ideational structures of invest-
ment arbitration – enhanced participation would still operate within
structural constraints.
Indeed, the analysis of ISDS cases has also shown that the multiplicity
of laws was framed from the perspective of the dominant interpretive and
legal frames of reference in the investment arbitration context and in
conformity with the interface norms recognized within the ISDS ‘com-
munity of practice’.120 In particular, investment tribunals approached
multiplicity from the standpoint of international investment law by
relying on the principle of ‘systemic integration’ in article 31(3)(c) of
the VCLT.121 This principle was used to tie bodies of formal international
law that were recognized by actors as the relevant law. Through this
integrating principle of treaty interpretation, lawyers and arbitrators
connected international investment and human rights norms by situating
them within the ‘system’ of general international law as opposed to
framing them as two separate legal systems122 and ordering them
through ‘reception norms’.123 The dominant structures of relation
observed reflect the institutional background in which ISDS lawyers have
been trained and work.124 ISDS professionals’ mindsets and the ‘discur-
sive policies’125 in which they are situated may contribute to explaining
the particular modes of ordering multiplicity in ISDS. These situated
jurists seem to share a particular ‘way of thinking’ about the law of
foreign investment arbitration, which shapes the way they practice it in
relation to ‘foreign’ legalities.126 These actors operate in a professional
120
Brunnée and Toope, ‘Interactional International Law’.
121
J. Alvarez, ‘“Beware: Boundary Crossings” – A Critical Appraisal of Public Law
Approaches to International Investment Law’ (2016) 17 The Journal of World
Investment & Trade 171–228.
122
R. Michaels and J. Pauwelyn, ‘Conflict of Norms or Conflict of Laws: Different
Techniques in the Fragmentation of Public International Law’ (2012) 22 Duke Journal
of Comparative & International Law 349–76.
123
On reception norms, see Chapter 1; Michaels and Pauwelyn, ‘Conflict of Norms or
Conflict of Laws’.
124
On the institutional context of ICSID, see Pauwelyn, ‘The Rule of Law’. On the ‘invest-
ment arbitration culture’, see Hirsch, ‘The Sociological Dimension’.
125
Bianchi, ‘Epistemic Communities’, 588.
126
On how different ways of thinking about law impact legal practice, see A. Bianchi,
International Law Theories: An Inquiry into Different Ways of Thinking (Oxford
University Press, 2016). On the implications of actors’ situatedness for the construction
of entanglements, see Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
environment that does not create strong incentives to question the
dominant schemes for thinking and practising law, much less to depart
from them. For example, these specialists have to behave in conformity
with the rules of the game of the institutional site in which they oper-
ate127 in order to pursue or maintain reputation.128 These rules include
shared presuppositions about the nature of ‘international investment
law’, its ‘sources’, institutional circumstances and the ‘rituals’129 of inter-
national arbitration. According to the recognized norms of investment
arbitration, the rules on jurisdiction, applicable laws and consent of the
parties have narrowed the space for linking bodies of norms in prac-
tice.130 For example, the doctrine of the limitation of tribunals’ jurisdic-
tion131 to ‘investment disputes’ has enabled adjudicators to create
distance between bodies of norms and strengthen the autonomy of their
legal order from the interference of competing legalities. Similarly, inter-
national investment lawyers perceive that there must be ‘legal grounds’
for tribunals to consider human rights norms.132 ISDS insiders may
benefit from the dominant mode of ordering legalities in this setting –
therefore there seem to be fewer incentives to change the status quo than
to maintain it.
In summary, the dominant interests, institutional structures and ‘legal
culture’133 in ISDS seem to have influenced the way situated actors have
ordered multiplicity in that setting. However, ultimate conclusions on the
implications of actors’ ideational context and strategic interests for the
particular forms of enmeshment observed seem premature. For example,
it is not clear whether investment arbitrators’ background had more
influence than the material incentives associated with the international
investment dispute settlement culture.134 Not only did arbitrators with
expertise in public international law decide in favour of foreign investors
in some cases, they also kept investment protection and human rights
127
Pauwelyn, ‘The Rule of Law’.
128
Schultz, ‘Arbitral Decision-Making’.
129
Gaillard, ‘Sociology of International Arbitration’.
130
On these rules, see Sornarajah, The International Law.
131
F. Balcerzak, ‘Jurisdiction of Tribunals in Investor–State Arbitration and the Issue of
Human Rights’ (2014) 29 ICSID Review 216–30.
132
F. G. Santacroce, ‘The Applicability of Human Rights Law in International Investment
Disputes’ (2019) 34 ICSID Review – Foreign Investment Law Journal 136–55.
133
Hirsch, Invitation to the Sociology, p. 146.
134
R. Howse, ‘Venus, Mars, and Brussels: Legitimacy and Dispute Settlement Culture in
Investment Law and WTO Law: A Response to Joost Pauwelyn’ (2015) 109 AJIL
Unbound 309–15.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
norms at a great distance from each other, against our expectations.135
This finding suggests that arbitrators’ proficiency in public international
law and human rights law would not automatically translate into an
outcome where the distance between bodies of norms is reduced, as
other factors may be simultaneously at play. For example, arbitrators’
interests, including reappointment as arbitrator, may have had greater
impact in shaping arbitrators’ decision-making. They may have created
proximity or distance between bodies of norms to pursue their own goals.
In this respect, the potentially ‘addictive’136 practice of investment arbi-
tration and the high financial stakes involved in it may have played a
greater role than, or at least interplayed with, the legal background of its
participants in the formation of relations between bodies of norms. From
this perspective, to ‘properly train’ the future operators of ISDS137 may
indeed be necessary but perhaps not enough.
135
For example, in the CMS dispute.
136
Howse, ‘Venus, Mars, and Brussels’.
137
J. Viñuales, ‘Foreign Investment and the Environment in International Law: Current
Trends’, in K. Miles (ed.), Research Handbook on Environment and Investment Law
(Edward Elgar, 2019), pp. 12–37.
138
Langford and Behn, ‘Managing Backlash’, 554–8.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
and investment dispute settlement. The reform process could pave the
way for greater civil society input than the status quo allows, thereby
creating room for closer proximity with other legalities. In this context,
struggles for change within and from international investment law are
situated at multiple sites and involve different actors with competing
interests and approaches to reform.
139
M. Langford, D. Behn and O. Fauchald, ‘Backlash and State Strategies in International
Investment Law’, in T. Aalberts and T. Gammeltoft-Hansen (eds), The Changing
Practices of International Law (Cambridge University Press, 2018), pp. 70–102.
140
The 2012 US Model BIT mentions in a relatively open-ended way the interface between
‘investment and the environment’ (art. 12) and ‘investment and labor’ (art. 13); the New
Zealand–Australia BIT, refers to the Treaty of Waitangi; the 2015 Norwegian Model BIT
refers to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights; the 2016 BIT between Morocco
and Nigeria imposes human rights obligations on investors too (art. 18). N. Zugliani,
‘Human Rights in International Investment Law: The 2016 Morocco–Nigeria Bilateral
Investment Treaty’ (2019) 68 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 761–70.
141
C. Titi, ‘International Investment Law and the European Union: Towards a New
Generation of International Investment Agreements’ (2015) 26 European Journal of
International Law 639–61.
142
Article 7(5) states: ‘[t]he Contracting Parties express their commitment to the inter-
national framework on Business and Human Rights, such as the United Nations Guiding
Principles on Business and Human Rights and the OECD Guidelines for Multinational
Enterprises, and commit to strengthen this framework’. For a commentary, see K.
Duggal and L. van de Ven, ‘The 2019 Netherlands Model BIT: Riding the New
Investment Treaty Waves’ (2019) 35 Arbitration International 343–74.
143
L. W. Mouyal, International Investment Law and the Right to Regulate: A Human Rights
Perspective (Routledge, 2016).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The Comprehensive Economic Trade Agreement (CETA) between the
EU and Canada has brought together investment protection, trade and
sustainable development and labour and environmental protection
norms, and article 8.9 of its investment protection chapter reaffirms state
parties’ ‘right to regulate’.144 Similar lawmaking practices, driven in
particular by the interests of economically powerful countries, include
‘mega-regulation’ instruments like the Trans-Pacific Partnership that has
incorporated environmental and labour norms, perhaps to address
demands by civil society actors concerned with the impact of ISDS on
social and environmental protection within domestic legal systems.145
Therefore, processes of investment treaty negotiations, especially if trans-
parent and open to the participation of affected stakeholders,146 are
potentially effective arenas for reshaping entanglements through textual
references.
Yet, we should not read too much into these references as they tell us
little about how relations with other, competing polities and their legal
orders ought to be ordered.147 On the one hand, their relationship
remains formally open and its shape will be determined only through
political processes and the practice of societal actors. On the other hand,
those references do not reflect the more contestatory claims of actors who
challenge the very existence of international investment protection.
While those provisions may enable linkages with ‘community interests’,148
it remains to be seen how the relevant decision-makers will weigh bodies
of norms in practice. Under current structural circumstances in ISDS,
144
Joint Interpretative Instrument on the Comprehensive Economic and Trade Agreement
(CETA) between Canada and the European Union and Its Member States, 2017.
145
E. Meidinger, ‘TPP and Environmental Regulation’, in B. Kingsbury et al. (eds),
Megaregulation Contested (Oxford University Press, 2019), pp. 175–95.
146
Benvenisti, ‘Democracy Captured’.
147
Similarly, references to international investment law in human rights instruments
provide little guidance in this respect. Principle 9 of the UN Guiding Principles on
Business and Human Rights expects state parties to investment agreements to ‘maintain
adequate domestic policy space to meet their human rights obligations’. The
Commentary to this article is not very helpful either in its explanation that: ‘States
should ensure that they retain adequate policy and regulatory ability to protect human
rights under the terms of such agreements, while providing the necessary investor
protection.’ OHCHR, ‘Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights:
Implementing the United Nations “Protect, Respect and Remedy” Framework’ (United
Nations, 2011).
148
S. Schill and V. Djanic, ‘International Investment Law and Community Interests’, in E.
Benvenisti and G. Nolte (eds), Community Interests Across International Law (Oxford
University Press, 2018), pp. 122–48.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
characterized by a substantial preference for ‘stronger rather than weaker
investor protection’149 and under-inclusiveness of relevant actors, a con-
crete change from dominant ways of dealing with multiplicity seems
unlikely. Future practice might tell us more about the interface norms
at play, and much is likely to depend on who the actors construing them
will be. However, efforts at rewriting investment treaties may be seen as
attempts to respond to growing voices of contestation stemming from
other sites in the overall order.
149
Mattias Kumm has argued that one general presupposition of these actors is to favour
‘stronger, rather than weaker investor protection’. See ‘An Empire of Capital?
Transatlantic Investment Protection as the Institutionalization of Unjustified Privilege’,
Verfassungsblog (27 May 2015), https://verfassungsblog.de/an-empire-of-capital-transat
lantic-investment-protection-as-the-institutionalization-of-unjustified-privilege/.
150
Sawhoyamaxa Indigenous Community v. Paraguay, Judgment (Merits, Reparations and
Costs), 29 March 2006.
151
Ibid., para. 115.
152
Ibid., para. 140.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Cançado Trindade, the court’s interpretation reflected a strong commit-
ment to human rights law.
Similarly, the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for
Human Rights (OHCHR) has approached investment agreements
through ‘overarching norms’, reflecting a conception of order under
international law where human rights are accorded primacy.153 For
example, the former independent expert on the promotion of a demo-
cratic and equitable international order has claimed that ‘in case of
conflict, only the highest public courts can decide in the light of the
totality of international law. Until amended by States Members, the
Charter of the United Nations remains the principal treaty that deter-
mines the structure and functioning of the international order.’154
Therefore ‘[s]tates must ensure that all trade and investment agreements
recognize the primacy of human rights and specify that, in case of
conflict, human rights obligations prevail’.155 In the eyes of the independ-
ent expert, international investment norms and human rights were to be
integrated within a hierarchical form ordered through the principle of
binding character of treaties, good faith and in conformity with article
103 of the United Nations Charter.156
In its General Comment 24, the UN Committee on Economic, Social
and Cultural Rights articulated a similar hierarchical conception of order
between competing legalities.157 The Committee claimed that: ‘[s]tates
parties should identify any potential conflict between their obligations
under the Covenant and under trade or investment treaties, and refrain
from entering into such treaties where such conflicts are found to exist, as
required under the principle of the binding character of treaties’.158 The
group of experts distinguished ‘investment treaties currently in force’
from ‘future treaties’. In the first case, interpretation ‘should take into
153
See Chapter 1.
154
OHCHR, ‘Report of the Independent Expert on the Promotion of a Democratic and
Equitable International Order, Alfred-Maurice de Zayas’ (2015) UN Doc. A/HRC/30/44.
155
OHCHR, ‘Report of the Independent Expert’, 20.
156
‘[P]acta sunt servanda requires States to fulfil their human rights treaty obligations in
good faith and prohibits them from entering into agreements that would delay, circum-
vent, undermine or make impossible the fulfilment of their human rights treaty obliga-
tions’. OHCHR, ‘Report of the Independent Expert’, para. 18.
157
Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (CESCR), ‘General Comment
No. 24 (2017) on State Obligations under the International Covenant on Economic,
Social and Cultural Rights in the Context of Business Activities’ (2017), UN Doc E/C.12/
GC/24.
158
CESCR, ‘General Comment No. 24’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
account the human rights obligations of the state, consistent with Article
103 of the Charter of the United Nations and with the specific nature of
human rights obligations’.159 In the second case, ‘[states parties] are
encouraged to insert, in future treaties, a provision explicitly referring
to their human rights obligations, and to ensure that mechanisms for the
settlement of investor–state disputes take human rights into account in
the interpretation of investment treaties or of investment chapters in
trade agreements’.160 The Committee’s stance towards the investment
protection suborder reproduced the Inter-American Court of Human
Rights’ approach discussed in Section 7.4.3.
Over time, human rights specialists have combined ‘overarching norms’
with less imposing practices aimed at persuading states to take account of
their human rights obligations when making new investment agreements.
One example is the 2018 initiative ‘Crowd-Drafting: Designing a Human
Rights-Compatible International Investment Agreement’.161 Its promoters
referred to a ‘human rights-based approach’ to international investment
treaty-making.162 Attempts at crafting a ‘human rights impact assessment’
norm, addressed both at states parties to international investment agree-
ments163 as well as companies as part of their due diligence obligations, fall
within these accommodation strategies.164 The United Nations Conference
on Trade and Development’s (UNCTAD) initiatives to investment law
reform have adopted a similar approach, seeking to promote greater
convergence with human rights and sustainable development norms, as
exemplified by the UNCTAD’s Investment Policy Framework for
Sustainable Development.165 Most recently, overarching norms seem to
159
Ibid.
160
Ibid.
161
See www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Business/Forum2018CrowdDrafting.pdf.
162
‘[A] human rights-based approach to trade and investment entails considering how
States’ obligations under trade/investment law agreements might impact on their ability
to fulfil their human rights obligations’, see further at: www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/
Globalization/Pages/GlobalizationIndex.aspx.
163
UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on the Right to Food, Olivier De Schutter.
Addendum, Guiding Principles on Human Rights Impact Assessments of Trade and
Investment Agreements’ (2011) UN Doc. A/HRC/19/59/Add.5.
164
Columbia Center on Sustainable Development and OHCHR, ‘Impacts of the
International Investment Regime on Access to Justice’ (Roundtable outcome document,
September 2018).
165
P. Muchlinski, ‘Negotiating New Generation International Investment Agreements: New
Sustainable Development Oriented Initiatives’, in S. Hindelang and M. Krajewski (eds),
Shifting Paradigms in International Investment Law (Oxford University Press, 2016),
pp. 41–64.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
have informed the ongoing struggle for a new international ‘instrument’
on global business and human rights, as reflected in particular in article
14 of its second revised draft, which demands that investment agreements
be consistent ‘with international law principles and instruments’.166
166
OEIGWG Chairmanship ‘Second Revised Draft, Legally Binding Instrument’.
167
S. Randeria, ‘The State of Globalization: Legal Plurality, Overlapping Sovereignties and
Ambiguous Alliances between Civil Society and the Cunning State in India’ (2007) 24
Theory, Culture & Society 1–33.
168
B. Rajagopal, ‘The Role of Law in Counter-Hegemonic Globalization and Global Legal
Pluralism: Lessons from the Narmada Valley Struggle in India’ (2005) 18 Leiden Journal
of International Law 345–87.
169
B. Rajagopal, ‘Counter-Hegemonic International Law: Rethinking Human Rights and
Development as a Third World Strategy’ (2006) 27 Third World Quarterly 767–83.
170
There have been calls to give more attention to these ‘invisible’ actors. See N. Perrone,
‘The “Invisible” Local Communities: Foreign Investor Obligations, Inclusiveness, and
the International Investment Regime’ (2019) 113 AJIL Unbound 16–21.
171
J. Rone, ‘Contested International Agreements, Contested National Politics: How the
Radical Left and the Radical Right Opposed TTIP in Four European Countries’ (2018) 6
London Review of International Law 233–53. See also M. Kumm, ‘An Empire of
Capital?’; Legal Statement on Investment Protection and Investor–State Dispute
Settlement Mechanisms in TTIP and CETA, 2016.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
proposal to replace ISDS with a multilateral investment court might open
a space for a wider number of actors to create different forms of relations
with human rights.172 The Court of Justice of the European Union
(CJEU) has recently shown a sign of resistance to investor–state arbitra-
tion by ruling that the ISDS provision in BITs between EU member states
is ‘not compatible’ with EU law.173 By contrast, in its recent ‘CETA
Opinion’, the CJEU has shown more openness to the prospect of an
investment court system.174
In the context of ISDS reform, currently under the auspices of
UNCITRAL Working Group III, the debate has focused on procedural
and institutional design issues rather than on questions about the rela-
tions between investment protection and other substantive norms.175
However, some states and international institutions have emphasized
connections with human rights, too. For example, in a letter addressed
to participants in the ISDS reform process, human rights experts have
highlighted that international investment agreements are often incom-
patible with international human rights law and the rule of law.176 They
called for a ‘fundamental systemic change’ of ISDS, beyond procedural
reform, and towards a ‘multilateral system’ that ‘takes into account the
rights and obligations of investors and states, in line with all applicable
international laws and standards concerning human rights’.177 They also
claimed that greater proximity to human rights and the Sustainable
Development Goals would enhance the legitimacy and effectiveness of
172
Robert Howse has concluded that ‘a multilateral court system is best suited to offering
standing or intervention to a wide range of actors who have concerns of international
justice that relate to foreign investment’. See R. Howse, ‘International Investment Law
and Arbitration: A Conceptual Framework’ (2017) IILJ Working Paper 2017/1 MegaReg
Series 69.
173
The Court ruled that EU law precludes: ‘a provision in an international agreement
concluded between Member States [. . .] under which an investor from one of those
Member States may, in the event of a dispute concerning investments in the other
Member State, bring proceedings against the latter Member State before an arbitral
tribunal whose jurisdiction that Member State has undertaken to accept’. Judgment in
Slovak Republic v. Achmea B.V. (Case C-284/16).
174
The Court found that the international investment system is compatible with EU law.
See Opinion 1/17 of the Court (Full Court) (CETA Opinion), 30 April 2019.
175
On different states’ approaches to ISDS reform, see A. Roberts, ‘Incremental, Systemic,
and Paradigmatic Reform of Investor–State Arbitration’ (2018) 112 American Journal of
International Law 410–32.
176
OHCHR, ‘Letter to the UNCITRAL Working Group III on ISDS Reform, Urging
Systemic Changes to the ISDS System’ (7 March 2019).
177
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the UNCITRAL process.178 The government of South Africa has also
strongly advocated to take account of human rights and the principle of
sustainable development.179
7.5 Conclusion
This chapter has analysed how relations between international invest-
ment and human rights norms have been construed in multiple global
governance sites. Investment treaty arbitration has remained a central
arena where foreign investors, states, investment adjudicators and NGOs
have supplied competing forms of relation between bodies of norms,
especially when defining the law applicable to the dispute. These relations
have reflected the preferences and the ideational context of the actors
involved in their construction.
In the majority of cases examined, the claims of investment arbitrators,
investors and states have been given greater consideration than the
claims by NGOs and the public at large, limiting room for contestation.
Foreign investors have sought to narrow the scope of relevant bodies of
norms whereas states and NGOs have aimed at expanding it. Over time,
ISDS participants, and investment adjudicators in particular, have tended
to regard relations with human rights norms with less hesitancy.
Although the decisions of investment tribunals affect many constitu-
encies, possibilities for these affected outsiders to make their claims heard
in investment arbitration have been limited. Their priorities have often
been silenced in sites of investment treaty negotiation too.
The analysis has observed an evolution in the way actors have dealt
with human rights in ISDS over time, although dialectic tendencies of
proximity and distancing persist. Initially, foreign investors adopted a
clear rhetoric against the relevance of human rights in ISDS. In a second
phase, they recognized their relevance but they kept them at a distance to
downplay any potential conflict with investment protection standards. As
states began to refer to human rights norms in their defences, investment
tribunals had to find ways to articulate relations with them. The current
phase seems marked by a very limited reliance on human rights on the
part of investors and tribunals and more frequent linkages construed by
178
Ibid.
179
United Nations Commission on International Trade Law et al., ‘Possible Reform of
Investor–State Dispute Settlement (ISDS) Submission from the Government of South
Africa’ (2019) UN Doc A/CN.9/WG.III/WP.176.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
states and NGOs, thereby creating entanglement on a rhetorical level but
one constantly undercut by using other tools to create distance. In most
of the cases examined, ISDS participants have used ‘overarching norms’
to order legal pluralism within international law, which may be explained
by reference to the cultural and institutional context of ISDS. However,
the dominant use of this ‘interface norm’ has not led to a new, fully
integrated system as considerable contestation persists in other parts of
the legal order. Indeed, forms and dynamics of entanglement have
become observable in struggles ‘at the margins’ of and beyond the
bounds of ISDS. These forms of contestation have led to a process of
reform of international investment agreements and investment adjudi-
cation that may create room for shaping new forms of relations with
human rights. However, only the future practice of actors will tell us how
they will be construed. In the different contexts examined, the practice of
taking other norms ‘into account’ has been one of the main tools for
ordering multiplicity, yet without determining the substantive outcome
of the practice of giving regard to other bodies of norms. Even when
using this interface norm, ISDS participants have had discretion to
determine the relative weight of the legalities brought together. Human
rights actors have also had recourse to a similar interface norm when
articulating their views of the relation with investment agreement, but
their vision of legal order differs from the one put forward in the practice
of investment arbitration.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
8
8.1 Introduction
Ever since the inception of the contemporary globalized trade regime,
environmental concerns found their way into the regulatory system
framed by international trade law. The interaction (and tension) between
trade and environmental interests further intensified with the develop-
ment of international environmental law, and global trade was placed
under the scrutiny of two overlapping regulatory regimes which are
commonly perceived as having diverging aims and rationales.
A pronounced outlet for this relationship was found within the World
Trade Organization (WTO) system, particularly in trade disputes in
which WTO rules interacted with public policies seeking to address
environmental externalities. This chapter explores the way in which the
relationship between international trade law and norms governing envir-
onmental protection are construed from within the WTO dispute settle-
ment system. The findings shine a light on evolving forms of legal
entanglement that challenge the dominant perception of the WTO as
an insular regime prima facie hostile to international environmental law.
Surprisingly, the analysis shows that even in controversial trade environ-
ment disputes (e.g. infamously Tuna Dolphin I), all parties to the dispute
routinely refer to norms of international environmental law to make their
respective claims. With respect to the Panels and the Appellate Body, the
findings indicate that external environmental norms are allowed to
penetrate WTO law more often than commonly assumed, although such
linkages do not necessarily result in more ‘environmentally friendly’
interpretations/applications of trade law. Moreover, without centralized
coordination, WTO judicial bodies tend to construe the relationship with
outside norms in an ad hoc and discretionary way, relying on ‘interface
norms’ to invoke external rules of international environmental law on a
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
case-by-case basis, while keeping them formally at bay. Although the
mechanisms of relationing employed by the WTO judicial bodies may
seem unprincipled at first glance, an analysis over time reveals how the
Panels and the Appellate Body repeatedly emphasize certain attributes in
their treatment of outside norms (such as multilateralism, inclusiveness
and consensus), and have allowed for more progressive interpretations to
evolve over time (through so-called irritative norm conflict).
1
W. Steffen, W. Broadgate, L. Deutsch, O. Gaffney and C. Ludwig, ‘The Trajectory of the
Anthropocene: The Great Acceleration’ (2015) 2 The Anthropocene Review 81–98.
2
E. B. Weiss, ‘The Evolution of International Environmental Law’ (2011) 54 Japanese
Yearbook of International Law 1–27, at 2.
3
Ibid., 12.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
Rio Declaration, for example, emphasizes the importance of ‘an open
international economic system’ and states that ‘[t]rade policy measures
for environmental purposes should not constitute a means of arbitrary or
unjustifiable discrimination or a disguised restriction on international
trade’, which is almost a word-for-word copy of the chapeau of GATT
Article XX.4 Notably, the same wording is reproduced in Article 3(5) of
the UNFCCC.5 Thus, international environmental law was actively
entangled with the body of norms that governs the multilateral
trading system.
From within the trade law sphere, efforts at legal entanglement with
international environmental law were more tentative. While a reference
to sustainable development was included in the preamble to the
Marrakesh Agreement establishing the WTO (1994), the 1947 GATT
was incorporated wholesale into the new WTO Agreement, with no
changes or additions to the environmental provisions of the original text
indicating how WTO law should relate to international environmental
law. This was problematic because a host of new multilateral environ-
mental agreements (MEAs) had sprung up since 1947, some of which
explicitly relied on potentially GATT-inconsistent trade measures for
their implementation (e.g. the Basel Convention and the Montreal
Protocol).6 Further, the extent to which WTO rules restricted national
environmental policy space also remained unclear, particularly in rela-
tion to environmental measures targeting processing and production
methods (PPMs) and the applicability of the precautionary principle.7
The lack of relationing can be explained by GATT signatories’ diver-
ging interests with regard to trade and environment concerns at the time
(and still prevailing today). While developed countries supported the
integration of environmental standards into international trade policy
to counter ‘environmental dumping’, developing countries resisted,
fearing market access restrictions due to ‘green protectionism’.8 Thus, a
meaningful debate for greater integration of environmental concerns
within the trade regime was ‘out of the question’. Politically, the
4
United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, ‘Rio Declaration on
Environment and Development’ (New York, 1992), Principle 12.
5
UNEP, ‘United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC)’ (1992).
6
A. Tancredi, ‘Trade and Inter-Legality’, in J. Klabbers and G. Palombella (eds), The
Challenge of Inter-legality (Cambridge University Press, 2019), pp. 158–87, at p. 159.
7
T. Santarius, H. Dalkmann, M. Steigenberger and K. Vogelpohl, ‘Balancing Trade and
Environment: An Ecological Reform of the WTO’, Wuppertal Papers (2004), p. 63.
8
Ibid., p. 10.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘environmental critique [also] came at an awkward time for GATT
signatories since the Uruguay Round entered a deep crisis in the early
1990s, and the agricultural dispute between the USA and the EU
threatened to scupper talks’.9 Thus, an opportunity for entanglement –
or at least clarification – between the two bodies of norms was missed.
This state of affairs was supposed to be remedied in the subsequent Doha
Round of trade negotiations, which gave members a mandate to negotiate
the relationship between WTO rules and specific trade obligations set out
in MEAs.10 The talks failed however (they were finally abandoned in
2015),11 and thus a second opportunity for ‘enhancing mutual support-
iveness’ was missed. Instead, it became incumbent upon the dispute
settlement bodies to mediate the relationship between free trade and
environmental protection (and, by extension, the ‘clash of interests’
between developed and developing countries).
9
Ibid., p. 10.
10
WTO, ‘WTO Ministerial Declaration Adopted on 14 November 2001’ (20 November
2001) WT/MIN(01)/DEC/1, para. 31.
11
R. Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years on: Global Governance by Judiciary’
(2016) 27 European Journal of International Law 9–77.
12
G. Marceau, ‘The Primacy of the WTO Dispute Settlement Mechanism’ (2015) 23
Questions of International Law 3–13, at 4.
13
Article 2(1) of the WTO DSU on Rules and Procedures Governing the Settlement of
Disputes, Marrakesh Agreement Establishing the World Trade Organization, Annex 2,
1869 U.N.T.S. 401, 33 I.L.M. 1226 (1994).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
relationship between WTO law and external norms raises the question of
whether (and to what extent) international law not contained in the
covered agreements is applicable in WTO dispute settlement.
While the majority of scholars maintain a restrictive view regarding
the extent to which other norms of international law may influence the
interpretation and application of WTO law,14 others have pointed out
that the DSU does not contain an explicit limitation with regard to the
applicable law.15 The distinction between the jurisdiction of the WTO
DSB and applicable law in WTO dispute settlement is relevant here.16
While the jurisdiction of the WTO DSB is restricted to disputes arising
out of the covered agreements,17 WTO law contains no explicit provision
which identifies or restricts the law that should apply to the disputes.18
Thus, international law from all sources is potentially applicable as WTO
law. Such a reading seems to be supported by the Panel in Korea-
Government Procurement, which held that ‘Customary international
law applies generally to the economic relations between the WTO
Members [. . .] to the extent that the WTO treaty agreements do not
“contract out” from it.’19 The Panel saw no basis ‘for arguing that the
terms of reference [set out in the DSU] are meant to exclude reference to
14
G. Z. Marceau, ‘A Call for Coherence in International Law’ (1999) 33 Journal of World
Trade 87–152; J. P. Trachtman, ‘The Domain of WTO Dispute Resolution’ (1999) 40
Harvard International Law Journal 333–77; G. Z. Marceau, ‘Conflicts of Norms and
Conflicts of Jurisdictions, the Relationship between the WTO Agreement and Meas and
Other Treaties’ (2001) 35 Journal of World Trade 1081–131, at 1116.
15
J. Pauwelyn, Conflict of Norms in Public International Law: How WTO Law Relates to
Other Rules of International Law (Cambridge University Press, 2003), p. 460. Pauwelyn
argues that the applicable law before a WTO panel is limited only by four factors: the
claims that can be brought to a WTO panel; the defences invoked by the defending party;
the scope of the relevant rules ratione materiae, ratione personae and ratione temporis;
and any conflict rules in the WTO treaty, general international law and other non-WTO
treaties.
16
Ibid., p. 460.
17
Articles 1(1), 3(2), 7(1) and 11 of the DSU.
18
L. Bartels, ‘Applicable Law in WTO Dispute Settlement Proceedings’ (2001) 35 Journal of
World Trade 499–519, at 504 et seq. Article 7 of the DSU, for example, has been used to
justify both closed and open positions with regard to the applicable law in WTO dispute
settlement procedures – although the provision itself is rather ambiguous. Indeed, while
Article 7 requires Panels to examine disputes ‘in light of’ relevant provisions in the
covered agreements, and to address relevant provisions in any covered agreement cited
by the parties to the dispute, it does not prevent Panels from addressing other sources of
law in the course of deciding the dispute.
19
Korea – Measures Affecting Government Procurement (2000) WTO Doc. WT/DS163/R,
para. 7.96.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the broader rules of customary international law’.20 There is no reason to
assume why the same logic should not also apply with regard to the
external rules of treaty law (applicable between the parties).
The degree to which ‘external’ international law has a bearing on
WTO law is thus largely up to the discretion of the WTO dispute
settlement bodies. However, the Panels and the Appellate Body are
viewed as having made insufficient use of this flexibility,21 and have been
criticized for creating ‘a value hierarchy that [favours] trade over envir-
onmental concerns and [operates] as a barrier to the integration of
environmental considerations into the law of the GATT/WTO’.22 Thus,
the dominant perception of international trade law is of a distinct legal
system that is bounded, rigid and hostile to environmental norms and
considerations. The following account of irritative norm conflict compli-
cates this picture.
20
Ibid., para. 7.101.
21
Tancredi, ‘Trade and Inter-Legality’.
22
O. Perez, Ecological Sensitivity and Global Legal Pluralism: Rethinking the Trade and
Environment Conflict (Hart Publishing, 2004), p. 51.
23
Trachtman, ‘The Domain of WTO Dispute Resolution’.
24
M. Jeffery, ‘Environmental Imperatives in a Globalized World: The Ecological Impact of
Liberalizing Trade’ (2007) 7 Macquarie Law Journal 25–52, at 29.
25
J. P. Trachtman, ‘WTO Trade and Environment Jurisprudence: Avoiding Environmental
Catastrophe’ (2017) 58 Harvard International Law Journal 273–310.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
Disputes brought before the WTO DSB constitute important historical
‘flashpoints’ for the study of legal entanglement, as they galvanize actors
to formulate claims about the relationship between international trade
law and other bodies of norms in legal terms.
26
United States – Restrictions on Imports of Tuna – Report of the GATT Panel,
(3 September 1991) DS21/R (unadopted) (‘Tuna Dolphin I’).
27
United States – Restrictions on Imports of Tuna – Report of the GATT Panel, (16 June
1994), DS29/R (unadopted) (‘Tuna Dolphin II’).
28
Tuna Dolphin I Panel report, para. 3.49.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
that CITES ‘did not include in its Appendix I list of species in danger of
extinction any of the species of dolphins which the United States was
claiming to protect’.29
The Panel, finding a violation of the GATT’s substantive provisions
(relating to quantitative restrictions and non-discrimination), turned to
the environmental exceptions contained in GATT Article XX. In a fateful
decision, the Panel interpreted a purely domestic scope to Article XX and
ruled that its exceptions could not be invoked to justify extraterritorial
measures.30 Trade restrictions in response to other countries’ environ-
mental policies or practices were per se inconsistent with the GATT.31
However, the Panel proceeded to argue that even if the GATT permitted
extraterritorial protection of life and health, the United States had to first
exhaust all GATT-consistent measures available to it, in particular
through the negotiation of international cooperative agreements.32 This
reasoning already hints at a general (though still implicit) understanding
that environmental measures should be based on multilateral consensus
in order to be taken into account by the WTO DSB/within the GATT
framework, a notion that was further developed in subsequent case law.
Ultimately, the Panel ruled in favour of Mexico, concluding that the
US trade embargo was inconsistent with the GATT and not justified
under Article XX. Crucially, the Panel also set up the ‘infamous product/
process distinction’ – prompting a debate that continues to this day – by
ruling that the US was not allowed to embargo tuna products from
Mexico based on the way tuna was produced.33 The Panel took a more
environmentally favourable stance with regard to the ‘dolphin-safe’ label,
ruling that it did not violate the GATT ‘because the labelling regulations
governing the tuna caught in the ETP [. . .] applied to all countries whose
vessels fished in this geographical area and thus did not distinguish
between products originating in Mexico and products originating in
other countries’.34 Notably, this measure became subject to a subsequent
29
Ibid., para. 3.44.
30
Tuna Dolphin I Panel report, para. 5.28.
31
Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 36. The rulings in Tuna Dolphin I
and II are widely regarded as having no textual basis in the GATT but to have been
informed instead by ‘some intuitive notion that allowing trade measures to address global
environmental externalities was somehow countenancing the slippery slope towards
unconstrained green protectionism’.
32
Tuna Dolphin I Panel report, para. 5.28.
33
Ibid., para. 5.12 – 5.15. Also see Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 37.
34
Tuna Dolphin I Panel report, para. 5.43–5.44.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
dispute brought by Mexico in 2008, in US-Tuna II. The Panel reports in
Tuna Dolphin I (1991) and II (1994) were never adopted due to the
consensus requirement under old GATT dispute settlement rules.35
8.3.1.3 Aftermath
Although the report remained unadopted, the Panel’s reasoning in Tuna
Dolphin I generated widespread ‘controversy over the capacity of the
multilateral trading system to accommodate legitimate environmental
concerns’.36 The United States, arguably one of the most powerful
‘shapers’ of the GATT/WTO legal regime, threatened to push for amend-
ments to the GATT in light of international environmental objectives.37
Proposals made towards this endeavour included a new ‘Environmental
Code’ as a side agreement to the GATT and establishing an international
tradeable pollution allowance system (similar to what was later instituted
in the Kyoto Protocol) under the auspices of the GATT.38 Although
neither of the Tuna Dolphin I and II Panels’ reports were ever adopted
and they retained little to no legal value following subsequent Appellate
Body rulings, they significantly contributed to the perception of WTO
insularity in relation to global environmental concerns.39
8.3.2 Shrimp-Turtle
8.3.2.1 Overview
The legal outcome of the Shrimp-Turtle dispute was seen by many
environmentalists as a breakthrough in the trade environment debate,
indicating a more environmentally friendly interpretation of WTO law
35
The new WTO dispute settlement mechanism instituted a reverse consensus rule, making
the adoption of post 1994 panel reports virtually automatic.
36
World Trade Organization, CITES and the WTO: Enhancing Cooperation for Sustainable
Development (WTO, 2015) p. 3.
37
T. E. Skilton, ‘GATT and the Environment in Conflict: The Tuna-Dolphin Dispute and
the Quest for an International Conservation Strategy’ (1993) 26 Cornell International
Law Journal 455–94. The US House of Representatives promptly passed a resolution
mandating the US representative to actively seek GATT reform in order to make
international trade rules more amenable to national and international environmental
laws and to secure a working party on trade and environment within the GATT as soon
as possible.
38
Ibid., 192.
39
G. M. Duran, ‘NTBs and the WTO Agreement on Technical Barriers to Trade: The Case
of PPM-Based Measures Following US – Tuna II and EC – Seal Products’ (2015) 6
European Yearbook of International Economic Law 87–136, at 109.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
by the DSB. The dispute was brought jointly by India, Malaysia, Pakistan
and Thailand, challenging a US environmental measure prohibiting the
import of shrimp harvested without the use of Turtle Excluder Devices
(TEDs). Not using TEDs during shrimp harvesting was linked to a high
number of deaths of endangered species of sea turtles. The measures in
Shrimp-Turtle ‘were thus closely analogous’ to those in Tuna Dolphin
with the crucial difference that sea turtles were listed as endangered
species in CITES.40
40
Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 37.
41
United States – Import prohibition of certain shrimp and shrimp products – Panel
Report (15 May 1998) WT/DS58/R (‘Shrimp-Turtle’), para. 3.94 Additionally, the USA
also invoked the UN Convention on the Law of the Sea (UNCLOS) Articles 61(2), (4) and
119(1)(b), and Agenda 21 in support of this claim.
42
Shrimp-Turtle Panel report, para. 7.57. Specifically, the USA referred to paragraph 17.46
(c) of Agenda 21, which promotes ‘the development and use of selective fishing gear and
practices that minimize [. . .] the bycatch of non-target species’ as a ‘multilateral environ-
mental standard to minimize bycatch’.
43
Shrimp-Turtle Panel report, para. 3.95.
44
Ibid., paras 3.5 and 3.98 (India); para. 3.221 (Malaysia).
45
Ibid., para. 3.146.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
however, were quick to qualify of the reference to sustainable develop-
ment by reading it in light of the principle of sovereignty and the special
rights of developing countries under the WTO framework.46
The dispute forced the Panel to revisit the question of extraterritori-
ality in relation to Article XX of the GATT. Although both the United
States and the complainants had put forward arguments relating to how
Article XX should be interpreted in light of outside norms (inter alia
UNCLOS47 and general principles of international law48), the Panel
restricted itself to interpreting Article XX within the object and purpose
of WTO law and relevant jurisprudence. Echoing the GATT Panel’s
reasoning in Tuna Dolphin I, it found that Article XX could not justify
measures conditioning market access upon the adoption of certain envir-
onmental policies by exporting members as that would threaten the
security and predictability of the multilateral framework for trade.49
The Panel did not completely ignore international environmental law,
however. It drew on the Rio Declaration to interpret the reference to
sustainable development in the WTO Agreement, but used it to empha-
size the right of each state to design its own environmental policies on the
basis of its particular environmental and developmental situations.50 The
Panel further emphasized the principle of international cooperation by
reference to inter alia Article 5 of the CBD (despite the USA not being a
party to the CBD).51 The Panel found that instead of resorting to unilat-
eral measures the USA should have entered into negotiations to develop
internationally accepted conservation methods.52
The Panel proceeded to examine whether international environmental
law provided a justification for the WTO-inconsistent measure.53
46
Pakistan, for example, referred to the concept of sustainable development as an environ-
mental norm to be taken into consideration while Pakistan exercises its sovereignty to
decide on the conservation measures to be taken within its jurisdiction (ibid., para. 3.54).
Pakistan also noted that the preamble required members to enhance their means for
protecting and preserving the environment in a manner consistent with the member’s
respective needs and concerns at different levels of economic development (para. 3.85).
47
Ibid., para. 3.95; para. 3.41; and para. 3.157.
48
Ibid., para. 3.274.
49
Ibid., para. 7.45.
50
Shrimp-Turtle Panel report, para. 7.52.
51
Article 5 of the CBD promotes the principle of international cooperation when it comes
to matters of mutual interest for the conservation and sustainable use of
biological diversity.
52
Shrimp-Turtle Panel report, para. 7.53.
53
Ibid., para. 7.58 et seq.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The Panel concluded that CITES ‘neither authorized nor prohibited’ the
US import prohibition as it was directed at shrimp and not listed species
of sea turtles.54 Furthermore, while acknowledging that UNCLOS and
Agenda 21 addressed the objective of limiting by-catches of non-target
species in trawling operations, the Panel noted that these instruments do
not require the application of specific methods.55
Even though the Panel’s finding in Shrimp-Turtle is generally regarded
as an environmental setback (primarily due to its restrictive interpret-
ation of Article XX), it is remarkable from the standpoint of legal
entanglement as all parties involved in the dispute frequently and directly
referred to external environmental norms/instruments to support their
claims. Notably, international environmental law was invoked both to
support a flexible (i.e. environmentally friendly) as well as a more
restrictive (i.e. trade-friendly) interpretation of GATT Article XX.
8.3.2.3 Appeal
On appeal, the Appellate Body acknowledged the right of WTO members
to legislate for the protection of natural resources extraterritorially,
overruling the Panel’s finding.56 Accordingly, Article XX could justify
measures conditioning market access on the adoption of certain conser-
vation policies by exporting members.57 Contrary to the Panel, the
Appellate Body proceeded to take full advantage of the reference to
sustainable development in the WTO Agreement in order to interpret
the environmental exceptions of Article XX. It noted that the preamble
gives ‘colour, texture and shading’ to the substantive obligations in the
WTO agreements.58 In particular, the Appellate Body held that because
migratory sea turtles were listed under CITES as being in danger of
extinction, they constituted ‘exhaustible natural resources’ within the
54
Ibid., para. 7.58.
55
Ibid., para. 7.59.
56
United States – Import Prohibition of Certain Shrimp and Shrimp Products – Appellate
Body Report (12 October 1998) WT/DS58/AB/R, paras 121–2.
57
Duran, ‘NTBs and the WTO Agreement on Technical Barriers to Trade’, 110. See also
Shrimp-Turtle Appellate Body Report, para. 121: ‘It is not necessary to assume that
requiring from exporting countries compliance with, or adoption of, certain policies
(although covered in principle by one or another of the exceptions) prescribed by the
importing country, renders a measure a priori incapable of justification under Article XX.
Such an interpretation renders most, if not all, of the specific exceptions of Article XX
inutile, a result abhorrent to the principles of interpretation we are bound to apply.’
58
D. A. Wirth, ‘Some Reflections on Turtles, Tuna, Dolphin, and Shrimp’ (1998) 9
Yearbook of International Environmental Law 40–7, at 42.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
meaning of Article XX(g) of the GATT.59 The Appellate Body further
stated that ‘[t]he words of Article XX(g) “exhaustible natural resources”
[. . .] must be read by a treaty interpreter in the light of contemporary
concerns of the community of nations about the protection and conser-
vation of the environment [. . .] From the perspective embodied in the
Preamble of the WTO Agreement, the generic term of “natural
resources” in Article XX(g) is not “static” in its content or reference
but is rather, “by definition evolutionary”’.60
Ultimately, however, the Appellate Body found that while ‘the overall
approach of the US shrimp ban was acceptable under the WTO’, the USA
had failed to do justice to the requirements of the chapeau of Article
XX.61 The Appellate Body held that in its application, the US measure
had ‘intended an actual coercive effect on the specific policy decisions
made by foreign governments’ since the application of the measure
required other WTO members to demonstrate that a regulatory scheme
was in place, which was essentially the same as in the USA.62 In addition,
the Appellate Body also faulted the United States for having negotiated
seriously with some but not other members about arrangements for sea
turtle protection (as an alternative to the embargo), which had a discrim-
inatory effect.63 To determine whether the discrimination was also
‘unjustifiable’ in relation to the stated objective of protecting sea turtles,
the Appellate Body turned to international environmental law.64
Invoking the Rio Declaration (Principle 12), Agenda 21 and the CBD
(Article 5), the Appellate Body found that the protection and conser-
vation of highly migratory species of sea turtles demanded ‘concerted and
co-operative efforts’,65 and that, in general, transboundary/global envir-
onmental problems should be dealt with through cooperation and con-
sensus to the greatest extent possible.66
59
Shrimp-Turtle Appellate Body Report, paras 128–31.
60
Shrimp-Turtle Appellate Body Report, paras 129–30.
61
Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 42.
62
M. Bowman, P. Davies and C. Redgwell, Lyster’s International Wildlife Law (Cambridge
University Press, 2010), p. 664.
63
P. Sands, J. Peel and R. MacKenzie, Principles of International Environmental Law
(Cambridge University Press, 2012), p. 970.
64
R. Howse, ‘The Appellate Body Rulings in the Shrimp/Turtle Case: A New Legal Baseline
for the Trade and Environment Debate’ (2002) 27 Columbia Journal of Environmental
Law 491–521, at 506.
65
Shrimp-Turtle Appellate Body Report, para. 168.
66
Sands, Peel and MacKenzie, Principles of International Environmental Law, p. 970.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
8.3.2.4 Aftermath
Following the Appellate Body’s ruling, which concerned the discrimin-
atory application of the US measure, the United States made modifica-
tions in order comply with the ruling. Nevertheless, one of the original
complainants, Malaysia, brought a compliance action under Article 21.5
of the DSU, ‘where it sought to reintroduce arguments about the per se
unacceptability of trade measures to target other countries’ environmen-
tal policy’.67 However, the Appellate Body ‘held its ground’, ‘[pronoun-
cing] itself fully satisfied that the USA had addressed its concerns under
the chapeau’, while ‘[expressing] surprise that Malaysia would, in effect,
challenge the authority of the Appellate Body’s original ruling with
arguments apparently inconsistent with it’.68 The rulings in Shrimp-
Turtle and the subsequent compliance proceedings thus represent a
significant departure from the way the Tuna Dolphin cases had been
handled by the GATT Panels. The Appellate Body corrected previous
rulings with regard to PPM-based measures and extraterritorial environ-
mental trade measures, while signalling a larger degree of deference
towards members’ environmental objectives.
8.3.3 EC-Hormones
8.3.3.1 Overview
The EC-Hormones dispute before the WTO illustrates how the
Agreement on Sanitary and Phytosanitary Measures (SPS Agreement)
operates in relation to international standards and in relation to other
norms of international law, specifically the precautionary principle.69
Like the Agreement on Technical Barriers to Trade (TBT Agreement)
(see US-Tuna II), the SPS Agreement goes beyond the non-
discrimination principles enshrined in the GATT by promoting ‘global
regulatory harmonization through the application of international stand-
ards’.70 By requiring WTO members to base their measures on either
international standards or on science and risk assessment (Articles 3.1
67
Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 41.
68
Ibid., 42.
69
European Communities – Measures Concerning Meat and Meat Products (Hormones)
(Canada) – Panel report (19 August 1997) WT/DS48/R/CAN; European Communities –
Measures Concerning Meat and Meat Products (Homones) (US) – Panel report,
(18 August 1997) WT/DS26/R/USA (‘EC Hormones’).
70
Tancredi, ‘Trade and Inter-Legality’, p. 171.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
and 3.2), the SPS Agreement actively encourages legal entanglement in
the area of sanitary and phytosanitary measures. The SPS Agreement
explicitly recognizes specific international standardizing bodies as points
of reference for compliance, including the Codex Alimentarius
Commission (CAC’).71 Conformity with Codex standards implies con-
formity with WTO law,72 whereas a member’s decision to set standards
higher than Codex standards is subject to a higher burden of proof to
defend its own measures.
From the perspective of legal entanglement, the implications of this
active coupling mechanism between the SPS Agreement and inter-
national standards versus the way WTO law relates to other norms of
international law is significant. The WTO’s contrasting approaches to
entanglement are best demonstrated in the EC-Hormones case. In the
1990s, following widespread public concern, the European Council intro-
duced a set of measures prohibiting the placing on the market of
hormone-injected meat. In 1996, the United States challenged these
measures and brought the dispute before the WTO alleging violations
of inter alia the SPS Agreement.73
71
Annex A.3 SPS.
72
Article 3.2 SPS.
73
EC Hormones Panel Report (US), para. 3.2 With regard to the SPS Agreement, the USA
claimed inter alia that the measures were not based on an assessment of risk and therefore
inconsistent with Article 5.1, that they lacked sufficient scientific evidence in contraven-
tion of Article 2.2, that they were not justified as a provisional measure under Article 5.7
and that they were not based on scientific principles thereby breaching Articles 2.2 and
5.6, that they were applied beyond the extent necessary to protect human life or health,
and that they were more trade restrictive than required to achieve the appropriate level of
sanitary protection.
74
Ibid., para. 4.203.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
members to base their measures on risk assessments and available scien-
tific data, the precautionary principle allows countries to take measures
in the face of scientific uncertainty. Notably, the EC did not invoke
Article 5.7 of the SPS Agreement which permits members to take interim
measures in the face of insufficient scientific evidence and is generally
viewed as reflecting the precautionary principle in the context of the SPS
Agreement. The EC reasoned that this decision was deliberate because
the measures were considered definitive and not provisional.75 The EC
also pointed out that the Codex standards had been adopted by a very
slim margin in what was ordinarily a consensus-based system. By ques-
tioning the level of support for the Codex standards the EC expressed
expectations about the substantive dimensions of the interface norm
contained in the SPS Agreement: international standards should only be
taken into account if they are considered legitimate, as indicated by
widespread to universal acceptance during adoption.76 The Panel
rejected the need to consider by what margin any relevant standard
was adopted,77 and found that the EC measure violated the SPS
Agreement by deviating from the relevant international standard (in
the sense that it afforded a higher level of protection) without sufficient
justification.78 Further, the Panel found that the precautionary principle
(to the extent that it could be considered as part of customary inter-
national law) ‘would not override the explicit wording’ of SPS provisions
relating to risk assessment techniques (and scientific evidence), ‘in par-
ticular since the precautionary principle [had] been incorporated
and given specific meaning in Article 5.7 of the SPS Agreement’.79 The
harmonization logic of the SPS Agreement thus contributed to lowering a
member’s chosen protection threshold – in accordance with international
standards adopted with only tenuous international support – while a
75
EC Hormones Panel Report (US), para. 4.239.
76
P. Delimatsis, The Law, Economics and Politics of International Standardisation
(Cambridge University Press, 2015), p. 90. The EU and other countries have repeatedly
expressed this claim that the Codex should respect consensus-based decision-making as
one of the fundamental principles of the organisation; see a recent example: Codex
Alimentarius Commission (35th Session) Rome, 2–7 July 2012, EU Statement on racto-
pamine ‘for standards to be universally applicable, they also need to be universally
accepted’.
77
EC Hormones Panel Report (US), para. 8.69.
78
Ibid., paras 8.75–8.77.
79
Ibid., para. 8.157.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
relevant norm of international law (the precautionary principle) was
dismissed in the process.
8.3.3.3 Appeal
The EC appealed the ruling, arguing that the precautionary principle’s
applicability extended beyond Article 5.7 to influence risk assessment
(and risk management) under Article 5.1 of the SPS Agreement, and thus
operated to justify higher protection thresholds.80 Notably the EC did not
refer to the precautionary principle in the context of international envir-
onmental law but in the context of general and customary international
law. The Appellate Body, siding with the Panel, found that while the
precautionary principle may have crystallized in the field of international
environmental law, its status as customary international law or a general
principle of law was less certain. By relegating the principle to the
confines of international environmental law, the Appellate Body down-
played its relevance for the dispute at hand. Further, the Appellate Body
stated that ‘the precautionary principle does not, by itself, and without a
clear textual directive to that effect, relieve a panel from the duty of
applying the normal (i.e. customary international law) principles of
treaty interpretation in reading the provisions of the SPS Agreement’.81
In effect, the Appellate Body communicated that whatever the state of the
precautionary principle in international law was, ‘the principle could not
override the explicit obligations contained in the SPS Agreement and it
could not be used to justify measures otherwise inconsistent with the SPS
Agreement’.82 The EC ultimately ‘lost’ the case as its measures were
found not to have been based on appropriate risk assessment: the EC
could neither prove ‘laboratory scientific evidence’ nor ‘real-world risk’
(misuse in the administration of hormones to animals).83 This ruling flies
in the face of the precautionary principle (as codified for example in
Principle 15 of the Rio Declaration), the purpose of which is precisely to
empower governments in the face of scientific uncertainty.
80
European Communities – Measures Concerning Meat and Meat Products (Hormones) –
Report of the Appellate Body (16 January 1998), WT/DS26/AB/R and WT/DS48/AB/R,
para. 16.
81
EC Hormones Appellate Body Report, paras 124–5.
82
M. L. Maier and C. Gerstetter, ‘Risk Regulation, Trade and International Law: Debating
the Precautionary Principle in and around the WTO’, TranState working papers
(2005), 12.
83
Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 58.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Nevertheless, the Appellate Body did point out that ‘a panel charged with
determining for instance, whether “sufficient scientific evidence” exists to
warrant the maintenance by a Member of a particular SPS measure may
[. . .] bear in mind that responsible, representative governments commonly
act from the perspectives of prudence and precaution where risks of irre-
versible, e.g., life-terminating, damage to human health are concerned’.84
This statement implies a greater degree of flexibility where the future
application of Article 5 is concerned; the implication is that in cases of grave
potential damage, Panels are to content themselves with a lower evidentiary
standard for assessing a measure’s SPS consistency.85
8.3.3.4 Aftermath
Following the EC-Hormones disputes, the EC made a concerted push for
strengthening the precautionary principle in international law. After
having unsuccessfully advocated for a renegotiation of relevant provi-
sions within the SPS Agreement, the EC turned its attention to multilat-
eral fora outside the WTO.86 In 2000, the Cartagena Protocol on
Biosafety to the Convention on Biological Diversity (the ‘Biosafety
Protocol’) was agreed upon, which regulates risks associated with the
transboundary movement of living modified organisms. The Biosafety
Protocol ‘[reaffirms] the precautionary approach contained in Principle
15 of the Rio Declaration on Environment and Development’87 and
grants importing states the right to make decisions that would avoid or
reduce potential adverse effects in the face of scientific uncertainty.88 The
Biosafety Protocol thus ‘multilateralizes the EU regulatory approach’
towards sanitary measures, opening the door to other countries to adopt
restrictive, EU-style market access rules.89 Unsurprisingly, one of the
84
EC Hormones Appellate Body Report, para. 172.
85
Maier and Gerstetter, ‘Risk Regulation, Trade and International Law’, 16.
86
Santarius et al., ‘Balancing Trade and Environment’. Notably, environmental organiza-
tions/groups – such as the Forum Umwelt und Entwicklung – and states had long been
pushing for the precautionary principle to be incorporated into WTO law in more
unrestricted form.
87
UNEP, Preamble, ‘Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety to the Convention on Biological
Diversity (the Biosafety Protocol)’ (2000).
88
This is in the context of the ‘advanced informed agreement’ procedure which applies to
the first transboundary movement of a living modified organism that is intended to be
released into the environment of an importing party.
89
G. E. Isaac and W. A. Kerr, ‘The Biosafety Protocol and the WTO: Concert or Conflict?’,
in R. Falkner (ed.), The International Politics of Genetically Modified Food: Diplomacy,
Trade and Law (Palgrave Macmillan, 2006), pp. 195–212, at p. 196.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
most contentious issues during the negotiation process was the
Protocol’s relationship with international trade law.90 In this regard,
the preamble ‘[recognizes] that trade and environment agreements
should be mutually supportive with a view to achieving sustainable
development’ and ‘[emphasizes] that [the] Protocol shall not be inter-
preted as implying a change in the rights and obligations of a Party
under any existing international agreements’ (while also ‘understanding
that the above recital [was] not intended to subordinate [the] Protocol
to other international agreements’). The EC also successfully campaigned
for the inclusion of the precautionary principle in the risk assessment
techniques developed by the Codex Alimentarius Commission.91 As
a result, two newly negotiated documents, the 2003 and 2007 Working
Principles for Risk Analysis for Food Safety for Application by
Governments, recognize precaution as an inherent element of risk
assessment.92
After several years of keeping its genetically modified organism
(GMO) measures in place while accepting the punitive tariffs imposed
by the USA and Canada in return, the EC was able to produce scientific
evidence to prove risk from synthetic growth hormones. The EC subse-
quently amended its law to bring them into compliance with the
Appellate Body’s ruling.93 Nevertheless, the USA and Canada continued
to retaliate, prompting the EC to challenge the legality of continued
retaliatory measures in 2005. This ‘follow-up dispute’ Canada/US –
Continued Suspension (2008), gave the Appellate Body the opportunity
to revisit its previous ruling (in light of the new normative developments
that had occurred outside the WTO). In Canada/US – Continued
Suspension, the Appellate Body developed the concepts of ‘risk assess-
ment’ and ‘sufficiency of scientific evidence’ as ‘relational concepts’
implying that issues such as ‘the appropriate level of protection’ chosen
by a government could shape the methodology and questions studied in
90
P. E. Hagen and J. B. Weiner, ‘The Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety: New Rules for
International Trade in Living Modified Organisms’ (2000) 12 The Georgetown
International Environmental Law Review 697–717, at 702.
91
Maier and Gerstetter, ‘Risk Regulation, Trade and International Law’.
92
FAO, Principle 11, ‘Working Principles for Risk Analysis for Application in the
Framework of the Codex Alimentarius’ (Risk Analysis Principles Applied by the Codex
Committee on Food Additives and Contaminants) (2003); FAO, Principle 12, ‘Working
Principles for Risk Analysis for Food Safety for Application by Governments (CAC/GL
62–2007)’ (2007).
93
Delimatsis, The Law, Economics and Politics of International Standardisation, p. 97.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
risk assessment.94 The Appellate Body also relativized the centrality of
international standards and conceded that scientific evidence could be
sufficient for one member but not for another.95 This more deferential
approach towards members’ right to regulate on the basis of precaution
significantly departed from the Appellate Body’s initial reasoning in
EC-Hormones.96
8.3.4 EC-Biotech
8.3.4.1 Overview
The EC-Biotech dispute represents another deliberation on the extent to
which the precautionary principle is applicable in relation to the SPS
Agreement. In 2003, three exporters of agricultural products containing
GMOs – the United States, Canada and Argentina – challenged the EC
on some of its measures relating to GMOs. The EC had instituted a
moratorium on the approval of GMOs during the period of October
1998 and August 2003 and, in addition, some EC member states had put
in place national restrictions on GMOs and genetically modified foods.
Notably, the EC’s regulatory regime for GMOs was (and is) significantly
informed by the precautionary principle.
The dispute came on the heels of the adoption of the Biosafety
Protocol, which was not only substantively relevant to the dispute at
hand (namely GMO-related measures) but also incorporated a more
robust version of the precautionary principle than the SPS
Agreement.97 Indeed, the complaint has been viewed as implicitly
targeting the Biosafety Protocol in order to weaken its relevance for the
SPS Agreement.98 With regard to the trade–environment interface, the
Panel’s reasoning in EC-Biotech is widely viewed as a setback for a
mutually supportive relationship as the Panel prima facie dismissed the
relevance of the Biosafety Protocol to the dispute.
94
Ibid., p. 97 et seq.
95
Ibid., p. 98.
96
Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 58.
97
J. Zhao, ‘The Role of International Organizations in Preventing Conflicts between the SPS
Agreement and the Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety’ (2020) 29(2) Review of European,
Comparative & International Environmental Law 1–11.
98
Isaac and Kerr, ‘The Biosafety Protocol and the WTO’, p. 196.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
8.3.4.2 Legal Entanglement
The EC justified some of the EC members’ national bans by invoking the
precautionary principle as codified in the Biosafety Protocol. The EC
argued that the SPS Agreement and the Biosafety Protocol were ‘so
closely connected that they should be interpreted and applied consist-
ently with each other, to the extent that is possible’; the two agreements
were ‘complimentary’ and therefore ‘the Protocol’s provisions on precau-
tion and risk assessment inform the meaning and effect of the relevant
provisions of the WTO agreements’.99 The complainants were not parties
to the Protocol and rejected its application to the dispute. They argued
that the Protocol did not constitute a ‘relevant rule of international law
applicable in the relations between the parties’ and should therefore not
be taken into account in the interpretation of the obligations under the
WTO Agreement.100
An amicus curiae brief is of note in the context of EC-Biotech as it
makes additional claims about how the interface between trade law and
environmental concerns/precaution should be managed. In its submis-
sion, the Centre for International Environmental Law (CIEL) noted that
the Appellate Body had emphasized the importance, in certain circum-
stances, of interpreting terms in the WTO agreements in light of ‘the
contemporary concerns of the community of nations’ (see Shrimp-
Turtle).101 CIEL argued that ‘interpreting bodies’ consequently had a
responsibility ‘to take into account [external treaties not ratified by all
parties to the treaty being interpreted], especially when they address
issues of global concern where the interests of the international commu-
nity were involved’.102
8.3.4.3 Aftermath
The EC decided not to appeal the ruling of the Panel and instead pursued
a ‘Mutually Agreed Solution’, decided between Canada and the EU in
2009, which established ‘a bilateral dialogue on agricultural biotech
99
European Communities – Measures Affecting the Approval and Marketing of Biotech
Products – Panel report (29 September 2006) WT/DS291/292/293/R (‘EC-Biotech’),
para. 7.55.
100
EC-Biotech Panel report, para. 4.600.
101
CIEL, ‘EC-Biotech: Overview and Analysis of the Panel’s Interim Report’ (Mach 2006),
p. 46.
102
Ibid., p. 49.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
market access issues of mutual interest’.103 This cooperation agreement
was subsequently reaffirmed in the EU–Canada Comprehensive
Economic and Trade Agreement (CETA), which largely reproduced the
text of the Mutually Agreed Solution in Article 25.2(1). Thus, CETA
institutionalizes international cooperation on biotech market access and
inter alia sets out the shared objective of promoting ‘efficient science-
based approval processes for biotechnology products [emphasis added]’.
This provision was criticized as running counter to the EC’s strict
regulation of GMOs as informed by the precautionary approach and
has generated concerns around the weakening of GMO protections in the
EU.104 Arcuri points out that while ‘international cooperation’ may
sound innocuous and indeterminate, the fact that an international body
of norms on low-level presence of GMOs already exists (the Global Low-
Level Presence Initiative) and given that most state members of this
framework are GMO producers with a clear interest in lowering GMO
protections, the requirement of international cooperation may in fact
further skew international standards on GMO protections, to the detri-
ment of the EC’s precautionary ‘zero tolerance’ approach.105 At the same
time, however, the preamble of the Joint Interpretative Instrument on the
CETA ‘reaffirms the commitments made with respect to precaution that
[the European Union and its members states and Canada] have under-
taken in international agreements’, hence relativizing the provisions
requiring science-based evaluations. Reading the relevant CETA provi-
sions in the context of the 2003 and 2007 Codex Working Principles for
Risk Analysis – which recognize precaution as an inherent element of
risk analysis – further neutralizes their potential to weaken the precau-
tionary principle.
8.3.5 US-Tuna II
8.3.5.1 Overview
Following the GATT Panels’ rulings in Tuna Dolphin I and II, ‘the
United States eventually allowed all tuna, no matter how it had been
103
European Communities – Measures Affecting the Approval and Marketing of Biotech
Products – Mutually Agreed Solution between Canada and the European Communities
(15 July 2009) WT/DS292/40, G/L/628/Add.1.
104
A. Arcuri, ‘Is CETA Keeping up with the Promise? Interpreting Certain Provisions
Relating to Biotechnology’ (2017) 41 Questions of International Law, Zoom-Out 35–58.
105
Ibid., 47 et seq.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
harvested, to be sold in its market’ while reserving the ‘dolphin-safe’ label
for tuna harvested in a particular manner.106 In 2008, Mexico requested
consultations with the United States with regard to its ‘dolphin-safe’
labelling requirements, initiating the next phase of the long-running tuna
dolphin dispute. This section will focus primarily on how the Appellate
Body in US-Tuna II (Mexico) (not to be confused with Tuna Dolphin II,
the 1994 dispute initiated by the EC against the USA concerning its
secondary embargo against re-exported tuna) shed light on how the
relationship between the TBT Agreement and international standards
should be construed. Like the SPS Agreement, the TBT Agreement
requires the harmonization of national regulations on the basis of inter-
national standards (Article 2.4). However, unlike the SPS Agreement,
which provides a list of international standard-setting organizations
(such as the Codex Alimentarius Commission), the TBT Agreement does
not list any institutional/authoritative sources of international standards.
The question of what counts as an international standardizing body is
important as such a classification automatically triggers the harmoniza-
tion obligation (i.e. pressure for entanglement) established in Article 2.4
of the TBT.107
Mexico challenged the ‘dolphin-safe’ labelling requirements as incon-
sistent with inter alia the TBT Agreement.108 Notably, the (state-
administered) voluntary labelling scheme was considered to be a manda-
tory technical regulation, thus falling within the remit of the TBT
Agreement.109 As such, Mexico claimed that the US measure should
have been based on the relevant international standard (according to
Article 2.4), specifically the labelling scheme established under the
Agreement on the International Dolphin Conservation Program
(AIDCP). Notably, the AIDCP is only a regional organization to which
only a subset of WTO members adheres. The Panel and the Appellate
Body were tasked with determining whether the AIDCP labelling scheme
106
P. C. Mavroidis, ‘Last Mile for Tuna (to a Safe Harbour): What Is the TBT Agreement
All About?’ (2019) 30 European Journal of International Law 279–301, at 280.
107
TBT 2.4 requires national technical regulations, standards and conformity assessments
to be based on relevant international standards except where such standards would be an
ineffective or inappropriate means for the fulfilment of the legitimate objectives pursued.
108
M. A. Crowley and R. Howse, ‘Tuna–Dolphin II: A Legal and Economic Analysis of the
Appellate Body Report’ (2014) 13 World Trade Review 321–55, at 321.
109
Both the Panel and the Appellate Body in Tuna Dolphin II found that the US measure
constituted a mandatory technical regulation because it prescribed by law minimum
requirements for accessing the ‘dolphin-safe’ labelling scheme in the USA.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
constituted an international standard within the meaning of the TBT
Agreement. Section 8.3.5.2 focuses on the Appellate Body’s rulings as
the Panel’s findings are of little relevance to the question of legal
entanglement.
110
P. V. den Bossche and D. Prévost, Essentials of WTO Law (Cambridge University Press,
2016), p. 190.
111
United States – Measures Concerning the Importation, Marketing and Sale of Tuna and
Tuna Products – Panel report (15 September 2011) WT/DS381/R (‘US-Tuna II’),
para. 7.691.
112
United States – Measures Concerning the Importation, Marketing and Sale of Tuna and
Tuna Products – Report by Appellate Body (16 May 2012) WT/DS381/AB/R, para. 399.
113
US-Tuna II Appellate Body Report, para. 390.
114
Ibid., para. 377.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
year 2000 (‘the Decision’), which sets out guiding principles and
procedures that standardizing bodies should observe when developing
international standards, inter alia transparency, openness, impartiality
and consensus.115 The Decision is significant as it spells these principles
out in some detail, thus defining a relatively precise guidance for the
entanglement of WTO law with standards from other sources. In an early
case under the TBT Agreement, EC-Sardines, the Panel had dismissed the
Decision as ‘a [mere] policy statement of preference and not the control-
ling provision in interpreting the expression “relevant international
standard” as set out in Article 2.4 of the TBT Agreement’.116 In Tuna
Dolphin II, the Appellate Body reversed this finding, stating that the
Decision constituted a subsequent agreement of the parties in the mean-
ing of Article 31(3)(a) VCLT and should be read together with the
TBT.117
The weight that the Appellate Body gave to the Decision is significant
because it directly clarifies several points of contention with regard to
interpreting the TBT and how it relates to international standards.
Principle three, for example, explicitly emphasizes consensus as a require-
ment for international standards in the TBT Agreement, even though an
explanatory note to TBT Annex I.2 states that the TBT also covers
documents not based on consensus. Notably, the Appellate Body in
EC-Sardines had rejected the consensus requirement.118 The Appellate
Body’s ruling in EC-Sardines had also implied a large measure of regula-
tory harmonization and ‘a very close fit or relationship between any
technical regulation and the international standard, providing very little
flexibility for regulatory diversity’.119 By contrast, the Appellate Body in
US-Tuna II resisted ‘demands for regulatory harmonization through
Article 2.4’ by emphasizing the criteria contained in the Decision relating
to transparency and meaningful participation.120 Thus, the Appellate
Body effectively transformed the Decision into ‘a code of administrative
115
TBT Committee, ‘Decision on Principles for the Development of International
Standards, Guides and Recommendations’ (13 November 2000) G/TBT/9, Annex 4.
116
European Communities – Trade Description of Sardines – Panel report (29 May 2002)
WT/DS231/R, para. 7.91.
117
US-Tuna II Appellate Body Report, para. 372.
118
European Communities – Trade Description of Sardines – Report by Appellate Body
(26 September 2002) WT/DS231/AB/R, para. 224.
119
Howse, ‘The World Trade Organization 20 Years On’, 56.
120
Ibid., 56.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
procedure and practice for international standardization’ in the vein of
global administrative law.121
Ultimately, the Appellate Body found that while the ‘dolphin-safe’
labelling provisions did not violate Article 2.4 of the TBT, they were
inconsistent with Article 2.1 of the TBT because of a lack of even-
handedness in the manner in which risks from different fishing tech-
niques in different areas of the ocean were addressed.
8.3.5.3 Aftermath
In response to the Panel and the Appellate Body reports, the United
States modified its dolphin-safe labelling requirements to comply with
the Appellate Body’s ruling. However, the US measure continued to
impose different certification and tracking and verification requirements
depending on the fishery where the tuna was caught, with more burden-
some requirements for tuna caught in the ETP. After several rounds of
compliance proceedings, in which Mexico continued to challenge the
United States’ measure due to discriminatory effects and with both
parties repeatedly appealing, the Panel found that the US measure was
not discriminatory and exonerated the USA from responsibility, a finding
that the Appellate Body confirmed. The distinctions made in the United
States’ measure (i.e. its discriminatory elements) were found to be cali-
brated to the different levels of risk posed by the practice of ‘setting’ on
dolphins vis-à-vis other fishing methods. Thus, the detrimental impact
caused by the US measure stemmed exclusively from a legitimate regula-
tory distinction and did not result in ‘treatment less favourable than that
accorded to like products from the United States and other countries’
(consistency with Article 2.1 as well as with the chapeau of GATT Article
XX).122 The final compliance report (with no finding of non-compliance)
was circulated to members in December 2018, and adopted in January
2019, thereby concluding a dispute that had run on for almost thirty
years.
121
Crowley and Howse, ‘Tuna–Dolphin II’, 342.
122
United States – Measures Concerning the Importation, Marketing and Sale of Tuna and
Tuna Products – Recourse to Article 21.5 of the DSU by the United States; United
States – Measures Concerning the Importation, Marketing and Sale of Tuna and Tuna
Products – Recourse to Article 21.5 of the DSU by Mexico, Report by Appellate Body (14
December 2018) WT/DS381/AB/RW/USA; WT/DS381/AB/RW2, paras 7.1–7.14.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
8.4 Main Findings
8.4.1 Irritative Norm Conflict Over Time
The unadopted Panel report in Tuna Dolphin I set the stage for an
antagonistic relationship between the GATT-based multilateral trading
system and environmental trade measures for the achievement of global
environmental objectives. Through repeated ‘irritations’ of trade law by
environmental norms (through litigation in the WTO combined with
external pressure), subsequent rulings by Panels and the WTO Appellate
Body significantly corrected/recalibrated controversial aspects of the
trade and environment interface, a process that is referred to here as
irritative norm conflict over time.123
The ‘Tuna Dolphin saga’ (in which Shrimp-Turtle constitutes a crucial
building block) illustrates how irritative norm conflict over a period of
almost thirty years allowed WTO judicial bodies to adjust elements of
previous jurisprudence that had ‘gone too far’ in asserting trade object-
ives over members’ right to regulate. Although Tuna Dolphin I had found
unilateral environmental trade measures with extraterritorial effects
prima facie incapable of justification under the GATT, the Appellate
Body in Shrimp-Turtle reversed this finding and clarified that GATT
Article XX could, in fact, justify measures conditioning market access on
environmental policies/PPMs abroad – as long as the measures do not
amount to arbitrary or unjustifiable discrimination.124 As a result, the
ruling of the Appellate Body in Shrimp-Turtle was widely perceived as ‘a
bold attempt to construct a broader societal vision of the WTO [. . .]
more sensitive to environmental concerns’.125 Both the Shrimp-Turtle
import requirements and the Tuna Dolphin/US-Tuna II labelling provi-
sions were ultimately found to be consistent with WTO law; however,
this was only after the United States had been subjected to several (costly)
rounds of litigation and revisions of the law. Thus, while environmental
norms have gained clout in the WTO, the fundamental objective of the
WTO system – an open international economic system – is preserved
through the meticulous enforcement of non-discrimination principles.
123
On irritative norm conflicts, see N. Krisch, F. Corradini and L. L. Reimers, ‘Order at the
Margins: The Legal Construction of Interface Conflicts over Time’ (2020) 9 Global
Constitutionalism 343–63.
124
J. Pauwelyn, ‘Recent Books on Trade and Environment: GATT Phantoms Still Haunt the
WTO’ (2004) 15 European Journal of International Law 575–92.
125
Perez, Ecological Sensitivity and Global Legal Pluralism, p. 65.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
In EC-Hormones, EC-Biotech, and Canada/US-Continued Suspension –
a series of distinct but interrelated disputes – what was being negotiated
was inter alia the scope/applicability of the precautionary principle in the
WTO context. Repeated irritations of international trade rules (and pres-
sure from both within and outside of the WTO) led to a shift in the
Appellate Body’s construction of precaution in the WTO and SPS context
(Canada/US-Continued Suspension). While the tension between the pre-
cautionary principle (as codified in international environmental law) and
the emphasis on scientific evidence and risk assessment in the SPS
Agreement is not completely resolved, the role of precaution has been
significantly strengthened (both in WTO law and outside of it – e.g. in the
Codex Alimentarius Commission and in the Biosafety Protocol). The
compromise around the role of precaution versus scientific risk assessment
in CETA shows how WTO dispute settlement is not the only arena in
which actors negotiate and navigate irritative norm conflict.
Finally, it is of note that the appeals mechanism in the WTO serves to
process – and to accelerate – irritative norm conflict, allowing the
Appellate Body to make (rapid) adjustments in the wake of contentious
Panel findings, member state pressure and public protest. ‘Follow-up’
disputes prompted by issues around compliance or continued retaliation
also provide the opportunity for rebalancing or ‘fine-tuning’ previous
findings (e.g. Canada/US-Continued Suspension).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
international trade law and international environmental law will not
necessarily result in more ‘environmentally friendly’ rulings. In this vein,
some of the foundational critiques directed at the multilateral trading
system can also be levelled against the international environmental
regime, which has incorporated into its body of norms a bias against
unilateral trade measures and has embraced the objective of liberalized
trade (e.g. Principle 12 of the Rio Declaration). The two bodies of norms
have always been more entangled (and mutually reinforcing) than
generally assumed.
The reference to sustainable development in the Preamble of the
WTO Agreement plays a central ‘entangling’ function at the interface
between trade and environment, opening the door for outside environ-
mental norms to enter WTO law through GATT Article XX (e.g. in
Shrimp-Turtle). However, such forms of relationing between inter-
national trade law and outside bodies of norms are tenuous and remain
contingent on the Panels’ and Appellate Body’s willingness to take
outside norms into consideration on a case-by-case basis – essentially
at their discretion. For instance, while the Appellate Body in Shrimp-
Turtle had referred to outside treaty law not binding on all the disput-
ing parties (the CBD), the Panel in EC-Biotech rejected the applicability
of the Biosafety Protocol because the United States was not a party to it,
and it could therefore not be considered ‘applicable’ in the relations
between the parties according to Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna
Convention.
Resistance to legal entanglement comes in the form of strategies for
distancing. In EC-Hormones, various techniques for creating distancing
between the precautionary principle and obligations under the SPS
Agreement were employed by the disputants, the Panel and the
Appellate Body, including (1) relegating the precautionary principle to
the realm of international environmental law while calling into question
the status of the precautionary principle as a general principle of inter-
national law or a rule of customary international law; (2) restricting the
applicability of the precautionary principle to its (partial) reflection in the
SPS Agreement (Article 5.7) but rejecting its general applicability with
regard to other provisions (namely Articles 5.1 and 5.2); and (3) pointing
to the absence of a ‘clear textual directive’ that would allow an external
norm to affect the interpretation of a provision in a WTO Agreement.
Article 3.2 of the DSU requires treaty interpreters to refer to any relevant
rules of international law applicable in the relations between the parties
(according to Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Convention). As customary
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
and general international law is always applicable between all parties to a
dispute, relevant customary norms or general principles of international
law will more likely be brought into relation with WTO law than external
treaty norms which may not have been ratified by all WTO members/
parties in a given dispute. It is therefore unsurprising that emphasizing
the customary or general international law nature of an external norm or
lack thereof is a dominant mechanism for creating either entanglement or
distancing between WTO law and other bodies of norms.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
equivalent norms identified by some,126 the reference to sustainable
development provides a linkage function and enhances the discretion
of Panels and the Appellate Body to interpret the environmental excep-
tions of Article XX expansively (e.g. the Appellate Body in Shrimp-Turtle
construed a close relationship between WTO rules and international
environmental norms according to preambular directive). In this way,
interface norms can be mutually supportive.
While the WTO, on the whole, keeps substantive norms from other
areas of international law at bay, it actively seeks entanglement with
international standards. International standards attract linkages with
WTO law more readily due to the WTO’s inherent harmonization
dynamic. This is done through the TBT and SPS Agreements, which
coordinate the relationship between international standards and WTO
harmonization obligations through Articles 2.4 and 3.1 respectively. The
contrasting approaches to entanglement are best illustrated in EC-
Hormones, where the Panel and the Appellate Body interpreted the SPS
Agreement in a way as to promote entanglement with Codex norms,
while creating distancing with an external substantive norm originally
developed in the context of international environmental law, namely the
precautionary principle.
126
See T. Broude and Y. Shany (eds), Multi-sourced Equivalent Norms in International Law
(Bloomsbury Publishing, 2011).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
constellation). It follows that linkages with external norms are more
easily produced if the latter are considered general or customary inter-
national law (see Section 8.4.2), as well as when there are ‘docking norms’
in the text that can provide the Panel or the Appellate Body with a
‘textual directive’ – that is, a mandate – for linkage.
Further, entanglement between WTO law and international standards
is explicitly encouraged through the TBT Agreement and the SPS
Agreement, which promote the harmonization of national regulations
on the basis of international standards. The substantive dimensions of
entanglement between WTO law and international standards is gradually
being ‘fleshed out’ with additional (still contested) criteria such as the
level of international support for the adoption of the norm in question
(consensus, broad membership, inclusiveness/participation). For
example, in EC-Hormones the EC did not recognize a specific set of
Codex standards as being ‘international standards’ due to the narrow
margin by which it was adopted. The EC thus expressed expectations
about the substantive dimensions of the interface norm contained in the
SPS Agreement: international standards should only be taken into
account if they are considered legitimate, as indicated by broad accept-
ance during adoption (see Section 8.3.3.2). While the Panel in EC-
Hormones rejected the EC’s reasoning, the Appellate Body in US-Tuna
II gave significant weight to a 2000 TBT Committee Decision, which
contains a set of substantive criteria that qualify the appropriateness of
international standards from the perspective of the WTO (specifically the
TBT Agreement), including transparency, openness, consensus and
effectiveness. In this regard, the Appellate Body also indicated that the
number of countries participating in a standard-setting process relative
to the total number of WTO members is relevant for the entry of
international standards into WTO law via TBT Article 2.4.
8.5 Conclusion
This chapter addressed horizontal ways of relationing between inter-
national trade law and international environmental law, and explored
how these different legalities respond to each other and manage tensions
without subordination. The findings show how repeated ‘irritations’ of
trade law through environmental norms, expressed in WTO dispute
settlement and combined with external political pressure (including by
building and harnessing pressure in other multilateral fora), can prompt
‘recalibrations’ at the interface of WTO law and encourage the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
’
clarification of the relationship over time. What emerges from this
analysis is a kind of modified ‘island’ view of the WTO in relation to
other bodies of norms. Interface norms allow for the contingent adapta-
tion of ‘foreign’ rules into WTO law while broader systemic connections
are resisted through mechanisms of distancing. Thereby new develop-
ments in international law can be reflected in jurisprudential interpret-
ations without compromising the stated objective of ensuring the
‘security and predictability of the multilateral framework for trade’. To
this end, the WTO regime actively encourages legal entanglement with
international standards because harmonization helps facilitate trade.
Ultimately, this chapter demonstrates how the WTO has successfully
negotiated legal entanglement on its own terms and in service to the
regime’s overarching goal of free trade.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
PART III
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
9
9.1 Introduction
Jurists and legal historians have increasingly come to the realization that
the story of their discipline is not, in fact, that of the gradual diffusion of
Western concepts to the rest of the world. The emergence of new norms
of global governance and the history of international law more generally
are made up of multiple stories that have no single point of departure.1
The history of legal concepts, imaginaries and fields of practice is full of
examples of such ‘legal entanglements’ between various systems of law,
located at different scales, and generated according to different temporal-
ities and historicities.2 The new historiography on colonialism and
empires, for instance, has insisted on the two-way transport of legal
concepts and practices and the plurality of legal orders that were consti-
tuted over time during the Spanish, British, French and even German
empires.3 In many cases, scholars of colonial law have demonstrated that
This chapter is directly based on a project headed by Grégoire Mallard that received funding
from the European Research Council under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research
and innovation program (Grant Agreement PROSANCT, ‘Bombs, Banks and Sanctions’,
Project 716216). The authors thank all the interviewees who participated in the research.
1
T. Duve, ‘Entanglements in Legal History. Introductory Remarks’, in T. Duve,
Entanglements in Legal History: Conceptual Approaches (Max Planck Institute for
European Legal History, 2014), pp. 3–25.
2
B. S. Chimni, International Law and World Order: A Critique of Contemporary Approaches
(Cambridge University Press, 2017).
3
L. Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–1900
(Cambridge University Press, 2001); G. Steinmetz, The Devil’s Handwriting:
Precoloniality and the German Colonial State in Qingdao, Samoa, and Southwest Africa
(University of Chicago Press, 2008); Duve, Entanglements in Legal History; J. Go, ‘Global
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the colonizers’ rule was far from being the sole source of authority and
legitimacy in disputes between colonizers and colonial subjects.4 The
resulting ‘legal entanglements’ may have looked contradictory in
principle but were effective in practice.5
Similarly, political scientists have looked at the co-constitution of
normative and/or rules-based regimes, which has grown increasingly
more complex through practices of interlinkages. Experts often push
the boundaries of technical fields of governance by claiming jurisdiction
over the regulation of innovations in adjacent fields. Such practices
promote an ever tighter entanglement between expert knowledge and
policy domains, leading to either conflict, cooperation or free-riding by
transnational policy networks, private companies and states.6 Political
sociologists and socio-legal scholars have also recently paid attention to
the circulation of various kinds of capital (economic, cultural, political or
even colonial) and their transmission across entangled national and
international regulatory fields. These scholars conclude that the distribu-
tion of such forms of capital does not follow a purely national logic, such
that we need a transnational perspective on the workings of the state in
the age of globalization.7
Although these various disciplines differ in methods and findings, we
find, across fields, a number of scholars who seek to explain the evolution
of complex forms of transnational legal rules as ‘legal entanglements’.
These scholars converge on some epistemic principles. They hold that
history originates from many parts of the world; that asymmetries of
Fields and Imperial Forms: Field Theory and the British and American Empires’ (2008) 26
Sociological Theory 201–29; G. Mallard, Gift Exchange: The Transnational History of a
Political Idea (Cambridge University Press, 2019).
4
S. E. Merry, ‘Legal Pluralism’ (1988) 22 Law & Society Review 869–96; see also S. E. Merry,
Human Rights and Gender Violence: Translating International Law into Local Justice
(University of Chicago Press, 2009).
5
Colonial legal entanglements were not tightly tied together, and the multiple actors who
circulated from one imperial order to another well tolerated multiplicity and contradiction
in the interpretation of plural legal orders (see Benton, Law and Colonial Cultures).
6
S. C. Hofmann, ‘Overlapping Institutions in the Realm of International Security: The Case
of NATO and ESDP’ (2009) 7 Perspectives on Politics 45–52; K. J. Alter and K. Raustiala,
‘The Rise of International Regime Complexity’ (2018) 14 Annual Review of Law and Social
Science 329–49.
7
Y. Dezalay and B. Garth, The Internationalization of Palace Wars: Lawyers, Economists
and the Struggle to Transform Latin American States (Chicago University Press, 2002); Y.
Dezalay and B. Garth, Asian Legal Revivals: Lawyers in the Shadow of Empire (Chicago
University Press, 2010); Steinmetz, The Devil’s Handwriting; Go, ‘Global Fields and
Imperial Forms’; Mallard, Gift Exchange.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
power are inscribed in norms but that it is mostly in practice where
power actually manifests itself – most often, through practices of know-
ing, classifying and reifying certain visions of the world.8 They also tend
to agree that although some hidden path dependency may well explain
the overall direction of history, the continued existence of normative
contradictions within any given ‘regime complex’9 leaves room for con-
tingencies and even sudden reversals. Importantly, scholars who use the
notion of ‘legal entanglement’ accept that normative contradictions do
not necessarily threaten the working and stability of a transnational legal
order.10 This position departs from the traditional rationalistic view that
a normative system can only be stable if it is based on clear, self-
reinforcing and non-contradictory principles, such that one can derive
from it rules of conduct and agreed-upon punishments in case of viola-
tions. The notion of ‘legal entanglement’ therefore introduces a ‘post-
modern’ perspective11 to modernity’s rationalist project of building
universal rules beyond the nation state based on clear and quasi-
constitutional foundations.
In this chapter, we adopt a similar perspective on ‘legal entanglements’
to explain contemporary dynamics in transnational legal orderings in the
field of security. In particular, we want to explain the normative order by
which states adopt international sanctions against individuals and/or
states which have threatened international security and/or violated
agreed-upon rules. We start from the assumption that sanctions are
better thought of as bodies of norms and practices, also known as
‘sanctions regimes’.12 These sanctions regimes have long been elaborated
at the intersection of various bodies of law, both at the domestic and
international levels, which define principles related to the responsibility
of states and/or norms ensuring the protection of human rights. For
8
M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (Vintage, 1995).
9
Alter and Raustiala, ‘The Rise of International Regime Complexity’.
10
T. C. Halliday and G. Shaffer, Transnational Legal Orders (Cambridge University Press,
2015); D. Halberstam and E. Stein, ‘The United Nations, the European Union, and the
King of Sweden: Economic Sanctions and Individual Rights in a Plural World Order’
(2009) 46 Common Market Law Review 13–72.
11
M. Koskenniemi and P. Leino, ‘Fragmentation of International Law? Postmodern
Anxieties’ (2002) 15 Leiden Journal of International Law 553–79.
12
T. J. Biersteker, S. E. Eckert and M. Tourinho, ‘Thinking about United Nations Targeted
Sanctions’, in T. J. Biersteker, S. E. Eckert and M. Tourinho (eds), Targeted Sanctions: The
Impacts and Effectiveness of United Nations Action (Cambridge University Press, 2016),
pp. 11–37.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
instance, the notion that innocent civilians should not suffer from the
application of sanctions was translated in the United Nations Security
Council (UNSC) sanctions regimes that were once ‘comprehensive’ and
showed little respect to the human rights of populations in sanctioned
areas, and that have become more targeted – or, in other words,
‘smarter’.13 This ‘miniaturization’ of UN sanctions began with various
sanctions against conflict actors in Africa in the late 1990s and early
2000s, and it was further developed with the well-known sanctions
regimes against Iran and North Korea, at least in their earlier stages in
the 2000s. These processes occurred according to different temporalities
and scales depending on where they were located.
This chapter argues that, on the one hand, the developments that have
affected the sanctions regime have strengthened the normative coherence
of the UN system of norms and rules, giving it more legitimacy and
unity. The new UNSC sanctions regime was indeed greeted as a recon-
ciliation of the UNSC’s main responsibility to safeguard international
peace and security with better respect for other pillars of international
law and the UN, namely human rights, which include the right to access
vital goods such as food or medical care.14 On the other hand, it remains
to be seen whether new contradictions have not also spurred from some
of the latest developments in the broader ‘sanctions regime’, which not
only includes the UNSC sanctions but also multiple domestic sanctions
regimes, in particular in the United States and Europe. In contrast to the
story of a clear paradigmatic shift characterized by the emergence of a
new ‘targeted sanctions’ paradigm, relegating to the dustbin of history all
previous forms of comprehensive sanctions that clashed with other UN
norms, we explain how, particularly in counter-proliferation sanctions,
contradictions persisted in the legal entanglements between targeted and
comprehensive logics and in overlapping multilateral and domestic legal
sources of sanctions. We further explain why the presence of such
contradictions in counter-proliferation regimes has gone largely
unnoticed by ‘targeted sanctions’ designers and advocates who do not
use the notion of ‘legal entanglement’.15
13
D. W. Drezner, ‘How Smart Are Smart Sanctions?’ (2003) 5 International Studies Review
107–10.
14
E.g., Article 25 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.
15
J. J. Lew and R. Nephew, ‘The Use and Misuse of Economic Statecraft: How Washington
Is Abusing Its Financial Might’ Foreign Affairs (November/December 2018), 139–49.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
In this chapter, we will thus show the heuristic power of the notion of
‘legal entanglement’ when applied to the evolution of global sanctions
regimes in the last thirty years. To demonstrate how targeted sanctions
regimes in the field of counter-proliferation are best analysed as ‘legal
entanglements’ between targeted and comprehensive logics, as well as
between multilateral and unilateral regimes, the chapter proceeds in three
parts. In Section 9.2, we show how a discourse on the ‘targetedness’ of
sanctions was promoted by sanctions entrepreneurs, policy experts and
international governmental and non-governmental organizations in the
context of the ‘War on Terror’ during which sanctions increasingly
targeted specific individuals listed by states for their association with
non-state networks of terrorists, namely Al Qaeda, the Taliban and later
ISIS. In Section 9.3, we show how the multilateral machinery that was
created in the context of counter-terrorism initiatives, especially under
the aegis of the UNSC, extended its reach to the field of counter-
proliferation, when specific sanctions committees modelled after the Al
Qaeda Sanctions Committee were created in the UNSC to monitor UN
member states’ compliance with new UNSC Resolutions (UNSCRs) that
targeted the Democratic People’s Republic of Korea (DPRK) and Iran’s
sanctioned nuclear activities. In Section 9.4, we show how, during the
early 2010s, the targeted sanctions that the UNSC imposed on the DPRK
and Iran were ‘comprehensivized’. This process of comprehensivization,
we show, followed different pathways: the comprehensivization of UNSC
sanctions occurred either directly at the level of the UNSC (as in the case
of the DPRK), or indirectly (as in the case of Iran), because of the
entanglement between UNSC sanctions with the comprehensive logic
of domestic sanctions adopted in a unilateral fashion by the United States
and the European Union. This was the case regardless of claims by the
USA, and especially by the EU, that their ‘multilateral restrictive meas-
ures’ (as sanctions are called in EU parlance) did not amount to compre-
hensive measures.
Our analysis shows that the legal entanglements between targeted and
comprehensive logics that traverse the global sanctions regimes rest on a
few core mechanisms. These mechanisms include the assertion of judicial
authority by US regulators over the world’s financial transactions
denominated in US dollars; the use of instruments that designated central
actors within designated jurisdictions (in particular, the central banks of
sanctioned states); and the ambiguity of the concept of ‘risk’ held by
global financial actors, which allowed financial institutions to adopt a
‘zero-risk’ approach when it came to the implementation of financial
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
sanctions.16 The ambiguity of this concept of risk, which circulated
through a network of cross-references across regulatory documents,17
led financial institutions to massively cut their operations in the targeted
economy while remaining, on the face of it, within the bounds of the
targeted logic of ‘risk-based approaches’. We conclude by highlighting
key normative reflections that derive from the realization that such
entanglements between targeted and comprehensive logics are central
to the operation of counter-proliferation sanctions.
16
G. Mallard, ‘Governing Proliferation Finance: Multilateralism, Transgovernmentalism
and Hegemony in the Case of Sanctions against Iran’, in E. Brousseau, J.-M. Glachant
and J. Sgard (eds), Oxford Handbook of Institutions of International Economic
Governance and Market Regulation (Oxford University Press, 2019).
17
A. Riles, ‘Models and Documents: Artifacts of International Legal Knowledge’ (1999) 48
International and Comparative Law Quarterly 805–25.
18
M. Finnemore, The Purpose of Intervention: Changing Beliefs about the Use of Force
(Cornell University Press, 2004).
19
M. de Goede and G. Sullivan, ‘Introduction: The Politics of the List’ (2016) 34
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 3–13; for a comprehensive review of
the legal and technical developments in the UNSC counter-terrorism sanction regime, see
G. Sullivan. The Law of the List: UN Counterterrorism Sanctions and the Politics of Global
Security Law (Cambridge University Press, 2020).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
proved too devastating in a less divided world. From 1945 until 1989, the
world was divided into trading blocs; thus, a country that was excluded
by one bloc could still trade with the other bloc. Therefore, ‘sanctions’ in
the sense of trading restrictions applied by the West for instance may
have been comprehensive in design, but never fully sealed off a country.
Furthermore, the UNSC sanctions that were adopted in 1966 against
Rhodesia, and in 1977 against South Africa, were limited to arms embar-
goes. This changed with the end of the Cold War. In 1990, the UNSC
unanimously imposed comprehensive sanctions on Iraq after Saddam
Hussein’s invasion of Kuwait. While these sanctions were modelled on
the initiative of the West, in particular the USA, they were backed by
universal condemnation of the Iraqi act of aggression. These sanctions
initially consisted of an embargo against all Iraqi imports and exports
and were to be applied by all UN member states. Their effects were
drastic and counterproductive: even though exemptions on food and
medical supplies were gradually introduced, the impact on the civilian
population was devastating, while hardly hurting – or, by some accounts,
even strengthening – Saddam Hussein’s regime.20 This paradigmatic case
of comprehensive sanctions convinced the international community to
move towards a targeted design of sanctions to avoid hurting civilians in
sanctioned territories.21
In the following years (i.e. the late 1990s and early 2000s), a ‘trans-
national policy network’ of diplomats, national politicians and academics
promoted these targeted sanctions, consisting of tools such as assets
freezes, travel bans, sectoral economic restrictions and arms embargoes.22
These targeted sanctions became the only type of sanctions imposed by
the UNSC since, with early applications responding to internal armed
20
D. Cortright and G. A. Lopez, The Sanctions Decade: Assessing UN Strategies in the 1990s
(Lynne Rienner, 2000); J. Gordon. Invisible War: The United States and the Iraq Sanctions
(Harvard University Press, 2012).
21
M. W. Reisman and D. L. Stevick, ‘The Applicability of International Law Standards to
United Nations Economic Sanctions Programmes’ (1998) 9 European Journal of
International Law 86–141.
22
T. J. Biersteker, ‘Scholarly Participation in Transnational Policy Networks: The Case of
Targeted Sanctions’, in M. E. Bertucci and A. F. Lowenthal (eds), Narrowing the Gap:
Scholars, Policy-Makers and International Affairs (Johns Hopkins University Press, 2014),
pp. 137–54.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
conflicts in Angola, Sierra Leone, and Liberia in the late 1990s and early
2000s.23 Since then, as a sign of the normative appeal of targeted sanc-
tions, human rights organizations – staunch critics of the comprehensive
sanctions against Iraq – have repeatedly called for the imposition of
targeted sanctions in the context of various civil wars.24 Consequently,
academic literature on sanctions has usually spoken of a clear break
between the comprehensive Iraq sanctions and the post-Iraq era of
‘targeted sanctions’,25 whose coherence with the broader system of UN
norms is emphasized by many.26
In the late 1990s and early 2000s, a series of large-scale terrorist
attacks – most prominently 9/11 – pushed states to confront trans-
national non-state groups as significant threats to their security. The
ensuing War on Terror involved UN targeted sanctions that were similar
in their formal setup to the peacebuilding sanctions put in place in
response to African civil wars, but came with longer lists of targeted
individuals and entities. As a further difference, while early peacebuilding
sanctions included sectoral trade embargoes (such as diamonds), the
targets of counter-terrorism sanctions were too amorphous for such
measures. Instead, these sanctions regimes relied chiefly on financial
measures and travel bans. During the 2000s, under the stimulus of the
UNSC, the financial sector thus became heavily mobilized in the quest
for more efficiency and more targetedness in the fight against individual
terrorists linked to Al Qaeda.27 The range of measures imposed on those
individuals who were added to the list of identified terrorists were (and
continue to be) forceful, including asset freezes and the systematic
screening of all cross-border transactions. Immediately after 9/11, the
United States – and then the UNSC – asked the financial sector to help
them with implementing this targeted logic with measures to counter the
23
D. Cortright and G. A. Lopez, ‘Introduction: Assessing Smart Sanctions: Lessons from the
1990s’, in D. Cortright and G. A. Lopez (eds), Smart Sanctions: Targeting Economic
Statecraft (Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2002), pp. 1–22.
24
A. Niederberger, ‘Expert Networks and the Emergence of Practice in UN Arms Embargo
Monitoring’, Paper presented at EISA PEC 2019 (2019).
25
Biersteker, Eckert and Tourinho, ‘Thinking about United Nations Targeted Sanctions’; E.
Solingen, Sanctions, Statecraft, and Nuclear Proliferation (Cambridge University Press,
2012).
26
R. Nephew, The Art of Sanctions: A View from the Field (Columbia University Press,
2017).
27
J. Zarate, Treasury’s War: The Unleashing of a New Era of Financial Warfare (Hachette,
2013).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
financing of terrorism (CFT). This request inspired new conceptions,
practices and technologies.28 For instance, before 9/11, banks conceived
of financial fraud as a problem of organized crime and corruption and
used almost no digital technology to detect such fraud among their
clients; after 9/11, however, financial watchdogs and software companies
offered their techniques as weapons in the War on Terror, enabling
identification and blocking of specific transactions, as well as automatic
freezing of the money held in suspicious accounts.29 It was, therefore, as
part of the War on Terror that targeted financial measures were devised
and implemented on a large scale.30
Thus, after targeted sanctions were initially designed as a response to
the costly impact of comprehensive sanctions against Iraq (as explained
earlier in this section), the War on Terror played an important role in
further developing and promoting this tool. Throughout the years, the
UNSC made a consistent effort to keep the sanctions directed at the right
targets and not to harm innocent civilians by constantly improving the
technical characteristics of its mode of designation. For instance, the
UNSC sought to specify the identities of targeted terrorists with enough
detail to prevent banks from unintentionally applying the penalties
against ‘false positives’ (i.e. entities or individuals who are mistakenly
identified as sanctioned actors because their names coincide with names
on the sanctions list). After international pressure and legal conflicts in
European countries, the UNSC also created the office of the
‘Ombudsperson’ which gives listed individuals the possibility to appeal
for delisting by demonstrating that they no longer meet the listing
criteria.31 The ‘politics of lists’32 and financial surveillance thus became
intrinsic parts of the logic of targetedness that was developed in the new
War on Terror, first within the Bush administration and later by the
international community at the UNSC level.
28
See Sullivan, The Law of the List.
29
G. Mallard and A. Hanson, ‘Embedded Extra-Territoriality: US Judicial Litigation and the
Global Banking Surveillance of Digital Money Flows’, in C. Beaucillon (ed.), Research
Handbook on Unilateral and Extraterritorial Sanctions (Edward Elgar, 2021), pp. 269–86.
30
M. S. Navias, ‘Finance Warfare as a Response to International Terrorism’ (2002) 73 The
Political Quarterly 57–79.
31
M. de Goede and G. Sullivan, ‘Between Law and the Exception: The UN
1267 Ombudsperson as a Hybrid Model of Legal Expertise’ (2013) 26 Leiden Journal of
International Law 833–54.
32
De Goede and Sullivan, ‘Introduction: The Politics of the List’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
New actors entered the domain of CFT, as counter-terrorism sanctions
incited new cooperation (or intensified existing cooperation) between
member states’ bureaucracies (notably intelligence agencies and treasury
departments), private companies (especially airline companies and global
banks) and international organizations.33 Prominent among the last of
these was the Financial Action Task Force (FATF): an international
organization of like-minded states that was established at a G7 summit
in 1989 with the mandate to ‘examine and develop measures to combat
money laundering’.34 In October 2001 – in the aftermath of 9/11 – the
FATF mandate was then extended from anti-money laundering (AML)
to CFT, leading to FATF’s entry into the field of international security;
as we show in Section 9.3, the mandate was later expanded to include
counter-proliferation finance (CPF). It wasn’t so much the FATF staff
which lobbied to be entrusted with these security-related tasks, as at that
time it possessed little expertise and credentials in international security.
However, according to policy insiders we interviewed, the member states
deemed it preferable to entrust a small organization, largely dependent
upon member state intel, with the tasks of improving CFT strategies and
helping the UNSC enrol the banking sector in its fight against terrorists.
The FATF worked hard to empower member states with ‘better’
legislation through the diffusion of best practices or model law in
AML, CFT or CPF fields, as well as to provide private financial insti-
tutions with knowledge about typical money-laundering and terrorism-
financing schemes.35 As such, the UNSC and the FATF have cooperated
in the elaboration of a logic of targetedness in the design of counter-
terrorism sanctions. In parallel, in the UNSCRs against Iran (for instance,
in UNSCR 1803),36 the UNSC started to make explicit references to and
praise the work of the FATF, and called on all governments to push
legislation addressing financial sector reform that would enable banks
33
See Mallard, ‘Governing Proliferation Finance’.
34
The FATF is an organization with strong expert authority and little legal authority as it
only counts thirty-seven state members (as of 2020, up from thirty-four in 2008) and two
regional organizations (the European Commission and the Gulf Co-operation Council)
among its members. Monitoring and enforcement mechanisms are restricted to its
member states, on the basis of the yearly questionnaire that FATF member states conduct
as self-evaluations of their implementation of the FATF’s core principles (namely its forty
general recommendations and its nine recommendations to counter the financing of
terrorism), and on the basis of periodic mutual evaluations, see J. Johnson, ‘Is the Global
Financial System AML/CFT Prepared?’ (2008) 15 Journal of Financial Crime 7–21.
35
FATF, ‘Typologies Report on Proliferation Financing’ (18 June 2008).
36
UNSC Res 1803 (3 March 2008) UN Doc S/RES/1803.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
and other private financial operators to fully cooperate with the creation
of the new system of targeted sanctions. All international organizations
with a stake in the global sanctions regimes have thus seemed to converge
towards the same goals, well in line with broader UN norms.
When applied against ‘pariah’ states designated by the Bush adminis-
tration in 2003 – in this case, Iran and the DPRK – the same logic of
targetedness that shaped the design of counter-terrorism sanctions meant
that new counter-proliferation sanctions would also avoid hurting the
civilian populations who were not responsible for the undeclared nuclear
programmes.37 After Iran’s file was sent from the International Atomic
Energy Agency (IAEA) Board of Governors to the UNSC in 2006, as well
as after the UNSC passed sanctions against the DPRK in the wake of its
first nuclear test in 2006, the UNSC adopted successive rounds of sanc-
tions against both countries that were targeted rather than comprehen-
sive in scope, and discriminatory rather than non-discriminatory in
nature.38 Their targeted nature was exemplified by the specific designa-
tion of companies and individuals allegedly associated with Iran’s or the
DPRK’s nuclear programmes. These entities were systematically listed
in the appendices of each of the UNSCRs targeting the two countries –
just like the UNSC Al Qaeda sanctions listed scores of names associated
with the terrorist network.
In the case of Iran, for instance, UNSCR 1737, passed in December
2006, banned the supply of specific goods (e.g. nuclear-related material)
to Iran and froze the assets of specific individuals and companies associ-
ated with Iran’s hidden centrifuge programme.39 Similarly, UNSCR 1929,
passed in June 2010, only called upon states to exercise vigilance over the
transactions of the assets of entities associated with the procurement of
illicit goods, such as members of the Iranian Revolutionary Guard Corps
listed in its Annex II.40 The same logic of targetedness characterized UN
sanctions against the DPRK, at least until the end of the Obama presi-
dency, whose focus was on negotiations with Iran rather than the DPRK.
Therefore, the UN counter-proliferation sanctions were indeed initially
devised as targeted sanctions.
37
G. Mallard, ‘Antagonistic Recursivities and Successive Cover-Ups: The Case of Private
Nuclear Proliferation’ (2018) 69 The British Journal of Sociology 1007–30.
38
Zarate, Treasury’s War.
39
UNSC Res 1737 (23 December 2006) UN Doc S/RES/1737.
40
UNSC Res 1929 (9 June 2010) UN Doc S/RES/1929.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The institutionalization of the logic of targetedness in the domain of
counter-proliferation was facilitated by the UNSC’s cooperation with
other international organizations and by intertextuality and cross-
referencing across various actors. As with the counter-terrorism sanc-
tions, the UNSC worked in tandem with other organizations, again
notably with the FATF.41
The UNSC passed UNSCR 1803 in 2008, which commended the
guidelines issued by the FATF that same year with regard to the detection
of suspicious activities in proliferation finance.42 UNSCR 1803 ‘called
upon’ all states to exercise ‘vigilance’ regarding activities of financial
institutions in their territory with banks domiciled in Iran ‘in order to
avoid such financial support contributing to the proliferation sensitive
nuclear activities’ (para. 10), and to report to the UNSC’s Sanctions
Committee on Iran the steps undertaken to this end.
The UNSC and the FATF thus incentivized states and banks to work
towards a decentralized and autonomously targeting financial system, in
which private and public financial institutions are individually respon-
sible for establishing mechanisms to ensure compliance with sanctions
regimes. In principle, these institutions remained committed to the same
logic of targetedness: both FATF documents and UNSCRs promoted
specific measures (like ‘enhanced due diligence’ protocols) that global
banks could adopt in order to conduct proper calculations of the risk of
certain activities of their clients being related to Iran’s sanctioned nuclear
activities. Banks should only prevent those activities if the risk was
substantial. As described in interviews we conducted with US sanctions
specialists, such intertextuality and cross-referencing were strengthened
due to the fact that the same experts (largely Western experts, in particu-
lar those working on sanctions in the US State and Treasury
41
The first important FATF report on counter-proliferation financing was published in
2008, although according to its website, it was only in 2012 that combating proliferation
finance was added to the FATF’s mandate (www.fatf-gafi.org/about/whatwedo/).
42
In the context of the DPRK, it was only in 2013 that UNSCR 2094 referred to the FATF,
when it ‘welcomed’ the FATF’s recommendation 7 and the interpretative note along with
that recommendation, which was newly added to the list of FATF recommendation in
2012. The recommendation simply calls upon states to implement targeted sanctions in
compliance with UNSCRs. As the UNSC ‘urged’ states to apply this recommendation
(more precisely, the FATF’s interpretive note on the recommendation), it did so only in
the preamble of the UNSCR, that is, not as a binding Chapter VII measure. The UNSC
reinforced this call three years later, in 2016, and now in the decision part of the
resolution (UNSCR 2270 from 2016, para. 38), still referring, however, only to recom-
mendation 7 and using the less binding expression to ‘call upon’ states.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
Departments) contributed to the activities of both institutions (the
UNSC and FATF).
Still, some other trends in the sanctions against Iran and the DPRK
force us to rethink the narrative of a clear break with the comprehensive
logic of sanctions. Considering the increasing difficulties that countries
under sanctions (like Iran or DPRK) meet when they have to respond to
the humanitarian needs of their populations,43 does that mean that the
paradigmatic shift towards targeted sanctions has been reverted? Or has
that paradigmatic shift in fact never fully happened, as a comprehensive
logic (or a process of comprehensivization) continued to be produced as
a result of the entanglement between various sanctions regimes, some at
the unilateral level, others at the multilateral level? As UNSC sanctions
haven’t operated in a vacuum since the turn to ‘targeted sanctions’, and
as they have consistently been complemented by domestic sanctions
unilaterally adopted by UNSC permanent member states (especially the
P3 – the USA, the UK and France), has the UNSC relinquished its duty of
ensuring the coherence of its actions vis-à-vis the broader UN normative
system? These questions are especially urgent to ask since the legality and
normative coherence of unilateral sanctions adopted by the P3 with other
UN principles, such as the protection of human rights, has increasingly
been the object of criticism, even from within the UN system, as illus-
trated for instance by the many reports published by the office of the UN
Special Rapporteur on the Negative Impact of Unilateral Coercive
Measures on the Enjoyment of Human Rights.44
43
G. Mallard, F. Sabet and J. Sun, ‘The Humanitarian Gap in the Global Sanctions Regime:
Assessing Causes, Effects and Solutions’ (2020) 26 Global Governance: A Review of
Multilateralism and International Organizations 1–33.
44
OHCHR, ‘Research-Based Progress Report of the Human Rights Council Advisory
Committee Containing Recommendations on Mechanisms to Assess the Negative
Impact of Unilateral Coercive Measures on the Enjoyment of Human Rights and to
Promote Accountability’ (10 February 2015) UN Doc A/HRC/28/74; OHCHR, ‘Report
on the Negative Impact of Unilateral Coercive Measures on the Enjoyment of Human
Rights’ (30 August 2018) UN Doc A/HRC/39/54.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
standard of hitting those responsible while avoiding costs for innocent
civilians.45 However, we argue that those sanctions also entailed a redir-
ection of intervention practices, new types of expertise, technologies and
cooperative engagements that amounted to a loss of control in how
UNSC sanctions were to be implemented by the private parties (global
banks especially) in charge of blocking financial transactions on the basis
of suspicion rather than a demonstrated relation to the nuclear pro-
grammes of Iran or North Korea. In this section, we want to show how
the logic of targetedness that the UNSC and FATF inscribed in the
regulation of counter-proliferation finance was gradually entangled with
a logic of comprehensiveness.
The UNSC’s innovative approach to targeted sanctions went well
beyond the publicization of lists of names of suspected terrorists and
nuclear proliferators, and the description of their financial practices,
found in the documents voted upon by fifteen UNSC and thirty-seven
FATF member states. The powerful states behind the edification of the
new sanctions regimes called for implementation by all states and for
cooperation by private actors around the world (such as global banks and
airline companies), asking them to deeply reform their compliance
systems in order to catch suspicious transactions. It is thus important
to understand UN sanctions and FATF recommendations not simply as
an attempt by the UNSC or FATF to reign in one specific actor (Al Qaeda
and its individual affiliates, or the individual companies and persons
related to the nuclear programmes of Iran and the DPRK), but as an
attempt to govern states – all of them – and to convince them to reform
their banking sectors so as to ensure that they can detect suspicious
transactions and freeze the assets of terrorists and suspected nuclear
proliferators in seconds, without hurting the rest of their population.
Here is, thus, a particular mélange of international and transnational
logics inherent to targeted sanctions, as they target non-state actors
through addressing state jurisdictions. States were furthermore not just
asked to inhibit certain flows of finances, goods and people, but to change
their domestic financial regulations more broadly. This focus on broader
financial regulations was likely promoted by the FATF, as the FATF is
less concerned with individual security threats such as those emanating
from Al Qaeda, Iran or the DPRK, and more with systematic patterns
and risks of abusing the financial system. These more systematic
45
Zarate, Treasury’s War.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
concerns were increasingly integrated into UNSC resolutions, asking all
UN member states to change their domestic jurisdictions.
These demands contain the seed of a ‘comprehensivization’ of sup-
posedly targeted sanctions, as banks worldwide were pushed by the
UNSC and FATF (through the pressure these two international organiza-
tions placed on governments) to become part of a larger governance
infrastructure, whose algorithms automatically hooked the compliance
departments of global banks to the listing decisions of the UNSC and
other entities. Even though the UNSC itself remained rather conservative
with regards to listing individuals (its list of targeted terrorists containing
about 350 individuals/entities), its regulations contributed to a dynamic
of ever-growing lists and their almost automatic adoption by global
banks: the targeting is supposed to become decentralized and automa-
tized at a systematic level, a far cry from the few handpicked, high-profile
targets of the early peacebuilding sanctions whose evolution remained
heavily centralized in the hands of the UNSC.
The banking reforms adopted by the UNSC and FATF have led to the
creation of a system of private ‘algorithmic governance’46 which led to
eternally growing lists that were supposed to capture a fluid enemy. Given
the fluidity of this non-state enemy, the asset-freezing measures could
never be called ‘comprehensive’: soon, private companies such as World-
Check proactively identified targets on their own and sold these listings to
global banks.47 As many compliance officers working in the banking sector
told us in the context of a large-scale interviewing campaign conducted
between 2017 and 2019, once individuals are on a list sold by compliance
software companies to banks, they will remain black-listed by some banks
for the rest of their lives, even if their name is later removed from listings
due to the decision of a court or the UNSC ombudsperson. The exclusion
of individuals has also become maximalist because private companies have
tended to pile up names from not only UNSC listings, but also all the
domestic lists that states from all over the world publicize, rarely having
the means of checking in which jurisdictions any given individual is listed
and therefore just applying all lists globally.
46
F. Pasquale, The Black Box Society (Harvard University Press, 2015); M. Ziewitz,
‘Governing Algorithms: Myth, Mess, and Methods’ (2016) 41 Science, Technology &
Human Values 3–16; S. U. Noble, Algorithms of Oppression: How Search Engines
Reinforce Racism (New York University Press, 2018); C. Katzenbach and L. Ulbricht,
‘Algorithmic Governance’ (2019) 8 Internet Policy Review, https://doi.org/10.14763/2019
.4.1424.
47
De Goede and Sullivan, ‘Introduction: The Politics of the List’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The demands for domestic regulatory change that the UNSC made on
behalf of international security concerns have had other important
implications. Existing literature has analysed it as an indication of the
UNSC becoming a ‘global legislator’.48 Here, however, we want to point
out a different implication, namely the creation of new institutions and
monitoring mechanisms that would contribute to a network of cross-
referencing reports and regulatory guidelines. As the UNSC set up new
sanctions regimes, it instituted new Sanctions Committees, to which it
appended specific Panels of Experts (PoEs), which participated in the
expansion of lists of designated individuals and which changed the
relationship between political negotiation and the rule by experts. PoEs
are mandated to ‘gather, examine and analyze information from States,
relevant United Nations bodies and other interested parties regarding
the implementation of the measures imposed in [the respective reso-
lutions]’ and to ‘make recommendations on actions the Council, or the
Committee or Member States, may consider to improve implementation
of the measures’ in their annual or biannual reports.49 PoEs are supposed
to have the necessary independence from UN member states to scrutinize
the national implementation of specific UNSCRs, like those targeting Al
Qaeda, Iran or the DPRK.
It is necessary to point out that the setup of these PoEs has been
very political, as the nationalities of their members mirror the five
permanent members of the UNSC plus the composition of member
states involved in the broader negotiation with, respectively, Iran and
the DPRK.50 This political dimension of their work goes largely
unacknowledged, even though some observers of the UN sanctions
machinery acknowledge in interviews a divide between PoE members
48
E. Rosand, ‘The Security Council as Global Legislator: Ultra Vires or Ultra Innovative
United Nations and the Law of War’ (2004) 28 Fordham International Law Journal
542–90; K. L. Scheppele, ‘The Migration of Anti-Constitutional Ideas: The Post-9/11
Globalization of Public Law and the International State of Emergency’, in S. Choudhry
(ed.), The Migration of Constitutional Ideas (Cambridge University Press, 2007),
pp. 347–73; N. Krisch, ‘International Law in Times of Hegemony: Unequal Power and
the Shaping of the International Legal Order’ (2005) 16 European Journal of International
Law 369–408; N. Krisch, ‘Decay of Consent: International Law in an Age of Global Public
Goods’ (2014) 108 American Journal of International Law 1–40.
49
UNSC Res 1874 (12 June 2009) UN Doc S/RES/1874, para. 26.
50
For Iran, each of the E3+3 (or, in the language of the UN, the P5+1) sends one expert; for
the DPRK, each of the member states involved in the Six Party talks sends one expert,
plus one further member. In addition, one panel member from a non-aligned country is
added to both panels.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
who adopt a maximalist interpretation of the UNSCRs, which come
closer to the views of the P3, and others who take a minimalist
interpretation closer to the souverainism of Russia and China. It
should be noted that, despite their formal independence, many PoE
members hold a background in national ministries or agencies and
sometime maintain close contacts with their country representatives in
New York or even with their capital throughout the mandate, and
interpret sanctions violations in accordance with their capital’s view.51
As for PoE members from P3 countries, this also entails closer direct
or indirect ties to other multilateral institutions which hold similar
views, like the FATF, or with like-minded think tanks specialized
in the monitoring of the global arms trade or illicit finance, like the
Stockholm International Peace Research Institute or the International
Crisis Group. In their daily practice as PoE members, they are entitled
to escape the logic of pure diplomatic negotiation by checking infor-
mation that they obtain through personal networks and then pushing
for factual consensus on such sensitive issues as sanctions implemen-
tation, enforcement, and redress.52
In the field of CPF, PoEs and the FATF have reinforced each other,
mutually ‘enhanc[ing] their own position by linking up with bodies of
norms produced by other, reputed institutions’.53 In so doing, they
elaborated and universally promoted a set of financial rules that origin-
ated in Western states and was diffused by the P3 to the rest of the world.
To begin with, PoE reports – which are submitted to the UNSC and
made public – regularly refer to FATF reports: for example, the section
on financial sanctions in the first report of the DPRK PoE mostly just
reprinted the heuristics on money laundering from a 2008 FATF report.
Already in its first report on the DPRK sanctions, the PoE recommended
that ‘[a]ll Member States should be encouraged to adopt and implement
the non-proliferation and anti-money-laundering/combating the finan-
cing of terrorism guidelines published by FATF’ (DPRK S/2010/571,
51
This accounts for the DPRK PoE and the Iran PoE (prior to the JCPOA), rather than the
PoEs responsible for African regimes, see: A. Niederberger, ‘Independent Experts with
Political Mandates: “Role Distance” in the Production of Political Knowledge’ (2020) 5(3)
European Journal of International Security 350–71.
52
A. Niederberger, ‘Investigative Ignorance in International Investigations: How United
Nations Panels of Experts Create New Relations of Power by Seeking Information’ (2018)
69 The British Journal of Sociology 984–1006; Niederberger, ‘Independent Experts with
Political Mandates’.
53
See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
recommendation 15).54 We should assume that the term ‘member states’
refers to UN member states here (as it usually does in PoE reports), not
to FATF member states, meaning that the PoE recommended that states
adopt FATF guidelines even if they are not a member of the organization.
Another illustrative example concerns measures against front com-
panies, which have frequently been used to circumvent sanctions: front
companies have been repeatedly problematized in FATF reports,55 but
remained largely ignored by UNSCRs, with the minor exception of a few
designations of front companies in UNSCR 1803 on Iran.56 However,
after the DPRK PoE recommended more systematic measures be force-
fully undertaken against front companies (S/2015/131, recommendation
B7),57 the issue was addressed more systematically in UNSCRs (from
UNSCR 2270/2016).58 This process of cross-citation shows how UNSC
permanent member states, like the United States, the United Kingdom or
France, who place a lot of attention on the work of the FATF, can
leverage the work of PoEs to raise the relevance of certain issues related
to sanctions implementation, CFT or CPF in the global international
security agenda; and how they can use the UNSC and its complex insti-
tutional architecture to commend FATF recommendations at multiple
levels.
PoEs have played another important role by increasing the frequency
of the monitoring and evaluation of national financial sanctions adopted
by the UNSC. PoEs have sometimes gone beyond the FATF, which has a
relatively thorough monitoring mandate involving eighteen-months of
mutual evaluations, but at distant intervals – every five years or so. In
contrast, PoEs conduct all-year-long, more or less independent investi-
gations of any UNSC sanctions breaches reported by states, and issue up
to two reports per year. Through their monitoring activities, the FATF
and the PoEs participate in strengthening the expert belief that new
‘targeted’ sanctions always need to be added to past rounds of sanctions,
according to a logic of a continuous progress in the detection of new
54
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 12 May 2010 from the Panel of Experts Established Pursuant to
Resolution 1874 (2009) Addressed to the President of the Security Council’ (5 November
2010) UN Doc S/2010/571.
55
FATF, ‘Typologies Report on Proliferation Financing’.
56
See UNSC Res 1803.
57
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 23 February 2015 from the Panel of Experts Established Pursuant to
Resolution 1874 (2009) addressed to the President of the Security Council’ (23 February
2015) UN Doc S/2015/131.
58
UNSC Res 2270 (2 March 2016) UN Doc S/RES/2270.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
types of practices and actors associated with illicit finance and sanctions
violations. Whereas new measures are usually only added to an existing
sanctions regime in response to actions that threatened international
security and/or constitute a serious breach of the existing sanctions
regime, PoE reports are routinely suggesting new targets to existing
sanctions, based on the discovery of new methods or actors of sanctions
evasion. With the precise enumeration of verified violation cases by PoEs,
and the submission of their documentation to the scrutiny of the UNSC
and its Sanctions Committees, the PoEs diffuse the view that new sanc-
tions designations shall always improve the system of ‘targetedness’ and
perfect the sanctions regimes already in place. Typical demands in PoE
reports on the DPRK, for instance, are to close down new shell com-
panies and new circuits of exchange (from cash economies to hawalas or
networks exchanging digital currencies), which are created by prolifer-
ators in response to past rounds of targeted sanctions. PoEs not only seek
to verify the validity of leaked intelligence and public information on new
sanctions evasion techniques, but also lobby the UNSC member states to
pass new rounds of sanctions meant to close the observed loopholes.
Whether such an accumulation of targets leads to the progressive com-
prehensivization of sanctions or whether they can remain targeted in
scope and discriminatory in nature is the question that we assess in
Section 9.4.
Some examples illustrate how PoEs have encouraged states to go
beyond the explicit requirements of UNSCRs and leave the ethos of
diplomatic prudence in favour of a more expert-based justification for
independent monitoring and forceful implementation of all of the
UNSCRs’ obligations and recommendations by UN member states. For
instance, the UNSC decided in 2013 that member states shall prevent
transfer of bulk cash through/to/from their territories if it ‘could contrib-
ute to the DPRK’s nuclear or ballistic missile programmes, or other
activities prohibited by resolutions’ (2094/2013 para. 11, emphasis added;
UNSCR 2270 subjected gold transports to the same measures).59 The
term ‘could’ is ambiguous and may invite very broad interpretations, but,
if interpreted along a logic of targetedness, the measures should refer to
cases with a credible risk that the gold/cash is being used for prohibited
purposes. However, the wording suggests a broader interpretation, rec-
ommending that smuggled bulk cash or gold by DPRK nationals should
59
UNSC Res 2094 (7 March 2013) UN Doc S/RES/2094, para. 11.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
be frozen and that member states ‘ensure that [frozen gold/cash
amounts] cannot be used for prohibited activities or evasion of sanctions
before releasing them’ (S/2017/150, para. 253).60 Ensuring that assets
cannot be used for prohibited tasks is a higher threshold pertaining to
an eventual future that goes beyond the threshold of a credible risk that
was more likely implied by the UNSCR.
To add another example, in UNSCR 2321,61 the UNSC decided that
‘all States shall take steps to limit the number of bank accounts to
one per DPRK diplomatic mission and consular post, and one per
accredited DPRK diplomat and consular officer, at banks in their
territory’. The PoE repeatedly asked member states to go beyond these
measures; in the following year, it passed the recommendation that
member states ‘must ensure that additional accounts are not estab-
lished in the names of family members’ (S/2017/742 recommendation
C 5).62 Yet another year later, the PoE also recommended that
member states apply the restrictions to all embassy personnel,63 as
opposed to only the ‘accredited DPRK diplomat and consular officers’
mentioned in the UNSCR.64 A year later, the PoE recommended that
states provide banks with a list of names of all family members of
DPRK diplomats, to ensure that diplomats cannot open bank accounts
in their names65 and that only one bank within each country be
allowed to hold accounts of DPRK diplomats.66 Furthermore,
the PoE recommended that ‘Member States advise their financial
60
PoE reports gave extensive evidence of sanctions evasions through the smuggling of cash
and gold and that the PoE should thus feel a responsibility to propose counter-measures;
likewise, the same report containing those recommendations stated that such contraband
is frozen only exceptionally by states anyways; see UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 17 February 2017
from the Panel of Experts Established Pursuant to Resolution 1874 (2009) Addressed to
the President of the Security Council’ (27 February 2017) UN Doc S/2017/150.
61
UNSC Res 2321 (30 November 2016) UN Doc S/RES/2321, para. 16.
62
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 28 August 2017 from the Panel of Experts Established Pursuant to
Resolution 1874 (2009) Addressed to the President of the Security Council’ (5 September
2017) UN Doc S/2017/742.
63
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 1 March 2018 from the Panel of Experts Established Pursuant to
Resolution 1874 (2009) Addressed to the President of the Security Council’ (5 March
2018) UN Doc. S/2018/171, para. 210, recommendation 3.
64
Ibid.
65
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 21 February 2019 from the Panel of Experts Established Pursuant to
Resolution 1874 (2009) Addressed to the President of the Security Council’ (5 March
2019) UN Doc S/2019/171, para. 161.
66
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 21 February 2019 from the Panel of Experts’, para. 162.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
institutions not to open accounts for diplomats of the Democratic
People’s Republic of Korea who are not accredited to their country’,67
based on the finding that North Korean embassies have served as
traditional conduits of illicit financing. Still, if DPRK diplomats are
prohibited, per UNSCRs, from holding more than one bank account, it
lies in the discretion of the UNSC and its Sanctions Committee to
designate any third-party individual assisting in the violation of this
rule and there is, as of now, no UNSCR demanding that banks target
family members of diplomats or that diplomats should not be allowed
to choose a bank of their preference. The PoE thus recommends states
to prevent sanctions evasions by recommending additional sanction-
ing measures that are not asked for by the UNSC. This is the very logic
of illicit finance expertise that PoE members have endorsed.
A last example shows how private financial actors, too, can respond
to the recommendations of the PoEs. In its 2017 report, the PoE on
DPRK sanctions remarked that the Society for Worldwide Interbank
Financial Telecommunication (SWIFT) maintained in its system
North Korean banks that were designated for special attention by
the UNSC.68 As SWIFT is (only) the messenger between banks
exchanging value through its system, and to the extent that banks
are supposed to conduct the risk analysis related to specific payments
(depending on a range of criteria), SWIFT’s decision to keep these
banks in its system may not have appeared a case of violation of the
new UNSCR to its managers. Indeed, SWIFT provides the infrastruc-
ture that allows money to flow between accounts, and it leaves to those
using that messaging infrastructure and ordering the money move-
ments (e.g. banks sending messages through SWIFT) the responsibility
to comply with the rules of UNSC, EU and US sanctions, and any
other local systems of sanctions that may apply. This view of SWIFT’s
neutrality, however, was strongly challenged in the run-up to the Iran
nuclear deal, when the P3 repeatedly asked SWIFT to disconnect some
Iranian banks from its system between 2012 and 2015, and yet again
after the USA left the Joint Comprehensive Plan of Action (JCPOA)
after 2018. After the publication of this 2017 DPRK PoE report,
SWIFT cut off the last North Korean banks from its messaging
networks, thus cutting the whole North Korean formal financial
67
Ibid., para. 163.
68
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 28 August 2017 from the Panel of Experts’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
system from the global network.69 In so doing, the Belgian-based
financial organization implemented what looks like comprehensive
rather than targeted sanctions against North Korea’s financial system.
It may have responded to the pressure due to the publication of the
PoE report, or it may also have been retaliating due to the fact that the
DPRK had manipulated its system by hacking the financial software
that SWIFT sells to banks in order to initiate transfers of funds from
one bank to another. In fact, in the last five years, it is estimated that
the DPRK made more than US$1 billion in this way,70 a huge sum
compared to the income that the DPRK regime generated over the
same period from arms sale in certain African countries, like Namibia
or Ethiopia.71 These hacks may have convinced SWIFT that it needed
the protection of the long arm of US judicial authorities to chase the
hackers, bring them to justice and thus obtain a deterrent against
other hacks in order to re-establish its credibility in the market of
financial data management equipment.72 Whatever the reason, the
publication of the PoE report was likely factored into its calculation
69
T. Bergin, ‘SWIFT Messaging System Cuts Off Remaining North Korean Banks’, Reuters
(14 March 2017), www.reuters.com/article/us-northkorea-banks/swift-messaging-
system-cuts-off-remaining-north-korean-banks-idUSKBN16N2SZ.
70
Bloomberg, ‘U.S. Sanctions North Korean Hackers for Swift Hack, Wannacry and Other
Cyberattacks that Fund Its Weapons Programs’, Japan Times (14 September 2019), www
.japantimes.co.jp/news/2019/09/14/asia-pacific/u-s-sanctions-north-korean-hackers-
swift-hack-wannacry-cyberattacks-fund-weapons-programs/#.XibZ1L97nq1.
71
Notorious victims include the Bangladesh Bank, whose money (to the amount of US$80
million) held in accounts at the New York Fed, was ordered in 2015 and 2016 to be
transferred to the benefit of DPRK-controlled entities elsewhere (see FireEye, ‘North
Korean Hackers Used Swift Network to Steal More Than $100m – Fireeye’ Finextra (5
October 2018), www.finextra.com/newsarticle/32742/north-korean-hackers-used-swift-
network-to-steal-more-than-100m—fireeye). The fake money orders sent through
SWIFT were impossible to distinguish from real money orders, which exposed vulner-
abilities in the global SWIFT messaging system prior to the release of the 2017 PoE
report. See also S. Pham, ‘North Korea Still Making Millions from Small Arms Exports’
CNN (14 September 2017), https://money.cnn.com/2017/09/14/news/north-korea-small-
arms-trade/index.html.
72
The US judicial authorities are the only ones with such sweeping powers thanks to the
International Emergency Economic Powers Act, which lets them indict persons for
comparably small offenses like giving a conference on Blockchain technology in the
DPRK as an attempt to ‘conspire’ to violate the Act (See J. Brett, ‘Internet Man of
Mystery Virgil Griffith Indicted for Crypto Trip to North Korea’, Forbes (11 January
2020), www.forbes.com/sites/jasonbrett/2020/01/11/internet-man-of-mystery-virgil-grif
fith-indicted-for-crypto-trip-to-north-korea/#2514738d18b0).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
when SWIFT decided to cut off the whole financial system of the
DPRK regime from its messaging system.
It is understandable that PoEs would come up with strict interpret-
ations of sanctions implementation, given that they are supposed to
conduct monitoring and see themselves confronted with numerous
violations. What matters in our context, however, is that the PoE
recommends to member states that they take a maximalist interpret-
ation of measures in UNSCRs that is mutually reinforcing with FATF
recommendations and the comprehensive sanctions favoured by the
USA in its campaign for ‘maximum pressure’ against states like Iran
and the DPRK. It is worth emphasizing that the PoEs also formulate
recommendations to the UNSC Sanctions Committees, which the
UNSC Committees then discuss and vote upon. And even if Sanctions
Committees do not act upon these recommendations, today, public and
private authorities use the biannual PoE reports as interpretation guide-
lines for UNSCRs. As a consequence, PoE reports have shaped the
expectations of the financial industry and their willingness to take risks,
as each exchange in goods or financial transaction carries a remaining
risk of inadvertently violating sanctions, should one, for instance, fall
victim to deception or incomplete information. Just like the FATF,
PoEs have continuously stressed that both private and public actors
must be made aware of the importance of adopting a ‘risk-based
culture’.73 But this call for a ‘risk-based culture’ can be interpreted very
differently: either that you should accept that every decision comes with
the risk of making the wrong decision, and that risks are part of life; or
that you should take no risk of making a mistake by authorizing
suspicious payments, especially when the penalty for making the wrong
decision is too high. Clearly, the latter became the dominant interpret-
ation, and this extension of the domain of what can be considered a
‘risky activity’ plays a role in the comprehensivization of sanctions, so
we argue.
73
UNSC, ‘Letter Dated 1 March 2018 from the Panel of Experts’, para. 210 (recommenda-
tion 2): ‘The Panel recommends that Member States, as part of their implementation of
the financial provisions of the resolutions, ensure that their financial institutions imple-
ment a risk-based approach to identifying sanctions violations in their “know-your-
customer” and compliance programmes . . . To that end, Member States should provide
their financial institutions with more detailed and regular information on sanctions
evasion risks.’
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
9.4 The External Dynamics in the Comprehensivization of
Sanctions: Legal Entanglements between Multilateral and
Domestic Sanctions
If the institutional innovations of the 2000s may give the impression of a
general, sudden and unbeatable adoption of the targeted sanctions para-
digm, and a stark contrast to the comprehensive sanctions against Iraq,
some other trends already highlighted point to the entanglements
between targeted and comprehensive logics as well as multilateral and
unilateral sanctions regimes. One reason for this is that targeted sanc-
tions were embedded in a broader decentralized network of comprehen-
sive domestic prohibitions on any type of trade with certain countries
under UNSC sanctions, especially Iran. We have already identified vari-
ous facilitating dynamics in the entanglement of targeted and compre-
hensive logics at the level of the UNSC, which were most prevalent in the
case of the DPRK, where the ‘maximum pressure’ campaign has been
steered by the UNSC itself.
However, in cases like Iran, the UNSCRs only served to give a legal basis
for sanctions that were otherwise mostly adopted in a unilateral manner,
supposedly to ‘complement’ ‘soft’ UNSCRs that only ‘called upon’ states to
adopt certain financial restrictions. In this case, the decentralization of
targeting practices at the level of the P3, and the ‘deputization’ of sanctions
implementation to Western-led global banks in charge of enforcing finan-
cial sanctions, as well as the inherent tendency of lists to grow74 under the
proactive efforts of private sector vendors of sanctions lists, were much more
influential processes explaining the comprehensivization of UNSC sanctions
than efforts by PoEs and other international organizations like FATF. In
what follows, we focus on a key driver of the entanglement between
comprehensive (domestic) and targeted (UN-based multilateral) logics: a
change in the notion of risk that was particularly fostered by US regulators.
While this section further works out the role of the USA as a key actor in
fostering this entanglement, it also shows how ‘the scope of relevant actors
goes well beyond the governmental [or intergovernmental] sphere’75 by
pointing out the important role of private financial institutions. As the history
of the last ten years of US judicial prosecution of financial crime shows,76
74
De Goede and Sullivan, ‘Introduction: The Politics of the List’.
75
See Chapter 1.
76
G. Mallard and J. Sun, ‘Viral Governance: How the US Unilateral Sanctions against Iran
Changed the Rules of Financial Capitalism’ American Journal of Sociology, under review.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
financial institutions have come to adopt a strategy of complete risk aversion
with regards to sanctions under the influence of two important mechanisms:
the adoption of comprehensive sanctions by the United States against Iran
and the DPRK, and the extraterritorial effect of such unilateral sanctions on
multinational companies – even outside the USA. These multinational com-
panies were thus forced to choose between applying those sanctions to their
global activities or facing the risk of exclusion from the US financial sector.
Hence, when considering the risk of imposing comprehensive sanctions on
civilian populations in Iran, global banks weighted another risk: that of being
excluded from the leading world market and losing all of their US revenues.
Furthermore, many of the UNSC sanctions against Iranian businesses
involved prohibitions related to trade finance, and when they were framed
by additional sanctions adopted by the USA and then by the EU (with the
prohibition, after 2011, of oil import and export as well as of investment,
insurance and credit related to the oil trade), it became easy for the US
government to use the UNSCRs against Iran as a lever to police the activities
of the world’s leading banks in general, and the field of trade finance in
particular.
For two decades, domestic US legislative acts slowly built up a
comprehensive net that was supposed to catch any activity involving
Iranian oil and the import/export of other commodities, with preten-
sions of legal extraterritoriality. At the domestic level, beginning in
1994 the USA passed the Nuclear Proliferation Prevention Act and
Executive Order (EO) 12938 instituting a ban on US procurement from
any person who, on or after 30 June 1994, knowingly and materially
contributes, through the export of nuclear-related goods or technology,
to the efforts of any individual, group or non-nuclear weapon state to
acquire a nuclear explosive device or unsafeguarded special nuclear
material. Through EO 12938, President Clinton declared a ‘state of
emergency’ with respect to the proliferation of weapons of mass
destruction. Then, the Export-Import Bank Act of 1996 instituted a
ban on access to credit to any person who, after 23 September 1996,
knowingly aided or abetted a non-nuclear weapon state to acquire a
nuclear explosive device or unsafeguarded material, like Iran’s enriched
uranium not currently placed under IAEA safeguards. In the 2000s, a
number of EOs complemented this legal basis, leading up to EO 13622,
and EO 13645, which was adopted in 2013 and which prevented
European and Japanese car companies present in Iran from continuing
to sell cars and spare parts to the Iranian market. In parallel, the US
Congress also passed a wide range of acts which banned trade with Iran
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
and claimed extraterritorial competence: from the Helms–Burton Act
to the 2011 Comprehensive Iran Sanctions, Accountability, and
Divestment Act to the Iran Freedom and Counter-Proliferation Act
and the Nuclear Iran Prevention Act of 2013 as well as various Defense
Appropriation Acts in the early 2010s. During this period, reports
abound of US pressure exerted directly by the US Treasury on foreign
banks without going through national finance ministries, to directly
push them ‘to stop dealing with Iran’.77
Taken together, these US ‘emergency’ measures with extraterritorial
ambitions banned credit, guarantees or insurance in support of
exports to Iranian sanctioned individuals; forbade US imports from
sanctioned entities; and froze the assets of Iranian sanctioned entities
within US jurisdiction even before a trial could be held. From
2008 until 2015, wholesale sectoral prohibitions (especially targeting
Iran’s financial sector), which had been opposed – and specifically
vetoed – by the Russian and Chinese governments in the UNSC, were
unilaterally added post hoc by EU and US governments in the form of
domestic instruments. For private actors like global banks, applying
only the targeted sanctions of the UNSCRs against Iran would thus
have meant ignoring US and EU sanctions, and exposing themselves
to the ‘risk’ of committing sanctions violations in the two largest
economies of the world, even if the transactions concerned didn’t take
place in the USA or Europe.
Some banks originally contemplated such action, but they were con-
vinced to change strategy and take maximal measures to avoid any kind
of financial contact with individuals and entities targeted by the US
Treasury – and not only with them, but also with entities that may be
suspected of carrying a second or third degree of relationship with such
targeted entities, as interviewees in Washington told us. In a few years,
from 2005 to 2015, the US government levied fines against global banks
that handled transactions to Iran and Sudan which were prohibited
under US law (but not under UNSC resolutions or even EU law) if these
transactions were denominated in US dollars. These fines amounted to
billions of dollars, as in the case of the fine that BNP-Paribas had to pay
to US authorities for clearing transactions in its New York branch related
77
S. Fayazmanesh, The United States and Iran: Sanctions, Wars and the Policy of Dual
Containment (Routledge, 2008), p. 198; see also S. Fayazmanesh, ‘The Politics of the US
Economic Sanctions against Iran’ (2003) 35 Review of Radical Political Economics 221–40.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
to Iranian oil proceeds coming from or going to Iran and Iranian entities
that were denominated in US dollars.78
Our interviewees, who worked as compliance officers in private finan-
cial institutions before the signing of the JCPOA, insisted that it was
impossible to apply the logic of targeted sanctions to Iran during this
period: for them, the potential benefits of admitting Iranian clients or
carrying out transactions from/to Iran were not worth the intense vetting
procedures that would have been required each time; furthermore, the
remaining risk of unwittingly admitting prohibited transactions despite
such vetting procedures was even less acceptable. While it is true that
entities linked to either Iran’s or now North Korea’s nuclear programmes
have taken many covert identities and used many masks to hide their
links to these programmes, with this amount of suspicion in these cases,
banks and their compliance departments that were asked by the UNSC to
adopt ‘vigilance’ and its associated concepts of ‘enhanced due diligence’
in fact stopped calculating the risks associated with every transaction and
rather engaged in wholesale practices of derisking.79
The signing of the JCPOA didn’t change that situation, as it left in place
many US domestic sanctions based on the US designation of many Iranian
entities as linked to groups (like Hezbollah) that the US government
designated as terrorists, which meant that global banks were still wary of
too quickly changing their regulation with regard to Iran. After the JCPOA
was signed, the logic of targetedness should have meant that, with the
lifting of the comprehensive EU and US trade sanctions that targeted the
oil trade and investment activities in Iran, the financial sanctions would
have been lifted at the same time as sectoral restrictions. This is not what
happened. The post-JCPOA situation in Iran suggests that sanctions
against Iran followed the logic of comprehensive sanctions.80 According
78
For instance, see Department of Justice, ‘Standard Chartered Deferred Prosecution
Agreement’ (2012), www.justice.gov/opa/pr/standard-chartered-bank-agrees-forfeit-227-mil
lion-illegal-transactions-iran-sudan-libya-and; OFAC (Office of Foreign Assets Control,
U.S. Treasury Dept.), ‘BNP Paribas Deferred Prosecution Agreement’ (2014), www.treasury
.gov/resource-center/sanctions/CivPen/Documents/20140630_bnp_settlement.pdf.
79
P.-E. Dupont, ‘Compliance with Treaties in the Context of Nuclear Non-proliferation:
Assessing Claims in the Case of Iran’ (2013) 19 Journal of Conflict and Security Law
161–210; Mallard, Sabet and Sun, ‘The Humanitarian Gap in the Global Sanctions
Regime’; Department of Justice, ‘Standard Chartered Deferred Prosecution Agreement’;
OFAC (Office of Foreign Assets Control, U.S. Treasury Dept.), ‘BNP Paribas Deferred
Prosecution Agreement’.
80
P. Clawson, ‘Sanctions as Punishment, Enforcement, and Prelude to Further Action’
(1993) 7 Ethics & International Affairs 17–37.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
to the logic of comprehensive sanctions (and, as previously illustrated in
the case of sanctioned individuals whose names are likely to stay on the
financial sector’s blacklists forever, even if they have been delisted by the
UNSC), once a country has been labelled as a ‘cause of money laundering
concern’ by the organizations in charge of issuing such statements (e.g. the
FATF, or the US Treasury and its Office of Foreign Assets Control
(OFAC)), it becomes almost impossible for that country and its economy
to be brought back into the community of global banks.
It is therefore not a surprise that, after the Iran nuclear deal of 2015, the
first law that Iran contemplated was the so-called ‘FATF bill’ – heatedly
debated in the Iranian Parliament – which required that Iranian banks
adopt AML and CFT measures promoted by the FATF in order to
convince the FATF to change its designation of Iran as a country of
money-laundering concern. But even as this legislative effort was pursued
in Iran, it was clear that the efforts would hardly bring a change in the
FATF’s assessment of Iran’s political economy, not to speak of OFAC’s
assessment, and that the reinclusion of Iranian financial institutions (after
years of exclusion) was next to impossible, even if the JCPOA explicitly
called on European private companies and banks to work towards Iran’s
economic recovery by investing massively in its oil sector.
This path dependency illustrated the comprehensive logic of CPF sanc-
tions. It was reinforced, in the specific case of Iran, by the decision made by
the US president to pull out of the JCPOA, despite the fact that UNSCR
2231 gives it the force of law. After 2018, banks faced for the first time a
stark option: either follow the logic of targeted sanction, by applying only
the prohibitions contained in the UNSCRs, or to follow US domestic
changes in their worldwide activities. Their over-cautious behaviour, and
their refusal to touch any oil-financing schemes in Iran clearly shows
which direction they have chosen to follow since 2018. It is unlikely that,
even with the change in the US administration, the contradictions between
US and multilateral sanctions will be eliminated and that the logic of
targetedness will be strictly followed in the counter-proliferation field.
9.5 Conclusion
Today, many international organizations, including the World Bank81 or
the International Monetary Fund (IMF), have issued warnings after
81
World Bank, ‘De-risking in the Financial Sector’ (7 October 2016) www.worldbank.org/
en/topic/financialsector/brief/de-risking-in-the-financial-sector.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
realizing that global banks and other financial actors have massively
pulled out of sanctioned jurisdictions as they applied sanctions in a
comprehensive manner rather than by implementing narrow sanctions
exclusively targeting the culprits responsible for a country’s wrong policy
course.82 International organizations such as the IMF or the World Bank
see such cases of overcompliance as illegitimate in an age when compre-
hensive sanctions are no longer deemed appropriate under new norms of
‘civilized’ state conduct. Still, global banks and other financial actors are
not solely responsible for that ‘comprehensivization’ of sanctions: the
movement is spurred by the entanglements between targeted and compre-
hensive logics, especially in the field of counter-proliferation sanctions.
These legal entanglements have been patiently weaved together by a
proliferation of other international organizations, including the FATF
and the Panel of Experts created by the UNSC Sanctions Committees,
particularly those verifying the implementation of sanctions against Iran
and the DPRK. Together, these organizations have participated in the
creation of a fiction which implies that ‘targetedness’ would necessarily
rhyme with ‘narrowness’, when in fact ‘targetedness’ is not necessarily
incompatible with ‘comprehensiveness’: if the list of ‘targets’ is gradually
or suddenly extended to become all-encompassing, then targeted sanctions
could be both targeted and comprehensive in principle.
If we observe a general trend towards the ‘comprehensivization’ of so-
called ‘targeted’ sanctions, then why do all these institutions still claim to
design, monitor and enforce ‘targeted’ sanctions? In fact, we claim that
the logic of targetedness is no longer an empirical fact, or even a policy
goal, which would be shared by UNSC member states, but it has become
a functional assumption that is necessary for the system to continue
operating. By implicitly accepting that states are compartmentalized
and cannot be assumed to be in full control of their many state agencies
nor private actors, all the organizations which claim that the system
operates under the logic of targetedness enact a useful charade or ‘fic-
tion’83 that allows all governments to distance themselves from the
entities suspected of breaching US, EU or UNSC sanctions: if parts of a
government are blamed by a PoE or by a foreign government branch (the
US Department of Justice or OFAC in particular) for sanctions violation,
the central authorities can always claim that such entities couldn’t have
82
Mallard, Sabet and Sun, ‘The Humanitarian Gap in the Global Sanctions Regime’.
83
A. Riles, Collateral Knowledge: Legal Reasoning in the Global Financial Markets
(University of Chicago Press, 2011).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
acted on behalf of the state, and that they weren’t responsible for such
failings. Here, the logic of ‘targetedness’ – with its separation between
states and individual perpetrators – protects member states and thus
makes their consent to sanctions, including sanction enforcement and
monitoring, more likely.
We not only see this protective mechanism functioning in the cases of
US sanctions enforcement against Europe’s major banks (from BNP-
Paribas to HSBC), in which European governments have largely turned
their eyes away from the settlements, but also during PoE investigations,
as in the case of the DPRK. It is standard practice for most UNSC PoEs
that PoE members would never publish information in their report
without first giving the monitored state (for instance, Russia, Vietnam
or Ethiopia) the chance to either deny and disprove accusations or work
to solve problems. Thus, where PoEs uncover sanctions violations in a
given country, they tend not to link violations to governments as a whole
but only to specific actors or entities within a country (even if the actors
in question are state agencies). For instance, as reported by the DPRK
PoE in 2018 in the case of Russia, Russian companies that forged joint
ventures with DPRK state companies in violation of UNSC sanctions
needed to be investigated, and the PoE members could gain Russia’s
support for their investigations by allowing the government to claim that
such entities had violated the government’s will if they did create such
joint ventures. By operating under the assumption that states are not
complicit in sanctions violations before having been alerted of the exist-
ence of these violations by PoEs or by OFAC investigations, multilateral
and domestic investigatory bodies give them the benefit of the doubt, and
strengthen the belief that a few bad apples within the state may have
covered up such illegal behaviours, or that miscommunication problems
within complex administrations may have prevented such information
from surfacing. Investigatory bodies in the field of sanctions enforcement
normally use this assumption as a public script when interacting with
states or private actors, even where they may find it hard to believe it
themselves.
In this chapter, we have also identified several reasons why UNSC
member states (especially the P3) have preferred to entangle a compre-
hensive set of interventions with a targeted sanction regime, rather than
imposing comprehensive sanctions in the first place: first, the lack of
legitimacy of blatantly comprehensive regimes, at least since the Iraq
case; second, the fact that within the UNSC, Russia and China, and
sometimes European states, would not agree to adopt comprehensive
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
?
sanctions against a UN member state, as they are rather critical of
sanctions; and third, because the fiction that enforcement actions against
sanctions violations should also be targeted helps protect UN member
states from being accused of having been complicit in sanction violations,
which means, in turn, that sanctions violators are likely to opt more often
for cooperation rather than conflict when accused of misdeeds.
Sanctions experts and policy-makers who pursue an interest in
upholding peace and the rule of international law through sanctions
(rather than war) as well as a concern for human rights may be con-
vinced of the necessity to fight the trend towards comprehensivization, as
it risks creating the same human rights disasters in Iran, Venezuela or
Syria today that were witnessed in Iraq in the 1990s. They may see this
trend as a distortion of their original intent and a misuse of the instru-
ments of algorithmic governance that they collectively created. However,
we argue that the financialization of the sanctions regimes bore in its
premises an inherent dynamic towards comprehensivization, which
could only reveal itself after the first wave of sanctions were adopted
and implemented, when contradictions between comprehensive domes-
tic sanctions regimes and narrower multilateral sanctions regimes were
partially solved to the benefit of the former, with one reason being the
private financial sector’s changing notion of ‘risk’.
To that extent, we believe that the concept of legal entanglement,
which places the focus of socio-legal scholars and international organiza-
tions specialists at the intersection between these domestic, transnational
and multilateral dynamics, is particularly useful to social scientists who
are dissatisfied with the old notion of ‘international regime’, even
reworked through the use of the updated notion of ‘regime complexity’,
as well as to policy-makers who are interested in reconciling sanctions
with a concern with human rights. Its use suggests that although efforts
to arrive at a more coherent system of rules are welcome, they rarely
achieve complete success, and that regimes traversed by a plurality of
contradictory rules are not inherently unstable: to the contrary, such legal
entanglements can be quite stable over time.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
10
Lex mercatoria, lex petrolea, lex electronica and lex sportiva have grad-
ually entered the mainstream vocabulary of legal scholarship as phenom-
ena highlighting the functionalization and privatization of law in a
globalizing world.1 They embody what are often qualified as distinct
legal orders or systems arising out of transnational communities segre-
gated along functional lines.2 This chapter aims to show that the work of
the Court of Arbitration for Sport (CAS), which is often identified as the
institutional centre of the lex sportiva,3 can be understood as that of a
seamstress weaving a plurality of legal inputs into authoritative awards.
In other words, the CAS panels are assembling legal material to produce
(almost) final decisions that, alongside the administrative practices of
sports governing bodies (SGBs), govern international sports. It is argued
that, instead of purity and autonomy, the CAS’s judicial practice is best
characterized by assemblage and hybridity. This argument will be sup-
ported by an empirical study of the use of different legal materials, in
particular pertaining to Swiss law, EU law and the European Convention
1
Gunther Teubner has been a precursor in charting this transformation, see G. Teubner,
‘Global Bukowina: Legal Pluralism in the World-Society’, in G. Teubner (ed.), Global Law
without a State (Dartmouth, 1996), pp. 3–28 and G. Teubner, ‘Breaking Frames: Economic
Globalization and the Emergence of Lex Mercatoria’ (2002) 5 European Journal of Social
Theory 199–217. For a general overview of the by now extremely vast literature, see R.
Michaels, ‘Global Legal Pluralism’ (2009) 5 Annual Review of Law and Social Science
243–62.
2
Specifically, on the role of transnational communities, see R. Cotterrell, ‘Transnational
Communities and the Concept of Law’ (2008) 21 Ratio Juris 1–18.
3
See F. Latty, La lex sportiva: Recherche sur le droit transnational (Brill, Nijhof, 2007) and L.
Casini, ‘The Making of a Lex Sportiva by the Court of Arbitration for Sport’ (2011) 12
German Law Journal 1317–40.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
on Human Rights (ECHR), within the case law of the CAS. The view
advanced here should not be confused with one arguing that the CAS is
fully integrated into the Swiss legal order, the EU legal order or into a
monistic international legal order. Its main claim is that the judicial
practice of the CAS can be captured as the work of a seamstress weaving
‘different bodies of norms with one another’4 and that lex sportiva can
‘no longer be understood without an account of the ways in which its
different parts are entangled’.5
The CAS plays a central role in the governance of international sports
as the main judicial body to which athletes, clubs or federations can turn
to challenge the decisions of international SGBs.6 Its core function in
global sports governance is to act as a review mechanism through its
appeal procedure which is regulated by the Code of Sports-Related
Arbitration (CAS Code).7 Thus, the CAS is dealing with almost all the
high-profile disputes that occupy the sports pages (and sometimes
beyond) of our newspapers. It decided whether Caster Semenya or
Oscar Pistorius can participate in athletics competitions,8 it determined
whether Michel Platini or Sepp Blatter can be banned from football for
violating FIFA’s (Fédération Internationale de Football Association)
ethics rules9 and it assessed whether Maria Sharapova or Alejandro
Valverde have committed a violation of the World Anti-Doping Code
(WADC).10 In short, very few of the fundamental decisions that shape
the way we experience international sports escape the CAS. While there
is no doubt that international sports are being ruled by a transnational
4
See Chapter 1.
5
Ibid.
6
The latest CAS statistics available indicate that 458 appeals procedures were initiated in
2016. See www.tas-cas.org/fileadmin/user_upload/CAS_statistics_2016_.pdf.
7
On the appeal procedure, see Articles R47 to R59 of the CAS, Code of Sports-Related
Arbitration 2019 (entered into force 1 January 2019) (‘CAS Code’). For a detailed
commentary of these provisions, see A. Rigozzi and E. Hasler, ‘Commentary on the
CAS Procedural Rules’, in M. Arroyo (ed.), Arbitration in Switzerland: The Practitioner’s
Guide (Kluwer Law International, 2013), pp. 982–1060.
8
CAS 2018/O/5794, Mokgadi Caster Semenya v. International Association of Athletics
Federations, award of 30 April 2019 and CAS 2008/A/1480 Pistorius v. IAAF, award of
16 May 2008.
9
TAS 2016/A/4474, Michel Platini v. FIFA, award of 9 May 2016 and CAS 2016/A/4501
Joseph S. Blatter v. FIFA, award of 5 December 2016.
10
CAS 2016/A/4643, Maria Sharapova v. International Tennis Federation (ITF), award of
30 September 2016 and CAS 2009/A/1879 Alejandro Valverde Belmonte v. Comitato
Olimpico Nazionale Italiano, award of 16 March 2010.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
regime in which private associations play a fundamental role and dispose
of considerable regulatory powers, this regime also provides an interest-
ing terrain to study transnational legal entanglements.11
To this end, I focus on the way the CAS produces its awards. I aim to
show that the lex sportiva is not an isolated set of norms produced by an
autonomous community but results from the blending of different laws
assembled through discursive weaving by CAS panels. In this regard, not
all national laws are equal at the CAS and, as we will see in Section 10.1,
Swiss law is more equal than the others. In practice, the CAS panels draw
heavily on Swiss law, its actors, doctrines, rules and decisions.12 Despite
being a global court, the CAS remains anchored (physically, sociologic-
ally and legally) in a local context. In addition to Swiss law, Sections 10.2
and 10.3 highlight how CAS arbitrators are also weaving references to EU
law and the ECHR into their awards. This chapter is a first attempt at
looking at the hermeneutic practice of the CAS from the perspective of a
transnational legal pluralism that goes beyond the identification of a
plurality of autonomous orders to turn its sights towards the enmesh-
ment and entanglement characterizing contemporary legal practice.13
11
For another attempt, see A. Duval, ‘What Lex Sportiva Tells You about Transnational
Law’, in P. Zumbansen (ed.), The Many Lives of Transnational Law: Critical Engagements
with Jessup’s Bold Proposal (Cambridge University Press 2019), pp. 269–93.
12
A. Rigozzi, ‘L’importance du droit suisse de l’arbitrage dans la résolution des litiges
sportifs internationaux’ (2013) 1 ZSR 301–25.
13
See P. Zumbansen, ‘Transnational Legal Pluralism’ (2010) 1 Transnational Legal Theory
141–89 and J. Klabbers and G. Palombella (eds), The Challenge of Inter-Legality
(Cambridge University Press, 2019).
14
A full text search (in the CAS appeal awards) of ‘Swiss law’ in the CAS database yields hits
in 1031 CAS awards (out of 1,636 appeal awards included in the database). A comparable
search of ‘German law’, ‘Italian law’ and ‘French law’ yields exactly the same number of
awards: nineteen. These searches were all conducted on the same date (11 December
2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
cases Swiss law will be subsidiarily applicable under R58 CAS Code
which determines the applicable law and acts very much as a ‘reception
norm’ in the sense outlined in Chapter 1.15 Furthermore, the appeals are
often based on CAS arbitration clauses enshrined in the statutes of the
SGBs which can expressly provide for the application of Swiss law.16
Second, the legal seat of the CAS is Lausanne. Hence, its awards can only
be appealed at the SFT where they are reviewed, relatively leniently, on
the basis of Article 190(2) of the Swiss Private International Law Act.17
The CAS panels are naturally aware of the need for their awards to pass
this (relatively low) bar and therefore pay specific attention to Swiss law
in their decisions. Finally, arbitrators, lawyers or administrators active at
the CAS often have a Swiss background.18 In this section, I aim to
substantiate the depth of the entanglement between Swiss law and CAS
awards through a case study focused specifically on appeals against FIFA
decisions.
15
R58 CAS Code (2019 version) provides: The Panel shall decide the dispute according to
the applicable regulations and, subsidiarily, to the rules of law chosen by the parties or, in
the absence of such a choice, according to the law of the country in which the federation,
association or sports-related body which has issued the challenged decision is domiciled
or according to the rules of law the Panel deems appropriate. In the latter case, the Panel
shall give reasons for its decision.
16
See, for example, the Article 57(2) FIFA Statutes 2019 discussed further in Section 10.1.1.
17
On the limited scope of this review, see A. Rigozzi, ‘Challenging Awards of the Court of
Arbitration for Sport’ (2010) 1 Journal of International Dispute Settlement 217–65.
18
Lindholm in a recent empirical study of the CAS identified a high number of Swiss parties
and arbitrators active at the CAS, see J. Lindholm, The Court of Arbitration for Sport and
Its Jurisprudence: An Empirical Inquiry into Lex Sportiva (T.M.C. Asser Press, 2019),
pp. 270–4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
family’)19 and therefore bound by the choice of Swiss law enshrined in
Article 57(2) FIFA Statutes 2019.20
Yet, the applicability of Swiss law is not only justified by the parties’
contractual choice but also on functional grounds, that is, in order to
‘level the playing the field’ in football disputes. For example, a CAS panel
concluded in 2005 that the ‘indispensable need for the uniform and
coherent application worldwide of the rules regulating international
football’ is secured ‘[o]nly if the same terms and conditions apply to
everyone who participates in organized sport’.21 Similarly, another panel
concluded, ‘if the desired uniformity is to be achieved, also the interpret-
ation of the FIFA rules and regulations cannot be affected by the peculi-
arities of the domestic legal system in which they are called to apply’.22
Thus, appeals against FIFA decisions will necessarily trigger the applica-
tion of Swiss law ‘for all the questions that are not directly regulated by
the FIFA Regulations’.23 In this context, ‘there is no place for the
application of the rules of another national law, except in the case where
these rules would have to be considered as mandatory according to the
law of the seat of the arbitration, i.e. Swiss law’.24
Nevertheless, based on the wording of R58 CAS Code, Swiss law
should not prevail over the express choice of law of the parties.25 Even
19
CAS 2013/A/3165, FC Volyn v. Issa Ndoye, award of 14 January 2014, para. 68.
20
CAS 2008/A/1517, Ionikos FC v. C., award of 23 February 2009, paras 7 and 17; CAS
2006/A/1180, Galatasaray SK v. Frank Ribéry and Olympique de Marseille, award of
24 April 2007, para. 13. See also CAS 2008/A/1482, Genoa Cricket and Football Club S.p.
A. v. Club Deportivo Maldonado, award of 9 February 2009, para. 18.
21
TAS 2005/A/983 and 984, Club Atlético Peñarol v. Carlos Heber Bueno Suarez, Cristian
Gabriel Rodriguez Barrotti and Paris Saint-Germain, award of 12 July 2006, para. 24. See
also in CAS 2006/A/1180, para. 13; CAS 2006/A/1123, Al-Gharafa Sports Club v. Paulo
Cesar Wanchope Watson and CAS 2006/A/1124, Paulo Cesar Wanchope Watson v. Al-
Gharafa Sports Club, award of 18 December 2006, para. 12; CAS 2008/A/1517; CAS 2011/
A/2375, FK Dac 1904 a.s. v. Zoltan Vasas, award of 31 October 2011; CAS 2013/A/3165,
para. 67; TAS 2014/A/3505, Al Khor SC v. C., award of 3 December 2014, para. 85; CAS
2014/A/3742, US Città di Palermo S.p.A. v. Goran Veljkovic, award of 7 April 2015,
para. 47.
22
CAS 2006/A/1123, para. 13. Similarly, see CAS 2013/A/3383–3385, Volga Nizhniy
Novgorod v. Levan Silagadze, award of 13 November 2014, para. 48 and TAS 2016/A/
4569, Abdelkarim Elmorabet v. Olympic Club Safi and Fédération Royale Marocaine de
Football (FRMF), award of 20 September 2016, para. 5.8.
23
CAS 2005/A/871, FC Rodopa v. Markovitch, award of 19 September 2006, para. 4.15. Or
‘if there is a gap in the FIFA regulations’, CAS 2013/A/3165, para. 69.
24
CAS 2009/A/1956, Club Tofta Itróttarfelag, B68 v. R., award of 16 February 2010,
para. 15.
25
CAS 2006/A/1024, FC Metallurg Donetsk v. Leo Lerinc, para. 27.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
then, recent awards determined that such cases give ‘rise to a co-existence
of the applicable regulations, Swiss law and the law chosen by the
Parties’, in which ‘Swiss law is confined to ensuring uniform application
of the [FIFA] Regulations’.26 In other words, in order to protect the
uniform interpretation of FIFA Regulations, Swiss law is deemed to
supersede the parties’ choice of law.27 This view, first advanced by
Professor Ulrich Haas, was subsequently endorsed as the ‘Haas doctrine’
by a series of CAS panels.28 Finally, if FIFA Regulations are considered
sufficiently clear and comprehensive by the CAS panels, Swiss law does
not come into play, as it ‘does not supersede or supplant all aspects of the
regulations of FIFA’.29 Yet in practice, as Section 10.1.2 shows, the FIFA
Regulations are often ambiguous and in need of interpretation.
26
CAS 2016/A/4605, Al-Arabi Sports Club Co. For Football v. Matthew Spiranovic, award of
22 February 2017, para. 5.6. See also CAS 2017/A/5341, CJSC Football Club Lokomotiv
v. Slaven Bilic, para. 59.
27
See CAS 2010/A/2316, Stoke City FC v. Brescia Calcio S.p.A., award of 6 December 2011,
para. 20.
28
See U. Haas, ‘Applicable Law in Football-Related Disputes: The Relationship between the
CAS Code, the FIFA Statutes and the Agreement of the Parties on the Application of
National Law’ (2015) Bulletin TAS/CAS Bulletin 7. CAS 2016/A/4605, para. 5.6; CAS
2017/A/5341, paras 57 and 59; CAS 2017/A/5465, Békéscsaba 1912 Futball v. George
Koroudjiev, award of 20 September 2018, paras 74 and 76; CAS 2017/A/5402, Club Al-
Taawoun v. Darije Kalezic, award of 7 June 2018, para. 89; CAS 2016/A/4471, Abel
Aguilar Tapias v. Hércules de Alicante FC, award of 2 February 2017, paras 69–70; CAS
2016/A/4859, Hong Kong Pegasus FC v. Niko Tokic, award of 30 June 2017, paras 60–1;
TAS 2016/A/4569, paras 5.8 and 5.9.
29
CAS 2012/A/2919, FC Seoul v. Newcastle Jets FC, award of 24 September 2013. In other
words, FIFA regulations apply in ‘priority’, TAS 2005/A/983 and 984, para. 49.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
30
CAS 2008/A/1521, VfB Admira Wacker Modling v. A.C. Pistoiese s.p.A., award of
12 December 2008; CAS 2010/A/2316; CAS 2013/A/3365, Juventus Football Club S.p.A.
v. Chelsea Football Club Ltd and CAS 2013/A/3366, A.S. Livorno Calcio v. Chelsea
Football Club Ltd, award of 21 January 2015.
31
CAS 2008/A/1485, FC Midtjylland A/S v. Fédération Internationale de Football
Association (FIFA), award of 6 March 2009 and TAS 2016/A/4490, RFC Seraing
v. Fédération Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), award of 9 March 2017.
32
CAS 2006/A/1206, Milan Zivadinovic v. Iraqi Football Association (IFA), award of 2 April
2007; CAS 2006/A/1192, Chelsea Football Club Limited v. Adrian Mutu, award of 21 May
2007; CAS 2007/A/1329, Chiapas F.C. v. Cricuma Esporte Clube and CAS 2007/A/1330,
Chiapas F.C. v. R., awards of 5 December 2007; CAS 2008/A/1518, Ionikos FC v. L., award
of 23 February 2009; CAS 2012/A/2906, Alain Geiger v. Egyptian Football Association
(EFA) and Al Masry Club, award of 12 February 2013; TAS 2013/A/3351, Fédération de
Football de la République Islamique de Mauritanie (FFRIM) and ASAC Concorde v. CS
Hammam-Lif and Fédération Tunisienne de Football (FTF) and Fédération Internationale
de Football Association (FIFA), award of 24 January 2014; CAS 2013/A/3278, Maritimo de
Madeira – Futebol SAD v. Desportivo Brasil Participacoes LTDA, award of 2 June 2014;
CAS 2017/A/5227, Sporting Clube de Braga v. Club Dynamo Kyiv and Gerson Alencar de
Lima Junior, award of 8 March 2018; CAS 2017/A/5352, FK Sileks v. GFK Dubočica
Leskovac, award of 24 April 2018.
33
CAS 2009/A/1909, RCD Mallorca SAD and A. v. Fédération Internationale de Football
Association (FIFA) and UMM Salal SC, award of 25 January 2010; CAS 2009/A/1956;
CAS 2013/A/3444, S.C. FC Brasov S.A v. Renato Ferreira Da Silva Alberto, award of 29
October 2015.
34
CAS 2011/A/2354, E. v. Fédération Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), award
of 24 August 2011; CAS 2015/A/3883, Al Nassr Saudi Club v. Jaimen Javier Ayovi Corozo,
award of 26 August 2015.
35
CAS 2008/A/1521; CAS 2010/A/2316; CAS 2013/A/3207, Tout Puissant Mazembe
v. Alain Kaluyituka Dioko and Al Ahli SC, award of 31 March 2014.
36
CAS 2016/A/4720, Royal Standard de Liège v. FC Porto (Player T.), award of 19 May
2017 and CAS 2016/A/4721, Royal Standard de Liège v. FC Porto (Player C.), award of
19 May 2017.
37
CAS 2006/A/1100, E. v. Club Gaziantepspor, award of 15 November 2006; CAS 2007/A/
1210, Ittihad Club v. Sergio Dario Herrera, award of 3 July 2007; TAS 2007/A/1233, FC
Universitatea Craiova v. Marcos Honorio Da Silva and TAS 2007/A/1234, FC Universitatea
Craiova v. Eduardo Magri, awards of 19 December 2007; CAS 2008/A/1447, E.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
cases involving FIFA decisions. It is relevant to a majority of appeals
against the decisions rendered by international SGBs. It shows that the
CAS is not engaging in the production of denationalized awards with
little connection to state law. Instead, it is weaving the local and the
global, as the transnational private rules of the SGBs are being entangled
with norms, case law and doctrinal authorities grounded in Swiss law.
What might, from a distance, appear like a sort of global law without a
state is actually intimately linked to, and reliant on, the law of the
Swiss state.
The fact that Swiss law has a prominent position at the CAS is not an
original claim. Scholars and practitioners had emphasized it before.44
Yet, it raises interesting questions connected to the theme of this
volume, which have so far been widely ignored. How are the CAS
panels applying Swiss law? What is the purpose and effect of this
entanglement between Swiss law and the private regulations of the
SGBs? What is the responsibility of Switzerland with regard to the
shape of the transnational sporting regime? How can Swiss law be
leveraged to change the shape of this regime in one way or another?
These questions can become relevant only once we perceive the lex
sportiva as a transnational assemblage and see the fundamental role of
Swiss law in it. This intertwining of normative material at the CAS
extends, in much more limited fashion, to other types of legal filaments,
such as EU law or the ECHR.
44
A. Rigozzi, ‘L’importance du droit suisse de l’arbitrage’.
45
A. Duval, ‘La Lex Sportiva face au droit de l’Union européenne: guerre et paix dans
l’espace juridique transnational’, PhD thesis, EUI (2015). On the interaction between EU
law and sport, see S. Weatherill, Principles and Practice in EU Sports Law (Oxford
University Press, 2017).
46
Case C-415/93, Union royale belge des sociétés de football association ASBL v. Jean-Marc
Bosman, Royal club liégeois SA v. Jean-Marc Bosman and others and Union des associ-
ations européennes de football (UEFA) v. Jean-Marc Bosman [1995] ECR I-04921.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
until recently quite absent from the CAS.47 Nevertheless, in an important
award dating back to 1999, a CAS panel already recognized the applic-
ability of EU law. It found:
With regard to EC competition law, the Panel holds that, even if the
parties had not validly agreed on its applicability to this case, it should be
taken into account anyway. Indeed, in accordance with Article 19 of the
LDIP, an arbitration tribunal sitting in Switzerland must take into con-
sideration also foreign mandatory rules, even of a law different from the
one determined through the choice-of-law process, provided that three
conditions are met:
(a) such rules must belong to that special category of norms which need
to be applied irrespective of the law applicable to the merits of the case
(so-called lois d’application immédiate);
(b) there must be a close connection between the subject matter of the
dispute and the territory where the mandatory rules are in force;
(c) from the point of view of Swiss legal theory and practice, the
mandatory rules must aim to protect legitimate interests and
crucial values and their application must allow an appropriate
decision.48
47
A. Duval, ‘The Court of Arbitration for Sport and EU Law: Chronicle of an Encounter’
(2015) 22 Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 224–55.
48
CAS 98/200, AEK Athens and SK Slavia Prague v. Union of European Football
Associations (UEFA), award of 20 August 1999, para. 10.
49
Before 2010, we find mentions of EU law in the following CAS awards publicly available
in the CAS database (on 1 September 2019): TAS 92/80, B. v. Fédération Internationale de
Basketball (FIBA), award of 25 March 1993; CAS 98/200; TAS 2000/A/290, Abel Xavier
and Everton FC v. Union des Associations Européennes de Football (UEFA), award of
2 February 2001; TAS 2002/A/423, PSV Eindhoven v. Union des Associations Européennes
de Football (UEFA), award of 3 June 2003; TAS 2004/A/708, Philippe Mexès v. Fédération
Internationale de Football Association (FIFA) and TAS 2004/A/709, AS Roma v. FIFA and
TAS 2004/A/713, AJ Auxerre c. AS Roma and Philippe Mexès, awards of 11 March 2005;
CAS 2005/A/951, Guillermo Cañas v. ATP Tour, revised award of 23 May 2007; CAS
2006/A/1125, Hertha BSC Berlin v. Stade Lavallois Mayenne FC, award of 1 December
2006; CAS 2007/A/1272, Cork City FC v. FIFA (Healy), award of 15 October 2007; CAS
2007/A/1287, Danubio FC v. Fédération Internationale de Football Association (FIFA)
and FC Internazionale Milano S.p.A., award of 28 November 2007; CAS 2008/A/1485;
CAS 2008/A/1644, M. v. Chelsea Football Club Ltd., award of 31 July 2009; CAS 2009/A/
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
addressing at length EU law questions.50 Such a development is poten-
tially related to the greater sensitivity of legal counsels to EU law and to
the arbitrators’ growing awareness of the considerable risk that the cases
would in fine reach the European Commission or the CJEU. In general,
EU law has found two main applications at the CAS: it has been
mobilized to challenge the legality (even constitutionality) of the SGBs’
regulations and it has been constructed as part and parcel of the
SGBs’ regulations.
1757, MTK Budapest v. FC Internazionale Milano S.p.A., award of 30 July 2009; CAS
2009/A/1788, UMMC Ekaterinburg v. FIBA Europe e. V., award of 29 October 2009.
50
For deep engagements with EU law, see, for example: TAS 2016/A/4490 and CAS 2016/
A/4492, Galatasaray v. UEFA, award of 3 October 2016.
51
The centrality of the idea of justification in the European integration process has been
theorised by J. Neyer, The Justification of Europe: A Political Theory of Supranational
Integration (Oxford University Press, 2012).
52
See TAS 2000/A/290, para. 17.7; CAS 2005/A/951, para. 29; CAS 2008/A/1644, para. 44.
53
CAS 2007/A/1272, para. 32; CAS 2007/A/1287, paras 37–40; CAS 2009/A/1757, paras
29–30; CAS 2009/A/1810 and 1811, SV Wilhelmshaven v. Club Atlético Excursionistas
and Club Atlético River Plate, award of 5 October 2009, paras 48–9; CAS 2009/A/1957,
Fédération Française de Natation (FFN) v. Ligue Européenne de Natation (LEN), award of
5 July 2010, paras 37–40; CAS 2013/A/3119, Dundee United FC v. Club Atlético Vélez
Sarsfield, award of 20 November 2013, paras 70–1; CAS 2014/A/3710, Bologna FC 1909 S.
p.A. v. FC Barcelona, award of 22 April 2015, para. 81.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of recent cases, the CAS panels quite comprehensively engaged in a
proportionality assessment of the reviewed regulations.54
More precisely, in the Galatasaray55 and Seraing56 awards, delivered in
2016 and 2017, the CAS was asked to review the compatibility of two
controversial rules introduced respectively by the Union of European
Football Associations (UEFA) and FIFA. It is interesting to note that
Jean-Louis Dupont, who represented Jean-Marc Bosman, was acting for
the claimants in both cases. The Galatasaray case involved the UEFA
Club Licensing and Financial Fair Play Regulations (UEFA FFP
Regulations) and their compatibility with EU law. It is not the right place
to revisit the debate on the compatibility of the UEFA FFP Regulations
with EU law, but it is interesting to note that the CAS panel decided to
conduct a comprehensive proportionality analysis relatively similar to the
one that would have been conducted by the European Commission or
the CJEU if they were asked a similar question. Likewise, the Seraing case,
in which the Belgian club was challenging the validity under EU law of
FIFA’s 2015 ban on third-party ownership, also led to the integration of a
proportionality analysis grounded in EU law into the CAS award.57 In
both cases, the CAS concluded that the regulations were pursuing a
legitimate objective and represented necessary and proportionate means
to attain that objective.
It is uncertain whether the CJEU or the European Commission would
reach the same conclusion, but the above awards highlight that the two
CAS panels were in the position of decentralized EU law enforcers, not
unlike national courts but without the obligation or capacity to refer a
preliminary question to the CJEU. The question whether the CAS is
applying EU law properly, for example as the CJEU would, is almost
impossible to settle until a case reaches Luxembourg. A review of the
CAS awards involving EU law shows that the SGBs’ regulations are very
54
CAS 98/200; CAS 2009/A/1788, paras 22–47; CAS 2012/A/2852, S.C.S. Fotbal Club CFR
1907 Cluj S.A. and Manuel Ferreira de Sousa Ricardo and Mario Jorge Quintas Felgueiras
v. Romanian Football Federation (FRF), award of 28 June 2013; CAS 2014/A/3561 and
3614, International Association of Athletics Federation (IAAF) and World Anti-Doping
Agency (WADA) v. Marta Domínguez Azpeleta and Real Federación Española de
Atletismo (RFEA), award of 19 November 2015, paras 172–91; TAS 2016/A/4490; CAS
2016/A/4492.
55
CAS 2016/A/4492. See my commentary in A. Duval, ‘CAS 2016/A/4492, Galatasaray
v. UEFA, Award of 3 October 2016’, in A. Duval and A. Rigozzi (eds), Yearbook of
International Sports Arbitration 2016 (T.M.C. Asser Press, 2017), pp. 377–91.
56
TAS 2016/A/4490.
57
TAS 2016/A/4490, paras 90–144.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
rarely deemed in contravention of EU law. In fact, there is only one
example in which a CAS panel struck down an SGB regulation on this
basis.58 It involved the Romanian Football Federation (FRF) and its
home-grown players regulations, which imposed a fixed quota of locally
trained players in the teams of Romanian clubs participating in national
competitions. The panel was not convinced that the FRF had demon-
strated that its regulations were necessary and proportionate. In any
event, the use of EU law as a vehicle to conduct a constitutional check
of the SGBs’ regulations constitutes another (rare) form of legal entangle-
ment at the CAS. Additionally, beyond this constitutional role, EU law is
also directly interwoven in the genome of the FIFA RSTP.
10.2.2 Interpreting the FIFA RSTP with a Little Help from EU Law
After the Bosman ruling, FIFA devised a new transfer system regulating
the transnational movement of football players between clubs.59 This
new system, however, was quickly challenged at the European
Commission on the basis of EU competition law and a protracted
negotiation started between the European Commission, FIFA, the
players’ union FIFPro, the European Club Association and UEFA.60 It
concluded with the adoption of the general principles upon which the
FIFA RSTP is officially grounded.61 This peculiar transnational geneal-
ogy of the RSTP became relevant at the CAS because panels have
considered that, insofar as the statutes of large entities are concerned,
‘it may be more appropriate to have recourse to the method of interpret-
ation applicable to the law’ and therefore adopt a ‘contextual
approach’ that entails reviewing the legislative history and purpose.62
58
See CAS 2012/A/2852.
59
On the FIFA RSTP and its interpretation by the FIFA Dispute Resolution Chamber in
general, see F. De Weger, The Jurisprudence of the FIFA Dispute Resolution Chamber
(T.M.C. Asser Press, 2016).
60
For a detailed history of this episode of transnational law-making, see A. Duval, ‘The
FIFA Regulations on the Status and Transfer of Players: Transnational Law-Making in
the Shadow of Bosman’, in A. Duval and B. Van Rompuy (eds), The Legacy of Bosman:
Revisiting the Relationship Between EU Law and Sport (T.M.C. Asser Press, 2016),
pp. 81–116.
61
European Commission, ‘Outcome of Discussions between the Commission and FIFA/
UEFA on FIFA Regulations on International Football Transfers’ (press release IP/01/314,
5 March 2001).
62
CAS 2013/A/3365 and 3366, para. 143.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The first case involving an interpretive use of EU law was the Mexès
case which concerned the interpretation of Articles 21(1) and 23(1) FIFA
RSTP 2001 edition.63 The key question was whether the prolongation of
the contract of a professional football player would trigger an extension
of the stability period – a period during which the player could not leave
the club without risking a sporting sanction. To answer this question, the
Panel analysed the question in light of EU law as it decided to go back to
the ratio legis of the provisions to determine their concrete meaning.64
The text of the award refers to the Bosman ruling as well as to the
decision of the European Commission in the competition law case
opened against FIFA.65 Hence, to support its decision, the CAS panel
felt that it had to grapple with EU law requirements, although whether it
did so in an orthodox fashion is another matter. This first example of
recourse to EU law as part of the relevant context for a proper interpret-
ation of the RSTP was endorsed in following awards.66 Most promin-
ently, in a case pitching the Italian football clubs Juventus F.C. and A.S.
Livorno Calcio against the English club Chelsea F.C., the CAS provided
an extensive analysis of this interpretive link between EU law and the
RSTP.67 The case was related to the legal saga surrounding Chelsea’s
2005 dismissal of Adrian Mutu over his consumption of cocaine. The
CAS panel considered it necessary to do an in-depth review of the
legislative history of the FIFA RSTP in order to determine whether
Article 14(3) FIFA RSTP 2001 edition applied, and therefore whether
Juventus and Livorno jointly owed a considerable transfer fee to Chelsea.
In doing so, it carefully scrutinized the case law of the CJEU and the
decisions of the European Commission.68 This led the arbitrators to
reject the interpretation advanced by Chelsea as contrary to the EU law
63
TAS 2004/A/708 and 709 and 713.
64
Ibid., paras 24–30.
65
Ibid., paras 25–6.
66
See CAS 2006/A/1125, paras 43–7; CAS 2010/A/2316, para. 37; CAS 2016/A/4903, Club
Atlético Vélez Sarsfield v. The Football Association Ltd., Manchester City FC and
Fédération Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), award of 16 April 2018, paras
91–105.
67
CAS 2013/A/3365 and 3366. See A. Duval, ‘CAS 2013/A/3365 Juventus FC v. Chelsea FC
and CAS 2013/A/3366 A.S. Livorno Calcio S.p.A. v. Chelsea FC, Award of 21 January
2015’, in A. Duval and A. Rigozzi (eds), Yearbook of International Sports Arbitration 2015
(T.M.C. Asser Press, 2016), pp. 155–68.
68
CAS 2013/A/3365 and 3366, paras 149–57.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
foundations of the RSTP and to conclude that Livorno and Juventus were
free to recruit Adrian Mutu without compensation after his dismissal.69
As demonstrated, EU law finds its relatively narrow way at the CAS.
This limited enmeshing of EU law in CAS awards is most likely driven by
external challenges to the SGBs’ regulations and decisions in national
courts or before EU institutions. In fact, EU law’s capacity to disrupt the
authority of CAS is certainly a (rational) pathway to drive the entangle-
ment of EU law into its awards.70 However, by harnessing EU law, the
CAS panels might also be betraying it. The CAS is not referring questions
to the CJEU and CAS awards are, for reasons of costs and time, rarely
challenged in national courts on EU law basis. In the absence of system-
atic control of CAS awards, the panels’ approach to EU law escapes the
possibility of direct oversight by EU institutions. In other words, CAS
might be speaking an EU law dialect that is primarily fitted to the needs
and power structure of its social context, while at the same time formally
proximate to and at a substantial distance from the EU law of the EU
institutions.71
69
Ibid., paras 161–3.
70
Most recently in the ISU decision of the European Commission, see Case AT.40208 –
International Skating Union’s Eligibility rules, 8 December 2017.
71
On the dialectic between proximity and distance in the context of legal entanglements, see
Chapter 1, Section 1.4.3.
72
For a general summary of the ECtHR cases applying to sport, see ECtHR, ‘Sport and the
European Convention on Human Rights, Factsheet’ (October 2019), www.echr.coe.int/
Documents/FS_Sport_ENG.pdf. However, few of the cases mentioned are directly related
to the regulations or decisions of SGBs.
73
See Mutu and Pechstein v. Switzerland, app. no. 40575/10 and 67474/10, judgment of
2 October 2018; Fédération Nationale des Syndicats Sportifs (FNASS) and Others
v. France, app. no. 48151/11 and 77769/13, judgment of 18 January 2018; Platini
v. Switzerland, app. no. 526/18, judgment of 11 February 2020.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
regularly mentioned in CAS awards.74 Even though some panels
expressed ‘serious doubts’75 regarding the applicability of the ECHR to
the SGBs’ private regulations or even sometimes squarely denied it,76
when confronted with claimants invoking the ECHR most CAS awards at
least considered its application. This inconsistency can be traced back to
the unstable composition of CAS panels and non-binding nature of CAS
precedents. In any event, most panels at least emphasized the need to
respect the procedural rights enshrined in Article 6(1) ECHR.77 Indeed, a
panel ‘should nevertheless account for their [the provisions of the ECHR]
content within the framework of procedural public policy’.78 In a more
direct language, a sole arbitrator found ‘rather obvious’ that ‘a federation
cannot opt out from an interpretation of its rules and regulations in light
of principles of “human rights” just by omitting any references in its rules
and regulations to human rights’.79 In this latter version, the ECHR
seems to be even assimilated to an ‘overarching norm’.80
74
See for a general overview U. Haas, ‘Role and Application of Article 6 of the European
Convention on Human Rights in CAS Procedures’ (2012) 3 International Sports Law
Review 43–60.
75
CAS 2008/A/1513, Emil Hoch v. Fédération Internationale de Ski (FIS) and International
Olympic Committee (IOC), award of 29 January 2009, para. 9.
76
See CAS 2009/A/1957, para. 14; TAS 2011/A/2433, Amadou Diakite v. Fédération
Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), award of 8 March 2012, para. 23; TAS
2012/A/2862, FC Girondins de Bordeaux v. Fédération Internationale de Football
Association (FIFA), award of 11 January 2013, paras 106–7.
77
The first award in this regard is TAS 2000/A/290, para. 10. The ECHR is seen as
’indirectly applicable’ (TAS 2011/A/2433, para. 24) and CAS Panels as ‘indirectly bound’
(CAS 2015/A/4304, Tatyana Andrianova v. All Russia Athletic Federation (ARAF), award
of 14 April 2016, para. 46). See also CAS 2013/A/3139, Fenerbahçe SK v. Union des
Associations Européennes de Football (UEFA), award of 5 December 2013, para. 93.
78
CAS 2011/A/2384, Union Cycliste Internationale (UCI) v. Alberto Contador Velasco and
Real Federación Española de Ciclismo (RFEC) and CAS 2011/A/2386, World AntiDoping
Agency (WADA) v. Alberto Contador Velasco and RFEC, award of 6 February 2012,
para. 22.
79
CAS 2015/A/4304, para. 45.
80
See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the arbitration clause on the basis of the ECHR.81 In order to allow the
case to proceed, the CAS had to determine whether the clause was
compatible with the ECHR. The main argument advanced by the claim-
ant was that the unequal bargaining power between the parties to the
arbitration (i.e. the athlete and the SGB) threatened the validity of the
arbitration agreement. The panel considered that ‘[i]f – according to this
jurisprudence of the ECtHR – the right of access to the courts enshrined
in Art. 6.1 ECHR can be subject to a weighing up in the event that
arbitral jurisdiction is prescribed by statute, then the same must apply
also in a case of unequal bargaining power’.82 Therefore, it concluded:
‘only if there were no reasons in terms of “good administration of justice”
in favour of arbitration a violation of article 6.1 ECHR could be acknow-
ledged’.83 As the panel, maybe unsurprisingly, identified some reasons
which justified that CAS arbitration was linked to the ‘good adminis-
tration of justice’, it decided that the arbitration agreement was valid
under the ECHR.84
Furthermore, the CAS jurisdiction in appeal cases is dependent on the
conditions enshrined in statutory arbitration clauses enshrined in the
SGBs’ regulations. This has led in particular to challenges, on the basis of
the ECHR, against a ten-day time limit to request a decision from FIFA’s
dispute resolution bodies in order to lodge a CAS appeal. While the CAS
panel recognized ‘that the time limit of ten days is short’, it concluded:
‘the provision serves a legitimate purpose i.e. to cope with the heavy
caseload of FIFA and contributes to the goal of an efficient adminis-
tration of justice’.85 To support this conclusion, the panel invoked the
fact that ‘even’ the ECtHR ‘has all along allowed the right of access to the
81
CAS 2010/A/2311 and 2312, Stichting Anti-Doping Autoriteit Nederland (NADO) and the
Koninklijke Nederlandsche Schaatsenrijders Bond (KNSB) v. W, awards of 22 August
2011, paras 14–18.
82
Ibid., para. 18, referring to Lithgow and others v. The United Kingdom, app. nos. 9006/80,
9262/81, 9263/81, 9265/81, 9266/81, 9313/81, 9405/81, judgment of 8 July 1986.
83
Ibid.
84
Ibid., para. 19. For a more sceptical view, see J. Lukomski, ‘Arbitration Clauses in Sport
Governing Bodies’ Statutes: Consent or Constraint? Analysis from the Perspective of
Article 6(1) of the European Convention on Human Rights’ (2013) 13 The International
Sports Law Journal 60–70.
85
CAS 2008/A/1708, Football Federation Islamic Republic of Iran (IRIFF) v. Fédération
Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), award of 4 November 2009, para. 21; CAS
2008/A/1705, Neue Grasshopper Fussball AG Zurich v. Club Alianza de Lima, award of
18 June 2009, para. 23; see also CAS 2011/A/2439, Football Association of Thailand
v. Fédération Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), award of 17 June 2011,
para. 16.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
courts to be limited “in the interests of the good administration of
justice”’.86 However, this does not extend automatically to any other
statutory limitation to the scope of the review of the CAS.87 Indeed, the
CAS also invoked the ECHR to remind that ‘[r]estrictions to the funda-
mental right of access to justice should not be accepted easily, but only
where such restrictions are justified both in the interest of good adminis-
tration of justice and proportionality’.88 In this latter case, the sole
arbitrator failed ‘to see why a restriction of his mandate – contrary to
the clear wording of the Art. R57 of the CAS Code – would be in the
interest of good administration of justice’.89
As one can gather from these examples, the ECHR and its interpret-
ations by the ECtHR are used by CAS panels to justify fundamental
choices regarding their scope of jurisdiction. The entanglement is com-
plex as the ECHR is both used against an athlete, who is challenging the
validity of a CAS arbitration clause, and SGBs, who are trying to reduce
the scope of the CAS review of their decisions. It highlights the import-
ance of references to the ECHR as legitimating devices to support the
CAS’s interpretation of its jurisdictional space.
86
CAS 2011/A/2439.
87
CAS 2013/A/3274, Mads Glasner v. Fédération Internationale de Natation (FINA), award
of 31 January 2014, para. 65.
88
Ibid.
89
Ibid.
90
J. Soek, The Strict Liability Principle and the Human Rights of the Athlete in Doping Cases
(T.M.C. Asser Press, 2006). See also C. Tamburrini, ‘WADA’s Anti-doping Policy and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
raised this issue and it is therefore unsurprising to see the validity of the
WADC being tested on the basis of the ECHR.91 As a consequence, the
World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) has along the years requested a
number of opinions from respected scholars and practitioners to certify
the compatibility of the WADC with human rights, and the ECHR in
particular.92 Numerous CAS panels have religiously invoked these opin-
ions as authoritative material supporting the compatibility of the WADC
with the ECHR.93 Jean-Paul Costa, the former president of the ECtHR,
concluded in his 2013 expert opinion that the WADC is ‘in harmony’
Athletes’ Right to Privacy’ (2013) 1 Revista de Filosofía, Ética y Derecho del Deporte
84–96; A. J. Schneider, ‘Privacy, Confidentiality and Human Rights in Sport’ (2004) 7
Sport in Society 438–56; M. Hard, ‘Caught in the Net: Athletes’ Rights and the World
Anti-Doping Agency’ (2010) 19 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal
533–64.
91
The ECtHR has recently decided two cases related to anti-doping, see Fédération
Nationale des Syndicats Sportifs (FNASS) and Others v. France and Bakker
v. Switzerland, app. no. 7198/07, judgment of 3 September 2019.
92
G. Kaufmann-Kohler, G. Malinverni and A. Rigozzi, ‘Conformity of Certain Provisions of
the Draft WADC with Commonly Accepted Principles of International Law’ (February
2003), www.wada-ama.org/en/resources/legal/conformity-with-international-law;
G. Kaufmann-Kohler and A. Rigozzi, ‘Conformity of Art. 10.6 with Fundamental
Rights of Athletes’ (November 2007), www.wada-ama.org/en/resources/world-anti-
doping-program/conformity-with-fundamental-rights-of-athletes; J.-P. Costa, ‘Legal
Opinion Regarding the Draft World Anti-doping Code’ (June 2013), www.wada-ama
.org/en/resources/legal/legal-opinion-on-the-draft-2015-world-anti-doping-code; and J-
P. Costa, ‘Legal Opinion on the 2021 Code’ (October 2019), www.wada-ama.org/en/
resources/the-code/legal-opinion-on-the-2021-code-by-judge-jean-paul-costa.
93
The opinion by G. Kaufmann-Kohler, G. Malinverni and A. Rigozzi is cited in CAS 2004/
A/690, H. v. Association of Tennis Professionals (ATP), award of 24 March 2005, para. 54;
CAS 2005/A/830, S. v. FINA, award of 15 July 2005, para. 41; CAS 2006/A/1025, Mariano
Puerta v. International Tennis Federation (ITF), award of 12 July 2006, para. 78; CAS
2009/A/2012, Doping Authority Netherlands v. Mr Nick Zuijkerbuijk, award of 11 June
2010, para. 50; CAS 2009/A/1915, World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) v. Polish
Wrestling Federation (PWF), Kamil Blonski and Wojciech Zieziulewicz, award of
12 August 2010, para. 17; CAS 2010/A/2307, WADA v. Jobson Leandro Pereira de
Oliveira, CBF and STJD, award of 14 September 2011, paras 45 and 99. While the
Costa opinion is referred to in CAS 2016/A/4534, Maurico Fiol Villanueva
v. Fédération Internationale de Natation (FINA), award of 16 March 2017, para. 52;
CAS 2017/A/4927, Misha Aloyan v. International Olympic Committee (IOC), award of
16 June 2017, para. 82; CAS 2017/A/5099, Artur Taymazov v. International Olympic
Committee (IOC), award of 4 December 2017, para. 82; CAS 2018/A/5546, José Paolo
Guerrero v. FIFA and CAS 2018/A/5571, WADA v. FIFA and José Paolo Guerrero, awards
of 30 July 2018, para. 87; CAS 2018/A/5581, Filip Radojevic v. Fédération Internationale
de Natation (FINA), award of 10 July 2018, para. 85; and CAS 2018/A/5739, Levi
Cadogan v. National Anti-Doping Commission of Barbados (NADCB), award of
20 February 2019, para. 81.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
with ‘the accepted principles of international law and human rights’.94
Based on this conclusion, one Panel noted that ‘the previous President of
the European Court of Human Rights’ had ‘vouched for’ the proportion-
ality of the WADC.95 More broadly, with regard to the fixed minimum
sanctions in doping cases, a CAS panel concluded ‘that legal scholars,
CAS panels and the Swiss Federal Tribunal seem to concur that the
current sanctioning system based on the WADA Code does not conflict
with fundamental human rights’.96 Finally, an award endorsed the com-
patibility with Article 8 ECHR of the long-term storage of samples (for
up to eight years).97 In all these cases, the panels did not engage in deep
proportionality assessments of the compatibility of the WADC with the
ECHR but merely invoked the (scholarly or professional) authority of
expert opinions to reject the challenges.
94
CAS 2017/A/4927, para. 82 and CAS 2017/A/5099, para. 82.
95
CAS 2018/A/5546 and 5571, para. 87 and CAS 2018/A/5739, para. 81.
96
CAS 2015/A/4184, Jobson Leandro Pereira de Oliveira v. Fédération Internationale de
Football Association (FIFA), award of 25 April 2016 (operative part of 24 March 2016),
para. 188. Or that ‘CAS case law and various legal opinions confirm that the WADC
mechanisms are not contrary to human rights legislation’ in CAS 2009/A/2012, para. 47.
97
TAS 2009/A/1879, para. 81.
98
CAS 2014/A/3516, George Yerolimpos v. World Karate Federation, award of 6 October
2014, para. 104 and CAS 2016/A/4921 and 4922, Maria Dzhumadzuk, Irina Shulga and
Equestrian Federation of Ukraine v. Federation Equestre Internationale (FEI), award of
30 May 2017, para. 62.
99
CAS 2014/A/3516, para. 104.
100
Strict liability foresees that a disciplinary violation, such as a violation of anti-doping
rules, can be constituted even without fault of the accused. See CAS 2013/A/3139 above
and CAS 2014/A/3628, Eskişehirspor Kulübü v. Union of European Football Association
(UEFA), award of 2 September 2014 (operative part of 7 July 2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
ECHR. One award referred to ECtHR case law to support the claim that
the recourse to strict liability is not per se contrary to the ECHR.101 In
another more recent case, the panel rejected Article 6(2)’s applicability to
the disciplinary sanctions of SGBs ‘as Article 6(2) is only applicable to
criminal proceedings and the present proceedings are not of a criminal
nature’.102 Furthermore, the CAS also touched upon whether disciplinary
proceedings run counter to the privilege against self-incrimination rec-
ognized by the ECtHR,103 rejected on the basis of the ECHR the retro-
active application of a longer statute of limitation to a case that was
already time-barred at the time of the entry into force of the new
provision104 and invoked the lex mitior principle and its interpretation
by the ECtHR.105 In short, while disciplinary sanctions have a direct and
profound effect on those subjected to them, the CAS has been quite
reluctant to engage in a constitutional review of the SGBs’ decisions on
the basis of the ECHR.
10.3.3 The CAS and the Procedural Guarantees of Article 6(1) ECHR
The procedural rights guaranteed by Article 6(1) ECHR, and in particu-
lar their interpretation by the ECtHR, are more present in CAS awards.
The ECtHR’s case law plays a fundamental role in defining the intensity
of procedural review exercised by the CAS with regard to the decisions of
the SGBs, as well as in justifying the key procedural constraints applic-
able to the CAS itself.
101
See CAS 2009/A/1768, Hansen v. Fédération Equestre Internationale (FEI), award of
4 December 2009, para. 21 referring to Salabiaku v. France, app. no. 10519/83, judgment
of 7 October 1988, paras 28–9.
102
CAS 2013/A/3139, para. 91.
103
CAS 2018/A/5769, Worawi Makudi v. Fédération Internationale de Football Association
(FIFA), award of 11 February 2019, paras 135–6.
104
CAS 2015/A/4304, para. 48. Referencing decision dated Oleksandr Volkov v. Ukraine,
app. no. 21722/11, judgment of 9 January 2013, marg. no. 137.
105
The reference to the ECtHR decision Scoppola v. Italy, app. no. 10249/03, judgment of
17 September 2009 is found in CAS 2012/A/2817, Fenerbahçe Spor Kulübü v. Fédération
Internationale de Football Association (FIFA) and Roberto Carlos Da Silva Rocha, award
of 21 June 2013, para. 122 and CAS 2010/A/2083, UCI v. Jan Ullrich and Swiss Olympic,
award of 9 February 2012, para. 63.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
only a small share of these decisions is subsequently appealed at the CAS.
Yet, the CAS has consistently refused to assess the compatibility of these
first instance proceedings with Article 6(1) ECHR, relying instead on the
curative quality of an appeal before the CAS.
Sometimes awards simply exclude the applicability of the ECHR to
internal proceedings of the SGBs, such as when a panel noted that it ‘does
not see any reason in the present case to depart from the line established
in earlier jurisprudence, namely that the ECHR is not applicable to
disciplinary proceedings before a Sport association’s jurisdictional
bodies’.106 In other words, ‘procedural fundamental rights protect citi-
zens against violations of such rights by the State and its organs and are
therefore only applicable to a jurisdiction established by a State and not
to legal relationships between private entities such as associations and
their members’.107 The panel would only consider otherwise if the SGB
had ‘inserted into its Constitutional Rules and Regulations procedural
rights based on the ECHR or if it had referred to the ECHR as applicable
to disciplinary proceedings before its jurisdictional bodies’.108
Many panels, however, do not share this view. Contrariwise, another
panel recognized that ‘there are more and more authorities in legal
literature advocating that the ECHR also applies directly to sports asso-
ciations’.109 Yet, CAS panels have also long held that ‘if the hearing in a
given case was insufficient in the first instance [. . .] the fact is that, as
long as there is a possibility of full appeal to the Court of Arbitration for
Sport, the deficiency may be cured’.110 This curative ability has been
supported with references to the case law of the ECtHR.111 Awards claim
106
CAS 2009/A/1957, para. 14. In particular, the award referenced previous decisions such
as CAS 2000/A/290 above and CAS 2005/A/895, Al-Hilal Al-Saudi Club v. Fédération
Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), order of 12 December 2008.
107
Ibid., para. 15.
108
Ibid., para. 20.
109
CAS 2008/A/1513, para. 9.
110
CAS 94/129, USA Shooting and Q. v. Union Internationale de Tir (UIT), award of
23 May 1995 para. 59. For similar conclusions, see CAS 2009/A/1957, para. 21; CAS
2009/A/1985, Franchon Crews v. International Boxing Association (AIBA), award of
10 June 2010; para. 24. For a hint of a different direction, see CAS 2015/A/4095,
Bernardo Rezende and Mario da Silva Pedreira Junior v. Fédération International de
Volleyball (FIVB), award of 6 October 2015, paras 74–7.
111
The Wickramsinghe v. The United Kingdom, app. no. 31503/96, decision of 9 December
1997 is referenced in CAS 2007/A/1396 and 1402, World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA)
and Union Cycliste Internationale (UCI) v. Alejandro Valverde and Real Federación
Española de Ciclismo (RFEC), award of 31 May 2010, para. 43; CAS 2009/A/1920, FK
Pobeda, Aleksandar Zabrcanec, Nikolce Zdraveski v. UEFA, award of 15 April 2010,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
that this jurisprudence is ‘in line’112 with the Bryan v. The United
Kingdom ruling of the ECtHR and the Wickramsinghe decision of the
European Commission of Human Rights. The latter held, citing the
former, that ‘even where an adjudicatory body determining disputes over
civil rights and obligations does not comply with Article 6(1) [ECHR]
in some respect, no violation of the Convention will be found if the
proceedings before that body are subject to subsequent control by a
judicial body that has full jurisdiction and does provide the guarantees
of Article 6 (1)’.113
This position of the CAS has fundamental consequences for those
going through the internal judicial systems of the SGBs, as it basically
endorses, with the (alleged) blessing of the ECtHR, any type of proced-
ural wrongs at the level of the internal adjudicative bodies of the SGBs.
para. 28; CAS 2009/A/1985, para. 24; CAS 2011/A/2430, Football Club Apollonia
v. Albanian Football Federation (AFF) and Sulejman Hoxha, award of 18 October
2012, para. 9.24; CAS 2013/A/3262, Joel Melchor Sánchez Alegría v. Fédération
Internationale de Football Association (FIFA), award of 30 September 2014 (operative
part of 18 June 2014), para. 83; CAS 2016/A/4871, Vladimir Sakotic v. FIDE World Chess
Federation (FIDE), award of 2 August 2017, para. 120. The ECtHR’s A. Menarini
Diagnostics S.r.l. v. Italy, app. no. 43509/08, judgment of 27 September 2011, paras
58–9 is cited in CAS 2011/A/2362, Mohammad Asif v. International Cricket Council,
award of 17 April 2013, para. 41. Finally, the Bryan v. The United Kingdom, app.
no. 19178/91, judgment of 22 November 1995 is referred to in CAS 2008/A/1513,
para. 9.
112
CAS 2009/A/1985, para. 24; CAS 2011/A/2430, para. 9.24; CAS 2013/A/3262, para. 83.
113
Wickramsinghe v. The United Kingdom, para. 41.
114
CAS 2009/A/1920, para. 13. See as well CAS 2011/A/2384 and 2386, paras 167–86.
115
Ibid. However, in CAS 2011/A/2384 and 2386, para. 184, the CAS refused to allow a
witness to testify anonymously because the Panel considered that ‘it was insufficiently
demonstrated that the interests of the witness worthy of protection were threatened to
an extent that could justify a complete protection of the witness’ identity from disclosure
to the Respondents’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
highlighting that the right to be heard must be guaranteed by other
means such as ‘by cross examination through “audiovisual protection”
and by an in-depth check of the identity and the reputation of the
anonymous witness by the court’.116
Second, the CAS has had to decide whether the use of illegally
obtained evidence in disciplinary proceedings is contrary to the
ECHR.117 For example, a panel refused to draw an analogy between the
Texeira de Castro decision of the ECtHR, which found that Portugal
contravened the ECHR in a case in which the police had gathered
evidence through illegal means, and the reliance by FIFA on evidence
gathered illegally by an English newspaper.118 This led the arbitrators to
deny the claimant the right to rely on the ECtHR’s case law to challenge
the admissibility of evidence obtained indirectly through unlawful wir-
etapping by the press. In support of this conclusion, the panel referenced
the ECtHR’s case law on freedom of expression insofar as it protects the
intrusion of the press in a person’s private life.119 In a subsequent award,
the CAS panel went further by invoking the ECtHR’s finding that ‘the
courts shall balance the interest in protecting the right that was infringed
by obtaining the evidence against the interest in establishing the truth’.120
While another panel concluded that ‘the interest underlying the fight
against doping can be preponderant over the individual’s interest,
whether an athlete or athlete support personnel, in not having an illicitly
obtained evidence admitted in an arbitral procedure concerning an
alleged anti-doping rule violation’.121 The arbitrators insisted that this
balancing test is ‘in line’122 with the jurisprudence of the ECtHR.
116
CAS 2009/A/1920.
117
TAS 2011/A/2433. On the use of the secret recordings that led to the recent Russian anti-
doping scandal, see CAS 2016/A/4480, International Association of Athletics Federations
(IAAF) v. All Russia Athletics Federation (ARAF) and Vladimir Kazarin, award of 7 April
2017, paras 76–7; CAS 2016/A/4486, International Association of Athletics Federations
(IAAF) v. Ekaterina Poistogova, award of 7 April 2017, paras 104–6; and CAS 2016/A/
4487, International Association of Athletics Federations (IAAF) v. Alexey Melnikov,
award of 7 April 2017, paras 104–6.
118
Ibid., para. 27. Referring to Teixeira de Castro v. Portugal, app. no. 25829/94, judgment
of 9 June 1998.
119
Ibid., paras 31–2.
120
CAS 2016/A/4480, para. 76.
121
CAS 2016/A/4486, para. 105.
122
Ibid., para. 106. In particular the award refers to K.S and M.S v. Germany, app.
no. 33969/11, judgment of 6 October 2016.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The question of the admissibility of evidence is crucial in determining
the outcome of any judicial process. Instead of relying on self-made
principles, it is interesting to note that the CAS has borrowed from the
ECtHR’s jurisprudence to support its relatively liberal view regarding the
admissibility of evidence. The latter can be traced back to the difficult
position in which SGBs are placed when enforcing their regulations, as
they do not enjoy the police powers (or the capacity) to conduct typical
investigatory measures and are mostly reliant on indirectly (and often
illegally) obtained information.
123
CAS 2014/A/3561 and 3614.
124
CAS 2014/A/3561 and 3614, para. 196.
125
Ibid., para. 197–207.
126
Ibid., para. 207.
127
Ibid.
128
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
exact opposite conclusion on both the free consent of athletes to CAS
arbitration and the need for the publicity of CAS hearings in doping
cases.129 This fundamental divergence highlights the potential gap
between the CAS’s application of the ECHR (or Swiss law and EU law)
and the ECtHR’s own interpretation (or the SFT’s and the CJEU’s
interpretation). This situation of interpretive pluralism is not dissimilar
to the interaction between national courts and the CJEU or the ECtHR.
Thus, this entanglement opens up a field of dialectical play between
textual proximity and interpretative distance which will never be
entirely bridged.
In different ways, and for different purposes, CAS arbitrators have
weaved the ECHR into their judicial reasoning. Such intertwinement is
never anodyne, however. It supports important substantial and proced-
ural choices with clear distributive consequences for the parties to CAS
arbitration.
10.4 Conclusion
The CAS is a special place. It is not really an arbitral tribunal, nor is it a
proper international court, but it stands as a living embodiment of the
‘unidentified legal objects’130 that proliferate in transnational legal prac-
tice. It is often presented as necessary to the transnational governance
(and mere existence) of international sports. Important CAS decisions,
such as the recent Semenya award, are subjected to global attention and
intense scrutiny. This chapter portrays the CAS as a judicial site where
awards are being produced through a process of legal weaving that
enmeshes different types of legal material. Its practice is not a solipsistic
work based only on the denationalized law of an autonomous trans-
national community but rather an artistic mélange of styles producing a
textual assemblage that is tailored to each case. In the context of the lex
129
Mutu and Pechstein v. Switzerland above. See A. Duval, ‘Time to Go Public?
Transparency at the Court of Arbitration for Sport after the Pechstein Decision of the
European Court of Human Rights’, in A. Duval and A. Rigozzi (eds), Yearbook of
International Sports Arbitration 2017 (T.M.C. Asser Press, 2020), pp. 3–28.
130
In reference to what Benoît Frydman calls ‘objets juridiques non ou mal identifiés’, in
B. Frydman, ‘Comment penser le droit global?’ (2012) Working Papers du Centre
Perelman de Philosophie du Droit, www.philodroit.be/IMG/pdf/comment_penser_le_
droit_global_2011.pdf, p. 5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
sportiva, entanglement is undoubtedly the ‘normal state of the law’131
and the CAS represents a striving ‘Inter-Legality Hub’.132
Nevertheless, it is true that not all legal texts are equally present in CAS
awards. As we have seen, Swiss law is much more present than, say,
French law (or any other national law for that matter). Similarly, EU law
and the ECHR are regularly invoked while there are very few mentions of
other sources of international law. One should not lose sight of the fact
that the CAS is not an a-national construct hovering above our heads,
but is embedded (like many international SGBs) in the territorial and
legal context of Switzerland. Furthermore, entanglements cannot be
severed from the actors.133 Many of the professionals active before the
CAS as arbitrators or lawyers are Europeans or even Swiss. Finally, the
main avenue to challenge CAS awards is the SFT (and, to a much lesser
extent, other European courts and administrative bodies). It is thus quite
logical that when CAS panels are called to assemble an award, they draw
on both what they know and what they want to assuage. Thus, the CAS
works not so much as an autarkic judicial machinery reliant on its own
supply of power and inputs but rather as a transnational legal assembly
line importing various parts of its awards from different suppliers on a
case-by-case basis. Hence, the judicial practice of the CAS can help us
move beyond the billiard ball model of autonomous transnational legal
orders or systems in order to perceive the hybridity of transnational legal
practice.134 At the CAS, Swiss law, EU law and the ECHR are not so
much clashing with the lex sportiva as they are entangled within it. They
become an integral part of the lex sportiva. This conclusion does not
imply that the ECtHR or the CJEU should defer to the CAS, to the
contrary. It means that they should scrutinize closely the way it speaks
‘their’ language, like they assess the way national courts are speaking it.
In a world where nobody is in a position to impose top down a single set
of global rules applied in a uniform way, transnational legal practice is
bound to be the result of strange loops and contextual assemblages.
The complex beauty of these rhetorical entanglements should not hide
the fact that the CAS is taking distributive decisions which are very hard
(i.e. costly) to challenge. This chapter has not focused on the politics
131
Chapter 1.
132
Y. Shany, ‘International Courts as Inter-legality Hubs’, in J. Klabbers and G. Palombella
(eds), The Challenge of Inter-legality (Cambridge University Press, 2019), pp. 319–38.
133
Chapter 1, Section 1.4.1.
134
See A. Duval, ‘What Lex Sportiva Tells You about Transnational Law’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
lurking behind these entanglements. In other words, what are their
underlying drivers or unspoken purposes? In order to answer this ques-
tion, one would need to carefully investigate who does the entangling and
why. There is no reason to believe that these entanglements are per se fair
or just. Therefore, the ethics of those producing legal entanglements must
be subjected to strict scrutiny.135 In fact, the dark face of the ubiquity of
transnational legal entanglements might be that ultimate political
accountability becomes difficult to locate as decisions are enmeshed in
a plurality of political and legal contexts. Who should be blamed for a
particular interpretation of the FIFA RSTP? Is it the responsibility of
FIFA, the European Commission, the CAS or the SFT? Where can we ask
to change it and how? The risk is that entanglements lead to a form of
organized irresponsibility, as if the legal assemblages of the CAS were not
the result of deliberate choices but natural reflections of what a patch-
work of laws say. Hence, the age of entanglements calls for a relentless
critique of the politics lurking behind the textual assemblages. If legisla-
tors are found simultaneously in multiple places and levels, inside the
SGBs, at the Swiss parliament or in Brussels, we need to think about how
to recreate a transnational democratic space (and process) adapted to this
multiplicity. Similarly, if the CAS is in a position to assemble its awards
relatively freely, in light of the extremely limited control exercised by the
SFT and the high costs of challenging a CAS award elsewhere, then we
must seriously consider those who are doing the assembling. Who are
they? How is their legitimacy and authority justified? Are they sufficiently
impartial and independent from the SGBs? How are they selected? What
are the mechanisms in place to prevent the rise of conflicts of interests?
Once we recognize that the assembling or entangling of transnational law
is the new normal, we must urgently grapple with these questions. The
hybridization and pluralization of transnational legal practice might be a
necessary consequence of the liquefaction of our transnational lives, but
it raises fundamental problems for the way in which political agency is
exercised and decision-makers are held accountable. One answer to this
conundrum could be to move towards entangling our politics and
accountability mechanisms, meaning that the citizenry has to exercise
agency at multiple levels (e.g. through social movements, consumer
boycotts or simply voting at the European Parliament elections) and to
move strategically between different accountability fora (e.g. the
135
J. Klabbers, ‘Judging Inter-legality’, in J. Klabbers and G. Palombella (eds), The Challenge
of Inter-legality (Cambridge University Press, 2019), pp. 339–62.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
European Commission, national competition authorities, national courts,
Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development contact
points or the ECtHR).136 In the context of the CAS and the lex sportiva,
Claudia Pechstein has shown the way, even though it came at great
personal costs,137 by challenging her doping ban before the SFT, the
German courts and the ECtHR. To initiate these critical shifts in the way
we engage in politics and law, it is first essential to grasp the ubiquity of
legal entanglements in the operation of transnational law. The aim of this
chapter was to contribute to this prise de conscience by exposing how the
CAS transforms transnational sporting disputes into legal gold: authori-
tative awards.
136
This shift in the exercise of power is theorised by U. Beck, Power in the Global Age
(Polity, 2005).
137
‘Pleite zwingt Pechstein zu dramatischem Hilferuf’ Die Welt (1 July 2015), www.welt.de/
sport/article143390802/Pleite-zwingt-Pechstein-zu-dramatischem-Hilferuf.html.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
11
11.1 Introduction
The global financial order is key to our economy but highly fragile. And
the norms and institutions to stabilize it are themselves plural and
fragmented – in fact, a prime example of multiple bodies of norms
coexisting in global governance. This order is characterized by a multi-
plicity of norms and institutions with various claims to authority, reflect-
ing different priorities and normative orientations. How have actors dealt
with the tensions that this plurality generates and where has this left the
multiple legalities and their relations?
To answer this question, this chapter examines the recent history of
the global administration of financial stability. In the last two decades,
this area of financial regulation has been shaped by responses to the
perceived risks associated with multiplicity of norms and institutions.
The contemporary administration of financial and monetary affairs
seems to be surrounded by ‘mystery’1 and ‘ambiguity about the
relationship between all of the various sources of international regulatory
standards’.2 This complexity may partly depend on our limited
I am particularly grateful to Professor Nico Krisch for his generous support and comments
on earlier versions of this chapter. I wish to thank the participants in the workshop
‘Entangled Legalities’, in May 2018, where a first draft of this text was presented, and
Tomáš Morochovič for his careful editing of this text. I also gratefully acknowledge the
financial support by the SNF, which made this research possible.
1
D. Kennedy, ‘The Mystery of Global Governance’, in J. L. Dunoff and J. P. Trachtman
(eds), Ruling the World? Constitutionalism, International Law, and Global Governance
(Cambridge University Press, 2009), pp. 37–68.
2
A. Riles, ‘Managing Regulatory Arbitrage: A Conflict of Laws Approach’ (2014) 47 Cornell
International Law Journal 63–119, at 80–1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
understanding of the organizational structures of these relationships and
the drivers behind them.
In various contexts of global financial governance, characterized by a
significant degree of informality, regulatory decentralization and
dynamic institutional interactions, societal actors have shaped differ-
ent ordering projects in opposition to ‘chaos’ over time. From a macro
perspective, previous studies have helpfully analysed the broad histor-
ical and political contexts in which these ordering projects have come
about by placing emphasis on ‘the power and interests of leading
financial powers, domestic political dynamics, and the role of trans-
national actors’.3 Yet we do not quite know the forms through which
institutional multiplicity has been organized and with what effects for
the overall order. Drawing upon the concepts of this volume, this
chapter analyses different forms of entanglements in contexts of global
financial regulation, focusing on some of the sites, actor constellations
and dynamics behind them.4 This chapter uses the term bodies of
norms to connect the variety of recommendations, standards, best
practices and codes recognized by regulators as factors of financial
stability. At various decision-making settings, financial regulators,
legal professionals and economic experts disagreed over the identifica-
tion of the relevant sources of authority and their organizational
structures. For example, the prevailing regulatory response that
followed the global financial crisis of 2008 was a call for a more or less
centralized institutional framework for ‘a global banking and financial
system’. Some lawyers imagined a new field of international financial
law or lex financiera.5 Many argued that the International Monetary
Fund (IMF) should have institutional primacy, while others regarded
the Financial Stability Board (FSB) as the appropriate locus of author-
ity, and yet others suggested that the function of a new World
Financial Authority should be allocated. However, opposing views
defended a more modest reform through a pluralist approach to
ordering.6 This chapter questions ambitious attempts at structuring
3
E. Helleiner, ‘Regulating the Regulators: The Emergence and Limits of the Transnational
Financial Legal Order’, in T. C. Halliday and G. Shaffer (eds), Transnational Legal Orders
(Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 231–57, p. 235.
4
See Chapter 1. Throughout the text, I use ‘entanglement’ and ‘enmeshment’ interchangeably.
5
See, for example, R. M. Lastra, ‘Do We Need a World Financial Organization?’ (2014) 17
Journal of International Economic Law 787–805.
6
C. Brummer, Minilateralism: How Trade Alliances, Soft Law, and Financial Engineering
Are Redefining Economic Statecraft (Cambridge University Press, 2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
and controlling multiplicity through one ‘common frame of reference’7
such as legalization in finance. I contrast this dominant view with the
perspective of ‘entangled legality’8 as an alternative way of thinking
about relations between multiple kinds of laws populating global
finance. From this perspective, the project of legalization is only one
among a variety of ways of ordering multiplicity, which may equally
contribute to dynamics of enmeshment. While these relations are
embedded in a mosaic of interactions between multiple orders, elem-
ents of this wider environment form the background of the analysis.
The analysis proceeds as follows. Following this introduction, Section
11.2 describes international financial standards as interrelated bodies of
norms and foregrounds how they became entangled in regulatory set-
tings over time. Drawing on public documents from the Bank for
International Settlements (BIS), the United Nations (UN) and the IMF,
I examine the forms in which these bodies of norms were brought into
relation by different actors. In the wake of the Asian financial crisis of
1997, officials at the IMF, UN and BIS made claims ordering institutional
fragmentation. In this context, the Financial Stability Forum (FSF)
emerged as a ‘site of entanglement’ and the drafters and users of its
Compendium of Standards came to play a central role in organizing
relations between norms that were identified as ‘international standards’.
Against this historical backdrop, Section 11.3 identifies different interface
norms and examines how they were used by actors in norm-making and
norm-implementation settings. Within the debate on the reform of the
international financial architecture, regulatory harmonization and over-
arching institutions have been dominant responses to the perceived risks
of institutional multiplicity. Yet, while there seems to be no consensus
over the content of these overarching institutions, competing forms of
ordering persist.
7
N. Krisch, ‘Pluralism’, in J. d’Aspremont and S. Singh (eds), Concepts for International
Law (Edward Elgar, 2019), pp. 691–707.
8
See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
this area of global governance are the informality, multiplicity and
dynamic interactions of its norms, institutions and sites of decision-
making.9 In many of these settings, state officials, international organiza-
tions, financial institutions and other private actors have recognized
norms that often take the form of best practices and standards rather
than more established categories of international law.10 Equally striking,
these norms have often made their appearance in groups, resembling a
relatively loose assemblage of ‘clusters’ of norms. In this respect, the term
bodies of norms seems apt to underline their interrelatedness.11
Institutional players in global financial regulation have often highlighted
this particular feature of international standards by placing emphasis on
their interconnectedness and interdependence as commonsensical, just
the ‘normal’ thing to do,12 and in doing so they have not found it
problematic to blur their boundaries, for example by referring to their
own previous work or work done by others.
An early manifestation of the discursive formation of these associ-
ations could be observed circa 1995 at the ‘Tripartite Group of Banks,
Securities and Insurance Regulators’. An informal working group created
by the Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, the Tripartite Group
facilitated the encounter of national bank, securities and insurance regu-
lators13 to exchange information and perform ‘intensive cooperation’ to
address regulatory problems related to ‘financial conglomerates’. A senior
official from the US Treasury reported that states’ competing interests
made it challenging to agree on one single supranational institution to
provide a solution to these problems.14 It is worth mentioning what this
9
C. Brummer, Soft Law and the Global Financial System: Rule Making in the 21st Century
(Cambridge University Press, 2015), see in particular chapter 2. Annelise Riles has
described ‘global financial regulation’ as a ‘global system that is inherently pluralistic’.
A. Riles, ‘Is New Governance the Ideal Architecture for Global Financial Regulation?’, in
C. Goodhart, D. Gabor, J. Vestergaard and I. Ertürk (eds), Central Banking at a
Crossroads: Europe and Beyond (Anthem Press, 2014), pp. 245–64.
10
According to Brummer, the three forms of soft financial law are: best practices, data and
information sharing agreements. Brummer, Minilateralism, pp. 96–8.
11
See Chapter 1.
12
‘The recognition of authority can flow from many sources: it can result from rational
calculus, normative internalization or a mere acceptance as “normal”.’ N. Krisch, ‘Liquid
Authority in Global Governance’ (2017) 9 International Theory 237–60, at 242.
13
For the list of members, see Basel Committee, ‘The Supervision of Financial
Conglomerates: A Report by the Tripartite Group of Bank, Securities and Insurance
Regulators’ (July 1995), at 67–8.
14
‘Since a single global financial regulator is not a feasible idea from our point of view due
to sovereignty concerns, we had to look at the problem in terms of promoting regulatory
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
informal working group aimed at innovating against. Until then,
challenges associated with ‘financial conglomerates’, in particular the
‘regulatory arbitrage’ problem, had been dealt with from the perspective
of different ‘regulatory groups’.15 In contrast, the Tripartite Group
responded to pluralism ‘from a joint perspective’. The making of this
‘joint perspective’ in opposition to the ‘different approaches adopted by
supervisors’ enabled national financial regulators to ‘synthetize’ the work
that had previously been done.
This synthesis was recognized by members of the Basel Committee
on Banking Supervision (BCBS), the Technical Committee of the
International Organization of Securities Commission (IOSCO) and the
International Association of Insurance Supervisors (IAIS) as a ‘sound
basis for further collaborative efforts’16 which led to the creation, in 1996,
of a ‘Joint Forum on Financial Conglomerates’.17 The Joint Forum was
an informal setting where senior bank, insurance and securities super-
visors from thirteen countries18 assembled to ‘exchange information’ and
practice ‘supervisory coordination’. The Basel Committee’s Minimum
Standards for the Supervision of International Banking Groups and their
Cross-border Establishments, IOSCO’s Principles for Memoranda of
Understanding and IAIS ‘Insurance Concordat’ – Principles Applicable
to the Supervision of International Insurers and Insurance Groups and
their Cross-border Establishments – were jointly recognized by members
of the Joint Forum as ‘a common set of principles’ to practice exchange of
information among supervisors.19
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Another informal site of interaction between ministers of finance,
central bankers from ‘industrial countries’20 and ‘emerging markets’21
and representatives from international institutions and international
standards organizations22 was the Working Party on Financial Stability
in Emerging Market Economies. In 1997, under the chairmanship of
Mario Draghi, the Working Party issued a report on the banking sector
in emerging markets, referring to ‘a corpus of sound principles and
practices’23 by which they brought norms produced by ‘international
groupings’ into relation.24
20
France, Germany, Japan, the Netherlands, Sweden, the United Kingdom and the
United States.
21
Argentina, Hong Kong, Singapore, Indonesia, Korea, Mexico, Poland, Singapore,
Thailand.
22
These actors were Representatives of the Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, the
International Accounting Standards Committee (IASC) and the International
Organization of Securities Commissions (IOSCO) and staff members of the Bank for
International Settlements (BIS), the European Commission, the International Monetary
Fund (IMF), the Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD)
and the International Bank for Reconstruction and Development (World Bank).
23
Working Party on Financial Stability in Emerging Market Economies, ‘Report on
Financial Stability in Emerging Market Economies, a Strategy for the Formulation,
Adoption and Implementation of Sound Principles and Practices to Strengthen
Financial Systems’ (April 1997). The members of the Working Party are listed on
pp. 101–2 of the report.
24
These actors were: the IASC, IOSCO, the Basel Committee on Banking Supervision of the
Group of Ten (G10) central banks, the Committee on Payment and Settlement Systems
of the G10 central banks, International Association of Insurance Supervisors.
25
Krisch, ‘Liquid Authority in Global Governance’, 249.
26
We might expect to observe different or similar forms of ordering plurality in other
settings, too. See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
in the historical development of the global financial order.27 They have
also been key historical contexts in which regulatory actors formulated
reform efforts to reorder institutional multiplicity. For example, in
response to the Asian financial crisis of 1997, IMF jurists and economists
placed emphasis on ‘international standards and codes’ against the dif-
ferent domestic laws that some IMF officials saw as problematic for
financial stability.28 However, the definition of these bodies of norms
and the articulation of their relations were neither uncontroversial nor
necessary decisions but occurred in multiple and incremental steps.
In 1997, Morris Goldstein,29 an IMF economist, published a book
entitled The Case for an International Banking Standard30 which
strengthened the project of international harmonization in the banking
area. Goldstein argued for the creation of a new international banking
standard (IBS) through the combination of existing norms and practices.
The envisaged standard had to be shaped through ‘vigorous cross-agency
cooperation’ rather than by one single decision-maker, and be compre-
hensive and broad in scope and design. The Basel Committee ‘should not
be the only group working on an IBS’31 – instead, the new norm should
draw not only on the expertise and norms of good banking supervision
by the Basel Committee but also on those of international accounting and
transparency, traditionally considered to fall under the jurisdiction of the
International Accounting Standards Committee (IASC) and IMF
respectively.32 Goldstein’s approach straddled boundaries between stand-
ards traditionally considered to be confined to well-defined domains. The
IBS would only aim at ‘partial’ as opposed to ‘full’ international harmon-
ization of banking standards, leaving ‘room for states to maintain their
27
Helleiner, ‘Regulating the Regulators’. See also C. Brummer and M. Smallcomb,
‘Institutional Design: The International Architecture’, in N. Moloney, E. Ferran and J.
Payne (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Financial Regulation (Oxford University Press,
2015).
28
On the historical background of the trajectory towards international standards, see R. P
Delonis, ‘International Financial Standards and Codes: Mandatory Regulation without
Representation’ (2004) 36 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics
563–604.
29
Deputy Director of the IMF Research Department (1987–94).
30
M. Goldstein, The Case for an International Banking Standard (Peterson Institute for
International Economics, 1997).
31
Ibid., at 53.
32
Ibid., at 35.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
national preferences towards risk, as well as to maintain some of their
institutional diversity’.33
Actors associated with the Bretton Woods institutions began referring
to ‘internationally accepted best practices’ and ‘international standards’
to bring together select bodies of norms that they recognized as central
features of the new international financial architecture.34 IMF officials
referred to ‘international financial standards’ to link multiple bodies of
norms deemed relevant to ‘the soundness of the financial system’.35
An international consensus on how standards relate to each other and
with domestic legal orders was shaped through various tools, including
monitoring practices performed by international financial institutions.
Through these practices, IMF and World Bank officials connected norms
produced by the IMF itself, the World Bank or other international
standard-setting organizations and associated them with domestic legal
orders in developed and developing economies.36 In particular, the
33
Ibid.
34
Michel Camdessus, former managing director of the IMF, referred to ‘internationally
accepted best practices’ to bind together the Basel Adequacy standards, internationally
accepted accounting standards and disclosure rules. M. Camdessus, ‘The Role of the IMF:
Past, Present, and Future – Speech’ (13 February 1998). He further stated: ‘the Fund has
been working to help disseminate a set of “best practices” in the banking area – as
developed by the Basle Committee – so that standards and practices that have worked
well in some countries can be adapted and applied in others. These efforts will now be
stepped up.’ See address by M. Camdessus to the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council
of Europe, ‘From the Asian Crisis toward a New Global Architecture’ (23 June 1998).
Stanley Fisher, first deputy managing director of the IMF (1994–2001) expressed similar
ideas: ‘As we help countries strengthen their financial systems, we need guideposts to
judge what has been achieved and what remains to be done. This requires international
standards against which to assess the soundness and stability of financial systems. There
are many players in the international community with a keen interest in such standards,
and their development requires the active participation of both private and official bodies,
domestic and international [. . .] But there has been a growing recognition of the links
between their work and the consequent need for collaboration [. . .] the main contribu-
tion of the Fund is in encouraging the implementation of standards that have been
determined by others and then using them in our work on the assessment of financial
systems [. . .] Standards cannot be written in stone. They are bound to evolve in the light
of experience.’ S. Fischer, ‘The IMF and the Financial Sector – Introductory Remarks’
(5 June 2000).
35
These bodies of norms were on: data dissemination, fiscal transparency, monetary and
fiscal policies, banking supervision, securities market regulation, insurance regulation,
accounting, auditing, bankruptcy and corporate governance. See IMF Policy
Development and Review Department, ‘Progress Report Developing International
Standards’ (1999).
36
T. Halliday, ‘Legal Yardsticks: International Financial Institutions as Diagnosticians and
Designers of the Law of Nations’, in K. Davis, A. Fisher, B. Kingsbury and S. E. Merry
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
creation of the Financial Sector Assessment Program (FSAP) authorized
IMF officials to link standards that they recognized as relevant for a safe
international financial system and bring them into relation with domestic
legal orders.37 One important outcome of monitoring practices per-
formed in the context of FSAP is the production of a report on
‘Financial System Stability Assessment’. This report is subsequently taken
into account when the IMF conducts ‘bilateral surveillance’ and performs
‘consultations’ with domestic authorities being assessed, under Article IV
of the IMF Articles of Agreement.38 Through these monitoring practices,
IMF officials have deferred to the authority of twelve international
standards setters39 they consider to be ‘relevant’ in the context of their
work.40 The report resulting from these monitoring practices verifies and
strengthens the recognition of standards but their recommendations also
provide ‘feedback’ to the standard-setting organizations that produce
standards.41
Previous historical analyses of international financial institutions have
argued that the IMF’s monitoring practices have normative power and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘hegemonic’ features. In particular, IMF conditionality has discursively
reinforced colonial relations of domination reinscribing the North–South
divide.42 Indeed, ‘globalization [. . .] requires the replacement of numer-
ous national laws and jurisdictions by uniform global standards in order
to remove the barriers to capital accumulation at the global level’.43 From
these perspectives, conditionality operates as a ‘path to entanglement’
based on coercion,44 which is often made invisible by taking the form of
‘incentives’. For example, according to the IMF, it is ‘in countries’ own
interest to adopt and implement internationally recognized standards
and codes’.45 For borrowing countries, highlighting linkages with inter-
national standards becomes crucial to persuade institutional creditors of
their creditworthiness. These linkages appeared for example in the ‘letters
of intent’ of Korea, Indonesia and Thailand as they requested institu-
tional creditors’ support to recover from an economic crisis.46 Similarly,
the government of Turkey deferred to the authority of international
standards47 and officials from Colombia gave weight to international
standards on auditing, the Basel core principles and codes of conduct
on money laundering and terrorism financing.48 From the perspective of
states seeking financial support there have been incentives and con-
straints to tie their domestic legal orders to international financial stand-
ards, although the latter are formally non-binding.49 In this context,
entanglement was driven by both states’ rational interests and the
42
S. Pahuja, ‘Technologies of Empire: IMF Conditionality and the Reinscription of the
North/South Divide’ (2000) 13 Leiden Journal of International Law 749–813.
43
B. S. Chimni, ‘Marxism and International Law: A Contemporary Analysis’ (1999) 34
Economic and Political Weekly 337–49; B. S. Chimni, ‘International Institutions Today:
An Imperial Global State in the Making’ (2004) 15 European Journal of International Law
1–37.
44
Brummer and Smallcomb, ‘Institutional Design’.
45
See www.imf.org/en/About/Factsheets/Sheets/2016/08/01/16/25/Standards-and-Codes.
46
Camdessus, ‘The Role of the IMF’.
47
Letter of Intent of the government of Turkey (2001), www.imf.org/external/np/loi/2001/
tur/02/.
48
Letter of Intent, Memorandum of Economic and Financial Policies, and Technical
Memorandum of Understanding of Colombia (2002), www.imf.org/external/np/loi/
2002/col/01/index.htm.
49
On the idea of conditioning the disbursement of funds to the adherence to such
standards, see B. J. Eichengreen, Toward a New International Financial Architecture:
A Practical Post-Asia Agenda (Peterson Institute for International Economics, 1999).
Giovanoli has called these determinants ‘official incentives’ (FSAP) and ‘unofficial incen-
tives’ (market expectations). See M. Giovanoli, ‘The Reform of the International Financial
Architecture after the Global Crisis’ (2009) 42 New York University Journal of
International Law and Politics 81–123, at 118–19.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
realization of their position in a relation of economic dependency, close
to a material condition of coercion.50 In the UN context, officials repre-
sented the ‘international financial architecture’ as a ‘system’. For
example, a UN Task-Force led by José Antonio Ocampo51 argued that
‘the international financial system is an organic whole and requires a
comprehensive approach’.52 From this systemic perspective, the UN
Task-Force articulated a vision of the international financial architecture
in close connection with human rights laws and UN institutions. UN
officials did not invoke the UN Charter but relied instead on the provi-
sions of the Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights to create
normative expectations for all the subsystems constituting the inter-
national financial architecture.
At the BIS, ‘international standards’ were also invoked against insti-
tutional pluralism.53 Here, Hans Tietmeyer54 criticized the ‘fragmented
supervisory structures’ characterizing the status quo and suggested
improve ‘international cooperation and coordination’ by ‘bringing
together the major international institutions and key national authorities
involved in financial sector stability’ and to include ‘emerging market
economies’.55 Arguing that the model of the Joint Forum56 had to be
applied ‘in a comprehensive manner’, Tietmeyer referred to ‘accepted
best practices’ to bind the ‘Core Principles issued by both the BCBS and
IOSCO, and those being developed by other international groupings’
together.57 Based on Tietmeyer’s report, the Group of Seven (G7) created
the Financial Stability Forum.58 The new organization enabled the
encounter of a large number of actors, mainly ‘public’ but also ‘private’
50
On these different paths to entanglement, see Chapter 1.
51
Report of the Task-Force of the Executive Committee on Economic and Social Affairs of
the United Nations, ‘Towards a New International Financial Architecture’ (21 January
1999), 14–15.
52
Ibid., 7.
53
Institutional pluralism seems the only form of pluralism considered by participants in
international financial regulation reform. This form of pluralism is different from ‘sys-
temic pluralism’. On this conceptual distinction, see Krisch, ‘Pluralism’, pp. 695–8.
54
Economist and former president of the Deutsche Bundesbank (1993–9).
55
H. Tietmeyer, ‘Report on International Cooperation and Coordination in the Area of
Financial Market Supervision and Surveillance’ (11 February 1999).
56
On the Joint Forum, see Section 11.2.
57
Tietmeyer, ‘Report on international cooperation and coordination’.
58
On the creation of the Financial Stability Forum, see Brummer, Soft Law and the Global
Financial System, p. 74. See also Helleiner, ‘Regulating the Regulators’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
ones.59 Andrew Crockett60 was appointed as first chairman for a three-
year term.61 A member of the Board of Trustees of the International
Accounting Standards Board (2000–3), an organization with the mission
to create a global financial reporting standard,62 Crockett was in favour
of global approaches to ordering multiplicity63 and regarded inter-
national financial standards as ‘interrelated’.64
59
These actors were: ‘the finance minister, central bank governor, and a supervisory
authority from each of the G-7 countries, as well as representatives from the IMF,
World Bank, Bank for International Settlements (“BIS”), Organization for Economic
Cooperation and Development (“OECD”), Basel Committee on Banking Supervision
(“BCBS”), International Accounting Standards Board (“IASB”), International
Association of Insurance Supervisors (“IAIS”), International Organization of Securities
Commissions (“IOSCO”), Committee on Payment and Settlements Systems (“CPSS”),
and Committee on the Global Financial System (“CGFS”). After its creation, the FSF
added the European Central Bank, and additional national members Australia, Hong
Kong, the Netherlands, and Switzerland.’ E. Carrasco, ‘The Global Financial Crisis and
the Financial Stability Forum: The Awakening and Transformation of an International
Body Global Financial and Economic Crisis Symposium’ (2010) 19 Transnational Law &
Contemporary Problems 203–20, at 206.
60
Andrew Crockett worked at the IMF (1972–89), was executive director of the Bank of
England (1989–93) and worked as general manager of the BIS (1994–2003).
61
Communiqué of G7 Finance Ministers and Central Bank Governors, 20 February 1999,
Petersberg, Bonn. On the role of Tietmeyer and the BIS in the creation of the FSF, see C.
Brummer, ‘A Theory of Everything: A Historically Grounded Understanding of Soft Law
and the BIS’, in C. Borio, S. Claessens, P. Clement, R. McCauley and H. Shin (eds),
Promoting Global Monetary and Financial Stability: The Bank for International
Settlements after Bretton Woods, 1973–2020 (Cambridge University Press, 2020),
pp. 112–33.
62
K. Camfferman and S. A. Zeff, Aiming for Global Accounting Standards: The
International Accounting Standards Board, 2001–2011 (Oxford University Press, 2015).
63
‘[A] set of global financial reporting standards that is accepted and, equally importantly,
widely and effectively implemented is a critical missing pillar in the emerging inter-
national financial architecture.’ A. Crockett, ‘Towards Global Financial Reporting
Standards: A Critical Pillar in the International Financial Architecture’ (BIS, 2002).
64
A. Crockett, ‘International Financial Arrangements: Architecture and Plumbing’ (BIS,
15 November 1999).
65
‘The Compendium is a joint product of the various standard-setting bodies represented
on the Forum. It will be reviewed and updated on an ongoing basis and is envisaged to
cover a range of areas relevant to sound and stable financial systems: (a) transparency of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Yet the FSF’s response to institutional pluralism was not uncontro-
versial. Born in the midst of controversies over a new ‘international
financial architecture’,66 the Compendium triggered opposing reactions.
Some interpreted it as ‘a single global rule book’ providing ‘reference
rules’ for the operation of financial markets.67 BIS officials supported the
‘pragmatic multitherapy’ approach to ordering provided by the
Compendium in contrast to an institutional framework.68 However,
some lawyers sought to embed its prescriptions within an institutional
structure, in particular within the jurisdiction of the rule of law.69 For
example, Mario Giovanoli70 invoked the rule of ‘international law’ as the
frame of reference to govern institutional multiplicity.71 The legalization
project was similar to the idea of ‘international regulation’ under a new
‘World Financial Authority’ advocated by economists Barry Eichengreen,
Lance Taylor and John Eatwell.72 Two institutional innovations pro-
voked by the 2008 financial crisis had implications for reorganizing
multiplicity. The Group of Twenty (G20) replaced the G7 as a central
forum of economic diplomacy and transformed the FSF in the Financial
Stability Board, enabling participation of state representatives from the
fiscal, monetary, and financial policies; (b) dissemination of economic and financial data;
(c) regulation and supervision of banking, securities, and insurance; (d) disclosure,
transparency, and risk management practices of financial institutions; (e) corporate
governance, accounting, auditing, and bankruptcy; and (f ) payment and settlement
systems.’ Background brief made available to the press at the second meeting of the
Financial Stability Forum, 15 September 1999.
66
J. Eatwell and L. Taylor, Global Finance at Risk: The Case for International Regulation
(Polity Press, 2000); Eichengreen, Toward a New International Financial Architecture; M.
Giovanoli (ed.), International Monetary Law: Issues for the New Millennium (Oxford
University Press, 2000).
67
G. Walker, ‘A New International Architecture and the Financial Stability Forum’, in R. M.
Lastra (ed.), The Reform of the International Financial Architecture (Kluwer Law
International, 2000).
68
A. Icard, ‘Strengthening Financial Stability: Institutional Approach or Pragmatic
Multitherapy?’ (BIS, 1999).
69
On law as a variant of jurisdiction, see S. Pahuja, ‘Laws of Encounter: A Jurisdictional
Account of International Law’ (2013) 1 London Review of International Law 63–98.
70
General Counsel of the BIS from 1989 to 2005.
71
‘[I]t is therefore important to examine all the possibilities which might strengthen
international financial standards by granting them an appropriate legal status in inter-
national law.’ Giovanoli, International Monetary Law, p. 59.
72
Eatwell’s and Taylor’s project was to construct ‘a framework within which a coherent
international policy can be worked out at implemented’. Eatwell and Taylor, Global
Finance at Risk. For a similar perspective, see A. Kern, R. Dhumale and J. Eatwell,
Global Governance of Financial Systems: The International Regulation of Systemic Risk
(Oxford University Press, 2006), at xiii.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
G20.73 These institutional rearrangements meant that a larger group of
actors was able to assemble and shape the Compendium by recognizing
new standards. However, the majority of FSB members were (and still
are) public regulators, and regulators from the Global North seem to
have greater influence than those from other regions. Furthermore,
interactions with market participants and other private actors have
remained limited.74
While the G20 and the FSB provided a limited ‘vertically integrated’
structure of economic decision-making,75 the two organizations also
sidelined ambitious efforts to create overarching institutions, including
through a reform of the IMF. Calls for ‘international harmonization’ and
attempts to ‘reset’ the ‘international financial (non-) system’76 became
the dominant responses to institutional heterogeneity.77 The project to
bring multiplicity within the jurisdiction of international law and inter-
national lawyers has been one manifestation of this trajectory towards
legalization.78 Finding a contradiction between a ‘global’ financial system
and the lack of a coherent institutional framework, many lawyers called
for a global ‘ruler’ in international finance. In keeping with a professional
sensibility shared by many jurists, the legalization project has sought to
conceptualize ‘international financial law’ as the frame of reference to
contain the panoply of norms and practices in finance. From the stand-
point of the legalization project, sometimes this heterogeneity is framed
73
On the transformation of the FSF into the FSB, see E. Carrasco, ‘The Global Financial
Crisis and the Financial Stability Forum’; S. Gadinis, ‘The Financial Stability Board: The
New Politics of International Financial Regulation’ (2013) 48 Texas International Law
Journal 158–75.
74
As Annelise Riles has observed: ‘the FSB process has mainly engaged representatives of
governments and international bureaucracies, with private parties participating only
through more attenuated opportunities for public comment’. Riles, ‘Is New Governance
the Ideal Architecture for Global Financial Regulation?’, 257.
75
Brummer, ‘A Theory of Everything’.
76
J. A. Ocampo, Resetting the International Monetary (Non)System: A Study Prepared by the
United Nations University World Institute for Development Economics Research (UNU-
WIDER, 2017).
77
For an analysis and critique of approaches to harmonization, see Riles, ‘Managing
Regulatory Arbitrage’, 77–87.
78
T. Cottier et al., The Rule of Law in Monetary Affairs: World Trade Forum (Cambridge
University Press, 2014); for a critique of this tendency in international economic inter-
actions, see A. Lang, ‘Rule of Law in International Economic Relations’, in T. Cottier and
K. N. Schefer (eds), Elgar Encyclopedia of International Economic Law (Edward Elgar,
2017).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
as a ‘black hole’.79 This expression refers to an absence of traditional
frames of international law, and the contrast is often made with more
established fields of international economic law, such as international
trade and investment law.
The rationale underlying this approach is that ‘international solutions
are needed for international problems’.80 Under this view, the IMF should
become the institutional centre of the international monetary and financial
system. Proponents of this way of thinking have regarded international
trade law as a model to design a rule of law-based system in international
financial and monetary interactions. The envisaged system would provide
for a ‘World Financial Authority’ and an international dispute settlement
mechanism to fill the ‘black hole’ in international law and finance.
Others have seen the FSB as a more suitable site and actor to promote
the movement of international financial law ‘from a heterarchical setting
to a more centralized and coordinated pattern’.81 When articulating their
position in relation to multiple bodies of norms, FSB members have
described themselves as providers of a ‘framework for strengthening
adherence to international standards’.82 They have called for ‘inter-
national coordination’ through practices of ‘international harmonization’
among domestic regulators. Another approach has sought to articulate a
vision of the global financial order against institutional pluralism through
the notion of ‘multilayered governance’. This perspective seeks to identify
‘common core values shared by the international community’ as guiding
principles for the allocation of regulatory power among the various layers
of governance.83 Similar to the legalization project, advocates of this
mode of ordering start from an intra-systemic perspective from which
79
‘In finance, we have a “black hole” with few formal international rules and no adequate
system to deal with cross-border crisis or conflicts.’ Lastra, ‘Do We Need a World
Financial Organization?’, 797.
80
Ibid., 804.
81
C. de Stefano, ‘Reforming the Governance of International Financial Law in the Era of
Post-Globalization’ (2017) 20 Journal of International Economic Law 509–33. See also M.
De Bellis, ‘Relative Authority in Global and EU Financial Regulation: Linking the
Legitimacy Debates’, in J. Mendes and I. Venzke (eds), Allocating Authority: Who
Should Do What in European and International Law? (Hart Publishing, 2018),
pp. 241–70.
82
See FSB, ‘Promoting Global Adherence to International Cooperation and Information
Exchange Standards’ (2010).
83
R. Weber, ‘Multilayered Governance in International Financial Regulation and
Supervision’, in T. Cottier, J. H. Jackson and R. M. Lastra (eds), International Law in
Financial Regulation and Monetary Affairs (Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 151–70,
at 158–69. For a similar perspective, see P. E. Avgouleas, Governance of Global Financial
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
they formulate a global regulatory framework to construct full coherence
among the different parts of the overall system.
Yet competing visions have been sceptical of legalization as a workable
way of organizing diversity in global financial governance. Critics have
contended that the idea of one overarching institution – a ‘global sher-
iff’84 of sorts – seems out of touch with the heterogeneity and competi-
tion of national concerns and interests driving global business firms
operating in modern global finance.85 For an environment characterized
by ‘increasing multipolarity’ and ‘dispersed economic power and inter-
ests’, a model of pragmatic ‘minilateralism’ may be a better fit than an
institutional grand design.86 The project of harmonization sought to
provide a centre of gravity – a new ‘architecture’ – against or irrespective
of the autonomous norms and practices of legal technique and self-
regulation that market actors, including private organizations such as
the International Swaps and Derivatives Association, use in their finan-
cial business operations on over-the-counter derivatives but that fly
under the radar of overarching institutions.87
Markets: The Law, the Economics, the Politics (Cambridge University Press, 2012),
chapter 8.
84
R. M. Lastra, International Financial and Monetary Law (Oxford University Press, 2015).
85
Brummer argues that the idea of a single global authority is impractical because ‘states are
unlikely to cede power to a global financial regulator’, Brummer, Soft Law and the Global
Financial System, p. 328. See also L. Baxter, ‘Understanding the Global in Global Finance
and Regulation’, in R. Buckley, E. Avgouleas and D. Arner (eds), Reconceptualising Global
Finance and Its Regulation (Cambridge University Press, 2016), pp. 28–48.
86
Brummer, Minilateralism.
87
A. Riles, Collateral Knowledge: Legal Reasoning in the Global Financial Markets
(University of Chicago Press, 2011).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
efforts to reimagine the global financial order. Two manifestations here
were the projects of ‘international regulation’ and ‘legalization’ advocated
by actors associated with the IMF institutional context. Though the two
projects had different nuances, they adopted an intra-systemic perspec-
tive to govern institutional relations from a central vantage point. Indeed,
they both imagined a common integrating principle – ‘international
regulation’ or ‘international law’ – at the apex of the ‘international
financial architecture’. Thus, the philosophy of overarching norms
informed both reform projects.88 In the UN context, the approach to
ordering followed a somewhat similar logic. Relying on a similar form
but a different content of interface norms, the UN Task-Force referred to
‘sustainable human development’ and ‘democracy’89 as principles
governing the decision-making process within the envisaged inter-
national financial architecture. The UN Task-Force interpreted
‘International codes of conduct, improved information, and enhanced
financial supervision and regulation’ as an overarching framework
governing the system. However, they went so far as to argue that the
framework would ‘include international standards to combat money and
asset laundering as well as corruption and tax evasion’ but also ensure
‘consistency’ with human rights, particularly those in the International
Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.90 Moreover, the UN
Task-Force went beyond a purely intra-systemic perspective to take into
view relationships between the international financial system and differ-
ent domestic legal systems. While emphasizing the ‘global’ character of
‘financial regulation and supervision’, the UN Task-Force also gave
weight to domestic legal orders and their ‘different national financial
structure and traditions as regards financial regulation and
supervision’.91
88
On ‘overarching norms’, see Chapter 1.
89
‘We must emphasize that any reform of the international financial system ought to be
based on a broad discussion, involving all countries, and a clear agenda, including all key
issues. The process must ensure that the interests of all groups of developing and
transition economies, including poor and small countries, are adequately represented.
The United Nations, as a universal and the most democratic international forum, should
play an important role in these discussions and in the design of the new system.’ Task-
Force of the Executive Committee on Economic and Social Affairs of the United Nations,
‘Towards a New International Financial Architecture’, 9.
90
Ibid., 15.
91
Task-Force of the Executive Committee on Economic and Social Affairs of the United
Nations, ‘Towards a New International Financial Architecture’, 15.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
While it is not obvious that UN officials perceived domestic legal
systems as integrated parts within the ‘international financial system’, it
seems more plausible that they relied on the more flexible interface norm
of ‘taking into account’ to connect ‘domestic’ and ‘international’
systems.92 When bringing these legal orders into a mutual relation, the
UN body of experts relied on reception norms in so far as they required
that ‘due account should be taken’ of local circumstances in domestic
legal systems.93 The project of international harmonization was never
uncontroversial and provoked tensions with domestic sites of govern-
ance, as evidenced by the attitudes of some national authorities creating
resistance to international standards. For instance, the deputy governor
of the Reserve Bank of India articulated a ‘national law perspective’
highlighting the ‘discretion’ and ‘considerable flexibility’ that officials in
India had while interpreting ‘general principles’ in international stand-
ards and bringing them in relation to the domestic legal order.94 This
language is similar to reception norms in its effect of creating distance
between international standards and the Indian domestic legal system.
After the 2008 financial crisis, the reform of the international financial
architecture emerged as a new site of struggle between lawyers, econo-
mists and policy-makers to redefine interactions between bodies of
norms.95 In this context, forms of entanglement mirrored the dominant
response to multiplicity, in particular at the IMF, that followed the Asian
financial crisis of 1997. Seeking more centralization and unity than
diversity and collaboration, many actors sought to frame multiplicity
from a systemic perspective, adopting a functional analysis. They have
often done so by deploying interface norms such as the ‘rule of law’.96
Particularly in Europe, a similar reliance on overarching norms charac-
terized most responses to institutional diversity,97 placing emphasis on
92
Chapter 1.
93
Task-Force of the Executive Committee on Economic and Social Affairs of the United
Nations, ‘Towards a New International Financial Architecture’, 15.
94
‘[T]here are several reasons to be circumspect about the role of standards and codes as
primary instruments of enhancing international financial stability.’ See Y. V. Reddy,
‘Legal Aspects of International Financial Standards – National Law Perspective’ (BIS
Review, 2002).
95
The financial press also promoted the idea of a formal amendment of Articles of
Agreement to transform the IMF in the new ‘guardian of the global financial system’.
See ‘Wanted: A Guardian of the World’s Financial System’, Financial Times (April 2007).
96
Cottier et al., The Rule of Law in Monetary Affairs.
97
C. Reinhart and K. Rogoff, ‘Regulation Should Be International’, Financial Times
(November 2008).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
regulatory coherence and centralization of authority.98 For example, the
‘de Larosière Report’99 proposed an integrated approach to financial
regulation in Europe and at the international level.100 Noting the ‘evident
lack of a coherent framework’, the authors of the report recommended
that a ‘reformed FSF would be in the best position for coordinating the
work of the various international standard-setters in achieving inter-
national regulatory consistency’.101 They envisaged a treaty establishing
a ‘full international standard-setting authority’ creating binding obliga-
tions for states and monitored by the IMF through its Article IV
Consultations powers.102 At a more general level, this argumentative
structure reflects the imagery suggested by proponents of constitutional-
ism in controversies over the shape of postnational law and politics.
Sharing a similar ambition, many theorists of international financial
regulation have sought to construe a legal system to ‘contain’ the plurality
of sources characterizing global financial governance.103
98
M. Giovanoli and D. Devos (eds), International Monetary and Financial Law: The
Global Crisis (Oxford University Press, 2011).
99
Report by the High-Level Group on Financial Supervision in the EU (Chaired by Jacques
de Larosière), 2009, at 59. See chapter 4 of the report (Global Repair, Promoting
Financial Stability at the Global Level), 2009.
100
The financial press appreciated the ‘step-by-step’ approach advocated by the de
Larosière group. See, ‘A Single Rulebook’, Financial Times (February 2009).
101
Report by the High-Level Group on Financial Supervision in the EU.
102
Ibid.
103
N. Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law
(Oxford University Press, 2010), chapter 2.
104
For the full list of members of the Task-Force, see FSF, ‘Issue Paper of the Task-Force on
Implementation of Standards’ (March 2000), 29–30.
105
Ibid., 3.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
recognized as relevant for ‘sound financial systems’, the Task-Force
highlighted a ‘subset’ of twelve standards that were ‘likely to make the
greatest contribution to reducing vulnerabilities and strengthening the
resilience of financial systems’.106 This group of experts recommended
that ‘policy-makers’ should focus on a ‘list of standards’ with ‘priority
implementation depending on countries’ circumstances’.
In a footnote of its report, the Task-Force articulated the rationale of
its decision-making by claiming that ‘while a broad range of political,
social, legal, and institutional factors impinge on financial stability, the
focus of the FSF is on economic and financial standards which are
generally accepted by the international community as being objective
and relatively free of national biases’.107 It is worth analysing how the
Task-Force simultaneously distanced a group of norms from the list
and brought other bodies of norms together. Indeed, it seems that the
Task-Force had recourse to a ‘knowledge practice’108 when it distin-
guished between, on the one hand ‘political’, ‘social’, ‘legal’ and ‘insti-
tutional’ norms, and on the other hand ‘economic and financial
standards for sound financial systems’. This practice of boundary-
drawing enabled the Task-Force to carve out what it termed ‘inter-
nationally accepted standards for economic, financial and market activ-
ities’, creating distance from norms that did not fit in that category.109
This technique contrasts with straddling practices, that is, ‘practices
that straddle different bodies of norms without being seen to belong to
either, thus blurring the boundaries between them’.110 However, strad-
dling practices were also at play in the making of the Compendium.
After distancing ‘political’, ‘social’, ‘legal’ and ‘institutional’ norms from
the scope of its work, the Task-Force assembled ‘the set of standards
it considers the most relevant to strengthening financial systems’.
By ‘drawing on prior work’111 the Task-Force connected twelve stand-
ards to create something new out of this assemblage, namely a
consolidated list of ‘key standards for sound financial systems’112
106
Ibid., 3.
107
FSF, ‘Issue Paper of the Task-Force on Implementation of Standards’, 7.
108
On ‘knowledge practices’ and their effects, see Riles, Collateral Knowledge.
109
FSF, ‘Issue Paper of the Task-Force on Implementation of Standards’, 7.
110
Chapter 1.
111
FSF, ‘Issue Paper of the Task-Force on Implementation of Standards’, 18.
112
Code of Good Practices on Transparency in Monetary and Financial Policies, Code of
Good Practices in Fiscal Transparency, Special Data Dissemination Standard/General
Data Dissemination System, Principles of Corporate Governance, International
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
around which ‘international consensus’ had to be forged. This list of
‘twelve key standards’ then was the effect of a straddling practice,
blurring the boundaries between the bodies of norms that were
assembled in it. From the perspective of the Task-Force, the definition
of this select group of bodies of norms as ‘key international standards’
was crucial to achieve international consensus. In this assessment, the
Task-Force placed emphasis on those standards that were ‘endorsed’ by
the ‘international community’, by which the Task-Force meant in
particular national regulators, the IMF, the World Bank and inter-
national standard-setting bodies. In this way, the Task-Force brought
into a mutual relation the standards that had been recognized as
authoritative by the official sector of which the Task-Force itself was
a part. As a creation of the FSF, the Task-Force included representatives
of national governments, the IMF, the World Bank and the Basel
Committee on Banking Supervision. By bringing together and giving
weight to the standards that had been recognized by FSF members,
international financial institutions and international standard-setting
organizations, the Task-Force manifested a certain degree of self-
referentiality.113
The choice of focusing on standards produced and used by the ‘official
sector’ (i.e. public actors)114 created distance from norms of private
origin, with the exception of standards developed by the IASC and the
International Federation of Accountants. The Task-Force framed the
Compendium as a ‘one-stop reference’ to forge international consensus
on ‘key standards’, limiting disagreement on their definition and with the
aim of accommodating ‘a large number of standards’ that users could
easily refer to.115 For the internal organization of the Compendium, the
Task-Force preferred a ‘web-based’ structure to a hierarchical form to
create linkages with a corpus of other ‘relevant standards’ that were ‘not
less important than the 12 key standards [. . .] but [were] complemen-
tary’ to them.116 These complementary standards ought to be ‘organized
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
separately’ under three different categories.117 The Task-Force also envis-
aged that additional standards could be added to the Compendium as
long as they were approved by relevant standard-setting bodies and FSF
members.118
After the financial crisis of 2008, the creation by the G20 of the FSB as
the successor of the FSF confirmed the forms of enmeshment construed
when the Compendium was still in the making. The number of standards
included in the Compendium grew considerably after the institutional-
ization of the FSB. As FSB members recognized new standards for ‘sound
financial systems’, the boundaries of the Compendium expanded akin to
the pages of a rule book, positing a distance between standards included
in the Compendium and other bodies of norms that were kept outside.
The incremental growth of the Compendium also strengthened the
position of the FSB as an actor in the organization of standards recog-
nized by the ‘official sector’.
At the FSB, structures and dynamics of entanglement may depend on
the actors involved in its decision-making.119 Here, the forms and con-
tent of interface norms may reflect the composition of the FSB but also
the set of relations that the FSB has with other actors and institutions in
the social and political environment in which it operates. With respect to
membership, existing analyses have placed emphasis on the interactions
between FSB members as central factors driving the activities of the FSB.
Characterized by a broader membership than the FSF, the FSB has been
portrayed as ‘a nexus point’ enabling interaction and communication
between ‘communities of private actors’ and ‘communities of states’.120
Stavros Gadinis has described it as ‘an umbrella organization that brings
together [. . .] networks of ministry executives, national regulators, and
private professionals’,121 placing emphasis on its strong ministry com-
ponent. As such analyses have shown, state officials from the G20 and
experts from standard-setting organizations have been the dominant
117
The categories that the Task-Force construed were: ‘broad headings’ (including macro-
economic fundamentals, institutional and market infrastructures, and financial regula-
tion and supervision), ‘policy areas’ and ‘functional areas’. Ibid., 21.
118
Ibid., 21.
119
On the centrality of actors in the construction of entanglements, see Chapter 1.
120
L. C. Backer, ‘Private Actors and Public Governance beyond the State: The Multinational
Corporation, the Financial Stability Board, and the Global Governance Order’ (2011) 18
Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 751–802.
121
S. Gadinis, ‘Three Pathways to Global Standards: Private, Regulator, and Ministry
Networks’ (2015) 109 American Journal of International Law 1–57, at 56.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
players shaping the agenda of the FSB. This dominance is reflected for
example in the fact that there is a higher number of members from
countries which are a part of the European Union than from other
economies.122
On the other hand, participation from market actors and public–
private collaboration appear to be limited. According to the FSB’s self-
representation, the degree of recognition of actors and norms of private
origin seems rather limited. For example, the International Accounting
Standards Board, formally a private organization, is a member of the FSB,
and the International Financial Reporting Standards that they produce
have been included in the Compendium of Standards. However,
according to Annelise Riles, the FSB ‘fails to recognize the practical
authority of organizations such as the International Swaps and
Derivatives Association in constructing their own forms of international
financial governance beyond the state’.123 Thus, the interface norms
construed within the Compendium are likely to be shaped by the con-
vergence or competition of interests of the dominant public actors that
have access to the FSB and by the wider institutional environment (i.e.
the ‘international financial architecture’) in which the FSB itself is situ-
ated. For example, interactions between the FSB and the G20 may have
consequences for the types of norms that are brought in relation in
this context.
In the FSB context, straddling practices were not the only form of
entanglement. Rather, conditional recognition practices originally per-
formed by the Task-Force were also instrumental in organizing relations
between ‘key standards’, the ‘complementary standards’ included in the
Compendium and those yet to be included. Over time, FSB members
have relied on a set of ‘criteria for inclusion’ to give weight only to
standards deemed to be ‘relevant’, ‘implementable’, ‘internationally rec-
ognized’ and ‘widely applicable’.124 However, the combined application
of these criteria also consolidated a distinction between standards per-
ceived to meet these criteria and standards which failed to do so. The
interpretation of these requirements then had a rejection effect because it
122
D. Arner and M. Taylor, ‘The Financial Stability Board and the Future of International
Financial Regulation’, in R. Buckley, E. Avgouleas and D. Arner (eds), Reconceptualising
Global Finance and Its Regulation (Cambridge University Press, 2016), pp. 51–66.
123
Riles, ‘Is New Governance the Ideal Architecture’, 257.
124
These criteria of recognition have been published on the website of the FSB. See www.fsb
.org/work-of-the-fsb/about-the-compendium-of-standards/.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
distanced laws of private origin, which many actors use in their practices.
For example, norms produced by the financial industry do not seem to be
considered as relevant by FSB members, hence their absence from the
Compendium. From this perspective, the ‘criteria for inclusion of stand-
ards in the Compendium’ may be seen as the content of an interface
norm governing interactions between internal and external bodies of
norms. In particular, the reproduction of this inside/outside distinction
was performed by a reception norm whose content was a specific set of
requirements defining ‘the ways in which outside norms enter a given
body of norms’.125 In sum, it seems that straddling practices and recep-
tion norms played a more prominent role than overarching norms in the
institutional site in which the Compendium took shape. The
Compendium was the outcome of a work of composition that consisted
of selecting, assembling and distancing bodies of norms. As the
Compendium was still in the making, the Task-Force relied less on
overarching norms than on straddling practices to perform this task.
Such a form of entanglement makes sense because the task at hand was
the creation of a new regulatory arrangement, in a context relatively free
from pre-existing systemic constraints. Indeed, the project of a
Compendium was in the first place the key innovation of the Task-
Force and therefore its boundaries were still in flux. The effect of using
this type of interface norm was closer to an assemblage type of order than
to a system with clear institutional boundaries. However, the Task-Force
also generated rules for the inclusion of ‘international standards’ and
these criteria of recognition form the content of the reception norm that
continues to order relations between the Compendium and external
bodies of norms.
125
See definition of ‘reception norms’ in Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
FSAP assessments every five years’.126 FSB members have practised
thematic and country-based peer reviews to assess compliance with
international financial standards through a ‘holistic approach’.127 These
practices have followed the FSB Handbook for Peer Review and taken the
FSAP’s and Reports on the Observance of Standards and Codes’ recom-
mendations into account.128 In the context of these monitoring practices
and ‘peer reviews’, acts of referring to the prescriptions of ‘the other’ have
also blurred the boundaries between bodies of norms and enabled a
mutual strengthening of their relations.
The straddling practice of compiling lists of international standards
was not unique to the FSF/FSB as other actors and institutions beyond
the FSB had recourse to similar techniques.129 Indeed, global governance
practices through the creation of lists have also been common in other
issue areas of global administration, for example international secur-
ity.130 The Basel Committee on Banking Supervision issued a
‘Compendium of Basel Committee documents’, which was subsequently
updated in 2001.131 In December 2019, the Committee published its
‘Consolidated Framework’ (referred to as ‘Basel Framework’) which
embodies all fourteen standards it produced since its creation.132
Beyond its own norms, the chapter on ‘Core Principles for Effective
Banking Supervision’ refers to other standards and practices, such as
the recommendations by the IMF formulated in its FSAPs.133 These
126
See www.fsb.org/about/leading-by-example/participation/.
127
Gadinis, ‘The Financial Stability Board’, 161.
128
The Handbook for FSB Peer Review specifies that ‘Country Reviews [. . .] examine the
steps taken or planned by national/regional authorities to address IMF-World Bank
Financial Sector Assessment Program (FSAP) and Reports on the Observance of
Standards and Codes (ROSCs) recommendations on financial regulation and supervi-
sion.’ See Standing Committee on Standards Implementation, ‘Handbook for FSB Peer
Reviews’ (2017).
129
M. De Bellis, ‘Global Standards for Domestic Financial Regulations: Concourse,
Competition and Mutual Reinforcement between Different Types of Global
Administration’ (2006) 6 Global Jurist Advances, https://doi.org/10.2202/1535-1661
.1184.
130
See, for example, G. Sullivan, The Law of the List: UN Counterterrorism Sanctions and
the Politics of Global Security Law (Cambridge University Press, 2020).
131
Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, ‘Compendium of Documents Produced by
the Basel Committee on Banking Supervision’ (May 2001).
132
Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, ‘The Basel Framework’ (December 2019).
133
‘The regular reports by the IMF and the World Bank on the lessons drawn from
assessment experiences as part of FSAP exercises constitute a useful source of infor-
mation which has been used as an input to improve the Principles’. Footnote 40 at p. 28
of the chapter on Core Principles.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
practices have allowed shaping an entanglement between international
financial standards and between these bodies of norms and domestic
legal orders.
Basel Committee members encouraged taking account of anti-money
laundering recommendations by the Financial Action Task Force
(FATF).134 IOSCO, the Basel Committee and IAIS have blurred bound-
aries between their recommendations on combating money laundering
and the financing of terrorism. In a joint statement, the three institutions
claimed that the FATF 40 Recommendations provided a basis that would
allow them to ‘take account’ of their respective standards in future
work.135 The FATF, on the other hand, also took account of Basel
Committee recommendations when it linked the ‘customer due diligence’
norm for banks originally crafted in 2001 by the Committee136 to its
recommendations to combat money laundering.137 The language of
‘taking into account’ other standards reappeared in another statement,
but this time the norms referred to were those of the FATF itself.138
Similarly, the interconnected structure of international standards has
134
‘[S]upervisors should encourage the adoption of those recommendations of the
Financial Action Task-Force on Money Laundering (FATF) that apply to financial
institutions.’ Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, ‘Core Principles on Banking
Supervision’ (1997).
135
‘The revised 40 FATF Recommendations will provide an opportunity for the standard-
setting organizations to review their standards and guidance taking account of each
other’s work in this respect with the aim of preventing as far as possible inconsistencies
between their standards and guidance where this is unwarranted from a risk-based
approach.’ The Joint Forum Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, International
Organization of Securities Commissions, International Association of Insurance
Supervisors, ‘Initiatives by the BCBS, IAIS and IOSCO to Combat Money Laundering
and the Financing of Terrorism – Joint Statement’ (3 June 2003).
136
Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, ‘Customer Due Diligence for Banks’
(October 2001).
137
Following this, the BCBS stated that it was ‘pleased to note the extent to which its
publication Customer Due Diligence for Banks [. . .], has been reflected in the FATF’s
recommendations concerning customer due diligence. In all substantive respects, the
spirit of the Committee’s paper has been incorporated within the FATF approach.’ Basel
Committee on Banking Supervision, ‘Basel Committee Welcomes Revised FATF
Recommendations’ (2003).
138
‘[T]he IAIS adopted a Guidance paper on anti-money laundering and combating the
financing of terrorism [. . .] The new guidance paper takes into account the revised
FATF 40 Recommendations of June 2003 and the Methodology for Assessing compli-
ance with the FATF 40 recommendations and the 8 special recommendations issued in
February 2004, as well as the 8 Special Recommendations on Terrorist Financing of
October 2001.’ The Joint Forum: Basel Committee on Banking Supervision,
International Organization of Securities Commissions, International Association of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
been emphasized by private norm addressees in financial markets.139
These statements have been subtle conduits in the discursive enmesh-
ment of financial standards. Financial regulators and producers of those
standards have often construed standards in connection with other
standards, which suggests that these norms have become entangled in
an interconnected ‘web’ of norms.140 As we have seen, the web-like shape
of the Compendium equipped with hyperlinks to enable users to connect
to the webpages of the different standard producers (and their standards)
was indeed foreseen by the Task-Force on Implementation of Standards.
This particular feature enabled users of the Compendium to create loose,
ad hoc connections between standards through their statements and
practices. It may be that this particular way of constructing relations
between bodies of norms was done for strategic reasons, perhaps to
strengthen the authority of the technical bodies that make those stand-
ards, including standard-setting organizations that are members of the
FSB itself.141
11.4 Conclusion
This chapter has focused on forms, locations and practices in which
relations between bodies of norms in global financial governance have
been defined in the aftermath of the Asian financial crisis and the global
financial crisis. Drawing on official pronouncements connected to the
IMF, the UN and the BIS, it has observed the different contexts in which
these relations have come about. The institutional memory examined has
provided traces of ad hoc but not uncontroversial construction of
entanglements and the participants and factors behind them. In many
of the sites of governance examined, different forms were articulated
through dynamic and informal interactions of a multiplicity of
Insurance Supervisors, ‘Initiatives by the BCBS, IAIS and IOSCO to Combat Money
Laundering and the Financing of Terrorism Update – Joint Statement’ (2005).
139
The European Banking Federation has referred to the plurality of norms contained in
the document ‘Basel III: Finalising Post-Crisis Reform’, which they call Basel IV, as a
‘package’. See EBF, ‘Summary on Basel IV in Europe’ (2019).
140
Chapter 1.
141
Previous work has suggested that international standards might be ‘mutually reinforcing’
through practices of cross-referencing and incorporation. See De Bellis, ‘Global
Standards for Domestic Financial Regulation’. On this ‘strategic’ path to entanglement,
see Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
regulators, international institutions and international standard-setting
organizations involved in the global governance of financial stability.
Competing ordering projects have emerged in different contexts in the
theory and practice of global financial governance over time. These
projects were also sites in which actors imagined different ways of
shaping ‘international standards’ and their relations, with implications
for the forms of entanglement that came about through their claims.
Since the second half of 1990s, the multiplication of standards deemed to
be relevant by financial regulators has triggered efforts to define their
relations, and regulators have relied on different interface norms at
different sites of governance to create order. International lawyers have
often imagined the global financial order from an intra-systemic perspec-
tive and sought to organize institutional pluralism through overarching
norms such as the rule of law.
Although many of the actors analysed imagine a global financial
system, there is a lack of general agreement on the implications for the
relations between different bodies of norms. Differently situated actors
defined their relative weight in different ways by placing emphasis on
different norms and sites of authority. For example, in their respective
ordering projects in response to multiplicity, officials at the UN, the IMF
and at the BIS have come up with conflicting views on the position of the
relevant sites of authority. From this perspective, the emerging overall
order remains pluralistic.
Drawing on the history of the Compendium of Standards, differences
between forms of entanglement connected with the Financial Stability
Forum and those linked to the IMF and UN contexts could be observed.
Standards included in the Compendium were ordered through an inter-
play of straddling practices and reception norms. When the
Compendium was still in the making, the former type of interface norm
appeared in the work of the Task-Force on Implementation of Standards.
In this context, boundary-drawing practices, too, were used to create
distance from norms that actors assembled at the FSF did not identify as
relevant. By contrast, other bodies of norms were connected to form an
official list of international financial standards, around which an inter-
national consensus had to be built. The making of a list of ‘twelve key
standards’ was the outcome of a straddling practice by the Task-Force,
which had the effect of blurring the boundaries between the bodies of
norms that were brought within this new list. However, the increasing
institutionalization of the FSB has been coupled with a greater emphasis
on practices of regulatory uniformity and centralization. Through the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Compendium of Standards, regulators assembled at the FSB sought to
provide a common frame to respond to the dilemmas of proximity and
difference of bodies of norms in global financial governance. Over time,
the FSB has sought to bring together multiple monitoring practices and
their bodies of norms within a single overarching ‘framework’.142 From
this perspective, it seems that a hierarchical ambition has also been
at play.
However, institutional pluralism provoked similar responses in other
settings, too, which triggered further forms of entanglement through the
production of further compendia, lists, and rule books to order relations
between bodies of norms for global financial stability. The emerging
picture is heterogeneous, as evidenced by the absence of a single global
decision-maker, the coexistence of different plans for reform and differ-
ent visions of the relevant sites of decision-making and forms of
authority.
142
FSB, ‘Framework for Strengthening Adherence to International Standards’ (January
2010); FSB, ‘A Coordination Framework for Monitoring the Implementation of
Agreed G-20/FSB Financial Reforms’ (2011).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
12
š č
12.1 Introduction
The field of corporate social responsibility (CSR) is a rapidly growing
area of transnational regulation that is characterized by a multiplicity of
norm-making processes in a variety of institutions and different forums.
These processes are reflexive, engaging in mutual interaction through
mirroring, distancing or complementing existing normative frameworks.
The resulting landscape of CSR is defined by contestation and entangle-
ment as CSR instruments of different origin coexist side by side, some-
times with competing claims to compliance. As a result, CSR is a
particularly fertile ground for studying how the relations between differ-
ent bodies of norms are construed.
This chapter sets out to understand how actors entangle CSR norms
and, in doing so, create an interlinked web of normative systems, both
formal and informal, operating within the state as well as without it.
Section 12.2 serves as a brief orientation within the complex world of
CSR, identifying the main discourses and categorizations. Out of the
multitude of collections of norms which come under the umbrella of
CSR, the chapter draws focus to meta-regulatory CSR norms, and in
particular the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and
Development (OECD) Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises (the
Guidelines).1 Being positioned at the intersection of traditional inter-
national law, soft law initiatives developed within international organiza-
tions, and private standards and codes, the Guidelines provide a focal
1
OECD, Declaration on International Investment and Multinational Enterprises Annex I:
Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises (adopted 21 June 1976, last amended 25 May
2011) OECD/LEGAL/0144.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
point for CSR entanglement. Section 12.3 looks at how the structural
features of the Guidelines have contributed to the coordinated legal
entanglement between various bodies of norms, which should be under-
stood as the creation of stable, systemic and lasting connections and
points of interaction. Coordinated legal entanglement can also create
space for ad hoc entanglement, which is analysed in Section 12.4. The
idea of ad hoc entanglement refers to more fluid and contingent inter-
actions which might deepen the ties between bodies of norms but also
sever them. The turn to ad hoc entanglement also involves a change of
the subject of enquiry, moving from the systemic features of the OECD
Guidelines to focus on actual instances of disputes around CSR, crystal-
lized in the case law arising out of OECD National Contact Points
(NCPs) – the Guidelines’ implementation mechanism. As indicated, the
picture here is more diverse, and interactions between various frame-
works are analysed on a scale ranging from distancing to proximity.
By exploring forms of legal entanglement in the field of CSR, the aim is
to glean more insight into the evolving shape of this global legal order,
which has expanded to include a range of new subjects, norm-making
institutions and regulatory tools. To this end, Section 12.5 draws atten-
tion to some of the dynamics which appear to be emerging through the
interaction of the Guidelines with other bodies of norms. These types of
structuring disrupt the traditional notion of a horizontal international
legal order. What we see instead is something more akin to a three-
dimensional and polycentric web created through new and irreverent
forms of linkage and accommodation over time.
2
J. A. Zerk, Multinationals and Corporate Social Responsibility: Limitations and
Opportunities in International Law (Cambridge University Press 2006), p. 30.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
basis’.3 On the opposite end of the spectrum, non-governmental organ-
izations (NGOs) – confronted with the reality of human rights abuses
and environmental harms associated with the activities of global corpor-
ations – often prefer not to use the term CSR at all, rejecting the way it
has been framed and operationalized by businesses. For example, the
Amnesty International homepage on ‘corporations’ does not mention
the term ‘corporate social responsibility’ once. Instead, Amnesty
International calls for corporate accountability, thus bringing it closer
to the notion of accountability under law.4
The dichotomy about CSR being either intrinsically voluntary or
binding is somewhat misleading, however. As Zerk notes, the regulatory
impact of CSR provisions does not necessarily correlate to their formal
binding power.5 More neutral definitions of CSR thus avoid references to
the mandatory/voluntary distinction, emphasizing instead the social and
environmental embeddedness of corporate activities and focusing on the
corporate responsibility to address negative impacts while maximizing
positive contributions. In this vein, Aguinis and Glavas define CSR as
‘context-specific organizational actions and policies that take into
account stakeholders’ expectations and the triple bottom line of eco-
nomic, social, and environmental performance’.6 Similarly, Zerk defines
CSR as ‘the notion, that each business enterprise, as a member of society,
has a responsibility to operate ethically and in accordance with its legal
obligations and to strive to minimise any adverse effects of its operations
and activities on the environment, society, and human health’.7
In sum, CSR can encompass adherence to both voluntary commit-
ments and legal obligations with regard to corporations’ impacts on
society in the broad sense of the term. CSR norms can be codified in
many different forms and may be produced by a host of different actors.
Individual companies produce ‘codes of conduct’ containing general
principles for ‘ethical business conduct’, often applicable in relation to
suppliers/subcontractors, and occasionally linked to specific monitoring
3
EU Commission, ‘Green Paper: Promoting a European Framework for Corporate Social
Responsibility’ (adopted 18 July 2001) COM (2001) 366.
4
Amnesty International, Everything You Need to Know about Human Rights and Corporate
Accountability, www.amnesty.org/en/what-we-do/corporate-accountability/.
5
Zerk, Multinationals and Corporate Social Responsibility, p. 32 et seq.
6
H. Aguinis and A. Glavas, ‘What We Know and Don’t Know about Corporate Social
Responsibility: A Review and Research Agenda’ (2012) 38 Journal of Management 932–68,
at 933.
7
Zerk, Multinationals and Corporate Social Responsibility, p. 32.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
(and even complaints) mechanisms, and with sanctions in case of non-
compliance. Codes of conduct are also produced at the sectoral level by
industry associations, or in the context of multi-stakeholder groups (e.g.
the Fair Labour Organization). NGOs and civil society actors have also
produced a wide-ranging set of CSR norms, including labelling initiatives
(e.g. Fairtrade), sectoral principles or certification schemes (e.g. the
Fairmined Standard for Gold from Artisanal and Small-Scale Mining),
multi-stakeholder initiatives (e.g. the Ethical Trading Initiative) and
guidelines (e.g. the Voluntary Principles on Security and Human
Rights). In many instances, governments have organized, facilitated,
funded or participated in the drafting of CSR codes, sometimes even
establishing their own labelling schemes (such as the EU’s Ecolabel).
A category of CSR norms which is of particular interest to this chapter
is the so-called ‘meta-regulatory’ instruments. These can be broadly
described as CSR norms produced by international organizations and
standard-setting organizations which are directed at multinational cor-
porations (e.g. the International Labour Organization (ILO) Tripartite
Declaration containing minimum labour standards). Some of these
instruments cover a broad range of areas (e.g. the OECD Guidelines)
and are linked to non-judicial complaints mechanisms, while others are
directed at specific sectors (e.g. the OECD-Food and Agriculture
Organization Guidance for Responsible Agricultural Supply Chains) or
cover only specific areas of impact (e.g. the UN Guiding Principles on
Business and Human Rights). Positioning themselves above other CSR
norms, they often attract entanglement and serve as focal points for
interaction.
8
Marx and Wouters map the dynamics of cooperation and competition in the more
narrowly construed space of voluntary sustainability standards – see A. Marx and
J. Wouters, ‘Competition and Cooperation in the Market of Voluntary Sustainability
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
inherently ‘regulate regulation’9 and, as a result of this, have a higher
propensity for coordinated entanglement – that is, creating lasting and
relatively stable regime interactions which contribute to an interlinked
web of normative bodies of norms. Among these CSR frameworks, the
OECD Guidelines stand out in particular due to their comprehensive
coverage of corporate behaviour and structural openness towards other
frameworks. As Backer notes, the Guidelines ‘are beginning to serve as
the focal point for the construction of an autonomous transnational
governance system that is meant to serve as the touchstone for corporate
behaviour in multinational economic relationships’.10
The history of the Guidelines dates back to 1976 when the document
was born as an annex to the OECD’s Ministerial Declaration on
International Investment and Multinational Enterprises. Other authors
have written comprehensively about the development of the
Guidelines;11 here it suffices to say that they are a soft law document
containing recommendations to multinational enterprises in relation to
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the adverse impacts which arise as part of their business activities. While
the recommendations themselves are not binding on corporations,
adhering countries (including some non-OECD countries) have an obli-
gation to promote the Guidelines.12 Over the years, the Guidelines have
undergone multiple revisions which have significantly expanded both
their subject scope and geographical reach, with the major revisions
happening in 2000 and 2011. From a legal entanglement perspective,
the earlier versions of the Guidelines were uninspiring as they ‘made no
reference to standards other than those created in the national sphere’.13
Despite the existence of reservations about the merits of ‘cross-pollin-
ation’ with other bodies of norms,14 however, the 2000 revision of the
Guidelines embraced coordinated entanglement through a number of
provisions in the updated text. First, the scope of regulation applicable to
corporate behaviour was extended beyond domestic norms to include all
‘applicable law’,15 clarified through the OECD’s commentary to the
Guidelines’ chapter on labour standards as referring to the idea that
enterprises can be subject to ‘national, sub-national, as well as supra-
national levels of regulation’.16 A similarly broad wording was adopted in
relation to the chapter on environment, which refers to ‘relevant inter-
national agreements, principles, objectives, and standards’.17 The
wording created an opening through which the Guidelines could be
entangled with other bodies of norms, at first being mainly restricted to
more traditional international law norms, but this continuously
expanded. Second, the 2000 version of the Guidelines explicitly identified
a number of instruments which were considered as a relevant resource to
determine the scope of obligations, or which the Guidelines were aligned
with. Out of those, the various ILO documents cited18 and the
International Organization for Standardization (ISO) Standard on
Environmental Management Systems stand out, as they can be seen as
directly competing with the Guidelines in the ‘market’ of transnational
12
OECD, ‘Decision of the Council on the OECD Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises’
(adopted 27 June 2000) OECD/LEGAL/0307. See also R. Nieuwenkamp, ‘The OECD
Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises on Responsible Business Conduct’ (2013)
Dovenschmidt Quarterly 171–5, at 172.
13
Murray, ‘A New Phase in the Regulation of Multinational Enterprises’, 258.
14
Tully, ‘The 2000 Review of the OECD Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises’, 397.
15
See 2000 edition of the OECD Guidelines, chapters I and IV.
16
Ibid., chapter IV commentary.
17
Ibid., chapter V.
18
Ibid., chapter IV.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
regulation of corporate conduct. By including such references in the text,
and predominantly in the Commentary which forms an integral part of
the Guidelines, the OECD began to create the sort of lasting, systemic
connections between bodies of norms which characterize coordinated
entanglement and enmeshment, and realize the benefits resulting from
cooperation between systems.19
The 2011 revision of the Guidelines further developed this trend.
‘Applicable law’ became ‘applicable laws and internationally recognized
standards’,20 providing a basis for entanglement with bodies of norms
which might not be considered law under doctrinal interpretations. The
collection of explicitly entangled frameworks grew as well. The undeni-
ably biggest contribution came from the inclusion of a new, standalone
chapter on human rights, inspired by the UN Guiding Principles on
Business and Human Rights (UNGPs).21 The alignment of the
Guidelines with the UNGPs significantly expanded the normative CSR
web, creating direct and indirect linkages with a multitude of bodies of
norms. The UNGPs are framed as a ‘conceptual and policy framework’
for business and human rights, elaborated through extensive multi-
stakeholder consultations led by Special Representative (SR) John
Ruggie. Having been adopted by the UN Human Rights Council,22 they
operationalize the three-pillar ‘Protect, Respect and Remedy’
Framework23 developed by SR Ruggie. While they perform a number
of complex roles vis-à-vis a multitude of actors, for the purposes of this
chapter we can classify them as a global soft law CSR framework, albeit
acknowledging their multifaceted nature. An important element of the
UNGPs is that their implementation takes place through ‘influence on or
integration into other transnational business governance instruments’.24
19
Such as mutually enhancing legitimacy and the prevention of a race to the bottom
between standards – Marx and Wouters, ‘Competition and Cooperation in the Market
of Voluntary Sustainability Standards’, 232.
20
See 2011 edition of the OECD Guidelines, chapter I [1].
21
Special Representative of the Secretary-General, ‘Guiding Principles on Business and
Human Rights: Implementing the United Nations “Protect, Respect and Remedy”
Framework’ (21 March 2011) UN Doc A/HRC/17/31.
22
UNHRC, ‘Human Rights and Transnational Corporations and Other Business
Enterprises’ (6 July 2011) UN Doc A/HRC/RES/17/4.
23
Special Representative of the Secretary-General, ‘Protect, Respect and Remedy:
A Framework for Business and Human Rights’ (7 April 2008) UN Doc A/HRC/8/5.
24
K. Buhmann, ‘Business and Human Rights: Understanding the UN Guiding Principles
from the Perspective of Transnational Business Governance Interactions’ (2015) 6
Transnational Legal Theory 399–434, at 426.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Among these, the Guidelines take pride of place, evidenced by SR
Ruggie’s assertions that in parallel to preparing the UNGPs he worked
closely with the OECD to ensure consistency between the two bodies of
norms.25 Beyond the Guidelines, the most recent amendment of the ILO
MNE Declaration26 takes into account normative developments within
the UNGPs, directly transposing some parts of the UNGPs with only
minor clarificatory changes in their wording; and both the International
Finance Corporation (IFC) Performance Standards and ISO
26000 Sustainability Standard have been coordinated so as to ensure
compliance of their respective human rights provisions with the
UNGPs.27 Buhmann describes this as ‘mutual piggybacking’ between
corporate governance schemes, providing implementation mechanisms
for the UNGPs, and the UNGPs in turn imbuing other bodies with
legitimacy.28 Using the categorization suggested by Krisch in Chapter 1,
the UNGPs are performing the role of ‘overarching norms’, characterized
by the intra-systemic and overarching nature which they display in regard
to the regulation of multiple bodies of norms within a single system.29
Thus, the UNGPs enable the weaving together of international human
rights law provisions across different normative bodies and, in doing so,
indirectly entangling the Guidelines in an intricate normative web.
A further major feature of the 2000 and 2011 revisions of the
Guidelines is the development of straddling practices – ‘norms and
practices that straddle different bodies of norms without being seen to
belong to either’30 – and again, the UNGPs are prominent in this regard,
with their introduction of the concept of human rights due diligence.
Although the notion of due diligence is not uncommon within
25
J. G. Ruggie, ‘Hierarchy or Ecosystem? Regulating Human Rights Risks of Multinational
Enterprises’, in C. Rodriguez-Garavito (ed.), Business and Human Rights: Beyond the End
of the Beginning (Cambridge University Press, 2017), pp. 46–61, at p. 49; J. G. Ruggie and
T. Nelson, ‘Human Rights and the OECD Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises:
Normative Innovations and Implementation Challenges’ Corporate Social
Responsibility Initiative Working Paper No. 66 (2015) 426.
26
ILO, Tripartite Declaration of Principles Concerning Multinational Enterprises and Social
Policy (adopted November 1977, last amended 17 March 2017).
27
Ruggie, ‘Hierarchy or Ecosystem?’, 49–50.
28
Buhmann, ‘Business and Human Rights’, 427.
29
See Chapter 1, Section 1.5.1.
30
The effect of such straddling is that boundaries between bodies of norms are blurred.
Straddling practices are thus closest to what we would understand as trans-systemic
norms which find applicability across multiple systems and have the ability to ‘weave’
linkages between them. See Chapter 1, Section 1.5.1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
international law, particularly in international environmental law,31 the
decision by SR Ruggie to reconceptualize it in the context of human
rights obligations of corporations, that is non-state actors, was novel. Yet,
when the human rights due diligence principle was incorporated into the
Guidelines, it was not restricted to the human rights chapter – the OECD
took the decision to make it applicable to all areas covered by the
Guidelines. A similar thing happened to the concept of Environmental
Impact Assessments (EIAs), introduced in the earlier versions of the
Guidelines. The fundamentals of the concept, which originated within
international environmental law, found application also in relation to
non-environmental impacts of corporate behaviour, morphing into
Environmental and Social Impact Assessments (ESIAs) and Social
Impact Assessments. As will become clear from Section 12.4, the imple-
mentation mechanisms of the Guidelines have steadily portrayed these
concepts as true straddling practices, being irreverent about their origins
and treating them as inherent to the Guidelines.
31
H. Cullen, ‘The Irresistible Rise of Human Rights Due Diligence: Conflict Minerals and
beyond’ (2015) 48 George Washington International Law Review 743–80, at 745–49.
32
See 2011 edition OECD Guidelines, Procedural Guidance, Chapter I (A).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
degrees of interministerial integration and stakeholder engagement.33
The diversity of actors already involved at the organizational level creates
space for a variety of perspectives, and bodies of norms, to be brought to
the table. The inclusion of external CSR norms is further facilitated by
the open-endedness of the provisions on specific instances. The mandate
for specific instances is defined vaguely – essentially, it ‘is intended to
provide a consensual, non-adversarial, “forum for discussion”’.34 What
this means in practice, however, is open to interpretation by NCPs, and
as this section shows, NCPs do diverge significantly in the way they
understand this mandate.
At its simplest, the procedure is supposed to bring together interested
parties to discuss issues arising in relation to activities of multinational
enterprises which potentially impact on the implementation of the
Guidelines. The term ‘interested parties’ is important, as it denotes the
open-ended definition of who can trigger a specific instance. Complaints
are generally brought by NGOs supporting the claims of affected com-
munities but can also be initiated by trade unions, directly by concerned
individuals, multi-stakeholder initiatives, local communities, businesses
and even the NCPs themselves, showing that the potential range of actors
who can initiate procedures is extensive.35 There is similar flexibility
when it comes to the determination of relevant CSR norms, with the
Guidelines simply stating that specific instance proceedings should be
carried out ‘in accordance with applicable law’.36 In interpreting the
rather vaguely formulated provisions of the Guidelines, parties to the
NCP process can thus refer to external bodies of norms, including
international soft law. As neither the Guidelines nor the Procedural
Guidance set out how external norms should be brought to bear on the
Guidelines, normative relationing between bodies of norms in the NCP
process often has an ad hoc, even haphazard quality to it, relying on the
discursive contributions of the various actors involved in specific
instances. NCP case law thus provides a window into the still fuzzy,
emerging structures of the postnational world of law in which actors
33
OECD, ‘Annual Report on the OECD Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises 2018’
(2019) 35–6. For example, some NCPs are organised within a single ministry, others can
involve multiple ministries or governmental agencies, and the most unusual ones could
involve a multitude of stakeholders or be led by external experts.
34
OECD, ‘Guide for National Contact Points on Coordination When Handling Specific
Instances’ (2019), 4; 2011 edition OECD Guidelines, Procedural Guidance, Chapter I (C).
35
OECD, ‘Annual Report 2018’, 34.
36
2011 edition OECD Guidelines, Procedural Guidance, Chapter I (C).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
irreverently weave loose ties between non-hierarchically situated bodies
of norms in new governance spaces.
The case studies in Sections 12.4.1–12.4.3 allow us to look through the
window and see whether patterns and common dynamics can be identi-
fied. The study provides an overview of over 130 concluded NCP cases
dating back to 2011 when the second revision of the Guidelines took
place. The study also includes a number of pre-2011 cases which provide
perspective on how the NCP system dealt with entanglement before the
revision. It is important to note that the majority of submitted com-
plaints are not resolved (a small number are withdrawn, many are
rejected and a significant number of cases are concluded without a
mediated agreement due to withdrawal by one of the parties).37
Moreover, only in rare cases are NCPs willing to make assessments of
non-compliance with the Guidelines in the absence of a joint/mediated
agreement. The present study only focuses on those specific instances
concluded by the NCPs (whether with or without a mediated agreement),
thus excluding cases which were not accepted or are still pending.
The picture which emerges shows a nuanced approach to normative
entanglement. While most complaints are concluded without references
to external norms, interaction with other bodies of norms is not uncom-
mon – some form of relationing was identified in around a quarter of the
cases studied. A dominant feature apparent from the cases is the notion
of different ‘shades of entanglement’, with NCP-specific instances which
demonstrate distancing and proximity occupying opposite ends of the
spectrum. Some of the examples cannot be clearly categorized as either
but nevertheless prove informative regarding how participants in the
NCP process construct the responsibilities of corporations under the
Guidelines by reference to other bodies of norms and thus fall into a
grey area somewhere in-between. However, even specific instances falling
into a single category show different intensities of each dynamic and
variation as to the ‘commitment’ by an NCP to distancing or proximity
between bodies of norms. Thus, while the three main categories are
useful from an analytical perspective, entanglement within the system
of the OECD Guidelines is best understood as operating on a spectrum
with different shades being present both between and within the two
opposite ends of the distancing–proximity dichotomy.
37
This is also true for this study – in the relevant period, only about half of the submitted
specific instances were formally concluded.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
12.4.1 Distancing
While distancing can be understood as a dynamic of interaction between
bodies of norms and thus as a category of entanglement, it is a mechan-
ism of relationing which is closest to the notion of separation. However,
it does not solely perform the role of division. As Krisch notes in
Chapter 1, distancing creates space between bodies of norms but it can
also be strategically deployed to horizontalize the relationship between
them and prevent the emergence of hierarchies.38 It is necessary to keep
this in mind when analysing distancing within the NCP system, as the
overall approach adopted by NCPs is very subtle and indicates only
limited attempts to distance other CSR frameworks. Notably, none of
the cases studied here featured what could be classified as a clear effort at
separation, that is, an explicit rejection by an NCP of another normative
system as manifestly inapplicable or irrelevant in certain circumstances.
This indicates straight away that the Guidelines are a relatively open
system. However, it also means that we need to rely on implicit or hidden
forms of distancing which can create ambiguous interpretations of the
intentions behind them.
Arguably the strongest example of distancing is silence by an NCP in
the face of claims by another party in a specific instance as to the
applicability of a normative system.39 Such a situation occurred in the
Salini Impregilo S.p.A. (2016)40 specific instance handled by the Italian
NCP, in which the NGO Survival International Italia complained about
the alleged human rights violations caused by the Gibe III dam construc-
tion, carried out by Salini in Ethiopia. The complaint, brought on behalf
of affected Indigenous communities in Ethiopia and Kenya, relied on
provisions of the African Charter on Human and People’s Rights
(ACHPR)41 in apportioning blame on Salini for its failure to respect
38
See Chapter 1, Section 1.4.3.
39
In general, the research found only a handful of examples of distancing within the
analysed cases but this may be a result of the methodology adopted which focuses only
on final statements within the specific instance procedure. Thus, if a body of norms was
identified as relevant within the earlier stages of a specific instance and the NCP
subsequently remained silent on its interaction with the Guidelines in the final statement,
it would fall outside of the scope of this research. This limitation means that the number
of examples of distancing may be underrepresented.
40
Italy NCP, Survival International Italia v. Salini Impregilo S.p.A. (Final statement)
(8 June 2017).
41
OAU, African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights (adopted 27 June 1981, entered into
force 21 October 1986) OAU Doc CAB/LEG/67/3 rev. 5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
human rights. In response to this, the company highlighted its member-
ship of the UN Global Compact and adherence to a number of ISO
standards and sustainability policies. However, none of these found its
way into the examination carried out by the NCP nor into its final
recommendations. By remaining silent on their relevance to the specific
instance, the NCP can be seen as engaging in distancing and asserting the
dominance of the Guidelines. Another example of distancing through
silence occurred in Triumph International (2009).42 In this specific
instance, a coalition of labour unions and NGOs alleged that Triumph,
a Swiss company, had not complied with the Guidelines’ provisions
concerning employment. Unable to successfully initiate mediation
between the complainants and the company, the Swiss NCP concluded
the specific instance. Although the complaint referred to various bodies
of norms beyond the Guidelines, including the company’s own CSR code
of conduct and ILO documents, the NCP limited its analysis to the
Guidelines in the final statement. The silence of the Swiss NCP with
regard to assessing compliance with the OECD Guidelines in relation to
external bodies of norms can thus be interpreted as a form of distancing.
Interestingly, both of these specific instances related to conduct which
happened before 2011 and thus were decided on the basis of the pre-2011
Guidelines which contained only rudimentary human rights provisions.
The NCPs’ hesitant approach towards analysing compliance with regard
to human rights – as evidenced by the Italian NCP’s reluctance to engage
with external norms, including the ACHPR, in Salini – was indicative of
the uncertainty surrounding business and human rights at the time.
Sticking to the status quo position might have represented the conserva-
tive choice for NCPs unsure of where and how to position the 2000 ver-
sion of the Guidelines within the emerging business and human rights
‘galaxy of norms’.43
42
Switzerland NCP, Specific Instance regarding Triumph in the Philippines and in Thailand
(Final Statement) (14 January 2011).
43
E. Diggs, M. Regan and B. Parance, ‘Business and Human Rights as a Galaxy of Norms’
(2019) 50 Georgetown Journal of International Law 309–62.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
proximity. Silence still plays a role here, but it has both an integrative and
exclusionary function. The dynamic in these cases can be described as
‘silent entanglement’ – NCPs rely on particular norms (as opposed to
bodies of norms) which are not clearly featured within the OECD
Guidelines without referring to the framework in which the norm ori-
ginated. This has been the approach adopted by the German NCP in the
NORDEX SE (2014)44 specific instance, which concerned a complaint by
an individual against a German wind turbine supplier involved in a wind
park energy project in Izmir, Turkey. The complainant pointed to gen-
eral failures in the respondent’s risk management, including insufficient
due diligence and failure to carry out an environmental impact assess-
ment – both concepts which can be found in the Guidelines. However,
the measures recommended by the NCP and accepted by the respondent
through the mediation procedure were more extensive. They included,
among other things, the carrying out of environmental and social impact
assessments which are distinct from EIAs and external to the
Guidelines.45 Despite recommending the use of a measure external to
the OECD system, the NCP did not provide any indication as to its origin
or contents, at least not publicly.
A similar process has occurred in relation to the concept of free, prior
and informed consent (FPIC) under the auspices of the Swiss NCP,
which utilized it on a couple of occasions without giving due consider-
ation to its integration into the Guidelines. FPIC is not mentioned within
the Guidelines, yet it was utilized in the World Wildlife Fund for Nature
International (WWF) (2016)46 specific instance. In 2016, Survival
International filed a landmark complaint against WWF for adverse
human rights impacts, including the establishment of protected areas
without the free, prior and informed consent of the Baka, an Indigenous
tribe in Cameroon. While mediation efforts failed, with the complainant
withdrawing from the process, the NCP nevertheless issued a final
statement and recommended to WWF ‘to help ensure open and trans-
parent FPIC processes in Cameroon’.47 As with ESIAs in NORDEX SE,
the NCP did not give any consideration to the pedigree of FPIC, again
44
Germany NCP, Dominic Whiting v. NORDEX SE (Final statement) (31 August 2016).
45
IFC Performance Standards are an example of a normative body which works with the
concept of ESIAs.
46
Switzerland NCP, Survival International v. World Wide Fund for Nature International
(Final statement) (21 November 2017).
47
WWF, p. 6.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
engaging in silent entanglement. The Swiss NCP repeated this in the
Credit Suisse (2017)48 specific instance, brought in respect of the
respondent’s business relations with companies involved in the construc-
tion of the Dakota Access Pipeline. The mediation ended successfully,
with a joint statement in which the respondent committed to incorpor-
ating FPIC within its sector-specific policies. While the NCP simply
welcomed the respondent’s adoption of FPIC, it is notable that there
was not complete silence – Credit Suisse, quoting its modified internal
policies, traced FPIC to the IFC Performance Standards and the UN
Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (UNDRIP).49 If any-
thing, however, this creates further confusion, as the silence by the NCP
stands in contrast with the acknowledgement by the corporation. There
are other plausible sources for the norm, notably ILO Convention 16950
which, in contrast to the UNDRIP, is legally binding. Moreover, there is
considerable disagreement as to whether FPIC represents a standalone
right or should be treated more as an overarching principle, with differ-
ences in interpretation existing depending on the norm-system within
which FPIC is being deployed.51 In such circumstances, the potential
problems caused by silent entanglement are further accentuated.
There is one more group of cases falling within the grey zone category,
representing instances where an NCP acknowledged the relevance of
other bodies of norms but does not say which ones it is referring to. In
the Atradius Dutch State Business (2015)52 specific instance, the NCP
noted that the respondent had a duty to ‘comply not only with national
and regional laws and regulations, but also with relevant international
norms and standards, including – but not limited to – the Guidelines’,
without specifying which norms and standards it considers as relevant.53
48
Switzerland NCP, Society for Threatened Peoples Switzerland (Final statement) (16
October 2019).
49
UNGA, United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (adopted
2 October 2007) UN Doc A/RES/61/295.
50
ILO, Convention Concerning Indigenous and Tribal Peoples in Independent Countries
(adopted 27 June 1989, entered into force 5 September 1991) C169, Art. 16.
51
B. O. Giupponi, ‘Free, Prior and Informed Consent (FPIC) of Indigenous Peoples before
Human Rights Courts and International Investment Tribunals: Two Sides of the Same
Coin?’ (2018) 25 International Journal on Minority and Group Rights 485–529.
52
Netherlands NCP, Both ENDS et al. v. Atradius Dutch State Business (Final statement)
(30 November 2016).
53
Although in light of the mediation process, the details of which were mentioned in the
final statement, it can be implied that ‘relevant standards’ referred to the UNGPs and IFC
Performance standards.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Similarly, the UK NCP in the ENRC (2013)54 specific instance noted that,
in preparing its assessment, it ‘consulted open sources for information on
relevant international standards (including IFC performance standards
and UN conventions and reports on human rights)’. Yet, when assessing
the behaviour of the company, it only vaguely notes that ‘[i]nternational
standards (including the OECD Guidelines) oblige companies to con-
sider environmental and social aspects of projects throughout their life
cycle’.55 What standards other than the Guidelines the NCP is referring
to remains unclear. The most sensible interpretation of what NCPs are
doing here is interpreting the Guidelines as a system inherently open to
entanglement, which is in line with the analysis of the development of the
instrument in relation to other CSR norms in Section 12.3. This links us
back again to the idea of resonance, with NCPs situating the Guidelines
into a more extensive project of human rights protection which in turn
can be understood as providing legitimacy.
12.4.3 Proximity
The specific instances just covered show that the analysis is steadily
moving towards proximity between bodies of norms. Here, the existence
of varying shades of entanglement is particularly pronounced. It can
range from paying mere lip service to another framework by mentioning
it in passing, all the way to a thorough analysis of another system’s
approach to an issue and the intricate weaving together of norms. The
starting point here is those instances where entanglement is arguably
unsurprising because the external body of norms referred to is ‘inte-
grated’ or ‘enmeshed’ with the OECD Guidelines. The research then
turns towards the arguably most interesting examples of entanglement:
bodies of norms which are wholly external to the Guidelines.
54
UK NCP, Rights and Accountability in Development (RAID) v. ENRC (Final statement)
(February 2017).
55
ENRC, p. 15.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
proximity also appears in shades. In some specific instances, NCPs
simply note the alignment between the Guidelines and the other body
of norms, as the French NCP did in Michelin Group (2012) where the
UNGPs were mentioned as inspiration for the 2011 revision of the
Guidelines.56 On other occasions, alignment between the two standards
is noted in the context of applying a particular rule. This can be seen in
relation to the due diligence requirement of the UNGPs in the Danish
PWT Group (2014).57 Moreover, NCPs are not always the main drivers
behind proximity and the relevance of other bodies of norms is raised by
the parties to the complaint. This occurred in the Dutch NCP Bralima
and Heineken (2015)58 specific instance. Bralima, Heineken’s Congolese
subsidiary, was accused of labour misconduct in relation to the departure
of a group of employees from its Bukavu brewery in the period between
1999–2003, when an open conflict was ongoing in the Democratic
Republic of Congo. Given the historic nature of the complaint, the
NCP only played a restricted role and facilitated discussions between
the parties. With Heineken already having a human rights policy in place
by the time of the specific instance, the NCP encouraged ‘Heineken’s
commitment to continue working on an internal analysis of Heineken’s
existing policies and processes in the light of the Guidelines and the
[UNGPs]’.59 Another example is the Norconsult AS (2015) specific
instance, which was resolved through mediation and via a joint statement
between the complainants and respondent, endorsed by the Norwegian
NCP. In the statement, the respondent committed to respect Indigenous
peoples’ rights in accordance with ILO Convention 169 and acknow-
ledged the relevance of UNDRIP and the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights (UDHR) for its internal human rights policies. It is
interesting to see that parties to proceedings also push for proximity
through the specific instance procedure – it highlights that the inter-
twined nature of CSR norms is not only something imposed from above.
Efforts at creating proximity can also take a much stronger form, such
as an NCP extensively engaging with the substantive content of other
bodies of norms. One example is the Dutch specific instance VEON
56
France NCP, Tamil Nadu Land Rights Federation v. Michelin (Final statement) (29
February 2016).
57
Denmark NCP, Clean Clothes Campaign Denmark and Active Consumers v. PWT Group
(Final Statement) (17 October 2016).
58
Netherlands NCP, Former employees of Bralima v. Bralima and Heineken (Final state-
ment) (18 August 2017).
59
Bralima and Heineken, p. 5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
(2016),60 which focused on a labour dispute between VEON, its
Bangladeshi subsidiary, and a trade union established at the
Bangladeshi operations. The complainants claimed that VEON tried to
suppress the employees’ attempts to unionize. However, the respondents
challenged this by stating that the trade union was illegitimate as it lacked
registration with the Bangladeshi authorities – a mandatory requirement
under the laws of Bangladesh, but in direct violation of the OECD
Guidelines and ILO regulations. The NCP recognized the ILO’s compe-
tence in this area, noting that ‘the ILO has stated on many occasions that
the stringent procedural conditions for the registration of trade unions in
Bangladesh are not in line with international legislation and necessitate
amendment of local legislation’.61 It suggested to VEON ‘to comply with
international labour law standards to the fullest extent possible’.62 In
essence, entanglement was utilized here strategically by the NCP in order
to assert the authority of a desirable outcome which might be seen as
contrary to the requirements of domestic law. Another example of reli-
ance on the substantive provisions is the Dutch Bresser (2017)63 specific
instance. The company, a specialist in object relocation, was responsible
for the relocation of a fifteenth-century tomb as part of the construction
of the Ilisu Dam in Turkey. The complainants claimed that Bresser failed
to adequately consult the local population before moving the tomb,
violating their right to culture. With the NCP noting that this was the
first instance in which the right to culture has been the subject of an NCP
procedure, it had to decide whether the matter comes under the scope of
the Guidelines. It affirmatively did so, but only through reliance on
Principle 12 of the UNGPs and its commentary, as well as Art. 15 of
the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights and
the UNESCO Declaration concerning the Intentional Destruction of
Cultural Heritage.64 The unexpected reliance on other bodies of norms
in determining whether an issue comes within the ambit of the
Guidelines underlines the strong proximity between the Guidelines and
the integrated normative systems, in particular the UNGPs.
60
Netherlands NCP, UNI Global Union v. VEON (Final statement) (11 February 2020).
61
Ibid., p. 5.
62
Ibid., p. 6.
63
Netherlands NCP, FIVAS, the Initiative to Keep Hasankeyf Alive and Hasankeyf Matters
v. Bresser (Final statement) (20 August 2018).
64
Bresser, p. 4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
Moreover, the case also shows the tendency of NCPs to reach for
norms depending on their suitability to the subject matter of the specific
instance. This dynamic of ‘specialization’ is particularly common in
instances of entanglement with more traditional normative systems, such
as environmental or human rights law.65 It also stands somewhat in
contrast to how proximity is construed between the Guidelines and the
UNGPs, with those interactions occurring pretty much universally
regardless of the content of the proceedings. The UNGPs are usually
utilized to provide detail to norms of a more procedural nature, such as
due diligence or the concept of leverage, which find applicability regard-
less of the subject matter of a specific instance. In contrast, more trad-
itional international law documents (but also ILO standards and, as will
be seen, other external bodies of norms) are used more as precision tools
to provide details on substantive issues which may relate to a particular
right or a particular norm. For example, in the Danish Greenpeas
Enterprise ApS (2013)66 specific instance, Art. 8 of the International
Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) (prohibition on forced
and compulsory labour) was invoked by the NCP in a case addressing the
retention of workers’ passports against their will, creating ‘conditions
that can be associated with slavery’.67 Similarly, in Mercer PR (2016),68
the Australian NCP identified the right to privacy, as contained in Art. 12
of the UDHR and Art. 17 of the ICCPR, as relevant in a specific instance
in which a small Australian company distributed personal information
concerning an alleged sexual assault.
65
As far as ‘traditional’ human rights norms are concerned, the specialisation dynamic can
lead to the entanglement of norms which are not explicitly mentioned within the
Guidelines. This is as a feature of the text of the Guidelines which allows for the
consideration of additional human rights standards depending on the subject matter
which they address – see 2011 edition of the Guidelines, Chapter IV commentary at [40].
66
Denmark NCP, 3F v. Greenpeas Enterprise APS (Final Statement) (14 August 2014).
67
Ibid., p. 6.
68
Australian NCP, Australian Women Without Borders v. Mercer PR (Final statement)
(9 July 2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘applicable law’ not only international soft law, but also private agree-
ments and regulatory initiatives of a completely private nature. In add-
ition to having the consequence of ‘lumping together’ typologically
different bodies of norms with little nuance as to their bindingness, such
entanglement can have a major legitimizing effect for the external
systems due to the meta-regulatory stature of the Guidelines. In some
ways, this category of specific instances most closely demonstrates the
notion of entanglement as the cases often work with multiple bodies of
norms and create linkages between them in an unexpected, even irrever-
ent manner, weaving together a multidimensional web of CSR regulation.
Arguably a more doctrinally conservative collection of cases is repre-
sented by those specific instances displaying proximity between the
Guidelines and international normative systems developed within inter-
national organizations or as a result of agreement between states, and
such a dynamic predates the 2011 revision of the Guidelines. In Vedanta
Resources PLC (2008), Survival International submitted a complaint with
the UK NCP concerning Vedanta’s planned construction of a bauxite
mine in Orissa, India.69 Survival alleged that Vedanta’s operations were
inconsistent with the Guidelines and drew on international environmen-
tal law and human rights law to substantiate the claims. In coming to its
conclusions that the company had indeed breached the Guidelines, the
NCP emphasized the rights of Indigenous peoples under international
law, ‘including the [ICCPR], the UN Convention on the Elimination of
All Forms of Racial Discrimination, the Convention on Biological
Diversity and the UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous
People’.70 The NCP also found that Vedanta had not engaged in
adequate community consultation, interpreting the provision in light of
the 2004 Akwé Kon Guidelines produced by the Secretariat of the
Convention on Biological Diversity.71 Thus, the NCP found that the
company had breached the Guidelines by reference to an international
soft law produced by the secretariat of a multilateral environmental
agreement with no formal linkage to them. A post-2011 example is
the Dutch ING (2017)72 specific instance, which represented a broad
challenge to the respondent’s overall climate policy. The claimants
69
UK NCP, Survival International v. Vedanta Resources plc (Final statement)
(25 September 2009).
70
Ibid., p. 1.
71
Ibid., pp. 17–19.
72
Netherlands NCP, Oxfam Novib et al. v. ING (Final statement) (19 April 2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
specifically required ING to report its indirect carbon emissions, accrued
through its loans and investments. Despite the broadly framed com-
plaint, the NCP managed to secure cooperation from the respondent
and, in doing so, entangled the freshly negotiated Paris international
climate agreement into the Guidelines.73 Not only was the Paris
Agreement identified as relevant, but ING agreed to utilize the method-
ologies of the Paris Agreement in ‘measuring, target setting and steering
the bank’s climate impact’.74 This indicates another layer to the ‘special-
ization’ dynamic, as the international norm might have been chosen not
only because of its closeness to the subject matter, but also because it
provides effective and appropriate methodologies and solutions which
the respondent could incorporate within its CSR policies.
However, coupling also happens with bodies of norms which are not
normally considered law or which might originate outside of a state-
centric environment, and again this is not limited only to the post-2011
version of the Guidelines. In Intex Resources ASA and the Mindoro Nickel
Project (2009),75 the complaint concerned alleged violations of the
human and environmental rights of Indigenous peoples that would be
affected by Intex Resources’ planned nickel mine and factory in the
Philippines. The Norwegian NCP concluded that the company had, inter
alia, failed to properly consult the affected groups, thus breaching the
Guidelines. As Intex had previously declared its adherence to the IFC
Social and Environmental Performance standards and the Equator
Principles, the Norwegian NCP repeatedly drew on the content of those
standards when determining whether the company had complied with
the Guidelines’ recommendation ‘to consider the views of other stake-
holders’. In addition, the NCP referred to the UNDRIP, ILO Convention
169 in order to interpret and ‘flesh out’ the recommendations of the
Guidelines.76 In this instance, the NCP made full use of the in-text
references to other bodies of norms in the Guidelines, as well as the
fact that the company itself had proclaimed adherence to the IFC
Performance standards.
73
Ibid., p. 3.
74
Ibid., p. 4.
75
Norway NCP, Future in Our Hands (FIOH) v. Intex Resources ASA (Final Statement)
(28 November 2011).
76
Ibid., p. 21 et seq.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
In the KiK Textilien und Non-Food GmbH, C&A Mode GmbH & Co.,
and Karl Rieker GmbH & Co. KG (2013)77 specific instance, the German
NCP provided an illustration of how private agreements can be entan-
gled. The case concerned a fire at the Tazreen Fashion factory in Dhaka,
Bangladesh, in November 2012. The complainant asserted that the
respondent companies were jointly responsible for the fire because they
continued to produce clothing at the site, even though an independent
safety assessment carried out in 2011 found that safety measures were
inadequate. All three enterprises were producing clothes in the factory
indirectly through subcontractors. While the complaint against C&A was
forwarded to the Brazilian NCP,78 the German NCP did investigate the
allegations against KiK and Karl Rieker. It did not consider the two
respondents’ direct liability for the fire to be substantiated, however, as
both companies proved that they discontinued production at Tazreen
Fashion over six months before the fire.79 The NCP did initiate medi-
ation proceedings for the part of the claim which concerned breaches of
the duty of care in relation to the safety measures within the factory. As
part of the mediation, the NCP and the parties relied upon the
Bangladesh Safety Accord to which KiK and Karl Rieker were both
signatories. While all parties were supportive of the measures taken as
part of the Accord, it is interesting that these were not deemed to be
sufficient and the NCP recommended other supplementary measures.80
The dialectic deployed in the mediation shows that entanglement in a
single case can be nuanced, with efforts to increase proximity but also to
distance norms and create hierarchy. Entanglement can thus be used to
further both legitimization and delegitimization. The parties and the
NCP embraced the measures of the Accord, recognizing it as relevant.
Yet, at the same time, the NCP limited its legitimacy by stating that the
Guidelines require supplementary measures to be taken. In doing so, it
reinforced the meta-regulatory status of the Guidelines and provided a
hint as to the emergence of a hierarchy between the two bodies of norms.
A very similar dynamic can be seen in the Rabobank (2014)81 specific
instance, in which the Dutch NCP considered the respondent’s provision
77
Germany NCP, Uwe Kekeritz v. KiK Textilien und Non-Food GmbH, C&A Mode GmbH
& Co., and Karl Rieker GmbH & Co. KG (Final statement) (November 2014).
78
As a result of the legal structures of C&A’s operations in Bangladesh at the time, the
entity responsible in this case was the Brazilian subsidiary of C&A.
79
KiK Textilien, pp. 3–4.
80
KiK Textilien, p. 6.
81
Netherlands NCP, Friends of the Earth v. Rabobank (Final statement) (15 January 2016).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
of loans to the Indonesian palm oil company Bumitama. Interestingly, a
central part of the complaint became obsolete during the proceedings, as
Bumitama terminated the contract for the plantation which formed the
primary subject of the complaint. Nevertheless, the Dutch NCP con-
sidered that some parts of the complaint still merited further consider-
ation, allowing it to analyse more generally Rabobank’s policy in relation
to palm oil supply chains. A core part of this assessment was devoted to
Rabobank’s membership of the Roundtable for Sustainable Palm Oil
(RSPO), which is a global multi-stakeholder sustainability initiative.
A company wishing to become a member of the RSPO (and thus be able
to use the RSPO trademark ecolabel) has to undergo a certification
process, which itself is based on another set of private principles for
sustainability standards – the International Social and Environmental
Accreditation and Labelling (ISEAL) Alliance Credibility Principles,
which perform a meta-regulatory role within the sustainability standards
sector. By engaging the RSPO, the Dutch NCP is, possibly unknowingly,
entangling the Guidelines with two layers of normative systems.
Proximity within this specific instance takes the form of the NCP’s
cautious optimism about the RSPO in stating that its grievance mechan-
ism and commitment to a multi-stakeholder approach can be seen as
good practice within the palm oil production sector.82 However, the NCP
also notes the need for the respondent to develop its own practices
beyond the RSPO, even suggesting disengagement as an option of last
resort.
Thus, just as in the previous specific instance, we can identify a dual
dynamic of both proximity and distancing with an external standard. On
one hand, the NCP legitimizes the body of norms as a good practice, on
the other, it delegitimizes it by encouraging the respondent to look
beyond. The sense of hierarchy emerging between the Guidelines and
the RSPO is further reinforced by the fact that in RSPO (2018),83 a
complaint was brought directly against the Roundtable before the Swiss
NCP for the alleged failures of its complaint mechanism in dealing with a
land dispute between local communities in Indonesia and one of its
member companies. While the NCP was limited to the role of a mediator
and did not directly draw upon an external standard, the specific instance
is notable for the way in which it interacts with the RSPO as an external
82
Ibid., p. 4.
83
Switzerland NCP, TuK Indonesia v. Roundtable for Sustainable Palm Oil (Final state-
ment) (5 June 2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
system. The NCP carries out a somewhat supervisory role, relying on its
own leverage over the RSPO to push the sustainability standard itself
towards compatibility with the Guidelines. Thus, proximity and distan-
cing both seem to be present, drawing the bodies of norms closer but also
alluding to a hierarchy between them and, in doing so, demonstrating
another shade of the complexity of entanglement.
The Bresser specific instance and a number of others have already
shown NCPs drawing on multiple bodies of norms in one proceeding.
The final part of this section focuses on three specific instances featuring
this dynamic which were brought within the UK NCP system. These
arguably represent the strongest examples of proximity, invoking mul-
tiple normative systems and showing extensive interaction by the NCP.
The first specific instance is GCM Resources plc (2012),84 concerning
plans by the respondent to develop a mine in Bangladesh. The complaint
dates back to 2004 when GCM Resources began the planning and
consultation process for the mine. However, the company’s activities
were still effectively incomplete and on hold at the time of the complaint.
Thus, parts of the specific instance were handled under the 2000 version
as well as the 2011 version of the Guidelines. The respondent had
undertaken an ESIA as part of its planning and consultation process
which the NCP considered in light of the standards applied by the World
Bank and the IFC. While the NCP acknowledged that the self-regulatory
practices adopted by GCM Resources and based on the IFC standards
were sufficient, it pointed out inadequacies in relation to the respondent’s
communication of its plans to affected communities.85 In relation to
adverse human rights impacts before September 2011, the NCP noted
that the UNGPs were available to businesses from 2010 and also that
human rights concerns were incorporated in the IFC standards. The
NCP also noted the ‘company’s plans recognise the ILO standard on
Indigenous Peoples’.86 When considering activities happening after
September 2011, the NCP reiterated the relevance of the UNGPs and
highlighted the applicability a new set of IFC Performance Standards,
issued in 2012. The NCP also noted that the respondent’s updated plans
will have to consider the right to FPIC, as contained within UNDRIP.87
84
UK NCP, International Accountability Project and World Development Movement
v. GCM Resources plc (Final statement) (November 2014).
85
Ibid., p. 13.
86
Ibid., p. 15.
87
Ibid., p. 18.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
The GCM Resources plc specific instance underscores that engagement
with human rights norms intensified in the post-2011 Guidelines, but
also shows that human rights considerations were clearly present even
before. Interestingly, the NCP indicated that the IFC Performance
Standards played a major role in this regard. The way in which the
concepts of ESIA and FPIC were treated is also notable – in contrast to
the examples of silent entanglement in NORDEX SE, WWF or Credit
Suisse, the UK NCP in GCM Resources plc was very explicit about
connecting ESIA with the IFC Performance standards and FPIC with
UNDRIP. This again shows that entanglement is nuanced, with proxim-
ity being a more dominant dynamic in the UK context.
The second UK-specific instance to consider is G4S plc (2013),88 which
also concerned actions spanning both the 2000 and 2011 versions of the
Guidelines. The complaint was addressed against the respondent’s pro-
vision and maintenance of security equipment (CCTV, baggage scan-
ners) at Israeli checkpoints within the Palestinian occupied territory and
within Israeli prisons. At the outset of its fact-finding, the NCP noted the
relevance of the 2004 International Court of Justice (ICJ) Israeli Wall
Advisory Opinion89 and the UK’s acceptance of the advisory opinion.90 In
contrast to GCM Resources plc, the NCP predominantly focused on the
respondent’s human rights obligations after 2011, putting the UNGPs
under the spotlight and drawing extensively on their provisions, espe-
cially those in regard to the termination of a business relationship.91
Private standards were also engaged – the NCP recognized the relevance
of the International Code of Conduct for Private Security Providers, ‘of
which G4S was a founder signatory in 2010’.92 However, the NCP also
explicitly dismissed another private initiative suggested by G4S
(Voluntary Principles on Security and Human rights) as it was princi-
pally relevant to the sectors of mining and energy.93 Showcasing both
proximity and distancing, the approach in G4S plc is another good
example of the specialization dynamic mentioned earlier.
88
UK NCP, Lawyers for Palestinian Human Rights (LPHR) v. G4s plc (Final statement)
(March 2015).
89
Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory
(Advisory Opinion) [2004] ICJ Rep 136.
90
Such as the FCO Overseas Business Risk and FCO Human Rights and Democracy
reports. G4S plc, p. 11.
91
Ibid., p. 13.
92
Ibid., p. 14.
93
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Finally, the KPO Consortium (2013)94 instance involved a consortium
of companies from three OECD member countries (Italy, the UK and the
USA) operating an oil and gas production facility in Kazakhstan. After
mutual agreement between the relevant NCPs, the UK NCP took care of
handling the complaint and engaged KPO as a single entity. The adverse
human rights impacts arose in relation to two households located within
a protective zone around KPO’s facility and who were consequently
entitled to resettlement and compensation. Just as before, the issues were
of a long-term nature, dating back to the 1990s and potentially involving
three different versions of the Guidelines. The UK NCP changed tack
from the previous specific instances by ingeniously applying the extensive
human rights provisions of the 2011 Guidelines even to situations
where the adverse impact arose before 1 September 2011 but was still
ongoing.95 This enabled the UK NCP to draw on the UNGPs and their
predecessor, the UN Protect, Respect and Remedy Framework.96 The IFC
Performance Standards were also considered relevant, as KPO received a
loan from the IFC, making their provisions directly applicable to the
project.97 The UK NCP went into some detail in considering how the
IFC’s standard for involuntary resettlement applied to the situation,
noting that the situation wasn’t a typical case for the IFC standard but
that KPO should have nevertheless applied it as good practice.98
The three specific instances show that the UK NCP’s approach is
closest in resemblance to a more traditional, adversarial method of
adjudication.99 Maheandiran suggests that the nature of the approach
adopted by an NPC can have an impact on the objectives and structure of
the specific instance procedure.100 It can be argued that this is also true
for the dynamics of entanglement, with the UK approach showing the
most extensive entanglement with multiple bodies of norms. As a conse-
quence of establishing liability within its approach, the UK NCP neces-
sarily considers the applicability of particular norms and systems in
94
UK NCP, Crude Accountability v KPO Consortium (Final statement) (November 2017).
95
Ibid., p. 9.
96
KPO Consortium, p. 16.
97
Ibid., p. 16. In fact, the complainant NGO even utilized the IFC’s complaints system
before resorting to the NCP procedure.
98
Ibid., p. 18.
99
B. Maheandiran, ‘Calling for Clarity: How Uncertainty Undermines the Legitimacy of
the Dispute Resolution System under the OECD Guidelines for Multinational
Enterprises’ (2015) 20 Harvard Negotiation Law Review 205–44.
100
Ibid., pp. 227–37.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
detailed fashion. This can seem counterintuitive, as a more traditional
adjudication mechanism would probably draw clear lines between bodies
of norms in an effort to determine the applicable law, thus moving closer
towards distancing and possibly separation of systems. Yet the same
dynamic within the open system of the Guidelines appears to go in the
opposite direction and increase proximity between bodies of norms.
101
Corporations, but also state-owned enterprises, state ministries, institutional investors
and even sustainability standard bodies and NGOs.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
than framework conventions such as the Convention on Biological
Diversity, which does not have a clearly defined scope and contains only
general provisions.102
Indeed, the categorization of specific instances adopted within this
chapter can be deceptive, as it simplifies a very nuanced picture of
entanglement in which multiple dynamics can be present in a single
case. Even examples of the same dynamic can take various forms and can
be framed in different terms, with different language corresponding to
the different shades of entanglement. The UK-specific instances are again
informative in this regard. In GCM Resources and G4S, when the NCP
considered a particular norm or standard as applicable, it would often
(but not exclusively) use the phrase ‘the NCP notes’ and then refer to the
relevant provision in question, possibly engaging with it in more detail.
The KPO instance stands in contrast to this, with the wording of ‘notes’
and a particular norm being much less used, and has been largely
replaced by two separate subsections within the specific instance
(‘Applicable Standards’ and ‘Guidance Available on Human Rights’)
which include the majority (but, again, not all) of the standards referred
to. Given that KPO represents a more recent instance, the change might
indicate a move towards more systematization in engagement with
norms external to the Guidelines. Another NCP to draw upon is the
Dutch one, which has also utilized the combination ‘note’/‘notice’ and a
particular norm on occasions,103 but has also relied on other formula-
tions such as ‘in light of’104 a particular system, especially when it makes
recommendations as to the conduct expected of a respondent. In general,
some formulations are becoming standardized but the shades of
entanglement are really characterized by diversity, mirroring the
Guidelines’ system, and maybe some indifference by the NCPs as to
the language they use.
This indifference is also visible in the way in which NCPs treat bodies
of norms with different legal status. Across the specific instances, one can
see a strong tendency to ‘lump together’ systems and standards with little
consideration for their legal authority or the manner in which they apply
to a respondent in NCP proceedings. The issue seems to be partly
structural. While the Guidelines in their chapter on concepts and
102
N. Affolder, ‘The Market for Treaties’ (2010) 11 Chicago Journal of International Law
159–96, at 185.
103
See e.g. VEON, ING.
104
See e.g. Heineken.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
principles differentiate between ‘applicable laws’ on the one hand and
‘internationally recognised standards’ on the other,105 thus prima facie
recognizing the distinction between law in the strict sense of the word
and other bodies of norms, in other parts of the Guidelines the distinc-
tion is much more fluid. For example, the chapter on human rights
lumps together binding treaties and non-binding declarations without
differentiating between them. It is thus unsurprising to see NCPs being
indifferent in this regard, such as in Norconsult AS or Vedanta Resources
PLC, where the NCPs drew on the non-binding UNDRIP and Akwé Kon
Guidelines. This is particularly problematic when the NCP works with a
number of bodies of norms with different levels of bindingness. A similar
concern is the application of norms which are not addressed to corpor-
ations in the first place, but rather to states. Of course, the Guidelines do
provide a sort of transpositionary function in this regard, yet it is still
surprising to see that NCPs pay very little consideration as to how
normative systems developed for application in a state-centric (and thus
very different) context can be applied to corporations. Thus, while
instances of entanglement between transnational CSR norms and inter-
national law may strengthen the coherence of global law through active
coordination by the Guidelines, this may also lead to adverse effects as to
the integrity and normative force of international law. In this regard,
Affolder has drawn attention to how ‘corporate adoption and translation
of treaty norms’ may ‘ultimately undermine a treaty’s goals’ as companies
‘cherry-pick among treaty provisions, interpret treaty commitments in
their least onerous forms, and obscure the ways in which corporate
activities impede treaty implementation by selectively reporting on
instances where corporate policies and actions advance treaty norms’.106
From the evidence, it seems that NCPs might be complicit in allowing
corporations to do so through a mere lack of diligence within the specific
instance procedure.
The laxness in the NCPs’ approach might be partially attributed to the
perceived lack of enforceability and compliance with the specific instance
procedure.107 As the Guidelines are soft law and the specific instances do
not create legal obligations or benefit from formalized enforceability,
105
2011 edition of the Guidelines, chapter I [1].
106
Affolder, ‘The Market for Treaties’, 162.
107
A. Marx and J. Wouters, ‘Rule Intermediaries in Global Labor Governance’ (2017) 670
The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 189–206, at 195.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
NCPs can feel induced to be ‘generous’ with the application of bodies of
norms to a particular context. However, they would be well advised
to exercise caution in this regard as the decisions reached within a
specific instance are hardly inconsequential. As Nieuwenkamp high-
lights, the exercise of pressure by civil society, making diplomatic protec-
tion conditional upon compliance, or the consideration of specific
instances in decisions on the availability of export credits are only some
of the ways in which the Guidelines can have a major impact on
corporate behaviour.108 In fact, some elements of the Guidelines are
already undergoing a process of ‘hardening’ by being transposed into
domestic legislation, such as in the case of the due diligence obligation
within the US Dodd–Frank Act which uses the Guidelines’ provisions as
a reference point.109
Finally, it is notable what a prominent role has been assumed by
straddling practices within NCP proceedings, and in particular the
concept of due diligence. In the post-2011 specific instances analysed
in this chapter, the due diligence obligation of the respondent has been
invoked in the vast majority of cases. In the NCP system, due diligence
has outgrown the image of an import from the UNGPs and it is being
construed as inherent to the Guidelines. Such blurring of the origins of
the norm, coupled with its application in non-human rights-specific
contexts, provides attestation to its quality as a straddling practice
which distorts the boundaries of individual normative systems. The
OECD system doesn’t only apply the due diligence principle, it also
develops it further, going as far as producing a number of guiding
documents for the carrying out of due diligence.110 A similar dynamic
can be identified in relation to ESIAs and the concept of FPIC, with the
examples of silent entanglement identified showing that the norms are
being interpreted as cross-cutting norms and not necessarily
‘belonging’ to a single normative system. Thus, straddling practices
are emerging as one of the tools of entanglement within the system of
the Guidelines.
108
Nieuwenkamp, ‘The OECD Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises on Responsible
Business Conduct’, 174.
109
Ibid., 175; Cullen, ‘The Irresistible Rise of Human Rights Due Diligence’, 744.
110
E.g. OECD, ‘OECD Due Diligence Guidance for Responsible Business Conduct’ (2018);
or OECD, ‘OECD Due Diligence Guidance for Responsible Supply Chains in the
Garment and Footwear Sector’ (2017).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
š č
12.6 Conclusion
At the outset of this chapter, the inherent pluralism within the regime
of CSR regulation of business conduct was noted as a dominant
feature. Even though the analysis zoomed in on one particular focal
point for entanglement, the OECD Guidelines, multiplicity and vari-
ation did not leave the picture. Instead, the system of the Guidelines
can be still characterized by a plurality of bodies of norms which are
the target of engagement and a plurality of shades of entanglement.
Thus, in a sense the OECD Guidelines are reflective of the dynamic
which exists in the wider world of CSR normativity. As the section
dealing with coordinated legal entanglement has shown, the openness
of the Guidelines can be attributed to the structural features of the
system which provide the necessary flexibility for the interaction with
other bodies of norms. Moreover, the manner in which the UNGPs
were integrated into the Guidelines shows that these structural features
are not accidental – rather, they represent deliberate decisions to create
linkages between CSR systems, arguably motivated by the potential
benefits which accrue from cooperation between bodies of norms
within the field of CSR.
If the provisions of the Guidelines lay the groundwork for extensive
entanglement, the implementation mechanism of NCPs does a very good
job in building up the rest of the structure. It is in Section 12.4 where the
true scope of entanglement within the system of the Guidelines is
demonstrated. Although the dialectic of distancing and proximity is
utilized in order to frame the discussion, Section 12.4 illustrates that
the identified shades of entanglement are often not easily subsumed
within either of the main categories mentioned. This is exacerbated by
the fact that entanglement often happens with multiple bodies of norms
at once. Overall, NCPs appear to be more likely to engage other bodies of
norms in ways which enhance proximity between them, often creating
irreverent linkages with both public and private frameworks. While some
bodies of norms are relied upon in general contexts, other external norms
are used as specialized precision tools when their provisions are closely
related to the subject matter of a specific instance. The use of certain
norms is characterized by silence as to the normative system in which
they originate, underlining their status as straddling practices which can
span across multiple bodies of norms. On the distancing end of the
spectrum, we saw only limited efforts at drawing borders between
systems – instead, efforts at distancing were utilized to hierarchically
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
position the Guidelines against other bodies of norms or as instances of
the specialization dynamic. Despite such efforts, however, the picture of
CSR which emerges is certainly not of a top-down, integrated system, but
rather one which is best defined as a polycentric and multilayered web of
bodies of norms.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
PART IV
Situating Entanglements
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
13
13.1 Introduction
At the outset, I ask the historian to look upon Indian America as a Middle
Ages which was missing its Rome: a confused mass that emerged from an
ancient syncretism, which was without doubt very loosely textured, that
had contained within itself at one and the same time, for many centuries,
centres of advanced civilisation and savage peoples, centralizing tenden-
cies and disruptive forces.1
1
C. Lévi-Strauss, Mythologiques: Le Cru et le Cuit (Plon, 1964), p. 16 (own translation): ‘On
commencera donc par inviter l’historien à voir, dans l’Amérique indienne, un Moyen âge
auquel aurait manqué sa Rome: masse confuse, elle-même issue d’un vieux synrétisme
dont la texture fut sans doute très lâche, et au sein de lacquelle subsistèrent çà et là,
pendant plusiers siècles, des foyers de haute civilisation et des peuples barbares, des
tendances centralisatrices et des forces de morcellement.’
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
seemingly ‘confused mass’ of Amerindian myth.2 I begin with Lévi-
Strauss and his vision of ‘a Middle Ages which was missing its Rome’
in order to problematize the idea of centralized authority itself. More
specifically, this chapter challenges the seemingly natural idea, typified
here by Lévi-Strauss, that the presence of a Rome – or a Brussels, or a
United Nations, or even a UNIDROIT – implies the development of a
centralized, hierarchical model through which various, heteronomous,
normative orders politely interact.
‘Rome’ here performs as shorthand for the deceptively complex idea
that law and governance should be understood primarily in the context
of imperium: the power to command. As Karen Alter states: ‘Most people
presume that law is only meaningful when backed by a central enforcer.’3
Hence for much of the twentieth century, in the absence of a ‘world state’,
international relations could be conceptualized as operating outside the
domain of law. Since 1989 the number of international courts has more
than quadrupled in number from six to over twenty-four – resulting in
the collective issuing of over 37,000 binding legal rulings in individual
contentious cases.4 Yet even this intensified judicialization of the inter-
national arena still tends to be framed by a persistent ‘image of law
beyond the nation state as a weak ordering and regulatory system, rather
than a constitutive element in the ongoing tumble of transnational life’.5
The field of private international law – ‘the legal discipline that deter-
mines in which cases a court must apply a foreign law’ – also rests on a
paradigm of Westphalian state governance.6 Private international law
‘does not lay out substantive rules for such situations, but merely resolves
2
Ibid., p. 11: ‘Des filaments épars se soudent, des lacunes se comblent, des connexions
s’établissent, quelque chose qui ressemble à un ordre transparait derrière le chaos. Comme
autour d’une molécule germinale, des séquences rangées en groupes de transformations
viennent s’agréger au groupe intial, reproduisant sa structure et ses déterminations. Un
corps multi-dimensionnel nâit, dont les parties centrales dévoilent l’organisation alors que
l’incercitude et la confusion règnent encore au portour.’
3
K. J. Alter, The New Terrain of International Law: Courts, Politics, Rights (Princeton
University Press, 2014), p. 3.
4
Ibid., p. 3.
5
D. Kennedy, ‘Law in Global Political Economy: Now You See It, Now You Don’t’, in P. F.
Kjaer (ed.), The Law of Political Economy: Transformation in the Function of Law
(Cambridge University Press, 2020), pp. 127–51, at p. 128.
6
Quotation from R. Michaels, ‘What Is Non-state Law? A Primer’, in M. A. Helfand (ed.),
Negotiating State and Non-state Law: The Challenge of Global and Local Legal Pluralism
(Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 41–58, at p. 55. On ‘the peace of Westphalia’
(1648) and the emergence of the modern state as ‘an international subject’ see A. Cassese,
‘States: Rise and Decline of the Primary Subjects of the International Community’, in
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
conflicts between the legal orders themselves’, relying on relevant domes-
tic choice-of-law principles and rules in order to resolve legal disputes
with a foreign element.7 As Neil Walker notes, choice-of-law rules ‘and
the interpretative aids of transnational law do not “stand above” the
domestic systems in which they are applied. Rather, they are formulated
or interpreted each in the context of their own system – in deference to
and under the self-validating terms prescribed by each domestic legal
order’s sovereign authority.’8 Notwithstanding the ‘equality’ between
different domestic legal orders, the system of private international law
prioritizes national sovereignty and is grounded within a hierarchical – in
a Kelsenian sense – approach to international governance.
In contrast, the ‘postnational’ approach, as defined by Nico Krisch
in his 2010 Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of
Postnational Law and further developed by the ‘Entangled Legalities’
project underlying this volume, argues that ‘national’ and ‘international’
law are interwoven to such an extent within the supranational legal order
that norms and principles from both spheres interact heterarchically:
‘operating side-by-side without the presumptive authority of one over the
other’.9 Like Lévi-Strauss’ pre-conquest Amerindian myths, there is no
centre or hierarchy (no ‘Rome’) to structure postnational law.
Nonetheless, again like Lévi-Strauss’ account of Amerindian myth-
making, there is a structure at work: ‘the nation-state itself shares ultim-
ate authority with multiple regional and international legal orders with
which it interacts without a common normative framework – hence a
post-national law within a pluralist structure’.10 Instead of mapping the
contours of an emerging global constitutional framework in which
B. Fassbender and A. Peters (eds), The Oxford Handbook of the History of International
Law (Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 49–69.
7
R. Michaels, ‘A Symmetry of Asymmetries? A Private-International-Law Reconstruction
of Lindahl’s Work on Boundaries’ (2019) 29 Duke Journal of Comparative and
International Law 405–22, at 410.
8
N. Walker, ‘Beyond Boundary Disputes and Basic Grids: Mapping the Global Disorder of
Normative Orders’ (2008) 6 (3–4) International Journal of Constitutional Law 373–96, at
377.
9
C. Mac Amlaigh, ‘Pluralising Constitutional Pluralism’, in N. Roughan and A. Halpin
(eds), In Pursuit of Pluralist Jurisprudence (Cambridge University Press, 2017), pp. 64–89,
at p. 68.
10
G. Shaffer, ‘A Transnational Take on Krisch’s Pluralist Postnational Law’ (2012) 23 The
European Journal of International Law 565–82, at 566 (review of N. Krisch, Beyond
Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law (Oxford University Press,
2010)).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
overarching principles govern relations between different normative
orders, this volume’s project seeks to reimagine the global legal order
‘through the paradigm of entangled legalities’:
In short, we advance a view of global legal order that dissociates itself
from the idea of law as a hierarchical system. In its place, we envision
global law as having a fluid, network-like structure [. . .] the Interface Law
Project proposes the concept of interface norms that structure fluid and
shifting relations between different bodies of norms. Interface law (or law
at the interfaces) allows us to isolate and describe the form and substance
of these interactions through which the global legal order is being negoti-
ated, constructed and contested, as well as enabling us to catch glimpses of
the social practices shaping these processes.11
11
L. L. Reimers and F. Corradini, ‘The Entanglement of Global Legal Order’, The Global
(9 July 2018), https://theglobal.blog/2018/07/09/the-entanglement-of-global-legal-order/.
12
Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism, 69.
13
R. Domingo, ‘Roman Law and Global Constitutionalism’ (2019) 21 San Diego
International Law Journal 217–40, at 218. See also T. Duve, ‘Entanglements in Legal
History. Introductory Remarks’, in T. Duve (ed.), Entanglements in Legal History:
Conceptual Approaches (Max Planck Institute for European Legal History, 2014),
pp. 3–25, at p. 3: ‘In large part, legal historical research is dedicated to times and spaces
in which the notion of the “modern state” did not exist, or to historical situations of
limited statehood.’
14
D. J. Bederman, International Law in Antiquity (Cambridge University Press, 2001). For
further discussion see R. Lesaffer, ‘Roman Law and the Early Historiography of
International Law: Ward, Wheaton, Hosack and Walker’, in T. Marauhn and H. Steiger
(eds), Universality and Continuity in International Law (Eleven International Publishing,
2011), pp. 149–84, at pp. 149–52.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
diplomacy, including interstate peace treaties. Beyond the political and
economic ordering of interstate relations, guaranteed by mutual oath-
taking and divine invocation, Greco-Roman peace treaties also included
clauses providing for the resolution of on-the-ground disputes that might
otherwise threaten the newly agreed order. For example, the treaty
concluded in 562 CE between the (Eastern) Roman Emperor Justinian
I and the Sasanian King of Kings Xusro I set out – in both Greek and
Persian languages – the terms of a fifty-year peace agreed between Rome
and Sasanian Iran.15 This 562 CE treaty contains two articles that could
be compared loosely with modern ‘private international law’ provisions.
Article 7 specifies that individuals who ‘have suffered some hurt at the
hands of subjects of the other state’ should settle the dispute according to
law: ‘either those who have suffered harm themselves, or their represen-
tatives, shall meet on the frontier before the officials of both states, and in
this manner the aggressor shall make amends for the damage’.16 Article
11, on the other hand, specifies the procedure to be followed in the case
of intercity disputes that fall outside the ‘rules of war’:
If one city damages another or in any way destroys its property not in
accordance with the rules of war and with a regular military force, but by
guile and theft (for there are such godless men who do these things so that
there might be a pretext for war), it was agreed that the judges stationed
on the frontiers of both states should make a thorough investigation of
such acts and remedy them.17
15
The Greek text is included in a sixth-century CE history written by ‘Menander Protector’,
Fragment 6.1. 314–97. English translation from G. Greatrex and S. Lieu, The Roman
Eastern Frontier and the Persian Wars: Part II AD 363–630 (Routledge, 2002), pp. 132–3
(revised Menander Protector, The History of Menander Protector, ed. and trans. R.
Blockley (F. Cairns, 1985).
16
Greatrex and Lieu, The Roman Eastern Frontier, p. 133 (my emphasis).
17
Ibid., p. 133.
18
Walker, ‘Beyond Boundary Disputes and Basic Grids’, 376–85 and 394–5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
be seen to structure an overall order. We shall return to this idea of the
‘centrality of the margins’ in Sections 13.2 and 13.3.
Whether there is anything in Classical or Postclassical Roman legal
sources that could be mapped accurately onto the modern concept of
‘private international law’ is doubtful at best.19 In fact, as we shall see in
Section 13.3, the coordination of legal sources within the Roman Empire
has more in common with the heterarchical approach of ‘postnational
law’ than with the state sovereignty model of private international law. As
Ulrike Babusiaux argues in a 2020 article comparing the legal ordering of
imperial Rome with the legal ordering of the European Union, the
question of ‘how to coordinate different legal sources without abstract
hierarchy’ is an ancient one.20 During the late Roman Republic, practical
and concrete jurisdictional questions arose in the context of Roman
imperial expansion and the creation of the provincial system.21 Contact
between Roman citizens and ‘foreigners’ (peregrini, free citizens of any
political community besides the Roman) was unavoidable, especially in
relation to commerce and business dealings more generally.22 Roman
magistrates, legal experts (iurisperiti), the emperors and their officials
were thus well aware of a world of private legal transactions involving
‘non-citizens’ of various different types and recognized the need to
regulate those transactions from within the Roman legal system. At
Rome, from at least the time of the first Emperor Augustus, the praetor
peregrinus handled litigation between ‘foreigners’ and also cases between
‘foreigners’ and Roman citizens.23 The activity of the praetor peregrinus
(and the praetor urbanus) at Rome may, to some extent, explain the
origins of the Roman ius gentium: ‘those legal habits which were accepted
19
For further discussion see H. Cotton, ‘Private International Law or Conflicts of Laws:
Reflections on Roman Provincial Jurisdiction’, in R. Haensch and J. Heinrichs (eds),
Herrschen und Verwalten. Der Alltag der römischen Administration in der Hohen
Kaiserzeit (Böhlau, 2007), pp. 235–55.
20
U. Babusiaux, ‘Coordination of Different Layers of Law in the Roman Empire and in the
European Union’, in U. Babusiaux and M. Igimi, Messages from Antiquity: Roman Law
and Current Legal Debates (Böhlau Publishers, 2020), pp. 131–67, at p. 131 (my
emphasis).
21
Famous examples include Cicero’s discussion of Roman jurisdiction in Sicily, 70 BCE
(Against Verres II, 2.32) and the Cyrene edicts of the Emperor Augustus, 7–4 BCE. See
further J. Richardson, ‘Roman Law in the Provinces’, in D. Johnston (ed.), The Cambridge
Companion to Roman Law (Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 45–58.
22
G. Minaud, Les gens du commerce et le droit à Rome: Essai d’histoire juridique et social du
commerce dans le monde antique romain (Presses universitaires d’Aix-Marseille, 2011).
23
D. Daube, ‘The Peregrine Praetor’ (1951) 41 The Journal of Roman Studies 66–70.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
by the Roman law as applying to, and being used by, all the people they
met, whether Roman citizens or not’.24 The elaboration of this concept
enabled Roman jurists to define certain private law interactions between
peregrini, ‘Latins’ (who had some of the rights and privileges of Roman
citizenship via Roman grants of the ius Latii) and Roman citizens, as
falling under Roman jurisdiction. For example, peregrini could acquire
ownership through ‘natural’ modes of acquisition (traditio, occupatio,
accessio) and certain contracts of buying, selling and letting were also
understood to be part of the ius gentium; slavery was iure gentium, all
peoples had it although there were aspects of the (Roman) law of slavery
that were peculiar to the Roman ius civile alone; and in certain Roman
law actions a legal fiction even enabled foreigners to sue or be sued ‘as if’
they were Roman citizens.25 The important point to note here is that
while Roman jurists and magistrates worked within a conceptual frame-
work that acknowledged different ‘layers of law’ (Rechtsschichten),
including the ius gentium, their start and end point was the resolution
of cases – hypothetical and real – in accordance with the citizen-law of
Rome itself.26 The opening of Gaius’ Institutes, a mid-second-century
introduction to Roman law, famously refers to ‘all peoples who are
governed by laws and customs’ as having their own bodies of citizen-
law – yet there are no extended discussions of clashes between national
laws, nor ‘cases [in which] a court must apply a foreign law’, in Classical
Roman juristic texts.27 There is, however, an explicit discourse in both
extra-legal and legal Roman texts acknowledging ‘overlapping spheres’
and entangled norms within Roman private law.28
24
J. Crook, Law and Life in Ancient Rome (Cornell University Press, 1967), p. 29.
25
C. Humfress, ‘Law’s Empire: Roman Universalism and Legal Practice’, in P. du Plessis
(ed.), New Frontiers: Law and Society in the Roman World (Edinburgh University Press,
2013), pp. 73–101.
26
On the concept of Rechtsschichten, see Babusiaux, ‘Coordination of Different Layers of
Law’, 131–2.
27
Cf. J. Waldon, ‘Partly Laws Common to All Mankind’: Foreign Law in American Courts
(Yale University Press, 2012), pp. 33–5, which makes use of the same Gaius passage in its
title: Gaius, Institutes 1.1.1 (The Institutes of Gaius, trans. W. Gordon and O. Robinson
(Duckworth, 1988), p. 19).
28
K. Tuori, ‘The Reception of Ancient Legal Thought in Early Modern International Law’,
in B. Fassbender and A. Peters (eds), The Oxford Handbook of the History of International
Law (Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 1012–33, at pp. 1016–18, citing Cicero, On
Duties 3.17.69 and 3.5.23, Tusculan Disputations 1.13.30 and The Divisions of Oratory
37.130; Gaius, Institutes 1.1; Aulus Gellius, Attic Nights 6.3.45; and Justinian Digest,
1.1.1.2, 1.1.4, 1.1.6 (Ulpian).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Alongside the ius gentium (discussed by some Classical Roman jurists
in relation to ‘natural law’), Babusiaux identifies three layers of Roman
private law: the ius civile narrowly understood (the law of the citizen-
body of Rome); the ius praetorium or ius honorarium (the law of the
urban praetor – the praetor with jurisdiction between Roman citizens);
and ‘imperial law’ (law enacted by or on behalf of the Roman
emperors).29 Through a series of detailed case studies, Babusiaux con-
vincingly demonstrates how the application of these different layers of
law to specific legal questions could seemingly create clashes, requiring
conflicting legal outcomes. The Roman jurist’s solution was not to rank
the layers of law within an abstract hierarchy of precedence, but rather to
reason out their application case by case:
It must therefore be underlined that the Roman jurists were very well
aware of the different requirements in the ius civile and ius praetorium, on
the one hand, and the imperial law on the other hand. But neither did
they coin a general principle in order to overcome these differences nor
did they see a general conflict between these requirements. In fact, they
seem to stick to a case by case view, in which the different layers had to be
harmonised according to the individual circumstances.30
The structuring of the different layers of (Roman) law was thus case-
specific and dependent on the specialized reasoning techniques of the
jurists themselves. In one sense, then, these Roman layers of law can be
said to have operated heterarchically: side by side without the presump-
tive authority of one over the other. Yet the crucial point here is that it
was the Roman jurists, the expert legal actors, who provided the overall
structure by reasoning out potential overlaps, entanglements and clashes
casuistically.31
As I argue in Section 13.2, ‘postnational’ law’s focus on legal norms
and principles is itself influenced by a modern (Western) tradition: a
tradition that links normative-conceptual approaches to ‘defining what
law is’ with territorial approaches to defining nation state sovereignty.32
Rather than locating multiplicity and plurality in different bodies of
29
Babusiaux, ‘Coordination of Different Layers of Law’, 132–43.
30
Ibid., 142–3.
31
Babusiaux, ibid., suggests that the relevant Roman juristic techniques were developed
from Roman rhetorical theory and practice. The article goes on to suggest the potential of
applying a similar approach to the ‘coordination of different layers of law’ within the
European Union.
32
See further M. Madero, ‘Penser la tradition juridique occidentale’ (2012) 67(1) Annales.
Histoire, Sciences Sociales 103–32, at 109–10 on the ‘fundamental link between the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
overlapping and entangled norms and then positing ‘a set of new types of
norms at the interfaces between different legal sub-orders’, Babusiaux’s
analysis suggests that we should look to legal actors – in this case the
Roman jurists – as structuring agents in their own right. As I suggest in
Section 13.3 through a case study of the record of a protracted sixth-
century dispute, this focus on legal actors as structuring agents is not
simply a question of how different individuals and groups apply legal
norms and principles in different times, places and contexts. Rather than
adopting a modern ‘law in action’ or ‘law in practice’ perspective, Section
13.3 aims to develop an approach to norms and legal actors that is more
akin to Lévi-Strauss’ disentanglements of Amerindian myths: ‘We thus
do not pretend to show how men think in myths, but how myths are
thought in men, and without their knowledge.’33
political stakes of theories of the state and the role of law in the Western political
tradition’.
33
Lévi-Strauss, Mythologiques, p. 20: ‘Nous ne prétendons donc pas montrer comment les
hommes pensant dans les mythes, mais comment les mythes se pensent dans les hommes,
et à leur insu.’
34
D. Roth-Isigkeit, The Plurality Trilemma: A Geometry of Global Legal Thought (Springer
International Publishing, 2018), p. 66.
35
Walker, ‘Beyond Boundary Disputes and Basic Grids’, especially 373.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
conventionally separate, structures of constitutional law (considered as
the law of the Keynesian-Westphalian state) and international law (con-
sidered as the law between Keynesian-Westphalian states)’.36 According
to Nico Krisch, ‘The resulting “postnational law” is thus a frame com-
prised of different orders and their norms.’37 Norms which, as we saw in
Section 13.1, exist in heterarchical – rather than hierarchical – relation to
each other. Hence one of the central claims of Krisch’s ‘postnational law’
paradigm: ‘that global law fares better if it embraces plurality, rather than
trying to tame it in an institutional model’.38
To a historian whose research interests lie mainly within the presover-
eigntist, prenationalist and prepositivist world, the centrality of norms
within ‘postnational law’ and the ‘Entangled Legalities’ project seems
striking. Not only is the ‘frame’ of postnational law made up of orders
which in turn are made up of norms, but the mechanism through which
norm interaction is seen to take place is defined as a set of new types of
norms, operating at the interfaces between different legal suborders. This
set of new types of norms includes ‘reception norms’: ‘the typical form
through which a legal system deals with norms from the outside; they
reproduce the inside/outside distinction and define the ways in which
outside norms enter a given body of norms’ (also referred to as between
systems/conflict-of-law norms); ‘overarching norms’ which ‘regulate rela-
tions centrally and with binding character for the different bodies of norms
involved’ (also referred to as within system/intra-systemic norms); and
‘connecting norms’ and ‘straddling pactices’, the ‘norms and practices that
straddle different bodies of norms without being seen to belong to either,
thus blurring the boundaries between them’ (‘straddling boundaries’).39
Norms have a ‘travelling content’ through which they perform their
operations, becoming entangled within a broader discursive context:
Actors – litigants, judges, dispute settlers, observers, addressees – make
claims about the relation of norms from different backgrounds, and they
thus define and redefine the relative weights and interconnection between
the norms at play. They also define the extent to which norms are
perceived to form part of broader assemblages – in the relatively stable
and firm mode of modern state legal orders, or in more porous ways, with
a more open interplay of norms and characterized more through their
36
Walker, ‘Beyond Boundary Disputes and Basic Grids’, 374.
37
Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism, p. 12 (my emphasis).
38
Roth-Isigkeit, The Plurality Trilemma, p. 158.
39
Chapter 1, Section 1.5.1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
linkages across boundaries than any strong form of belonging to an order
as such [. . .] When we focus on legal entanglement here, we mean such
discursive entanglement: the universe of statements that link different
bodies of norms with one another. This is similar to the ‘relational’ (as
opposed to ‘material’) entanglement in cultural studies: an entanglement
in which the difference in origin remains visible even if the object is
embedded in a different practice.40
The modern (Western) idea that every legal rule carries with it a ‘ticket’
to institutionalized enforcement links back to the presumption, discussed
40
Chapter 1, Section 1.2.
41
Roth-Isigkeit, The Plurality Trilemma, p. 60 (my emphasis).
42
L. M. Friedman, ‘Legal Rules and the Process of Social Change’ (1967) 19 Stanford Law
Review 786–840, at 788.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
in Section 13.1, that law is only meaningful when backed by state
power or – to phrase it more loosely – when structured by a Lévi-
Straussian ‘Rome’.
‘Law in action’ and ‘law in practice’ approaches tend to rely on this
modern, Western, idea of legal norms and rules carrying a jurisprudential
aspect. It is inherent, for example, in Neil MacCormick’s call for a ‘user-
orientated understanding of norms’ and also in the wider context of his
definition of law itself as an ‘institutional normative order’.43 It is implied
in Lon Fuller’s ‘interaction theory of law’ which ascribes an active role to
individuals within the ‘legal system’ through an analysis of their ‘inter-
actional expectancies’ when engaging with ‘enacted law’ (i.e. law that is
accompanied by an explicit ticket to institutionalized enforcement).44 In
terms of the international legal sphere, the ‘Transnational Legal Process
model’ relies on norms having a jurisdictional aspect, enabling it to move
beyond a formalist concept of rules, in order to stress the role of ‘intern-
alized obedience’ in developing ‘sets of normative practices’.45 Finally, the
‘Entangled Legalities’ project’s account of ‘norm entanglement’ – I would
suggest – also relies on the idea of ‘strong’ legal norms from different
origins carrying different jurisdictional ‘tickets’. It is precisely this juris-
dictional aspect which prevents individual norms from becoming inte-
grated – rather than entangled – through the (repeated, dynamic) ‘social
interplay of actors’:
Norms from different origins become relevant in the same situation, and
they often come with divergent prescriptions or at least orientations.
Their relations are not predefined but remain to be determined through
the social interplay of actors. A common state of affairs in the law – and
likely a more common one than legal ‘systems’ with aspirations of hier-
archy, order and coherence, as depicted in the standard image of law in
the context of the modern, Western nation state.
43
N. MacCormick, Institutions of Law: Essay in Legal Theory (Oxford University Press,
2007), p. 287.
44
S. Taekema, ‘The Many Uses of Law: Interactional Law as a Bridge between
Instrumentalism and Law’s Values’, in N. Roughan and A. Halpin (eds), In Pursuit of
Pluralist Jurisprudence (Cambridge University Press, 2017), pp. 116–35, at p. 121.
45
Roth-Isigkeit, The Plurality Trilemma, p. 181.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘political’ framework.46 Classical Roman jurists did not understand law
(or legal order) as a system of binding, imperative norms. As the Roman
legal historian José Luis Alonso Rodriguez states: ‘Legal positivism not
only means identifying law with legislation tout court [. . .] It means also
the thorough normativisation (“Durchnormierung”) of the law, the con-
struction of the entire legal system as a system of imperative, binding
norms. Nothing can be more remote from the Roman legal experience in
the late Republic and early Empire.’47
We saw in Section 13.1 that relations between the different layers of
Roman law were dynamic and heterarchical: they depended on the skill
of Roman jurists to reason out potential overlaps, entanglements and
clashes on a case-by-case basis. Alonso Rodriguez continues: ‘Legal
Positivism [. . .] stems from the normative monopoly of the sovereign
and the subjection of the jurisdiction to the law, as theorized in modern
political thinking from Hobbes onwards. Such normative monopoly and
jurisdictional subjection are alien to the Roman political theory and
practice of the late Republic and early Empire.’48 In other words,
Roman legal norms, rules and principles did not carry with them an
automatic jurisprudential aspect: ‘a ticket to some person, agency, or
institution’. Roman jurisdiction was not subjected to the law, but was
accorded to specific individuals and groups. These individuals and
groups ranged from the formal iurisdictio cum imperio of Roman magis-
trates and provincial governors, to the legal authority granted to arbitra-
tors by contractual Roman arbitration agreements, to the auctoritas
exercised by jurists on account of their technical expertise, to the author-
ity of a Christian bishop, a freelancing ‘holy man’, an Arab tribal leader,
or any other local ‘big man’, recognized by two parties jointly seeking a
(negotiated, mediated or adjudicated) resolution to a dispute.
Legal norms, then, did not define a Roman legal system any more than
they defined a Late Antique Talmudic or early Christian legal order. My
argument in Section 13.3 is not that legal norms, rules and principles
were irrelevant to entangled legalities in Late Antiquity. Rather, I am
suggesting that if we place the emphasis on Roman legal norms, we risk
46
Chapter 1, Section 1.1. On the Keynesian-Westphalian frame as an ‘at root [. . .] political
settlement’ see Walker, ‘Beyond Boundary Disputes and Basic Grids’, 393.
47
J. L. Alonso Rodriguez, ‘Customary Law and Legal Pluralism in the Roman Empire: The
Status of Peregrine Law in Egypt’ (2013) 43 The Journal of Juristic Papyrology 351–404, at
391.
48
Ibid., 391.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
importing a modern jurisprudential aspect to them; and this would be at
the expense of neglecting the plurality of entangled legalities that oper-
ated, in practice, through concrete appeals to multiple, different, types of
power. Section 13.3 thus emphasizes the construction of legalities –
plural – on the ground and, more specifically, the juris(dictional)-
generative practices revealed in one sixth-century document: P.
Petra IV.39, a report of proceedings before arbitrators from the Eastern
(Byzantine) Roman Empire.49
49
P. Petra IV.39 – see M. Kaimio (ed. and trans.), ‘Settlement of a Dispute by Arbitration’,
in A. Arjava, M. Buchholz, T. Gagos and M. Kaimio (eds), The Petra Papyri IV (American
Centre of Oriental Research, 2011), pp. 41–120.
50
See Chapter 1, Section 1.6.2.
51
K. Tuori, ‘Legal Pluralism and the Roman Empire’, in J. W. Cairns and P. J. du Plessis
(eds), Beyond Dogmatics: Law and Society in the Roman World (Edinburgh University
Press, 2007), pp. 39–52; and C. Ando, ‘Legal Pluralism in Practice’, in P. J. du Plessis, C.
Ando and K. Tuori (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Roman Law and Society (Oxford
University Press, 2016), pp. 283–93.
52
C. Humfress, ‘Laws’ Empire: Roman Universalism and Legal Practice’, in P. J. du Plessis
(ed.), New Frontiers: Law and Society in the Roman World (Edinburgh University Press,
2013), pp. 73–101; and G. Kantor, ‘Local Law in Asia Minor after the Constitutio
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
pluralism existed within the Roman Empire between the fourth and early
seventh centuries – it did – but rather what kinds of legal plurality and
hybridity we are talking about.53 There is no reference in P. Petra IV.39
to formal Roman court proceedings or imperial bureaucratic legal
officials.54 Instead, the legal actors mentioned in the document seem to
have understood justice-seeking as an interconnected web of possibil-
ities – making use of practical, localized and provisional (at least when
viewed from beyond the relevant immediate time frame) – accommoda-
tions. As we shall see in the case of the multiple dispute settlements
recorded in P. Petra IV.39, Late Antique legal entanglements could
stretch across jurisdictional, religious and ethnic boundaries. Through
an analysis of P. Petra IV.39 we thus move from pluralism ‘as a way an
observer might see things from without – to pluralities: to seeing the
world as experienced by those who inhabited it’.55
Since the 1950s, a wealth of new sixth- and early seventh-century
documentary evidence has opened up the field of Late Antique juristic
papyrology – the study of law through mainly documentary evidence
recorded on papyri – beyond the large mass of texts recovered from
Egypt.56 The American Center of Oriental Research in Amman, Jordan,
has recently coordinated the publication of a remarkable five-volume set
of papyri from sixth-century Petra, the remotely located metropolis of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the Roman border province Palaestina Tertia.57 The papyri were found
in December 1993, as part of ongoing excavations of the Byzantine
Church of the Virgin Mary in Petra led by the American Center of
Oriental Research. Two teams of papyrologists – an American team from
Michigan University and a Finnish team from Helsinki – worked with
around 140 carbonized rolls, reconstructing the private papers of a
certain Theodoros, son of Obodianos (born 514 and died 591 ), a
property owner, deacon and later archdeacon of the Christian Church of
the Virgin Mary in Petra (the location where the papyrus rolls were
found).58 Taken as a whole, the Petra archive provides evidence for the
persistence of Roman forms and structures in the city of Petra and its
surrounding localities: there was a continued Roman military presence
and the centralized land-tax system of the Byzantine Empire was still
being implemented up to at least the period of the Arab conquests
(c.634–8 ).59 Yet when read together with Late Antique papyri from
Egypt, in addition to other papyri from the Near East, the Petra archive
does not reveal an Eastern Provincial law: ‘a hybrid, indigenous law of the
Near East’.60 Instead, we see a series of concrete situations in which
individuals and groups around and beyond the Late Antique eastern
Mediterranean – Syria, Palestine, the Arabian Peninsula and Egypt –
made use of numerous, entangled, legal practices, forms of argument and
juris(dictional)-generative situations in order to get things done.
P. Petra IV.39 is a complex and incomplete text, reconstructed from
around 3,000 fragments of papyri by its editor Maarit Kaimio and others.
The document is a report of proceedings before arbitrators (dikastai),
probably drawn up on 8 August 574 by an official notary from the
Kastron Zadakathon (Sadaqa), a garrisoned, fortified settlement 20 km
south of Petra on the margins of the Eastern Roman Empire. The
reconstituted papyrus’ extant length is a remarkable c.6.2–6.5 metres,
57
J. Frösen, A. Arjava and M. Lehtinen (eds), The Petra Papyri I (American Centre of
Oriental Research, 2002); L. Koenen, J. Kaimio, M. Kaimio and R. W. Daniel (eds), The
Petra Papyri II (American Centre of Oriental Research, 2013); A. Arjava, M. Buchholz
and T. Gagos (eds), The Petra Papyri III (American Centre of Oriental Research, 2007);
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV; and A. Arjava, J. Frösén and J. Kaimio (eds), The Petra
Papyri V (American Centre of Oriental Research, 2018).
58
L. Koenen, ‘The Decipherment and Edition of the Petra Papyri: Preliminary
Observations’, in L. H. Schiffman (ed.), Semitic Papyrology in Context: A Climate of
Creativity (Brill, 2003), pp. 201–26, at p. 202.
59
See ibid., p. 212, on the centralised land-tax system in operation at Petra.
60
P. Crone, Roman, Provincial, and Islamic Law (Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 99.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
with 523 lines of text surviving. Nine different hands can be distinguished
in the document, with one clear cursive hand indicating a trained
scribe.61 The document itself is written in Greek, but its contents reveal
a multilingual environment. At certain points the papyrus refers to two
languages being used simultaneously: Greek and ‘Syriac’ (probably an
Aramaic dialect).62 Both of the parties involved in the 574 dispute –
Theodoros, son of Obodianos, and Stephanos, son of Leontius – are
clergymen; as is Heiros, son of Thomallos, who drafted the arbitration
agreement’s stipulation of penalty, and one of the arbitrators, Theodoros,
son of Alpheios who is identified in the document as an archdeacon. The
other arbitrator, Flavius Thomas, son of Boethos, was a senior officer in
the local military unit garrisoned at Sadaqa.63 As discussed in more detail
later in this section, the record of the 574 arbitration settlement refers
to two previously negotiated settlements: one probably from the 530s,
decided by an Arab tribal leader and a further settlement from sometime
before 574 that had been mediated by a Christian cleric from a
neighbouring rural area. In addition to arbitration and mediation pro-
ceedings, P. Petra IV.39 also refers to other forms of justice-seeking,
which include trips to the ‘sacred shrine of the holy and glorious martyr
Kerykos’ (in Sadaqa) in order to swear oaths of innocence on the
Christian Holy Scriptures.64
The report of proceedings given in P. Petra IV.39 touches upon
numerous points of dispute, all related to the fact that Theodoros son
of Obodianos and Stephanos son of Leontius owned neighbouring prop-
erties in Sadaqa, as had their fathers before them. Theodoros and his
father, however, seem to have been absentee property owners; at line
103 in the text Theodoros responds indignantly to an accusation that he
does not ‘care for local matters’. Stephanos, on the other hand, seems to
have taken advantage of Theodoros’ absence from Sadaqa in order to
build new physical structures and make alterations to the flow of the
61
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV, p. 45.
62
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV, p. 72, lines 475–85, mentions documents being presented in
both Greek and Syriac letters.
63
Ibid., p. 45. Further discussion in Z. T. Fiema, ‘The Byzantine Military in the Petra Papyri:
A Summary’, in A. Lewin, P. Pellegrini, Z. T. Fiema and S. Janniard (eds), The Late
Roman Army in the Near East from Diocletian to the Arab Conquest (Archaeopress,
2007), pp. 313–19.
64
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV, pp. 72–3, lines 475–85 and 485–95.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
water supply without Theodoros’ approval.65 This led to disputes over
Stephanos’ and Theodoros’ rights to the water that drained from a roof-
spout, which had originally been constructed by Theodoros and was the
subject of an earlier dispute mediated by the ‘country bishop’ Sergios.66
Who owned which parts of the adjacent properties was also at issue,
including rights of access across a central courtyard and rights of owner-
ship relating to a refuse pit and an outbuilding.67 Theodoros claimed that
the outbuilding was his by right of inheritance, producing a written deed
of sale made for his father seventy years ago.68 He also seems to claim
that he had been sold the outbuilding by two other individuals
(Kassisaios and Gregoria), but could not produce any supporting
written documents. Stephanos, meanwhile, counter-claimed that his
father had bought the outbuilding and surrounding courtyard fifty-three
years ago, apparently from Theodoros’ father. Stephanos produced
two deeds of sale, but Theodoros responded that the outbuilding and
surrounding land had not been included in the transaction. Added to
this complex situation, P. Petra IV.39 also includes accusations of
encroachment and theft of building materials – timber, blocks of stone
and doors – by local soldiers, possibly under the command of one of
the 574 arbitrators: Flavius Thomas.69 In addition, the document
records a further, rather murky, claim for two solidi (gold coins) related
to an earlier dispute between the families over a vineyard.70 Perhaps
unsurprisingly, the hostilities between the two families spilled out into
the local community, with Stephanos accusing Theodoros of deliberately
stirring things up with the neighbours – who, we are told, made many
‘unwritten accusations’.71 P. Petra IV.39 thus records a longstanding
series of disputes between two local families, spanning several decades.
There is obviously a complex backstory to the 574 arbitration. As a
546/7 papyrus from the Egyptian city of Antinoe put it, ‘many words
65
Ibid., p. 51, and M. Wojczak, ‘Settlements of Claims as a Way of Dispute Resolution in
the Light of P. Petra IV 39: A Legal Commentary’ (2012) 42 The Journal of Juristic
Papyrology 353–80 at 359.
66
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV, p. 54.
67
Ibid., p. 53. The refuse pit, in particular, seems to have been the object of a
longstanding feud.
68
Ibid., pp. 52 and 69, lines 69–79.
69
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV, p. 55.
70
Ibid., p. 55.
71
Ibid., p. 71, lines 305–19.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
have been said and many moves have been made’ before the parties
brought their case before the arbitrators.72
Arbitration (and mediation), in contrast to judicial settlement by a
standing tribunal, is designed by the parties to the dispute. The basic
modern ‘principle of party autonomy’ – that the parties agree which
issue(s) to submit to arbitration, that is, the issues to be decided upon; the
choice of arbitrator(s); and the ‘applicable law’, that is, the law applicable
to the dispute, including soft law and ‘non-binding’ law – can also be
seen in operation in Roman arbitration proceedings. Similarly, the
modern distinction between ‘ad hoc arbitration’ and ‘institutional arbi-
tration’ (where the parties rely on the procedural rules of an arbitral
institution determined by the relevant institution) can also be seen in
Late Antique contexts. Arbitrations and other negotiation settlements
before Late Antique Christian bishops and clerics, for example,
developed institutionally specific norms and practices. Records of pro-
ceedings held before arbitrators and formal arbitration agreements sur-
vive on papyri from both the Late Antique Near East and the West. These
include an Egyptian record of a dispute settled by arbitration in 647
and recorded in Coptic, which the editor of P. Petra IV.39, Maarit
Kaimio, notes as the closest parallel to our 574 text. P. Petra IV.39,
however, is unique in that it refers to the submission of written pleas and
documents at an early stage of the proceedings, but records the parties’
oral pleas before the arbitrators in direct speech: ‘the speech flows in
personal style, often becoming agitated and even insulting’.73 In other
words, aside from the opening and concluding formalities of the arbitra-
tion procedure and the stipulation of penalty, the language used by the
parties is not formulaic. What we see recorded in P. Petra IV.39 is a
localized culture of argumentation.
Chronologically, the earliest negotiated settlement mentioned in
P. Petra IV.39 relates to the vineyard and the claim for two solidi. This
dispute, the papyrus states, occurred sometime in the past – Kaimio
suggests the late 520s or 530s – between Theodoros, son of Obodianos
and Leontius, the father of Stephanos. It was resolved before a mediator
referred to in the document as ‘Abou Cherebos’. This is probably Abu
Karib ibn Jabala, part of the Jafnid dynasty that acted as power brokers
between Rome and the Bedouin.74 Abu Karib ibn Jabala was granted the
72
Wojtczak, ‘Legal Aspects of Dispute Resolution’, 36.
73
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV, p. 48.
74
Ibid., pp. 55 and 90 (commenting on lines 163–87 of the text).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Phylarcate of Palestine (including southern Jordan and Petra) by the
Roman Emperor Justinian sometime in the 530s.75 Thus we have a
relatively minor dispute over a vineyard, involving two landowners of
middling means, mediated by an Arab tribal leader with a network of
contacts that stretched all the way from (present-day) Jordan to the
Emperor in Constantinople.76 In choosing Abu Karib as the mediator
of their dispute, Theodoros and Leontius deliberately exploited local and
imperial networks. The second negotiated settlement mentioned in P.
Petra IV.39 took place sometime before 574 and was concluded between
Theodoros, son of Obodianos, and the individual whom he claimed to
have bought the disputed outbuilding from: a certain Kassisaios. The
memorandum of this agreement, included in the documents submitted to
the 574 arbitrators, states that it was made through ‘Sergios, priest and
“country-bishop” (chorepiscopos)’.77 Here we have the parties appealing
to a Christian cleric from a neighbouring rural area, perhaps either
exploiting a personal network or, conversely, attempting to remove the
dispute from its immediate, urban, context. We also see the use of a
Christian cleric as arbitrator in the 574 settlement itself, alongside a
high-ranking military officer who may have been directly implicated in
the circumstances of the case. P. Petra IV.39 thus presents us with
multiple justice-seeking attempts, before multiple individuals of different
types. The crucial point to note here is that each of the different venues
for dispute resolution were put into relation with each other by the
parties to the disputes themselves. The interlinkage here is literally created
through the parties’ own juris(dictional)-generative practices.
We turn, finally, to the legal norms and principles that the parties rely
upon in their justice-seeking activities. In common with other papyri in
the Petra and Nessana archives, the protocol of P. Petra IV.39 seems
to make use of procedural terms and concepts derived from Roman
75
Procopius, History of the Wars I.xix.10–13, states that Justinian received a gift of ‘the
palmtrees’ from Abu Karim, ‘who now guarded the land from plunder’. In a brilliant
example of Late Antique realpolitik, however, Procopius goes on to explain that, ‘In
formal terms the emperor holds the Palmtrees, but for him [Justinian] to possess himself
of any of the country is in practice utterly impossible [. . .] The Palmtrees themselves are
worth nothing and Abocharabos [Abu Karib ibn Jabala] only gave the form of a gift, and
the emperor accepted it with full knowledge of the fact.’
76
E. K. Fowden, The Barbarian Plain: Saint Sergius between Rome and Iran (University of
California Press, 1999), pp. 167–70, notes that the Jafnid family constructed an ‘audience
hall’ south of the town of Resafa which functioned as a Church and a place for dispute
settlement for people coming on pilgrimage to the shrine of St Sergius.
77
Arjava et al., Petra Papyri IV, pp. 50, 54 and 69.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
law: ‘Instances of such terms in the text demonstrate beyond doubt that
the parties and arbitrators had some, considerable, specific legal know-
ledge.’78 Marzena Wojtczak’s careful and cautious reconstruction of the
substantive Roman rules and concepts that can be pieced together from
P. Petra IV.39 also suggests the use of legal norms and concepts derived
from Roman law, while at the same time highlighting the specificity of
localized practices.79 According to Wojtczak, P. Petra IV.39 ‘gives an
impression that we are actually dealing with a sequence of debts and
securities between the two families’, involving ‘a sequence of fiduciary or
fictitious sales’ with multiple ownership changes over a relatively short
period of time (what a modern lawyer might refer to as a situation of
relational contracting).80 As Wojtczak’s article concludes: ‘It should be
considered that ordinary people, not acquainted with dogmatic legal
patterns, sought solutions which would appear to protect their rights in
[the] best possible manner. Transfer of ownership treated as a security
for credit seems to be in accord with this idea.’81
The use of a technical Roman legal register in P. Petra IV.39 thus
needs to be understood within the context of local relations and localized
practices. Evidence for these localized practices can be difficult to pin-
point in Late Antique legal and documentary source material, nonethe-
less, as Wojtczak’s example of the creative, ‘localized’ use of multiple
fiduciary or fictitious sales suggests, Roman legal concepts and practices
were put to work differently, by different networks of individuals, fam-
ilies and groups, operating within different localities around the empire.
Moreover, the fact that this creative use of Roman legal norms in P. Petra
IV.39 is apparent across a succession of settlements, decided in turn by
Christian clerics, a Roman military official and an Arab tribal leader,
underscores the fact that the Roman legal norms themselves were con-
sidered ‘portable’. Once again, there may be modern parallels to be teased
out here in terms of exploring the relationship between entangled legal-
ities on the ground and ‘strategic legal argumentation’. For example,
Adam Bower stresses the role played by ‘strategic legal argumentation’
in contemporary multilateral settings: ‘First, in multilateral settings
actors will tend to invoke justifications based in legal principles, norms,
and rules – potentially in conjunction with coercive efforts – in pursuing
78
Wojtczak, ‘Settlements of Claims as a Way of Dispute Resolution’, 357–8.
79
Ibid., 360–80.
80
Ibid., 377–9.
81
Ibid., 379–80.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
policy goals. This strategy is preferable even when the actor making a
claim does not fully endorse the standards it employs.’82 Strategic legal
argumentation, I would suggest, is at least as important as (‘travelling’)
legal norms when it comes to the construction of entangled legalities past
and present.
While it may be tempting to interpret P. Petra IV.39, and the Petra
archive more generally, as evidence for the persistence of Roman forms
and structures (the Roman military, the Roman land ownership and
taxation system, Roman legal norms and principles), this would risk
sidelining the situated, entangled web of practices that I discuss in this
chapter. The fact that Roman legal norms underpin some of the parties’
direct speech as recorded in P. Petra IV.39 is an important point, but
Roman law should not be understood as ‘the’ centralizing, organizing,
principle at work across the life of these disputes. What P. Petra IV.39
suggests instead is a complex picture of connected localisms: Roman
military networks are enmeshed within civilian, urban, life; Arab tribal
leaders mediate property disputes between Christian clerics; and urban
clerical networks intersect with wider rural connections. To reduce this
connectivity to a static (Roman) provincial law would in fact sideline the
extent to which Roman legal norms were put to work, by the parties
themselves, in concrete situations and contexts. P. Petra IV.39 shows us
sixth-century legal actors operating at the margins of empire, mobilizing
multiple networks and regimes – local, regional, trans-regional, imperial –
and in the process creating connected, but crucially not integrated, legal
orderings of their own.
13.4 Conclusion
With our analysis of the presovereigntist, prenationalist and prepositivist
world of P. Petra IV.39 we have moved far beyond a modern, state-
sovereigntist, court-centric framework. P. Petra IV.39, in contrast, under-
scores the central role of legal actors in creating localized and entangled
legalities on the ground; entangled legalities within which arguments
from – portable – Roman legal norms and principles play a significant,
but not determinate, role. One of the central questions posed by the
‘Entangled Legalities’ project is how to reimagine the global legal order
82
A. Bower, ‘Arguing with Law: Strategic Legal Argumentation, US Diplomacy, and
Debates over the International Criminal Court’ (2015) 41 Review of international
Studies 337–60, at 339.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
through the paradigm of entangled legalities. I would argue that one
answer involves reframing the analysis so that it shifts from a predomin-
ate concern with legal norms towards a ‘user theory of jurisdiction’: an
analysis of the ways in which different legal actors shape themselves to
the jurisdictional claims made by state, non-state and extra-state author-
ities and, in turn, work to shape the concept of jurisdiction itself. As Nico
Krisch states: ‘the systemic, hierarchical and exclusive [image of law] may
well constitute the exception rather than the rule’.83
83
See Chapter 1, Section 1.6.2.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
14
1
A note on terminology: for the purposes of this chapter, we use as interchangeable
‘Indigenous peoples’, ‘Aboriginal peoples’ and ‘First Nations’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
to existing relations and explanations, and moreover, this entanglement
presents what may over time become the replacement of Canada’s
foundational unitary constitution by an equally durable pluriform
foundation.
A brief foreshadowing of the context of our argument together with an
explanation of its structure will serve as a helpful beginning. Canada was
created in 1867 with the Constitution Act, 1867 (also known as the
British North America Act, 1867, an act of the United Kingdom
Parliament). Sections 91 and 92 of the Constitution Act, 1867 divide
the powers and authority of the Canadian state, without remainder,
between the federal and provincial governments. No constitutional
power or authority is allocated to Indigenous peoples. Indigenous rights
and claims have nonetheless been recognized in diverse ways since 1867.
The Indian Act, 1876, a constitutional amendment in 1982 and several
Supreme Court of Canada decisions have acknowledged the existence of
Indigenous legal orders, albeit always through the particular lens of the
Canadian legal institution undertaking an act of recognition – viewing
claims of Indigenous law from the perspective and authority of the
Canadian legal system and subject to the limitations set by Crown
sovereignty and associated doctrines. Until very recently, this interaction
was readily explained by what we have called elsewhere a state-centred
approach to legal theory, taking the legal system of the sovereign state as
the central instance and object of legal theory as a consequence of the
sovereign state’s centrality to legal order in the post-Westphalian era.2
The bulk of our argument presents evidence for the claim that practically
and theoretically significant changes are occurring in the way Canadian
legal institutions are engaging with Indigenous peoples’ legal claims rooted
in the assertion of the existence of Indigenous legal orders existing without
recourse to Canadian recognition as a condition of their existence. We
demonstrate a gradual yet unmistakably foundational change as institutions
of the Canadian legal system embrace a different approach to recognizing
Indigenous peoples’ rights, claims and legal orders, through various letters
of understanding, framework agreements and protocols. This new approach
suggests a reconception of the basic terms of what this volume refers to
as entangled legalities, from a supremacy-claiming systematicity view to one
2
See K. Culver and M. Giudice, Legality’s Borders: An Essay in General Jurisprudence
(Oxford University Press, 2010); and K. Culver and M. Giudice, The Unsteady State:
General Jurisprudence for Dynamic Social Phenomena (Cambridge University Press, 2017).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of ‘government-to-government’ partnership between state (federal and
provincial) governments and Indigenous governments.
We proceed as follows. In Section 14.1, we show how claims to
supreme authority made by Canada’s legal institutions have exemplified
the descriptive-explanatory picture of law offered by state-centred ana-
lytical legal theory, while noting along the way the beginnings of recog-
nition of the limitations or inaptness of such claims in the context of
Canada’s changing relation with Indigenous peoples and their legal
orders. In Section 14.2, we provide historical and recent Canadian evi-
dence for the contingency of the relation between systemic claims of
supremacy and the presence of durable legal order. Legal order, we argue,
can and does exist in conditions of entanglement where there are no
overarching legal systems claiming and enjoying some degree of supreme
authority. In Section 14.3, we suggest an alternative to the system-centred
view and the insistence on the necessity of a supremacy-claiming author-
ity to the existence of durable legal order. That alternative was introduced
in previous work, and is developed further here in the context of state–
Indigenous entangled legality in Canada.
3
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law, 3rd ed. (Oxford University Press, 2012).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
distinctive features of law are the provision it makes by secondary rules
for the identification, change, and enforcement of its standards and the
general claim it makes to priority over other standards’.4 While Hart left
the notion of supremacy or ‘priority’ with little further development of its
content, the idea became central to Joseph Raz’s largely complementary
explanation of the concept of legal system. As Raz explains, in addition to
comprehensiveness and openness, a general claim to supremacy is one of
the unique and distinguishing characteristics of legal systems:
The condition means that every legal system claims authority to regulate
the setting up and application of other institutionalized systems by its
subject-community. In other words, it claims authority to prohibit,
permit, or impose conditions on the institution and operation of all the
normative organizations to which members of its subject-community
belong.5
Raz offers this observation in the context of discussion about the neces-
sary features ‘of all the intuitively clear instances of municipal legal
systems’.6 Raz’s claim is carefully delimited, announcing a focus on
obvious central instances of state systems of law, leaving unexamined
what might be regarded as borderline cases, and forms of legal order
beyond the state, as may be found in international law. Yet even Raz’s
delimited claim is subject to doubt, as critics argue that it may not be
necessary to the nature of law that it claims supremacy, whether in state
systems or other legal orders.7 Here we leave this debate to one side,
while observing that our argument regarding entangled legality in
Canada supports the view that the relation between law and claims to
supremacy is a contingent relation. So while our primary goals remain
the demonstration of the existence of entangled legality and argument
that entangled legality may be a good thing, our argument is of additional
interest to the extent that it has implications for the project of general
jurisprudence as an attempt to develop an explanation of law capable of
scoping over all instances, without limitation to the post-Westphalian
state which has dominated so much discussion at least since the initial
1961 publication of The Concept of Law.
4
Ibid., p. 249 (emphasis added).
5
J. Raz, The Authority of Law, 2nd ed. (Oxford University Press, 2009), p. 118.
6
Ibid., p. 104.
7
See, e.g., A. Marmor, Positive Law and Objective Values (Oxford University Press, 2001),
p. 40; and B. Tamanaha, A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society (Oxford University
Press, 2001), p. 140.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The utility and limitations of the supremacy claim are usefully
explored in application of the claim to explain the Canadian context in
both historic perspective, and as new evidence shows Canadian adoption
of something other than a supremacy claim in the self-conception of the
Canadian legal system and the Canadian polity. Claims of supremacy
have certainly been prominent, but now seem to be withdrawn in certain
instances with regards to some Indigenous peoples, creating an explana-
tory demand unmet by the supremacy claim. Let us set out an outline of
the historical presence of the supremacy claim, in preparation for dem-
onstration of its recent retreat.
The supremacy claim has (at least) three dimensions, divided
as follows.
Supremacy of norms. Like other sovereign states, at the foundation of
the Canadian legal system is a unitary constitution, first the Constitution
Act, 1867, now the Constitution Act, 1982. And like other state consti-
tutions, the Constitution Act, 1982 contains a common supremacy
clause. Section 52(1) reads: ‘The Constitution of Canada is the supreme
law of Canada, and any law that is inconsistent with the provisions of the
Constitution is, to the extent of the inconsistency, of no force or effect.’8
There is of course more than just constitutional law in Canada: there is
federal law and regulation, provincial law and regulation, and judicial
precedents. Yet these all occupy a particular place in the hierarchy of
norms in Canada, with constitutional law serving as the top-down source
of validity or authorization for all other types of law. The supremacy
claim of the Canadian constitution, and its associated hierarchy of
sources of law, is readily observable. John Borrows, for example, recounts
the first time he encountered the idea of hierarchy as a law student in
Canada:
I remember my property law professor telling me that all laws had to be
consistent with the Constitution Acts to be valid. Then we were told that
below the Constitution were parliamentary or legislative enactments,
which were greater in authority than common law pronouncements made
by judges. Underneath these sources came law’s subsidiary origins, such
as parliamentary privilege, the royal prerogative, particularly persuasive
published commentaries, followed finally by customs and conventions.
This pattern for organizing the sources of Canadian law is evident in
many of today’s legal textbooks. I could not help but notice that custom
8
The Constitution Act, 1982, section 52, https://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/const/page-16
.html#docCont.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
was at the bottom of Canada’s legal structure, and that custom was the
kind of law Indigenous peoples were presumed to have, if they were
regarded as having any law at all.9
9
J. Borrows, Canada’s Indigenous Constitution (University of Toronto Press, 2010), p. 13.
10
See The Constitution Act, 1982.
11
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the Supreme Court of Canada is of course to view Indigenous rights
through a lens which presumes the underlying supremacy of that court
and the legal order it implements, and moreover, lacks the institutional
means to interrogate or vary this presumption. The force of this pre-
sumption is usefully emphasized by Patricia Monture-Angus:
There is an insurmountable problem in taking Aboriginal claims to
territory before the courts. Courts owe their creation to the fact of
Canadian sovereignty. They cannot question that sovereignty because,
to find it wanting would in fact dis-establish their own legitimacy.
Without legitimate claim and control over territory, the international
definition of sovereignty collapses.12
12
P. Monture-Angus, Journeying Forward: Dreaming First Nations’ Independence
(Fernwood Publishing, 1999), p. 65 (internal notes omitted).
13
A. Mills, ‘What Is a Treaty? On Contract and Mutual Aid’, in J. Borrows and M. Coyle
(eds), The Right Relationship: Reimagining the Implementation of Historical Treaties
(University of Toronto Press, 2017), pp. 223–4 (internal notes omitted, original
emphasis).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
lawyers, that this ‘Indian sovereignty argument challenges the basic con-
stitutional framework of Canada,’ was probably fair, in the sense that the
Aboriginal sovereignty claim was made against, not under or pursuant to,
the Constitution of Canada . . . Often Indigenous claimants . . . invoke
international law as well as the laws of their Indigenous nation against the
validity of the Canadian state. In general, judges respond to existential
threat cases by quickly denying the claims, often by citing the sovereignty-
without-a-doubt passage from Sparrow and/or the act of state doctrine.14
While the Supreme Court of Canada and other Canadian courts have on
occasion questioned their jurisdiction to hear certain disputes, and
sometimes refuse to offer judgements or opinions on issues they find
not (or not yet) justiciable, there is entirely unsurprisingly little historical
indication that courts conceived of themselves as institutionally able to
question their general legitimacy as institutions of the sovereign
Canadian state.15 Yet as sometimes happens in social affairs, a sea change
in attitudes and eventually practice has occurred in recent years, for
various reasons beyond easy traceability, but with significant effects.16
For example, in a 2014 decision then Chief Justice McLachlin of the
Supreme Court wrote this about the test for establishing Aboriginal title
to land:
what is required is a culturally sensitive approach to sufficiency of occu-
pation based on the dual perspectives of the Aboriginal group in ques-
tion – its laws, practices, size, technological ability and the character of the
land claimed – and the common law notion of possession as a basis for
title. It is not possible to list every indicia of occupation that might apply
in a particular case. The common law test for possession – which requires
an intention to occupy or hold land for the purposes of the occupant –
must be considered alongside the perspective of the Aboriginal group
which, depending on its size and manner of living, might conceive of
possession of land in a somewhat different manner than did the common
law.17
14
M. D. Walters, ‘“Looking for a Knot in the Bulrush”: Reflections on Law, Sovereignty, and
Aboriginal Rights’, in P. Macklem and D. Sanderson (eds), From Recognition to
Reconciliation: Essays on the Constitutional Entrenchment of Aboriginal and Treaty
Rights (University of Toronto Press, 2016), pp. 54–5 (author’s notes omitted).
15
Even more unlikely would be to find acknowledgment by the Supreme Court of Canada
(or any other Canadian court) that its authority to decide disputes regarding the status
and nature of Indigenous rights depends on delegation or recognition by First Nations.
16
Among these causes it is worth identifying the work of the Truth and Reconciliation
Commission emerging from an inquiry into residential schools in Canada. See generally:
www.trc.ca/about-us/our-mandate.html.
17
Tsilhqot’in Nation v. British Columbia [2014] 2 S.C.R. 256.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Consideration of the ‘dual perspectives’ of Aboriginal groups and the
common law when establishing title is a marked change from the Indian
Act and earlier Aboriginal title decisions, but it still presumes that
authority to make binding decisions regarding Aboriginal title rests with
state courts and institutions, not Aboriginal ones. It is nonetheless clear
that the demand for judgement incorporating ‘dual perspectives’ is the
foundation of not just recognition of de facto entanglement, but choice of
entanglement in the growth of the body of constitutional norms.
Supremacy of force. A further characteristic claim of legal systems of
sovereign states, found hand in hand with claims of supremacy of norms
and supremacy of institutions, is the claim to a monopoly on the lawful
use of force. The Supreme Court of Canada has expressed this dimension
of the Canadian supremacy claim in the course of identifying limits to
Aboriginal rights in its 2001 decision Mitchell v. M.N.R.:
Canadian sovereign authority has, as one of its inherent characteristics, a
monopoly on the lawful use of military force within its territory. I do not
accept that the Mohawks could acquire under s. 35(1) a legal right to
deploy a military force in what is now Canada, as and when they choose
to do so, even if the warrior tradition was to be considered a defining
feature of pre-contact Mohawk society. Section 35(1) should not be
interpreted to throw on the Crown the burden of demonstrating subse-
quent extinguishment by ‘clear and plain’ measures [. . .] of a ‘right’ to
organize a private army, or a requirement to justify such a limitation after
1982 under the Sparrow standard. This example, remote as it is from the
particular claim advanced in this case, usefully illustrates the principled
limitation flowing from sovereign incompatibility in the s. 35(1)
analysis.18
18
Mitchell v. M.N.R. [2001] 1. S.C.R. 911, para. 153 (original emphasis).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
to authority in fact generally accepted and practised by the society with
which the legal system exists in an intimate relationship. In a relatively
durable system such as that found in Canada, supremacy claims are
generally accepted, as when provincial and federal governments accept
the supremacy of constitutional law over their legislative acts (e.g. where
courts strike down some legislative provision citing violation of a
Canadian Charter right or provision), or when the police cede authority
to the military over the use of force in times of emergency or martial rule.
In other instances, claims to supremacy can be rejected in ways that are
not readily explained as mere rule-breaking, or as attempts at revolution
resulting in the dissolution of the state. Rejection of claims of supremacy
of the Canadian legal system by Indigenous peoples are easily found, in
contexts of entanglement where durable models for social life are sought
beyond the discourse available in a supremacy-presuming state and
peoples subject to its supremacy claim. For example, in This Is Not a
Peace Pipe, Dale Turner begins with the following observations about the
legal status of Aboriginal rights in Canada:
Aboriginal rights, as constitutional rights, are still developing in law;
that said, one important principle is now embedded in Canadian
law and politics: the meaning and content of Aboriginal rights is
expressed in the legal and political discourses of the Canadian state, and
therefore Aboriginal rights exist or have legitimacy only within the
Canadian state [. . .] But many Aboriginal peoples do not understand
their rights in terms that are amenable to the state’s legal and political
discourses. This is because many Aboriginal peoples do not perceive the
political relationship as one of subservience; that is, they do not view their
rights as somehow legitimated by the Canadian state. Rather, many
Aboriginal peoples understand the political relationship as one of ‘nation
to nation’.19
19
D. Turner, This Is Not a Peace Pipe: Towards a Critical Indigenous Philosophy (University
of Toronto Press, 2006), pp. 3–4 (original emphasis).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘peace, friendship, and respect’20 and serves to constitute the relationship
and standing between Indigenous peoples and settlers:
One reason why the Two Row Wampum is useful for a kind of ‘pan-
indigenous’ political thinking is that it demonstrates that European
nations became nations because of the forms of political recognition the
Iroquois bestowed on them. The kind of nationhood that remains embed-
ded in Iroquois has retained its normative force throughout the historical
relationship. This supports McNeil and Borrows’s thesis that the
Canadian legal system has gained its legitimacy by virtue of indigenous
law.21
20
On the origins of the Guswentha or Two Row Wampum, see Turner, This Is Not a Peace
Pipe, p. 48, quoting Grand Chief Michael Mitchell of Akwesane.
21
Ibid., pp. 54–5 (original emphasis).
22
See J. Borrows, ‘Constitutional Law from a First Nation Perspective: Self-government and
the Royal Proclamation’ (1994) 28 University of British Columbia Law Review 1–47; J.
Borrows, ‘Canada’s Colonial Constitution’, in J. Borrows and M. Coyle (eds), The Right
Relationship: Reimagining the Implementation of Historical Treaties (University of
Toronto Press, 2017), pp. 17–38; J. Borrows, Recovering Canada: The Resurgence of
Indigenous Law (University of Toronto Press, 2002); and J. Borrows, Freedom and
Indigenous Constitutionalism (University of Toronto Press, 2016).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
substantially displaced Indigenous peoples. There is nonetheless room in
the content of the Canadian legal system’s self-conception for a return to
a collaborative, entangled stance with respect to Indigenous legal orders,
warranting further attention to past and present conditions of engage-
ment between Canadian and Indigenous legal orders.
Borrows’ work is again instructive. In light of the Supreme Court’s
acknowledgement of the need for a ‘dual perspective’, we can ask the
question of what, from a First Nations perspective, gives treaties between
Indigenous peoples and settler peoples their validity, which sets terms for
engagement and perhaps entanglement. Borrows notes that for many
Indigenous peoples, there is an important idea of sacred law: ‘Laws can
be regarded as sacred if they stem from the Creator, creation stories or
revered ancient teachings that have withstood the test of time. When laws
exist within these categories they are often given the highest respect.’23
Sacred laws, then, as supreme laws or laws deserving the highest respect,
can serve as the source of validity for treaties. Borrows explains how this
view can be found regarding treaties signed in parts of Western Canada:
I encountered this view when working with Elders in Saskatchewan. They
spoke of their treaties as being sacred because they brought Canada into
existence within their territories [. . .] In listening to the Elders speak
about the meanings of these legally binding promises, it was clear that
they regarded the treaty as flowing from a sacred source. They did not rely
on the written text of the treaty to arrive at this conclusion. Because First
Nations followed their own legal traditions in creating treaties, their
interpretation was that treaties were made with the Creator as well as
the Crown.24
As Borrows explains, however, the Creator and Crown are not on equal
footing in this respect. The Crown, much like Indigenous peoples, is
subject to the laws of the Creator, who is supreme. Borrows quotes one
particular Elder:
It was the will of the Creator that the White man would come to live with
us, among us, to share our lives together with him, and also both of us
collectively to benefit from bounty of Mother Earth for all time to come
[. . .] Just like the treaty, that’s what it is, one law was given, Indian and
white, we both gave something special, something to keep, something to
reverence, just like the treaty, both Indian and white beneficiaries, we were
23
Borrows, Canada’s Indigenous Constitution, p. 24.
24
Ibid., pp. 25–6.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
given a gift from the Creator. The Creator owns us, he is still the boss,
nothing is hidden.25
25
Ibid., p. 26.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
and friendship, which would honour First Nations’ ownership of land
and self-government.26 The Royal Proclamation, in this sense, was
understood by First Nations to be a kind of sovereignty-protecting
international treaty. This understanding and relationship was threatened,
as many First Nations believed, by the Constitution Act, 1867, as well as
the subsequent patriation of the constitution to include a domestic
amending formula:
For most Canadians, the lack of a domestic amending formula led them to
seek constitutional reform in 1927, 1931, 1935–6, 1950, 1960–1, and 1964.
Indigenous peoples were not part of these efforts, because they were not
invited, and may not have even been interested had such an invitation been
extended. As noted, many Indigenous people regarded the Queen as their
ally and the Canadian state as their oppressor and thus saw domestication
as a great political and legal evil. The substitution of the Canadian state for
the British Crown would not have been regarded as a positive development.
This fact has led many Indigenous peoples through the years to declare that
they possessed or desired a stronger constitutional relationship with Britain,
as opposed to a diminished one. When the British (rather than the
Canadian) Crown was regarded as their partner, a nation-to-nation rela-
tionship with the British Crown made greater political sense.27
26
Borrows, ‘Constitutional Law from a First Nation Perspective’. Many First Nations
continue to make reference to the Royal Proclamation of 1763 in their claims. For
example, the Kingsclear First Nation cites the Royal Proclamation as law protecting their
rights to land which was violated on several occasions throughout their history in what is
now New Brunswick. See www.kingsclear.ca/about/history/.
27
Borrows, Freedom and Indigenous Constitutionalism, p. 114. See also Borrows, Canada’s
Indigenous Constitution, pp. 26–7. For comparison, in New Zealand, renewed respect for
the Treaty of Waitangi of 1840 began and has continued to grow since 1986, when the
state introduced the first of several legislative acts recognizing the Treaty as a source of
law in New Zealand. For an account of some of the similarities and differences in
Indigenous–settler relations between Canada and New Zealand, see J. Ruru,
‘Constitutional Indigenous Jurisprudence in Aotearoa, New Zealand’, in P. Macklem
and D. Sanderson (eds), From Recognition to Reconciliation, pp. 415–48.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
by the Gus-Wen-The or Two Row Wampum. There is a bed of white
wampum which symbolizes the purity of the agreement. There are two
rows of purple, and those rows have the spirit of your ancestors and mine.
There are three beads of wampum separating the two rows and they
symbolize peace, friendship, and respect.
These two rows symbolize two paths or vessels, traveling down the same
rivers together. One, a birch bark canoe, will be for the Indian people,
their laws, their customs, their ways. The other, a ship, will be for the
white people and their laws, their customs and their ways. We shall each
travel the river together, side by side, but in our own boat. Neither of us
will try to steer the other’s vessel.
The principles of the Two Row Wampum became the basis for all treaties
and agreements that were made with the Europeans and later the
Americans.28
28
Turner, This Is Not a Peace Pipe, p. 48 (internal notes omitted). See also Mitchell
v. M.N.R., paras 127–30. Also valuable on the importance of such an understanding of
state-settler relations is J. Tully, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of
Diversity (Cambridge University Press, 1995). Tully does not examine the relations
through the lens of the concept of legal system, but his account of the difference between
ancient constitutionalism, modern constitutionalism and contemporary constitutional-
ism offers a nice parallel.
29
See, for example, the Letter of Understanding between the Tsilhqot’in Nation and the
Government of British Columbia (2014), www.tsilhqotin.ca/Portals/0/PDFs/LOU_
Tsilhqotin_BC.pdf; the Letter of Understanding between the Tsilhqot’in Nation and the
Government of Canada (2017), www.tsilhqotin.ca/Portals/0/PDFs/Press%20Releases/
2017_01_27_Tsilhqotin_Canada_LOU.pdf; Kunst’aa guu – Kunst’aayah Reconciliation
Protocol, signed between the government of British Columbia and the Haida Nation
(2009), www.haidanation.ca/wp-content/uploads/2017/03/Kunstaa-guu_Kunstaayah_
Agreement.pdf; and the Shíshálh Government-to-Government Agreement (2018),
www2.gov.bc.ca/assets/gov/environment/natural-resource-stewardship/consulting-with-
first-nations/agreements/shishalh_g2g_2016–06–21_final_-_public.pdf.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
are quite recent, so have yet to be seen in full operation, but an early
framework agreement and subsequent legislation and practice provide a
good illustration of the way in which state and First Nations relations are
evolving. The Framework Agreement on First Nation Land Management
was created in 1996 and signed by the government of Canada and
thirteen First Nations, and is expressly characterized as a ‘government-
to-government’ agreement.30 The central purpose of the Framework
Agreement is to allow ‘First Nations to opt out of the land management
sections of the Indian Act and take over responsibility for the manage-
ment and control of their reserve lands and resources’.31 As its name
suggests, the Framework Agreement has since served as a framework and
source of law for both the government of Canada as well as First Nations:
Canada enacted the First Nations Land Management Act (FNLMA), as
part of its obligation to ratify the Framework Agreement. It was given
royal assent on June 17, 1999. The FNLMA brought into effect the terms
and conditions agreed to in the Framework Agreement. It is the
Framework Agreement that is actively being implemented by First
Nations and Canada.32
30
See a news release here: https://labrc.com/framework-agreement/, and the full text of the
agreement here: https://labrc.com/wp-content/uploads/2016/08/FA-current-to-2013.pdf.
31
See https://labrc.com/framework-agreement/. At the beginning of 2019, 153 First Nations
already had their own land codes or were actively developing them. See: www.aadnc-
aandc.gc.ca/eng/1327090675492/1327090738973.
32
See https://labrc.com/framework-agreement/.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
What makes the Framework Agreement, together with the First
Nations Land Management Act and the many First Nations land codes
now in operation, an example of entangled legalities, and why is it
important to understand the social situation in this way? It might be
tempting to suppose that First Nations gaining greater control over
management of their lands, which also includes the authority to create
a range of criminal offences,33 authority which has historically been held
in Canada by the federal government alone, represents a step towards
independence of the sovereign state kind. If this were true, then we would
not have an instance of entangled legalities but perhaps some form of
secession then treaty under international law. However, under arrange-
ments such as the Framework Agreement, fragmentation into several
sovereign states within Canada is not contemplated. Rather, what is
sought are forms of self-government which depend on mutual recogni-
tion and thick intermingling of norms and institutions from diverse
sources of ultimate authority. A recent case provides a good illustration.
The K’omoks First Nation in British Columbia created their own land
code in 2016 in accordance with the Framework Agreement and the First
Nations Land Management Act. Section 31.1 of their land code reads:
‘Any person who resides on, enters or remains on KFN [K’omoks First
Nation] lands other than in accordance with a residence or access right
under this Land Code or under a Law is guilty of an offence.’34 Two non-
K’omoks First Nation renters, Thordarson and Sorbie, had failed to pay
their rent for several months on a property on K’omoks First Nation
lands, and after having been given formal notice to vacate by the
K’omoks First Nation, did not leave the premises. They were then
considered trespassers by the K’omoks First Nation and guilty of an
offence under the Land Code. As the Provincial Court of British
Columbia recounts, the K’omoks First Nation requested assistance from
the Provincial Prosecution Service and Federal Crown, a provincial insti-
tution and federal institution respectively, to help in prosecuting and
enforcing the laws of the K’omoks First Nation Land Code, since the
Land Code, in accordance with the Framework Agreement, makes refer-
ence to the Canadian Criminal Code, a federal statute, as establishing the
process for prosecuting the range of criminal offences created in the
33
Section 22 of the First Nations Land Management Act, https://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/
acts/f-11.8/page-4.html#docCont.
34
K’omoks First Nation v. Thordarson and Sorbie [2018] BCPC 114, www.canlii.org/en/bc/
bcpc/doc/2018/2018bcpc114/2018bcpc114.html.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
K’omoks First Nation Land Code. However, ‘both the Provincial
Prosecution Service and Crown Federal have declined to assist
K’omoks’.35 The court writes:
This leaves the K’omoks First Nations in a situation where their case must
be pursued under 22[3] [a] [of the First Nations Land Management Act].
The Band has a law on the books that may give relief from trespass, by
way of a court order, but no ability to enforce the law without the
cooperation of authorities outside the Band, unless it assumes the burden
of prosecution.
K’omoks First Nations, therefore, has applied to this Court pursuant to
s.508 of the Criminal Code for what has been deemed as a private
prosecution or prosecution by the Band. That section of the Criminal
Code provides a justice who receives information laid under s.505 shall
hear and consider ex parte the allegations of the informant and the
evidence of witnesses where he considers it desirable to do so.36
35
K’omoks First Nation v. Thordarson and Sorbie, para. 15.
36
Ibid., paras 16–17.
37
For news coverage of the case, see B. Lindsay, ‘They Did It “Their Own Damn Selves”:
First Nation Wins Unusual Bid to Evict Bad Tenants’, CBC News (8 October 2018), www
.cbc.ca/news/canada/british-columbia/they-did-it-their-own-damn-selves-first-nation-
wins-unusual-bid-to-evict-bad-tenants-1.4852788.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
assumed and so created the power itself. If we keep in mind as well that
criminal offences are typically considered to be the most serious forms of
voluntary wrongdoing, which therefore concern not just individual
victims but political communities in their entirety, then assumption of
the power to prosecute can easily be understood as assumption of a
public power to address issues which are not merely of a private nature.
Recognition by state courts of such a power might then be much more
than simply toleration of a private exercise of power by federal and
provincial courts; it might be part of the mutual recognition by state
and Indigenous authorities to share in the creation, application and
enforcement of criminal law, which was once within the sole purview
of the federal government but no longer.
The details of the K’omoks case show, we suggest, that it is implausible
to see First Nations law and state law (provincial and federal) as repre-
senting distinct legal systems, operating independently at the level of
both norms and institutions. The entanglement is unmistakable. The
ultimate source of law and authority of First Nations land codes such
as the K’omoks First Nation Land Code is shared between First Nations
and the federal government by virtue of the Framework Agreement. And
at the level of application and enforcement of law, norms sourced in
First Nations law as well as federal law coexist and complement each
other, and institutions from both the K’omoks First Nation and state
government (e.g. provincial courts) are envisioned in a relationship of
coordination and assistance. Thordarson and Sorbie might become a
precedent-setting case, and likely one which establishes some of the
relations of entanglement required for First Nations law and state law,
as well as their respective institutions, to coexist and operate
within Canada.
Still, one might object, why could we not understand the relation
between the state and First Nations, in instances such as those presented
in Thordarson and Sorbie, as distinct but interacting legal systems, much
like some claim we see in the European Union where there are long-
standing rival supremacy claims made between member state courts and
the Court of Justice of the European Union on behalf of their respective
legal orders?38 To see why, we must remember from earlier discussion
that to be a legal system requires a distinctive claim to supremacy over all
other legal and normative orders in the same social space, as the ultimate
38
See, e.g., N. MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation in the
European Commonwealth (Oxford University Press, 1999), chapter 7.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
foundation for all other applicable law, and this is precisely what is
missing in the interaction between state and First Nation institutions
regarding First Nation land codes. The foundation of such land codes is
the Framework Agreement, a government-to-government framework of
mutual understanding and recognition between the federal government
and First Nation governments. In broader terms, as one of us elaborates
elsewhere,39 legal systems are social constructions, constructed out of the
beliefs, intentions, self-understandings and practices of relevant actors.
Supremacy claims are part of the beliefs, intentions, self-understandings
and practices of relevant actors for the creation and existence of legal
systems, so where these are absent, legal systems are absent as well. The
framework agreements, letters of understanding and reconciliation
protocols we find in Canada are evidence that, however incrementally,
the relevant beliefs, intentions, self-understandings and shared practices
of state institutions and First Nation institutions are moving away from
supremacy-claiming systematicity towards something else. Simply put,
we might be witnessing the social reconstruction of the character of legal
relations between the state and First Nations.
To bring the argument of this section full circle, even while further
coordination is required to manage the entanglement, for First Nations
law and state law to coexist, all that is required is mutual recognition of
each other’s legal orders. Claims of one order to supremacy over the
other are neither necessary nor inevitable as a matter of social fact
regarding the existence of law in the durable alignment and intimate
relationship between law and society most familiar from the life of the
sovereign state. And as we have seen, claims of supremacy, and in
particular claims of supremacy made by state institutions over First
Nations institutions, would only act as political obstacles to shared goals
of reconciliation and partnership.
39
See M. Giudice, Social Construction of Law: Potential and Limits (Edward Elgar, 2020).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
state-based form) for thinking about law in general, and more particu-
larly the relations between legal orders.40 In previous work we have
developed what we call an ‘inter-institutional view of legality’ amplifying
themes found in Neil MacCormick’s work on institutional normative
order. The inter-institutional view is particularly useful for the explan-
ation of relations between Canadian state institutions and First Nations
legal institutions. The primary descriptive-explanatory benefit of our
view lies in its showing how relations of mutual reference can arise
between institutions within and across legal orders, operating in ways
that need not be viewed as carrying implicit or explicit supremacy
competitions as part of their purpose or function. Relations of mutual
reference, whether codified in law or formal agreements, or simply found
as a matter of social practice, may of course take the form and character
of hierarchical relations of supremacy and comprehensiveness; but it is
also possible for them to take the form and character of horizontal
relations of partnership or shared governance, as we have seen in the
case of Canada–First Nations relations. The actual form and character of
relations of mutual reference, in other words, is variable, and contingent
upon the particular ways in which social groups intend, practice and
understand – that is, socially construct – their relations to each other.
The inter-institutional view is designed as a morally neutral
descriptive-explanatory view of law, and as such, its possibility and
success as a conceptual view of law stands or falls on its success in
explaining in general terms (i.e. across as wide a range of contexts as
possible) the social fact existence of law (including the existence of legal
order between legal orders) wherever and whenever it exists. That said, if
such a view is successful on descriptive-explanatory grounds, its adoption
in practice may identify political options or possibilities of a morally
desirable nature which might otherwise remain hidden from view under
prevailing conceptual understandings, such as the understanding of law
which ties it squarely to the idea of a state-based legal system. As we have
seen in the context of Canada, where there is a politically desired goal of
reconciliation between settler and Indigenous peoples, the inter-
institutional view seems superior to the state system-centred view in
making visible and characterizing a form of non-dominating, non-hier-
archical relationship between legal orders. This reconceptualizing will not
of course solve all legal, political, moral and economic problems, but it
40
See again, Culver and Giudice, Legality’s Borders and Culver and Giudice, The
Unsteady State.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
&
has the potential to address one particular challenge of reconciliation
identified by Borrows, Turner and many others: the challenge of recon-
ceiving the status of Indigenous peoples and their legal orders as some-
thing other than subordinate to the comprehensive and supreme
Canadian legal system.41 The inter-institutional view of law may be a
particularly useful precursor or accompaniment to politically viable
reconciliation between Canada and First Nations.
Relations of mutual reference between institutions are also a particu-
larly helpful tool for detecting the emergence of new legal orders, espe-
cially in contexts where there is a plurality of entangled sources of law. In
the Canadian context, we might be witnessing a shift away from recog-
nition of a unitary constitution and towards a plurality of constitutional
sources.42 Since Confederation in 1867, the Constitution Act, 1867, then
the Constitution Act, 1982, have served as the unitary Constitution of
Canada. Yet if the socially accepted relations of mutual reference expand
to include various foundational framework agreements, letters of under-
standing and the Royal Proclamation of 1763, these ultimate sources of
rights and obligations might reasonably be viewed as constitutional
moments, and so new (or revived) constitutional sources of law and
authority. Unitary constitutions might be the ideal in some circum-
stances, but perhaps not so in others. Relations of mutual reference,
which might follow existing, established law or might not, can be seen
to have a kind of reconstitutional power if they occur at a basic, founda-
tional level. Such reconstitutional power might not only be possible but
highly desirable in some contexts.
Clearly, much remains to be done to specify how the inter-institutional
view works as an alternative to system- or supremacy-centred views in
particular contexts, including state–First Nations relations in Canada.
This is not our aim here, as we aimed to demonstrate only the existence
41
We also hope we are not read as supposing that such reconceptualization will be easy or
straightforward. Like other social constructions, such as those of race, gender and
disability, altering the social construction of law in Canada, beyond the handful of
examples identified in this chapter, is likely to be slow and difficult, if it is accomplished
at all. In general, the inter-institutional view is not a dominant, prevailing view. It is a
mostly revisionary view.
42
For sophisticated accounts of the nature and value of constitutional pluralism in a variety
of contexts, see MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty; N. Walker, ‘The Idea of
Constitutional Pluralism’ (2002) 65 Modern Law Review 317–59; and N. Krisch,
Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law (Oxford
University Press, 2010).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of entanglement and its desirability in some circumstances, and in that
context articulate a broader lesson regarding the contingency of the
system- or supremacy-centred view and the consequent importance of
exploring alternative explanations such as that offered by our inter-
institutional view. We plan to continue this line of argument in future
work. What does remain to be done here is to return to the organizing
theme of legal entanglement.
A system-centred concept of law is one way of characterizing relations
between multiple legal orders, so setting the basic terms of entanglement
as ones of hierarchy, supremacy and delegation. As we have demon-
strated, however, the system-centred concept represents one choice of
explanation among others. In particular contexts, such as that of Canada,
the choice of a system-centred concept may pose an obstacle to both the
explanation of changes occurring in an evolving constitution and its
relation to adjacent legal orders, and a further obstacle to an imaginative
exploration of ways to achieve particular political objectives such as
recognition and reconciliation between state institutions and
Indigenous peoples. Exploration and development of basic terms of
entanglement of mutual reference, partnership and non-hierarchical
shared authority is therefore important not only as a tool for successful
descriptive-explanation of the range of possible social facts comprising
law, but also for surfacing conceptual choices which might assist in
achieving morally desirable political objectives. We followed in detail
one instance of legal entanglement in the example of application and
enforcement of a First Nation land code, finding in this example the
elements of a new, positively entangled First Nations–state relation
showing the possibility of durable coexistence in an era of ‘nation-to-
nation’ or ‘government-to-government’ partnerships. Throughout our
exploration of legal system, entangled legality and evolving state–First
Nations relations, we have shown that there is choice in how to present,
understand and reconceive foundational state–First Nations relations.
This is a choice about the basic terms of legal entanglement, the basic
terms about how relations among legal orders of different communities
and cultures are to be characterized and practised, ahead of and during
the task of working out the particular ways in which norms and insti-
tutions will interact and mutually refer to each other.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
15
Entangled Hopes
Towards Relational Coherence
I would like to express my gratitude to Laura Affolter, Keebet von Benda-Beckmann and
Angela Lindt with whom discussing the questions raised in this article has been inspiring,
illuminating and enriching.
1
See Chapter 1, Section 1.2.
2
J. Eckert, ‘What Is the Context in “Law in Context”?’, in S. P. Donlan and L. Heckendorn
(eds), Concepts of Law: Comparative, Jurisprudential, and Social Science Perspectives
(Ashgate, 2014), pp. 225–36.
3
This is the case in some fields of law more than in others, and in some areas of the world
and for some people more than for others: Since state sovereignty and autonomy take
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Among the diverse processes that lead to an increasing entangle-
ment of laws in the current global situation as sketched out in
Chapter 1, I am here concerned with one specific movement of
entanglement, namely the way in which law is entangled by its
mobilizations in local social struggles. In a world in which ideas of
justice, rights and entitlements circulate among people far apart and
concerned with very different problems, people perceive themselves
to be in situations comparable to those of others and shaped by
similar forces. Such struggles have regularly invoked norms from
international conventions and from hitherto unrelated bodies of law
such as environmental law, trade law and human rights or consti-
tutional law. They have referred to presumed precedents from other
situations and claim that norms from different jurisdictions and
various bodies of law are applicable to their concerns. They hold
accountable actors far removed from the occurrences in question,
but who are, in their reasoning, deeply implicated in the conflicts at
issue. Last but not least, they mobilize norms not hitherto incorpor-
ated into state law or international law – moral norms or those
stemming from other (non-state) normative orders – and ‘translate’
them into the available legal instruments.
With these mobilizations, new possibilities for negotiation and the
pursuit of legal rights are being sought.4 Evocations of other norms
may be strategic, as they mostly are when activist lawyers campaign to
have certain interpretations of harms be heard, such as when they claim
that damage to the environment amounts to a violation of the human
rights of those affected in their health or livelihoods by environmental
degradation, and when they advocate specific avenues of redress.
contrasting forms in different regions of the world, people are subjected to varying bodies
of law and different constellations of legal entanglement, some being more directly
impacted by various international norms than those who happen to live in parts of the
world that are governed by clear rules of subsidiarity. See T. Bierschenk, ‘Sedimentation,
Fragmentation and Normative Double-Binds in (West) African Public Services’, in T.
Bierschenk and J.-P. Olivier de Sardan (eds), States at Work: Dynamics of African
Bureaucracies (Brill, 2014), pp. 221–45; L. Eslava, Local Space, Global Life: The Everyday
of International Law and Development (Cambridge University Press, 2015), p. 258.
4
K. von Benda-Beckmann, ‘The Contexts of Law’, XIIIth International Congress of the
Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism: ‘Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law in
Social, Economic and Political Development’, Chiang Mai, Thailand (9–13 April 2002),
p. 3. PDF on file with the author.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Evocations of other norms might also result from lay views of rights that
do not differentiate between different systems of law and are oblivious to
the origin of a norm in a specific system, assuming a general validity of
the legal norms that promise rights.5 Their hopes in law make broad
comparisons about what is to be treated as – structurally – the same in
cases far apart and located in multiple jurisdictions, and by making
claims about the comparability of such cases they seek access to norms
that promise rights. They operate by ignoring – strategically or idealistic-
ally – any boundaries between systems or bodies of law, be they jurisdic-
tional or material, and furthermore, they interpret such bodies and
systems of law in the light of moral norms which give them a particular
content. ‘Often enough, these linkages may connect individual norms,
rather than “bodies” of norms as such, thus taking us yet further away
from the notion of closed systems’ writes Nico Krisch in Chapter 1,6 and
we can see in these mobilizations of law ‘from below’ what he calls ‘the
trans-systemic, networked character of law’ emerging.7
These entangling mobilizations of law ‘from below’ often occur in
highly asymmetrical relations; they concern, in particular, struggles
around human rights violations and the destruction of the environment
along the long global chains of value production. I argue that because
they mobilize law in such asymmetrical relations against more powerful
adversaries, their entanglements of law most often strive – implicitly – for
a trans-systemic coherence. Entanglement stops short of integration, as
Nico Krisch explains. I would argue that the moves towards normative
relationality that these mobilizations of law from below engage in are
moves to overcome the boundaries around legal systems and bodies of
law and towards a trans-systemic and unsystematic coherence. Their end
is not integration in a systemic sense; in fact, they do not bother with
systematicity, but operate with fluid relations between existing norms.
Moreover, these moves are concurrent with moves towards the
5
J. Eckert, B. Donahoe, C. Strümpell and Z.Ö. Biner, ‘Introduction: Laws Travels and
Transformations’, in J. Eckert, B. Donahoe, C. Strümpell and Z.Ö. Biner (eds), Law against
the State: Ethnographic Forays into Law’s Transformations (Cambridge University Press,
2012), pp. 1–22, at p. 3.
6
See Chapter 1, Section 1.6.2.
7
B. de Sousa Santos and C. A. Rodríguez-Garavito, ‘Law, Politics and the Subaltern in
Counter-Hegemonic Globalisation’, in B. de Sousa Santos and C. A. Rodríguez-Garavito
(eds), Law and Globalisation from Below: Towards a Cosmopolitan Legality (Cambridge
University Press, 2005), pp. 1–26.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
‘distancing’ of legal orders and bodies of law, or their entanglement along
different lines – what could be called ‘counter-entanglements’.
However, at the same time that we see the plurality of legal orders
moving into such fluid and dynamic relations of conversation, entangle-
ment and distancing, we can also observe a tendency in law towards a
particularization, or rather ‘singularization’, that not only distances nor-
mative orders from each other, but disentangles law. As in the case of
entanglements, this is also a desystematization, but one that proceeds
through the treatment of individual cases as singular. There appears to be
a broader tendency in dispute resolution away from seeing the general
norm in the particular case and towards treating incidents and constella-
tions as solitary. This is evident most prominently in procedures such as
arbitration, out-of-court settlements and alternative dispute resolution.
These all focus on the specific circumstances of a single case, and the
unique constellation of parties concerned, and aim at an agreement
between those involved, rather than finding solutions according to a
general norm. Even though the procedural norms governing these prac-
tices of singularization might become more alike, given that forms of
arbitration and mediation are standardized and subject to increasing
professionalization, cases are treated in their singularity. This might
indicate an incremental but fundamental transformation in law that
coincides with increasing entanglement, and counteracts it. In the
following, I try to understand this coincidence and the dynamics of
entanglement and disentanglement that ensue and which possibly pre-
vent the legal change that is sought by movements towards
relational coherence.
8
K. Pistor, The Code of Capital (Princeton University Press, 2019); C. Menke, Kritik der
Rechte (Suhrkamp, 2018).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
increasingly perceived by those concerned as crossing the boundaries of
jurisdictions and entangling us in fundamental interdependencies. In her
response to Bruno Latour’s assumption about the prolongation of actor
networks in modernity, she held that while the chains of interaction may
become ever longer in modernity, modern institutions of law cut these
chains at particularly short intervals. Strathern takes the example of
intellectual property rights,9 which privilege the ‘invention’ and the
inventor, rather than accounting for the endless chains of actions that
make a certain invention or innovation possible. She observes that many
‘traditional’ legal institutions take into account the sociality of property,
and therefore reflect to some degree the actor networks that produce
‘property’, while modern legal institutions quintessentially abstract from,
and thus disregard, these social relations.
From such an anthropological perspective, contemporary legal insti-
tutions could be said to ‘cut’ interdependent chains of action in several
ways: first, as addressed by Strathern, they perform specific cuts around
who is actually legally recognized to be a participant in the production of
a situation or event. Such cuts can also take other forms. Stuart Kirsch,
for example, when comparing the notions of liability that were raised by
different Melanesian groups with those raised by multinational com-
panies on the basis of scientifically established causal relationships, found
that Melanesians hold accountable those who have created the context
for a particular social interaction that has led to harm:
The underlying principle of liability [relies on the idea that] social net-
works link specific losses to the person(s) or agent(s) responsible for the
context (the road, the feast, the town) in which events occurred, regardless
of their separation in time or the actions of other agents in the interim. In
all of these claims, social networks are stretched to their logical limits.10
Such varying scopes of the social networks that are considered relevant
for an issue concern not only the question of who is considered to have
participated in bringing about a state of affairs, but also who can be
considered affected by it in law. Here, too, liberal law relies on a narrow
idea of who is personally affected and can thus appeal to law, and has
instituted only a few exceptions in the form of public interest litigation.
9
M. Strathern, ‘Cutting the Network’ (1996) 2(3) Journal of the Royal Anthropological
Institute 517–35. See also K. Pistor, The Code of Capital, on the issue of intellectual
property rights, particularly pp. 108–31, 211.
10
S. Kirsch, ‘Property Effects: Social Networks and Compensation Claims in Melanesia’
(2001) 9 Social Anthropology 147–63, at 155.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Second, there are cuts around the time of an event. The most promin-
ent temporal ‘cuts’ are forfeiture and limitation periods, which might
fundamentally jar with the temporality of the effects of a contested
action, the time of harm and suffering.11 There are also more basic cuts
in the temporal reach of law, which concern the narratives of when a
situation actually begins and how long it lasts. This leads us back to
Strathern’s concern with the cuts within actor networks, which are, of
course, also cuts in time.
The third set of cuts in liberal law are the ways that it separates
different fields of practice. Particularly in international law, different
bodies of law stand in relatively independent relations to each other,12
separating trade from human rights, labour law from ecological issues,
etc. More generally, the differentiation of various fields of law might not
be entirely congruent with the factual interdependence of the fields of
interaction that they regulate. Anthropologists have long questioned the
adequacy of descriptions of social differentiation as conceived by under-
standings of modernity based on differentiation theory, observing the
continuing interdependence of different fields of interaction even in what
are considered highly differentiated societies.13
These cuts of liberal law culminate in distinctions concerning what can
actually be addressed by legal measures, and between what is offered legal
protection and what is not. These might constitute the most pressing cuts
for the mobilizations of law from below, since such mobilizations address
precisely the specific distribution of rights and privileges provided by
current legal instruments. Human rights, for example, often the instru-
ment of entangling legal struggles, protect only some concrete, specific
individual rights. Although ‘poverty, racism, sexism, imperialism, colo-
nialism and exploitation’ might be considered to violate the freedom and
dignity of individuals,14 these are forms of suffering that today cannot be
addressed legally as injuries for which someone is liable. The loss of
livelihood, or of employment, for example, is regulated via insurance and
social welfare, or not at all, but is in most places not legally considered a
violation of individual rights, because myriad forms of dispossession are
11
D. Loher, ‘Everyday Suffering and the Abstract Time-Reckoning of Law’ (2020) 4 Journal
of Legal Anthropology 17–38.
12
Von Benda-Beckmann, ‘The Contexts of Law’, 4.
13
See, for example, T. Thelen and E. Alber (eds), Reconnecting (Modern) Statehood and
Kinship: Temporalities, Scales, Classifications (Pennsylvania University Press, 2018).
14
R. Cotterrell, Sociological Jurisprudence: Juristic Thought and Social Inquiry (Routledge,
2018), p. 150.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
legal. The fact that contemporary legal instruments rely at base on
subjective private rights15 makes for their inability to address what are
still called structural issues or ‘root causes’.16
These cuts are increasingly challenged by the mobilization of law ‘from
below’ when people apply existing legal norms to their situations and
entangle them with others, making claims that reinterpret and widen the
scope of the norms’ applicability to address the forms of suffering that
they experience. They address the perceived inadequacies of current legal
instruments to reflect the factual relations that shape our world and strive
for (legal) change by advocating relations between different normative
realms. Thus, the very legal norms that are in themselves inadequate to
reflect the situations of suffering because of the diverse cuts through
social relations in time and space that they entail are entangled in a way
that produces novel meanings. They propose novel normative interpret-
ations, thereby creating what Susanne Baer has called ‘legal trouble’,17
claiming what does not – yet – exist in dominant legal discourse and
hence opening up the possibility to think and speak it18 – and possibly
think and speak it into being.
15
Pistor, The Code of Capital.
16
S. Marks, ‘Human Rights and Root Causes’ (2001) 74 Modern Law Review 57–78. See also
D. Kennedy, ‘The International Human Rights Movement: Part of the Problem?’ (2002)
15 Harvard Human Rights Journal 101–26; S. Moyn, Not Enough: Human Rights in an
Unequal World (Harvard University Press, 2018), particularly pp. 173–222.
17
S. Baer, ‘Inexcitable Speech: Zum Rechtsverständnis postmoderner feministischer
Positionen am Beispiel Judith Butler’, in A. Hornscheidt, G. Jähnert and A. Schlichter
(eds), Kritische Differenzen – geteilte Perspektiven (Westdeutscher Verlag, 1998),
pp. 229–43.
18
See the arguments of Maksymilian del Mar on how legal imagination in legal fictions and
other forms of legal reasoning provide new possibilities of interpretation ‘hinting at the
possibility, perhaps even desirability [. . .] of introducing, more explicitly, a new rule in
the future’. See M. Mar, ‘Legal Reasoning in Pluralist Jurisprudence’, in N. Roughan and
A. Halpin (eds), In Pursuit of Pluralist Jurisprudence (Cambridge University Press, 2017),
pp. 40–63, at p. 51.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
responsibility in the long chains of ‘distributed agency’ across the globe.
The second type of contestation is over which norms actually apply to a
case. This often also contests the limits of what can be addressed legally
as a harm.
The field in which such struggles against the ‘cuts’ of liberal law are
possibly most evident is struggles around human rights violations and
environmental damages along the long global chains of value production.
The transnational lawsuits brought by people affected by harm resulting
from the activities of multinational corporations concern the question of
who is to bear responsibility for this harm.19 Such transnational lawsuits
first attempt to expand the scope of responsibility from the person on the
ground, whose actions directly lead to harm, to the headquarters of
multinational companies. This move raises the question of where to
sue, and thus, which jurisdiction and which legal system comes to bear
on the case.20 Transnational lawsuits thus entangle the laws of host states
with those of the home states of multinational companies. Furthermore,
they often try to distribute the burdens of liability anew by renegotiating
mediate responsibility: actions and omissions that enable (rather than
directly cause) situations of damage and injury are increasingly moving
to the centre of litigation.21 They address a wider range of actors than
conventional legal treatments of global value chains, which typically cut
short these chains into contractual relations between a limited number of
actors. By addressing a larger set of actors, such struggles entangle the
laws that regulate liability, tort and criminal responsibility in the various
legal systems to which the actors partaking in these long chains of
production and consumption are subject. In both tort and criminal law,
claimants as well as lawyers are reaching ever farther, drawing causal and
moral connections between events, actions, suffering and remedies.
19
See e.g. M. Galanter, ‘When Legal Worlds Collide: Reflections on Bhopal, the Good
Lawyer, and the American Law School’ (1986) 36 Journal of Legal Education 292–310; S.
Sawyer, ‘Disabling Corporate Sovereignty in a Transnational Lawsuit’ (2006) 29 Political
and Legal Anthropology Review 23–43.
20
See N. Krisch, ‘Entgrenzte Jurisdiktion: Die extraterritoriale Durchsetzung von
Unternehmensverantwortung’ (Jurisdiction Unbound: Extraterritoriality and Corporate
Responsibility), in Deutsche Gesellschaft für internationales Recht (ed.),
Unternehmensverantwortung im internationalen Recht (2020), pp. 11–38.
21
In other fields, such as that of international criminal law, the role and responsibility of
those who enable violent conflicts by legally exporting weapons, trading in ‘conflict
resources’, etc. is also now receiving increasing attention, as is the role of states in human
rights violations committed by third parties.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Current legal initiatives such as the French loi de vigilance, the
Lieferkettengesetz debated in Germany or the Konzernverantwortungsinitiative
in Switzerland all seek to transform both the delineations of jurisdic-
tions22 and, to a lesser degree, the relative weight of primary and
secondary responsibility. However, to the extent that these laws and
legal proposals concern very specific obligations, such as disclosure
requirements or due diligence principles, and rely on rather nebulous
identifications of a corporation’s ‘sphere of influence’, they do not
overcome the narrow spatial or temporal cuts of current conceptions
of liability.23
At the same time, such struggles over the attribution of responsibility
are now sometimes carried onto a different level. Litigation against states,
the host states of multinational companies as well as – particularly in
relation to climate change – the home state of companies that globally
pollute or enable pollution, is increasingly chosen as an avenue of protest
via law. For example, in a case brought against the Ministry of the
Environment of Ecuador and the state-owned mining company
ENAMI EP over a mining concession granted to the Canadian company
Cornerstone, which Laura Affolter observed24 – the ‘Los Cedros case’ as
it is referred to – claims were made not against the corporation, and not
for harms that had occurred. Rather, the plaintiffs targeted the govern-
ment of Ecuador for issuing the licence for mining, thereby shifting
responsibility to the state for making economic activities possible that
would – in their perception – inevitably produce harms to the environ-
ment and the people living in the vicinity of the mine.
The shift from local causers to transnational enablers is now followed
by a shift from those transnational enablers to the states that make their
operation legally possible – the enablers of the enablers, so to speak. This
puts at issue the legal structure in which corporations, or rather corporate
activities, are embedded. Such legal structures are today not made by
states alone, particularly as concerns international law, as multiple actors
including corporations, international organizations and private law firms
22
Krisch, ‘Entgrenzte Jurisdiktion’, 22f.
23
They are often counteracted by bilateral or multilateral trade agreements, or the insti-
tution of special economic zones, which respond to movements of jurisdictional exten-
sion by limiting contractually what norms and regulations corporations are required to
comply with.
24
L. Affolter, ‘The Responsibility to Prevent Future Harm: Anti-mining Struggles, the State,
and Constitutional Lawsuits in Ecuador’ (2020) 4 Journal of Legal Anthropology 78–99.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
are increasingly involved in drafting law.25 International organizations
such as the World Trade Organization (WTO) and the International
Monetary Fund (IMF) have developed their own norm-generating for-
mats, and while they are formally constituted by their member states,
only some states have an effective say in them. This should not deflect
attention from legislatives as lawmakers, administrations as issuers of
licences and governments as signatories to investment treaties and the
governmental decisions that make corporate activities possible. Even if
some states are severely restricted in their choices of whether or not to
ratify international agreements, formally it is states that make the laws
that regulate the global economy and give corporations their legal shape.
More importantly, it is state governments that choose which laws to
enact, and how and when to enact them.26 This is what Shalini Randeria
pointed to with her observation of the ‘cunning’ of states to avoid
accountability towards their citizens.27 Randeria also points to the differ-
ences among states in the degree of autonomy they have towards inter-
national organizations, corporations and international law. However, it
could be claimed that even severely ‘dependent’ states have room to
manoeuvre, and the way they do so is a matter of political choice.
Ecuador is an interesting example in this regard, considering the different
choices subsequent Ecuadorian governments have taken.
The ongoing claim against the state of Ecuador in the Los Cedros case
mentioned above calls into question the mining policy adopted by the
current government, and with it its entire economic policy. In this way, it
inches closer to challenging the production of the structural possibilities
of harm that have so often been overlooked in human rights struggles.
Such claims not only shift responsibility onto states – host states as
well as the home states of multinational companies – but further, by
focusing on the creation of the legal conditions for harmful activities by
25
J. Mugler, ‘Regulatory Capture? Fiscal Anthropological Insights into the Heart of
Contemporary Statehood’ (2019) Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law 379–95;
P. Dann and J. Eckert, ‘Norm Creation beyond the State’, in M. C. Foblets, M. Goodale,
M. Sapignioli and O. Zenker (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Law and Anthropology
(Oxford University Press, 2020).
26
Dann and Eckert, ‘Norm Creation beyond the State’; Krisch, ‘Entgrenzte
Jurisdiktionen’, 34.
27
S. Randeria, ‘The (Un)making of Policy in the Shadow of the World Bank: Infrastructure
Development, Urban Resettlement and the Cunning State in India’, in C. Shore, S. Wright
and D. Però (eds), Policy Worlds: Anthropology and the Analysis of Contemporary Power
(Berghahn Books, 2011), pp. 187–204.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
multinational corporations, they involve a move from retrospective
responsibility to the prospective responsibility to prevent potentially
harmful operations. It might be too early to speak of ‘a (re)turn in the
understanding of responsibility’, as Klaus Bayertz28 put it, with prospect-
ive, precautionary responsibility, and possibly even strict liability gaining
in importance in law. However, such normative possibilities become part
of the debate as a result of mobilizations of this kind, and it is to some
degree independent of their legal outcomes whether they thereby provide
a model for new legal ‘imaginations’29 that ‘consider possible or alterna-
tive solutions to the problem’,30 and are taken up elsewhere, travelling to
new sites and situations and yet further interpretative translations.31
28
K. Bayertz, ‘Eine kurze Geschichte der Herkunft der Verantwortung’, in K. Bayertz (ed.),
Verantwortung – Prinzip oder Problem? (Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1995),
pp. 3–71, at p. 29.
29
Like the imagination in legal reasoning that Maksymilian del Mar call us to explore for
providing models of possible interpretation for the future (see Mar, ‘Legal Reasoning in
Pluralist Jurisprudence’), such mobilisations suggest new normative possibilities. .
30
See Mar, ‘Legal Reasoning in Pluralist Jurisprudence’, p. 45.
31
For this notion of translation, see e.g. A. Behrends, S-J. Park and R. Rottenburg (eds),
Travelling Models in African Conflict Management: Translating Technologies of Social
Ordering (Brill, 2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
with, or even identified with (and reduced to), rights to a healthy envir-
onment. They then changed course, and joined as amici curiae to invoke
Article 11 of the Additional Protocol to the American Convention on
Human Rights in the Area of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights
(Protocol of San Salvador), which establishes the right to a healthy
environment and states that everyone shall have the right to live in a
healthy environment and to have access to basic public services, and that
the signatory states shall promote the protection, preservation and
improvement of the environment. They referred to the Stockholm
Declaration of 1972 and to the judgement of the Inter-American Court
of Human Rights (IACrtHR) in the case of Indígena Yakye Axa v. The
State of Paraguay, which established property rights over ancestral land
and the state’s obligation to protect the traditional means of livelihood of
Indigenous communities as part of the right to life. Furthermore, they
referred to an Advisory Opinion of the IACrtHR (OC-23/17,
15 November 2017), the Rio Declaration on Environment and
Development (1992), the Convention on Biological Diversity, the
United Nations Framework on Climate Change and a judgement by
the Columbian Constitutional Court. In the second instance, the
‘Regional Agreement on Access to Information, Public Participation
and Justice in Environmental Matters in Latin America and the
Caribbean’ was added to this list.
The claim thus brought into relation regulations on biodiversity with
social and economic rights, judgements on Indigenous rights and reso-
lutions on states’ obligations to take measures preventing further climate
change. Moreover, the concept of buen vivir, which was incorporated in
the Ecuadorian constitution in 2008, could be said to directly challenge
the cuts that liberal law makes to separate different fields of human
action. Characteristic of the principle of buen vivir is that it overcomes
the opposition between human and non-human nature that modern law
creates by separating the bodies of law that regulate the economy,
intimate relations, the use of resources and the treatment of non-human
nature. Like the Indigenous approaches to law that Kirsten Anker
describes in Chapter 3, buen vivir provides for norms that perceive all
relations as inextricably entangled.32
32
The lawyers bringing the case were initially criticised by colleagues who were otherwise in
favour of their endeavour precisely for ‘mixing up’ the rights of nature and the right to a
healthy environment, which it was claimed would weaken the claim. They were also
critical of the employment of the instrument of a ‘consulta previa, libre e informada’,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Everywhere, the constitutional claims made in the name of the rights
of nature or in relation to the right to life and physical integrity aim at
structural change that goes far beyond legislating binding due diligence
norms for corporate legal responsibility. In this way, they transgress the
conventional limitations of which harms can actually be addressed by
law. The claim that issues regulated by different bodies of law are in fact
intricately connected is a central proposition in such struggles. Keebet
von Benda-Beckmann shows how, paradigmatically, in the dispute about
the availability of low-priced AIDS medicine, the WTO accepted the
argument that the prices of medicines were not only an issue of free
trade regulation, but also one of human rights: ‘In this dispute two bodies
of law that had been regarded as separate, had been successfully linked.
WTO could no longer reject the human rights as not belonging to its
relevant context. From now on, arguments of human rights are in
principle legitimate claims in WTO procedures.’33 The World Health
Assembly and the UN Human Rights Commission, following activist
campaigns, urged an interpretative entanglement of the different areas of
legal regulation. The discursive entanglement provided for the concepts
and (legal) arguments to become part of negotiations where they had not
been so before. The ‘cuts’ of liberal law around jurisdictions and the
limited reach of liability, including temporally (and regarding the ‘rights’
of future generations), are thus contested; different fields of interaction
and regulation are purported to be inseparable. In this contestation,
claimants draw upon hitherto unrelated norms from various bodies of
law and connect them in a ‘situation’. In this situation, the distinctions
between different bodies of law and between moral and legal norms are
dissolved. What emerges is interlegality.34 Interlegality, in the under-
standing of Santos, does not denote hybrids, but rather the mutual
informing of different norms and normative orders, through which novel
forms and meanings emerge.
which applies only to areas in which indigenous people and descendants of Africans live,
which this was not. The opinion that ecological preservation and human rights were
distinct legal fields and had little to do with each other was voiced, and different
interpretations of buen vivir were articulated in the case in Ecuador by the amicus curiae
of the defendants and that of the plaintiffs. See Affolter, ‘The Responsibility to Prevent
Future Harm’.
33
Von Benda-Beckmann, ‘The Contexts of Law’, pp. 4–5.
34
B. de Sousa Santos, Toward a New Legal Common Sense: Law, Globalization, and
Emancipation (Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. 473.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
15.5 Is This Entanglement?
We might debate at what point norms originating in different legal
systems or different bodies of law are truly entangled. References to other
norms and laws, which ‘are not heard’ and do not affect the way a case is
interpreted in the last instance, or do not determine what harms are seen
to be at issue, might arguably not actually entangle law. However, as
Krisch argues in Chapter 1, entanglement proceeds here discursively, that
is by way of the interpretative and argumentative realms that mobiliza-
tions of law(s) open up: ‘If we understand law as ultimately socially
constructed, a shift in the ways in which actors relate different parts of
the legal order to one another reshapes the law itself’.35 The actors that
need to be taken into consideration are not only judges, Krisch insists:
[W]e cannot limit ourselves to considering the formal rules that govern
these relations or the occasional pronouncement of a court – too much of
the postnational legal order only has loose connections with courts or
other formal dispute settlers. Instead, we need to take into view the ways
in which different kinds of actors – norm-makers, addressees, dispute
settlers and other concerned societal actors – construe these relations and
resolve (potential) conflicts between different norms.36
One might thus argue that norms inform each other not only when
incorporated into the effective normative legal realm through adjudi-
cation and the legal reasoning of judges,38 but also when rejected in
35
See Chapter 1, Section 1.2.
36
Chapter 1, Section 1.5.
37
Baer, ‘Inexcitable Speech’, p. 242 (my translation).
38
Stuart Kirsch also points particularly to adjudication as a process of ‘reverse translation’
that is the import of norms from other normative orders into liberal law. See S. Kirsch,
‘Juridification of Indigenous Politics’, in J. Eckert, B. Donahoe, C. Strümpell and Z. O.
Biner (eds), Law against the State: Ethnographic Forays into Laws Transformations
(Cambridge University Press, 2012), pp. 23–43, at p. 39. See also F. von Benda-
Beckmann, ‘Pak Dusa’s Law: Thoughts on Legal Knowledge and Power’, in E. Berg, J.
Lauth and A. Wimmer (eds), Ethnologie im Widerstreit: Kontroversen über Macht,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
courts as invalid alternatives. Even when rejected, norms that remain in a
dissident or minority position have an effect on the dominant norms that
they are set in opposition to. The arguments made to deny their applic-
ability themselves set norms in relation to each other. More importantly,
the relational meaning established might be taken up by other struggles,
and further imaginative interpretations.
Nonetheless, we can presume that not all actors’ entanglements have
the same effect on normative transformations. Judges import norms into
legal reasoning in a different manner than the claims of lay people do.
Therefore, different pathways of entanglement can be explored for their
different normative effects and processes of homogenization,39 standard-
ization,40 pluralization or coherence.
15.6 Counter-Entanglements
This is therefore not the end of the story. When local social struggles
against multinational corporations succeed either in winning their cases,
or in obliging their governments to regulate corporations’ activities more
strictly, the conflicts today often shift to arbitration between the corpor-
ations and host states on the terms of the investment regimes that host
states have concluded with the home states of the corporations in
question, or their national investment laws. In Ecuador, for example,
after the civil lawsuit against Chevron, in the so-called ‘oil dumping’ case
about the devastating pollution in relation to Texaco’s41 operations in the
Lago Agrio oil field, was won in all instances, the international arbitral
tribunal in the dispute between the government of Ecuador and Chevron
obliged Ecuador to pay compensation for damages to the company’s
Geschäft, Geschlecht in fremden Kulturen (Trickster Verlag, 1991), pp. 215–27. Here,
Benda-Beckmann argues that it is ultimately judges who determine what is law.
39
J. Eckert, ‘From Subjects to Citizens: Legalisation from Below and the Homogenisation of
the Legal Sphere’ (2006) 38 Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law 45–75.
40
F. von Benda-Beckmann, K. von Benda-Beckmann and J. Eckert, ‘Rules of Law and Laws
of Ruling: Law and Governance between Past and Future’, in F. von Benda-Beckmann, K.
von Benda-Beckmann and J. Eckert (eds), Rules of Law and Laws of Ruling: On the
Governance of Law (Ashgate, 2009), pp. 1–30.
41
Litigation against Texaco claiming for the clean-up of the polluted area and compen-
sation to its inhabitants began in 1993. In 2001 Chevron acquired Texaco and in 2011 was
ordered to pay compensation by an Ecuadorian court. However, a US court in 2014 over-
turned the verdict, arguing that the plaintiffs had used coercion and bribery, and opening
a case against their lawyer under the RICO Act. The Permanent Court of Arbitration in
The Hague in 2018 ruled in favour of Chevron, too.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
reputation on grounds of the US–Ecuador Bilateral Investment Treaty.
The arbitral tribunal also ordered Ecuador to quash the earlier
Ecuadorian court ruling.42 The tribunal held that the plaintiffs should
be prohibited from filing any further class actions against the group.43
Affected persons should only be able to file individual claims for dam-
ages. Furthermore, the arbitral tribunal suggested that Ecuador should
see to it that the plaintiffs did not file lawsuits in other countries where
Chevron has subsidiaries.44 Pablo Fajardo, the chief lawyer in the
Chevron case in Ecuador, presented a document at a lecture in Bern in
October 2019 showing that the Ecuadorian Attorney General’s Office had
asked the courts in Argentina, Brazil and Canada to stop dealing with the
cases there, and deny the plaintiffs the possibilities to collect the
Ecuadorian judgement.45 The General Prosecutor’s Office thereby hoped
to minimize the amount the Arbitration tribunal would allow Chevron to
request from Ecuador.46
As well as being prohibited from filing suits against the company,
Ecuador was also required to pay all outstanding debts it had accrued
through such arbitration cases in order to be eligible for a loan from the
IMF.47 The government is apparently willing to comply with all of these
requirements. Furthermore, when the bilateral investment treaty with the
USA was terminated in 2018, Ecuador adopted its own investment law
(Ley de Fomento Productivo), which provides that disputes arising out of
investment agreements are to be resolved through arbitration, and arbi-
tral awards arising therefrom are immediately enforceable in Ecuador,
without the need for any further recognition by the courts.48 The gov-
ernment repeatedly warned those organizing public consultation
42
See Chevron Corporation and Texaco Petroleum Company v. Ecuador, PCA Case no.
2009-23, UNCITRAL, Partial Award, 30 August 2018, part X, para. 10.13 (i).
43
Ibid., para. 10.13 (ii).
44
Ibid., para. 10.13 (iii).
45
Informe Ejecutivo Sobre Estado Del Caso Chevron Corporation y Texaco Petroleum
Company v. Republica del Ecuador (Caso CPA No 2009–23), Procuraduría General del
Estado, 2019), p. 2.
46
Personal communication from Pablo Fajardo to Laura Affolter, received by the author
13 November 2019.
47
Memorando No. MEF-SFP-2019-0036 (Subsecretario de Finanziamento Publico, 2019),
p. 15.
48
Article 37 of the law stipulates that the Ecuadorian state must agree to domestic or
international arbitration to resolve disputes regarding investment agreements. In a
further provision, the law states that for investment agreements whose value is over
US$10 million, the investor may initiate proceedings before a number of arbitral insti-
tutions, namely the Permanent Court of Arbitration, the International Chamber of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
meetings on international mining projects, such as those in the Los
Cedros case described in Section 15.3, that if such consultations succeed
in preventing mining, corporations would likely bring further disputes
against the Ecuadorian government in international arbitration tribu-
nals.49 The costs would be borne by all citizens.
This could be said to be the counter-entanglement to the entangle-
ments from below in transnational relations. It might be considered to
fall under the third pathway of entanglement identified by Krisch: coer-
cion. ‘Today, for example, the adoption of World Bank rules on resettle-
ment in the context of infrastructure programmes on the part of
borrowing states is often a matter of conditionality and necessity rather
than persuasion or attraction’, he writes in Chapter 1.50 In this particular
case, and this holds for many others, coercion forced the entanglement of
particular norms, counteracting other entanglements. Here, in several
steps culminating in the conditionalities of the IMF, but significantly
moving via the bilateral investment agreement between the USA and
Ecuador that was, upon termination, immediately followed by the new
investment law, Ecuador’s environmental law, human rights law ratified
by Ecuador, its trade law and even its administrative law are entangled.
Such coercive entanglements set the contexts for entanglements from
below; they limit the possibilities of entanglements and drive them to
strive for a trans-systemic coherence, so as to make binding norms for
more powerful opponents, thereby limiting the latter’s possibilities of
forum shopping.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
constellation rather than how they relate to general norms (regardless of
which system they might stem from). Rather than entanglement leading
to closer and more systematic relations between legal systems, entangle-
ment might actually support – possibly inadvertently – another tendency
in litigation, namely ‘singularization’.
We observe that the legal struggles against multinational corporations
that cross jurisdictional boundaries in seeking to attribute responsibility
for harm that occurs in relation to these companies’ economic activities
are rarely adjudicated but tend rather to be settled out of court, if they are
not simply dismissed beforehand.51 As in many such litigations, in the
Monterrico case analysed by Angela Lindt, an out-of-court settlement
was reached three months before the trial date. Claimants had sued
the British mining company Monterrico and its Peruvian subsidiary
Rio Blanco Copper for human rights violations in relation to a protest
against the mine, in which twenty-eight people were arrested. The claim-
ants sought damages for the involvement of Monterrico and Rio Blanco
personnel in the violence perpetrated against them during the three
days of detention, as well as for the material support provided to
the police, and the companies’ failure to prevent police violence. In a
way that was reminiscent of Union Carbide case in Bhopal and
many others, Monterrico did not admit any liability, but agreed to pay
compensation to the plaintiffs. In return, the plaintiffs withdrew their
complaint by accepting the compensation and waived the need for a
judgement on whether the parent corporation bore any responsibility.52
The exact content of the settlement and the precise sum of compensation
were not disclosed, and the plaintiffs were obliged not to make them
public.
Settlements concentrate not on what is specific to a case and how that
specificity might be related to a general norm. Rather, cases are treated as
singular, as concerning a singular relationship between the parties
51
See Chapter 8. See also A. Lindt, ‘Transnational Human Rights Litigation: A Means of
Obtaining Effective Remedy Abroad? (2020) 4 Journal of Legal Anthropology 57–77; J. A.
Zerk, ‘Corporate Liability for Gross Human Rights Abuses: Towards a Fairer and More
Effective System of Domestic Law Remedies’, report prepared for the UNHCHR (2014),
www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Business/DomesticLawRemedies/StudyDomesticeLaw
Remedies.pdf.
52
Lindt, ‘Transnational Human Rights Litigation’; C. Kamphuis, ‘Foreign Investment and
the Privatization of Coercion: A Case Study of the Forza Security Company in Peru’
(2012) 37 Brooklyn Journal of International Law 529–78.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
involved; they need not have any comparable aspects with others, and if
they do, these need not become an issue in the negotiations leading to
a settlement.
Since the settlement prevents a ruling on the question of whether a
corporation actually is at fault and thus bears legal responsibility, it
cannot be used as precedent in comparable cases.
The practice of pursuing out of court settlements before disputes are
finally determined, while benefiting the victims in the particular case,
impacts upon the development of jurisprudence and precedent. As a
litigation strategy, out of court settlement prevents the development of a
settled body of law, which may pave the way for more victims to bring
claims against corporations for human rights abuse.53
53
J. Robinson and L. Lazarus, Report for the UN Special Rapporteur on Business and Human
Rights – Obstacles for Victims of Corporate Human Rights Violations (Oxford Pro Bono
Publico, 2008).
54
This unrepeatability is apparently not always strong enough for the defendants, and is
therefore sometimes further enforced by the conditions they insist on for engaging in
such negotiations: ‘Several practitioners pointed to instances where the business defend-
ant required that the law firms make commitment to not representing any other plaintiff
in any similar case for a period of several years, or not providing even general infor-
mation about the kinds of harms identified during the case to any other person. Such
commitments may be enforced by a threat that a breach of the commitment by the law
firm will result in the plaintiffs having to forfeit the settlement.’ See M. B. Taylor, R. C.
Thompson and A. Ramasastry, Overcoming Obstacles to Justice: Improving Access to
Judicial Remedies for Business Involvement in Grave Human Rights Abuses (Amnesty
International, 2010), p. 17.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
other. The parties involved are free to agree over which norms come to
bear on the settlement. The privacy of the agreement can ‘convert [. . .]
the accountability of the perpetrators into a private matter’.55
When the parties involved are furthermore obliged to keep the out-
come secret, settlements and the norms that are activated within them
are entirely removed from public view. Thus, singularization proceeds in
several ways: the avoidance of a judgement about fault relating the case to
a general norm, the private agreement between the parties involved and
secrecy. Everything prevents the case from being a precedent, or simply
an example or model, for others; by making comparability irrelevant,
entanglement, too, is inhibited or at least left suspended.
The privatization inherent in such settlement negotiations thus intro-
duces new ‘cuts’ in Strathern’s sense, cuts around a single constellation of
actors brought together by the specific legal limitations regarding legit-
imate claimants in the event of a harm. Even when settlements include
compensation payments to collectives, or compensatory action in
affected regions, the limitations of who can actually be a party to a
settlement are decided by as yet unentangled law, as I mentioned earlier
in this section. The question of who is to be considered ‘involved’, that is,
who is a legitimate plaintiff, is most often determined according to the
conventions of the jurisdiction where the corporation has its headquar-
ters – its home country. As I briefly discussed in Sections 15.2 and 15.3,
liberal law tends to rely on comparatively narrow conceptualizations of
the reach of liability and likewise of identifying those who are affected,
particularly in cases related to human rights, because of the concen-
tration of human rights on specific violations of individual rights.
The avoidance of precedent, one could say, responds to entanglement
by actively making the comparability of cases irrelevant. Singularization
disentangles cases from the systematicity of law and redirects the hopes
that had once aimed at ‘justice’56 towards individual remedy. The fact
that these cases are settled out of court is not directly caused by the
entanglement of law so much as triggered by the arguments and claims of
the plaintiffs. They are settled out of court for various reasons,57 foremost
55
Kamphuis, ‘Foreign Investment and the Privatization of Coercion’, 562.
56
See Lindt, ‘Transnational Human Rights Litigation’; Loher, ‘Everyday Suffering and the
Abstract Time-Reckoning of Law’.
57
See e.g. M. Galanter, ‘A Settlement Judge, Not a Trial Judge’ (1985) 12 Journal of Law &
Society 1–18.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
among them the many obstacles that stand in the way of plaintiffs
successfully suing multinational corporations, such as the high costs
and long durations, time limitations and jurisdictional limitations. It is
commonly argued that such alternative forms of dispute resolution in
fact particularly benefit those plaintiffs who cannot afford long and
expensive court procedures. Settlements lessen the costs of procedures
and make restitutive measures more accessible for the victims, and
because they do not need to spend their efforts on attributing fault, can
ameliorate suffering more effectively.58 However, they often do not bring
about a judgement about where fault lies, nor do they produce a prece-
dent, the two issues which are often central to the plaintiffs’ hopes, their
ideas of justice and their desire for preventive signals.
We have here another form of the proximity-distancing dynamic
Krisch describes in Chapter 1: the ‘distancing’ entailed in singularization
not only preserves or increases the distance between different bodies of
law or among different systems of law. Rather, it creates a distance
between cases, so that cases cease to be ‘cases’ exemplary of a general
type, but become unique, that is singular. Singularization is thus a
specific form of distancing, possibly the most radical one, in as much
as singularization does not preserve an earlier distance but introduces a
new logic. This new logic concerns not merely the relation between
different laws, but the idea of law in itself. Law ceases to operate by
subsuming specific instances under a general principle, valid beyond the
specific parties to a legal dispute, and turns into a tool of mediation.
Singularization thus not only prevents precedent but also makes the
development of tertiary norms unnecessary, because it circumvents
rather than regulates the interface.59 A different logic emerges, one that
develops neither systematicity, nor modes of dealing with normative
58
See M. Galanter and M. Cahill, ‘Most Cases Settle: Judicial Promotion and Regulation of
Settlements’ (1994) 46 Stanford Law Review 1339–91, for a critical discussion of the
arguments for settlements as the preferred mode of conflict resolution.
59
Could singularization be considered a kind of tertiary procedure in which plurality is
accommodated by singularising cases? This conclusion could be drawn from the obser-
vation that judges, in response to the plurality of norms that could possibly be relevant for
a case, tend to adopt relatively minimalist stances, avoiding broader principles and
instead deciding cases on as narrow grounds as possible (just because the questions of
general principle are so wide open). See e.g. Mar, ‘Legal Reasoning in Pluralist
Jurisprudence’; and N. Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of
Postnational Law (Oxford University Press, 2010), in particular pp. 263–96. Theirs,
however, is rather a reaction to pluralism than an accommodation of it, inasmuch as
pluralism disappears from view in such minimalism.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
pluralism, but rather entails a radical singularization where common
ground can be found only in procedural norms at best. The paradox is
that entanglements engendered by strategic comparisons across legal
systems and bodies of law increase attention to the singular.
60
R. Sieder, ‘The Juridification of Politics’, in M. C. Foblets, M. Goodale, M. Sapignioli and
O. Zenker (eds), Oxford Handbook of Law and Anthropology (Oxford University Press, in
press).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The entanglements produced by the mobilization of law from below
I consider here do not strive for such accommodations of pluralism. In
fact, they are often at base anti-pluralist, in that they produce novel
relational meanings, thereby moving towards a trans-systemic and, at
the same time, unsystematic coherence. In their position of relative
weakness, they entangle law simply because they need to make use of
any norm that might provide them with benefits. It is beneficial for them
if all laws providing their claims with legal arguments, no matter where
they stem from, are applicable to their situation. They need to strive for
the normative amalgamation that comes to bear on their case to be
binding for their opponents, and thus for its trans-systemic (trans-juris-
dictional) validity. Hence, I argue that these entangling mobilizations of
law from below strive for coherence. Such coherence is trans-systemic
inasmuch as it refers to norms from various normative orders. It is
unsystematic in the sense noted earlier in this section, not being con-
cerned with systematicity, but rather with coherent relationality.
The vision of coherence that comes to the fore in these hopeful
mobilizations of law leaves behind the systemic character of individual
legal systems; it transcends global legal pluralism, and articulates a more
universal notion of the coherence of law. These mobilizations claim that
different norms, such as those of trade agreements or environmental
conventions and those of civil or human rights, are intricately related to
each other, inseparable even. This is a kind of ‘legal holism’, an approach
to law that attempts to counteract the differentiation of various legal
fields and the borders of different legal systems.
The fact that hopes are placed in the very law that underlies the
unequal distribution of rights and privileges might be due to the ‘appeal’
of the norms invoked, their charisma.61 Krisch distinguishes three path-
ways of entanglement, namely mutual benefit, appeal and coercion. The
appeal of norms, as Krisch writes, might arise ‘for their substantive
content but also for the aura of progress they come with, the Zeitgeist
they represent or the fit they produce with existing commitments.
Likewise, the actors creating such norms may appear as appealing – as
embodying the right values, as culturally superior, etc.’.62 Such appeal
might of course also indicate the hegemonic sway of liberal law and its
power to shape people’s understanding of the world, of themselves and of
61
Philipp Dann and I have distinguished between structural privilege, similar to Krisch’s
coercion, expertise and charisma. Dann and Eckert, ‘Norm Creation beyond the State’.
62
See Chapter 1, Section 1.4.2.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
their aims and conflicts. The question of whether an alternative imagin-
ation of the world is possible within the parameters of existing law has
been much debated. I have argued elsewhere that when people turn
towards legal norms to express their hopes and struggle for their future,
they interpret norms in the light of these aspirations – rather than simply
in terms of existing normative orders.63 Of course, these aspirations are
shaped by the normative orders that currently prevail in the historical
situation in which they live. More than being simply evidence of the
hegemonic power of the existing norms of liberal law, such mobilizations
of law from below put forth specific interpretations of rights and entitle-
ments and act upon them in order to shape institutions accordingly.64
Concepts such as ‘vernacularisation’, as proposed by Sally Merry,65 or
‘reverse translation’, as suggested by Stuart Kirsch,66 provide us with
instruments to turn this question into an empirical one.
Singularization that proceeds through the privatization of dispute
settlement and the move from public courts to private agreements
between specific parties runs counter to this. While circumventing rather
than resisting the challenges to current legal instruments and norms
posed by such entangling struggles, singularization prevents entangle-
ments of law from producing novel legal meanings and thus obstructs
legal change. By doing away with precedent, it inhibits the development
of normative entanglements that could better reflect current relations of
interdependence, position anew the various actors concerned in them
and respond to the enabling mechanisms that produce the conditions
that make harm possible.
Singularization does not revert the extensions of jurisdictions, nor does
it refute the plurality of normative possibilities. It rather proceeds in a
different way, namely by making comparability irrelevant, and relation-
ality obsolete; the very idea of normative coherence that drives hopes in
law is circumvented, and cases claimed to be equal to others are dissolved
into the singular relationships among parties to the individual agreement.
Singularization is a form of distancing that keeps not only different
bodies or systems of law apart, but even individual cases.
63
Eckert et al., ‘Introduction: Laws Travels and Transformations’, pp. 1–22.
64
De Sousa Santos and Rodríguez-Garavito, ‘Law, Politics and the Subaltern’, 1–26. S.
Kirsch, Engaged Anthropology (University of California Press, 2018).
65
S. Merry, ‘Transnational Human Rights and Local Activism: Mapping the Middle’ (2006)
108 American Anthropologist 38–51.
66
Kirsch, ‘Juridification of Indigenous Politics’, 36.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
If hope in law is hope in the coherence of law in the sense of the
promise of the applicability of norms to one’s concerns irrespective of
jurisdiction, the tendency to singularization does not bode well for it.
Time and again the argument has been made that law operates for the
‘haves’ not merely because of its substantive content, but also because of
the advantages the haves possess in negotiations.67 We see here that the
two are related, that is, that the substantive content, and above all the
distinctive ‘cuts’ of current law, are protected by the turn to settlement,
which prevents change. There is no hope in singularity.
67
Galanter, ‘A Settlement Judge, Not a Trial Judge’; Galanter and Cahill, ‘Most Cases Settle’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
16
Tertiary Rules
16.1 Introduction
The entanglement between legal orders is a topic that legal theory has,
until very recently, widely ignored or marginalized. For a long time, legal
theory happened in the singular: it was mostly a theory of law, not a
theory of laws. The object was one law, not many – whether that one law
was confined and contingent (as in legal positivism) or all-encompassing
and universal (as in natural law). In such a singular theory of law,
relations between legal orders are ignored because, by definition, a
multitude of laws is not conceptualized. Or, at best, multiple laws are
subsumed, somewhere, under one ultimate law.
Such a multitude of legal orders is a theme of legal pluralism, a
conceptualization of law as plural that has been discussed not only in
legal anthropology and sociology but also in legal theory. Here, entangle-
ment is recognized, but it is often not sufficiently theorized. In legal
sociology, the interrelation between legal orders is often conceptualized
as interlegality, a rather vague concept that obfuscates more than it
actually explains.1 In legal theory, attempts have been made to concep-
tualize entanglement, and some of these are discussed in this chapter.
However, there is a wide disparity of views. Some discuss entanglement
as a matter of social fact, others as a matter of legal ordering. Some
discuss entanglement from a neutral perspective, others view it from the
perspective of peculiar legal orders, some as both. Some authors discuss a
plethora of mechanisms to reduce conflicts between legal orders, or to
organize interactions, or the like. But it does not always become clear
Thanks for valuable suggestions to David Dyzenhaus, Nico Krisch, and Tomáš Morochovič.
1
B. de Sousa Santos, ‘Law: A Map of Misreading – Toward a Postmodern Conception of
Law’ (1987) 14 Journal of Law and Society 279–302; J. Klabbers and G. Palombella (eds),
The Challenge of Inter-Legality (Cambridge University Press, 2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
what holds these mechanisms together and what keeps them apart. What
we lack is an overarching conceptualization of these mechanisms.
This chapter suggests that these mechanisms should be understood as
a peculiar type of legal rules. These rules are different from primary rules
because they do not provide commands, dos and don’ts. They are also
different from secondary rules because they do not determine issues of
validity and valid change of a legal system, at least not in the way in
which we traditionally understand secondary rules. Instead, they are a
different type of legal rules I propose to call tertiary rules. Tertiary rules
are rules with which one legal order designates, relative to itself, the
normative space of another legal order to which it is not hierarchically
superior. In an earlier publication, I discussed a special case of these
tertiary rules, namely the rule of external recognition.2 In this chapter,
I generalize the concept.
Tertiary rules are an element necessary for the development of a
concept of laws instead of law. The argument for a concept of laws rests
on the conviction that a proper understanding of global law is neither
monist or pluralist but instead must transcend the difference between
monism and pluralism. That global law is differentiated into distinct legal
systems, which interrelate and organize their interrelations through
tertiary rules. Such tertiary rules therefore presume that legal systems
are at least partly autonomous from each other, but at the same time they
also make such partial autonomy possible.
The argument rests on a number of assumptions. These assumptions
are not self-evident and will require justification at some point, but here
is not the right place to demonstrate why they are justifiable, and so I ask
the reader to accept them, for the purpose of this argument, as given.
The first assumption is that global law is both one and many at the
same time.3 Global law is many in the sense that we have many separate
legal orders, state and non-state, and we do not have a comprehensive
meta-law that brings them all together. Global law is one in the sense that
none of the many separate legal orders really exists in isolation from the
other: they interrelate with each other, and none of them can be fully
2
R. Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition: Towards a Relational Concept of Law’, in N. Roughan
and A. Halpin (eds), In Pursuit of Pluralist Jurisprudence (Cambridge University Press,
2017), pp. 90–115. Some of the material in this chapter draws on that earlier chapter.
3
Ibid; see also T. E. Riesthuis, ‘The Intertwinement of Legal Orders - A Critical
Reconstruction of Theories of Jurisprudence’ PhD Thesis, Erasmus University
Rotterdam (2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
explained without regard to the other. In this sense, entanglement is a
universal condition of law.4 If this is so, then legal theory must change
from a concept of law to a concept of laws, from a concept of law as
essentially one to a concept of law as one and many at the same time. For
this concept of laws, traditional legal theories, whether monist or dualist,
are useful but insufficient.
The second assumption is that legal systems are separate from each
other. This has become a minority position within pluralist theories of
global law. Such theories often emphasize that borders between alleged
systems are blurred, or that transnational law does not allow for such
borders altogether.5 In fact, there is a fascination with hybrid spaces that
transcend borders. This is not the place to demonstrate comprehensively
the assumption of this chapter in favour of separate legal systems, but
two remarks may be helpful. First, the observation that borders are
transcended is often a sociological and not a legal observation. As such
it is important but not novel: it is a core insight of empirical legal
pluralism that legal rules of different origins not only overlap but are
also frequently mixed. But such sociological observations are of limited
use for a legal theory that looks at the operation of legal rules. Second, the
assumption is not that legal systems are natural entities to which the law
only responds. In fact, the separatedness of legal systems is in no small
part itself a creation of law, and most importantly by tertiary rules.
Tertiary rules thus do not only respond to, and organize, a world of
separated legal systems, they are themselves involved in the creation of
such a system.
This last argument has already alluded to the third assumption,
namely that entanglement between legal orders is organized by law.6
Law organizes its own plurality through its own rationality: it is inad-
equate and incomplete to describe entanglement solely in extra-legal
ways (just as it would be inadequate and incomplete to describe, for
example, contractual relations solely in extra-legal ways). In this sense,
the theory is a positivist theory: it assumes that not only the definition
and the creation of law but also the way in which legal orders relate to
4
I take it that this is what Nico Krisch has in mind with the concept of entanglements: see
Chapter 1, Section 1.1.
5
In this context, Nico Krisch, in Chapter 1, speaks of ‘straddling norms’ or
‘straddling practices’.
6
See also Section 16.4.2.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
each other are themselves operations by the legal system.7 To this
extent, the concept of laws is autopoietic. However, in emphasizing
that legal systems mutually constitute each other, the concept also
includes an allopoietic aspect. While the law at large is autopoietic,
individual legal systems are not; they constitute each other through
mutual recognition. There may, of course, be other theories of law to
describe legal entanglement, and it may even be the case that a positivist
theory does not explain all aspects of entanglement – though it seems
that positivist approaches to global law, which had fallen somewhat out
of fashion, are becoming more defensible in recent times.8 But, I would
argue, any theory that is entirely non-positivist – that is, a theory that
does not account for the fact that entanglement is organized in legal
ways – is necessarily incomplete.
The fourth assumption is that this ordering takes place in a heter-
archical way. This is the kind of ordering that presents the greatest
challenge to legal theory. Where entanglement takes place between
legal orders that are in a clear hierarchical relation, entanglement is
relatively simple, because it is simply organized by the hierarchically
superior order.9 However, in many cases, entanglement takes place
between legal orders none of which is clearly hierarchically superior to
the other and therefore able to determine, with binding force for the
other, how the entanglement is organized. It is in these heterarchical
situations where we must understand and explain the way entangle-
ment is organized.
7
Legal positivism is here meant in the sense of normative positivism: the bindingness and
legitimacy of legal rules depends on legal, not extra-legal criteria. (See, e.g., J.-R.
Sieckmann, Rechtsphilosophie (Mohr Siebeck, 2018), pp. 14–15.) This definition is differ-
ent from the one in F. Schauer, ‘Normative Legal Positivism’, in P. Mindus and T. Spaak
(eds), Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism (Cambridge University Press, 2021),
pp. 61–78. It is not meant in the sense of sociological positivism: that legality is an
observable social fact. In this sense, it follows Kelsen rather than Hart. For a forceful
argument in favour of Kelsen’s basic norm over Hart’s rule of recognition for problems of
cross-border normativity, see D. Dyzenhaus, ‘The Janus-Faced Constitution’, in J.
Bomhoff, D. Dyzenhaus and T. Poole (eds), The Double-Facing Constitution
(Cambridge University Press, 2020), pp. 17–53, p. 17.
8
See, e.g., J. Kammerhofer and J. d’Aspremont (eds), International Legal Positivism in a
Post-modern World (Cambridge University Press, 2014); L. Siliquini-Cinelli (ed.), Legal
Positivism in a Global and Transnational Age (Springer 2019).
9
See also Section 16.4.3.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
16.2 Cross-Border Normativity
16.2.1 Primary and Secondary Rules within One Order
Because tertiary rules obviously present themselves as an addition to the
idea of primary and secondary rules, it makes sense to describe first why
the Hartian system of primary and secondary rules is incomplete.10
Hart’s own introduction of a distinction between primary and secondary
rules, introduced in his Concept of Law in 1961, came in response to a
perceived shortcoming of legal positivism at the time. As conceived by
John Austin, legal positivism reduced the law to a system of commands.
The problem with such a definition was its inability to differentiate
between legal and other commands. Why was the order by a sheriff to
hand out one’s assets a legal command, but the similar order of a mugger
was not? How, in short, should one distinguish legal rules from non-legal
threats?
Hart’s answer borrowed from the dual concept of internal and external
sovereignty: ‘The legal system of a modern state is characterized by a
certain kind of supremacy within its territory and independence of other
systems.’11 He went on to find an ingenious explanation for the first of
these aspects, that of supremacy, but not for the second.
For rules to count as law, Hart suggested, they have to emerge from a
source recognized as competent to do so. The rule that determines who
can competently set laws is the so-called rule of recognition – not a legal
rule but a sociological fact for Hart, though others have suggested that
the rule of recognition is better understood as a legal rule. The recogni-
tion of who is entitled to make laws does not yet, on its own, determine
the conditions under which that person’s orders actually are valid law.
The determination of this is done by an additional set of rules that Hart
calls secondary rules. Some of these rules determine who can make laws,
some of these rules determine through what processes laws are made,
some of these rules determine institutions and procedures
of adjudication.
10
My argument thus draws on Hart here in part for terminiological reasons, although it
might actually fit better with a Kelsenian conception of validity. See Dyzenhaus, ‘The
Janus-Faced Constitution’.
11
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law, 3rd ed. (Oxford University Press, 2012), p. 24
(emphases in original). On internal and external sovereignty, see, e.g., S. Krasner,
‘Sovereignty’, in G. Ritzer (ed.), The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology (Wiley-
Blackwell, 2007).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The introduction of secondary rules created a significant advance for
legal positivism. It was now possible to explain normativity without
having to resort to natural law foundations for the law. The distinction
between primary and secondary rules made it possible to distinguish
between the effectiveness of a rule – that had essentially been Austin’s
only concern – and its validity and applicability. Legal rules as opposed to
mere commands were now those rules that actually had legal validity –
because they were made by recognized officials in the ways provided for
by the law. Moreover, they were those rules that were not only followed
by ordinary citizens (out of concern over the threat that backed them up)
but also were those rules applied by officials asked to apply or enforce the
law. In addition, the separation between effectiveness on the one hand,
validity and applicability on the other, also enabled the construction of
law as a system, or at least an order. Commands backed by threats can
come in isolation. Primary rules created and validated through secondary
rules, by contrast, become part of a bigger whole: they relate to each
other. Where primary rules are in apparent conflict, secondary rules are
able to resolve that conflict, though whether they succeed may depend on
an additional account for law’s systematicity, either a juridical one (like
Kelsen’s idea of law as a system) or an extra-legal one (like Dworkin’s
idea of law as integrity).12
12
On potential parallels between Kelsen and Dworkin here, see Dyzenhaus, ‘The Janus-
Faced Constitution’, 41–2.
13
P. Eleftheriadis, ‘Law and Sovereignty’ (2010) 29 Law & Philosophy 535–69.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
but English law modelled after Russian law.14 Later, in a debate with
Hans Kelsen, he rejected Kelsen’s monist theory of a unity of all laws and
even began conceptualizing types of relations between laws: completion,
reception and delegation.15 Nonetheless, his statement that ‘there is a
good deal of unfinished business for analytical jurisprudence still to
tackle’16 seemed true then and still seems true today, despite a growing
and important body of scholarship tackling these questions.
Cross-border normativity describes the situation that legal rules from
system A somehow have normative force within and for system B. Cross-
border normativity plays a role in a number of contexts. The conflict of
laws provides the best, though by far not only, example for this. Whether
a marriage celebrated by two Syrians in Syria is considered valid in
Germany is, with some exceptions, determined by Syrian, not German,
substantive law. Article 13 of the German Introductory Act explicitly says
as much: the substantive validity of a marriage is governed by the law of
the parties’ nationality. Syrian law, therefore, becomes in some ways part
of German law – it will govern the relation of parties living in Germany,
and it will be the applicable law for judges. But it remains Syrian law.
14
This is similar to the so-called local law theory in private international law; see Section
16.3.2.
15
H. L. A. Hart, ‘Kelsen’s Doctrine of the Unity of Law’, in H. L. A. Hart, Essays in
Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1983), pp. 309–42. Cf. D. von
Daniels, The Concept of Law from a Transnational Perspective (Ashgate, 2010),
pp. 158–60.
16
See Hart, ‘Kelsen’s Doctrine’, 310.
17
In an earlier publication I distinguished three modes of responding to foreign law outside
of its recognition at law, namely incorporation, deference and delegation. See R. Michaels,
‘The Re-State-Ment of Non-state Law: The State, Choice of Law, and the Challenge from
Global Legal Pluralism’ (2005) 51 Wayne Law Review 1209–59, at 1231ff. The three
modes correlate with the three positions discussed in Sections 16.3.1–16.3.3 – deference
denies normativity, incorporation denies (or overcomes) foreignness, delegation estab-
lishes hierarchy.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
16.3.1 Denying Normativity
A first way to deal with foreign normativity is simply to deny its norma-
tive nature: to treat foreign normativity as fact. We used to find such
approaches quite frequently in legal doctrine. They emerged from a
concern about foreign normativity. But the responses proved to be
neither convincing conceptually nor to lead to adequate normative
results.
A first example is the fact doctrine in civil procedure. The doctrine
emerges from English law, where the only law that could be applied was
domestic law, and so foreign law had to enter the courts not as law but as
fact.18 This has implications in particular for the procedural treatment of
foreign law – under the doctrine, its validity and content must be proven
like that of any other law, and burdens of evidence can be allocated
according to who relies on the foreign law. The fact doctrine is not
entirely wrong: foreign law (like domestic law) is, of course, also a fact.19
But the doctrine cannot explain the normative force that foreign law has
in domestic courts – that it is applied as law, not merely referred to as
fact. Insofar as claims and defences are based on foreign law, it seems
impossible to deny that the foreign law has its own normativity within
domestic courts, and thus differs from facts. Indeed, the procedural
treatment of foreign law as fact demonstrates this (and is another reason
for the doctrine’s decline).20
A second example emerges from choice of law, in particular within an
approach popular for some time in England and the United States and in
a different way in France: the vested rights theory.21 Under this theory,
the applicable law in English courts is still only English law. But foreign
law can enter English courts in the form of rights that parties have
acquired abroad under foreign law and are now having enforced. This
seemed a clever trick to justify normativity while denying that an English
judge would actually apply foreign law, but it was an unsuccessful trick.
The main problem of the theory had already been shown by Wächter in
18
R. Fentiman, Foreign Law in English Courts: Pleading, Proof and Choice of Law (Oxford
University Press, 1998).
19
See N. Jansen and R. Michaels, ‘Die Auslegung und Fortbildung ausländischen Rechts’
(Interpreting and Developing Foreign Law) (2003) 116 Zeitschrift für Zivilprozess 3–55.
20
Comparatively, see Y. Nishitani, ‘General Report’, in Y. Nishitani (ed.), Treatment of
Foreign Law: Dynamics towards Convergence? (Springer, 2017), pp. 3–60, at pp. 18–19.
21
See R. Michaels, ‘EU Law as Private International Law? Reconceptualising the Country-
of-Origin Principle as Vested Rights Theory’ (2006) 2 Journal of Private International
Law 195–242.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
the nineteenth century: it is impossible to say that a right is ‘vested’ under
foreign law unless we determine previously that the law under which it
‘vested’ is actually applicable.22
It is worth noting that the vested rights theory continues to have a
(limited) existence in the enforcement of foreign judgements. Previously,
foreign judgements were not actually enforced but merely treated as
(irrebuttable) evidence for the existence of a claim that was then enforced
under the forum’s own law – they were, in other words, treated as facts.
Even today, foreign judgements are, in principle, enforceable without a
reference to the foreign law on which they may be based.
22
The relevant passage is translated in K. H. Nadelmann, ‘Some Historical Notes on the
Doctrinal Sources of American Conflicts Law’, in K. H. Nadelmann, Conflict of Laws:
International and Interstate. Selected Essays (Nijhoff, 1972), pp. 1–20, at p. 16.
23
See J. Raz, ‘Incorporation by Law’ (2004) 10 Legal Theory 1–17.
24
Ibid., 10.
25
W. W. Cook, ‘The Logical and Legal Bases of the Conflict of Laws’ (1924) 33 Yale Law
Journal 457–88; R. De Novo, ‘New Trends in Italian Private International Law’ (1963) 28
Law & Contemporary Problems 808–21, at 812–13.
26
D. F. Cavers, ‘The Two “Local Law” Theories’ (1950) 63 Harvard Law Review 822–32, at
823. See also Dyzenhaus, ‘The Janus-Faced Constitution’, 31–2.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Theories that explain how it is that a foreign rule isn’t foreign law when it
is used in deciding a case in another country might seem more useful if
I could forget the way in which my son resolved a like problem when, at
the age of four, he encountered tuna fish salad. ‘Isn’t that chicken?’ he
inquired after the first bite. Told that no, indeed, it was fish, he restored
his world to order and concluded the matter by remarking to himself,
‘Fish made of chicken’.
Cavers’ son seems right. When a judge has to apply foreign law, she must,
to a great extent, attempt to apply that law in the way in which it is
applied abroad. What is demanded from her, therefore, is the actual
application of a foreign law. Replication is a cumbersome fiction, made
necessary only if we assume that cross-boundary normativity is not
possible. These shortcomings are consequences from Hart’s thinking
within one legal system, namely his own.27
27
On Hart’s ‘parochialism’ see D. Dyzenhaus, ‘Kelsen’s Contribution to Contemporary
Philosophy of International Law’ (2020), https://ssrn.com/abstract=3571343.
28
N. Roughan, Authorities: Conflicts, Cooperation, and Transnational Legal Theory (Oxford
University Press, 2013), pp. 136 et seq.
29
N. Roughan, ‘Meet Me in the Middle?’ (2019) 29 Duke Journal of Comparative &
International Law 423–36.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
sense that they deliberately limit themselves without need. The English
law on negligence is, potentially, universal. Granted, there are cases in
which an English court will not apply that law, for example with regard
to a tort committed in France, and in that sense there is a sharing of
authority. But this is in consequence of (real or potential) conflicts, not
intrinsic to English law itself.
This first problem may seem banal on its own, but it is exacerbated by
a second one. Roughan calls her mechanism of cross-border authority a
‘justified inter-authority relationship’, but while she develops criteria for
that justification, she does not say where the normative foundation of the
justification derives from. The justification does not appear to come from
one of the two authorities, but where does it rest instead? Morality?
Natural law? Practical reasoning? None of these justifications is available
to a positivist theory of law. And none of them seems to account for the
way in which each legal order in fact mediates its relation to others.
A third problem concerns the border between the authorities: who
determines it, and how? Roughan proposes that conflicting authorities
should compromise, ‘meet in the middle’. This sounds like an attractive
solution, the likely result of a (real or hypothetical) agreement between
the orders. But such difference-splitting is problematic.30 Where exactly
is that middle? Why should we think legal orders agree on the middle,
rather than on any other point of the continuum between full authority
for one or the other legal order? And how do we account for a situation
in which the authorities actually do not agree where the middle is? Must
we defer analysis until such agreement occurs or one authority ‘wins’?
30
See D. Kennedy, ‘Strategizing Strategic Behavior in Legal Interpretation’ (1996) Utah Law
Review 785–825, at 795–6, 808–9.
31
J. P. Trachtman, The Future of International Law: Global Government (Cambridge
University Press, 2013), p. 272; T. Schultz, ‘Secondary Rules of Recognition and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
determine the scope of foreign, not domestic, law. Ignoring this crucial
difference leads to significant and consequential misunderstandings.
I am not the first to propose such a concept – my tertiary rules share
certain characteristics with Nico Krisch’s interface norms and with Detlef
von Daniels’ linkage rules.32 Even the term tertiary rules has been used
before: Joel Trachtman has used it to account for rules that ‘allocate
authority among constitutions: among state constitutions, between state
constitutions and international organization constitutions, and among
international organization constitutions’.33 But the concept is not yet,
I think, sufficiently precise. In the following I try to develop a precise
concept of tertiary rules, and discuss in what ways it differs from the
other projects mentioned.
A definition of tertiary rules is not easier than a definition of secondary
rules, but here is an attempt: Tertiary rules are rules with which one legal
order designates, relative to itself, the normative space of another legal
order to which it is not hierarchically superior. This definition requires
explanation, which takes place here. Perhaps more importantly, it
requires application and examples, which will take place in Section
16.5, where three different types of tertiary rules are explicated at some-
what greater length.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Tertiary rules do indeed give normative validity to (foreign) legal rules,
but that alone does not distinguish them from secondary rules, and that
similarity does not account for existing differences. The difference is this:
secondary rules operate within one legal order – they give validity to rules
that would otherwise have no validity at all. A legislative bill that does not
obtain the required parliamentary majority does not become a valid legal
rule at all. In the transnational realm, unlike in the domestic realm, we
are confronted not only with the relations between legal rules within one
system. We are additionally confronted with the limitations and cross-
references existing between, not within legal orders. In response, tertiary
rules operate between legal orders: they extend the validity that a rule in a
foreign legal order already has into another legal order where it does not
have that validity.
This focus on foreign normativity distinguishes tertiary rules from a
whole number of techniques that respond to the existence of compet-
ing normativities through self-restraint. The presumption against
extraterritoriality is one of many examples. According to this doctrine,
courts should choose an interpretation of statutes that confines its
scope of application to the home state’s own territory. Such techniques
are not tertiary rules, however. They determine the scope of applica-
tion of a legal order’s own rules and are, as such, secondary rules,
insofar as they are directed at adjudicators or other norm interpreters.
The restriction of a rule’s scope of application is an ordinary process
within domestic law; it does not change its nature when it happens in
response to normative claims from another legal order any more than
it does when it happens in response to other normative claims. Tertiary
rules do something different: they provide normative space to foreign
legal rules.
Unlike secondary norms, tertiary rules do not provide requirements
for the change of rules and institutions of foreign orders, nor do they
provide specific rules on adjudication. The courts and rules of legal order
B never derive their validity exclusively from legal order A. Instead,
tertiary norms deal with the recognition and application of foreign insti-
tutions and rules that are already valid under foreign law. Rules of Syrian
marriage law are valid, within Syrian law, regardless of whether they are
designated by a German conflicts rule or not. This is why it would be
misleading to say that tertiary rules allocate authority. The German
conflicts rule does not create the validity of the rule per se; all it does is
extend that validity and bindingness into German law. The question for
tertiary rules is not whether a law is binding or valid in the abstract – that
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
is, in principle, determined by the legal order to which the law belongs –
but to what extent it has normative force in the concrete case in the view
of another legal order. This means, firstly, that the issue of normative
space includes not only validity and normativity but also their respective
space and limitations. The normative space granted to legal order B by
legal order A may be narrower than that which legal order B grants to
itself. It means, in addition, that what matters are not only questions of
validity and general bindingness but also of applicability.
34
This does not deny that certain moves of diplomacy can be reconceptualized as conflict-
of-laws moves: K. Knop and A. Riles, ‘Space, Time and Historical Injustice: A Feminist
Conflict-of-Laws Approach to the “Comfort Women” Settlement’ (2016) 102 Cornell Law
Review 853–928, at 885ff.
35
See K. Knop, R. Michaels and A. Riles, ‘From Multiculturalism to Technique: Feminism,
Culture, and the Conflict of Laws Style’ (2012) 64 Stanford Law Review 589–656, at
648–52.
36
Hilton v. Guyot, 159 U.S. 113, 143 (1895).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
resolve disputes. But we call only some of these ways legal, and they are
distinct through their mode.
This leads to the second, more fundamental, possible objection. Maybe
it is wrong to refer to any techniques of cross-boundary normativity as
legal. It is now widely accepted that public international law is law. But
maybe private international law is not.37 Or, put more generally (and
plausibly), the legal rules of private international law are not really
different from secondary rules within a system, whereas the relation
between legal orders, that is, cross-boundary normativity, is in reality
regulated through extra-legal norms.
This would be a category error. It may of course be possible to
describe tertiary rules as mere social practices. It is also possible to
describe, in quasi-realist fashion, what factors courts actually use in
order to resolve conflict-of-laws issues, perhaps regardless of the existing
doctrine. Notably, however, that would not distinguish tertiary rules
from other rules. For Hart, the rule of recognition was a social, not a
legal rule. Andrei Marmor argues that all secondary rules are social and
not legal rules: they describe the practice of legal officials in determining
what should and what should not count as law.38 Scandinavian legal
realism explains even primary rules as social facts, not legal rules. But
such attempts could not account for the particular mode in which such
decisions are justified, namely through invocation of legal rules and
techniques. A description of choice-of-law reasoning as the mere
following of a certain social norm cannot account for the complexity
in which this reasoning occurs, the complexity of legal technique.
Non-legal modes of negotiating between legal orders – diplomacy, for
example – may at times also be complex. But their complexity is of a
very different kind.
37
See R. Michaels, ‘Post-critical Private International Law: From Politics to Technique’, in
H. Muir Watt and D. P. Fernández Arroyo (eds), Private International Law and Global
Governance (Oxford University Press, 2014), pp. 54–69, at pp. 54, 57–8.
38
A. Marmor, Positive Law and Objective Values (Oxford University Press, 2001).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
designated. If English law designates the normative space of Moroccan
law, it does so in a horizontal way. English law is not superior to
Moroccan law, and yet designates the latter’s normative space.
It is useful, first, to distinguish tertiary rules from two other types of
rules that are not horizontal in nature. The first of these are vertical
priority rules based on hierarchy within one legal system. The supremacy
clause of the US Constitution, for example, creates, within the US legal
system, a hierarchy between federal and state law. In this hierarchy,
state law is valid only insofar as it does not exceed the normative space
of the laws of the individual states (they are valid insofar they do not
contradict federal law). Within the system of US law, the supremacy
clause is a secondary rule, just like a rule that designates the later-in-time
rule to trump the former-in-time, or the special rule to trump the
general rule.
The other type are rules that exist in a legal system that is hierarchic-
ally superior to both legal orders between which it mediates. In this sense,
public international law allocates jurisdictional authority among states.
And in this sense, EU private international law rules allocate authority
between the laws of France and Germany. These EU rules are choice-of-
law rules, but although the relation between the laws of France and
Germany may be horizontal, the relation between EU law and these
two legal orders is not.
In several ways vertical priority rules look like tertiary rules:
they designate normative spaces, and they act inter-systemically.
However, they do not operate in a horizontal way, and this makes
the difference. A tertiary hierarchy rule is uniform for all affected
legal systems. By contrast, and this is crucial, tertiary rules are not
uniform for all affected legal system. Instead, each legal system has its
own tertiary rules, and because there is no hierarchy between the
affected legal systems, all of them coexist. English law has rules
designating the normative space of rules from Moroccan law, just as
Moroccan law has rules designating the normative space of rules from
English law.
As a consequence, tertiary rules are reciprocal. However, these rules
are not necessarily symmetrical. The way in which English law designates
the normative space of Moroccan law is independent from the way in
which Moroccan law designates normative space for English law.
A fortiori, the normative space given to Moroccan law by English law
may be different from the normative space given to English law by
Moroccan law.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
It follows that there is not one but two borders between English law
and Moroccan law.39 Or, put differently, the resulting border may look
different from the perspective of each system. As a consequence, a certain
set of facts may be within the limits of English law from the perspective
of English law, and within the limits of Moroccan law from the perspec-
tive of Moroccan law (a situation private international lawyers call a true
conflict). Or, conversely, it may be within the limits of Moroccan law
from the perspective of English law, and within the limits of English law
from the perspective of Moroccan law (a situation that private inter-
national lawyers call renvoi).40
Often, there will be such symmetry, or at least mutuality, and agree-
ment on the place of the border. Often, English law will only be willing to
grant normative space to Moroccan law if and insofar as Moroccan law
grants such normative space to English law in other cases. In this sense,
reciprocity is often viewed as the foundation of international relations
and, by extension, international law. But this is only a special case, and by
far not uniformly true. Tertiary rules, as explained here, are rules of each
domestic law, not of international law. Whereas reciprocity and mutual
respect provide good reasons for having such rules, they are neither
necessary for such rules to exist, nor are they sufficient in bringing such
rules about.
16.4.4 Relationality
All of this brings about the possibility that conflicts – or, put more
neutrally, disagreements about the place of the border between legal
systems – may exist. Such conflicts are a problem of theories of law that
are not plural in nature. One legal system cannot be a system, arguably, if
it does not provide mechanisms with which conflicts are resolved.
Indeed, most legal systems provide secondary rules to resolve such
conflicts if they occur within one system. Tertiary rules make it possible
to account for the fact that, as between legal systems, conflicts can
continue to exist. Thus, it may be possible that a certain conduct is
39
See R. Michaels, ‘A Symmetry of Asymmetries? A Private-International-Law
Reconstruction of Lindahl’s Work on Boundaries’ (2019) 29 Duke Journal of
Comparative and International Law 405–22, at 419.
40
Cf. H. Kelsen, ‘Observations’ (1957) 447 Annuaire de l’Institut de droit international, II,
115; republished in C. Leben (ed.), Hans Kelsen - Écrits français de droit international
(PUF, 2001), p. 309.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
governed by English law from the perspective of English law, and at the
same time governed by Moroccan law from the perspective of Moroccan
law. This means, however, that there no longer is an independent
position from which to determine whether some rules do or do not
count as valid and applicable law. Instead, there are separate legal
systems, each of which determines what counts as law for itself (through
a rule of internal recognition) and for other orders (through a rule of
external recognition). The normative space of each legal system differs
depending on the legal system from which it is designated.
The biggest challenge then from tertiary rules – the main reason why
they are so hard to conceptualize from the perspective of traditional legal
theory – is their relationality.41 What is meant by relationality is this: the
tertiary rules of English law designate normative spaces of foreign laws
only relative to English law itself. English law cannot designate the
normative space of Moroccan law with binding force for any order other
than English law. It can certainly not bind Moroccan law: if a rule of
Moroccan law is held to be inapplicable by a court in London, this does
not mean that it is inapplicable from the perspective of Moroccan law.
Nor can English law bind a third legal system, for example Japanese law
with regard to Japan’s own designation of the normative space of
Moroccan law. If a rule of Moroccan law is held to be inapplicable by a
court in London, Japan remains free to hold the rule applicable in
relation to Japan.
On the flipside, a legal order cannot designate its own normative space
with binding force for any other legal order. Certainly, it would be
unusual for a court in Morocco to consider a rule of English law
applicable even though an English court would not apply it. But it would
be perfectly possible. For example, take a case in which Moroccan law
designates the law of nationality to be the applicable law, whereas English
law designates the law of the domicile to be applicable. In that case,
arguably, Moroccan law would limit the normative space of its own legal
order so that it would not include an Englishman domiciled in Morocco.
Nonetheless, an English court would be free to apply Moroccan law to
this person regardless.42
This relationality and relativity of a concept of law are necessary
consequences of global legal pluralism. We no longer have an
Archimedean point from which we can determine whether something
41
See already Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition’.
42
The English court would indeed do so, provided it did not apply the doctrine of renvoi.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
is or is not law. If we accept that the definition of law is itself the fruit of
the operation of legal rules, then we have to find these rules in the law.
And if laws are interrelated, then we can find these rules not merely
within each legal system, but must instead look within other legal
systems, too. Because such rules operate between legal systems only, they
lead to a relational concept of law. The nature of law, the normative space
of law, is no longer determined in an absolute fashion but only relative to
other legal systems. Something can be a legal order vis-à-vis one other
legal system, but not vis-à-vis another legal system. The nature of a legal
system exists in relation to another legal system. The normative space of
a legal system in the world is determined, in part, by other legal systems.
43
This is discussed in more detail in Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
recognition, by contrast, determines the binding force of another legal
system. It is therefore properly called a rule of external recognition. That
external recognition cannot be universal, as was seen before. An Italian
judge can recognize Islamic law as law with effect only for Italian law, not
in general. On the other side, the rule of internal recognition is also
relative in this way, as Hart himself recognized. The rule of recognition of
English law designates English law as binding (as law) only with force for
the English.
Second, although both rules of internal and of external recognition
create the possibility of normative spaces, they do so in different ways.
The rule of internal recognition creates lawmaking power – without it,
the recognized institutions would have no lawmaking power at all. The
rule of external recognition, by contrast, does not create lawmaking
power. The lawmaking power of a Palestinian legislator does not depend
on recognition by English law. What does depend on that recognition is
the normative space of resulting law, with regard to English law.
Third, whereas there is debate over whether the rule of internal
recognition is a legal rule or a social fact, the rule of external recognition,
as understood here, is undoubtedly a legal rule. The recognition of
Moroccan law for English law is an operation of English law. That
operation may of course be brought about by factual acts, like a declar-
ation of recognition by a head of state. But that does not distinguish it
from other operations: most legal operations are brought about by a
factual act. If a pronouncement by the head of state of legal order A can
bring about the potential bindingness of laws and decisions of legal order
B for legal order A, then this is not a social fact but a consequence of the
rules of legal order B.
Fourth, whereas the rule of internal recognition is often discussed but
rarely practically relevant, the rule of external recognition is actually
important. The rule of internal recognition is largely irrelevant because
the operation of legal orders depends largely on the self-reinforcing day-
to-day operations of the law, based on the mutual and tacit, though rarely
effectively expressed or doubted, assumption of a valid recognition. If, for
example, some citizens in the southern states of the United States, or the
so-called Reichsbürger in Germany, refuse to recognize the authority of
their own governments, this is irrelevant not merely because they are
unjustified in their refusal, but also (mainly) because their recognition is
relatively unimportant. The rule of internal recognition is rarely ques-
tioned. By contrast, the recognition of foreign law as law is frequently
relevant. This is not only the familiar question of illegitimate
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
governments or of failed states, not even only that of non-recognized
states, but also the question of the ability to make law more generally.
44
See C. Jannsens, The Principle of Mutual Recognition in EU Law (Oxford University
Press, 2013); K. Lenaerts, ‘The Principle of Mutual Recognition in the Area of Freedom,
Security and Justice’, The Fourth Annual Sir Jeremy Lever Lecture (All Souls College,
University of Oxford 2015), www.law.ox.ac.uk/sites/files/oxlaw/the_principle_of_
mutual_recognition_in_the_area_of_freedom_judge_lenaerts.pdf .
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
under these conditions is a function of US law (in addition to inter-
national law, which I will ignore for purposes of the argument here).45
But it would be odd to claim that the United States, through its secondary
rules, authorized the German authorities to create valid passports. The
United States does have secondary rules for its own passports, which
designate both the competent authorities to create passports and the
processes through which this production takes place. It does not apply
those rules to German passports, however.
The passport’s validity under German law alone does not, however,
make it binding on US authorities. Rather, whether the passport is
recognized – and whether additional requirements must be met – is a
function of a tertiary rule of US law. It is that rule that designates
normative force to the passport vis-à-vis US authorities.
Documents may serve as the clearest example of recognition, but they
are not the only one. Another example concerns the recognition of
administrative acts. There is a question, for example, whether country
A should, in regulating the conduct of corporation X, take into account
that corporation X received a permit for its conduct from country
B. Under the principle of mutual recognition, there is a wide-ranging
duty to recognize such permits, but that duty, as emerging from a
hierarchically superior order, does not count as a tertiary rule. Such
recognition is the object of tertiary rules, however, insofar it emerges
from rules of the recognizing legal order itself.
Another example can be found in the recognition of foreign arrest
warrants. Take the European arrest warrant.46 This warrant is issued not
by a European authority but instead by one member state; it is, however,
with few exceptions, recognized and enforced by other member states.
Here, recognition does not go to a private privilege that an individual or a
corporation wants to carry with them across boundaries, but instead
expands the normative space of a foreign warrant beyond the territorial
borders that would normally limit a sovereign’s executive jurisdiction.
Again, insofar as the duty emerges from EU law, it follows from a vertical
45
International law obliges states to recognize foreign passports, but whether they do this
remains a function of their own sovereign decision. For the interplay, see, R. A. C. Alton
and J. R. Struble, ‘The Nature of a Passport at the Intersection of Customary International
Law and American Judicial Practice’ (2010) 16 Annual Survey of International and
Comparative Law 9–18.
46
See V. Mitsilegas, ‘Judicial Dialogue, Legal Pluralism and Mutual Trust in Europe’s Area
of Criminal Justice’ (forthcoming) European Law Review.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
hierarchy rule. By contrast, if one country recognizes a foreign arrest
warrant on its own, such recognition is a matter of a tertiary rule.
Finally, the recognition and enforcement of foreign civil and commer-
cial judgements can count as an example for this type of tertiary rule. The
old common law rule, by which judgements provided rights which, by
themselves, the winning party could enforce anywhere, was incompatible
not only with the idea of sovereignty but also with the justified interest of
legal orders to refuse recognition and enforcement to judgements they
considered incompatible with certain important values. By themselves,
judgements bind only within the borders of the sovereign whose courts
issued them. This is why a French seventeenth-century statute declared
all foreign judgements to be without force in France, and why some
countries still, technically, refuse to recognize and enforce foreign judge-
ments outside of a treaty. In such systems, a foreign judgement can be
considered as a fact, perhaps even, as in some theories, as irrefutable
evidence of the existence of the underlying right. It can also be internal-
ized into the enforcing legal order, as is the case in the technique of
naturalization of foreign judgements. Modern theories (and practices) of
judgement recognition follow neither of these twisted techniques, how-
ever. Instead, foreign judgements are recognized and enforced and
thereby given normative space beyond their traditional borders.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Nonetheless, many explanations of private international law try to
explain its rules by denying one of the criteria found here for tertiary
rules. The vested rights theory as a theory denying normativity was
already explained in Section 16.3.1. Another theory of private inter-
national law, the so-called datum theory, also denies foreign normativity
and claims to consider foreign rules as mere facts (data). That approach
has found a recent application in Article 17 of the Rome II Regulation,
which mandates that ‘account shall be taken, as a matter of fact and in so
far as is appropriate, of the rules of safety and conduct which were in
force at the place and time of the event giving rise to the liability’. The
wording demonstrates the desire to avoid normativity, but it can hardly
be denied that such ‘taking into account’ will often, effectively, amount to
application. How else should such rules be taken into account if not in
their normativity?
What choice-of-law rules do is to designate the normative space of law.
An English rule that designates Moroccan law as applicable to a certain
conduct thereby designates a normative space that Moroccan law would
not otherwise have. Moroccan law might (or indeed might not) be
applicable to the relevant facts relative to itself, that is, from the perspec-
tive of a Moroccan judge. But that normative space would not exist
universally. An English private international law rule cannot make the
space universal either. What it can do, however, is to designate a norma-
tive space relative to English law, that is, from the perspective of an
English judge.
16.6 Conclusion
In this chapter I have argued that some rules that exist in legal systems
cannot be understood as either primary or secondary rules but constitute
a different type of rules, called tertiary rules. These are the rules with
which a legal system organizes its own relation to other legal systems and
also designates those other legal systems’ normative space with regard to
itself. Those rules have proven to be more complex than primary and
secondary rules, and incompatible with certain postulates of traditional
theories of legal systems that emphasize internal coherence and consist-
ency. They are the consequence of a plural world in which law is not one
but many.
Recognizing tertiary rules is thus necessary for a pluralistic theory of
laws. However, the recognition of tertiary rules is not dependent on the
recognition of such a theory. Tertiary rules are an actually observable
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
category of rules within legal systems. This chapter does not invent them,
it merely brings them together and describes their qualities. If anything,
therefore, a pluralistic theory of laws is a necessary consequence of the
recognition of tertiary rules which do not have a proper space in monist
theories of law.
Regardless of such a theory, the concept of tertiary rules ought to be of
both theoretical and practical interest. Theoretically, they represent an
important category of rules and are instructive for the way in which such
rules operate across borders. Practically, they help see commonalities
between rules in different areas of law. And they help see differences
from other rules, like rules of unilateral restraint, or from non-legal
mechanisms to resolve normative conflicts. They thereby also provide
ammunition against those who claim that conflicts of laws cannot be
resolved except in extra-legal ways. The recognition of tertiary rules
demonstrates that law is more varied and therefore more flexible that
one may think on the basis of monist legal theories.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
17
For their helpful critical comments on earlier drafts, I thank Nico Krisch, Hanna
Birkenkotter, Sarah Nouwen and Ralf Michaels.
1
W. Twining, ‘Normative and Legal Pluralism: A Global Perspective’ (2010) 20 Duke
Journal of Comparative and International Law 473–518, at 487.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
outset and reappears in global legal pluralism, particularly in the work of
Paul Berman. Then I show why theoretical concepts of law cannot solve
this flaw, which ultimately led John Griffiths – the foremost champion of
legal pluralism – to repudiate the notion. I then address the profusion of
private and hybrid regulatory forms on the domestic and transnational
levels, and I mark the line between theory and practice. Thereafter,
I expose problems with the relational concept of law formulated by
Ralf Michaels, showing why it is unsuitable for many situations of legal
pluralism. These critical examinations lay a basis for the constructive
account that follows. The approach to legal pluralism I articulate involves
social constructions conventionally identified as law that vary and change
over time, which can be grouped in terms of three categories: community
law, regime law and cross-polity law. Finally, I set forth a handful of
specific lessons for a reconstructed transnational legal pluralism.
2
R. Michaels, ‘Global Legal Pluralism’ (2009) 5 Annual Review of Law and Social Sciences
243–62, at 244.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
This narrative, however, is misleading. Other than being about ‘law’
(though in different senses) and shining the spotlight on ‘pluralism’
(albeit in different senses), these three approaches have little in common.
John Griffiths, the leading proponent of the second approach, pointedly
rejected the first approach. He labelled postcolonial legal pluralism ‘weak’
because it involved recognition by the state of customary law, which
Griffiths construed as merely reinforcing legal centralism. ‘“Legal plural-
ism” in the weak [postcolonial] sense has little to do with the concept of
legal pluralism which is the subject of this article’,3 he declared, sharply
distancing his sociological conception from studies of postcolonial law.
Griffiths’ essay centres on ‘strong’ legal pluralism – ‘an empirical state
of affairs, namely the coexistence within a social group of legal orders
which do not belong to a single system’.4 This legal pluralism is based on
a sociological concept of law, which encompasses the normative ordering
of social associations and institutionalized rule systems generally (more
on this shortly). As Sally Engle Merry noted three decades ago in her
astute overview of legal pluralism, which boosted its academic profile,
these two contexts of legal pluralism ‘make odd companions’ in that they
have different targets and ‘they come out of different scholarly trad-
itions’.5 In Kuhnian terms, this is a revolutionary paradigm shift, not a
cumulative building on previous insights.
Comparative, international and transnational legal scholars who came
to legal pluralism changed the subject yet again, in multiple ways.
Contemporary global/transnational legal pluralism is the product mainly
of jurists who focus on public and private systems of law and regulation
between and across states, giving rise to multiple coexisting regulatory
forms with potential application in various contexts. Constitutional plur-
alism of the European Union involves the pluralism of coexisting, inter-
twined official systems of national and EU law; international legal
pluralism (or fragmentation) involves a pluralism of different subject
matter regimes and tribunals within international law. None of this
resembles postcolonial legal pluralism or sociological legal pluralism.
The characteristic feature of postcolonial legal pluralism is the coexist-
ence of bodies of law with profoundly different norms and processes –
mainly state law, and customary and religious law – operating
3
J. Griffiths, ‘What Is Legal Pluralism?’ (1986) 24 Journal of Legal Pluralism 1–56, at 8.
4
Ibid., 8.
5
S. E. Merry, ‘Legal Pluralism’ (1988) 22 Law & Society Review 869–96, at 874.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
independently as well as intertwined in various ways. A report issued by
the World Bank legal department observes:
In many developing countries, customary systems operating outside of
the state regime are often the dominant form of regulation and dispute
resolution, covering up to 90% of the population in parts of Africa. In
Sierra Leone, for example, approximately 85% of the population falls
under the jurisdiction of customary law, defined under the Constitution
as ‘the rules which, by custom, are applicable to particular communities in
Sierra Leone’. Customary tenure covers 75% of land in most African
countries, affecting 90% of land transactions in countries like
Mozambique and Ghana [. . .] In many of these countries, systems of
justice seem to operate almost completely independently of the official
state system.6
6
L. Chirayath, C. Sage, and M. Woolcock, Customary Law and Policy Reform: Engaging
with the Plurality of Justice Systems (World Bank Legal Department Paper, 2005), p. 3.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The point, again, is that these situations of legal pluralism have very
little in common. The claim of continuity between the first (postcolonial)
and third (global) approaches to legal pluralism trades on two distinct
connotations of pluralism: diversity and multiplicity. The former is fun-
damentally about legal diversity while the latter is about legal multipli-
city. The former is largely the product of legal anthropologists exploring
the various social consequences of these contrasting coexisting bodies of
law; and most of these works are not juristically oriented. The latter
largely involves academic jurists – many of whom are Europeans grap-
pling with the interaction between EU law and national law – focusing on
harmonization, reconciliation, assimilation, discussing choice of law and
conflicts of law, jurisdiction and the like.
The differences between the second (sociological) and third (global)
approaches to legal pluralism are also substantial – again grounded in
fundamentally different orientations and objectives. The second
approach was pioneered by sociologists whose goal was to construct a
science of society around a sociological concept of law. A scientific
positivist, John Griffiths was explicit about this objective:
Thus, if concepts such as law, legalness, and social control are to figure in
sociological theory, they must be taken as referring to identifiable social
facts, and variation in those social facts should ultimately be expressible in
quantitative terms.
The first problem for the sociology of law, given the preceding assump-
tions, is to identify the sort of social fact it takes as its subject matter.7
7
J. Griffiths, ‘The Division of Labor in Social Control’, in D. Black (ed.), Toward a General
Theory of Social Control (Academic Press, 1984), pp. 37–70, at p. 39 (italics added).
8
G. Teubner, ‘Two Faces of Janus: Rethinking Legal Pluralism’ (1991) 13 Cardozo Law
Review 1443–62.
9
Ibid., 1457.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
early theorist of transnational legal pluralism, Boaventura de Sousa
Santos, also had a sociological orientation, though from a postmodern
perspective that eschewed a systematic science of society.10 However,
most contemporary global/transnational legal pluralists are not sociolo-
gists engaged in scientific theorizing about law, but are academic jurists
largely focusing on, mapping and grappling with the multiplicity of
transnational regulatory forms and their various modes of interaction
and entanglement.11 Owing to these different backgrounds and object-
ives, what the second (sociological) approach to legal pluralism is about is
radically different from what the third (global) approach is about.
Understood on its own terms, this latest take on legal pluralism repre-
sents yet another revolutionary paradigm change. The only connective
link is that global legal pluralists regularly refer to the work of Griffiths,
Moore and Ehrlich, derived from the sociological approach. This link,
however, gives rise to irresolvable conceptual difficulties and disputes and
should be discarded for reasons I explain in Sections 17.2 and 17.3.
William Twining, who has written extensively about globalization as
well as about legal pluralism,12 found that ‘the many extensions and
applications of the idea of legal pluralism to new phenomena and
situations are so many and so varied that it is difficult to construct a
coherent answer to the question: what is the relevance of classical studies
of legal pluralism to the emerging field of “global legal pluralism”?’13
My point is that any relevance is minimal.14
10
B. de Sousa Santos, ‘Law: A Map of Misreading – Toward a Postmodern Conception of
Law’ (1987) 14 Journal of Law and Society 279–302; B. de Sousa Santos, Toward a New
Common Sense: Law, Science and Politics in the Paradigmatic Transition (Routledge,
1995).
11
See Chapter 1.
12
See W. Twining, General Jurisprudence: Understanding Law from a Global Perspective
(Cambridge University Press, 2009).
13
Twining, ‘Normative and Legal Pluralism’, 512–13.
14
Twining denied ‘any strong claims to continuity’, though he observed that global legal
pluralism exhibited a similar opposition to state centrism, recognition of non-state law,
taking religion seriously and more of an empirical orientation. Ibid., 515.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
stop speaking of law and find ourselves simply describing social life? Is it
useful to call all these forms of ordering law? I find that once legal
centralism has been vanquished, calling all forms of ordering that are
not state law by the term law confounds the analysis.’15 The sociological
conception of legal pluralism construes the normative ordering of social
associations (like the family) and institutionalized rule systems (like
corporations and universities) as forms of law. In Section 17.3,
I explain the source of this problem and why it cannot be resolved, but
here I flag its appearance in global legal pluralism.
Paul Berman, a prolific contemporary theorist of global legal plural-
ism, asserts that there is no need to define law. Yet, in effect, he presup-
poses a conception of law tied to social associations, but without
explicitly articulating it.16 Berman identifies law with norm-generating
communities: ‘From religious institutions, to industry standard-setting
bodies to not-for-profit accreditation entities to arbitral panels to univer-
sity tenure committees to codes promulgated within ethnic enclaves to
self-regulation regimes in semi-autonomous communities, the sites of
non-state lawmaking are truly everywhere.’17 (His reference to self-
regulation of semi-autonomous communities incorporates Sally Falk
Moore’s analysis, which I take up in Section 17.3) Berman has also
identified law within the family18 and ‘in day-to-day human encounters
such as interacting with strangers on a public street, waiting in lines, and
communicating with subordinates or superiors’.19 These examples reveal
that for Berman virtually all normative ordering is law. As a consequence,
law is a fuzzy notion and legal pluralism is extraordinarily pervasive.
In a recently published 1,000-plus-page Oxford Handbook on Global
Legal Pluralism (2020) that Berman edited, he makes a revealing state-
ment. After acknowledging that global legal pluralism is not really global
15
Merry, ‘Legal Pluralism’, 878–9.
16
By not making his concept of law explicit, Berman shields it from critical scrutiny and
denies the need to justify it. Berman has cited my position in support of his, but his
position is not mine. He applies an implicit concept of law, while refusing to specify what
it is. My position is that no abstract concept or definition of law comes into play in the
analysis, implicitly or explicitly; instead, I utilize collective identification of law in the
social arena at issue.
17
P. Berman, Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law beyond Borders (Cambridge
University Press, 2012), pp. 41–2.
18
P. Berman, ‘The New Legal Pluralism’ (2009) 5 Annual Review of Law and Social Science
225–42, at 236.
19
P. S. Berman, ‘The Globalization of Jurisdiction’ (2002) 151 University of Pennsylvania
Law Review 311–545, at 505.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
in reach and not fully pluralist (because he disallows illiberal values),
Berman observes: ‘Indeed, given the broad (and often undefined) vision
of law embraced by legal pluralists, it is perhaps not properly considered
“legal” either!’20 Global legal pluralism, under his conception, extends far
beyond law to encompass normative pluralism generally. This conceptu-
ally confused stance – the source of which lies in sociological legal
pluralism – confounds the analysis, as Merry observed three decades ago.
Not only is this understanding of law overinclusive, but global legal
pluralism is also all inclusive to an extent that borders on meaningless-
ness or totalizing ambition. Global legal pluralism apparently purports to
encompass all legal orders in the world – local, state, transnational,
customary, religious, non-state, etc. – considered together in a vast
bottomless bucket. If the assertion is that all legal orders in the world
in the aggregate constitutes legal pluralism, it is a true but empty claim; if
the claim is that their framework applies to all legal orders in the world
considered together or whenever legal multiplicities of any kind arise, it is
an audacious claim. Legal pluralism is everywhere, in so many different
manifestations and variations that no single framework can capture it all
except in the most general descriptive terms.
20
P. S. Berman, ‘Understanding Global Legal Pluralism: From Local to Global, from
Descriptive to Normative’, in P. S. Berman (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Global Legal
Pluralism (Oxford University Press, 2020), p. 62, https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers
.cfm?abstract_id=3715553.
21
J. Griffiths, ‘The Idea of Sociology of Law and its Relation to Law and to Sociology’ (2006)
8 Current Legal Issues 49–68, at 63–4. For helping him come to this realization, Griffiths
cites a Dutch article by G. van den Bergh, and two of my articles, ‘An Analytical Map of
Social Scientific Approaches to the Concept of Law’ (1995) 15 Oxford Journal of Legal
Studies 501–36, and ‘The Folly of the Social Scientific Concept of Legal Pluralism’ (1993)
20 Journal of Law and Society 192–217.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
This is a stunning reversal for Griffiths. To renounce a doctrine that
brought him academic renown is a testament to his inestimable intellec-
tual integrity. What doomed sociological legal pluralism is the problem
of overinclusiveness.
This insurmountable problem is detailed in other work,22 so here
I present a drastically abbreviated account. Almost all sociological as well
as jurisprudential concepts of law involve specifications of function and
form (structure). (This is true of all efforts to define social artefacts; for
example, a standard definition of a ‘chair’ is a seat (function) with legs
and a back (form).) While numerous variations exist, conceptions of law
fall into two basic streams. The first stream encompasses the normative
ordering of social associations (focused on law’s function) – put forth by
Griffiths, who melded Eugen Ehrlich’s living law with Sally Falk Moore’s
semi-autonomous social field. The second stream encompasses institu-
tionalized rule systems (a combination of function and form) – put forth
by Marc Galanter, who drew on H. L. A. Hart’s union of primary and
secondary rules.
The problem with identifying law as the normative ordering of social
institutions (the first stream), as Eugen Ehrlich did, including clubs,
community organizationsand business partnerships, is that a variety of
social mechanisms – customs, morals, habits, reciprocity, etc. – are
involved in the ordering of social associations. Defining law in terms of
the ordering of associations inevitably encompasses all of this. Jurists at
the time rejected his concept of law for this reason. Legal philosopher
Morris Cohen objected: ‘Ehrlich’s book suffers from the fact that it draws
no clear account of what he means by law and how he distinguishes it
from customs and morals.’23 John Griffiths concluded that Ehrlich’s
‘theory therefore lacks an independent criterion of “the legal”. He seems
to take it as obvious which sorts of rules of conduct are legal in charac-
ter.’24 Griffiths turned to Sally Moore’s semi-autonomous social field
(SASF), declaring: ‘law is the self-regulation of a semi-autonomous social
field’.25 However, Moore herself refused to use the label ‘law’ (she
proposed ‘reglementation’) owing to the same objection: an array of
22
See B. Z. Tamanaha, Legal Pluralism Explained: History, Theory, Consequences (Oxford
University Press, 2021).
23
M. R. Cohen, ‘Recent Philosophical Literature: Legal Literature in French, German, and
Italian’ (1916) 26 International Journal of Ethics 528–46, at 537.
24
Griffiths, ‘What Is Legal Pluralism?’, 27.
25
Ibid., 38.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
mechanisms support the rule-bound ordering within social groups that
her SASF centres on, including moral norms, reciprocity, potential loss of
future benefits and social ostracism. Griffiths understood that his con-
ception of law encompasses a broad continuum of normative ordering,
from informal to institutionalized, which led him to conclude that ‘all
social control is more or less legal’.26 This position results in the assertion
(per Berman) that law encompasses people queuing at a bar or bank.
The conception of law as institutionalized rule systems (the second
stream) is an abstract reduction of state legal systems, presenting law as
an institutionalized rule system (form) that enacts and enforces norms
for social ordering (function). An influential early work on legal plural-
ism, Marc Galanter’s ‘Justice in Many Rooms: Courts, Private Ordering,
and Indigenous Law’ (1981),27 builds on H. L. A. Hart’s account, defining
law in terms of ‘the organization and differentiation of norms and
sanctions. The differentiation is the introduction of a second layer of
control – or norms about the application of norms.’28 Since society is
filled with institutionalized norm-enforcement systems, it follows that
law is ‘found in a variety of institutional settings – in universities, sports
leagues, housing developments, hospitals, etc.’.29 A century ago, Italian
jurist Santi Romano articulated a theory of legal pluralism that takes this
line of thinking to its utmost extension, asserting that every institution is
a legal order and every legal order is an institution.30 Legal orders, in this
view, include states, municipalities, corporations, factories, political
parties, a prison, a church, a family, a criminal gang and much more.31
In a recent essay acknowledging legal pluralism, legal philosopher Joseph
Raz likewise identifies law in ‘the rules and regulations governing the
activities of voluntary associations, or those of legally recognized corpor-
ations, and more, including many very transient phenomena, like neigh-
bourhood gangs’.32 The legal institutions he has in mind, Raz elaborates,
‘are themselves rule-governed, ultimately governed by practice-based
26
Ibid., 39 n. 3.
27
M. Galanter, ‘Justice in Many Rooms: Courts, Private Ordering, and Indigenous Law’
(1981) 19 Journal of Legal Pluralism 1–48, at 2.
28
Ibid., 19.
29
Ibid., 17–18.
30
S. Romano, The Legal Order (Routledge 2017).
31
For a concise description of Romano’s account of law, see L. Vinx, ‘Santi-Romano against
the State?’ (2018) 11 Ethics and Global Politics 25–36.
32
J. Raz, ‘Why the State?’, in N. Roughan and A. Halpin (eds), In Pursuit of Pluralist
Jurisprudence (Cambridge University Press 2017) pp. 136–62, at p. 138.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
rules that determine if not all at least the most important aspects of their
constitution, powers, and mode of operation’.33 ‘In this sense’, he con-
tinues, ‘both the rules of the Roman Republic and those of the University
of Wales (disbanded 2011), just as the rules of the United States and of
Columbia University, are legal systems.’34
At bottom, these two streams of conceptions of law involve exercises in
relabeling. The first stream relabels the normative ordering of social
associations as legal ordering; the second stream relabels institutionalized
rule systems as law. Through this relabeling, both approaches immedi-
ately produce an immense profusion of law in society. However, their
conflation of law with broader social phenomena is theoretically unjusti-
fied and results in confusion. Rather than assert that all forms of social
control are more or less legal or that all institutionalized rule systems are
law, it makes far more sense to assert that multiple forms of social control
exist, some of which are law, and that innumerable institutionalized rule
systems exist, some of which of are law.
The most straightforward way to identify law from among the multi-
tude of normative orderings and institutionalized rule systems in society
is via conventional recognition of what is ‘law’ (droit, loi, lex, ius, recht,
gesetz, diritto, prawo, horitsu, fa, etc.) – which I elaborate further in
Section 17.7. The legal systems of France and Massachusetts (etc.) are
conventionally perceived as law, but not the internal rule systems of Saint
Laurent or Harvard (etc.), which are seen as rule systems specific to the
purposes of the organization. International law is law, not because it
satisfies abstract criteria of legality based on form, function or some other
basis (which no theorist has successfully formulated), but because it is
conventionally recognized as law by jurists, political leaders and the
public.35
33
Ibid., p. 142.
34
Ibid., p. 143 (emphasis added).
35
For a discussion showing the legal status of international law, see B. Z. Tamanaha,
A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017), chapter 6.
36
See Chapter 10.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
Alimentarius Commission on food standards, voluntary ‘soft law’ provi-
sions like corporate codes of conduct and UNIDROIT Principles of
International Commercial Contracts, International Organization for
Standardization and an increasing multitude more. The domestic level
has also witnessed a proliferation of private and hybrid bodies carrying
out legal functions, with the expansion of private arbitration, private
policing (gated communities, universities, sports venues, shopping malls,
etc.), private prisons (common in the USA) and private standard setting.
The underlying cause of the explosion of private and hybrid regulation
is plain: governments and public bodies lack the capacity to produce and
carry out the regulatory activities necessary to deal with countless trans-
actions and intercourse within society and across societies. It has long
been common for regulatory standards to be produced by private organ-
izations tied to non-profit consumer associations or trade associations in
specific industries, which have the requisite expertise as well as an
interest in maintaining quality and safety standards (as well as creating
barriers to entry against potential new competitors). Domestic and trans-
national private standard setting are frequently connected. The American
National Standards Institute (ANSI), a private organization created in
1918, accredits standards produced by private standard-setting organiza-
tions (many of which have been adopted by state regulators) across a
broad swath of matters (electrical standards, chemical standards, public
health standards, and so forth); ANSI is a member of the International
Organization for Standardization as well as the International
Accreditation Forum, propagating American standards more broadly as
well as introducing externally produced standards into the USA.
In addition, private organizations have long established and enforced
their own rule systems on their employees and consumers and users of
their goods and services. Twitter and Facebook famously demonstrated
this power in the aftermath of the insurrection on the Capitol building
when they banned President Donald Trump from using their platforms
for repeated violations of their terms of service. Private companies can
also directly enforce state law. Google enforces the EU’s ‘right to be
forgotten law’, thus far rendering judgements on over 845,000 requests,
delisting 45 per cent of the links.37 As Galanter made clear four decades
ago, a far greater amount of rule enforcement affecting people’s lives
takes place within private institutionalized rule systems than through
37
See L. Kelion, ‘Google Wins Landmark Right to be Forgotten Case’, BBC News
(23 September 2019), www.bbc.com/news/technology-49808208.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
state law, and private regulation has vastly increased since that time at
domestic and transnational levels.
These private and hybrid regulatory phenomena are undoubtedly
important. The issue for theorists and jurists is how they should be
characterized. They carry out legal functions, many are structured like
legal institutions and their rules and processes often supplement state
law. Based on these similarities, leading transnational legal pluralist
theorists have swept these phenomena within law – asserting that they
are law or that law is a matter of degree, thereby encompassing these
regulatory forms. This approach, however, inevitably results in the
overinclusiveness problem identified above (including as law univer-
sities, hospitals or corporations). A simpler approach is to call them
what they are – private and hybrid regulatory forms – noting the
manifold respects in which they are law-like and identifying the various
ways in which they interact with law. Rather than hold that all forms of
regulation are law, it is more sensible to see regulation as a broad
category, certain manifestations of which are law (conventionally rec-
ognized as such), while many others carry out legal functions but are
not law per se. All the same observations can be made by jurists and
theorists without stumbling over irresolvable theoretical hurdles involv-
ing the concept of law.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
he proposes that law involves institutionalized doctrine.38 Berman seeks
to develop for jurists ‘procedural mechanisms, institutions, and practices
that aim to manage, without eliminating, the legal pluralism we see
around us’.39 But it is doubtful that lawyers need or will utilize theoretical
concepts of law and legal pluralism, since they have been dealing with
these phenomena for many decades without such theories – and how
would they decide which is correct among the many theories of law
proposed in the literature? Few, if any, judges or lawyers would find
useful Berman’s assertion that law includes people queuing to get into a
bar. While it is common for academic jurists to construct frameworks for
lawyers and judges, they typically do so working with the same legal
materials, analysing applicable doctrines and legal mechanisms from the
internal standpoint of a jurist. In contrast, sociological and theoretical
concepts produced from an external standpoint – law as institutionalized
normative orders, autopoiesis, networks, entanglement, interlegality, the
semi-autonomous social field and other theoretical constructs referred to
in the literature – have little application in juridical tasks. Theory and
practice are different enterprises.
38
R. Cotterrell, ‘Do Lawyers Need a Theory of Legal Pluralism?’, in Roughan and Halpin
(eds), In Pursuit of Pluralist Jurisprudence, pp. 20–39.
39
P. S. Berman, ‘Jurisgenerative Constitutionalism: Procedural Principles for Managing
Global Legal Pluralism’ (2013) 20 Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 665–95, at
668–69.
40
See Chapter 16; R. Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition: Towards a Relational Concept of
Law’, in Roughan and Halpin (eds), In Pursuit of Pluralist Jurisprudence, pp. 90–115.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
recognition requirement and turn it into a general requirement of law – a
requirement that exists not just for non-state law, but for state law as well.
A legal order, in this definition, requires not two but three kinds of rules.
It requires primary rules as its content. It requires secondary rules for its
operation. And it requires tertiary rules to establish its relation with other
legal orders, whether they are called interface norms, linkage rules or
something else. The suggestion that such tertiary rules are a necessary
element of legal systems should not be so provocative.41
41
Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition’, pp. 107–8 (emphasis added). The reference to interface
norms is from N. Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of
Postnational Law (Oxford University Press, 2012); and the reference to linkage rules is
from D. von Daniels, The Concept of Law from a Transnational Perspective (Ashgate,
2010).
42
Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition’, p. 105.
43
Ibid., p. 106.
44
Ibid., p. 110.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
legal systems – which is a common occurrence in the history of legal
pluralism. Since the vast bulk of what legal systems typically address
relate to internal effectiveness, Michaels does not explain why a lack of
external effectiveness – which it can function without – justifies the
conclusion that an internally effective system is not law. A second prob-
lem is that a system can go from being not law until receiving external
recognition, then becoming law upon recognition, then not law when
recognition is withdrawn, then law again when recognition is restored
(and so on) – with its legal status dictated entirely at the whims and
interests of the external system (an example follows).
The third problem is a conceptual flaw within the relational theory
itself. If a necessary element to qualify as law is external recognition by
another legal system, as Michaels contends, then that in itself does not
necessitate tertiary rules within the system to establish relations with
others. As long as another legal system recognizes it, a given legal system
exists even if it does not recognize any other legal system on its part.
Since external recognition in his scheme is not conditioned upon recipro-
cal recognition, there is no logical basis in his theory for requiring tertiary
rules within a given system as a necessary feature of law. His account
requires only: (1) primary rules of content, (2) secondary rules of oper-
ation and (3) receiving external recognition. In Hart’s account, to sup-
plement his union of primary and secondary rules, he identified two
minimum conditions for the existence of a legal system: the populace
must generally obey the primary rules, and legal officials must accept the
secondary rules.45 Similarly, Michaels’ requirement of receiving external
recognition does not itself give rise to a third distinct body of rules, and
indeed it is not about rules at all. Instead, what his justification calls for is
another existence condition: an external legal system must recognize it as
law to be effective.
This conclusion reveals that his tertiary rules are neither necessary nor
sufficient to constitute law. Assume System A has primary, secondary
and tertiary rules – thus possessing the three features he identifies as
essential to law. However, if System B does not recognize A as a legal
system, it is not a legal system with respect to B. As Michaels put it,
‘System A can only determine whether and how it recognizes System
B and insofar be constitutive for System B. It cannot determine whether
45
Hart’s justifications for these two conditions were functionality and efficacy. If legal
officials do not accept the secondary rules the system cannot function, and if the populace
does not obey the primary rules it would be ineffective.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
and how System B recognizes System A.’46 So having tertiary rules (on
top of primary and secondary) is not sufficient to constitute A as law with
respect to B. Now assume System A has primary and secondary rules, but
not tertiary rules – thus lacking what he identifies as an essential feature
of law. If System B nonetheless recognizes A as a legal system, it does
count as law for B. So tertiary rules are not necessary to constitute law. It
turns out that tertiary rules, Michaels’ key addition to Hart’s concept of
law, are not actually essential to constituting law under his own
conceptual scheme.
The conceptual soundness of his theory of laws (positing pluralism
and interrelatedness as intrinsic) must be evaluated in terms of whether it
makes sense when applied to account for legal phenomena. However, his
theory construes law in counterintuitive ways. No system counts as law
in isolation or as a general matter because its legal status is constituted
only with respect to particular other legal systems that recognize it. It is
law in relation to Systems B, C, D, etc., which recognize it, but not law
with respect to Systems E, F, G, etc., which do not recognize it. Thus,
System A can be law and not law at the same moment (depending on
which relation one considers). Moreover, as we just saw, System A’s legal
status with respect to Systems B, C, and D, etc., can be turned on and off
at the sole discretion of each external system. Michaels extrapolates from
the correct proposition that System B alone has the power to determine
what counts as law for it (a direct implication of legal rules of validity),
but ratchets up the theoretical import of this proposition to be ‘consti-
tutive’ of A’s nature as law (an internal point about System B thereby
determines the legal nature of System A). This conceptual move
transforms a commonplace idea into a source of multiple puzzling
implications.47
The distorting lens his relational theory provides is evident through
application to actual situations of legal pluralism. Consider British treat-
ment of Aboriginal customary law. Upon arrival, they declared Australia
terra nullius, with no semblance of law or civil society, a blank legal slate,
enabling the colonial government and settlers to seize Aboriginal land
46
Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition’, p. 109.
47
A strange implication of this theory, which he acknowledges, is that a legal system cannot
exist unless another legal system exists that recognizes it, which itself is not a legal system
unless it is recognized by another existing legal system, etc. – thus involving an infinite
regress. Michaels dismisses this as a problem for all theories of law, but conventionalist
theories based on social recognition do not face an infinite regress.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
because no property rights existed.48 This stance conceptually erased the
reality that Aboriginal communities had lived for aeons, and continued
to live, in accordance with customary law on property rights, personal
injuries, marriage and so forth. In Mabo v. Queensland (1992), the
Australian court finally recognized that Aboriginal customary law indeed
conferred pre-existing property rights that must be respected.49
Aborigines had all along viewed and lived in accordance with their
customary law, but according to Michaels’ relational theory, Aboriginal
customary law was not law until external recognition by the Australian
legal system constituted it as law, putting its status as law entirely at the
leave of the state legal system.
Not only does this stance wholly discount the views and legal practices
of Aborigines, it twists the court’s inquiry into a logical pretzel. A court in
this position is inquiring whether customary law was (or is) a genuine
form of law. According to the court, the pre-existing legal status of
customary law provides the grounds for its decision, but according to
Michaels its legal status follows solely as a consequence of the decision
itself. Under his theory, it is not conceptually possible for Aboriginal law
to be law prior to recognition, so the court’s inquiry into whether it was
law (prior to the decision) is nonsensical.
In New Zealand, after a number of violent skirmishes, the British
entered the Treaty of Waitangi (1840) with powerful Maori chiefdoms,
acknowledging their right to rule in their home areas, and subsequent
statutes were enacted recognizing customary law. But this initial recog-
nition was withdrawn after the rapidly increasing settler population
became dominant. In an 1877 case, Wi Parata v. Bishop of Wellington,
Chief Justice Prendergast declared the Treaty of Waitangi a ‘simple
nullity’, ‘worthless’, because it had been signed by ‘barbarians without
any form of law or civil government’ incapable of entering a treaty with a
civilized nation.50 Furthermore, he concluded, the Native Rights Act of
1865 and Native Land Act of 1873, which recognized Maori customary
law property rights, were nullities because ‘no such body of law existed’,
and ‘a phrase in a statute cannot call what is non-existent in being’;
48
See Australian Reform Commission, ‘Recognition of Aboriginal Customary Laws (ALRC
Report 31)’ (1986) paras 39, 60, www.alrc.gov.au/publication/recognition-of-aboriginal-
customary-laws-alrc-report-31/.
49
Mabo v. Queensland [1992] HCA 23.
50
Wi Parata v. Bishop of Wellington (1877) 3 NZ Jur. (N.S.) S.C., language cited in J. Tate,
‘The Three Precedents of Wi Parata’ (2004) 10 Canterbury Law Review 273–308, at 293,
294 n. 92.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
subsequent statutes withdrew recognition of customary law. Only in
recent decades has Maori customary law again received recognition by
the New Zealand state legal system. Ironically, contrary to Justice
Prendergast’s assertion, according to Michaels’ theory, recognition of
customary law in a state statute or case does indeed bring previously
non-existent Maori law into being – but by the same reasoning the
withdrawal of said recognition also extinguishes it. External recognition
has a kind of magical ontological power to snap law into and out of
existence by declaration, a power wielded by the state legal system, while
Maori legal understandings and practices do not matter.
Now I shift from colonial settings to show how the relational theory
fails to adequately account for Jewish law and Sharia law in Western legal
systems, both mentioned by Michaels. Jewish law recognizes the law of
the state, but most state legal systems do not recognize Jewish law as law.
In the United States, the decisions of Jewish tribunals (Beth Din) are
enforced not as Jewish law, but rather as contractually binding arbitra-
tion decisions, no different from contract-based private arbitration gen-
erally. From the standpoint of believers, in contrast, these decisions are
based on Jewish law. The rules of Beth Din America declare: ‘The Beth
Din of America accepts that Jewish law as understood by the Beth Din
will provide the rules of decision and rules of procedure that govern the
Beth Din or any of its panels.’51 Thus Jewish adherents see two legal
systems operating. But according to Michaels’ theory, Jewish law is not
law unless state law recognizes it as such, which it refuses to do, so state
law is the exclusive form of law as far as it is concerned (enforcing private
arbitration grounded in state contract law is not recognition of the status
of Jewish law as a legal system, nor does it involve conflicts of law rules).
A number of states in the USA prohibit courts from recognizing religious
law of any kind. Since state legal systems typically assert a monopoly over
law, the consequence of his theory is to disqualify non-state law at the
outset, eliminating legal pluralism by automatically granting the monop-
olistic claim of state law.
The situation of Sharia law is even more problematic for Michaels’
theory. The UK government recently enacted provisions that would give
limited recognition (again as arbitration, not law) to decisions by Sharia
tribunals that meet specified criteria, but a number of Sharia councils
have expressed reluctance to obtain formal recognition under state law,
51
Rules and Procedures: Beth Din America, p. 5 (emphasis added), https://bethdin.org/wp-
content/uploads/2018/04/BDA118-RulesProcedures_Bro_BW_02.pdf.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
which they consider to be ‘un-Islamic’.52 In this instance, one form of law
rejects an offer of recognition from an external legal system, viewing such
recognition as unnecessary and perhaps an insult to its own independent
legal status – whereas for Michaels this very rejection disqualifies it from
constituting law. Both state law and religious law assert that their law is
binding and superior. The direct clash is evident in a fatwa on divorce
issued by the Islamic Council of Europe:
In conclusion, I would like to affirm that the divorce issued by the civil
court in response to the wife’s request is neither a valid divorce nor
legitimate marriage dissolution. This means that such a wife remains a
wife and is not free to marry another man. Marrying another man while
the original marriage is still in place is a violation of Islamic law and a
crime. What is more dangerous than this is the fact that all children she
gives birth to before obtaining a proper marriage dissolution may be
considered to be of the first husband from whom she assumed she had
been divorced. Wives who face intolerable situations may seek marriage
dissolution by a recognized body that is known and accepted in acting as a
judiciary body for Muslims.53
52
See S. Bano, ‘In Pursuit of Religious and Legal Diversity: A Response to the Archbishop of
Canterbury and the “Sharia Debate” in Britain’ (2008) 10 Ecclesiastical Law Journal
283–309, at 299.
53
S. H. Al-Haddad, ‘Fatwa: A Civil Divorce Is Not a Valid Islamic Divorce’, Islamic Council
of Europe (17 February 2017), https://iceurope.org/fatwa-a-civil-divorce-is-not-a-valid-
islamic-divorce/ (emphasis added).
54
H. Sherwood, ‘Islamic Faith Marriages Not Valid in English Law, Appeal Court Rules’,
The Guardian (14 February 2020), www.theguardian.com/world/2020/feb/14/islamic-
faith-marriages-not-valid-in-english-law-appeal-court-rules.
55
See G. Douglas, N. Doe, S. Gilliat-Ray, R. Sandberg and A. Khan, ‘The Role of Religious
Tribunals in Regulating Marriage and Divorce’ (2012) 24 Child & Family Law Quarterly
139–57.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The relational theory of law is antithetical to the thrust of legal
pluralism for reasons revealed by these examples. Law throughout history
and today is the product of recognition within communities that live by
and recognize their own forms of law. This holds for the Indigenous law
of the Maori, Australian Aborigines and Native American tribes of North
America, as well as Jewish law, Sharia law, Hindu law and other forms of
religious law, as well as customary law across Africa, Asia and the Pacific
Islands, and many other forms of law. To condition their status as law on
recognition by an external legal system, the state legal system in particu-
lar, denies communities their own agency in determining what counts as
law. Michaels asserts, ‘In all but the rarest cases, we will be faced with
external recognition from both sides.’56 This is true among state legal
systems, which uniformly recognize one another, but there are many
examples past and present of state legal systems not extending reciprocal
recognition to customary and religious law.
The examples in this section also illustrate that whether external
recognition is extended is not always a matter of comity and respect,
but rather is a function of relative power and self-interest. Under the
ideal of the monist law state, the state characteristically claims a monop-
oly over law backed by force of arms. Many forms of community-based
law have vigorously disputed this monopolistic assertion for centuries.
What Michaels clinically presents as ‘external recognition’ has often
involved existential contests in which a state legal system asserts its
dominance over community-recognized forms of law struggling to sur-
vive.57 His theory gives the state legal system determinative say over legal
status (a common assumption of jurists), while many communities
around the globe observing non-state law resolutely insist otherwise.
Although he is correct that state law determines what counts as law for
its own purposes, this does not, and should not, dictate the status of other
legal systems on their own terms.
These objections to the relational theory reinforce a point made earlier.
Michaels’ theory of law might fit state law recognition of other state laws
through conflicts of law rules (his scholarly expertise), and it might work
for transnational forms of law and regulation, but it is not suitable for
many contexts of legal pluralism.
56
Michaels, ‘Law and Recognition’, p. 114.
57
Chapters 3 and 14 discuss Indigenous legal orders in Canada struggling to maintain their
existence against state declarations of its legal dominance.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
17.7 Foundations of Legal Pluralism in Conventional
Recognition of Law
It is a commonplace that the social world we inhabit is socially
constructed. The social world is the product of our meaningful beliefs,
actions and projects, and their intended and unintended conse-
quences. People are born into, assume a place in, partake of and
modify existing language, knowledge, social practices and institutions,
conventions and technology, generated on an ongoing basis by the
community of actors – collectively giving rise to a common social
world made up of hospitals, schools, petrol stations, factories, govern-
ment offices, courts, movie theatres, grocery stores, universities and
everything else in society. These are the ubiquitous social phenomena
in which we are daily immersed and take for granted. Socially con-
structed institutions, furthermore, are interconnected within sur-
rounding cultural, social, economic, political, legal, ecological and
technological factors, and their existence endures over time (until they
expire), developing and changing in relation to exogenous and
endogenous factors.
The socially constructed Catholic Church, for example, has
changed immensely over its two millennia history. Put in grossly
broad strokes: from the claim that Christ designated the bishop of
Rome as the head; to the edict establishing Christianity as the official
religion of the Roman Empire; to a gradual split between the Western
and Eastern churches; to the investiture conflict; to the development
of canon law influenced by Roman law; to independent legal authority
exercised by the Church across Western Europe on marriage, inherit-
ance, defamation, moral crimes and other matters, alongside regal
law, law of the manor, local customary law, etc.; to the Reformation
and Counter-Reformation and decades of devastating religious wars;
to changing relations with consolidating state systems in Europe and
the stripping of ecclesiastical law from authority over the public; to
the immensely wealthy Catholic Church today, governing its own
affairs, operating its own legal system and ensconced in a sovereign
state, Vatican City.
Notice that law and legal pluralism in various respects, evolving over
time, have a prominent role in the history of the Catholic Church,
interacting with politics, religion, economics and everything else.
Accounts of this sort can be provided for all socially constructed, histor-
ically enduring, socially interconnected, varying and changing
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
manifestations of law throughout history and today.58 Whatever people
collectively recognize as ‘law’ (and its translations) is law – recognition of
legal status that has attached to innumerable instantiations and vari-
ations of law over time: European Union law, United Kingdom law,
Scottish law, New York municipal and state law, international law,
Halakha (Jewish law), Sharia law, Yapese customary law, Adat law in
Indonesia and countless more. These manifestations of law cannot be
captured in a single concept of law because their functions and features
vary and have changed over time. Informal customary law, and inter-
national and transnational law, do not have the same structures as state
law, which is why Hart, who explicitly based his concept on state law,
concluded that they are not fully fledged law, but pre-legal.
To know what law is for the purposes of legal pluralism does not
require an abstract concept or definition of law stating essential or
defining features – instead one must inquire into what people in a given
social arena collectively (conventionally) identify as law.59 As with any
social artefact, this inquiry presupposes a rudimentary sense of what is
law (likewise, one must begin with a sense of what a chair is to identify
what people collectively identify as chairs). Collective senses of what
counts as law – including customary and religious law, state law and
others – extend back millennia to a shared Western and Near-Eastern
tradition (Hammurabi’s Code, Greek law, Torah, Sharia, etc.). These
notions of law have spread around the world through contact, trade,
migration and interaction among peoples generally. Colonization spread
state legal systems globally through imposition or imitation, as well as
entrenched the notion of customary law in many societies, and inter-
national law was a companion of colonization, so these forms of law are
familiar in every society around the globe today. Translations for law
exist in all classical and contemporary languages – often in multiple
terms, like ius and lex, and recht and gesetz, all of which count as
conventionally identified law – instantly available on Google Translate.
58
See Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law.
59
Collective recognition involves the shared conventional identification within a group of
something as possessing legal status. Since law has substantial connotations of authority
within a group, the conventional attachment of this label is relatively restricted, applying
to a limited number of phenomena within societies. Under this approach, an interesting
question for examination is why in given arenas certain institutional forms are conven-
tionally identified as ‘law’, while others are not, which may relate to power, rhetorical
import, normative authority and other factors.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
In many social contexts today and in the past, multiple collectively
recognized forms of law coexist – this is legal pluralism.
The key constitutive factor in particular social constructions of law is
conventional recognition within social groups (including groups of legal
officials). Conventional recognition determines who counts as legal offi-
cials, which specified legal powers they exercise and what they must do
for their actions to count as legal.60 In highly institutionalized formal
legal systems this recognition is tied to official positions occupied by
legislators, prosecutors, judges, police, etc., exercising roles with attend-
ant legal powers. But a multitude of socially constructed arrangements of
conventionally recognized law exist. In many informal customary law
systems, village chiefs or elders preside in collective gatherings and
render decisions on the resolution of disputes over matters of property,
personal injuries, inheritance, property claims, etc. A single version of
law can come in many variations across different contexts. For Islamic
law, for example, respected Islamic jurists issue authoritative rulings
(fatwa) based on the Quran, Hadith (sayings of the prophet
Muhammad) and juristic teachings, although they do not operate within
official legal systems; in Iran, an Islamic theocracy, judges occupy pos-
itions within the state system applying Islamic law; and in Indonesia,
informal Adat tribunals apply mixtures of locally infused Islamic law and
customary law. In many contexts, collectively recognized official state
legal systems and non-state legal systems both operate, and can be
potentially invoked by parties, and sometimes international and trans-
national forms of law can be invoked as well. That is legal pluralism.
60
See N. MacCormick, Institutions of Law: An Essay in Legal Theory (Oxford University
Press, 2007), pp. 289–93; J. R. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (Free Press, 1995),
pp. 27–51.
61
The basis for these categories is in Tamanaha, Legal Pluralism Explained.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
social intercourse within communities addressing property, personal
injuries, marriage, divorce, sexual restrictions, inheritance, debts and
obligations and others; the body of rules through which people arrange
their daily affairs. Every society has rules addressing these matters, which
vary greatly across societies and change over time. Many existing systems
of customary and religious law involve the lengthy continuation of
fundamental rules of social intercourse going back many centuries, pre-
dating the establishment of state legal systems and evolving to adjust to
the presence of the state (and the state to them). Regime laws are laws tied
to ruling polities. They constitute, support and enforce the power of the
governing regime, including taxation and customs fees, forced labour and
military service, laws against sedition, border controls and much more,
with governing regimes frequently nested within or encompassing in
whole or part other subregimes. Cross-polity laws deal with matters
between and across organized polities, consisting of national law (includ-
ing conflicts of law), international law, transnational law and non-state
forms of law that extend across states (like fatwa).
Community law has remained roughly the same in its ambit across
place and time. Regime law has expanded enormously in the past two
centuries with the consolidation and proliferation of bureaucratic state
law and the rise of instrumental lawmaking to address a full range of
social, economic and political matters. Cross-polity law has multiplied
greatly in conjunction with modern globalization, accelerating in the past
half-century to deal with transnational capitalism, transportation, com-
munications, financial transactions, legal and illegal migration, ecological
harms and more.
All three categories of law are contained within many unified state
legal systems today, though significant exceptions remain. This unifica-
tion is a recent arrangement. Throughout history, from the Roman
Empire to the Ottoman Empire to the British Empire, empires have
imposed regime law to maintain imperial interests, while allowing local
community-based customary and religious laws and tribunals to address
matters of everyday social intercourse. Postcolonial legal pluralism across
the Global South today is the continuing legacy of Western imperialism.
Large polities that span multiple communities often comprise some
arrangement (officially or unofficially) in which pockets of community
law continue to function.
Many situations of legal pluralism involve juxtapositions of inconsist-
ent versions of community law, state law and cross-polity law (forms of
law from different categories and/or within the same category). In many
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
regions across the Global South, people in rural communities manage
their affairs through customary law and tribunals, apart from and often
inconsistent with official state laws and tribunals. Disputes over the
inheritance of land from a male who dies can involve, on the one side,
male brothers of the deceased invoking customary law on patrilineal
inheritance (community law), backed by the UN Declaration of Rights
of Indigenous Peoples (cross-polity law), to support their claim to the
land; while on the other side, widows (with help from non-governmental
organizations) may invoke state inheritance law on widow’s shares (state
law), backed by the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of
Discrimination Against Women (cross-polity law).62 Across Asia, sub-
sistence farmers invoke customary land tenure rights (community law),
clashing with governments and developers seizing land to establish
plantations or commercial projects, who invoke transplanted official
property rights and titling systems enacted by states (state law) at the
behest of the World Bank and Western development agencies (cross-
polity organizations transplanting law). European constitutional plural-
ism involves the juxtaposition of national law of the states (regime law)
with EU treaties and law (cross-polity law); the pluralism of coexisting
subject matter regimes in international law (WTO, TRIPS, World Health
Organization, environmental treaties, etc.) involves multiple examples of
cross-polity law with different orientations and objectives, interacting
with the laws of nations (regime law).63 Legal pluralism is thus mani-
fested around the globe in myriad variations. In pluralistic contexts it is
useful to pay attention to three different directions: (1) at the coexisting
complex of legal and regulatory institutions and their interaction; (2) at
individuals, entities and groups operating within contexts of coexisting
legal and regulatory institutions; and (3) at the broader social, cultural,
economic, political and legal consequences of the coexisting legal systems
(at the consequences of 1 and 2). In the first direction, one should look at
the relative power of each set of legal institutions, and the power and
resources of the social, economic and political interests that support or
align with each; at the normative commitments and personal interests of
the officials who operate within each form of law; and at whether, and
how, coexisting forms of law operate cooperatively, competitively or
combatively (or all three). In the second direction, one should observe
how people navigate legal pluralism for normative and strategic reasons:
62
For other combinations, see Chapters 2, 7 and 15.
63
For examples, see Chapters 8, 10 and 12.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
they may resort to a particular form of law for moral, cultural or
economic reasons; they may engage in forum shopping to achieve their
objectives; they may pit one legal system against another or enlist mul-
tiple systems for support.64 In the third direction, one should examine
the broader cultural, social, economic, political and legal consequences of
how the coexisting legal systems interact and how people, entities and
groups operate within these contexts. These three directions will expose
entanglements between the coexisting forms of law, entanglements
between people and coexisting forms of law and entanglements of both
with the surrounding interconnected society (culture, economics, polit-
ics, etc.). This trifold lens helps expose many of the dynamics at play in
contexts of legal pluralism.
64
See Chapter 1.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
.
law, UK law, individual treaties, national constitutions, international law,
human rights, German municipal, state and administrative law, etc.
These conventionally recognized manifestations of law are what trans-
national legal pluralists already discuss. That is why an abstract definition
of law is unnecessary. We know what is law because we – jurists,
government officials, citizens, native peoples, members of religious com-
munities, etc. – collectively identify them as law. Coexisting clashing
conventional identifications of law may exist in given contexts (for
example state law and Sharia), but they still count as law when they are
seen as such by communities of actors.
The fourth lesson, following directly from the second and third, is that
‘transnational legal and regulatory pluralism’ is a more suitable label for
the concerns of global/transnational legal pluralists. The label ‘global legal
pluralism’ is misleading and should be dropped, for it is neither global
nor exclusively legal. The label ‘transnational legal pluralism’ is problem-
atic because it prompts theorists to explain why what they study counts
as law (thereby generating the definitional problem). There is no juristic
or conceptual reason to assert that they are law – a superfluous claim that
inevitably runs into trouble. Adding ‘regulatory’ to the label immediately
dissolves this issue and recognizes that their work encompasses public,
private and hybrid regulatory regimes, a significant amount of which is
not collectively considered law – which does not diminish the fact that
they are important and accomplish a great deal. They are what they are:
private and hybrid regulatory forms that carry out and complement legal
functions, and frequently interact with manifestations of law. They bear
directly on the concerns of transnational legal pluralists and merit inclu-
sion in the label.
The final lesson, already mentioned but worthy of separate emphasis,
is that, beyond state, international and transnational law, many commu-
nities also collectively identify and constitute forms of non-state law,
mainly manifestations of customary law, religious law and Indigenous
law (though other forms exist, like Romani law). These are law as well,
which a huge number of people around the globe recognize and live by,
especially in rural areas or within insular communities. State legal offi-
cials frequently assert state law’s claim to supremacy and exclusivity, but
this ambition (never fully achieved) does not trump what people collect-
ively recognize, construct and live by as law. State legal systems are
themselves collectively recognized forms of law – so state law, inter-
national law, transnational law and non-state law are all built on the
same foundation of collective recognition.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
The unifying thrust of these five lessons is that we should simplify how
we view the complicated contexts of transnational legal and regulatory
multiplicities – and the best way to accomplish this is to engage in
modest, tailored theorizing that fits the matters at hand. Much of the
morass of transnational legal pluralism lamented by Twining is the self-
inflicted product of unnecessarily grand theories. The effort to construct
a theory that encompasses everything and addresses every context of
legal pluralism – as global legal pluralism suggests – is bound to lead us
astray.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
INDEX
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Awami League under transnational finance law,
in Bangladesh, 51, 54 121–2
in Pakistan, 44 European Court of Human Rights
and, 109
Babusiaux, Ulrike, 358, 360 European Economic Community,
Baer, Susanne, 412 116–17
Bangladesh, colonial entanglements in, goals and objectives of, 112–17
43–58 as governance project, 114–15
Awami League in, 51, 54 Greece and, 120
BNP Party in, 51 Hungary and, 124–7
Civil Codes and, 43–5, 55–6 under International Investment
Convention on the Elimination of Agreements, 119–20
All Forms of Discrimination legal pluralism and, 111
against Women and, 46–7, 53 localized effects of, 110–17
Convention on the Rights of the Ministry of Commerce and, 109
Child and, 46–7 One Belt, One Road initiative, 107–8
Covenant on Economic, Social, and Pakistan and, 122–3
Cultural Rights and, 46–7 separateness of legal norms and,
Criminal Codes and, 43–5, 55–6 108–9, 117–24
historical development of, 43–4 theoretical approach to, 107–10
after second partition of Indian Trans-Pacific Partnership and,
subcontinent, 43–4 112–13
International Covenant on Civil and under Treaty of Rome, 116–17
Political Rights and, 46–7 World Bank Group and, 115
Jamaat-e-Islami and, 45–6, 54 Benda-Beckmann, Kebbet von, 411
Kissinger on, 43 Benjamin, Walter, 41–2
Village Court Act, 55–6 Benton, Lauren, 37–8
Bangladesh Bank, 250 Berman, Paul, 449–50, 454–6
Bank for International Settlements Beyond Constitutionalism (Krisch), 355
(BIS), 291, 299–300 Bhandar, Brenna, 38
banking reforms, 243 bilateral investment treaties (BITs)
Basel Committee on Banking international investment governance
Supervision, 293–4 sites and, 165
Belt and Road Initiative (BRI), China, investor–state dispute settlement
18 mechanisms and, 174–80, 184
Asian Infrastructure Investment Biosafety Protocol, CBD, 210–11
Bank and, 115 BIS. See Bank for International
centralized goals of, 110–17 Settlements
Chinese Communist Party role in, BITs. See bilateral investment treaties
119 blacklists, in social credit initiatives, 97
Court of Justice of the European Blatter, Sepp, 261–2
Union and, 109 BNP Party, in Bangladesh, 51
entangled legalities of, 110–24 Borrows, John, 380–1, 386–7, 389
ethnographic methodology in, 118 Bouman, Marlies, 40
interdependence within, 124–7 Bower, Adam, 373–4
under international law, 120–1 BRI. See Belt and Road Initiative
sociological methodology in, British Empire, legal entanglement in,
118 8–9
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
British North America Act of 1867, See Canada/US Continued Suspension
Constitution Act, 1867 dispute, 220
buen vivir principle, in Ecuador, Canadian Constitution Act (1982),
409–11 66–7
Carrai, Maria Adele, 115
CAC. See Codex Alimentarius CAS. See Court of Arbitration for Sport
Commission Case for an International Banking
Camdessus, Michel, 296 Standard, The (Goldstein),
Campo, José Antonio, 299 295–6
Canada. See also Indigenous legalities CAT. See Convention against Torture
Aboriginal rights in, 385 CBD. See Convention on Biodiversity
Columbia Center on Sustainable CCSI. See Columbia Center on
Investment in, 178 Sustainable Investment
Comprehensive Economic Trade CED. See Convention on Enforced
Agreement, 185 Disappearances
Constitution Act 1867, 1982, 66–7, CEDAW. See Convention on the
73–4, 377, 380, 388–9, 397 Elimination of All Forms of
inclusion of Indigenous rights, 381 Discrimination against Women
EU–Canada Comprehensive Centre for International Environmental
Economic and Trade Law (CIEL), 213
Agreement, 214 CERD. See Convention on the
First Nations Land Management Act, Elimination of Racial
391–5 Discrimination
K’omoks First Nation land codes ‘cession’ treaties, 66
under, 392–5 CETA. See Comprehensive Economic
private prosecutions under, 393–4 Trade Agreement; EU–Canada
Framework Agreement on First Land Comprehensive Economic and
Management, 391–5 Trade Agreement
K’omoks First Nation land codes CFT. See counter-financing of
under, 392–5 terrorism
private prosecutions under, 393–4 Chanock, Martin, 37
Free Trade Agreement, with Peru, China. See also Belt and Road Initiative;
178–9 social credit initiatives
Indian Act 1876, 377 artificial intelligence in, 92
investor–state dispute settlement Chinese Communist Party, 91–2
mechanisms in, 178–9 Belt and Road Initiative and, 119
legal entanglements in, conceptual investor–state dispute settlement
development of, 376–8 mechanisms in, 168
North American Free Trade Ministry of Commerce in, 109
Agreement, 173–4 Twelve Core Socialist Values in,
reconciliation project, 73 94–5
Royal Proclamation of 1763, 386, UK economic relations with, 113
388–9, 397 choice of law, tertiary rules and,
supremacy claims in, Indigenous 431–2
legal systems and, 388–95 Christie, Gordon, 75
Supreme Court of Canada, 381–4 Chunnu, Saiful, 47–8
UN human rights treaties CIEL. See Centre for International
monitoring bodies in, 144–6 Environmental Law
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
CITES. See Convention on Treaty of Albany, 65
International Trade in religious laws and, 43–6
Endangered Species Hefazaat-e-Islamni movement, 45
citizenship Muslim Family Laws Ordinance,
ecological, 75–6 45, 49–50, 55–6
under Roman law, 366–7 under state law, 40–1
Civil Procedure Act, Norway, 137–8 theoretical approach to, overview of,
civil society, corporate social 57–8
responsibility and, 320–1 translation of, 39–43, 54–6
CJEU. See Court of Justice of the by NGOs, 54–5
European Union by non-state justice institutions,
CMW. See Convention on Migrant 55–6
Workers for secular women’s rights, 54–5
Codex Alimentarius Commission under transnational law, 39–40
(CAC), 206–8, 459–60 colonial laws, colonial entanglements
coercion and, constitutive effects of, 38–9
colonial entanglements through, 37 private property laws, 38–9
as pathway to legal entanglement, Columbia Center on Sustainable
17–19 Investment (CCSI), in Canada,
Cohen, Morris, 457 178
Colombia, investor–state dispute Comaroff, John, 38
settlement mechanisms in, 179 Commission on International Trade
colonial capital, 230 Law (UNCITRAL). See United
colonial entanglements. See also Nations
Bangladesh common law judges, 14
through coercion, 37 Communist Party of China (CPC),
colonial laws and, constitutive effects 91–2
of, 38–9 Belt and Road Initiative and, 119
private property laws, 38–9 community law, transnational legal
deferral of, 39–43, 51–3 pluralism and, 472–5
through appellate court decisions, compliance mechanisms, for social
51–3 credit initiatives, 103
denial of, 39–43, 47–50 Comprehensive Economic Trade
in media reports, 47–8 Agreement (CETA), 185
through Supreme Court verdict, Comprehensive Iran Sanctions,
48–53 Accountability, and Divestment
for fatwa practices, 48–50 Act, US (2011), 253–4
human rights issues, 52–3 Comprehensive Peace Agreement
historical trajectory for, 37–9 (2005), 41–2
legal interpretation of, 44–5 Concept of Law (Hart), 378–9, 428–30
legal pluralism and, 37–8 Conference on Environment and
under non-state law, 40–1 Development (UNCED). See
in North America, legal pluralism United Nations
and, 64–7 conflict-of-law norms, for international
conciliatory approaches to, 65 law, 5
for Indigenous peoples, 64–5 consent. See free, prior and informed
under Royal Proclamation of consent
1763, 65–6 Constable, Marianne, 75
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Constitution Act Economic Co-operation and
1867 (British North America Act of Development guidelines
1867) (Canada), 377, 380, ad hoc entanglement with, 318–19
388–9, 397 African Charter on Human and
1982 (Canada), 66–7, 73–4, 380, 397 People’s Rights and, 329–30
inclusion of Indigenous rights, Amnesty International and, 320
381 definitions of, 319–21
constitutional capture, 73 for civil society actors, 320–1
constitutional pluralism, European in EU, 319–20
Court of Justice and, 10 for non-governmental
constitutionalism organizations, 320–1
global, 356 norms for, 321
rooted, 69–70 under Paris Agreement, 338
sustainable, 61–2 pluralism within, 348
Convention against Torture (CAT), regulatory impact of, 320
Subcommittee on Prevention of scope of, 320–1
Torture, 135, 137 systems interactions in, 321–6
Convention on Biodiversity (CBD), 194 Environmental Impact
Biosafety Protocol, 210–11 Assessments, 326
Convention on Enforced Environmental Management
Disappearances (CED), Systems, 323–4
monitoring committee of, 135 International Finance
Convention on International Trade in Corporation, 325
Endangered Species (CITES), International Organization for
199–200, 202–4 Standardization, 323–4
Convention on Migrant Workers Social Impact Assessments, 326
(CMW), monitoring committee UN Guiding Principles, 324–6
of, 135 theoretical approach to, 318–19
Convention on the Elimination of All cosmopolitics, 76–7
Forms of Discrimination Cotterrell, Roger, 461–2
against Women (CEDAW), counter-entanglements, in Ecuador,
46–7, 53 413–15
monitoring committee of, 134–6 countering-financing of terrorism
in Spain, 155–8 (CFT), 236–41
Convention on the Elimination of anti-money laundering mechanisms,
Racial Discrimination 238–9
(CERD), monitoring through banking reforms, 243
committee of, 135 cooperation with other states, 238–9
Convention on the Rights of Persons counter-proliferation finance
with Disabilities (CRPD), mechanisms, 238–9
monitoring committee of, 135 design of, 237
in Germany, 149–50 Financial Action Task Force, 238–40,
Convention on the Rights of the Child 246
(CRC), 46–7 targetedness of, 239–41
monitoring committee of, 135 under US International Emergency
corporate social responsibility (CSR). Economic Powers Act, 250
See also National Contact counter-proliferation finance
Points; Organisation for mechanisms, 238–9
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
counter-terrorist sanctions regime, by UN Security Council Resolutions,
UN Security Council, 234–58. 233, 244–5
See also countering-financing of against Democratic People’s
terrorism Republic of Korea, 240, 248–9
9/11 terrorist attacks and, 236–7 Financial Action Task Force and,
Angola and, 235–6 246
Democratic People’s Republic of against Iran, 238–9, 252–3
Korea and, 233, 239–41, panel of experts and, 251
245–6 requirements of, 247–8
banking sanctions against, 248–9 War on Terror and, 236–7
SWIFT role in, 249–50 Court of Arbitration for Sport (CAS),
UN Security Council Resolutions 14, 260, 459
against, 240, 248–9 EU law and, 268–74
under US International as constitutional check, 270–2
Emergency Economic Powers Court of Justice of the European
Act, 250 Union, 268–70
domestic sanctions, 252–6 FIFA and, 272–4
by US, 253–6 European Convention on Human
external dynamics for, 252–6 Rights and, 260–1, 274–85
historical development of, 234–7 under Article 6(1), procedural
Iran and guarantees of, 280–5
Joint Comprehensive Plan of due process and, 280–2, 284–5
Action against, 255–6 jurisdictional issues, 275–7
UN Security Council Resolutions sports governing bodies’
against, 238–9, 252–3 regulations and, compatibility
Iraq and, 235–6, 239–41 with, 277–80
Kuwait and, 235 World Anti-Doping Code and,
Liberia and, 235–6 277–9
multilateral sanctions, 252–6 European Court of Human Rights
overview of, 256–9 and, 274–5
panels of experts for, evidence requirements, 282–4
comprehensivation through, French law and, 262
241–51 German law and, 262
evaluation and monitoring of goals and objectives of, 260–2
sanctions, 246–7 Italian law and, 262
implementation of sanctions, 244, lex sportiva, 260–2, 285–8
251 overview of, 285–8
institutional support for, 245–6 sports governing bodies and
political nature of, 244–5 administrative practices of, 260–1
UN Security Council Resolutions due process inside, 280–2
and, 251 European Convention on Human
Rhodesia and, 235 Rights and, compatibility with,
Sierra Leone and, 235–6 277–80
South Africa and, 235 under Swiss law, 262–3
state jurisdictions for, 242–3 World Anti-Doping Code and,
through trading restrictions, 235 277–9
transnational policy network for, Swiss law and, 262–8
235–6 exclusive applicability of, 265–8
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Court of Arbitration for Sport (CAS) for population data, 86–7
(cont.) social credit initiatives and, 84–6
FIFA cases, 263–8 governance actor relationships
Haas doctrine and, 265 influenced by, 88
sports governing bodies under, as substitute for legal norms, 87
262–3 theoretical approach to, 105–6
Swiss Federal Tribunal, 262–3 Declaration on the Rights of
Court of Justice of the European Union Indigenous Peoples (UNDRIP).
(CJEU), 109 See United Nations
Court of Arbitration for Sport and, deferral, of colonial entanglements,
268–70 39–43
investor–state dispute settlement in Bangladesh, 51–3
mechanisms in, 190 Democratic People’s Republic of Korea
Covenant Chain of friendship, 66, 68, (DPRK), 239–41, 245–6
71 banking sanctions against, 248–9
Covid-19 pandemic, social credit SWIFT role in, 249–50
initiatives during, in China, 91 UN Security Council Resolutions
CPC. See Communist Party of China against, 240, 248–9
Craft, Aimée, 69 UN Security Council sanctions
CRC. See Convention on the Rights of against, 233
the Child under US International Emergency
Criminal Procedure Act, Norway, Economic Powers Act, 250
137–8 denial, of colonial entanglements,
Crockett, Andrew, 300 39–43
cross-border normativity, for tertiary in Bangladesh, 47–53
rules, 428–34 dispute settlement agreements, during
authority sharing strategies, 433–4 Late Antique period, for Roman
challenges from, 429–30 law, 371–2
denial strategies, 431–2 Dispute Settlement Body (DSB), for
internalization strategies, 432–3 WTO, 196–8
in Syrian law, 430 claims process for, 197
cross-polity law, transnational legal jurisdiction of, 197
pluralism and, 472–5 dispute settlement mechanisms, for
CRPD. See Convention on the Rights of World Trade Organization,
Persons with Disabilities 196–8
CSR. See corporate social responsibility distancing strategies as part of, 221–2
cultural capital, 230 international law as influence on,
culture projects, social credit initiatives 197–8
for, 96–7 for legal entanglements, 220–2
Dispute Settlement Understanding
Daniels, Detlef von, 435 (DSU), 196–8
data-driven management systems distancing, through National Contact
artificial intelligence in, 82–3, 88–9 Points, 329–30
construction of, 84–91 distancing strategies, in dispute
in European Union, 89 settlement mechanisms, 221–2
Facebook and, 86–7 Doha Declaration, on TRIPS
governance of, 84–5, 88–9, 105–6 Agreement, 21
machine learning and, 88–9 Doha Round, GATT, 195–6
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
domestic law genetically–modified organisms in,
norms for, 1 212–14
UN human rights treaties legal aftermath of, 213–14
monitoring bodies and, 148–50 legal entanglements in, 213
acceptance and engagement of ECHR. See European Convention on
domestic law, 155–60 Human Rights
case-specific pathways, 151–5 ECJ. See European Court of Justice
judicial engagement in, 143–6, ecological citizenship, 75–6
155–60 ecological entanglement. See also Earth
judicial non-engagement in, jurisprudence project;
138–41 Indigenous legalities
normative pathways for, 150–5 Anthropocene and, 75–7
in Spain, 155–60 cosmopolitics and, 76–7
Domingo, Rafael, 356 ecological jurisprudence and, 76–7
DPRK. See Democratic People’s new materialisms and, 76–7
Republic of Korea physical interdependence, 60–1
Draghi, Mario, 294 definite states, 60
DSU. See Dispute Settlement recognition processes, 61
Understanding theoretical approach to, 59–61
dual perspective approach, to uncertainty principle, 60
Indigenous legalities, 386–7 ecological law
Dworkin, Ronald, 28 ecological entanglement and, 76–7
dynamics, of legal entanglement, 11–20 Indigenous legalities and, 75–6
actors’ role in, 12–15 economic capital, 230
governmental, 13–14 ECtHR. See European Court of Human
non-governmental, 14–15 Rights
horizontal context in, 19–29 Ecuador, 407–9
pathways as factor in, 15–18 buen vivir principle in, 409–11
coercion as, 17–19 counter-entanglements in, 413–15
ideational context, 15–16 investment law in, 414–15
rational choices in, 16 legal norms in, importation of,
resonance in, 16 409–11
temporal elements, 20 Ley de Fomento Productivo, 414–15
vertical context in, 18–29 oil dumping cases in, Texaco and,
413–14
Earth jurisprudence project, 63 US–Ecuador Bilateral Investment
Eatwell, John, 301 Treaty, 413–14
EC Hormones dispute, 206–12, 220 education projects, social credit
Agreement on Sanitary and initiatives for, 96–7
Phytosanitary Measures and, EEC. See European Economic
206–10 Community
appeals process for, 209–10 Ehrlich, Eugen, 450, 457
legal aftermath of, 210–12 EIAs. See Environmental Impact
legal entanglements in, 207–8 Assessments
EC-Biotech dispute, 212–14, 220 Eichengreen, Barry, 301
EU–Canada Comprehensive entanglement. See ecological
Economic and Trade entanglement; legal
Agreement and, 214 entanglement
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Environmental Impact Assessments Comprehensive Economic Trade
(EIAs), 326 Agreement, 185
environmental law. See international corporate social responsibility in,
environmental law 319–20
Environmental Management Systems, Court of Justice of the European
323–4 Union, 109
Equator Principles, 122 data-driven management systems in,
Ershad, Husain Md., 45–6 89
EU. See European Union EU–Canada Comprehensive
EU law, Court of Arbitration for Sport Economic and Trade
and, 268–74 Agreement, 214
as constitutional check, 270–2 European Court of Human Rights,
Court of Justice of the European 109, 123–4
Union, 268–70 investor–state dispute settlement
FIFA and, 272–4 mechanisms in, 168
EU–Canada Comprehensive Economic legal entanglement in (See also social
and Trade Agreement (CETA), credit initiatives)
214 with EU laws, 11–12
Europe. See medieval Europe with national laws, 11–12
European Convention for the Executive Order 12938, US, 253
Protection of Human Rights Export-Import Bank Act, US (1996),
and Fundamental Freedoms, 253–4
123–4 extraspatial zones, for social credit
European Convention on Human initiatives, 98–9
Rights (ECHR), Court of extraterritoriality issues, in General
Arbitration for Sport and, Agreement on Tariffs and
260–1, 274–85 Trade, 203
under Article 6(1), procedural
guarantees of, 280–5 Facebook, 86–7
due process and, 280–2, 284–5 fact doctrines, 431
jurisdictional issues, 275–7 fair and equitable treatment (FET)
sports governing bodies’ regulations claims, in ISDS mechanisms,
and, compatibility with, 172
277–80 Fajardo, Pablo, 414
World Anti-Doping Code and, FATF. See Financial Action Task Force
277–9 fatwa practices, in Bangladesh, 48–50
European Court of Human Rights as human rights issue, 52–3
(ECtHR), 109, 123–4 Feng Xiang, 90
Court of Arbitration for Sport and, FET claims. See fair and equitable
274–5 treatment claims
evidence requirements, 282–4 FIFA (Féderation Internationale de
European Court of Justice (ECJ), Football Association), 263–8,
constitutional pluralism and, 10 272–4
European Economic Community Financial Action Task Force (FATF)
(EEC), 116–17 counter-financing of terrorism and,
European Union (EU). See also 238–40, 246
European Economic global financial governance and,
Community; specific nations 314–15
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
financial law. See soft financial law during The Great Acceleration, 194
Financial Stability Board (FSB), 17, legal entanglement mechanisms,
290–1, 302–4, 310–15 220–2
Financial Stability Forum (FSF), 291, distancing strategies, 221–2
299–304, 312–15 multilateral environmental
First Nations Land Management Act agreements, 195
(FNLMA) (1999), Canada, norm conflicts over time, in cases
391–5 and disputes, 219–20
K’omoks First Nation land codes sustainable development issues
under, 392–5 under, 221
private prosecutions under, 393–4 Tuna Dolphin I case, 199–201, 219
First Nations peoples. See Indigenous Convention on International
legalities Trade in Endangered Species,
FNLMA. See First Nations Land 199–200
Management Act legal aftermath of, 201
FPIC. See free, prior and informed legal entanglements in, 199–201
consent regional factors, 199
Framework Agreement on First Land Tuna Dolphin II case, 199–201, 219
Management, Canada, 391–5 Uruguay Round, 195–6
K’omoks First Nation land codes US-Tuna II case, 214–18
under, 392–5 Agreement on Technical Barriers
private prosecutions under, 393–4 to Trade and, 215–18
Framework Convention on Climate appeals process for, 216–18
Change (UNFCC). See United legal aftermath of, 218
Nations legal entanglements in, 216–18
France genetically modified organisms
Court of Arbitration for Sport in, 262 (GMOs), 212–14
jurisdictional initiatives in, 407 George III (King), 68
Supply Chain Due Diligence Law, George IV (King), 68
103 Germany
Franklin, Benjamin, 68 Convention on the Rights of Persons
free, prior and informed consent with Disabilities in, 149–50
(FPIC), 331–2 Court of Arbitration for Sport in, 262
free trade agreements (FTAs) ius commune in, 8
Canada–Peru, 178–9 jurisdictional initiatives in, 407
North American Free Trade legal pluralism in, 8
Agreement, 173–4 local laws in, 8
FSB. See Financial Stability Board National Contact Points in, for
FSF. See Financial Stability Board OECD guidelines, 339
FTAs. See free trade agreements tertiary rules in, 436–7
Fuller, Lon, 364 UN human rights monitoring bodies
in, 149–50
Gadinis, Stavros, 310–11 Giovanoli, Mario, 301
Galanter, Marc, 457–8 Global Compact, 122
General Agreement on Tariffs and global constitutionalism, 356
Trade (GATT), 194–6 global financial governance
Doha Round, 195–6 Basel Committee on Banking
extraterritoriality issues, 203 Supervision, 293–4
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
global financial governance (cont.) shaping cultures, 100–1
bodies of norms, 291–304 transparency regimes, 100
competition between ordering governmental actors, legal
projects, 300–4 entanglement and, 13–14
international banking standards, Great Acceleration, The 194
295–6 Great Peace of Montreal, 68
ordering of, after financial crises, Greco-Roman international law, 356–7
294–304 peace treaties under, 357
overarching norms, 304–7 Greece, 120
by private actors, 300 Griffiths, John, 449–51, 456–8
reception norms, 304–12 Guidice, Michael, 361–2
scope of, 296
straddling practices for, 307–12 Haas, Ulrich, 265
Financial Action Task Force and, Haas doctrine, 265
314–15 Haraway, Donna, 77
Financial Stability Board and, 290–1, Hart, H. L. A., 28, 361, 378–9, 428–30,
302–4, 310–15 457–8
Financial Stability Forum, 291, rule of recognition, 428
299–304, 312–15 Hefazaat-e-Islamni movement, 45
historical development of, 289–91 Helms–Burton Act, US, 253–4
institutional pluralism and, 299 Henderson, Sákéj, 69–70, 75
International Accounting Standards Heng Wang, 115
Board and, 300 High Commissioner for Human Rights
International Federation of (OHCHR). See United Nations
Accountants and, 309 Hoffmann, Stanley, 27
international financial standards for, horizontal context, for legal
312–15 entanglement, 19–29
International Monetary Fund and, HRC. See United Nations
290–1, 295–9 human rights. See also women’s rights;
International Swaps and Derivatives specific conventions; specific
Association, 304 covenants; specific treaties
multiplicity in, 304–15 African Charter on Human and
harmonization as result of, 304–7 People’s Rights, 329–30
overview of, 315–17 European Convention for the
soft financial law, 292 Protection of Human Rights
Tripartite Group of Banks working and Fundamental Freedoms,
group, 292–3 123–4
World Bank and, 296–7 European Court of Human Rights,
GMOs. See genetically modified 109
organisms fatwa practices and, 52–3
Goldstein, Morris, 295–6 Inter-American Court of Human
governance, risk management, and Rights, 186–7
compliance systems, 99 international investment law and, 185
accountability in, 101 investor–state dispute settlement
Bank for International Settlements, mechanisms and, 186–9
291 Organisation for Economic Co-
controlling behaviours, 100 operation and Development
law enforcement regimes, 100 guidelines and, 336
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
privacy rights, 102–3 Ecological law and, 75–6
right to be forgotten, 102–3 First Nations Land Management Act,
UN High Commissioner for Human 391–5
Rights, 187 K’omoks First Nation land codes
Human Rights Committee (HRC). See under, 392–5
United Nations private prosecutions under, 393–4
human rights law, 133 floating rules in, 75
human–animal relationships, in Framework Agreement on First Land
Indigenous treaties, 69 Management, 391–5
Hungary, Belt and Road Initiative and, K’omoks First Nation land codes
124–7 under, 392–5
Hussein, Saddam, 235 private prosecutions under, 393–4
Great Peace of Montreal, 68
IACHR. See Inter-American Court of independence of First Nations,
Human Rights 385–6
ICCPR. See International Covenant on logics of contract, 70–6
Civil and Political Rights logics of kinship, 70–6
ICJ. See International Court of Justice Mitchell v. M.N.R., 384
IFC. See International Finance recognition of, 61–2
Corporation reconciliation of, 62
IIAs. See International Investment under Royal Proclamation of 1763,
Agreements 386, 388–9, 397
ILA. See International Law Association ‘social contract’, 71–2
ILC. See International Law supremacy claims, 378–95
Commission acceptance of, 385
Iliafi v. The Church of Jesus Christ and Canadian law and, relations
the Latter-Day Saints Australia, between, 388–95
144 supremacy of force, 384–7
IMF. See International Monetary Fund supremacy of institutions, 381–4
India supremacy of norms, 380–1
creation of, as nation-state, 43–4 Supreme Court of Canada decisions,
after second partition of Indian 381–4
subcontinent, 43–4 transnational legal pluralism and,
Indian Act 1876, 377 466, 469
Indigenous legalities, in Canada Truth and Reconciliation
Aboriginal rights, 385 Commission and, 383
Canadian state and, relation with, Two-Row Wampum
386–7 as symbolism, 73, 389–90
conceptual alternatives to, 395–8 as treaty feature, 385–6, 389–90
inter-institutional view, 396–8 Indigenous treaties, with colonial
system-centred law, 398 authorities, 63–4, 66–70
under Constitution Act 1867, 1982, Anishinaabe peoples and, 68–70
380, 388–9, 397 under Canadian Constitution Act
under Constitution Act 1982, 381 (1982), 66–7, 73–4
Covenant Chain of friendship and, ‘cession’ treaties, 66
66, 68, 71 human–animal relationships in, 69
dual perspective approach to, 386–7 implicate order, 69–70
ecological citizenship and, 75–6 kinship terms in, 68–9
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Indigenous treaties, with colonial international trade law influenced by,
authorities (cont.) 194–6
logics of contract, 70–6 multilateral environmental
logics of kinship, 70–6 agreements, 195
rooted constitutionalism and, 69–70 Rio Declaration and, 194–5
Treaty of Niagara, 66 Shrimp-Turtle case, 204
Two-Row Wampum symbolism and, sustainable development
73 mechanisms, 203
institutional pluralism, global financial International Federation of
governance and, 299 Accountants, 309
Inter-American Convention on Human International Finance Corporation
Rights, 186–7 (IFC), 325
Inter-American Court of Human International Investment Agreements
Rights (IACHR), 186–7 (IIAs), 119–20
interface norms, 222–4, 435 international investment governance
substantive dimensions for, 223–4 sites, 165–70
inter-institutional view, of Indigenous bilateral investment treaties and, 165
legalities, 396–8 competing interests in, 165–8
International Accounting Standards for non-governmental
Board, 300 organizations, 166
international banking standards, 295–6 ideational contexts for, 168–70
International Court of Justice (ICJ), 14, international law. See also international
162–3 trade law
UN human rights treaties Belt and Road Initiative under,
monitoring bodies and, 134–6 120–1
international courts. See also specific fragmentation of, 110
courts Greco-Roman, 356–7
expansion of, 354–5 peace treaties under, 357
International Covenant on Civil and legal entanglement in, 10
Political Rights (ICCPR), 46–7, norms for, 1
135–6 conflict-of-law, 5
in domestic courts private
in Ireland, 138–9 philosophical foundations for,
in Philippines, 139 354–5
investor–state dispute settlement tertiary rules and, 446–7
mechanisms and, 175–6 Westphalian state governance and,
International Covenant on Economic, 354–5
Social, and Cultural Rights, World Trade Organization dispute
46–7 settlement mechanisms
monitoring committee of, 135 influenced by, 197–8
International Emergency Economic International Law Association (ILA),
Powers Act, US, 250 140–1, 153–4
international environmental law International Law Commission (ILC),
Agreement on the International 142–3, 153–4
Dolphin Conservation International Monetary Fund (IMF),
Program, 215–16 18, 256–7
Centre for International global financial governance and,
Environmental Law, 213 290–1, 295–9
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
International Organization for through investment adjudication
Standardization (ISO), 323–4 reform, 189–91
International Swaps and Derivatives through investment agreement
Association, 304 reform, 184–6
international trade law. See also specific for multilateral investment treaties,
trade agreements 175–6
environmental law as influence on, multiplicity in, 170–83
194–6 distance issues, 173–5
historical development of, 194–8 hierarchies, 171–3
legal entanglement and, emerging integrationist perspectives, 175–80
forms of, 194–6 proximities, 173–5
multilateral environmental relational forms, 170–1
agreements and, 195 separations, 171–3
regulatory regimes for, 193–4 networks for, 167–8
theoretical approach to, 193–4 non-governmental organizations
investment governance and law. See and, 173–5
also international investment North American Free Trade
governance sites; investor– Agreement and, 173–4
state dispute settlement Permanent Court of Arbitration, 171
mechanisms Transatlantic Trade and Investment
in Ecuador, 414–15 Partnership and, 189–90
investor–state dispute settlement under Trans-Pacific Partnership, 185
mechanisms under, 185 in United Kingdom, 179–80
investment tribunals, 169–70 in US, 168
investor–state dispute settlement Vienna Convention on the Law of
(ISDS) mechanisms, 164 Treaties and, 173–4, 179–80
analysis of, 191–2 World Trade Organization and, 169
arbitrators in, 169 Iran
in Argentina, 176–8 Comprehensive Iran Sanctions,
bilateral investment treaties and, Accountability, and Divestment
174–80, 184 Act and, 253–4
in Canada, 178–9 Iran Freedom and Counter-
in China, 168 Proliferation Act and, 253–4
in Colombia, 179 Joint Comprehensive Plan of Action
under Comprehensive Economic against, 255–6
Trade Agreement, 185 Nuclear Iran Prevention Act and,
in Court of Justice of the European 253–4
Union, 190 UN Security Council Resolutions
in EU, 168 against, 238–9, 252–3
fair and equitable treatment claims, Iran Freedom and Counter-
172 Proliferation Act, US, 253–4
International Covenant on Civil and Iraq, 235–6, 239–41
Political Rights and, 175–6 Ireland, UN human rights treaties
under international investment law, monitoring bodies in, 138–9
185 ISDS mechanisms. See investor–state
investment tribunals, 169–70 dispute settlement mechanisms
legal entanglements and, 180–91 ISO. See International Organization for
for human rights claims, 186–9 Standardization
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Israel, UN human rights treaties Kissinger, Henry, 43
monitoring bodies in, 143–4 Kohn, Eduardo, 76
Italy, Court of Arbitration for Sport in, K’omoks First Nation, land codes for,
262 392–5
ius civile (law of Roman citizen-body), Krisch, Nico, 64–5, 355, 362, 374–5,
360 399
ius commune, in Germany, 8 on closed legal systems, 401
ius gentium (natural law), 360 on interface norms, 435
ius honorarium (law of urban praetor), on postnational law, 361–6
360 Kumm, Mattias, 186
ius praetorium (law of urban praetor), Kuwait, 235
360
Late Antique period, for Roman law,
Jamaat-e-Islami, in Bangladesh, 45–6, 366–74
54 dispute settlement agreements in,
JCPOA. See Joint Comprehensive Plan 371–2
of Action legal norms during, 372–4
Jewish law, transnational legal P. Petra IV. 9 document, 367–75
pluralism and, 467 strategic legal argumentation in,
Johnson, Harold, 68–9 373–4
Joint Comprehensive Plan of Action Latour, Bruno, 403
(JCPOA), 255–6 law. See also legal norms; specific topics
Jones v. Saudi Arabia, 145 coherence of, as expectation, 1
judges, common law, 14 expanded definitions of, through
jurisdiction legal norms, 361–6
of counter-terrorist sanctions mobilization of, 405–9
regimes, 242–3 through transnational lawsuits, 406
of Court of Arbitration for Sport, norms of, 1
275–7 conflict-of-law, 5
of Dispute Settlement Body, for origins of, 1
WTO, 197 postnational, 361–6
for European Convention on Human governance structures, 363
Rights, 275–7 jurisdictional aspect of, 363
in French law, 407 law in action approaches, 364
in German law, 407 law in practice approaches, 364
postnational law and, 363 Transnational Legal Process
in Roman law, 359, 365–6 model, 364
user theory for, 374–5 law in action approaches, to
in Swiss law, 407 postnational law, 364
law in practice approaches, to
Kaimio, Maarit, 368, 371 postnational law, 364
Kav Laoved v. Interior Ministry, 143–4 law of Roman citizen-body. See ius civile
Kazemi (Estate) v. Iran, 145–6 law of urban praetor. See ius
Kelsen, Hans, 361, 429–30 honorarium; ius praetorium
Kennan, George, 114 legal entanglement. See also specific
kinship terms, in Indigenous treaties, topics
68–9 ad hoc, with corporate social
Kirsch, Stuart, 403, 412–13, 422 responsibility, 318–19
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
of Belt and Road Initiative, 110–24 legal norms
ethnographic methodology in, 118 Belt and Road Initiative and,
interdependence within, 124–7 separateness of norms and,
under international law, 120–1 108–9, 117–24
sociological methodology in, 118 conflict-of-law, 5
under transnational finance law, data-driven management systems as
121–2 substitute for, 87
in British Empire, 8–9 for domestic law, 1
definition of, 412–13 in Ecuador, importation of, 409–11
dynamics of, 11–20 during Late Antique period, 372–4
actors’ role in, 12–15 for religious law, 1
horizontal context in, 19–29 for state law, 1
pathways as factor in, 15–19 for transnational law, 1
temporal elements, 20 legal orders, 1. See also tertiary rules
vertical context in, 18–29 legal entanglements through, 26–31
forms of, 21–6 conflict as result of, 27–8
overarching norms, 24 consolidation as result of, 27–8
reception norms, 23–4, 29 future challenges for, 28–31
straddling practices, 24–6 reception norms and, 29
typologies, 23–6 legal pluralism and, 424–5
history of, 2–3 post-law
cultural studies, 3 pan-legalist objections, 80–1
legal orders and, 5 theoretical approach to, 79–84
legal pluralism in, 3–5 primary rules for, 428–9
in international law, 10 rule of recognition and, 428
through legal orders, 26–31 secondary rules for, 428–9
conflict as result of, 27–8 legal pluralism. See also transnational
consolidation as result of, 27–8 legal pluralism
future challenges for, 28–31 Belt and Road Initiative and,
reception norms and, 29 111
in medieval Europe, 7–9 colonial entanglements and, 37–8
in modern states, 7–11, 127–9 in Germany, 8
norms in global, 10–11
bodies of, 5–6 legal entanglement and, in history of,
tertiary, 5–6, 21 3–5
protesting of, from below legal orders and, 424–5
coherence in approaches to, 420–3 legal positivism, 365
through importation of other legal tertiary rules and, 427–8
norms, 409–11 Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 353–4
through mobilization of law, lex sportiva, 260–2, 285–8
405–9 Ley de Fomento Productivo, Ecuador
through settlement negotiations, 416 (2018), 414–15
singularization of, 415–20, 422–3 Liberia, 235–6
vernacularization and, 422 Lindt, Angela, 416
reverse translation of, 412–13, 422 logics of contract, 70–6
in Roman Empire, 7–9 logics of kinship, 70–6
theoretical approach to, 1–6 Luhmann, Niklas, 30
in transnational law, 10 Luther, Martin, 79–80
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
MacCormick, Neil, 364, 396 National Contact Points (NCPs), for
machine learning, 88–9 OECD, 318–19
Mallard, Grégoire, 229 ad hoc legal entanglement, 326–33
Mar, Maksymilian del, 405 ambiguous cases for, 330–3
Marmor, Andrei, 438 analysis of, 344–7
Marrakesh Agreement, WTO and, 195 distancing through, 329–30
Marry, Sally Engle, 37 free, prior and informed consent,
Mawani, Renisa, 35–6 331–2
MEAs. See multilateral environmental in Germany, 339
agreements implementation mechanisms for,
medieval Europe, legal entanglement 348–9
in, 7–9 integrated normative systems, 333–6
Merry, Sally Engle, 422, 451, 454–6 long-term implications for, 344–7
Mészáros, Lőrinc, 126–7 in Netherlands, 339–40
MFLO. See Muslim Family Laws in Norway, 338
Ordinance proximity between, 333–44
Michaels, Ralf, 449–50, 462–9. See also in Switzerland, 340–1
transnational legal pluralism in United Kingdom, 341–4
Migdal, Joel, 43 national reputation systems, in China,
Mills, Aaron, 63, 69–73, 382 92–3
on constitutional capture, 73 natural law. See ius gentium
Ministry of Commerce (MOFCOM), in NCPs. See National Contact Points
China, 109 Netherlands, National Contact Points
Mitchell v. M.N.R., 384 in, for OECD guidelines,
Modern Slavery Law, Australia, 103 339–40
modern states. See also specific states new materialisms, 76–7
legal entanglement in, 7–11, 127–9 New Silk Road. See Belt and Road
MOFCOM. See Ministry of Commerce Initiative
Monture-Angus, Patricia, 382 New Zealand, Treaty of Waitangi, 389,
Moore, Sally Falk, 450, 453–5 466–7
Morocco, tertiary rules in, 439–41, NGOs. See non-governmental
444–5 organizations
multilateral environmental agreements 9/11 terrorist attacks, 236–7
(MEAs), 195 non-governmental actors, legal
multilateral investment treaties, entanglement and, 14–15
investor–state dispute in Bangladesh, 54–5
settlement mechanisms for, non-governmental organizations
175–6 (NGOs)
multilateral sanctions, by UN Security corporate social responsibility for,
Council, 252–6 320–1
Muslim Family Laws Ordinance deferral of norms by, 36
(MFLO), Bangladesh, 45, denial of norms by, 36
49–50, 55–6 international investment governance
Mutu, Adrian, 273–4 sites and, competing interests
within, 166
Nadasdy, Paul, 69 investor–state dispute settlement
NAFTA. See North American Free mechanisms and, 173–5
Trade Agreement translation of norms by, 36
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
non-state justice institutions. See also corporate social responsibility,
non-governmental actors 318–19. See also National
in Bangladesh, 55–6 Contact Points
non-state law, colonial entanglements analysis of, 344–7
under, 40–1 external bodies of norms, 336–44
norms historical development of, 322–6
for domestic law, 1 human rights norms under, 336
interface, 222–4, 435 implementation framework for,
substantive dimensions for, 223–4 326–8
for international law, 1 long-term implications for, 344–7
conflict-of-law norms, 5 revisions of, 322–6
for legal entanglement overarching norms, 24, 304–7
bodies of, 5–6 Oxford Handbook on Global Legal
overarching norms, 24 Pluralism, 455–6
reception norms, 23–4, 29
tertiary norms, 5–6, 21 P. Petra IV. 9 document, Roman law
non-governmental organizations and, 367–75
and, 36 Pakistan
overarching, 304–7 Awami League, 44
reception, 304–12 Belt and Road Initiative and, 122–3
for religious law, 1 creation of, as nation-state, 43–4
for state law, 1 Muslims in, 43–4
for transnational law, 1 after second partition of Indian
North American Free Trade Agreement subcontinent, 43–4
(NAFTA), 173–4 on sustainable development
Norway mechanisms, 203
Civil Procedure Act, 137–8 panel of experts (PoE), for UN Security
Criminal Procedure Act, 137–8 Council, 241–51
National Contact Points in, for evaluation and monitoring of
OECD guidelines, 338 sanctions, 246–7
Nuclear Iran Prevention Act, US implementation of sanctions, 244,
(2013), 253–4 251
Nuclear Proliferation Prevention Act, institutional support for, 245–6
US (1994), 253 political nature of, 244–5
UN Security Council Resolutions
OBOR initiative. See One Belt, One and, 251
Road initiative Paris Agreement, corporate social
OECD guidelines. See Organisation for responsibility under, 338
Economic Co-operation and pathways, to legal entanglement,
Development guidelines 15–18
OHCHR. See United Nations coercion as, 17–19
oil dumping cases, in Ecuador, 413–14 ideational context, 15–16
One Belt, One Road (OBOR) initiative, rational choices in, 16
107–8 resonance in, 16
Orbán, Viktor, 126–7 PCA. See Permanent Court of
Organisation for Economic Co- Arbitration
operation and Development Peat, David, 69–70
(OECD) guidelines, for Pechstein, Claudia, 287–8
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Permanent Court of Arbitration (PCA), private rule systems, transnational legal
171 pluralism and, 459–61
Peru, Free Trade Agreement, with processing and production methods
Canada, 178–9 (PPMs), 195
Philippines
UN human rights treaties Rahman, Ziaur, 45
monitoring bodies in, 139 Randeria, Shalini, 408
Wilson v. Ermita, 139 rational choices, in pathways to legal
Pistorius, Oscar, 261–2 entanglement, 16
Platini, Michel, 261–2 Raw and the Cooked, The (Lévi-
pluralism. See also legal pluralism; Strauss), 353–4
transnational legal pluralism Raz, Joseph, 361, 379, 458–9
constitutional, 10 reception norms, 23–4, 29, 304–12
within corporate social regime law, transnational legal
responsibility, 348 pluralism and, 472–5
institutional, 299 regulatory pluralism, 475–7
regulatory, 475–7 relabeling, in transnational legal
PoE. See panel of experts pluralism, 459
political capital, 230 religious law
population data in Bangladesh, colonial
data-driven management systems entanglements in, 43–6
for, 86–7 Hefazaat-e-Islamni movement,
social credit initiatives for, in 45
Western nations, 101 Muslim Family Laws Ordinance,
positivism. See legal positivism 45, 49–50, 55–6
post-law legal orders. See also data- norms for, 1
driven management systems Rhaman, Mujibur (Sheikh), 44
pan-legalist objections, 80–1 Rhodesia, 235
theoretical approach to, 79–84 right to be forgotten, 102–3
postnational law, 361–6 Riles, Annelise, 302
governance structures, 363 Rio Declaration, 194–5
jurisdictional aspect of, 363 Rodriguez, José Luis Alonso, 365
law in action approaches, 364 Roman Empire. See also Roman law
law in practice approaches, 364 legal entanglement in, 7–9
Transnational Legal Process model, Roman law
364 citizenship under, 366–7
PPMs. See processing and production Greco-Roman international law,
methods 356–7
primary rules, for legal orders, 428–9 peace treaties under, 357
privacy rights, 102–3 historical development of, 356–61
private international law imperial expansion as influence on,
philosophical foundations for, 354–5 358–9
tertiary rules and, 446–7 ius civile, 360
Westphalian state governance and, ius gentium, 360
354–5 ius honorarium, 360
private property laws, colonial ius praetorium, 360
entanglements and, 38–9 jurisdictional aspect of, 359, 365–6
private Roman law, 367 user theory in, 374–5
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Late Antique period, 366–74 Siddiqui, Dina, 48–9
dispute settlement agreements in, Sieder, Rachel, 420
371–2 Sierra Leone, 235–6
legal norms during, 372–4 singularization, 415–20, 422–3
P. Petra IV. 9 document, 367–75 ‘social contract’, Indigenous legalities
strategic legal argumentation in, and, 71–2
373–4 social credit initiatives
layers of, 360 in China, 91–8
legal entanglements in, 366–74 application mechanisms for,
legal positivism and, 365 95–7
private, 367 baseline systems, 97
provincial system under, 358–9 blacklists, 97
Romano, Santi, 458 Chinese Communist Party
rooted constitutionalism, Indigenous influences on, 91–2
treaties and, 69–70 in commercial activities, 95–6
Roughan, Nicole, 433–4 during Covid-19 pandemic, 91
Royal Proclamation of 1763 (Canada), for culture projects, 96–7
386, 388–9, 397 for education projects, 96–7
Ruggie, John, 324–6 goals and objectives of, 92–5
rule of recognition, 428 national reputation systems and,
‘The Ruse Law’, Sudan, 41 92–3
as new type of law, 93–4
Sachenspiegel, 7 social ordering and, 93
Salomon, Noah, 41 Twelve Core Socialist Values and,
sanction regimes. See also UN Security 94–5
Council data-driven management systems
colonial legal entanglements and, and, 84–6
230 governance actor relationships
Western law and, historical influenced by, 88
development of, 229–30 in Western nations, 98–104
Santos, Boaventura de Sousa, 30 for census data, 101
SASF. See semi-autonomous social field compliance mechanisms, 103
secondary rules, for legal orders, 428–9 extraspatial zones for, 98–9
Semenya, Caster, 261–2 governance, risk management,
semi-autonomous social field (SASF), and compliance systems,
457 99–101
SGBs. See sports governing bodies governance mechanisms, 103–4
Sharapova, Maria, 261–2 for privacy rights, 102–3
Sharia law and, 467–8 for right to be forgotten, 102–3
Shehabuddin, Elora, 54–5 Social Impact Assessments, 326
Shrimp-Turtle case, 201–6, 219 social ordering, in social credit
appeals process for, 204–5 initiatives, 93
Convention on International Trade sociological positivism, tertiary rules
in Endangered Species and, and, 427
202–4 soft financial law, 292
under environmental law, 204 Sousa Santos, Boaventura de, 453–4
legal aftermath of, 206 South Africa, counter-terrorist
legal entanglements in, 202–4 sanctions against, 235
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Spain exclusive applicability of, 265–8
Convention on the Elimination of FIFA cases, 263–8
All Forms of Discrimination Haas doctrine and, 265
against Women in, 155–8 sports governing bodies under,
UN human rights monitoring bodies 262–3
in, 155–8 Swiss Federal Tribunal, 262–3
Usatges de Barcelona, 7 jurisdictional initiatives in, 407
sports governing bodies (SGBs) National Contact Points in, for
administrative practices of, 260–1 OECD guidelines, 340–1
due process inside, 280–2 Syria, tertiary rules in, 436
European Convention on Human cross-border normativity and, 430
Rights and, compatibility with, system-centred law approach, to
277–80 Indigenous legalities, 398
under Swiss law, 262–3 systems theory, 30
World Anti-Doping Code and,
277–9 Taylor, Lance, 301
SPS Agreement. See Agreement on TBT Agreement. See Agreement on
Sanitary and Phytosanitary Technical Barriers to Trade
Measures tertiary norms, 5–6, 21
Stark, Heidi, 69 tertiary rules, for legal orders
state law application of foreign laws, 446–7
colonial entanglements under, 40–1 arguments for, 425–6
norms for, 1 characteristics of, 434–42
Staying with the Trouble (Haraway), 77 designation of normative spaces,
Strathern, Marilyn, 402–3 435–7
Sudan, ‘The Ruse Law’, 41 horizontal nature, 438–40
Supply Chain Due Diligence Law, legal nature, 437–8
France, 103 relationality, 440–2
supremacy claims, for Indigenous choice of law, 431–2
legalities, in Canada, 378–95 cross-border normativity and,
acceptance of, 385 428–34
Canadian law and, relations between, authority sharing strategies,
388–95 433–4
supremacy of force, 384–7 challenges from, 429–30
supremacy of institutions, 381–4 denial strategies, 431–2
supremacy of norms, 380–1 internalization strategies, 432–3
Supreme Court of Canada, 381–4 in Syrian law, 430
sustainable constitutionalism, 61–2 definition of, 435
sustainable development mechanisms, in English law, 439–41, 444–5
203 external recognition, of national
under General Agreement on Tariffs laws, 442–5
and Trade, 221 fact doctrines, 431
World Trade Organization, 221 in German law, 436–7
SWIFT, in counter-terrorist sanctions, hierarchy in, 439
249–50 legal positivism and, 427–8
Switzerland in Moroccan law, 439–41, 444–5
Court of Arbitration for Sport and, private international laws and, 446–7
Swiss law as influence on, 262–8 recognition of, 447–8
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
recognition of foreign acts, records, as relational legal concept, flaws of,
and judicial proceedings, 444–6 462–9
sociological positivism and, 427 separation of theory and practice
in Syrian law, 436 under, 461–2
cross-border normativity in, 430 Sharia law and, 467–8
in US law, 444–5 sociological approaches to, 453,
vested rights theory and, 432 456–9
Teubner, Gunther, 453–4 theoretical approach to, 449–50
Texaco, 413–14 Transnational Legal Process model, for
This Is Not a Peace Pipe (Turner), 385 postnational law, 364
Thomas, Flavius, 370 Trans-Pacific Partnership (TPP),
Tietmeyer, Hans, 299 112–13
Todd, Zoe, 77 investor–state dispute settlement
TPP. See Trans-Pacific Partnership mechanisms under, 185
Trachtman, Joel, 435 transparency regimes, 100
trade law. See international trade law Treaty of Niagara, 66
Transatlantic Trade and Investment Treaty of Rome, 116–17
Partnership (TTIP), 189–90 Treaty of Waitangi, New Zealand, 389,
transnational finance law, Belt and 466–7
Road Initiative under, 121–2 tribunals. See investment tribunals
transnational law Trindade, Cançado, 186–7
colonial entanglements under, 39–40 Tripartite Group of Banks working
for finance, Belt and Road Initiative group, 292–3
under, 121–2 TRIPS Agreement. See Agreement on
legal entanglement in, 10 Trade-Related Aspects of
norms for, 1 Intellectual Property Rights
transnational legal pluralism Trump, Donald, 460–1
in Australia, 466 Truth and Reconciliation Commission,
bodies of law within, multiplicity of, 383
451–2 TTIP. See Transatlantic Trade and
collective recognition and, 471 Investment Partnership
community law and, 472–5 Tully, James, 61–2, 114.10. See also
conventional recognition and, 472 Indigenous legalities;
cross-polity law and, 472–5 sustainable constitutionalism
foundations of, 470–5 Tuna Dolphin I case, 199–201, 219
global approaches to, 453 Convention on International Trade
Indigenous legalities and, 466, 469 in Endangered Species, 199–200
Jewish law and, 467 legal aftermath of, 201
jurisprudential legal concepts and, legal entanglements in, 199–201
456–9 regional factors, 199
over-inclusiveness flaw in, 454–6 Tuna Dolphin II case, 199–201, 219
paradigms of, 450–4 Turner, Dale, 385
postcolonial approaches to, 453 Twelve Core Socialist Values, in China,
private rule systems and, 459–61 94–5
regime law and, 472–5 Twining, William, 449, 454
regulatory forms in, 459–61 Two-Row Wampum
regulatory pluralism and, 475–7 as symbolism, 73, 389–90
relabeling and, 459 as treaty feature, 385–6, 389–90
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
UK. See United Kingdom against Iran, 238–9, 252–3
UN. See United Nations panel of experts and, 251
UN human rights treaties monitoring requirements of, 247–8
bodies. See also specific UNCED. See United Nations
conventions; specific treaties uncertainty principle, 60
in domestic courts, 148–50 UNCITRAL. See United Nations
acceptance and engagement of, UNDRIP. See United Nations
155–60 UNFCC. See United Nations
case-specific pathways, 151–5 United Kingdom
judicial engagement in, 143–6, economic relations with China, 113
155–60 investor–state dispute settlement
judicial non-engagement in, 138–41 mechanisms in, 179–80
normative pathways for, 150–5 National Contact Points in, for
in Spain, 155–60 OECD guidelines, 341–4
goals and objectives of, 133 tertiary rules in, 439–41, 444–5
International Court of Justice UN human rights treaties
engagement with, 134–6 monitoring bodies in, 144–6
judicial engagement with, 143–8, United Nations (UN). See also UN
155–60 human rights treaties
acceptance of, 155–60 monitoring bodies; UN Security
in Australia, 144, 146–8 Council
in Canada, 144–6 Commission on International Trade
in domestic courts, 143–6, 155–60 Law, 171, 190–1
in Israel, 143–4 Conference on Environment and
normative pathways for, 146–8 Development, 194
as substantive, 144–6 Declaration on the Rights of
in UK, 144–6 Indigenous Peoples, 332
judicial non-engagement with, 138–43 Framework Convention on Climate
in domestic courts, 138–41 Change, 194
in international courts, 141–3 Guiding Principles, 324–6
in Ireland, 138–9 High Commissioner for Human
in Philippines, 139 Rights, 187
jurisprudence of, domestic relevance Human Rights Committee, 21, 135
of, 135–8 judicial decisions for, 140
normative pathways for, 133–4 obligations to cooperate, 158–60
theoretical approach to, 133–4, United States (US). See also counter-
160–1 terrorist sanctions regime
Vienna Convention on the Law of 9/11 terrorist attacks against, 236–7
Treaties, 146–7 Comprehensive Iran Sanctions,
UN Security Council (UNSC), 231–4 Accountability, and Divestment
Democratic People’s Republic of Act, 253–4
Korea and, sanctions against, Executive Order 12938, US, 253
233 Export-Import Bank Act, 253–4
UN Security Council Resolutions Helms–Burton Act, 253–4
(UNSCRs), 233, 244–5 International Emergency Economic
against Democratic People’s Powers Act, 250
Republic of Korea, 240, 248–9 investor–state dispute settlement
Financial Action Task Force and, 246 mechanisms in, 168
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
Iran Freedom and Counter- Whyte, Kyle Powys, 77
Proliferation Act, 253–4 Williams, Robert, Jr., 63–4
North American Free Trade Wojtczak, Marzena, 373
Agreement, 173–4 women’s rights, in Bangladesh, 54–5
Nuclear Iran Prevention Act, 253–4 World Anti-Doping Code (WADC),
Nuclear Proliferation Prevention 277–9
Act, 253 World Bank Group, 115, 256–7
tertiary rules in, 444–5 global financial governance and,
US-Ecuador Bilateral Investment 296–7
Treaty, 413–14 World Health Assembly, 21
War on Terror and, 236–7 World Trade Organization (WTO)
UNSC. See UN Security Council Agreement on Technical Barriers to
UNSCRs. See UN Security Council Trade, 206–7
Resolutions Canada/US Continued Suspension
Uruguay Round, GATT, 195–6 dispute, 220
US. See United States Codex Alimentarius Commission
Usatges de Barcelona, 7 and, 206–8
US–Ecuador Bilateral Investment Dispute Settlement Body, 196–8
Treaty, 413–14 claims process for, 197
user theory for jurisdiction, 374–5 jurisdiction of, 197
US-Tuna II case, 214–18 dispute settlement mechanisms,
Agreement on Technical Barriers to 196–8
Trade and, 215–18 distancing strategies as part of,
appeals process for, 216–18 221–2
legal aftermath of, 218 international law as influence on,
legal entanglements in, 216–18 197–8
for legal entanglements, 220–2
Valverde, Alejandro, 261–2 Dispute Settlement Understanding,
VCLT. See Vienna Convention on the 196–8
Law of Treaties EC Hormones dispute, 206–12, 220
vernacularization, 422 Agreement on Sanitary and
vertical context, for legal entanglement, Phytosanitary Measures and,
18–29 206–10
vested rights theory, 432 appeals process for, 209–10
Victoria (Queen), 68 legal aftermath of, 210–12
Vienna Convention on the Law of legal entanglements in, 207–8
Treaties (VCLT), 146–7 EC-Biotech dispute, 212–14, 220
investor–state dispute settlement EU–Canada Comprehensive
mechanisms and, 173–4, Economic and Trade
179–80 Agreement and, 214
Village Court Act, Bangladesh (2006), genetically–modified organisms
55–6 in, 212–14
legal aftermath of, 213–14
WADC. See World Anti-Doping Code legal entanglements in, 213
Walker, Neil, 355, 357–8 establishment of, 194
Walters, Mark, 382–3 Marrakesh Agreement and, 195
War on Terror, 236–7 interface norms, 222–4
White, Sarah, 43, 54 substantive dimensions for, 223–4
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A
World Trade Organization (WTO) Convention on International Trade
(cont.) in Endangered Species and, 202–4
investor–state dispute settlement under environmental law, 204
mechanisms and, 169 legal aftermath of, 206
norm conflicts and, 198–224 legal entanglements in, 202–4
in cases and disputes, over time, sustainable development issues
219–20 under, 221
processing and production methods theoretical approach to, 193–4
and, 195 World Wildlife Fund (WWF), 331–2
Shrimp-Turtle case, 201–6, 219 WTO. See World Trade Organization
appeals process for, 204–5 WWF. See World Wildlife Fund
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 223.190.87.18, on 26 Nov 2021 at 14:08:02, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/04306155350E1A8D300AFFABF4A3A58A