Materiality Movement and Meaning Archite
Materiality Movement and Meaning Archite
To begin with, I’m thinking here of two related examples of emergence: firstly
the ontogenetic process – how we as human beings mature into apparently
rational sense-making individuals, when we didn’t start out that way at birth –
and secondly, what we might call (after the editor of Alexander Luria’s book on
Language and Cognition) the ‘micro-genetic’ process by which we make sense
of our ongoing flow of embodied experience ‘in real-time’ as it were, of what
actually goes on in that curious overlapping of immediate past with anticipated
future that we usually refer to as ‘the present moment’. Of course I’m thinking
here of Edmund Husserl’s analysis of the consciousness of time as a multi-
layered experience of what he called ‘retentions’ and ‘protentions’, and also of
the more recent work by the neurophilosopher Daniel Dennett in his book
Consciousness Explained, from 1991, where he explores these ideas in a much
more accessible way, also drawing on more recent experimental data from
research in the neurosciences.
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 305
Keynote lecture
In order to explore this apparently circular relationship between the human and
the technological, in what follows I will describe some examples of the ways in
which we engage with technologies on a day to day level, and how the process
of ‘incorporation’ – literally, absorbing into our body-image, or more accurately
our body-schema – entails a number of important cognitive consequences. In
the final part of the paper I will also try to outline what I think this might mean for
the continuing relevance of tectonic articulation and materiality in architecture,
for example, in the creation of engaging and richly layered environments that
contain visible traces of both the processes of construction and occupation –
spaces that invite engagement with both the bodies and minds of future building
users. And this is the reason why I think this way of thinking about time, as just
mentioned, as a multi-layered continuum of past recollections and future
projections – especially in relation to tools and technologies - is so important for
architects to consider.
Another more dramatic illustration of the flexibility and plasticity of the boundary
between brain, body and world, can be seen in the experiment carried out by
the Australian performance artist Stelarc, adding a prosthetic ‘Third Hand’ to his
own biological body (Massumi, 1998: 336). The hand is controlled by nerve
impulses picked up from surface electrodes attached to his upper thigh and
abdominal area. While the device took some time to learn how to operate –
basically by a process of trial-and-error experiment – with practiced use it can
be quite precisely controlled, independently of the artist’s two biological hands.
This example also reminds us of the fact that - from birth onwards – we have all
passed through a similar process of exploratory bodily ‘training’, swinging our
limbs about more or less wildly until we gradually learn how to control and
apply them, and to reach out and take up other bits of the world in order to
extend our bodily capacities.
Figure 1: Stelarc - THIRD HAND,
Tokyo, Yokohama, Nagoya 1980. The idea that technical extensions of the body can also become intrinsic to our
Photographer: Toshifumi Ike. © individual sense of self is also suggested by the philosophers Andy Clark and
Stelarc / T. Ike..
David Chalmers in their 1998 essay ‘The Extended Mind’. They describe how
we commonly rely on various technical props and supports to help us to deal
with everyday mental tasks, from note-pads and pencils for writing down ideas
to electronic calculators and digital search-engines for retrieving and
manipulating useful information. The all-too-familiar misfortune of losing a wallet
or a mobile phone also reminds us how distressing it is to be denied access to
what can suddenly seem like a vital organ. Robbed of our taken-for-granted
ability to make phonecalls, look up addresses, check diary entries and access
the internet, it is easy to feel that we are not quite the complete person that we
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 306
Keynote lecture
previously assumed we were. Likewise with the kind of crisis of self-identity that
often accompanies a loss of memory and a lack of ability to navigate complex
environments that can often be a consequence of the degenerative illnesses of
old age.
As if to dramatise this reliance on the ability of the environment to ‘think for us’
so to speak, the French philosopher Bernard Stiegler in his book Technics and
Time (1998) even goes as far as to say that - far from being simply an optional
extra – these technological extensions that we routinely incorporate into our
extended body-schema should be seen as a fundamental part of what it is to be
a human-being (1998: 152). In the next section I will explore this idea within an
evolutionary framework, drawing an analogy between the ontogenetic
processes that we have just been considering (the development of the
embodied individual enhanced by various technical extensions), and the longer
timescale of the phylogenetic process by which the human species itself can be
seen to have emerged. To do this, I will be apply a model of ‘circular causality’ –
the idea that a kind of feedback loop between technical development and
biological mutation has been helping to steer the course of human evolution.
Or, in relation to architecture, as Winston Churchill once famously said: “We
make our buildings and thereafter our buildings make us” (1951).
My first piece of evidence is taken from a recent book called The Prehistory of
the Mind by the cognitive archeologist Steven Mithen. In it he shows a timeline
of the development of early Hominid species, showing increases in average
brain size over the last 4 million years (1996: 7). The key points are the two
major periods of significant brain enlargement, initially from about 2 million
years ago, and then again from half a million to 200,000 years ago. In parallel
with these developments archeologists have also found evidence of the
emergence of early stone tool technology, in the period from 2.6 million years
ago, up to 250,000 years ago, showing the increasing complexity of strategic
planning involved in the transition from so-called Oldowan to the more
advanced Late Acheulean tool-making processes.
Of course, it is difficult to infer direct causality in one direction or the other: one
might claim that bigger brains are the ‘cause’ of more complex technology – or,
equally, I could try to claim that it actually works the other way round: the
existence of more complex tool-making practices could be the selective
pressure required to ‘cause’ the preservation of genetic mutations that happen
to confer additional tool-making ability. What I actually want to claim here is
simply that both these forces are interacting in a circular process of mutual
support.
Another important point worth noting about this evolutionary development is the
relation between these early technical practices and the emergence of spoken
language. While evidence for the existence of language is notoriously difficult to
find we can at least infer it from fossilized anatomical fragments. The increasing
complexity of the vocal tract, as well as the size and shape of the skull, both
imply the possibility of early human linguistic ability. And there is also the
circumstantial evidence of sophisticated social interaction that could have been
facilitated by verbal communication which is suggested by the archeological
remains of complex communal settlements.
This potential evolutionary link between technology and language has also
been described quite recently by the neuroscientist Michael Arbib in a chapter
of the book called Architecture and Neuroscience, published in Finland in 2013.
Arbib has been writing on this theme since his earliest work from the 1970’s but
in fact it is an idea that has been around since at least a decade before that.
In research from the 1960s which is published in English in the book called
Figure 2: Andre Leroi-Gourhan – Gesture and Speech, the French paleo-anthropologist Andre Leroi-Gourhan
Cortical picture of voluntary motor had also found evidence of a neural feedback circuit that seemed to connect
function (after Penfield and technical and linguistic ability. A key part of his evidence was based on the
Rasmussen). Right hemisphere of human
brain in cross-section. © MIT Press, 1993.
organisation of brain activity in the sensory-motor cortex, where the major areas
P. 82. devoted to control of the hands and the vocal apparatus are located in
immediately adjacent areas. He supports his claims with a dramatic image
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 307
Keynote lecture
taken from the 1940s work of neurologists Penfield and Rasmussen, showing
where the major parts of the body’s sensory-motor apparatus are processed
within the brain (1993: 82). This diagram also emphasises the variation in the
proportions of cortical space given over to the different parts of the body, with
the largest areas devoted to those needing the most precise levels of control
and articulation.
Leroi-Gourhan also partly bases his argument on the evolutionary shift from
moving on all-fours to walking upright, claiming that this innovation
simultaneously liberated both the hands and the face for new uses. In place of
their previous focus on ground-based movement and exploration, both are now
able to be employed in new forms of communication. He further suggests that
manual ability with tool-making might have provided the initial stimulus to the
use of the hands to communicate, thus encouraging a refinement of a kind of
proto-language of bodily posture into a set of more precisely articulated manual
gestures. This idea has been further developed more recently in the work of the
evolutionary psychologist Michael Corballis, in a book called From Hand to
Mouth published in 2002, as well as by Tim Ingold, who I mentioned earlier, in
an edited volume called Tools, Language and Cognition in Human Evolution
(1993). Ingold makes the connection more convincingly in my view, partly in the
way he considers language itself as a form of technology –another kind of ‘tool’
for reaching out beyond the body to make things happen in the world around
us.
Leroi-Gourhan for his part, accepts the speculative nature of this connection,
given that the early historical traces of spoken language have clearly not been
physically preserved. But if we consider the ways in which technical processes
and procedures are visibly evident in the form of the tool itself, then perhaps
this provides an example of how bodily communication can be captured and
passed on from one generation to the next. The French philosopher Jacques
Derrida, intrigued by the apparently inferior philosophical status of written as
opposed to spoken forms of language, was also inspired directly by Leroi-
Gourhan to speculate on the evolutionary function that physical traces of human
memory might actually have performed:
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 308
Keynote lecture
as he says, both ‘constituted and effaced’ in the movement that both solidifies
and objectifies the individual identity of the maker within the artefact itself, and,
at the same time, projects it out into the world to take its place among countless
other more or less anonymous objects.
For another way of looking at this we could turn to the writing of the physician-
turned-philosopher Raymond Tallis in his remarkable book on The Hand, (2003)
where, like Derrida, he also uses this idea as the basis for a theory of the
emergence of human self-consciousness. The book elaborates on Freidrich
Engels’ famous statement that:
“The hand is not only the organ of labour, it is also the product of
labour” (1940: 281).
Tallis suggests that out of the ‘objectifying’ of human action in the repeated
patterns of technical processes and the material forms of tools and artefacts,
emerges a growing awareness of the hand itself as a kind of proto-technical
object.
While this might also, perhaps, explain the special prominence given to the
image of the hand in many examples of paleolithic cave-painting, the major
implication of this is that the ability to see one’s actions ‘sedimented’ in the solid
residues of technical practices might even have been the stimulus to early
humans’ sensing of the ambiguous subject-object status of the body: that is, in
other words, what Merleau-Ponty has described as our curious status as
integrated ‘body-subjects’. Therefore, moving beyond the idea of the
technological prosthetic that was introduced at the beginning of this discussion:
rather than thinking of technology merely as an extension of the human body, it
may even be true to say that thinking of ourselves as having a body – and
having a choice as to what to do with it – might actually be a consequence of
our prehistorical development of technology.
And perhaps – leaping forward again in historical time – this is what Karl Marx
also had in mind when he described the satisfaction of the manual worker in the
contemplation of an accomplished act of making:
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 309
Keynote lecture
‘read’ an environment in terms of two related narratives of interaction, or what
could be called encounters or ‘collisions’ between people and things. I am
thinking here of the building as both a historical record of interaction and a kind
of future projection, presenting us with the material evidence of both how it
might have been made and also how it might be used. What I am suggesting is
a direct connection between the tectonic articulation of the processes of
construction, and the accumulating traces of occupation left by the users’
repeated patterns and habits of use, while also making a further link to the ways
in which spaces have been consciously designed for use, or what the American
psychologist James J Gibson called the functional ‘affordances’ offered by an
environment. In other words, to paraphrase the thought of the philosopher Paul
Ricoeur, we might say that the hermeneutics of architecture involves a double
process of interpretation: both of the ‘space behind the work’ (understanding the
intentions of its author, designer and maker) and, even more importantly, the
space ‘in front of the work’- understanding the experience that the building
makes possible for its future ‘readers’, users and occupiers (Ricoeur, 1981:
141).
Figure 3: Apparatus for equating motion and consequent visual feedback for actively moving
and passively moved kittens. (After: Hein and Held, 1964: 873)
I use it to illustrate one of the key principles behind the connection between
perception and action. The basic scenario is that the two kittens involved in the
experiment are just a few days old and their brains are developing rapidly –
neural networks are being created in response to the ongoing experience of
movement. The key issue is that normal development involves a coupling
together of visual and bodily information: the brain interprets changing visual
perceptions in relation to bodily movement and this is what enables any
complex organism to navigate effectively in 3-dimensional space. What goes
wrong in this case is that only the kitten on the right can control its own
movements – its feet are touching the floor and as it moves around the
apparatus its visual perception changes in the normal way – the brain can
therefore match these up and the neural circuits can develop normally. The
kitten on the left however has no control over its own bodily movement and its
brain fails to make this same association. When the kittens are released after a
few days inside the apparatus the one on the right can move around normally,
but the one on the left behaves as if there is something wrong with its visual
system: bumping into barriers or stepping off edges and exhibiting a form of
‘experiential blindness’. While the kitten’s eyes are actually working perfectly
well, the problem is that its brain has not developed the capacity to match up its
bodily movements with the associated changes in incoming visual information.
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 310
Keynote lecture
The second piece of neuro-scientific evidence I would like to cite in support of
this vital connection between perception and action comes from the recent
discovery of the so-called mirror-neuron system, first described by Vittorio
Gallese and his colleagues from the University of Parma in Italy. The basic
principle is that the neurons involved in the production of bodily movement are
also active during the observation of movement in other people. In other words,
when I am watching someone performing a particular action I am activating the
same neural network as the one that controls my own performance of same
action. As the philosopher Shaun Gallagher has described it in his book How
the Body Shapes the Mind:
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 311
Keynote lecture
video showing the process of its construction – was to be shown as part of the
exhibition installation within the gallery itself. Of more interest to me personally
was another more subtle detail – apparently less deliberate and more easily
overlooked: on the upper landings of the main stairs a number of partial
footmarks are visible to the attentive visitor – fragments of builders’ boot-prints
cast permanently into the concrete floor. While the power-float machines used
to finish the floors would normally be expected to smooth these over, in this
case the architects have perhaps even encouraged the builders not to be too
careful about ‘covering their tracks’. As these permanent traces of the
construction process appear alongside the more transient footprints left by the
building’s users, they invite us in a modest way to connect how the building was
made to the possibilities of how it might be occupied.
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 312
Keynote lecture
“…it must be said that we understand ourselves only by the long detour
of the signs of humanity deposited in cultural works.” (1981:143)
Bibliography:
Arbib, Michael. (2012) ‘(Why) Should Architects Care about Neuroscience?’ In
Philip Tidwell (ed.) Architecture and Neuroscience: a Tapio Wirkkala - Rut Bryk
Design Reader. Espoo: Tapio Wirkkala Rut Bryk Foundation. pp. 43-75.
Clark, Andy and David Chalmers (1998) ‘The Extended Mind’, Analysis, 58: 7-
19.
Freedberg, David and Vittorio Gallese, (2007) ‘Motion, Emotion and Empathy in
Aesthetic Experience’, in Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol 11, No 5, 197-203.
Gallagher, Shaun (2005) How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Lewis Williams, David (2002) The Mind in the Cave: Consciousness and the
Origins of Art. London: Thames and Hudson.
Luria, Alexander (1981) Language and Cognition. Ed. James V. Wertsch. New
York: Wiley.
Maravita, Angelo and Atsushi Iriki (2004) ‘Tools for the Body (Schema)’, Trends
in Cognitive Sciences, 8(2): 79-86.
Mauss, Marcel (2006 [1935]) ‘Techniques of the Body’. Tr. Ben Brewster, in
Nathan Schlanger (ed.), Techniques, Technology and Civilisation, New York:
Berghahn Books/Durkheim Press. pp. 77-95.
______ (1964) "Eye and Mind" in The Primacy of Perception. Tr. Carleton
Dallery. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. pp. 159-90.
Mithen, Steven (1996) The Prehistory of Mind: A Search for the Origins of Art,
Religion and Science. London: Thames and Hudson.
Pallasma, Juhani (2009) The Thinking Hand: Existential and Embodied Wisdom
in Architecture. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons.
Tallis, Raymond (2003) The Hand: A Philosophical Enquiry into Human Being.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Proceedings of the 6th Annual Architectural Research Symposium in Finland 2014 314
Keynote lecture