Agnosis - Theology in The Void (PDFDrive)
Agnosis - Theology in The Void (PDFDrive)
George Pattison
Dean of Chapel
King's College
Cambridge
First published in Great Britain 1996 by
MACMILLAN PRESS LTD
Houndmills. Basingsloke, Hampshire RG2I 6XS
and London
Companies and representatives
throughout the world
A catalogue record for this book is available
from the British Library.
ISBN 0-333-63864-6
Introduction 1
Notes 170
Bibliography 188
Index 192
Acknowledgements
A work such as this is the product, for good or ill, of insights and
arguments gleaned from many different sources - more, probably,
than I am myself able to recognize. I do, however, acknowledge a
particular debt to colleagues and friends who have read and com-
mented on sections of this book at various stages in its production
or discussed some of the ideas in it with me, especially Pippa Berry,
David Ford, Wolfram Kinzig, Irena Makarushka, Steve Shakespeare,
Shudo Tsukiyama and Yasugi Yamaguchi. Many of the thoughts on
Nietzsche and Kierkegaard came into focus through the Nietzsche
and Kierkegaard reading groups in which I participated between
1993 and 1995 and I would like to thank the members of those
groups. I am also particularly grateful to the Provost and Fellows of
King's College for permitting me to take a period of leave during
the early stages of work on this project. Many of the ideas pre-
sented here have been discussed over the years with my good friend
Ulrich Fentzloff and I am specifically indebted to him for introduc-
ing me to Heidegger's Beitriige zur Philosophie and for the days spent
reading in his guest room.
The challenge of Don Cupitt's work was a major motive in set-
ting to work on this project, which, though in one respect intended
as a critique of elements in his writing, is also offered as an ac-
knowledgement of his courage in expanding the boundaries of theo-
logical thinking in Britain.
My family have had to endure long hours of distractedness, as
I stared into the abyss of agnosis. Sorry - but thank you Hilary,
Charlotte, Neil and Beth.
Introduction
In calling for a transformation of religious belief that would make
it accessible to inhabitants of the postmodern world, the English
philosopher of religion Don Cupitt, in his 1982 book The World to
Come, suggested that such a transformation would involve looking
'long enough into the Void to feel it turn our bones to water'. Cupitt
described such a willed endurance of the Void in terms that recall
the language of mysticism, stating that it requires of us an 'inner
transformation' and 'a discipline of selflessness' until the Void itself
is transformed into 'the Ineffable', arousing '(non-cognitive) wor-
ship'.1 Yet, if this seems to imply an understanding of the contem-
porary experience of the void as corresponding in some way to the
moment of purgation or to 'the dark night of the soul' that various
forms of ascetical theology have often described, Cupitt's concep-
tion of the void is distinctively modern. For, as he understands it,
the void is not simply some inner state, a subjective feeling of aban-
donment or dereliction. No: 'the Void' is a characterization of the
religious situation of our time; it is that into which all the inherited
concepts and categories, icons and images of God have collapsed.
It is the situation left by that 'death of God' proclaimed by the
madman of Nietzsche's parable, a death that not only shakes the
foundations of religious constructions of reality but also undermines
all systems of social order, ethical existence and metaphysical specu-
lation. In a world that is in this radical sense Godless no 'reality'
can be taken for granted, no all-embracing framework holds to-
gether the diverse realms of science and culture, no ultimate refer-
ent secures the ever-shifting helix of symbolic systems. The world
is only what we make it, only how we represent it, only a function
of language.
The adepts of such a Void can no longer cohabit with the reas-
suring doctrines of the theistic belief that provided mystics and
knights of faith of previous ages with a stabilizing frame of refer-
ence for their wilder ventures of godly desire. For this Void is itself
inseparable from the death of God and the end of theism. Yet,
Cupitt maintains, some form of religion is possible on the far side
1
2 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
of the Void, a form that (in his writings at least) has become known
as 'non-realism', that is, a form of belief that no longer claims the
sanction of reality for its beliefs and practices. Such belief is a self-
consciously 'merely' human invention, a way of speaking.
However, such 'Hyperborean faith' (as Cupitt called it in The
World to Come) is inseparable from the experience of the void itself.
But can that experience be turned into a secure 'result' on which a
future theology can safely build its postpostmodern structure? Won't
a truly post-realist faith find itself returning ever again to the void
that is its birth-place, whence alone it can be born and re-born,
again and again?
We have been here before. From the 'theology of the death of
God' of the 1960s, through Tillich's confrontation with the manifes-
tation of non-being in existentialist meaninglessness, through Karl
Barth's 1921 portrayal of a humanist world laid waste, through
Nietzsche himself and back, past Kierkegaard, to Hegel (at least):
the encounter with nothingness has been a recurrent motif of mod-
ern religious thought. Nor is it any wonder that many in the West
have found themselves attracted to Buddhism as a form of religion
in which that encounter appears to have been successfully internal-
ized. Indeed, Cupitt himself has referred to his own style of Chris-
tianity as 'Christian Buddhism'.
It is not only religious thought that has succumbed to the lure of
the abyss, however. Secular culture has been - and continues to be
- highly productive of verbal and visual evocations of the void.
'There's no lack of void,' as Samuel Beckett's tramp Estragon said
to his associate Vladimir. Painting, music, literature and film can all
provide examples enough. The void is not just a matter of modern
religious experience: it is integral to the modern experience as such.
Of course, there is a considerable body of opinion that maintains
that all this concern with the void is somewhat passe', being too
redolent of postwar depression and existentialist despair. Writing
in 1966 Robert Martin Adams could claim that 'Nothing is closer to
the supreme commonplace of our commonplace age than its preoc-
cupation with Nothing.'2 Today, however (or so the story goes),
we've left all that behind. Cupitt himself declares that 'the mourning
is over':3 the death of God is no longer an occasion for anxiety, grief
or despair but the beginning of a 'joyful wisdom'. Such a wisdom
indulges itself in the creation of new values and new symbols with-
out the kind of guilt or melancholy that characterized the first wave
of post-theistic thinkers such as Schopenhauer and Kierkegaard.
Introduction 3
and debt to Japanese Buddhism. But this is not to say that Agnosis
is merely a heavily coded autobiography, for (to stay with this
particular instance) the world-historical encounter between Europe
and East Asia is one that has massive implications at every level for
the shape of human existence in the twenty-first century. In terms
of autobiographical influences, it may be added that the biggest
single such influence in the present work is my own repeated real-
ization of my inability to live by the faith I profess. But that too - the
record suggests - is no unique experience. On the contrary, it is one
with which all those who seek to live Christian lives and to under-
stand Christian thought must come to terms.
It is always possible, of course, that other works and other writ-
ers have important things to say on nothingness. One such is Meister
Eckhart. Such omissions must be acknowledged - but, precisely
because I am not attempting a Hegelian world-history of nothing-
ness, they do not require apology, since I am aiming neither to
produce an exhaustive survey of all relevant material nor to achieve
any kind of finality.
A separate, methodological comment may also be of some use at
this point. A number of discussions of nothingness have begun by
attempting to offer a clear definition of the concept itself. An exam-
ple of this is Paul Tillich's development of the distinction between
me on and ouk on as the distinction between a relative kind of non-
being that can come into some sort of dialectical relation to being
and an absolute kind of non-being that is sheer nothingness. How-
ever, such attempts to stabilize usage have been, at best, disap-
pointing in terms of results. The key Greek terms to einai, he ousia
and to on have between them been variously translated as being,
reality, substance, essence and existence and both the original terms
and their translations have been variously assimilated to each other
or distinguished from each other. Already in the classical world
there was, as Christopher Stead has put it in his study Divine Sub-
stance, 'extraordinary chaos and incongruity' amongst the various
senses of ousia and correlative terms.6 Nor have matters improved
since - and if that is the case with 'being' how much more are the
difficulties going to be compounded when it comes to the negative
terms! In any case, even if a single author can achieve consistency
within the covers of a single book, there is little to suggest that one
person's usage is going to command the kind of consensus that
would be a chief aim of any such exercise. A definition that cannot
take its place in the world of conventional usage is of very limited
6 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
value. More often the only result is to torture language into impos-
sible and unsustainable positions.7
Thus, although terminological exactitude is an ideal not to be
scorned and although (in another respect) there is much that is
appealing in the kind of profound reflection on 'basic words' prac-
tised by a Heidegger, I have chosen to paint with a broader brush
and to allow the sense of such terms as void, non-being and noth-
ingness to emerge from their place in the larger picture. Once again
it is a matter of enabling the question to emerge with just enough
distinctness as to point us towards an appropriate response.
The Augustinian
Inheritance
Despite the contemporary repudiation of Augustinianism, Augus-
tine remains a defining thinker for Western Christianity and for
Western thought in many fields.1 For in Augustine we can see the
drawing together of the manifold threads of Platonizing Christian-
ity and thus an expression of what theology, when it is at its most
metaphysical, might have to say. Moreover, with regard to the very
specific area of questioning to be pursued in what follows, Augus-
tine's formulation of the issues remained determinative even for
those traditions of Christian metaphysics that looked more to Aris-
totle than to Plato.
What then is the place of nothingness in Augustine's theology
and how important is it in the overall structure of that theology?
One primary context in which nothingness is discussed is the
problem of evil, in relation to which the concept of nothingness or
non-being is used to harmonize faith in the goodness and omnipo-
tence of God with a vision of the world as fallen. This suggests that
the topic is one of vital importance to the whole structure of Augus-
tine's theology. For although the problem of reconciling belief in an
all-good and all-powerful deity with the all too apparent evidence
of evil was not unique to Christianity (and, as we shall shortly see,
Augustine was able to draw heavily on Platonic sources in his for-
mulation of and response to this problem), the Judaeo-Christian
emphasis on the sovereign and personal character of God inscribed
this problem in the very heart of the theological project.
It is by no means coincidental that this is one of the questions
where Augustine's appropriation of Platonism is most apparent
and yet, at the same time, most transformative. To anticipate: it is
precisely in his manner of appropriating the Platonic doctrine of
evil as non-being that Augustine prepares the ultimate demolition
of Platonic cosmology and the advent of an existential and radically
religious understanding of human existence - an understanding
that, in its turn, was to provide the paradoxical foundation for a
8 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
PLOTINUS
Yet the status of this 'evil' is problematic, since the realm defined
by limit and measure is coterminous with the realm of being and of
goodness. What follows?
beauty must fill us with veneration for their creator and convince
us of their origin in the divine, forms which show how ineffable
is the beauty of the Supreme since they cannot hold us but we
must, though in all admiration, leave these for those. Further,
wherever there is interior beauty, we may be sure that inner and
outer correspond... if anyone tells me he has seen people
fine-looking but interiorly vile, I can only deny i t . . . the All is
beautiful...
(Enn. II.9.17)
The outer world then - the material world in the modern sense
- is in some measure participant in, related to or a reflection of the
intellectual, intelligible world, the world of Ideas, of Forms. Lying
between that which is incapable of form and manifestation on the
one hand and the Goodness that is 'beyond being' on the other, it
is, in varying degrees and combinations, a mixture of being and
non-being. In this lies its character as a world of becoming, a world
of change and chance, of instability and impermanence, a world in
which what is formed and shaped and knowable is prone to defor-
mation, to the disintegration of shape and to a falling away from
knowledge. In this respect non-being, just as much as being, can be
said to characterize everything we experience and everything which
is for us an object of consciousness apart from what is purely and
solely intellectual. The question for Plotinus is essentially the moral
or religious question: whether we allow the guiding thread of being
within a world permeated by non-being to lead us to the vision
of absolute Beauty, or whether we allow non-being, disorder, to
frustrate such contemplation and obscure its analogues within the
world of sense.
To ask, then, about the 'time' 'when' truth first entered the mind
would not, on Augustine's understanding, be properly answered
by appearing to check a mental event (the moment of learning truth)
against an external, objective 'time'; rather, the question as to the
'time' of truth is answered by referring time itself to the synthetic
function of memory. It is memory that provides the measure of
time and not vice versa.
To see the wider implications of this statement, we need to note
further aspects of the concept of time.
Augustine's initial attempt to answer the question 'What is time?'
involves an examination of the three dimensions of time - past,
present and future. The question is, however, soon brought to a
standstill by the nature of the object of enquiry, since, as we expe-
rience it, neither can time be grasped in an essential definition nor,
more profoundly, 'is' time at any point, in the sense of an enduring
presence-to-consciousness.
Of these three divisions of time, then, how can two, the past and
the future be, when the past no longer is and the future is not yet?
As for the present, if it were always present and never moved on
to become the past, it would not be time but eternity. If, there-
fore, the present is time only by reason of the fact that it moves
on to become the past, how can we say that even the present is,
when the reason why it is is that it is not to be? [... cui causa, ut
sit, ilia est, quia non erit.. . ] In other words, we cannot rightly say
that time is, except by its impending state of not being. [... non
vere dicamus tetnpus esse, nisi quia tendit non esse.]26
Now the nature of the Living Being was eternal, a character with
which it was impossible fully to endow a generated thing. But he
planned to make as it were a moving likeness of eternity; and, at
the same time that he set in order the Heaven, he made, of eter-
nity that abides in unity, an ever-flowing likeness moving ac-
cording to number - that to which we have given the name Time.27
to bear the stamp of the ex nihilo (i.e. will still be a creature), but it
will no longer be 'in time'; in the pure intellectual contemplation of
God by the mind (memory) it will, as creature, be, with God, out-
side of and purged of time.
This is not to say that the concept of time can of itself explain
how creatures created ex nihilo fall away from their Creator towards
another kind of non-being, a kind that is both utter and culpable.
For the sceptic can always rephrase his question by asking why the
Creator should make a temporal creation if time by definition is
separation from God? But if time does not 'explain' the fall, it does
focus more precisely the place in or at which the non-being of the
creature qua creature (and specifically the willing creature, the hu-
man being) is exposed to the non-being of evil - its own evil and
the evil that befalls it. The non-being of time is thus a bridge be-
tween the non-being of the ex nihilo and the non-being revealed in
rebellion, fall and punishment.29
From his reflections on evil, time and the origin of the world,
Augustine created a composite picture in which the character of the
human subject is determined by its creation ex nihilo, its temporality
and its fall towards nothingness. If this leads to the concept of
nothingness having a central role in the ontological schematization
of existence, it also influences the psychological account of the will,
which comes to be seen as permeated by the nothingness from
which it was created and also endowed with responsibility for the
self's subsequent choice of nothingness over against being. But even
when Augustine 'explains' the malfunctioning of the will by means
of ontological categories, the will as we encounter it and as he
describes it is first and foremost revealed in the world of concrete
existence: the living, passional and volitional situation of the hu-
man subject. This existential situation is thereby constituted as a
phenomenological surface on which Augustine is able to map non-
being in narrative and psychological terms. In attempting to read
that map with Augustine, we begin to see how the existential story
of non-being-as-fallen-will-in-time is sowing the seeds of destruc-
tion of the very metaphysics to which Augustine himself appeals,
indeed these seeds are sown in the very process by which Augustine seeks
to explain that story metaphysically.
Let us then attempt a brief reconstruction of Augustine's existential
The Augustinian Inheritance 21
Such precepts would not be given unless a man had a will of his
own, wherewith to obey the divine commandments; and yet it is
God's gift which is indispensable for the observance of the pre-
cepts of chastity . . . It follows, then, that the victory in which sin
is vanquished is nothing else than the gift of God, who in this
contest helps the free-will of the combatant.
(APW, pp. 22-3)
22 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
All this, however, applies only to those who are already engaged
in attempting to live the Christian life; but the foundation of that
life depends entirely on grace. For Augustine, as for many of his
later interpreters, the testimony of St Paul was decisive - and not
only the testimony of Paul the theologian but of Paul the man, the
persecutor of the Church who became the Apostle to the Gentiles.
With regard to the state of Paul prior to his conversion Augustine
remarks: 'Now there was, no doubt, a decided merit in the Apostle
Paul, but it was an evil one, while he persecuted the Church . . . and
it was while he was in possession of this evil merit that a good one
was rendered to him instead of the evil' (APW, p. 26). Nonetheless,
Augustine does not adduce Paul's miraculous conversion in order
to do away with the need for the exercise of the freedom of the will
by the believer. There is, or will be, a place for such exercise, but the
basis must be clear: 'For the accomplishment, however, of the radi-
cal change within him - his call from heaven, and his conversion by
that great and most effectual call - God's grace operated alone,
because his merits, though great, were yet evil' (ibid.). If Augustine
concedes a degree of freedom in all this, it is not so great as to
legitimate the kind of talk of human merit that he ascribes to his
opponents.
His essential purpose remains the justification of God in the face
of human complaints. As he says in responding to the Pelagian
writer Julian: 'They are not, then, free from righteousness except by
the choice of the will, but they do not become free from sin save by
the grace of the Saviour' (APW, p. 240).
Augustine returns again to Paul and, in particular, the seventh
chapter of Paul's letter to the Romans where Paul is addressing the
contradiction between the content of the Jewish Torah, which he
affirms, and its effectiveness in bringing about the fulfilment of its
own commandments. The discussion issues in a string of paradoxi-
cal assertions: 'For that which I do, I allow not: for what I would,
that do I not; but what I hate, that I do' (v. 15); ' . . . for to will is
present with me; but how to perform that which is good I find not.
For the good that I would I do not: but the evil which I would not,
that I do' (vv. 18-19) and 'For I delight in the law of God after the
inward man: but I see another law in my members, warring against
the law of my mind, and bringing me into captivity to the law of
sin, which is in my members' (v. 24).
Augustine takes this to mean that the struggle between sin and
grace continued in Paul after his conversion. So, when Paul writes:
The Augustinian Inheritance 23
'For we know that the Law is spiritual: but I am carnal, sold under
sin' (7.14), Augustine takes the 'I am carnal' to refer, not to Paul the
Pharisee, persecutor of the Church, but to Paul the Apostle, one
who has received the gift of faith but does not yet enjoy the fullness
of that blessedness to which he aspires. The statement is to be read,
as it appears, as a statement in the present tense and not an oblique
reference to a conquered past. Nor does Augustine - perhaps sur-
prisingly given the persistent traces of the Manichean distrust of
matter to be found even in his mature thought - soften the impact
of this reading by allowing the admission of carnality to be taken
solely as a reference to the body in which, as a mortal human being,
Paul still lives. It is of the whole of himself, of the two inseparable
elements of body and spirit, that Paul is here speaking.
The picture that emerges in Augustine's exegesis is thus a picture
of a self divided against itself. This is the situation both of the
Apostle and of all who, like him, are 'established under grace . . .
[but]... not yet established in that perfect peace in which death
shall be swallowed up in victory' (APW, p. 255). In this intermedi-
ate state, even though we have withdrawn our consent to sin, we
still lack the power to overcome it. Indeed, in a sense, conversion
intensifies the predicament of the divided self. For the turning
of the will, through grace, towards the good sharpens the conflict
between the different factors in the situation. For, though still sub-
ject to carnal lust (meaning by this an active perversion of the self
rather than the vehemence of bodily desires), the 'spiritual' self
refuses its consent to such lust; though 'free from the consent of
depraved lusts' Paul and the other Apostles 'still groaned concern-
ing the lust of the flesh, which they bridled by restraint with such
humility and piety, that they desired rather not to have it than to
overcome it' (APW, p. 256).
It is thus possible to speak of three forms of willing in Augus-
tine's view of the self. The first, or lowest, is that of the carnal self,
the will determined by selfish lust; the second is that of the believer
whose will, in the mode of free choice, is directed to the good, even
though he is incapable of bringing that good to fruition; the third
is the good will sustained and endowed with perseverance by grace
and no longer subject in any way to the power of nothingness.
If the first of these forms belongs to humanity apart from faith,
even Christians can only attain the second form in this life, poised
between the moment of conversion and the final triumph of the
City of God. Precisely because this life is a life lived in time, a life
24 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
and, therefore, the source of the being and goodness of all else that
is. As was the case for Augustine, 'no being, as being' can be evil.34
Thomas did not, of course, monopolize the discourse on nothing-
ness in the Christian Middle Ages. Important and provocative con-
tributions come also from the more radically mystical line of
medieval thinking. Some of these will be examined in another con-
text.35 Yet metaphysical ontology continued to provide a frame-
work within which the basic issues of Christian faith were thought.
The most radical challenge to such assumptions was, paradoxically,
to come from a theology that was itself strongly Augustinian -
albeit a theology that pitted the Augustine of the Pelagian conflict
against Augustine the Platonic metaphysician. This was the theo-
logy of the Protestant reformation and, above all, of Luther and
Calvin.
Few texts were more central to the theology of the Protestant
Reformation than Paul's Letter to the Romans, in particular as me-
diated by Augustine. Luther's own Lectures on Romans of 1515/16
were a pivotal moment in his discovery of 'justification by faith
alone' as a foundational principle in theology. He summarized the
teaching of the letter thus: "The chief purpose of this letter is to
break down, to pluck up, and to destroy all wisdom and righteous-
ness of the flesh . . . We must be taught a righteousness that comes
completely from outside and is foreign. And therefore our own
righteousness that is born in us must first be plucked up.'36 In this
concern for a righteousness that comes solely from God, Luther
makes explicit the transformation of the metaphysical language of
nothingness in Augustine's analysis of the divided self in order to
turn it against metaphysics. For example, with reference to Romans
3.7 Luther wrote:
form; again a 'potential idea' does not receive form unless at its
inception it has been stripped of all form and is like a tabula
rasa.37
But this does not mean that the material and spiritual depend-
ence of the creature on the Creator is defined in such a way as to
inscribe 'non-being' as some kind of ontological deficiency (and
thus an abiding potentiality towards evil) in the creature. In his
Commentary on Genesis Luther specifically rejects Augustine's inter-
pretation of the primeval matter as 'almost nothing', as that which
exists only on the very lowest threshold of being, an interpretation
which, as we have seen, helped to install Platonic metaphysics with-
in the edifice of Christian theology. 'How,' Luther asks, 'can you
apply the term "mere nothing" to something that is a genuine sub-
stance of the kind Moses calls heaven and earth?'39 Interestingly, he
associates this repudiation of a Platonizing interpretation of the
28 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
When it is said, then, that the will of the natural man is subject
to the power of the devil, and is actuated by him, the meaning is,
not that the will, while reluctant and resisting, is forced to
submit... but that, fascinated by the imposture of Satan, it nec-
essarily leads to his guidance, and does him homage.
(Inst. I, p. 266)
anything external to the will of man, in which the root of evil lies,
and in which the foundations of Satan's kingdom, in other words,
sin, is fixed' [ibid.].)
The will itself is therefore responsible for its own bondage; the
power which binds or which annihilates the will is its own power.
Yet what do 'necessity' and 'compulsion' or 'what is done voluntar-
ily' and 'what is done by free choice' mean in this context?
Calvin answers such questions by reflecting on the character of
God's goodness and the devil's badness. 'Were anyone to ask... Is
not God necessarily good, is not the devil necessarily wicked, what
answer would they give?' The answer, Calvin thinks, is obvious.
'The goodness of God is so connected with his Godhead, that it is
not more necessary to be God than to be good ...' (Inst. I, pp. 253-
4). Yet it would sound absurd to speak of God as being good be-
cause of some external compulsion. Similarly, the characteristic evil
of the devil's actions does not depend on a power outside his own
personality. The same goes for human beings: 'If the free will of
God in doing good is not impeded, because he necessarily must do
good; if the devil, who can do nothing but evil, nevertheless sins
voluntarily; can it be said that man sins less voluntarily because he
is under a necessity of sinning?' (Inst. I, p. 254). The conclusion is
that:
Man, since he was corrupted by the fall, sins not forced or un-
willing, but voluntarily, by a most forward bias of the mind; not
by violent compulsion, or external force, but by the movement of
his own passion; and yet such is the depravity of his nature, that
he cannot move and act except in the direction of evil.
(Inst. I, p. 254)
Calvin finds this conclusion not only in Augustine but also, per-
haps surprisingly, in Bernard of Clairvaux, whom he quotes to the
following effect:
Thus the soul, in some strange and evil way, is held under this
kind of voluntary, yet sadly free necessity, both bond and free;
bond in respect of necessity, free in respect of will: and what is
still more strange, and still more miserable, it is guilty because
free, and enslaved because guilty, and therefore enslaved because
free.
(Inst. I, p. 254)
The Augustinian Inheritance 33
PASCAL
Luther and Calvin, I have argued, sought to separate out the task
of Christian theology from the enterprise of speculative metaphys-
ics and to keep it uncontaminated by any kind of ontology. From
the standpoint of the Reformation the question about Being (and
therefore of the ontological status of descriptions of the human
subject in terms of nothingness) has no place in theology. But is it
possible to exclude this question from any important interpretation
of human existence on anything other than a provisional basis?
Indeed, even if the question as to what kind of being the human
being is is ultimately unanswerable, doesn't that final unanswer-
ability only reveal itself to those who have followed the question
through to the bitter end? To put it another way: doesn't the tactic
of simply declaring the question to be irrelevant, leave it free to
play in the margins of theology in such a way that it will continue
to interrupt the discourse of theology with a never-ending stream
of absurd, irrelevant and phantasmagoric interventions? To say, as
a grammatical remark, This question cannot be asked' doesn't help
resolve a situation where the question is being asked. Since it is
being asked there is therefore a job to be done in asking what the
question means and why, in its own terms, it must be superseded.
These interventions by a marginalized question represent, I have
suggested, something like the 'return of the repressed' in Freudian
psychology. In twentieth-century theology Karl Barth represents a
particularly interesting example of just such a return.48
As for Augustine, Luther and Calvin, so too for Barth does Paul's
Letter to the Romans represent a defining moment in theology. In
Barth's commentary on this the theme of human nothingness be-
fore God is evoked in an extraordinarily powerful sequence of words
and images. The apostle is one in whom 'a void becomes visible',
a void that reveals to us our situation as wanderers in the night,
worshippers of the No-God, subject to the 'No' of the true God and
utterly questionable in our manner of existing; God 'is He whom
we do not know', 'the hidden abyss', from whom we are separated
by 'the crevasse, the polar zone, the desert barrier' - by a distance
whose 'ultimate significance' is 'sharp, acid and disintegrating', for
God is 'Wholly Other'. So, 'if the experience of religion is more than
a void . . . it is a shameless and abortive anticipation of that which can
proceed from the unknown God alone.' Our sole reality is - death.49
The Augustinian Inheritance 39
41
42 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
HEGEL: LOGIC
is why logic must begin with what is only given in, with and under
the concept of knowing itself, and this, Hegel says, is 'Being': to
know something is, at its simplest, to be able to say 'it is'. Being is
the most immediate form of consciousness, the undifferentiated unity
of subject and object. Simple immediacy and pure Being correspond
to one another completely. Being cannot therefore be differentiated
either internally or in relation to anything else. It is pure indeter-
minacy and completely empty. If - to think what cannot be thought
- we imagine any mental act at all in this context, even the simplest
act of intuition (Anschauen), it can only be an intuition of Being by
Being itself and, as such, without content. We can think nothing in
connection with such an intuition. It is completely empty. Or (if we
read the Logic as making no pretensions beyond the analysis of the
conditions of truthful predication) to say of something 'It is' is not
yet to have said anything meaningful. In such an expression we
have said nothing at all. Either way we have no way of differentiat-
ing between Being and Nothing (Nichts).
Being and Nothing are, therefore, inseparable. They coexist in a
relationship of always already having passed over into one another.
This unity Hegel calls Becoming (Werden). Becoming, however, has
a double-structure in which Nothing relates to Being and Being to
Nothing. These two relations are defined as Emergence and Disso-
lution (Entstehen and Vergehen respectively) - and yet Hegel draws
back from claiming that with this move he has created out of purely
logical resources any obligatory relationship to an external world of
phenomenal change. For these terms, though seemingly charged
with a certain descriptive force, exist logically in a state of mutual
cancellation and reciprocal paralysis. It is only when grasped as a
whole, as a motionless unity of Being and Nothing, that Becoming
is constituted as a new immediacy, which Hegel calls Dasein.
But what is Hegel actually saying in all this?
According to Trendelenburg, he has already played a sophistical
trick in order to move from the realm of pure thought to the realm
of things, a move which, Trendelenburg argues, can only be made
with the (in this case unacknowledged) assistance of empirical ex-
perience. Trendelenburg ('a man who has preferred to be content
with Aristotle', as Kierkegaard put it3) confronts the dialectical
'movement' with the following dilemma:
HEGEL: PHENOMENOLOGY
Spirit has broken with the world it has hitherto inhabited and
imagined, and is of a mind to submerge it in the past, and in the
labour of its own transformation... But just as the first breath
drawn by a child after its long, quiet nourishment [Hegel means
its embryonic life] breaks the gradualness of merely quantitative
growth - there is a qualitative leap, and the child is born - so
likewise the Spirit in its formation matures slowly and quietly
into its new shape . . . But this new world is no more a complete
actuality than is a new-born child . . . So too, Science, the crown
of a world of Spirit, is not complete in its beginnings . . . the ini-
tial appearance of the new world is, to begin with, only the whole
veiled in its simplicity12
If the subjective idealists have been prepared to take the initial step
in understanding Substance as Subject, they have failed, as yet, to
grasp the true character of such subjectivity.
This Substance is, as Subject, pure, simple negativity, and is for this
very reason the bifurcation of the simple; it is the doubling which
sets up opposition, and then again the negation of this indifferent
diversity and of its antithesis. Only this self-restoring sameness,
or this reflection in otherness within itself - not an original or
immediate unity as such - is the True.16
The circle that remains self-enclosed and, like substance, holds its
moments together, is an immediate relationship, one therefore
which has nothing astonishing about it. But that an accident as
such, detached from what circumscribes it, what is bound and is
actual only in its context with others, should attain an existence
of its own and a separate freedom - that is the tremendous power
of the negative; it is the energy of thought, of the pure T. Death,
if that is what we want to call this non-actuality, is of all things
the most dreadful, and to hold fast what is dead requires the
greatest strength. Lacking strength, Beauty hates the Understand-
ing for asking of her what it cannot do. But the life of Spirit is not
the life that shrinks from death and keeps itself untouched by
devastation, but rather the life that endures it and maintains itself
in it. It wins its truth only when, in utter dismemberment, it finds
itself... Spirit is this power only by looking the negative in the
48 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
KIERKEGAARD: INTRODUCTION
The book of this name, which, despite the bearing of its content on
such dogmatic questions as the fall and original sin, Kierkegaard
carefully defines as 'psychological', draws heavily on the Hegelian
account of the fall as the transition from nature to Spirit or from
innocence to knowledge. It also reflects Kierkegaard's critical but
not unappreciative reading of Karl Rosenkranz's Psychologie, an
application of Hegelian principles to the field of psychology. This
reading is, for example, reflected in what is a decisive point in
Kierkegaard's text, when he defines 'the concept of anxiety' itself.
Set against an assumed background of the biblical story of creation
and fall, Kierkegaard describes the emergence of the human subject
as taking place only in and by means of the awakening of anxiety.
Does this mean, then, that freedom must fall and has therefore
been brought into the domain of ontology? Against this conclusion,
it should be noted that the passage quoted is taken from a section
'Subjective Anxiety' in a chapter 'Anxiety as Explaining Hereditary
Sin Progressively' in which Kierkegaard assumes Adam's fall and
seeks to develop the implications of that for the manifestations of
anxiety in subsequent individuals. In other words, the question is:
how does the manifestation of freedom as a failure to be itself in-
fluence a subsequent individual's relation to his own freedom - a
freedom to be attained, of course, precisely in and through anxiety?
The 'necessity' of the fall is not being stated as a necessary conse-
quence of anxiety per se, but anxiety is being framed - for the present
- by the history of the failure of freedom. It is also significant that,
Nothingness and the Return of Metaphysics 55
The true concrete choice is the one by which I choose myself back
into the world in the very same moment I choose myself out of
the world. That is, when repenting I choose myself, I collect myself
in all my finite concretion, and when I have thus chosen myself
out of the finite in this way, I am in the most absolute continuity
with it.
(EO II, p. 249)
Nothingness and the Return of Metaphysics 59
and this nothing as that which exists' (WWR I, p. 410). From such
a point of view we would, for instance, no longer speak of the
denial of the will-to-live in terms of nirvana or the annihilation of
the self, but of 'ecstasy, rapture, illumination, union with God' (ibid.).
In terms of his own system, however, Schopenhauer must deny
that we can ever 'know' such a condition, since knowledge belongs
precisely to the world conditioned by the principle of sufficient
reason, the world as representation. As long as we ourselves exist
as the will-to-live (that is to say: as long as we exist) and since like
can only be known by like, the view that 'the nothing' (jenes Nichts)
is that which actually exists, is 'real', 'can be known and expressed
by us only negatively . . . No will: no representation, no world' (WWR
I, pp. 410-11). And so:
. . . we freely acknowledge that what remains after the complete
abolition of the will is, for all who are still full of the will, assur-
edly nothing. But also conversely, to those in whom the will has
turned and denied itself, this very real world of ours with all its
suns and galaxies, is - nothing.
(WWR I, p. 412)
This is a standpoint which Schopenhauer identifies in a footnote as
that of the Pmjnaparamita Sutra.
Such denial, however, cannot be an event in the 'real' world
constructed according to the principle of sufficient reason and there-
fore has no ontological status. Yet, even if the will cannot be con-
sidered the ground of being in any causal sense, it is within the
dimension of will that it is decided what is and what is not to
count, for us, as being. Being, and ontology as the theory of being,
are thereby conceivable only within or in the light of a more pri-
mordial act of evaluation. Outside such evaluation 'being' (and, of
course, 'non-being') have no meaning for us. The dimension of will
is conceived as a non-noetic, non-ontological dimension of valua-
tion, of experiencing-as - and, precisely, yet only, as such, deter-
minative for ontology.
In this concept of evaluative experiencing-as, Schopenhauer moves
the question of nothingness beyond the kind of oppositions be-
tween faith and knowledge, between psychology and ontology or
between subjective and objective points of view that are character-
istic of the Augustinian tradition in its various forms. Evaluative
experiencing-as prescinds from the kind of truth claims that inhere
in all speculative world-picturing.
Nothingness and the Return of Metaphysics 69
echoes, via Schopenhauer, of Kant. But the a priori that Kant por-
trays as a timeless categorical structure Nietzsche describes as an
act of will, of subjective evaluation. Speaking to 'the wise' he says
of them that it is they themselves who, by an act of will, create the
world before which they subsequently kneel.
And life itself told me this secret: 'Behold/ it said, 'I am that
which must overcome itself again and again.
'And you too, enlightened man, are only a path and footstep of
my will...
. . . Unchanging good and evil does not exist! From out of them-
selves they must overcome themselves again and again.
(Z, pp. 138-9)
81
82 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
Nothing of the other is retained but the footstep, and the hole
that opens up beneath the feet. This is the fortune of the super-
man - those footsteps that circle endlessly round and round the
same radii of a circle and thus keep their balance even on the
dizzying edge.
All that remains of the other is a taut rope that plays with the
void by keeping it always at an even distance. There is no other
but the axle that allows an infinite series of cartwheels, a dizzy
rapture every moment that never loses its spell.
TO BECOME AS NOTHING
its difference from the continuity of its natural milieu. The merely
animal existence of the human being is likened to being 'an
instrument... in the service of inexplicable drives, indeed, in the
service of the world' or 'like a mirror in which... the world reflects
itself.'12 This, in the terminology of The Concept of Anxiety, is the 'psy-
chic' level of existence. To become a self, however, involves grasping
one's self precisely in respect of the difference between the human
subject and its environment. By internalizing this difference, the
self establishes itself by means of and as a process of self-transcend-
ence. Thus far, we might expect nothingness to be identified with
this capacity for transcendence over the given. That might be the
case if we were dealing with Hegel, but Kierkegaard's picture is
more ambiguous, for the Kierkegaardian self:
. . . struggles not with the world but with himself. Observe him
now; his powerful figure is held embraced by another figure, and
they hold each other so firmly interlocked and are so equally
matched in suppleness and strength that the wrestling cannot
even begin, because in that moment that other figure would over-
whelm him - bat that other figure is he himself.
(UD, pp. 308-9)
gets the explanation he wants. For, Kierkegaard asks, 'is this the
explanation, that God denies him the understanding and requires
only faith and consequently wants only the understanding with
him that is in the realm of the ununderstanding?' (UD, p. 395). The
'result' of the process is thus the faith that 'with God all things are
possible', yet, since this 'result' is neither guaranteed by experience
nor by reason, its only 'evidence' is the process itself, i.e. that the
struggle continues, that the one who prays 'proves' his faith in God
by carrying on praying - even (especially) when such prayer is, in
any external sense, pointless.
Fully aware of the limitations of such similes, Kierkegaard likens
the turning point in the struggle of prayer to a child sitting down
to draw, whose fumbling efforts are corrected and transformed into
a thing of beauty by an invisible artist standing behind it. The ex-
planation that the one who prays seeks is like the child's drawing.
It is an attempt to represent God within the limitations and, ultim-
ately, in the likeness of the praying subject.
Ah, but now comes the difference, because the child has to be
helped by the addition of something, but more and more is taken
away from the struggler. The external world and every claim on
life were taken away from him; now he is struggling for an ex-
planation, but he is not even struggling his way to that. Finally
it seems to him that he is reduced to nothing at all. Whom should
the struggler desire to resemble other than God? But if he himself
is something or wants to be something, this something is suffi-
cient to hinder the resemblance. Only when he himself becomes
nothing, only then can God illuminate him so that he resembles
God. However great he is, he cannot manifest God's likeness;
God can imprint himself in him only when he himself has be-
come nothing. When the ocean is exerting all its power, that is
precisely the time when it cannot reflect the image of heaven, and
even the slightest motion blurs the image; but when it becomes
still and deep, then the image of heaven sinks into its nothing-
ness.
(UD, p. 399)
This, Kierkegaard concludes, may not give the one who prays the
explanation (forklaring) he wanted, but, what he does receive or
experience is transfiguration (forklarelse) in God. Although the God-
relationship as established in this 'moment' hinges on the sharpest
90 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
possible contrast being drawn between the divine and the human,
between the God who is everything and the one who prays who is
nothing, yet, paradoxically, it is in this very nothingness that the
one who prays is said to resemble God, to have God imprinted in
him, to be transfigured in God or to reflect the image of God.14
The teaching of the discourses, then, would seem to be in direct
continuity with the Lutheran understanding of the self existing 'as
nothing' before God and needing to be completely reorientated
under the guidance of divine grace, while simultaneously qualified
in terms of its own essential nothingness.
But as in The Concept of Anxiety, the God-relationship coincides
with the subject's discovery of its essential freedom. To have the
possibility of the God-relationship is to be free and to be free is to
be able to understand one's life in the reflection of the God-relation-
ship in which one understands oneself as a sinner, as nothing. The
'failure' of the one who prays to get the answer he wants or the ex-
planation he wants is an experienced occurrence in the life of the
believer, that discloses the self to itself in its most fundamental char-
acteristic, in what belongs to the very possibility of a human way of
existing. If this is to be spoken of as a 'merely' ontical event, it is
nonetheless an event, an experience, that must engage its subject
totally and without reserve. It is, in Tillich's phrase, a matter of
ultimate concern.
This experience of nothingness, then, is not the object of a special
kind of religious experience accessible only to a religiously-minded
cognitive minority. It is the experience, the 'owning', of that noth-
ingness that belongs to the human subject as such and, in parti-
cular, to the human subject as having the 'possibility of possibility',
the possibility of freedom; the possibility to find, to become and
to be a self, 'in spirit and in truth'. Moreover, it is not a nothing-
ness in which and as which the self produces itself: it is a nothing-
ness revealed to and experienced by the self as a disclosure of its
essential truth. In knowing itself 'as nothing' before God, the self
understands itself as being unconditionally derivative, absolutely
dependent and owing itself entirely and utterly to this Other, to
whom the disclosure of this truth is also owed. Moreover, in con-
trast to Hegel, such spirit, such truth, is 'founded' on a nothingness,
a non-being, that cannot be encompassed within any system of
knowledge; it constitutes a hinge between being and non-being that
is humanly unthinkable and that, for the one who prays, can only
be a matter for faith, an 'ununderstanding'.15
The Experience of the Void 91
Yet the suspicion may still remain that all this talk of nothing or
nothingness conceals a prolepsis of an eschatologically predeter-
mined value and thus a hidden metaphysics. For Kierkegaard's talk
of God transfiguring the nothingness of the religious subject seems
to determine in advance what happens on the site of nothingness as
if there were an almost causal link: become as nothing and God will
(perhaps it can even be said: God must) shine through you. In this
respect, an image from Kierkegaard's early journals may be taken
as paradigmatic: 'The old Christian dogmatic terminology is like an
enchanted castle where the most beautiful princes and princesses
rest in deep sleep - it needs only to be awakened, brought to life,
in order to stand in its full glory.'16 Behind the rhetoric of nothing-
ness (and, in Kierkegaard's case, the whole complex machinery of
indirect communication), the old dogmatic answers are always
already lying in wait, as if 'nothingness' is just a filmy mist conceal-
ing the 'enchanted castle' of doctrine from the eye of the unseeing
traveller. To be sure, one must enter into that mist in order to arrive
at the castle, one must pass into the moment of obscured vision that
befalls all who enter the mist - but it is only for a moment: one re-
emerges into the brightness of a day in which everything is just as
it always was.
In seeking to penetrate further into what can be derived from
Kierkegaard's thought in this respect, it will be necessary to untan-
gle two closely interconnected issues: the first is centred on the
question of the priority of God or of the ontological other in the
religious life, the second on the question of time. That these two
questions are necessarily interconnected can be seen by reflecting
on the way in which the main point at issue here has been con-
ceived. For the identification of the metaphysical God with the
ideological function of a prolepsis of eschatological reality means
that the radicality with which the human situation vis-h-vis time is
thought will react upon the way in which the priority of God in the
religious relationship is conceived. Here I shall, firstly, address the
question as to how the experience of nothingness can be under-
stood as allowing for an assertion of the priority of God in such a
way as to slip the net of prolepsis and then, secondly, see how the
experience of nothingness is given to the subject in, with and as its
experience of temporality.
With regard to the question of time, I shall continue to focus
primarily on Kierkegaard, although it is worth repeating (as was
noted in the Introduction) that it is not the historical unfolding of
92 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
the question but the question itself that is the primary focus of this
enquiry: Kierkegaard is important only in so far as he serves to help
illuminate what is essential in the question. Firstly, however, I shall
address the question of the experience of nothingness as the expe-
rience of God as that is described and analysed by one of the found-
ers of the modern understanding of religious experience: Friedrich
Schleiermacher.
Would that I could and might express it, at least indicate it, with-
out having to desecrate it! It is as fleeting and transparent as the
first scent with which the dew gently caresses the waking flowers,
as modest and delicate as a maiden's kiss, as holy and fruitful as
a nuptial embrace; indeed, not like these, but it is itself all of these.
A manifestation, an event develops quickly and magically into an
image of the universe. Even as the beloved and ever-sought-for
form fashions itself, my soul flees toward it; I embrace it, not as
a shadow, but as the holy essence itself. I lie on the bosom of the
infinite world. At this moment I am its soul, for I feel all its
powers and its infinite life as my own; at this moment it is my
body, for I penetrate its muscles and its limbs as my own and its
innermost nerves move according to my sense and my presenti-
ment as my own. With the slightest trembling the holy embrace
is dispersed, and now for the first time the intuition stands before
me as a separate form; I survey it, and it mirrors itself in my open
soul like the image of the vanishing beloved in the awakened eye
of the youth; now for the first time the feeling works its way up
from inside and diffuses itself like the blush of shame and desire
on his cheek. This moment is the highest flowering of religion.
(OR, pp. 112-13)
This 'love scene', as Richard Crouter has called it, makes clear how
'intuition' is of itself a mere reflection, 'the image of the vanishing
96 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
word? Who tricked me into this whole thing and leaves me stand-
ing here? Who am I? How did I get into the world? Why was I not
asked about i t . . . ?' {R, p. 200 adapted).
In such a situation there can be no falling-back on some ready-
made explanation. Recollection must give way to repetition, the striv-
ing in time to attain selfhood in and by the ever-renewed/repeated
commitment to the concrete moment. But the price of repetition is
the abandonment of any fixed concept of the self. The self that
exists by repetition exists not otherwise than in the flux and void of
time.
Constantin himself is portrayed as one who knows that repetition
is the only ground of an authentic life but who, at the same time,
is unable to bring it about. He sees that the relentless forward rush
of time makes recollection unsustainable, but, for himself, he can
only experience that onrush as annihilating negativity, as a being-
towards-death:
. . . one sits calmly in one's living room; when all is vanity and
passes away, one nevertheless speeds faster than on a train, even
though sitting still... Farewell! farewell! You exuberant hope of
youth, what is your hurry? After all, what you are hunting for
does not exist, and the same goes for you yourself. Farewell, you
masculine vim and vigour! Why are you stamping the ground so
violently? What you are stepping on is an illusion!... Travel on,
you fugitive river! You are the only one who really knows what
you want, for you want only to flow and lose yourself in the sea,
which is never filled! Move on you drama of life - let no one call
it a comedy, no one a tragedy, for no one saw the end! Move on,
you drama of existence, where life is not given again any more
than money is!
(R, pp. 175-6)
Es schwinden, es fallen
Die leidenden Menschen
Blindlings von einer
Stunde zur andern,
Wie Wasser von Klippe
Zu Klippe geworfen,
Jahrlang ins Ungewisse hinab.
108
Nothingness and the Place of Religious Experience 109
our dealings with life' and what are the respective roles and limits
of immediate experience and of reflective understanding in this
'point of view'? More fundamentally still: is the self that acquires
such a new point of view independent of that process of acquisition
(as if, for example, it were confronted with a supermarket shelf
stocked with possible points of view from which it could freely
choose), or is the self itself inseparable from the point of view it
occupies in such a way that the view on the world that the self
acquires in satori is the self altogether and exclusively? But what if
this particular point of view is precisely no particular point of view
at all but the point of view of absolute nothingness, a view that sees
the world as total emptiness - the 'place', 'field' or 'standpoint' of
sunyata, as Nishida and Nishitani (see below) were to put it?
What, then, is the understanding of self and of self-and-world
presupposed in the religious phenomenon of satoril
Many of the accounts of how particular aspirants came to realize
their satori would seem to suggest that it is a specific and concrete
experience of a certain kind, an event in the psychological develop-
ment of the individual that has a particular time and a particular
place. A word or even a blow from the Master suddenly awakens
the seeker and opens his eyes to the truth - or perhaps it is the
seeker's own relentless quest that leads him to the decisive break-
through. If this is so then we must think of Zen and Zen experience
as of a piece with 'religious experiences' such as that of Huxley,
described in the previous chapter (Huxley, of course, explicitly links
his account to a Buddhist understanding of Enlightenment which
he defines as 'to be aware, always, of total reality in its immanent
otherness'6).
But is there really any experience capable of yielding an imme-
diate and incorrigible intuition of the ultimate referent of religious
language and symbolism? And, even if there is, can we give an
account of that experience without immediately falsifying it in the
distorting mirror of language, shot through as all language inevit-
ably is with the cultural preconditioning of experience?
In the light of these comments, it is significant that Suzuki him-
self does not so much speak of 'experience' as of 'acquiring a point
of view', or, in the language of existentialist theology, an 'under
standing of existence'. But to acquire a point of view or an under-
standing of existence can be only loosely associated with the mo-
mentary and intense character of an 'experience'. As Kierkegaard
remarked with regard to the Socratic method of instruction, the
Nothingness and the Place of Religious Experience 111
There is no Bodhi-tree,
Nor stand of mirror bright.
Since all is void,
Where can the dust alight?
Nishida's A Study of Good, his first major work and one of the sem-
inal texts of modern Japanese philosophy. The first section of A
Study of Good is devoted to the concept of 'pure experience'.
Against the background of his reading of such Western psycholo-
gists as Wundt and James and of his own immersion in Zen, Nishida
aims to locate Zen Enlightenment in a relation to experience that is
entirely intuitive, stripped of all subjectively-determined structur-
ing and, as such, standing in a direct relation to reality. Such 'pure
experience', Nishida says, signifies 'a condition of true experience
itself without the addition of the least thought or reflection' and
'When one directly experiences one's own state of consciousness,
there is not yet a subject or an object, and knowing and its object
are completely unified.'9
As Nishida goes on to expound this 'pure experience' it becomes
clear that such experience neither excludes nor negates the differ-
entiating activities of thought or will, but is presupposed as the
ground without which such differentiations would dissolve into
chaos. In this respect 'pure experience' is the foundation of our
knowledge of reality, of ethics and of art but finds its supreme
manifestation in religion. Although we have access to it through an
intellectual intuition, this should not be understood as a merely
passive contemplation or reflection of life. Consciousness is, for
Nishida, the primary aspect of reality and this consciousness is no
less corporeal, emotional and active than it is mental or theoretical:
the intellectual intuition is in essence the unifying activity that unites
and thus grounds the manifold of functions and manifestations of
the self. Yet even to talk of 'self is misleading, since this already
seems to presuppose the separation of self and world and the split-
ting up of the single reality into the duality of the subject-object
structure. Nishida is insistent that we should not take 'pure experi-
ence' as something that a separated individual self or consciousness
'has': 'It is not that there is experience because there is an indi-
vidual, but that there is an individual because there is experience.
The individual's experience is simply a small distinctive sphere of
limited experience within true experience.'10 Again: ' . . . we think
that... feeling and the will are purely individual. Yet it is not that
the individual possesses feeling and the will, but rather that feeling
and the will create the individual. Feeling and the will are facts of
direct experience.'11 Similarly, the unifying function of the intellec-
tual intuition is not to be understood as a subjective consciousness
imposing a unity on a manifold of experience given from without:
114 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
Or:
presupposed by them and thus in some sense given in, with and
under them even in their everyday functioning as (apparently) sepa-
rate and distinct: in the spirit of Hui-Neng's poem, we do not need
to polish the mirror, we only need to see what is already there.
There is no separate or special 'religious' experience, because reli-
gious experience is the true face of all experience.
If the comparison with such forms of Western idealism holds,
however, it raises the possibility that Nishida's thought could be
brought into the orbit of a metaphysics that is, ultimately, oriented
towards being rather than (as we might have assumed from its
Buddhist provenance) nothingness. Yet for Nishida it is axiomatic
that absolute nothingness and not being is the fundamental princi-
ple of philosophy. How then does the characterization of the ultim-
ate ground as absolute nothingness qualify the description of pure
experience?
In the first instance, it involves denying the ultimacy of the dis-
criminatory function of mind. Or, to put it the other way round, the
unity of all phenomena is thought through to a point at which the
structures of differentiation between the various facets of being and
consciousness break down. Each particular function, each particu-
lar thing, is, as individual and separate, without substance, devoid
of absolute being.
Correlative to this is the assertion that the reality of religious
experience cannot be given a definitive form based on the stand-
ards of knowledge (in so far as these standards invariably assume
the reflective division of subject and object, self and world). That
which is the foundation of all knowledge and experience is so com-
pletely and equally the foundation of all, that it is not the founda-
tion of any in particular. There is no point or moment of privileged
access to it and no kind of experience or knowledge is nearer to it
than any other. It is thus equally describable as an absolute fullness
or an absolute emptiness.
The critique of knowledge implied in this position is carried fur-
ther in Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness, where Nishida
appeals to the neo-Kantian prioritizing of value over being, quoting
Heinrich Rickert: 'Meaning precedes and surpasses all existence'
and, in his own words, 'Before being there is meaning.'17
With this, however, we return to the ambiguity of Suzuki's talk
of 'acquiring a new viewpoint' on the world. For Nishida's account,
despite the emphasis on 'experience', is not, in any usual sense,
concerned with 'experience of' phenomena, since such experience is
116 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
The Great Doubt comes to light from the ground of our existence
only when we press our doubts (What am I? Why do I exist?) to
their limits as conscious acts of the doubting self. The Great Doubt
represents not only the apex of the doubting self but also the point
of its 'passing away' and ceasing to be 'self. It is like the bean
whose seed and shell break apart as it ripens: the shell is the tiny
ego, and the seed the infinity of the Great Doubt that encom-
passes the whole world. It is the moment at which self is at the
same time the nothingness of self, the moment that is the 'locus'
of nothingness where conversion beyond the Great Doubt takes
place. For the Great Doubt always emerges as the opening up of
the locus of nothingness as the field of conversion from the Great
Doubt itself.32
Lightning flashes -
Close by my face,
The pampas grass!
thought, above all with the great German idealists and their critics.
Also like Nishida, he gave a central role to the concept of absolute
nothingness as the foundation of both religion and philosophy. On
the other hand, inevitable differences in emphasis led to a breach
which seemed to be both personally and philosophically unresolv-
able.39 It is not to the purpose here to pursue the course of this dispute,
other than to highlight how one of Tanabe's key concepts - that
of repentance (or metanoesis: zange) - can be used to break through
the impasse generated by the subject's paradoxical standpoint
vis-h-vis its own grounding in absolute nothingness. Indeed, the
very paradoxicality of that standpoint is itself the point of break-
through, intellectually and existentially. Whether that breakthrough
is in itself to be understood as demanding a complete break with
all that Nishida had said of the pure experience of absolute noth-
ingness or whether the relationship is more akin to that of the
Hegelian Aufhebung is an issue to which we shall return later: for
the time being I comment only that Nishitani, at least, understood
himself to have learned from both teachers and to have arrived at
some kind of mutual mediation of their philosophies in his own
thought.
One further introductory remark may be in place at this point,
namely that Tanabe's exposition of the paradoxical relationship
between the human subject and its own ground in absolute noth-
ingness establishes a very real and a very concrete 'point of contact'
with the Augustinian discourse on the divided self.
Tanabe himself relates his discovery of metanoesis to a specific
time and place. Typically for his thought this time and place and the
character of the act it occasioned give the concept both a social and
a practical dimension. Metanoesis is, for Tanabe, a non-conceptual
concept; metanoetics a non-philosophical way of doing philosophy.
Nor is metanoesis a purely individual act: it is, typically, an act in
which the destiny of a community is realized (both in the sense of
'understood' and in the sense of 'made real') by the individual but,
by the individual, as the meaning of the common situation. These
comments are exemplified in Tanabe's own experience of metanoia,
which he dates to the closing months of the Second World War and
to the completely impossible situation that the national crisis of
Japan caused for one who, as a teacher of philosophy, was a servant
of the state and one, moreover, whose own philosophy had encour-
aged the view that the nation-state was to be regarded as 'the
Nothingness and the Place of Religious Experience 125
Not only did this redirection of his intellectual focus give Tanabe
a new subject for philosophical analysis. It gave him, as he experi-
enced it, a new standpoint from which to do philosophy - albeit a
standpoint that generated a sequence of philosophical paradoxes:
freedom in the true sense, and that only the negation of the former
assures us of the latter.
(PM, pp. 4-5)
. . . a person who relies on the good that he does through his self-
power fails to entrust himself wholeheartedly to Other Power
and therefore is not in accord with Amida's Primal Vow. But
when he abandons his attachment to self-power and entrusts
himself totally to Other Power, he will realize birth in the Pure
Land.
It is impossible for us, filled as we are with blind passions,
to free ourselves from birth-and-death through any practice
whatever... Hence the evil person who entrusts himself to Other
Power is precisely the one who possesses the true cause for birth.45
When the self realizes its complete incapacity and its need to rely
completely on the Vow of Amida, the religious situation is radically
individualized and personalized. Enlightenment is no longer 'a state'
to be attained: it is that which, under the figure of the Pure Land,
is found only in and through the love of an Other. This individu-
alization is most succinctly stated by Shinran in a remark he is
reported as having often repeated: 'When I consider deeply the
Vow of Amida, which arose from five kalpas of profound thought,
I realize that it was entirely for the sake of myself alone!'46 - a
comment that is to be understood in the light of the dialectics of
the 'thrown project', i.e. that it is only (yet precisely) in relation to
our contingency, the complete concreteness and specificity of our
existential situation, that we can realize our being as freedom.
The distinction between self-power and Other-power is devel-
oped by Tanabe as a critique of Zen, in so far as Zen represents a
132 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
religion of self-power. "The lofty words and noble deeds of the Zen
masters recorded in various accounts can fill us with admiration/
he acknowledges - but, he adds, they 'lie beyond the reach of our
own learning and practice' (PM, p. 124). He comments similarly on
Nietzsche and Heidegger. Their 'ways' may, at one level, be true -
or would be if human beings had the capacity to carry through the
projects they represent.
The distinction between self- and Other-power is, of course, also
operative in his strictures on the limitations of intuition and reason.
Indeed, it may be described as the key-thought of metanoetics.47
Where, then, does this lead our enquiry into how to contextualize
the experience of absolute nothingness in the empirical givenness
of human existence?
At first glance, it may seem to have made our problem still more
intractable, since the severity of Tanabe's disjunction between what
belongs to self-power and what belongs to Other-Power, evidenced
in his strictures on the role of intuition and of reason, would seem
to preclude any possibility of 'experience' in the normal sense at all.
Outside the world constructed noetically by the human subject there
would indeed seem to be nothing at all, nothing to experience and
nothing to know.
Yet Tanabe's philosophy of metanoetics begins precisely at the
point where this subjectively-determined world-construction breaks
down, at the point where, as Kierkegaard might have put it, sub-
jectivity is untruth. From the point of view of absolute nothingness
attained in metanoia, the requirement of self-transcendence and the
ecstatic horizon opening towards Other-power run together in such
a way that we can only speak, authentically of the presence of the
Other in the measure that we abandon all given constructions of
the self (including not only the constructions bequeathed to us by
our social and cultural heritage but also those that we are ourselves
even now (even I, as I write) are in the process of constructing).
If we say that in metanoia we experience the presence of the Other
in and as absolute nothingness, we can only do so with the proviso
that the 'we' that does the experiencing only comes into being on
the far side of metanoia. The 'we' that does the experiencing is
presented to itself as self-constituting freedom only in and by its
repentance-metanoia-zange. Here too it might be relevant to invoke
Nishida's concept of the absolute near side. For Tanabe, however,
the emphasis would not be on the lightning flash of intuition but
on the absolute near side of the self's continuing recognition and
Nothingness and the Place of Religious Experience 133
resolved on doing his best for them. Here Shinran's insistence that
the Vow was made precisely for himself alone comes into play. For
this individualization brings into view the inseparability of the Vow
from the contingent situatedness of each human subject in relation
to which the Vow 'was' made. Nishitani suggests that in order to
adequately demythologize the Pure Land doctrine we need to con-
sider, firstly, that "The fulfilment of the Primal Vow is further back
in the past than any point in the past. The time of fulfilment is one that
is, at whatever point in time, always historically the past.'50 That is
to say, the 'pastness' (and with that the givenness) of the Vow is not
measurable on any scale of chronological, historical time. Its
'pastness' is a symbol of its transcendent quality. Secondly, and
apparently in contrast to that quality of transcendence, 'the Primal
Vow fulfilled in that time manifests itself directly to each individual
sentient being within historical time.'51 Yet, thirdly, this is not to say
that the Vow exists in an eternal present, equally near and equally
far from all points of history. It is present always (and only) 'in
conformity with the succession of before and after in time.'52 His-
torical time 'is simultaneously the time of the working of the power
of the Primal Vow, and the time of the working of that power is
simultaneously the time of its fulfilment.'53 The conjunction of 'that
time' and 'this time' in a simultaneity or contemporaneity (and
Nishitani appeals in this respect to Kierkegaard) of present lived
experience is the true moment of historicity: for it is not as if the
religious act is constrained by laws of temporal progression over
which it has no influence; it is rather that religious existence itself
is generative, through the relationship of self- and Other-power, of
time. Time is the time of relation, not that within which relation
occurs.
Shinran's teaching is in this way interpreted as indeed emphasiz-
ing the priority of Other-power, but not as a priority that can be
established or quantified in categories alien to the religious rela-
tionship itself. It is only as the practitioner of metanoia, only as one
who knows himself to be the beneficiary of the saving power of the
Vow, that I am able to affirm the transcendence or priority of Other-
power. It is a matter of confession and faith, not of knowledge. As
'experience' of absolute nothingness, it is an experience in which I
find myself as always already given to myself 'ransomed, healed,
restored, forgiven' - and yet, at the same time not other than the
self I am in my division, failure and sin. Because this is not merely
an experience of my own nothingness as a sinful human subject
136 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
over against an absolutely good and absolutely real God, but is also
an experience of 'absolute nothingness', it is not quantifiable in any
way and can never become or be made into the ground or evidence
of any particular concepts or descriptions. As against Nishida, this
is not a 'place' on which any system of knowledge can be raised.
Should Tanabe's objections to Nishida's affirmation of continuity
between the existing subject and its life-world (including its knowl-
edge of that life-world) and the ground of absolute nothingness be
upheld? Not entirely. For although Nishida does indeed speak the
language of intuition his critique of the subject-object schema an-
ticipates and undermines the attempt to understand 'pure intuition'
as a form of knowledge in any conventional sense. Nothingness is
not at all the object of such intuition. The concept of absolute noth-
ingness as the 'place' of all particular acts of consciousness involves
the withdrawal of nothingness itself from any objective or causal
relation either to the subject or to any other objects in the world.
Given with every act of consciousness, implicated in every function
of mental and moral existence, absolute nothingness can never be
separated out from such instantiations as their object, cause or even
meaning.
Nonetheless, both in terms of the rigour with which he trans-
poses the dialectic of absolute nothingness into the paradoxical
dialectic of sin and holiness and in terms of how the emphasis on
an absolute disjunction between self- and Other-power makes pos-
sible the concept of a non-culturally-determined 'experience' of
absolute nothingness that, appropriated as saving grace, is the power
of religious existence - 'a power, not ourselves, that accepts our
unrighteousness' - we conclude that Tanabe's metanoetics is likely
to prove more fruitful in breaking through the paralysis of nihilism
and, even under the twin constellations of the death of God and of
the end of metaphysics, opening a path to the rebirth of religious
experience. We may not, however, refuse to acknowledge the price
that must be paid by all who would venture that path: the aban-
donment of all pretensions to secure a basis in knowledge for reli-
gious existence or to make of religion itself a ground for other
forms of knowledge. The religious way through the void is the way
of agnosis, of unknowing, not in the sense of mystical contempla-
tion but of active repentance and metanoetic freedom.55
One further comment may be in place at this point. If, in Tanabe's
reinterpretation of Pure Land teaching we have found human exist-
ence to be characterized from the ground up by a structural grace
Nothingness and the Place of Religious Experience 137
138
Agnosis: Thinking God in the Void 139
significant than the 'turn to the subject' associated with early mod-
ernism, namely the 'linguistic turn' that, in a variety of ways and
in a variety of representatives, has been largely determinative for
twentieth-century philosophy and theology. These disciplines have,
it seems, less and less defined themselves as being concerned with
how the world is or how we may know the world, but with the
way in which we represent the world to ourselves, especially in
and through language. Symptomatic of this turn are philosophies
as diverse as those of Ayer, Heidegger, Wittgenstein, Derrida and
Habermas. In the wake of the redefining of the tasks of philosophy
in linguistic terms, many would regard the popular model of the
self as a subject who 'has' experiences of an object world (even
when these experiences are as uncanny as an experience of nothing-
ness) and which then translates these experiences into language as
no longer tenable. There is no subject and no object, no self and no
world to which we have privileged access: there is only represen-
tation, only language, propagating and disseminating itself across
the face of the world. Indeed 'the world' is nothing more nor less
than the sum of linguistic self-production.
'Humanity' is therefore no longer conceived in terms of some
supra-historical or supra-cultural essence as was the humanity of
traditional humanism, idealistic or materialistic. Humanity is hu-
man in and as that which has broken through the silence of the
animal realm.1 Once this breakthrough is effected, 'the whole land-
scape [that was once beheld silently] is overrun with words as with
an invasion, it is henceforth but a variant of speech before our
eyes.. .'2 Merely to speak is to locate ourselves within a never-
ending verbal chain that, as Derrida has forcefully represented it,
has the fundamental characteristics of writing: the immediacy of
presence is always already deferred by the 'spaced' differentiation
of articulated discourse, rendering impossible the kind of subject-
object embrace that is determinative for all concepts of 'experience'.
But it is not even necessary for the argument to be taken into the
more controversial regions of post-structuralist theory in order to
query the kind of statements regarding experience that I have been
making. Some of the key issues are well-focused by George Lindbeck,
a self-styled 'post-liberal' theologian, who has categorized theories
of religion and doctrine into three main groupings. The first is shaped
by an understanding of doctrines as cognitively or informationally
meaningful. The second is the approach he calls the 'experiential-
expressive' that 'interprets doctrines as noninformative and
140 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
But now you will ask me, 'How am I to think of God himself, and
what is he?' and I cannot answer you except to say 'I do not
know!' For with this question you have brought me into the same
darkness, the same cloud of unknowing where I want you to be!
For though we through the grace of God can know fully about all
other matters, and think about them - yes, even the very works
of God himself - yet of God himself can no man think.17
And, though your natural mind can now find 'nothing' to feed
on, for it thinks you are doing no thing, go on doing this no
thing, and do it for the love of God. Therefore, do not give up but
work vigorously on that nothing, with vigilant longing and will
to have God, whom no man can know. For I tell you truly that
I would much rather be nowhere physically, wrestling with that
obscure nothing, than I would be some great potentate who
whenever I wanted could be anywhere I liked, and enjoy every-
thing as if it were my own.19
performed. At the other end of the scale are writings, almost cer-
tainly including the works of Pseudo-Dionysius, The Cloud of Un-
knowing and Meister Eckhart, 'in which the mystical discourse turns
back relentlessly upon its own propositions and generates distinc-
tive paradoxes that include within themselves a large number of
radical transformations, particularly in the area of temporal and
spatial relationships.'23 What such performative intensity achieves,
according to Sells, is a kind of self-deconstruction that, while not
abandoning the burden of reference (i.e. while maintaining the in-
tentionality of theological discourse towards the reality of God),
guards 'referential openness' and refuses the temptation 'to fill in
the open referent'.24 Instead of offering a mystical ontology, such
high performance writings explore a disontology, described by Sells
as 'the ongoing attempt to gain a momentary liberation from the
delimitation of predication and reference as represented by thus
and not thus.'25 Such disontology does not aspire to treat its subject
as an element, not even as the primary element, in any causal or
explanatory chain, but, by the use of 'split, fused and shifting ref-
erence' it seeks to establish 'a moment of receptivity free from the
security of referential delimitation.'26 It is prepared to acknowledge
that 'the smallest semantic unit is not the sentence or proposition,'
as is assumed both by the metaphysics of being and by positivist
assaults on such metaphysics, 'but the double sentence or dual
proposition' - that is, a sentence or proposition that retains its
propositional character and yet cannot be determined with respect
to any one single meaning.27
Sells' study is largely devoted to readings in those writers whom
he regards as exemplary practitioners of performative intensity -
Plotinus, John the Scot Eriugena, Ibn 'Arabi, Marguerite Porete and
Meister Eckhart. For, in practice, it is only by dint of interpretative
work that it can be demonstrated that the acceptance of such non-
monological logic does not lead to incoherence but, on the contrary,
enlivens and enriches the language of theology. Indeed, Sells' study
is devoted to showing that such language is, in the full sense of the
word, the realization of theological discourse, the only way in which
it can do justice to the character of religious experience and exist-
ence as essentially qualified by love.28
Not the least significant of Sells' contributions to understanding
the knot of issues with which we are currently concerned is the
warning that negative theology should not be treated as if it repre-
sented a consistent and uniform theological position. A weak ac-
knowledgement of divine unknowability functions quite otherwise
148 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
. . . relative to profane life this sacred animality has the same mean-
ing that the negation of nature (hence profane life) has relative to
pure animality. What is denied in profane life (through prohibi-
tions and through work) is a dependent state of the animal, sub-
ject to death and to utterly blind needs. What is denied by means
of divine life is still dependence, but this time it is the profane
world whose lucid and voluntary servility is contested.
(AC II, pp. 92-3)
. . . the glass of wine gives him, for a brief moment, the miraculous
sensation of having the world at his disposal... Beyond need,
the object of desire is, humanly, the miracle; it is sovereign life,
beyond the necessary that suffering defines. This miraculous ele-
ment which delights us may be simply the brilliance of the sun,
which on a spring morning transfigures a desolate street... It
may be w i n e . . . the form of beauty, of wealth - in the form,
moreover, of violence, of funereal and sacred sadness; in the form
of glory. What is the meaning of art, architecture, music, painting
or poetry if not the anticipation of a suspended, wonder-struck
moment, a miraculous moment?
(AC II, pp. 199-200)
Sovereign moments may thus break out in the midst of the every-
day - a glass of wine, a ray of sunlight. They may also be experi-
enced through art. Literature, for instance, 'continues the game of
religion, of which it is the principal heir.' It does this in so far as it
plays the game of looking death in the face, offering a vicarious
enactment of the individual's exposure to death and his attainment
of sovereignty in such exposure - effectively the function of sacri-
ficial ritual itself.
But do such periodic releases of excess energy - whether in col-
lective orgies of carnivalistic licence or in the discreet pleasures of
literature - really liberate us from bondage to laws of servility and
utility? On the contrary, don't such releases function, as Marcuse
put it, as a repressive tolerance, securing the homeostatic stability
of the profane world and thereby functionally determined with
regard to that world? Isn't the whole thing a feint? Hasn't prolepsis
always already triumphed in advance?
And, in any case, what would it mean to conceive of the sover-
eign subject or the sovereign moment? Aren't we back with the old
problem: that the moment we think it, it is no longer what we need
it to be? Derrida comments that Bataille must, consistently, 'mark
the point of no return of destruction, the instance of an expenditure
without reserve which no longer leaves us the resources with which
Agnosis: Thinking God in the Void 157
understands him) that such a world also invites the reversal of its
own values, its own construction. The aim that, by means of the
Aufhebung, humanity might establish and represent to itself its suc-
cessful transcendence over the mere givenness of the natural order
can equally well be achieved by the festal reversal of everything
established by means of the Aufhebung, for by this reversal it brings
itself back into the presence of death, of unmeaning and of primal
continuity, in relation to which alone the revelation of the mira-
culous, the poetic and the divine can be ecstatically communicated.
What the Hegelian system represents as completed and secured
through determinate historical moments must be enacted ever again
under the sign of repetition - and always as if from the very begin-
ning. Without the organizing teleology of the system, however, the
system can henceforth be read in any direction: backwards or for-
wards. Laughter and anguish alike ripple up and down and across
all the surfaces of our hierarchical constructions of experience.
But how does this excursus help our understanding of the inter-
relationship between language, experience and negative theology?
If Hart is correct, then Bataille's privileging of inner experience-
sovereignty-general economy is itself always open to deconstruc-
tion, always itself lapsing into restricted economy - and doing so
precisely because it lays claim to a particular kind of uniquely
privileged zone of experience from which to interpret the totality of
phenomena. Experience cannot deliver us from the self-deconstructing
processes of language - while language, in turn, means that we can
never lose ourselves in experience in the way that Bataille seems to
think we can.
Yet Derrida's reading of Bataille makes things somewhat more
complicated, because Derrida acknowledges that Bataille's sover-
eignty is not a particular experience demanding a particular lan-
guage. 'Sovereign speech is not another discourse.' But this also
means (though Derrida doesn't say so) that inner experience is not
a certain kind of experience. It is not the experience of something
(that would be objectifiable and susceptible to the machinery of
Aufhebung). It is the experience of nothingness. But that experience
itself, qua experience, frustrates any attempt to construct a uniquely
privileged language or a uniquely privileged interpretative stand-
point. Bataille - and this is a possibility left open precisely by
Derrida's (though not by Hart's) reading of Bataille - gives voice to
Agnosis: Thinking God in the Void 159
Where does this leave the question of questions, the question con-
cerning knowledge of God?
There is, after all, a faculty within the academy that has such
knowledge as its special province. If it can no longer claim to be
queen of all sciences, its representatives are still jealous of its title
to 'theology' and are reluctant to concede the entirety of their en-
deavour to the less ambitious concept of 'religious studies', i.e. the
study of religion as no more than one aspect among others of hu-
man social, psychological or cultural reality.
Nor can it be denied that the present work is, in a quite definite
sense, theological. Its starting-point was the contemporary crisis of
belief in God and the exigency arising out of this crisis that we seek
a way of thinking God within the void of modern and postmodern
nihilism.
Yet no one would regard the kind of experience that has been
adumbrated in the course of this enquiry and the kind of under-
standing of religious language that has been explored in the last
few pages as 'scientific' in any hard sense. Even in comparison with
other subjects from within the spectrum of the humanities, the kind
of experience and the kind of language that have been our concern
here, cannot claim the coherence that is a sine qua non of any aca-
demic discipline - a remark that is no less true if it is extended to
areas of interdisciplinary study which are also required to justify
themselves in terms of a rigorous and distinctive specification of
subject-matter and methodology. In any case, even apart from the
162 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
cannot for one moment stand apart from the ongoing engagement
with contiguous disciplines in relation to which it must convinc-
ingly demonstrate the force of its insights in practice. The point is
rather that theology, if it is prepared to accept the implications of
such diverse theological critiques of metaphysical knowledge as
those associated with Luther and Kierkegaard on the one hand and
with mysticism and negative theology on the other, has consider-
able and indeed unique resources to bear on the question of how
thinking remains possible 'after' metaphysics. For this question is
not new to theology. It has accompanied theologians from biblical
times onwards.
For theology, no less than philosophy, is concerned with ques-
tions concerning the limits of possible knowledge, but, to a much
greater extent than philosophy, it can accommodate itself to the
thought that reason and the world of facts certified by reason are
not final. 'Let religion begin where it will, it must begin with that
which is above reason,' as Dean Mansel put it.49 One way in which
theology has acknowledged this is by a willingness to admit an
element of mystery into the structuring of human experience and
reflection.
Mansel himself, John Henry Newman, Rudolf Otto, Gabriel
Marcel, Karl Rahner and, more recently, Gordon Kaufman and D.Z.
Phillips are just some who have made a place for mystery at the
very heart of theological endeavour.50 Inevitably the way in which
they have done so bears the stamp of their various distinct ap-
proaches to theology - and yet they provide a convergent testi-
mony regarding (a) the importance of mystery; (b) that, in Marcel's
phrase, 'The recognition of mystery... is an essentially positive act
of the mind ...'; (c) that mystery has to do with what is most fun-
damental to our self-identity; and that (d) mystery can never be
translated without remainder into knowledge.
The question of mystery shows one way in which theology has
been able to find its most interesting questions precisely at those
points where the limits of reason or of human knowledge come into
view. Moreover, if it is true that it is in the interests of critical
thinking in general to distinguish between what does and what
does not require rational justification - if, as Kierkegaard put it,
thought is always governed by its own paradoxical will 'to discover
something that thought itself cannot think' (PF, p. 37) - then to raid
the inarticulable world of religious experience will not be without
value for those who also value reason as a guide to life's perplexities.
164 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
Such raids help us, as perhaps nothing else can, to reflect on what
can and what cannot be thought, what can and what cannot be
known - even if, in the nature of the subject itself, the best they can
yield is a body of case-law that requires continuing interpretation
rather than any final or definitive 'answer'.
In this respect, then, we may say that theology, precisely by vir-
tue of its willingness to place its own status as 'science', as an
'academic discipline', at risk, may nonetheless also serve the wider
community of thought.
But how far can talk of an experience of nothingness or a theol-
ogy that owes its specific shape to such an experience really ad-
dress that wider community?
David Tracy has forcefully argued the case for recognizing and
maintaining the character of theology as public discourse. Taking
note of the three public realms for which the contemporary Euro-
pean or North American theologian writes (the realms of church,
academy and what he calls 'the wider society'), he states that 'the
drive to genuine publicness... is incumbent upon every theolo-
gian .. .'51 Although the extent to which any one particular public
is held in the foreground of the theologian's view will vary, thus
affecting the specific colouring of the resultant theology, public it
will and must be. Not only must it relate to the continuing life of
the church community, it must also meet 'the highest standards of
the contemporary academy and engage with matters of weight and
concern to the complex life of society as a whole.'52
The argument presented here could be read as failing to meet this
challenge. The concern with some kind of (apparently) inarticulable,
mysterious experience and the prominence given to such theologi-
cal arcana as negative theology, mysticism and nothingness could
be seen as a surrendering of the requirement to engage with broad
issues of vital contemporary concern on the ground established by
agreed criteria of truth.
That is a judgement I would reject. On the contrary, the challenge
to think God in the void of contemporary nihilism belongs very
much to the public realm of our time, engaging the attention of aca-
demy, church and wider society alike. Moreover, the methodological
commitment to dialogue across religious boundaries consciously re-
flects the global event of the encounter of world religions that is of
momentous significance for the future of the religious conscious-
ness - despite the current ascendancy of various forms of funda-
mentalism and communalism. Moreover, although it has not been
Agnosis: Thinking God in the Void 165
The shape and outcome of this enquiry has been largely deter-
mined by the choice of works discussed. These have, intentionally,
been of a decisively religious orientation, even when their religious
concern has issued in radical revisions or even the repudiation of
prevailing models of religious existence and thought.
Even if the tactic of focusing on religious texts in this way should
be unexceptionable within the restricted economy of a theological
enquiry, however, it may seem arrogant - particularly in the light
of the closing remarks of the previous section - to have passed by
a thinker who has done so much to determine not only the under-
standing of nothingness in the twentieth century but also the
problematics of ontology in a post-metaphysical situation. I mean,
of course, Martin Heidegger.
Allusion has been made to Heidegger's own categorization of
Kierkegaard's thought as 'merely ontical' in contrast to his own
concern for fundamental ontology and surely this distinction itself
Agnosis: Thinking God in the Void 167
170
Notes 171
CHAPTER 2 NOTHINGNESS
AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYSICS
1. G.W.F. Hegel (ed. Lasson), Wissenschaft der Logik I (Samtliche Werke
Bd. Ill) (Leipzig: Felix Meiner) p. 31.
2. J.M.E. McTaggart, Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1896) p. 49.
3. S. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1992) p. 110.
4. A. Trendelenburg, Logische Untersuchungen I (Berlin, 1840) p. 44.
5. McTaggart, p. 32.
6. McTaggart, p. 34.
7. McTaggart, p. 91. In the context of his discussion of Kant's critique
of the ontological argument, Hegel himself draws a sharp distinction
between Sein and Da-sein that depends precisely on Da-Sein's func-
tioning as a predication of actual existence. See Logik, p. 73.
8. Hegel, Aesthetics. Lectures on Fine Art (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1975) p. 29.
9. A. Kojeve, Introduction a la Lecture de Hegel (Paris: Gallimard, 1947)
p. 540.
10. It is, of course, no coincidence that Kojeve's reading is focused pre-
cisely on the Phenomenology.
11. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977) p. 9.
12. Ibid., pp. 6-7.
13. Ibid., p. 6.
14. Ibid., p. 5.
15. Ibid., p. 7.
16. Ibid., p. 10.
17. Ibid.
18. Ibid., pp. 18-19.
19. N.P. Williams, The Ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin (London:
Longmans, Green and Co., 1927) p. 505. For precedents to such a
position in the Christian tradition, see John Hick's account of what
he calls the 'felix culpa' theme in Christian theology, alluding to a
medieval verse which read 'O happy fault, which secured such and
so great a redemption.' In John Hick, Evil and the God of Love (Lon-
don: Fontana, 1968) pp. 103-4 and 323f.
20. See, for example, the debate between Thulstrup and Taylor. N.
Notes 175
32. A. Schopenhauer, Parerga und Paralipomena II./l Werke Bd. IX, p. 326.
33. F. Nietzsche, The Will to Power (New York: Vintage, 1968) 855 (refer-
ences will be given according to entry rather than to page number;
further references will be given as WP in the text). In a similar vein
are such remarks as the following: "The spread of Buddhism (not its
origin) is thus to a considerable extent dependent on the excessive
and almost exclusive rice-fare of the Indians, and on the universal
enervation that results therefrom.' F. Nietzsche, The Joyful Wisdom
(London: Foulis, 1910), p. 173 (Book III.134). Noting the reservation
regarding the 'origin' of Buddhism, the thrust of the passage is in a
strongly reductionist direction. On a grander scale is the whole of
Book Four of The Will to Power. 'Discipline and Breeding'.
34. For a further discussion of issues of language, see Chapter 5 below.
35. Rather than speak of the 'Superman' or 'Overman' of previous trans-
lations, I shall use the expression 'the More-than-Human-Being'
which, to my mind, better captures the continuities and discontinuities
between the Ubermensch and contemporary humanity, while leav-
ing ambiguous what Nietzsche leaves ambiguous. It is also valuable
in this case to do as much as possible to undermine the view that
we already know - for good or ill - what Nietzsche means by this
concept.
36. We may note that in The Fourfold Root Schopenhauer had signalled
the field of volition precisely by reference to the question 'why' as
opposed to the 'how' of causal explanation (p. 161).
37. F. Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Penguin: Harmondsworth, 1961,
1969) pp. 41-2. Further references are given as Z in the text. I have
occasionally adapted Hollingdale's translation.
38. Nietzsche's sarcastic allusion to plant and ghost suggests that de-
spite the claims of the idealists this synthesis has still not been ad-
equately worked out. The More-than-Human-Being will therefore be
the one who achieves what idealism promised but failed to deliver.
188
Bibliography 189
Chestov, L., In Job's Balances (London: J.M. Dent, 1932). See also under Shestov.
Cobb, J.B. and Ives, C. (eds), The Emptying God. A Buddhist-Jewish-Christian
Conversation (New York: Orbis, 1990).
Cupitt, D., Creation out of Nothing (London: SCM, 1990).
Cupitt, D., Taking Leave of God (London: SCM, 1980).
Cupitt, D., The Time Being (London: SCM, 1992).
Cupitt, D., The World to Come (London: SCM, 1982).
Derrida,}., Glas (Lincoln and London: University of Nebraska Press, 1986).
Derrida, ) . , Writing and Difference (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978).
Eckhart, Meister, Sermons and Treatises, 3 vols (Shaftesbury: Element, 1987-
90).
Gilson, E., Being and Some Philosophers (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of
Mediaeval Studies, 1952).
Hart, K., The Trespass of the Sign (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1989).
Hegel, G.W.F., Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977).
Hegel, G.W.E. (ed. Lasson), Wissenschaft der Logik, I (Siimtliche Werke Bd. Ill)
(Leipzig: Felix Meiner).
Heidegger, M., Being and Time (Oxford: Blackwell, 1962).
Heidegger, M., Beitrage zur Philosophic (Vom Ereignis) (Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann, 1989).
Heidegger, M., The Concept of Time (dual language edition - Oxford:
Blackwell, 1992).
Heidegger, M., Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik (Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann, 1983).
Heidegger, M., Nietzsche (tr. Krell in four volumes - San Francisco: Harper
& Row, 1979, 1982, 1984, 1987).
Heidegger, M., The Question of Being (dual language edition - London:
Vision, 1959).
Heidegger, M., What is Metaphysics? in Heidegger (tr. and ed. Krell), Basic
Writings (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978).
Irigaray, L., The Marine Lover of Friedrich Nietzsche (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1991) .
James, W., The Varieties of Religious Experience (London: Collins/Fontana,
1960).
Kahn, C.H., "The Greek Verb "to be" and the Concept of Being', Founda-
tions of Language, vol. 2 (1966).
Katz, S.T., 'Language, Epistemology and Mysticism', in Lindbeck, G. (ed.),
Mysticism and Philsophical Analysis (London: Sheldon Press, 1978).
Kaufman, G.D., In Face of Mystery. A Constructive Theology (Cambridge,
Mass: Harvard University Press, 1993).
Keenan, J.D., The Meaning of Christ. A Mahayana Theology (New York: Orbis,
1989).
Kierkegaard, S., Concluding Unscientific Postscript (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1992).
Kierkegaard, S., Eighteen Upbuilding Discourses (Princeton: Princeton Uni-
versity Press, 1990).
Kierkegaard, S., Philosophical Fragments. Johannes Climacus (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1985).
190 Agnosis: Theology in the Void
192
Index 193
Freedom (see also Will, willing) Kant, I. 42, 49-50, 60-1, 71, 76,
21-5, 30, 48, 51, 52-5, 58-60, 65, 80, 117, 128
90, 103, 128-9 Katz, S.T. 140
Kaufman, G. 163
Gilson, E. 171n Kerouac, J. 109
God 144-6, 151-2, 161-6 Kierkegaard, S. 2, 39, 41, 42, 43,
God (and Being) 12, 13, 25-6, 81, 50, 51-60, 69, 82, 86-92, 93,
169 100-7, 108, 110-11, 128, 132,
Grace 21-5, 29, 30, 31, 84, 85, 151, 152, 153, 162, 163, 165, 166,
128, 134,136-7, 138, 161 175n, 177n, 178n, 179n, 185n,
Griinewald, M. 39 186-7n; pseudonymity in 51-2,
69
Habermas, J. 139 Knowledge 9-10, 28, 30-1, 37,
Harding, D.W. 183n 42-4, 46-7, 48, 55-7, 59-60, 62,
Hart, K. 146, 148-50, 158-9 68, 76, 80, 93-6, 113, 115-17,
Hegel, G.W.F., Hegelianism 4, 126, 128, 130, 133, 135-6, 140,
41-50, 51, 60, 80, 81, 82, 87, 88, 144-9, 151-2, 157, 161-6
90, 93, 108, 128, 149, 157-8, Kojeve, A. 45
174n, 186n Kyoto School 4-5, 108-9
Heidegger, M. 6, 39, 80, 83, 85-6,
88, 99, 108, 129, 132, 139, 166-9, Language 85, 96, 98-9, 134,
170n, 173n, 175n, 178n, 181-2n, 138-43, 146-50, 157, 177n
186-7n Laughter 153, 155, 158
Hermeneutics 3, 98-9, 143, 165 Lindbeck, G. 139-40
Hick, J. 174n Logic 41-5
Hinduism 67 Love 87, 96, 100-1, 134, 138, 147
Historicity of thought 4,14,168-9 Luther, M. 25-30, 36-7, 38, 39,
Holderlin, F. 106-7, 186n 60, 134, 162
Hui-Neng 111-12, 115, 123, 179n
Humility 30, 33 McTaggart, J.E.M. 42, 44, 174n
Hung Jen 111 Manicheanism 12-13
Huxley, A. 84-5, 110 Mansel, H.L. 163
Marcel, G. 163, 177n
Ibn 'Arabi 147 Marcuse, H. 156
In-itself, the 61, 63, 64, 71, 117 Marion, J.-L. 3, 173n
Incarnation, the 57 Matter 9-11, 12, 14
Intuition 43, 45, 50, 92-7, 105, Memory 15-18
113, 114, 117, 126, 127, 132, 136, Merleau-Ponty, M. 139, 141,
160 183n
Irigaray, L. 82-3 Metanoia, metanoetics see
Repentance
James, W. 84-5, 113, 177n Metaphysics 7-8, 20, 26-7, 30,
Jansenius 34 33-4, 38-40, 41-50, 59-60, 71,
Jeremiah 39 80, 81, 91, 92, 98, 136, 148-50,
Jesus Christ 55 168-9, 186-7n
John the Scot Eriugena 147 Moment, the 56, 57, 101, 104-6,
Jones, J. 148 110-11
Jungel, E. 174n, 179n Murdoch, I. 3
Jiinger, E. 187n Mystery 95, 163-4
194 Index
Subjectivity 37, 41, 45, 47, 48, 53, Trendelenburg, A. 41, 43-4
75, 77, 81-2, 85, 86-7, 93, 119, Truth 16, 46-7, 56, 86, 90,
133-4, 138, 168 110-11
Sunyata 110, 120-2, 181n
Suzuki, D.T. 109-13, 115 Values 72, 76-8
System, the 41, 51, 56, 158
Walsh, S. 175n
Tanabe, H. 108, 123-7, 181-2n Watts, A. 109
Taylor, Mark C. 174-5n, 178n Will, willing 14, 20-5, 28-9,
Theology 38, 161-9 31-3, 36, 41, 63-9, 72, 73, 75-80,
Thulsturp, N. 174-5n 113, 114
Tillich, P. 2, 5, 90, 181n Williams, N.P. 49
Time 15-20, 23-4, 41, 48, 51, Wittgenstein, L. 139, 157, 177n
56-60, 91, 101-7, 129-30, 134-5, Wundt, W. 113
179n
Topos, concept of, see Place, Zange see Repentance
concept of Zen 109-23, 131-2, 140, 182n
Tracy, D. 164 Zum Brunn, E. 171n