Philosoohy and Science. Consciousness
Philosoohy and Science. Consciousness
Giulio Tononi (
)
School of Medicine, Department of Psychiatry, University of Wisconsin–Madison, Madison,
WI 53719, USA
E-mail: giulio.tononi@gmail.com
Owen Flanagan (
)
Department of Philosophy, Duke University, Durham, NC 27708, USA
E-mail: ojf@duke.edu
Philosophy and Science Dialogue: Consciousness 333
now call the computational unconscious or the Freudian unconscious. It looks like
the conscious and the unconscious were woven together at the beginning. By the
time we get to the 17th century and Descartes, the word “consciousness” means
something about the first-person perspective. When Descartes says, “I think,
therefore I am,” what he means by “think” is that he perceives, he doubts, he feels,
etc. It encompasses all the mental states that seem to have phenomenal character or
“what it is like”-ness from the first-person point of view. That’s what
“consciousness” typically means.
What “consciousness” refers to is an entirely different question. Back in ancient
Greece, we have the classic example. If you wake up in the morning and say,
“Look, the morning star,” someone during that time might have informed you that
the morning star is called “Phosphorus.” I might, then, while writing poetry, say
that your eyes are like Phosphorus where I use “Phosphorus” to mean the morning
star. In the evening, I look up at the sky and see the evening star which is called
“Hesperus.” I then write a different poem that says your eyes are like Hesperus, the
evening star. An expert astronomer then comes along and says, “Even though
‘Phosphorus’ means morning star and ‘Hesperus’ means evening star, we’ve
discovered that they are one and same heavenly object. In fact, they are not stars at
all, they both refer to the planet Venus.” This is a nice case because the meanings
of the terms are different and though they seem to refer to two different things, as it
turns out, they refer to one and the same thing. That has lessons for what we are
talking about here.
What we are phenomenally aware of and what “consciousness” has historically
meant is the first-person experience. What “consciousness” refers to and how
consciousness is actually realized is a little bit like the evening star/morning star,
that’s up to experts (like astronomers and scientists) to tell us. That’s not for any
old person to figure out on his or her own.
At the end of the day, there’s a problem, and here’s why the poetry example is
important. If I say in my poem that your eyes are like the evening star and someone
says you could shorten the poem and simply say your eyes are like Venus, then one
could respond that that won’t work because that changes the meaning of the poem.
It changes the meaning even if they refer to the same thing. So, the million-dollar
question is: given that we know what consciousness is first―personally in an
intuitive way (like the way we know about the evening star/morning star and the
way we know water is wet)―how do we learn about its deep structure? That
requires scientific theory.
TONONI: I agree with everything. I will simply add a couple things. First, it is
always useful to remind ourselves that consciousness refers to “subjective
experience”—“what it is like to be.” Having experiences can happen in dreams
just as much as when we are awake. And even the experiences of reflecting hard
334 Giulio Tononi, Owen Flanagan
distinction dissolves. This may be what David Chalmers (and others) are after
when they attempt to make a distinction between the Hesperus-Phosphorus-
Venus case and the consciousness-brain case. It seems that what we mean is what
we’re referring to. Once you bring in the science it almost seems like we’re
changing the topic. Can you help us make progress in this area? Can
consciousness be scientifically explained?
TONONI: First, going back to Chalmers and the hard problem of consciousness,
he acknowledged that it was a good public relations move on his part. This is
what he said in Tucson, Arizona (Chalmers 2014). It was the 300th anniversary of
Leibniz’s Monadology which, among other things, contains a beautiful thought
experiment: Leibniz’ Mill.
Leibniz invites each of us to enter this giant mill with wheels and ropes going
around. It’s a very intricate machine. Now think about your brain. Make
everything in your brain very big so that you can walk into it like Leibniz’ mill.
You will see the axons, the synapses, the dendrites and the cell bodies. You name
it, whatever you want. As you walk around your brain you realize it’s just a giant
machine! When you approach things that way it seems impossibly hard to
Philosophy and Science Dialogue: Consciousness 337
understand how your brain has anything to do with consciousness. If it’s just
mechanical or electro-chemical, why would there be experiences associated with
it? It seems impossible.
Second, in order to make progress, you must go in exactly the opposite
direction. You should not start with the postulated fact that the world is made of
atoms and neurons. Instead you must begin with yourself—you certainly exist
and you are certainly conscious. The model that we are working with is about the
world, not about my consciousness. My consciousness is foundational, it exists
period. But our understanding of physics is a model of the world. It can be a
good model, but it is, nevertheless, a model. This way of seeing things inverts the
problem and, I believe, this is the way to approach consciousness. If you don’t
start in this way you’ll never get anywhere.
Third, by using IIT as an example, let’s consider what it means to explain
something. In what sense is IIT a scientific theory? There are many things one
can ask of a scientific theory in terms of explanation. One is, it must have
theoretical validity and coherence. It needs to be a theory with a few primitives
or principles from which many other things follow. We strive to avoid
explanations that are as long and complex as the phenomenon itself. We know
this intuitively as scientists. We know that the best explanation is the shortest
explanation. The theory working from the fewest principles is good.
You also want this theory to account for a vast array of data based on these few
principles. The classic example in biology is natural selection. That has been
dubbed by Daniel Dennett as the best idea anybody ever had. Rightly so because
natural selection gives us a beautiful and general framework for explaining all of
the many different things on earth that all look impossibly different.
More generally, successful examples in physics involve the ability to take
many different phenomena and show that they boil down to the same thing. The
Hesperus and Phosphorus example is a simple-minded version of this idea. You
have two disparate things, two different stars, but then we learned that one planet
accounts for all the observable phenomena.
Finally, you want to have predictive power. If you have a good theory, not only
do you have relatively few principles to explain many disparate things, you also
make extrapolations. If things are like this, then others things should be like that.
And the more counterintuitive those predictions are the better the theory is. This
is what you want from a good theory.
IIT tries to do all of this. It’s based on a few principles. It explains many
phenomena. It explains why the cerebellum does not generate consciousness
even though it has so many neurons. It explains why you lose consciousness
during sleep even if the brain remains active. It makes predictions. For example,
if IIT is correct, then a brain that is not active yet functional should have
consciousness. Some of these predictions have been tested very roughly, others
338 Giulio Tononi, Owen Flanagan
TONONI: Many people understand the term “physical” differently. In the end, it
has to do with things we can manipulate and observe. One of the important
manipulations is to cut. Common sense has gone a long way by cutting and
observing. This, after all, is what our naïve realist view of the world is based on.
Philosophy and Science Dialogue: Consciousness 339
Beyond this, there are also the general questions involving the metaphysical
and epistemological implications of a scientific theory. I think you say something
about both of these things that involve unfamiliar terminology for philosophers.
Insofar as they are rigorous, they don’t sound right even on your own view. So,
let me give you some examples.
First, you often say the only thing that is real, or the only thing that matters, is
intrinsic existence. Now intrinsic existence, philosophically, usually means
something like existence which has no relational properties whatsoever. But I
think, on your view, you emphasize the claim that the qualitative system has
inputs and outputs. That is, when I have a blue experience there are light waves
being received by my retina that form signals being sent up to my brain to be
computed. When I have an auditory experience, there are sound waves being
received by my ears that also form signals being sent up to my brain to be
computed. That means that the system that has the property of being conscious
has relations with the external world. I don’t want to say that the sound waves
coming in are conscious or that the light is conscious. While I’m happy to say
that the qualitative properties are contained in the system the way IIT suggests, I
think that we’re not really dealing with intrinsic existence in IIT since we’re
dealing with matters of function.
It also looks to me that your metaphysics can sound like transcendental
idealism. It’s almost as if you claim that the only things that exist are subjective
beings and their experiences. There’s no real reason to posit an external world. In
fact, the dream metaphor, which I like, can also function that way. All the work
that you and your team have done on the phenomenology of what we call
dreaming (non-REM and REM2) is well studied and it’s a different kind of
consciousness than wakeful consciousness. So, I think it’s important not to
tamper with these distinctions.
Moreover, we have a general theory about reality (cobbled together from all
the sciences). This then lends itself to an epistemology which tells us how
reliably we’re picking up and detecting what’s out there in the world. I don’t
think we need to tamper with this either—especially not everything at once.
On all our best scientific theories, the universe has been around for 10 billion
years. The cause and effect relations were operating for 10 billion years before
we arrived on the scene. And the world may well be here after we leave. Are you
questioning the physical view of the universe as a system of cause and effect
relationships that existed long before sentient beings ever showed up? We could
say that we’re the only kind of existence that matters. I’m almost certain that for
most of us, we’re the only kind of system that we care about, but that seems to be
a psychological fact about us, not a claim about what reality is.
2
REM—rapid eye movement.
Philosophy and Science Dialogue: Consciousness 341
In your theory, however, all these different features are being addressed
simultaneously and there is potential for confusion and unnecessary conceptual
mistakes.
TONONI: I can extract two or three main criticisms from what you said. One,
leaving aside metaphysics and epistemology, is the natural criticism of
overreaching. I might respond by saying that if a theory of consciousness has any
pretense of being in the right direction then necessarily it will have very
far-reaching impact. It’s the nature of the beast. Schopenhauer called it the
world-knot because it’s at the center of everything. If consciousness turns out to
be, say, intrinsic existence as defined by IIT then it’s going to change our views
about what it means to know about the world. It will change our view about what
is worth treating as an entity that has value in and of itself versus an entity that
only has functional value. I think if it is a good theory of consciousness it will
necessarily have an impact on these things. Having said that, before trying to
make these connections one must rigorously and carefully develop the theory
along with its mathematics.
The second important point you raised is in essence that IIT may ground a
solipsistic nightmare. I will say with no hesitation that there is a real world “out
there.” I don’t have the slightest doubt about it. But the way to look at it is,
perhaps, different. One way to think about it is that we always have a model of
how the world is. There is the common-sense model of rocks and trees and there
is the scientific model of rocks and trees. We are constantly trying to integrate
these models of the world but the scientific model is becoming increasingly
difficult to understand. I look at you and I know that you have a brain that is
responsible for the way you are looking at me. 2000 years ago, I didn’t know that
and I would have understood you differently. All of this knowledge has been
incorporated into the scientific model.
Pure solipsism will say that it’s all just a dream. It is a position that is
impossible to prove wrong. But, at the same time, it doesn’t make sense.
Consider all the regularities that are in my experience. Does it happen according
to rules in my dream which have no further explanations? It will be predictively
useless. It will explain nothing. Instead, if there is a world outside of myself
which is made of stuff that follow certain rules then the scientific model is a good
model—a powerful one with excellent predictive resources.
But it’s still possible that cause-effect power is the foundation for everything
and, on this theory, we can tell ourselves a story that accounts for both the
regularities in my flow of experiences, my own “movie,” and also for the
regularities in the “movie itself.” That’s the divide between intrinsic and extrinsic
existence. It is a realist position. There is a world. The panpsychist version of IIT
would say, the world is constituted of things that exist intrinsically—lots of
342 Giulio Tononi, Owen Flanagan
various small entities. Everything that exists, exists intrinsically. If they enter
particular relationships, bigger entities come to exist intrinsically. They can get as
big as us. For these entities, all the other entities that exist intrinsically start to
exist extrinsically in the shape of trees, people, and so on. It is realist, but you
must keep in mind that it’s a model.
FLANANGAN: I agree with everything you said. I’m still going to resist the
use of “intrinsic” and the way you use it may not be as helpful as you think
since the entities you posit still seem to be constituted by relations. I agree that
the right scientific theory will change everything. It changes our metaphysics,
epistemology, and ethics. But I am concerned that because everything changes so
radically, it can easily become difficult to keep track of the relevant issues in
clear ways.
TONONI: Intrinsic in IIT means, in line with the original use of the term in
Latin, “from the inside, i.e. from the perspective of the entity itself.” It does not
mean independent of everything external, as in many philosophical writings.
I will add one thing. At the end of your second lecture, I showed a few slides
in which we have these animats3 and they interact with a simple environment.
Everything is simulated. Nevertheless, the animats increased their level of φ (or
their level of consciousness) by adapting to regularities in their environment in
order to survive. This is useful because it offers us the beginnings of a
perspective on why it might be that consciousness evolved. This suggests that
there is an explanation for why ceteris paribus there is a trend towards
consciousness. With limited resources, it pays to do things in an integrated way.
If consciousness, as IIT claims, is integrated information, then everything fits
nicely together.
The other thing we are working on related to epistemology is the notion of
matching. If you exist as a set of complicated forms that evolved over time, these
forms must be adapted to the environment such that you do the right things at the
right time. So, there must be some correspondence between the internal forms
and the external causal structure of the world. This correspondence can be
measured mathematically and is always relative to the conscious entity. There is
no one way for the world to be represented. It is essentially relative to how I
categorize it according to the kind of consciousness I have. It’s an interesting
story and it’s only beginning. While meaning is all internal, like the concepts
allied with the morning star and the evening star, it nevertheless refers to things
out there. This reference relation is captured by the notion of “matching” that we
are working out mathematically. It gives us another way of approaching
3
To see these animats in action, see http://integratedinformationtheory.org/animats.html.
Philosophy and Science Dialogue: Consciousness 343
Can we build conscious machines? What is it, if anything, that is special about
humans?
TONONI: You can build conscious machines. If IIT is correct then as long as a
machine satisfies the relevant principles it will be conscious. The problem is the
machines we are currently building are most likely not conscious. At most they
will amount to one bit of conscious dust. This is because of their nature as Turing
Machines. Everything goes through an ALU (Arithmetic Logic Unit) and that is
not, from what we can tell, a good architecture to have a system that has a high φ
value. Indeed, you can simulate something with very high φ without having any
φ. You can make a Turing Machine that does everything you can do. It simulates
everything perfectly. It simulates someone who has consciousness and high φ.
Yet, it’s implemented in such a way that it will have no φ.
In principle, we could build a conscious machine that is not made of neurons.
It’s unclear right now how close such a conscious machine would be in terms of
its similarity to a network of neurons, but there is no principled reason why a
silicon-based system (like a neuromorphic computer) could not be conscious.
The functionalist approach says that as long as you reproduce the function of
something, then there’s nothing else to be said. This is very common in
philosophy and in science. We study ourselves in terms of machines and every
neurophysiologist will tell you that once they understand how you go from input
to output with all the internal processing steps, there’s nothing more to
understand. That is absolutely false in IIT. If you did that for the brain, if you
knew exactly what happens in every neuron at every time step, you may be able
to predict what the brain does, but you would, in some sense, understand nothing.
You would miss what I call the elephant in the brain—consciousness! You would
have no idea that, while the whole brain is doing this, in some parts of the brain
there are experiences and in other parts things are going on, but there are no
experiences. You would miss the most important thing about the brain.
344 Giulio Tononi, Owen Flanagan
TONONI: Consider the outside world as a task domain—you must carry out
certain tasks in the world in order to survive. There are some tasks that are, by
nature, rather modular. Certain forms of physical movement, for example, can be
easily modularized. Other tasks can’t be broken down or analyzed in this way.
When you are faced with processing the causal structure of the world as an
organism, some aspects of that causal structure can be modularized. Other
aspects are not of this nature. Consciousness is what you need, given constraints
on the number of available processing units, to deal with the most complex and
integrated parts of the world. Without certain levels of integration, you will not
be able to effectively work with these parts of the world. These parts of the world
are integrated causally across time. Instead, things that can be dealt with in a
modular manner, like ensuring that a muscle doesn’t always stretch, can devolve
into an unconscious localized module that does its job very well. In fact, it does it
better if it’s not taking care of all kinds of other tasks at the same time.
So in some sense the prediction would be that for all of those tasks that can be
modularized, evolution will be able to construct mechanisms that successfully
perform the relevant tasks without developing consciousness. When you are
trying to take in regularities that work over large spatiotemporal scales, then
evolution will be forced to develop something like consciousness.
TONONI: One of Lakoff’s most famous books is Women, Fire, and Dangerous
Things (Lakoff 1990). What is consciousness most like of these three?
If you remember, IIT makes a distinction between low and high-level concepts,
where a concept is a cause-effect repertoire within a conceptual structure. This
may sound like a new language, but it’s interesting because it is an attempt to put
the perceptual and the conceptual together. A high-level concept is what is
usually called an invariant or an abstraction. A face can be a high-level concept
because it is a disjunction of many lower-level conjunctions. Much of our interest
in consciousness derives from high-level concepts that makes language possible.
Describing the details of a visual scene, pixel by pixel, is useless. But saying
there is a person there is very useful. The concept of a person, however, is a
high-level abstraction. One important thing about this that may seem trivial is
this: If we do have high level concepts in our brain (as we know we do) that
develop in a certain way through plasticity over the course of evolutionary
development, then anything more that you learn (including a beautiful poetic
metaphor) is going to have to be built on the basis of stuff you already have.
346 Giulio Tononi, Owen Flanagan
FLANAGAN: A quick addition to that. Lakoff and Johnson talk about metaphors
we live by (Lakoff and Johnson 2003). The example of one’s beloved, the
brightness of her eyes, is a common cross-cultural metaphor. It’s ubiquitous. Of
course, the fact that we live by conceptual structures that operate at the
metaphorical level doesn’t mean that science is best done by using metaphors,
and that relates to my suggestion that the metaphor of consciousness of being
like a dream doesn’t quite work. The dream phenomenology that I have is
different from the phenomenology I have when I am awake. I don’t want to
absorb it all into one.
FLANAGAN: It’s certainly true that the problem of consciousness has been
around for a long time. Humans are very selfish about time intervals. We want
big scientific problems solved by next Thursday in our lab. So, I admit, the
problem of consciousness is difficult. The fact that a problem has a history that is
centuries (or even millennia) old, given that the universe has been around for 14
billion years, doesn’t seem to be very long.
There are two kinds of mysterians I defined back in the 1990s. One is an “old”
or traditional mysterian—they are dualists. They will hold that you’ll never be
able to solve the consciousness brain problem physically because the mind is not
a physical thing. You can’t absorb the mind into a physical theory because it’s
simply not a physical thing! It will mean that the nature of consciousness will
Philosophy and Science Dialogue: Consciousness 347
References
Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chalmers, D. 2014. The Hard Problem of Consciousness: 342 Years On. Toward a Science of
Consciousness. Tucson, Arizona: Center for Consciousness Studies, University of Arizona.
Flanagan, O. 1992. Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Flanagan, O. 2007. The Really Hard Problem: Meaning in a Material World. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Lakoff, G. 1990. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal About the
Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. 2003. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Logothetis, N., & Schall, J. 1990. “Binocular Motion Rivalry in Macaque monkeys: Eye
Dominance and Tracking Eye Movements.” Vision Research 30.10: 1409–19.
McGinn, C. 2000. The Mysterious Flame: Conscious Minds in a Material World. New York:
Basic Books.
Strawson, G. 2015. “Consciousness Myth.” The Times Literary Supplement, February 25.
Tononi, G., Boly, M., Massimini, M., & Koch, C. 2016. “Integrated Information Theory: From
Consciousness to Its Physical Substrate.” Nature Reviews: Neuroscience 17: 450–61.