(2018) Cross-Cultural Aesthetics
(2018) Cross-Cultural Aesthetics
Anthropological aesthetics
Franz Boas is credited with establishing the study of aesthetics within anthropology,
arguing that, without postulating an aesthetic impulse in humans, it is not possible
to understand how artistic behaviors such as elaborate patternmaking could have
C R O S S - C U L T U R A L A E S T H E T I CS 3
historian Herschel B. Chipp (1960) used an approach derived from Boas to explore how
studying the emic aesthetic appreciation of formal qualities, combined with analysis of
mythology and ritual, could be used to explore meaning and symbolism in primitive
art. Also influenced by Boas, the art historian Robert Farris Thompson (1973) stud-
ied Yoruba art history and aesthetic values, establishing a method for identifying emic
systems of evaluation. Two important articles extending the account of aesthetics from
an anthropological perspective were George Mills’s “Art: An Introduction to Qualita-
tive Anthropology” ([1957] 1971) and Warren L. d’Azevedo’s “A Structural Approach
to Esthetics: Towards a Definition of Art in Anthropology” (1958). Both these accounts
focus on the manipulation of qualities as a form of expression within a culture in a
manner that provide an opportunity for aesthetic reflection, and they use the process
of aesthetic reflection and skill as the basis for an anthropology of art.
Mills’s contribution was to develop a connection between art and cognition that is
closer to Baumgarten’s interest in the relationship between ideas and qualities as a dis-
tinct kind of knowledge than it is to Kant’s aesthetics. Through the qualitative study
of culture, Mills argued, the aesthetic patterns of cultures (called “styles”) may provide
insight into the interior articulation of cultures and values. Mills points out that art as
a medium of expression is consistently overlooked by anthropological accounts of art.
Art is expressive as “art is the creation, by manipulating a medium, of public objects or
events that serve as deliberately organized sets of conditions for experience in qualita-
tive mode” (Mills [1957] 1971, 95). Qualitative experiences are a result of presentation,
suggestion, and structure. Materials of creation arouse sensations that have qualities.
Paint may be shiny or dull, the tone of a sound may be mellow or sharp, a particular
color is chosen, movements are fast or slow, and so forth. Structures are also perceptual,
such as tight or monumental or swirling or chaotic. Together, structures and qualities
are suggestive and associated with other parts of life that enable expression, such as
when the qualities of action are symbolic, where qualities augment or add to the utility
or purpose of a thing as an opportunity to experience qualities, such as in the decorative
arts, and where arts cease to be an incident in life and life becomes an incident in art
(as in drama, portraiture, or the novel).
D’Azevedo developed a distinction between aesthetic appreciation, which may be
diffused throughout all aspects of life, and artistic behavior, in which objects are cre-
ated through a specific process involving technical skills and aesthetic perception. In
aesthetic appreciation, he noted, there is an affective aspect of enhancement or enjoy-
ment and a rational aspect of ideation associated with the form of an everyday event
or object, such as the recognition of the gracefulness with which a gift is presented. For
d’Azevedo, aesthetic appreciation is possible through “a faculty of cognition by which
values are selected, organized, and reinforced from the general experience of the indi-
vidual in correspondence with the symbolic values evoked by the intrinsic elements and
qualities of an object” (1958, 708).
Similarly, Clifford Geertz (1976) explored a semiotic approach to art that is more
reminiscent of Baumgarten’s theory of aesthetics than Kantian. Against formalist
approaches to art, Geertz argues that the formal relations of qualities such as sound,
volume image, or color cannot explain the aesthetic power of art, nor the concerns
of the artist. In this claim, he moves away from Boas’s theory, in that he suggests that
C R O S S - C U L T U R A L A E S T H E T I CS 5
the concern of an artist grows out of more than a detached pleasure in the intrinsic
properties of a medium or the marks being made, instead deriving from the meanings
of the marks. Arts are “never wholly intra-aesthetic” (Geertz 1976, 1475). The chief
problem for anthropology, he suggested, was how to connect aesthetic phenomena
into a particular pattern of cultural significance. This connection is cognitive because
the central connection between art and life is semiotic in that qualitative features
materialize a way of experiencing the world.
More recent anthropological work has focused on the nature and role of aesthetic
affect, rather than the question of whether something is art. For instance, Ellen
Dissanayake (1992) argues that the origin of art is a “making special” or elaboration,
akin to ritual and play, that emerged as a biologically adaptive feature of humanity.
While no society demonstrates all the behaviors commonly considered to be art to
the same extent, all societies develop the human potential for material poetic and
expressive forms, and most have some kind of evaluative vocabulary for excellence in
those forms. Dissanayake approaches aesthetics from the perspective of evolutionary
ethology and anthropology, arguing for the existence of an unconscious aesthetic
impulse in the objects we view as art from other civilizations and cultures, even if
they were not made to be art. Jeremy Coote developed an anthropological concept
that consists in “the comparative study of valued perceptual experience in different
societies” (1992, 247). Coote explored how Nilote cattle keepers, who had no material
arts, valued the various markings on cattle and how they perceived, appreciated, and
described the world through terms drawn from this value system.
These different approaches to cross-cultural aesthetics have not only influenced
the anthropology of art but also inspired new anthropological methods and foci
including visual and sensory anthropology. The focus of study is not necessarily on
art but on the aesthetic sensibilities of communities and the means by which sensory
qualities constitute a kind of epistemology and knowledge. Such studies enrich not
only anthropology but also the new areas of philosophical analysis called “everyday
aesthetics” and “social aesthetics.”
people at all times in Western societies. According to Bourdieu, art is not defined by a
type of creation but by a kind of social institution. The disinterested contemplative atti-
tude of the art lover is a product of history. This is because the process of aesthetic appre-
ciation is inseparable from the historical appearance of producers of art motivated by
artistic intention and from the production of fine art as autonomous and as having ends
and standards that are found or created by the artist. The “pure” aesthetic response, how-
ever, has more in common with twentieth-century formalism than Baumgarten’s epis-
temology of sensitive knowing. Bourdieu’s argument is based on what is known as an
institutional account of art. The argument is that objects and events created specifically
for the purpose of aesthetic contemplation emerged in response to, or at the same time
as, the philosophical analysis of judgments of beauty and taste in Britain in the eigh-
teenth century. At the same time, there emerged the fine art institution or “art world” of
galleries and dealers, academies, critics, and museums of art in relation to the objects.
Artists create works for contemplation by an audience in the context of this institution.
Any culture that lacks this institution, or a similar institution, therefore lacks art and the
practice of aesthetic appreciation associated with it. Moreover, if the institutional theory
of art is true, the objects of other cultures in museums are art only because they have
been “metaphorphosed” into art objects through a process of selection by a curator.
Much of the debate concerning the applicability of aesthetics as a cross-cultural
concept concerns differing definitions of art and aesthetic appreciation that are at
cross purposes. Joanna Overing argues that the concept of aesthetics disconnects art
“from the social, the practical, the cosmological” and makes “artistic activity especially
distinct from the technological, the everyday, the productive” (1996, 210). In contrast,
she argues, for some cultural groups, such as the Piaroa, the notion of beauty “cannot
be removed from productive use,” and the conception of beauty is different because
“beautification empowers” (1996, 210). Similarly, Alfred Gell argues that art functions
as a “technology of enchantment” and provides an example of the prow-boards of
Kula canoes, which are intended “to dazzle the beholder” (1992, 94) rather than to
be contemplated aesthetically. Such approaches emphasize formalism in aesthetics.
In contrast, twentieth and early twenty-first-century philosophers, historians, and
anthropologists of art have engaged in cross-cultural aesthetics argue that aesthetic
features, such as color, tone, or pattern, may serve functional purposes other than
contemplation. The purpose of the object need not be aesthetic, and the aesthetic
features may enhance the instrumental purpose of the object. If body painting or dress,
or certain patterning, is undertaken to make the wearer more beautiful (in order to be
more powerful or effective) or, as in the case of the prow-boards Gell (1992) discusses,
more dazzling, then that use is aesthetic.
Overing’s criticism overlooks the fact that aesthetic appreciation is not limited to the
appreciation of art, but she does point to a significant problem concerning how objects
in art museums are viewed and displayed. Not everything created with aesthetically
rewarding properties is created for the purpose of aesthetic contemplation. This has
raised numerous ethical issues in relation to the display of cultural forms in museums
and galleries about whether the aesthetic appreciation of them is always appropriate, or
deep. In Western societies, art and aesthetics are often considered among the highest
human achievements. On this view, to suggest that fine art and aesthetic appreciation
C R O S S - C U L T U R A L A E S T H E T I CS 7
are specific to European cultures is to suggest that European cultures are superior
to others. However, to consider the objects created in another culture fine art is to
overlook the fact that it is a Western institution naming and categorizing the objects,
which is expressive of unequal power relations and control. This issue of categorization
and control over the meaning of artifacts has arisen in postcolonial countries such as
Australia, Canada, and the United States and manifests itself in conflicts over what may
be shown or displayed in art galleries and museums. Such conflicts are connected to the
historical looting of colonies but also to a failure of imagination concerning the nature
of aesthetic evaluation that does disconnect it from everyday life and that overvalues
form. For instance, the Zuni people of Mexico have demanded the repatriation of their
war gods, or Ahauutas, from the Smithsonian on the basis that they are inalienable
property and cannot be morally or legally owned by anyone else. The Iroquois have
asked for the removal of masks from the National Museum of Canada on the grounds
that the masks are not only sacred but also dangerous. The institutional theory of
art may provide an unsatisfactory definition of art, or an unsatisfactory explanation
of why those objects belong in a gallery, but it works well as a description of what
happens to objects from other cultures within a museum context. The challenge for
museums, beyond recognizing indigenous property rights, is how to educate audiences
and deepen appreciation beyond surfaces.
In general, the critics who reject the usefulness of aesthetics as a cross-cultural
concept argue that aesthetics as a field of study involves a strong functionalist definition
of art and a formalist approach to aesthetic appreciation (both of which those critics
reject). A third feature that these critics may share is acceptance of an institutional
definition of art. A strength of these criticisms is that they alert us to ethical issues of
appropriation and display within museum contexts. What characterizes cross-cultural
aesthetics as an area of study, however, is a broad definition of art that is only weakly
functionalist, in that it presupposes that the creators of some material culture are
aesthetically engaged with their medium in the process of creation. This aesthetic
engagement is not based on formalist assumptions but takes a cognitive, or ideational,
approach to aesthetic appreciation and attempts to uncover the emic perspectives
that inform aesthetic value. In the process, anthropologists engaged in cross-cultural
aesthetics have opened up new methods of exploring human culture and engagement
with the world around them.
SEE ALSO: Art and Agency; Art, Anthropology of; Boas, Franz (1858–1942); Bourdieu,
Pierre (1930–2002); Cognition and Visual Art; Colonialism and the Museum; Dance,
Anthropology of; Design, Anthropology of; Frobenius, Leo (1873–1938); Geertz,
Clifford (1926–2006); Gell, Alfred (1945–97); Iconography and Style; Kant, Immanuel
(1724–1804): Influence on the Origins and Development of Anthropology; Montage;
Objecthood; Senses, Anthropology of; Shimmer; Visual Anthropology
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. (1739) 2013. Metaphysics. Translated and edited by Courtney
D. Fugate and John Hymers. London: Bloomsbury.
8 C R O S S - C U L T U R A L A E S T H E T I CS