The Autonomy Myth. A Theory of Dependency (Martha Fineman)
The Autonomy Myth. A Theory of Dependency (Martha Fineman)
BERTSON FIN
37131 043 384 619
CL NY Central
LAW/SOCIOLOGY/FEMINIST THEORY $25.95
£17.95
$39.95 CAN
'H
f
V
The Autonomy Myth
\
\ '
■r
\
A Theory of Dependency
NEW YORK
LONDON
© 2004 by Martha Albertson Fineman
All rights reserved.
No part of this book may be reproduced, in any form,
without written permission from the publisher.
Published in the United States by The New Press, New York, 2004
Distributed by W. W. Norton & Company, Inc., New York
Fineman, Martha.
The autonomy myth : a theory of dependency /
Martha Albertson Fineman.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 1-56584-760-1 (he)
1. United States—Social policy—1993- 2. Family policy—
United States. 3. Autonomy (Philosophy)—United States.
4. Social justice—United States. 5. Equality—United States.
I. Title.
HN59.2.F56 2004
361.610973 dc2i 2003051302
The New Press, 38 Greene Street, 4th floor, New York, NY 10013
www.thenewpress.com
Composition by dix!
10 987654321
A
Acknowledgments ix
Preface xi
Introduction xiii
PART ONE
Foundational Myths: Autonomy, Dependency,
Chapter One
Chapter Two
Dependency and Social Debt: Cracking the
Foundational Myths 31
I. Introduction 31
II. The Rhetoric of Dependence and Independence 33
III. Dependency and Choice 40
IV The Dependency Deficit—A Society in Default 44
V The Rhetoric of Subsidy and Self-Sufficiency 49
VI. Conclusion 33
VI CONTENTS
«
PART TWO
Institutionalizing Autonomy 55
Existing Societal Arrangements 57
Chapter Three
The Family in the Rhetoric of Civil Society—
Privileging Marriage 7\
I. Introduction 7\
II. Defining the Problem—The Civil Societarian
Perspective 7g
III. Family Function and Family Form—
Collapsing the Distinction 79
IV Regulating the Family—Moral Justification and
Beyond gj
V Poverty and Well-Being gg
Chapter Four
Why Marriage? gg
I. Introduction gg
II. The Many Meanings of Marriage 97
III. The I .aw of Marriage ] Qg
IV Defining the Family j 1q
V Marriage in Context \ jg
VI. Conclusion j 1g
Chapter Five
The Future of Marriage \gj
I. Introduction 121
II. “Man and Wife”—From Protected to Partnered 124
III. Backlash * * 1 2q
IV Rethinking the Relationship of State to Marriage—
A Thought Experiment '' 133
V Outside of Contract > 13g
VI. Conclusion ' 1
CONTENTS VII
r
PART THREE
Feminist Critiques of the Family 143
Equality and Family 145
Chapter Six
Feminism and the Family: Implementing Equality,
Achieving Autonomy 156
I. Introduction 156
II. The Wake of Feminist Family Law Reform 166
III. The Future of Family Reform 175
IV Conclusion 180
Chapter Seven
Mothering in a Gender-Neutral World 182
I. Introduction 182
II. Valuing Care 188
III. Fatherhood 195
IV Conclusion 202
PART FOUR
The Autonomous Individual and the
Chapter Eight
Recasting the Social Contract 218
I. The Metaphoric Social Contract:
Ordering the Public, Defining the Private 218
II. The Social Contract—The (Mis)use of the
Private Family 228
III. Taking Change into Account: Rethinking the
Social Contract 236
IV Social Contract in Action 237
V Conclusion 239
VIII CONTENTS
Chapter Nine
The Tentative Workplace 241
I. Introduction 241
II. The Tenuous Workplace 244
III. Work and Social Goods 249
IV Unions, Equity, and Market Distribution of
Social Goods 252
V Wealth and Entitlement 255
VI. Right to Work/Equality of Opportunity 259
Chapter Ten
The Tenable State 263
I. Structuring State and Society 263
II. Ideology and Politics 264
III. Posing the Philosophy for an Active State 269
IV The Politics of Substantive Equality 275
V Historical Roots for a More Substantive Equality 278
VI. International Norms 280
VII. Forging a More Just Social Contract 284
Postscript
What Place for Family Privacy? 292
I. Privacies 295
II. Limitations of Privacy 299
III. Revisioning Privacy 300
IV Autonomy for Family Functioning 302
V Conclusion 307
v
\
\
Acknowledgments
AV.
±. s a preliminary matter, I want to thank all the people (too
numerous to mention) who questioned my ideas about depen¬
dency and encouraged me to expand them after the publication
of The Neutered Mother, the Sexual Family, and Other Twentieth Century
Tragedies (Routledge, 1995). Their interest and probing provided
the initial incentive to develop a theory of dependency and col¬
lective responsibility.
The wonderful students who worked on this project as it was
transformed from miscellaneous articles and drafts into a
“proper book” deserve special thanks: Sarah Brady, Homa
Dashtaki, Victoria Hadfield, Joanne Roman, and, in its very
final (and very hectic) stage, Luke Zachary Fenchel. Many peo¬
ple commented on early drafts of this book. In this regard 1 am
particularly indebted to: Terence Dougherty, Jack Jackson,
Douglas A. Kysar, Risa Lieberwitz, Benjamin Meier, Adam
Romero, and Teemu Ruskola.
t
\
Preface
with which many in the United States and most of the world dis¬
agreed. The debates about the topics of concern in this book—
need and dependency, families and state, welfare and the
dimensions of the social contract—have been largely muted,
victims of a war mentality that defines the threats to the United
States as external, terroristic, and violent. But these problems
remain. Unaddressed, they will continue to undermine the
health and general well-being of the United States, even as they
are displaced in our national consciousness by more dramatic
concerns.
The issues surrounding dependency remain constant, a part
of everyday reality for many who struggle to survive in America
and in the world. Dependency has not disappeared; it may even
have been exacerbated by the “war” against terrorism that we
now wage. Publication of this book at this time is undertaken
with that realization in mind.
M.L.A.F.
Ithaca, New York
Introduction
T-L his book examines some of the core myths of American so¬
ciety as they are interwoven through political rhetoric and pop¬
ular ideology at the beginning of the twenty-first century. One
of its major premises is that our particular way of thinking
about the desirability and attainability of autonomy for individ¬
uals and families has seriously limited the ways in which we
think about equality. Ideas about individual autonomy and self-
sufficiency create this limitation, as do corresponding institu¬
tional arrangements that support privatization and the market
as an absolute good and governmental action and regulation as
presumptively bad. One consequence of this has been the con¬
ceptual separation of the family from other societal institutions
and the assignment to it of primary responsibility for the de¬
pendency of those deemed not autonomous and independent.
Contrary to this trend, I argue for the adoption of an inter-
generational and cross-institutional notion of collective respon
sibility for dependency. In doing so, I examine the rhetorical and
xrv INTRODUCTION
Chapter ten serves as the conclusion for the book, making the
argument that there is a need for a responsive state, a state with
which to address the dilemmas presented by the changes in
other institutions in regard to dependency. In this chapter, I ad¬
dress the state in its relation to societal institutions as well as its
relation to the individual.
Defining the appropriate relationship among the state, socie¬
tal institutions, and individual citizens is important for several
reasons. In the first instance, American foundational documents
such as the Constitution are understood as conferring limits on
state authority, serving to establish a space for citizen freedom
and autonomy. This dimension of the relationship of the state to
the individual is of particular relevance in today’s political cli¬
mate, in which many are suspicious of governmental interven¬
tion into private matters.
The rhetoric of economics, which is increasingly the lan¬
guage of government and policy-making, warns us that society
and its market institutions operate efficiently only when unregu¬
lated individuals are free to act to maximize their interests.
Competition produces the best results for all, as the inefficient,
and therefore “inferior,” are swept away in a free market free-
for-all.
But there are also affirmative aspects to the historic relation¬
ship between state and individual—protections offered by the
state against arbitrary actions on'the«part of governments and
fellow citizens in some contexts. Theories about law and justice
compete with “scientific” economic concepts in an effort to es¬
tablish guidelines for assessing which formal governmental ac¬
tions affecting individual behavior fnay be condemned as
inappropriate intervention, as contrasted with necessary regula-
INTRODUCTION XXIII
\
The Autonomy Myth
I
» 4
\
Part One
Foundational Myths:
Autonomy, Dependency,
and Social Debt
«
1
A Dystopian Fantasy
what we should do, but to have us think about how much con¬
text does matter for all of us. We do not begin our lives in equal
circumstances. We begin in unequal ones. Society’s winners and
losers become so in some large part because of benefits and
privileges or disadvantages and burdens conferred by family po¬
sition in a society with extreme and unequal distribution of so¬
cial and economic goods. In such a society, the approach to a
resolution to this type of inequality is not found in simplistic and
hypothetical prescriptions or ideological placebos of independ¬
ence, autonomy, and self-sufficiency.
Chapter One
A
Ji litany of terms accompanies our approach in the
United States to policy-making regarding family and poverty.
These terms have mythic dimensions. As defined in The New
Webster’s Encyclopedic Dictionary of the English Language, three con¬
cepts are particularly relevant to this book:
Autonomy: i) independence or freedom, as of the will or
one’s actions. 2) the condition of being autonomous; self-
government or the right of self-government: independence.
Independence: 1) not influenced or controlled by other;
thinking or acting for oneself. 2) not depending or contingent
upon something else. 3) not relying on another for aid or sup¬
port. 4) refusing to be under obligation to others. 5) possessing a
competence: financially independent. . .
Self-sufficiency: 1) able to , supply one’s . . . own needs
without external assistance. 2) having extreme confidence in
one’s own resources or powers.
These concepts are strung together, representing comple-
8 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
I. INTRODUCTION
America.
12 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
«
B. Mythical Politics
The tendency of political myths to evade self-conscious recon¬
sideration by each new generation is unfortunate. Times and
circumstances change and evolve, sometimes dramatically.
When societal change is sweeping and profound, it affects aspi¬
rations and expectations as well as behavior. In the wake of
change it may be that certain foundational myths need adjust¬
ment in order to be made compatible with contemporary cir¬
cumstances and situations. Altered social realities may require
the explication of a more nuanced understanding of a cher¬
ished national characteristic or value. It is also sometimes the
case that changing contexts and circumstances will cast histori-
i6 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
«
ft
cally compatible foundational aspirations in tension with one
another.32 In such a case, there is also a need for realignment in
order to regain a sense of consistency among cherished objec¬
tives, a reconsideration of the very nature of our goals and val¬
ues and the weights historically conferred upon each in relation
to others.
Such a project would require express consideration of the na¬
ture and function of the current versions of our foundational
myths because they do not stand alone and are not easily identi¬
fiable. Political myths operate in extremely complex cultural
contexts and are usually embedded and interwoven into “the
framework of a general ideology,” combined with philosophy,
history, and science.33 As a result, they are difficult to examine
critically, as they are only one element of a series of mutually
supporting points of view.34 Change in understanding is slow.
However, the excavation and reevaluation of the current ver¬
sions of our political myths is a crucial project because such
myths may be used rhetorically to bolster positions that are fun¬
damentally incompatible with healthy social programs. Recon¬
sideration is important because, while myths can be used for
many, even contradictory purposes, they tend to operate in a
conservative manner. They are more often used to preserve the
status quo than to inspire change.35
While myths tend to support conservative policies, they can
be used progressively and actively. Political myths can be power¬
ful tools in forging many types of social policy. In our current
ideological climate, however, they are most often wielded by
those in power, who argue for curtailment of emerging family
forms, as well as of progressive welfare policies perceived to be
undesirable because they support those forms. By evoking the
language of foundational myths—words such as “autonomy,”
“independence,” “justice,” and “liberty”—political players may
shield a very radical agenda from societal scrutiny. When dis-
.4*
FOUNDATIONAL MYTHS
B. Autonomy
Autonomy is indisputably important in our constellation of
foundational myths, perhaps more centrally so today than ever.
However, in recent years the myth of autonomy has become
opaque and illusive. This is partly because this myth does not
encompass only one situation or circumstance where we set up
autonomy as a paramount objective, but confuses and speaks in¬
terchangeably about several different aspects of the concept.
Autonomy is the term we use when describing the relationship
between the individual and the state. Autonomy in this regard is
individual freedom from state intervention and regulation, the
ability to order one’s activities independent of state dictates. In
particular, we think of an economically self-sufficient individual
as autonomous in relation to society and its institutions.
EXPLORING FOUNDATIONAL MYTHS 21
n
C. Manifesting Equality
Equality guarantees that the same rules-will apply to us all, un¬
influenced by our station or status in life. Of course, the original
American notion of equality applied oply to white, male, and
EXPLORING FOUN-DATIONAL MYTHS 23
r
tional concepts that set out further expectations for the citizen in
regard to the state, as well as ordering the relationships among
diverse societal institutions, such as the family and the market.
In fact, these other foundational concepts have had a profound
effect on the way in which equality has been understood histori¬
cally, actually shaping the course and direction of its legal his¬
tory and limiting the potential scope of the concept. Paramount
among the limiting values in this regard are contemporary ideas
about individual freedom, which is reduced to the idea of au¬
tonomy with its complementary components of individual inde¬
pendence and self-sufficiency.
ft
flicting and incompatible ways. These concepts often become
battle cries for diverse political movements.40 Their amorphous,
overarching, and imprecise nature means that they can be used
simultaneously by those holding disparate positions in regard to
any proposal.41
The foundational myth of individual autonomy can be un¬
derstood to mandate that there be “equality of opportunity” so
that each individual can succeed or fail according to her or his
own merits and initiative. But it is not clear exactly what equal¬
ity of opportunity might entail in the way of either individual or
regulatory effort and action. For example, equal opportunity
can be used to justify the institutional creation of an affirmative
action program to “equalize” the possibilities for people who are
members of historically excluded groups, while simultaneously
serving as a rallying cry for those resisting such schemes because
they give members of certain groups an “unequal advantage.”
The first group would be arguing that their individual aspira¬
tion for autonomy is frustrated and the whole ideal twisted if ex¬
isting systems of privilege and power prevent them from
competing on equal footing with those who have not been his¬
torically excluded. Those resisting affirmative action would
argue, in contrast, that “special” treatment for some in society
compromises the autonomy of others and is a “perversion” of
the principles of independence and self-sufficiency, signaling
the very end of meritocracy.
Likewise, one may assume that a modern marriage is a “part¬
nership” and that both parties should be treated equally should
the marriage end in divorce. However, there are many different
interpretations of “equal” treatment in such contexts. One
could argue that equal treatment means the family assets should
be divided in half, which would constitute a version of equal
treatment at the moment of divorce, and that there should be no
ongoing entitlement to the future' wages of the primary wage
earner.
EXPLORING FO UN DATIONAL MYTHS 27
B. Rethinking Autonomy
The very terms of autonomy—as exemplified by economic in¬
dependence and a detached notion of self-sufficiency—might
well be redefined or reimagined in the public mind. Indepen¬
dence is not the same as being unattached. Independence from
subsidy and support is not attainable, nor is it desirable; we want
and need the webs of economic and social relationships that sus¬
tain us.42 A different understanding''of autonomy and what it en¬
tails is needed. It is not beyond our current ability to imagine a
new concept of autonomy, one that recognizes that the individ¬
ual lives within a variety of contexts and is dependent upon
them. ;
Certainly popular culture seems open to the idea. This can be
EXPLORING F 041 N D,A TIONAL MYTHS
29
I. INTRODUCTION
A. “Inevitable”and “Derivative”Dependency
It is puzzling, as well as paradoxical, that the term dependency
should have such negative connotations. Far from being patho-
DEPENDENCY aAND SOCIAL DEBT 35
A. Deficit
Unfortunately, in many situations, peither the economic nor the
structural supports for caretaking are adequate. Within families,
DEPENDENCY AND SOCIAL DEBT 45
A . „
r
caretaking work is unpaid, expected to be gratuitously and un¬
complainingly supplied. Even when non-family members, such
as nannies or nurses, supply caretaking labor, the family remains
primarily responsible for the care. Furthering the assumption
that this type of work is not valuable, the wages are supplied
from family funds, not through social subsidies, ensuring that
the pay remains low.24
In some atypical instances, employers offer a more communal
approach to caretaking or the state assumes some responsibility,
such as with company-sponsored child care or home health aids
provided by public funds. However, such nonfamily assistance is
not compelled (and in fact is contradicted) by our understanding
of who is responsible for dependency. This sort of assistance is
viewed as “generous,” an unexpected benefit supplementing the
primary responsibility of the family.
If we measure success by poverty statistics, it seems clear that
many families are failing in their socially assigned task as the
repository for dependency. Many caretakers and their depend¬
ents find themselves impoverished or severely economically
compromised even if they are operating within the context of a
marital family. Suzanne W. Helburn and Barbara R. Bergmann
illustrate that even with both parents working full-time at mini¬
mum wage, taking into consideration the required poverty-line
expenditures, they are unable to pay the cost of licensed child
care.25 As can be expected, single working mothers have an even
more difficult time making ends meet and providing for child
care than families with two adults present.26
For others, divorce or the death of a primary wage earner can
prompt an economic freefall into poverty. Some women in these
situations are in worse positions than women who remain single,
since they have cut back on their career commitments as a result
of the partnership, to raise children or to allow the partner to
advance his career.27
Even families that “conform,” in that they are both intact and
46 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
r
This dual and complementary responsibility is consistent
with our deeply held beliefs about how rights and obligations
are accrued and imposed in a just society: societal obligations
have both an individual and a collective dimension. Certain
members of society may volunteer, be recruited, or even be
drafted for service, but they have a right to be compensated for
their services from collective resources. They also have a right to
the necessary tools to perform their assigned tasks and to guar¬
antees that they will be protected by rules and policies that facil¬
itate their performance. Caretakers should have the same right
to have their society-preserving labor supported and facilitated.
Provision of the means for their task should be considered the
responsibility of the collective society.
holds or the potential value their endeavors have for the larger
society. Sometimes the benefits we receive are public and finan¬
cial, such as direct governmental transfer programs to certain
individuals or business entities, such as farmers or sugar grow¬
ers.38 Public subsidies can also be indirect, such as the benefits
given in tax policy.39 Private economic subsidy systems work in
the forms of foundations, religions, and charities.
A. Types of Subsidy
Typically, a subsidy is thought of as the provision of monetary
or economic assistance. However, a subsidy can also be deliv¬
ered through the organization of social structures and norms
that create and enforce expectations. A subsidy can also be non¬
monetary, such as the subsidy provided by the uncompensated
labor of others in caring for us and our dependency needs as in¬
dividuals, as well as members of a larger dependent society. Tak¬
ing this observation into account, along with the ideas of
inevitable and derivative dependency, it seems obvious that we
must conclude that subsidy is also universal. We all exist in con¬
texts and relationships, in social and cultural institutions, such as
families, which facilitate, support, and subsidize us and our en¬
deavors.
In complex modern societies no one is self-sufficient, either
economically or socially. Whether the subsidies we receive are fi¬
nancial (such as governmental transfer programs or favorable
tax policy) or nonmonetary (such as the uncompensated labor of
others in caring for us and our needs), we all live subsidized lives.
In fact, all of us receive both (orms of subsidy during our
lives. 1 hose who adhere to the myths.'of autonomy and inde¬
pendence must recognize that the uncompensated labor of
caretakers is an unrecognized subsidy, not only to the individu¬
als who directly receive it but, more significandy, to the entire so¬
ciety. yV
DEPENDENCY AND SOCIAL DEBT
* • . 51
VI. CONCLUSION
\
Part Two
Institutionalizing Autonomy
«
%
Existing Societal Arrangements
SOCIETY
SOCIETY
(A
C
o
3
ra
'o
o
(A
(A
<
re
■*-»
c
3
Philanthropy
Diagram II. The Family depicted in this diagram is the egalitarian fam¬
ily the modern version of the marital arrangement in which Husband
and Wife are viewed as equals and the Child has an elevated, if some¬
what subservient, position. Within the larger society, the Family coex¬
ists with market and nonmarket institutions, some having greater
impact on the family than others. Voluntary and private institutions,
such as religion, can and do have effects on specific, individual Family
units, but it is the more structured and dominant institutions the ones
we cannot avoid or opt out of that must be part of a comprehensive
consideration of the Family and its place in society. Here I am referring
to the relationship between Family and;S.tate, but later chapters ad¬
dress the market, which is most certainly a dominant societal institu¬
tion with which the Family must deal. The line drawn around the Family
is the demarcation of family privacy, which sets the entity apart from
other societal institutions. It is porous ,since, in the egalitarian family, the
state will intervene to prevent abuse or neglect. In the common-law ver¬
sion of the Family, the privacy line would be more intact.
EXISTING SOCIETAL ARRANGEMENTS 63
tr
space that is occupied by organizations such as religious or phil¬
anthropic entities. However, in this book I am concerned with
those institutions that are clearly contained within and defined
by the state. It is those institutions that are correctly understood
as “coercively constituted,” in that they are creatures of the
state. While law may affect voluntary entities, it is those institu¬
tions, such as the family and the market, that are actually cre¬
ated and constituted as coherent institutions through law. Their
very existence as objects of state regulatory concern comes
into being through law: it is law that gives them consequence
and meaning even outside of the wishes or demands of their
members.
Of course, these various state-constructed entities may spill
over into the voluntary field. There is a well-developed sense of
family in religion, for example. So, too, individuals and groups
outside of the regulated space may clamor for entry into it, will¬
ing to trade the freedom of nonlegal status for the benefits of the
legal and privileged institutional form. Such overlapping inter¬
est on the part of the coercive and voluntary realms in regard to
an entity such as the family might provide an occasion for ten¬
sion, even for transformation or adjustment in state rules. In this
way these coercive institutions are potentially dynamic in na¬
ture. The state has the authority and power to monitor (or im¬
pede) their transformations.
If this model of the family/state relationship is accurate, it
has important implications for public policy. In the first instance,
it indicates that the family’s relationship to the state is not fixed
or static. State policies can profoundly affect the form and func¬
tioning of the family. Correspondingly, if the family is con¬
structed through interaction with the state and society, the
family cannot be posited as a “natural entity with a form that is
constant over time and culture. Nor can a preferred family for m
be assumed essential to family functioning, such as caring for
children or providing emotional and psychological support lor
64 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
group goals.”3
SOCIETY
Philanthropy
SOCIETY
Philanthropy
I. INTRODUCTION
During the past generation, our families have come under intense
pressure, and many have crumbled. Neighborhood and commu¬
nity ties have frayed. Many of our streets and public spaces have
become unsafe. Our public schools are mediocre for most stu¬
dents, and catastrophic failures for many. Our character-forming
institutions are enfeebled. Much of our popular culture is vulgar,
violent, and mindless. Much of our public square is coarse and
uncivil. Political participation is at depressed levels last seen in the
1920’s. Public trust in our leaders and institutions has plunged.9
focusing only on the first year or two after divorce.70 She asserts
that over a longer time frame, the majority of children from di¬
vorced homes “looked a lot like their contemporaries from non-
divorced homes.”71
It may also be that younger scholars, not as tied to the institu¬
tion of marriage as their elders, might look with a more critical
eye on existing gloom-and-doom material.
In an interesting paper examining the causal basis of commu¬
nitarian family values (and Galston’s work in particular), Andrew
Lister concludes that the connection between family structure
and negative outcomes is far from clear and documents the ob¬
stacles that stand in the way of gathering evidence on this rela¬
tionship.72 For example, mere associations, such as that between
single-parent families and poor school performance, do not tell
us very much about causation.73 Children in two-parent families
may graduate from high school at a higher rate, but children liv¬
ing in one-parent households are less likely to have college-
educated parents and are more likely to be black or Hispanic
(hence subject to discrimination, language barriers, and rela¬
tively diminished pools of family resources available for educa¬
tion).74 If such factors are not taken into account, it is impossible
to determine how much of the difference in school achievement
is due to family structure and how much to other parental char¬
acteristics.75 Lister concludes that it is misleading to focus our de¬
bate on scientific evidence about the effects of family structure
on children’s well-being and suggests that we directly consider
the moral balancing involved in setting family policy.76
In regard to moral issues, feminists raise additional points of
contention that are normative in natu're, reflecting concern for
the historic role of marriage in the subordination of women.
Professor Iris Marion Young has questioned Galston’s exclusive
focus on children, noting that .a preference for marriage
“amounts to calling for mothers to'depend on men to keep them
THE FAMILY IP*. CIVIL SOCIETY 87
r
These are the questions to which I would urge the civil soci-
etarians to turn their attention. The problem with society is not
that marriage is in trouble. The real crisis is that we expect mar¬
riage to be able to compensate for the inequality created by and
within our other institutions.
\
Chapter Four
Why Marriage?
I. INTRODUCTION
v
WHY MARRIAGE? 97
A . ^
A. Individual Meanings
Of course, today both individuals and society know that mar¬
riage constitutes a legal relationship. The law defines some
meanings of marriage for individuals. It is also an exclusive, and
excluding, institution—not everyone can enter. Through law,
the state establishes uniform standards for marriage, specifying
who may marry whom and what formalities must be observed.
In addition, law sets out the consequences of marriage at the
dissolution of the relationship, be it by death or divorce. These
consequences have become clear and predictable to lawyers and
others administering the system.1
However, making predictions about the ultimate content and
conduct of any given ongoing marriage is far from a clear-cut
task. Within the boundaries establishing entry into and exit from
the institution, individuals are free to create a variety of mean¬
ings of marriage for themselves. This is because society, through
its laws, has historically covered existing marriage relationships
with a shroud of “privacy,” shielding them from direct state mi¬
cromanagement and supervision, and thus allowing the conduct
of individual marriages to vary widely. This concept of privacy
still affects the way we think about the relationship between the
state and the marital family.
For ongoing marriages, the norms for state/family relations
are those of nonintervention and minimal regulation. There are
exceptions to this norm of privacy, but most of them are fairly
recent innovations, such as increased legal recognition of and
response to domestic abuse and neglect, and removal of the
common-law interspousal tort immunity, which precluded one
spouse from recovering from the other for negligendy inflicted
injuries.2 Other regulatory interventions into ongoing family re¬
lationships, such as the rules that preclude spousal testimony in
THE AUTONOMY MYTH
98
B. Societal Meanings
The contemporary meaning of marriage is no easier to pin
down and ascertain if we look at it from a societal, rather than
IOO THE AUTONOMY MYTH
from 1835 that there was “no other country in the world where
the tie of marriage is more highly or worthily appreciated” and
that “the American derives from his own home that love or order
which he afterwards carries with him into public affairs” are used
to bolster the connection between marriage and freedom.12
These arguments conflate marriage and family (and also
virtue, morality, and marriage). Having done so, they fail to rec¬
ognize that even if marriage was central in the nineteenth cen¬
tury, it may not be so today. Perhaps in the nineteenth century,
the institution of marriage was considered central in discussions
about the nature of “domestic habits” as a “ ‘necessary precon¬
dition’ for maintaining the constitutional Republic,”13 but those
who merely reiterate ancient platitudes do not adequately re¬
spond to today’s critics of the institution.
Those who urge that marriage is essential to democracy are
using nineteenth-century arguments based on nineteenth-
century institutions—historic notions of what constitutes
democracy, virtue, marriage, and family. In this regard, it is im¬
portant to remember that the version of our democracy in oper¬
ation during the nineteenth century denied all women and a
good number of men the right to vote and otherwise participate
in political life. Our virtuous nation and its Constitution legiti¬
mated slavery. So, too, the marriage invoked was the common-
law version that reflected a very different sort of sensibilities
than ours today—lifelong, patriarchal, and hierarchical. Even
if called by the same name, the institution of the nineteenth
century is certainly not the vision of marriage we have today.
Neither marriage nor democracy has remained constant in def¬
inition over time and across changes in our culture.
Finally (and I believe this is the real issue for many advocating
its centrality), marriage can have important expressive meaning
for a society, reflecting its moral or religious conventions. This
role, however, seems problematic for a diverse and secular state
104 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
the right to receive a portion of the estate of a spouse who dies in¬
testate and protection against disinheritance through elective
share provisions; preference in being appointed as the personal
representative of a spouse who dies intestate; the right to bring a
lawsuit for the wrongful death of a spouse; the right to bring an ac¬
tion for loss of consortium; the right to workers’ compensation sur¬
vivor benefits; the right to spousal benefits statutorily guaranteed
to public employees, including health, life, disability, and accident
insurance; the opportunity to be covered as a spouse under group
life insurance policies issued to an employee; the opportunity to be
covered as the insured’s spouse under an individual health insur¬
ance policy; the right to claim an evidentiary privilege for marital
communications; homestead rights and protections; the presump¬
tion of joint ownership of property and the concomitant right of
survivorship, hospital visitation and other rights incident to the
medical treatment of a family member; and the right to receive,
and the obligation to provide, spousal support, maintenance, and
property division in the event of separation or divorce.14
C. Arguing Meanings
People are not always clear about which of the many ways of
thinking about marriage inform the arguments that they make.
It is legitimate to demand that our policymakers and politicians
be specific about the roles or functions they ascribe to marriage
as they tinker with the institution. How do they understand mar¬
riage from a societal perspective, and how are they filling the
marriage-meaning void as the institution relates to individuals?
It may be the case that some advocates of privileging mar¬
riage are substituting an individualized meaning for a societal
rationale in their support for the institution. I argue that only so-
cietally based rationales should be considered legitimate in fash¬
ioning society-wide regulations and rules associated with the
institution of marriage. So long as we leave the infusion of
meaning into marriage to the individuals engaged in the institu¬
tion one couple at a time, the state should maintain a neutral
stance. State privileging is only justified when there is a corre¬
sponding legitimate state interest in the institution. Therefore,
society must justify the expression of its interest in marriage
through regulation and subsidy. What exactly is the state interest
should be the first question—the second is, why is this particular
intervention necessary to preserve or manifest it?
io6 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
v
role of marriage as the exclusive mechanism to provide certain
economic benefits and protections can be appropriately main¬
tained. This was the question that set off the line of reasoning
used in Hawaii and Vermont cases in which the Supreme
Courts of those states mandated that same-sex couples be enti-
ded to all the privileges and benefits conferred on marital cou¬
ples.17 Looking at the current state of both marriage and
patterns of intimate behavior, the majorities in those cases con¬
cluded that the state must either open up that institution to
same-sex couples or create a nonmarriage category that confers
all the economic benefits of that status. The allocation of state
economic benefits was not to be limited by the moral or histori¬
cal and traditional meanings of marriage.
The questions faced by the courts in those cases—the ques¬
tions the rest of us have been avoiding thus far—included a con¬
sideration of when history and tradition should give way to new
patterns of behavior (such as nonmarital and same-sex cohabita¬
tion), as well as a reflection on the broader issue of when laws
should mirror a purely moral condemnation. This consideration
is particularly compelling when there is no societal consensus as
to whether the conduct in question is immoral. As the Hawaii
majority in Baehr noted, “constitutional law may mandate, like it
or not, that customs change with an evolving social order.”18
As illustrated in this chapter, the questions associated with a
modern consideration of marriage might become more compli¬
cated and difficult to answer if we must first reveal the meaning
(or meanings) we assign to the institution of marriage. This type
of consideration forces our focus away from the historic, sym¬
bolic nature or form of the marital relationship to the role or
function we want the institution of the family to serve in our so¬
ciety. It also reveals that we are making certain assumptions
about the capabilities and capacities of marriage as distin¬
guished from other types of family relationships in society—as-
io8 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
entity. The unique nature of these rules has been justified by ref¬
erence to the family’s relational aspects and its intimate nature.
In fact, “family law” can be thought of as a system of exemp¬
tions from the everyday rules that would apply to legal interac¬
tions among people in a nonfamily context, such as the law of
contract and tort, as well as criminal law, property law, and rules
of equity. These exemptions are complemented by the imposi¬
tion of a set of special family obligations. Law defines the re¬
sponsibilities of family members toward one another and the
claims or rights they have, placing more duties on them vis-a-vis
one another than would apply were they strangers.19 It is not
surprising, therefore, that one common subject of family law lit¬
erature has been how to use law to redefine, reform, or regulate
intrafamily dynamics.
But family law does more than confer rights, duties, and obli¬
gations within the family. It also assumes and reflects a certain
type of relationship between family and state. As diagrammed
in the introduction to this section, during the nineteenth century
this relationship was typically cast as one of “separate spheres.”
Family (the private sphere) and state (the public sphere) were
perceived as largely independent of one another. This
metaphor of separation reflected an ethic or ideology of family
privacy in which state intervention was the exception.
The characterization of the family as autonomous—distinct
and separate from the state—still resonates in our rhetoric about
families. The family is designated the quintessentially “private”
institution. Family is distinguished from both the market and the
state (the quintessentially public institution) by its privateness. In
a sense, privacy is what defines the family, sets it apart from other
societal entities, and gives it coherence as a concept. For the
modern private family, protection from public interference re¬
mains the articulated norm—state intervention continues to be
cast as exceptional, requiring some justification.20
no THE AUTONOMY MYTH
While there might have been some consensus about the superi¬
ority of the marital family over other forms at some point in our
nation’s history (at least among political and economic elites),
today there is much disagreement about just who should be con¬
sidered “family.” The traditional core of husband and wife (with
or without children) seems to qualify under all definitions of
family. In fact, this reproductive unit is considered by many peo¬
ple to represent the “natural” and essential form of the family.
Some people argue that it should also be considered an exclusive
vision of family in terms of policy and law.22 In spite of the ten¬
dency of traditionalists to continue to equate the family with the
marital family, on an empirical level, family-like intimate entities
come in many different forms.
The most recent census data for the United States reveal that
for the first time in our nation’s history, less than a quarter of
households are made up of married, couples with their chil¬
dren.23 This is the form of family labeled by the Census Bureau
WHY MARRIAGE? Ill
r
V. MARRIAGE IN CONTEXT
say the identity, of interest and views, which belong, or should be¬
dence that a woman had no legal existence separate from her hus¬
VI. CONCLUSION
\
Chapter Five
I. INTRODUCTION
This chapter asks the question: given changes in the legal regu¬
lation of marriage, coupled with changing patterns of intimate
behavior, why should marriage continue to be the exclusive, pre¬
ferred core or basic family connection? It is marriage that is as¬
serted to be the tie that defines which families are legitimate.
For some critics of the status quo, the issue is the inclusion of
alternatives to the husband/wife dyad within the category of
marriage. For others, the question is marriage itself as a legal
construct that carries with it significant societal benefits. Why
should marriage be so privileged? Some proponents of abolish¬
ing marriage as a legal category argue that marriage should be
replaced by contract, allowing couples to structure their rela¬
tionships in the ways they want. According to this position, there
is no reason for the state to be involved in the articulation and
imposition of those terms any more than it would be involved in
the enforcement of contracts in general.
122 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
Feminists might also point but that one of the state’s historic
interests in the institution was to use regulation of marriage and
divorce to mediate relations of dependency between husbands
and wives. Since wives are no longer dependent persons who are
confined to home and hearth, there is no longer any appropriate
rationale for the state’s involvement in marriage. Given aspira¬
tions of gender equality, which posit that couples are capable of
making their own marital terms and freely deciding when and
for what reasons to dissolve their relationship, it should be they,
not the state, who make such determinations. What is, and what
should be, left of marriage as a status in modern American soci¬
ety? What societal purposes could state intervention and regula¬
tion of marriage serve in a no-fault, prenuptial-recognizing,
gender-egalitarian world? Shouldn’t private lives be left to pri¬
vate ordering—to contract?
Further indicating to many that it is time for a serious re¬
assessment of marriage and its role in society is the fact that
marriage drags along with it certain historic assumptions about
the institution and its members that limit the coherent develop¬
ment of family policy. Marriage also impedes other policy for¬
mation: it is offered as the social policy resolution for poverty in
welfare debates. Marriage may in fact be the only clear and con¬
sistent family policy idea developed in the United States. The
existence of the institution and assumptions surrounding it dis¬
tort our policy and politics. The theoretical availability of mar¬
riage interferes with the development of other solutions to social
problems involving children and poverty.
As the various (and by no mqans exhaustive) meanings of
marriage listed in the previous chapter indicate, marriage is ex¬
pected to do a lot of work in our society. It is not to quibble that
much of this work must be done. Children must be cared for and
nurtured; dependency must be addressed; and individual happi¬
ness is of general concern. However, we should be asking our-
THE FUTURE OF MARRIAGE 123
* - ,
r
selves as we consider each of these tasks, what does marriage
have to do with it? Is the existence of the institution of marriage,
in and of itself, essential to accomplishing any of the societal
goals or objectives we seek to bring about?
In this chapter, I argue that for all relevant and appropriate
societal purposes, we do not need marriage and we should abol¬
ish it as a legal category. I argue that we should transfer the social
and economic subsidies and privilege that marriage now re¬
ceives to a new family core connection—that of the caretaker-
dependent. In making this proposal, I want to be very clear
about two things. First, to state that we do not need legal mar¬
riage to accomplish many societal objectives is not the same
thing as saying that we do not need a family to do so for some.
However, family as a social and legal category should not be de¬
pendent on having marriage as its core relationship. Nor is fam¬
ily synonymous with marriage.
Family affiliations are expressed in different kinds of acts,
only some of which are recognized by the law. Some affiliations
are sexually based, as with marriage. Some are forged biologi¬
cally, as with parenthood, although this tie can also be created
legally through adoption. Other affiliations are more relational
in nature, such as those based on nurturing or caretaking or
those developed through affection and acceptance of interde¬
pendence.
Second, even if we conclude we don’t need marriage as a
legal category, this does not mean that marriage as a societal in¬
stitution would disappear. The symbolic dimension of mar¬
riage—the coming-together of two individuals with vows of
love and commitment—would most likely continue to exist as a
social, cultural, and/or religious construct.1 Without legal sta¬
tus, however, marriage would no longer be the privileged mech¬
anism whereby the state distributes certain social goods.
124 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
v
THE FUTURE* OF MARRIAGE
I27
r
r
economic adjustments at the termination of a nonmarital co¬
habitation relationship in ways similar to the rules that apply
upon divorce in many states.16 In its Proposed Rules, the Ameri¬
can Law Institute recommends that when domestic partners ter¬
minate their partnership, their property be defined and divided
by the same body of rules by which this process would occur if
the parties were legally married.17 Domestic partners are de¬
fined as “two persons of the same or opposite sex, not married
to one another, who for a significant period of time share a pri¬
mary residence and a life together as a couple.”
Unlike the Vermont statute that recognizes civil unions for
same-sex couples and grants them the “common benefits and
protections that flow from marriage under Vermont law,”18 the
ALPs Proposed Rules include all domestic partnerships,
whether the parties are same-sex or opposite-sex nonmarital
couples.19 The rules also do not require registration or any kind
of formal affiliational act, which further distinguishes the ALI
proposal from the Vermont statutory scheme.
In fact, the ALI proposal creates a presumption based on cer¬
tain behavior that people who are living together are domestic
partners: “Persons not related by blood or adoption are pre¬
sumed to be domestic partners when they have maintained a
common household ... for a continuous period [of specified
duration]. The presumption is rebuttable by evidence that the
parties did not share life together as a couple . . .” “Sharing life
as a couple” is determined by reference to such things as repre¬
sentations to others, intermingling of finances, the existence of
a relationship that fostered economic interdependence or de¬
pendence of one partner upon the other, assumption of special¬
ized or collaborative roles in furtherance of life together,
emotional or physical intimacy, and other factors indicating
commitment, even if there is no formal declaration of such.20
The point is that it is not the formal status of marriage, or
130 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
III. BACKLASH
v
directed to “take submission into their own hands.”24 This state
of affairs is viewed not as benefiting the husband, at least not
primarily, but as consistent with God’s natural order of things—
“a mirror of the relationship between Christ and church.”25
Feminist criticism was noted during discussions of this posi¬
tion, but was dismissed because, even though such objections
may raise “sensitive and important issues . . . none of them is
substantial enough to move Bible-believing Christians away
from affirming the truths [that Paul teaches].”26 Feminist the¬
ologians and others who favor a more egalitarian approach to
marriage have been accused of taking a position that “assumes
the egalitarian worldview and then ‘hijacks’ the Bible to make it
fit. Texts are either accepted, rejected, ignored, revised accord¬
ing to the way they fit in with that motif... a mistake of the
greatest gravity [because] it is plain that while the Bible teaches
equality, it does not affirm egalitarianism or interchangeability in
all things, but rather calls for distinguishable roles between men
and women.”27
The Promise Keepers treat feminists even more harshly. A
prominent Promise Keepers leader has said: “I believe that fem¬
inists of the more aggressive persuasion are frustrated women
unable to find the proper male leadership. If a woman were re¬
ceiving the right kind of love and attention and leadership, she
would not want to be liberated from that.”28 In this view,
women, like children, are not equals, but dependents who must
be guided and controlled.
Even if pro-traditional-marriage/antidivorce sentiments are
not based in religion, as they are with the Promise Keepers, as¬
sertions about the significance of marriage abound. These ideas
do not exist in isolation, but are an integral part of systems of
belief about the appropriate ordering of the world. Some mem¬
bers of society believe that the no-fault divorce laws have gone
too far, in that people can now marry without serious considera-
I32 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
tion of the consequences (since they know they can leave the re¬
lationship more easily than before) and can divorce too quickly,
without trying to address solvable problems in their marriage.
Part of the political backlash against no-fault divorce has re¬
sulted in the introduction in Louisiana and a few other states of
something called “covenant marriage,” which has been de¬
scribed as “part of a larger effort to redefine and bolster tradi¬
tional marriage in order to reduce divorce, unwed mothering
and single parenthood.”29 Covenant marriage is an attempt to
create a situation that is described as supporting the more “tra¬
ditional” vision of marriage, in that it is more than just a return
to the former fault-based requirements for divorce.
Couples who wish to enter a covenant marriage must attend
premarital counseling, after which they must produce a nota¬
rized affidavit signed by them and their counselor indicating
that they have discussed topics relating to the seriousness of
marriage. They also must sign a “Declaration of Intent” that af¬
firms the following principles: “[A] marriage is an agreement to
live together as husband and wife forever; the partners chose
each other carefully and disclosed to each other everything
about their personal histories that might hurt the marriage; the
couple received premarital counseling from a priest, minister,
rabbi, or state-recognized marriage counselor; and the partners
agree to take all reasonable efforts to preserve their marriage if
they experience marital difficulties.”30
Although the name evokes religious imagery, covenant mar¬
riage, proposed and passed by the legislature, is a legal entity
rather than a religious construction. It is an alternative to the
marriage in operation under the no-fauit divorce system, and it
is presumably more difficult to dissolve. While it is available to
all Louisianans who apply for a marriage license, it appears that
covenant marriage has not become widespread since its intro¬
duction in 1997. One survey, done'in 1998, showed that only 1.5
THE FUTURE* O F MARRIAGE
*33
r
A THOUGHT EXPERIMENT
V. OUTSIDE OF CONTRACT
VI. CONCLUSION
*
Part Three
Feminist Critiques
of the Family
«
*
Equality and Family
* * *
faire always insisted that the state protect their property interests
and that courts enforce contracts and adjudicate torts. They took
this state action for granted and chose not to consider such pro¬
I. INTRODUCTION
A. Gender
“Gender” is a term that refers to the-cluster of characteristics
deemed feminine or masculine in society, as distinguished from
mere biological or genetic categories. Gender is socially con¬
structed; it is imparted through socialization and culture rather
than inherent. Part of the evidence for this is that characteristics
FEMINISM AJJD THE FAMILY
J57
0
hibit both from choosing the paths they will pursue in life based on
church and the king was the head of the state. The respective
positions of husband and wife were rigidly distinct and patri-
archically ordered—the husband’s role, as frail wife’s protector,
was deemed “divinely ordained.” Bradwell v. Illinois,1 a case dis¬
cussed in chapter four, involved a prohibition on women’s ad¬
mission to the practice of law, indicating that this hierarchical
thinking had implications well beyond the family and affected
women’s career and other opportunities. Women, whose pri¬
mary calling was as wives and mothers, were considered unfit
for the harshness of public life.
Common-law rules and regulations aided in the construction
and maintenance of the subordinate gender roles in the family.8
The structure of the common law mired married women, in
particular, in family responsibility and left them on a legal plain
far from access to independent and autonomous decision mak¬
ing. Given the power of the legal construct of the common-law
family, in retrospect it seems naive of feminists to think they
could just import concepts of equality developed in other con¬
texts onto the existing inequality of the family. The prevalent
understanding of equality that developed in the “public” sphere
demanded an individualized notion of sameness of treatment
and gender neutrality. Such notions seem singularly inappropri¬
ate in confronting what has historically been the most gendered
institution in society.
«
vention and monitoring is considered inappropriate absent
some significant breakdown. This is important because these
perceptions mean that state intervention into any specific family
situation is improbable.
The practice of gender equality exists only to the extent that
individual married couples choose to embrace it, unsupervised
by the state. Yet, within the marital relationship, independent of
any legal assurance of equality, the spouse with superior eco¬
nomic and social power can wield such power in ways that pre¬
serves the status quo. Therefore, it is not surprising that many
couples continue to act out traditionally gendered scripts of be¬
havior, mimicking the roles taught through unreformed social¬
ization processes.
As a result, while equality in the context of the marital family
might be imposed in a formal manner, each couple designs the
actual terms of their marriage relationship. Their respective
bargaining power will be influenced by the bargaining power
they bring to that relationship, which is often the product of how
much they can mobilize social resources outside of the family—
how much autonomy they have. Unless the marital relationship
dissolves and the courts are asked to intervene to allocate eco¬
nomic resources in the context of a divorce, equality is realizable
only at the whim of the person with the most economic and cul¬
tural clout. The monitoring and implementation of equality for
the intact marital family is left to the individual family and its
members—it is a self-regulating system.
Self-regulation is not the primary assumption made in the
context of imposing gender equality in the public sphere, how¬
ever. In the workplace, equality is not only imposed, but also
monitored. Laws structure working relationships in the first in¬
stance, and mandate that employers provide equal pay for equal
work and otherwise treat women equally with men. If there is
discrimination, individual and governmental actions are pro-
FEMINISM AND THE FAMILY 165
r
vided to remedy this, and unlike the case of the marital relation¬
ship, the benefits of equality are not withheld until the worker
terminates the relationship.
Recently, some reformers have turned their attention to the
relationship between the traditional demands of motherhood
and the failure of women to achieve equality in the workplace in
spite of legal dictates. It should be increasingly apparent that if
we want to change the family, we must also transform the work¬
place to accommodate that change. A few feminist legal scholars
are now focused on what has been labeled the “work-family con¬
flict.” The problem with this focus, from the- perspective of
American policymakers, who are saddled with an antiregulatory
rhetoric and a free-market ideology, is that to resolve the con¬
flict, it will be necessary to regulate the workplace, placing de¬
mands and obligations on employers. Undoubtedly, this will be
perceived as interfering with the autonomy of those employers
and the freedom of the marketplace—transgressions of consid¬
erable magnitude in today’s political contexts.
However, it is exactly this type of reform that must occur.
Feminists must confront the difficult issues and political pitfalls
involved, and argue for a more humane workplace and a more
responsive state to emphasize the democratic and egalitarian
traditions in our capitalistic system. Until the structures that
make it so difficult and costly to combine caretaking responsibil¬
ities with paid work are changed, the status quo of family dy¬
namics and workplace demands will continue to place women in
a relatively disadvantageous position.
What are needed are not more legal reforms of the family, but
a restructuring of the conditions of the workplace, which will
most likely require substantial state intervention. This is not a
plea for more “mommy track” options or other minor adjust¬
ments that separate out women for different treatment and thus,
in practice, work in a discriminatory manner. As discussed more
166 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
within the family visible. They generated instability in, and sub-
FEMINISM A«N D THE FAMILY 167
equality (at least initially) and direct our attention to the place
and meaning of marriage and the marital family in our cultural,
social, and ideological systems. It also brings us into direct con¬
frontation with the implications of economic ideology and prac¬
tices of capitalism, which some argue have not been enough of a
focus for feminists within the United States. However, until we
undertake this kind of exploration, it will be impossible for us to
consider what kinds of reforms are likely to make things better
(more equal and just) within marriage, within the family, or
within society in general. Real reform cannot proceed, or even
be adequately theorized, until we understand and appreciate
the way changes in the expectations for and functioning of the
marital family in order to gain greater gender equality will chal¬
lenge and threaten other social institutions. In the sense that
they are built around the continuation of a gendered family
structure, these institutions are actually dependent on it. If that
structure is undermined, so are the institutions weakened. Fem¬
inists must respond to these threats with ideas for new structur¬
ing that will benefit us all.
In her article, Bartlett alluded to a backlash against existing
feminist reform. Certainly that backlash is generated in part by
the realization that feminism, insofar as it equalizes ambitions
and opportunities, threatens the traditional family. If women re¬
ally aspire to equality, the family will not be able to perform its
historic task of being the repository for dependency. Those who
lash back against feminist egalitarian aspirations realize some¬
thing we should also take seriously: successfully transforming ex¬
pectations and behavior within the family will necessitate
profound corresponding transformations and accommodations
on the part of other societal institutions.
Feminists must not replicate the same sort of mistakes that
mar other theoretical and policy discussions, focusing only on
one area of law and set of relationships and failing to consider
THE AUTONOMY MYTH
i74
Katz speculates that among the reasons that economics has en¬
joyed “relatively less influence” in family law than other doctri¬
nal fields have is the persistent tendency to conceptualize the
market and family as separate realms.23 Equally significant is his
identification of the difficulty associated with the “fundamental
issues of liberalism” raised by the “recurring need” (inherent in
the whole idea of family) for some family members to make de¬
cisions for others who are incapable of protecting their own in¬
terests.24 Katz thus labels the family “the archetypal paternalist
institution.”25 An economic modgl that posits independent, ra¬
tional individuals not only interacting with each other, but also
seeking to maximize their own utility in that interaction, does
not reflect what is assumed about family relationships.26
The “recurring need” for a “paternalist” family presents a
dilemma not only for economists but also, as I have argued, for
FEMINISM AaN D ,THE FAMILY
177
P
treated worse than other disabilities is the same one that will allow
creates not only the desired floor under the pregnant woman’s
rights but also the ceiling. ... If we can’t have it both ways, we
My own feeling is that, for all its problems, the equality approach
is the better one. The special treatment model has great costs. . ..
IV. CONCLUSION
I. INTRODUCTION
norm.26 But the nature and source of these arguments are curi¬
ous. Economic irresponsibility is excused and justified by fa¬
thers’ rights advocates, who argue that men’s widespread failure
to pay child support is attributable -to the frustration and pain
they experience as a result of their unjust treatment as second-
class parents. Overwhelmingly, male policy bodies have ac-
MOT H^E RJNG
I95
v
III. FATHERHOOD
What has been missing from policy and reform discussions thus
far is a debate about the nature of fatherhood and the transfor¬
mation of the role of the father in response to changing expec¬
tations, norms, and practices. How does the desire for gender
neutrality and the ideal of egalitarianism play a role in the cre¬
ation of a new set of norms for fatherhood? Men should be en¬
gaged in this type of rhetorical and conceptual exercise,
following the consciousness-raising and conversational models
of the last few decades through which women successfully trans¬
formed their roles.
Much of contemporary fathers’ rights discourse, however,
has concentrated almost exclusively on the perceived failings of
mothers and their alleged vindictiveness and irresponsibility.
The strategy is successful, and as a result, the failures of fathers
are turned back on mothers. Male foibles are cast as merely re¬
sponsive to women’s actions and as understandably defensive. A
sense of crisis for fathers has been generated concerning visita¬
tion rights, for example. The assertion of fathers’ rights groups
is that mothers typically persist in interfering with fathers’ access
to children. There are suggestions that in retaliation, these
mothers should be subject to fines and/or imprisonment or
should lose custody of the children.
It is also alleged that mothers are at fault for misuse of child-
support payments. Fathers’ rights advocates speculate that
mothers use their meager and sporadic child-support awards to
support vile habits or indulge new lovers.28 These undocu-
THE AUTONOMY MYTH
i96
state, and market, and to realize that all are mutually contin¬
gent. We now limit and confine obligations and responsibilities
to one institution and ignore the responsibility of others by con¬
structing independent spheres. What is needed is integration. If
we want to recognize that people have a right to work, but that
workers are also family members who may have responsibility
for the dependency of others, then we will have to develop po¬
lices directing workplaces to accommodate caretaking responsi¬
bility.
It is naive to think that transformation in the family will not
necessitate some complementary restructuring of the workplace
and increased participation on the part of government.43 Gov¬
ernment and market in combination must remove the obstacles
and burdens associated with combining caretaking and paid
work that have developed around an antiquated, unrealistic
model of the family in which there was a caretaker who comple¬
mented the wage earner.
The new workplace norm should be that of the dually re¬
sponsible worker. The question would then become: how can we
ensure the caretaker’s right to work—her right to earn while not
sacrificing the well-being of her children or other dependents?
The market must be transformed. If it does not do so on its
own, the government must structure family-friendly policies in
the workplace. This can be accomplished by regulation or by in¬
centives offered through the tax system. The list of proposals
may be long and details will be vexing, but at a minimum, paid
family leave for all workers, flexible workweeks, and subsidized
child-care facilities in which the workers are decendy paid
would be foundational.
By making nurturing and caretaking a central responsibility
of the nonfamily arenas of life, we structure an equal opportu¬
nity to engage in nurturing and caretaking. Under these circum¬
stances, men may actually be more likely to take time and
202 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
«
IV. CONCLUSION
tempts to coax men into caretaking and instead require that all
social institutions assume some responsibility for the needs of
caretakers.44
Instead of structuring incentives for men to act responsibly,
we should worry about the double burden that has been foisted
on mothers, and seek to make it possible for them to meet the
conflicting demands society is imposing. This will require sub¬
stantial societal reordering, but when caretakers have the means
to meet the demands of those for whom they have assumed
responsibility, the entire society, including our children, will
benefit.
Child support is not a viable solution to the problems of child
care and dependency. In fact, the theoretical development of
child support stands as a diversion to the development of effec¬
tive policy.45 On an ideological level, primarily because it is
based on the traditional notion of a nuclear family, child sup¬
port furthers the assumption that dependency is a private mat¬
ter.46 Indeed, insistence on child-support policy is an attempt to
reconstruct the gendered complementarity of the traditional
family through the imposition of the economically viable
male.47
On a practical level, child support will not end child poverty.
Even when it is paid, the typical amounts are woefully inade¬
quate to actually support a child.48 Many of the fathers who are
under an obligation do not pay the child support they are re¬
quired to, either because they are unwilling (deadbeat dads) or
unable (dead-broke dads).49 The Institute for Women’s Policy
Research, in a report prepared in 1999 on the relationship be¬
tween child poverty and child support, concluded that
\ . .
fact, as earlier chapters indicate, the family’s importance is re¬
vealed in its very segregation from other areas of human
endeavor. In setting it up as separate and distinct, we accom¬
modate the otherwise messy problem of dependency. Earlier
chapters review the doctrinal implications of this dual charac¬
terization of the family as both separate and essential, which is
reflected in the conceptual division of the world (and law) into
the realms of “the public” and “the private.”1 The family em¬
bodies the private sphere of human experience—a sphere in op¬
position to the public world of market and economic efforts.
Furthermore, the characterization of the family as the preemi¬
nent private space carries with it sets of assumptions about fam¬
ily relationships. These are cast as different in formation,
function, and form than relationships existing in the public
world. Families are assumed to be altruistic institutions held to¬
gether by affectional bonds.
Instead of being cloaked with the mantle of privacy, the fam¬
ily must be brought to the center of legal and jurisprudential
theory and made an explicit part of that theory. In the chapters
in this section, I further articulate the nature of the family as a
sociolegal institution and explain why I feel it is essential to
reconceptualize and transform our notions about the family and
its relationship to the state and other societal institutions. This
analysis is based on the insight that the family is not separate and
should not be segregated into the “private” sphere. The family is
an interactive and dynamic public institution that has been as¬
signed an historic role that is essential to society. That role, as
well as the aspirational and erdpirrcal dimensions of the family,
must be explicit considerations in the development of any
worthwhile social theory.
In recent debates over social policy related to family, caretak¬
ing, and dependency, there is little attention paid to figuring out
what might be the optimal or appropriate distribution of re-
sponsibility for dependency across societal institutions. Nor is
there consideration of how we might structure the correspon¬
ding relationships among government, market, and family in re¬
gard to dependency.
Of course, we do debate and theorize about structuring
responsibilities in regard to some institutional arrangements.
It is just the family that seems to be left out of debates as an
explicit unit of analysis. For example, there is a great deal of at¬
tention paid to what might be the appropriate institutional
interrelationship between state and market. Scholars and po¬
liticians set forth and defend competing positions on how to
define the appropriate balance between freedom and respon¬
sibility; between subsidy and self-sufficiency, in regard to eco¬
nomic and regulatory matters involving state and market
institutions.
My task in the chapters in this section is to lay the foundation
for similar arguments about the family and its interrelation¬
ship with other societal institutions. How should the work asso¬
ciated with dependency be distributed? Should caretaking be
publicly subsidized and supported or kept within the private
family? How can we justly allocate the costs of caretaking? Of
course, my goal in developing these arguments is ultimately
to show how compelling is the case for the state and the market
to assume more (or some) primary responsibility for depend¬
ency.
In developing my arguments about the need for adjustment
in our basic social structures in chapter seven, I use the concept
of contract. Specifically, I resort to the metaphor of “social con¬
tract” as a way to think about how institutions and relationships
are thought to embody norms of justice asserted to be widely
shared by members of a society. I do not intend to engage in the
extensive, abstract (often turgid) debates about social contract
theory undertaken by political theorists. My modest objective is
THE AUTONOMY MYTH
210
<
fi
eration.7
which they give to the state power to enforce the rule of law so that
This statement reflects what lias been termed the most perva¬
sive” and “indispensable” principle of contract theory gener¬
ally—that the will of the parties sets their legal relationship.
This is recognition of private autonomy’s primacy in contract
theory and the basis for the formal requirements of contract law,
particularly the idea that there must be a “meeting of the
minds” and “consent.”9
Of course, the social contract is not a real contract, re
duced to writing and signed by the parties, as private contracts
typically are. The idea of the social contract is a way of ap¬
proaching the relationship between the individual and the sys¬
tems of coercion and authority within which she or he lives. The
exact nature of this symbolic contract and its specific contours
have been the subjects of political theory and legal debate for
decades.
The works of Professors Robert Nozick and John Rawls illus¬
trate two positions often named as contrasting models of social
organization. Nozick’s position is that basic social i elationships
are found in the interaction among autonomous and indepen¬
dent individuals, ideally unencumbered and unburdened by
legal regulation and state interventions.10 Nozick begins with the
speculative assumption that in the state of nature, an individual
owns himself, his own labor, and any property it produces or
procures.
In this regard, the state appropriately assumes responsibility
for the mechanism whereby a free market (for individual trans¬
actions) might be facilitated and maintained. But beyond pro¬
viding police protection and institutions such as courts for the
maintenance of order, enforcement of contract, and transmis¬
sion of property, the state maintains a minimal role. Individuals
owe little to the collective and have no moral or legal responsi¬
bility to others except that fashioned through criminal or con¬
tract law.
AUTONOMY WITHIN T it E SOCIAL CONTRACT 213
Under this view, the market is the basic social institution, dis¬
tributing goods and values in a manner that is both just and effi¬
cient. If individuals fail, it is their own responsibility and reflects
their lack of ambition, motivation, or talent. This position de¬
fines the basic parameters of the economic “conservative” argu¬
ment today. Market relations are viewed as the most efficient
way to create individual wealth and order society. Government
intervention is condemned as fostering poverty and undermin¬
ing family and other “private” institutional relations, ultimately
leading to crime, social disintegration, and disorder. Corre¬
spondingly, the solution for existing social problems (caused by
governmental intervention) is to return to the private sector—
the market—allowing it to perform the collective function of ef¬
ficient distribution.11
In contrast to Nozick, Rawls posits that the collective does
have legitimate claims on the individual and that the state may
appropriately work to perpetuate the “collective good,” a social
resource to which individuals may be required to contribute
through taxation and other tithes.12 Distribution of property is
potentially problematic and susceptible to challenges based on
injustice. Rawls is the intellectual descendant of John Locke,
who, in 1690, asserted:
and it is fit every one who enjoys his share of the protection should
pay out of his estate his proportion for the maintenance of it. But
still it must be with his own consent—i.e., the consent of the ma¬
by them; for if any one shall claim a power to lay and levy taxes on
the people by his own authority, and without such consent of the
cating children does not fall more heavily on women, thereby un¬
\ ...
often ignore the implications of the fact that individual choice
occurs within the constraints of social conditions (including ide¬
ological constraints) that funnel decisions into prescribed chan¬
nels and often operate in a practical and symbolic manner to
limit or virtually eliminate options.
As discussed in chapter two, the idea of consent is problem¬
atic in examinations of existing social oppression. Using notions
of individual choice or responsibility as justification for existing
conditions fails to recognize that quite often a choice carries
with it consequences not anticipated or imagined at the time of
the initial decision. For example, in assessing who should bear
the burdens or costs associated with dependency and child care,
we may believe (cultural, familial, and societal imperatives
aside) that a woman chose to become a mother, but does this
choice mean she has also consented to the societal conditions at¬
tendant to that role and the many ways in which that status will
negatively affect her economic prospects? Did she even realize
what those costs might be? Is it possible that the society and cul¬
ture might even have led her astray on the issue of costs, and
misled her about the returns and rewards of caretaking?
It is worth repeating that social conditions, particularly condi¬
tions of oppression, are of far more than individual concern.
They are of public concern in a society that has established
norms of justice, incorporating ideals of equality and inclusion.
These norms have been fashioned in ways that allow us (perhaps
even encourage us) to measure individual circumstances inde¬
pendent of the idea of consent, at least initially. In taking this
measure, individual situations cah inform a discussion about the
underlying fairness of the existing social contract.19 There are
instances in which we do not enforce private contracts, even
those to which the parties have consented, such as when they are
unconscionable, based on mistake, of impossible to perform.20
Of course, the traditional contractual requirement of con-
RECASTING THE SOCIAL CONTRACT 227
r
lic/private dichotomy is a false one and that most things are both
public and private.23 Questioning the public/private compart-
mentalization to some extent also involves questioning the struc¬
ture of the debates associated with the idea of a social contract.
If everything is both public and private simultaneously, then the
labels will not resolve important questions concerning the cur¬
rent allocation of authority and responsibility among family,
market, and state.
Feminists are not the only ones to have deconstructed the
public/private divide. Others have made similar observations.
Even though the market may be posited as private in social con¬
tract debates, how it functions and what it produces are of pub¬
lic concern and can generate a lot of political attention. Market
institutions do not exist in a void—their actions have economic
and other implications for the society in which they are located.
Decisions about whether or not to provide “incentives” to busi¬
nesses seeking to relocate, for example, can be as provocative to
politicians and their electorate as decisions about who may
marry whom or what should be the economic ramifications of
single parenthood. Concern over certain practices, such as
sloppy safety measures in a workplace, can generate as much
will to regulate as can violations of an explicit criminal code.
Beyond the arguments based on public concern about the so¬
cial goods and services produced by private transactions, how¬
ever, is another realization about the nature of the market and
its transactions within society. Economists and others have
noted in the first instance that markets need law in order to func¬
tion—they require enforcement by the public sectors4 Private
agreements rely on legal (state) structures, as the following dis¬
cussion further details. Private contracting is ultimately a public
activity because those who would rely on contract must also rely
on law, courts, and police power as the default enforcement
mechanisms. It seems sound public policy to allow some public
230 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
«
ft
monitoring to determine which private arrangements (whether
in or outside the family) should be enforceable, entitled to legal
protection and recognition, and which should not. In fact, this is
why the law sometimes intervenes to regulate private contrac¬
tual bargains and imposes on contracting parties duties such as
that of good faith and fair dealing.25 Contracts are not always
enforced, and sometimes they are altered by practices, such as
custom, that are independent of the individual parties to the
contract.26
In addition, contract jurisprudence suggests there are always
“background conditions” to the practice of contracting.27 Often
these background conditions are the assumed existence of other
societal institutions, such as courts and law, which are clearly in
the public realm. Commentators have argued that the tradi¬
tional market paradigm, which views law as primarily a re¬
sponse to market failure, is wrong.28 To such writers, law is also
seen as a precondition to the very development of the market.
The existence of background rules—law—is necessary so that
actors can bargain and contract. This approach is distinct from
the typical law and economics analysis in that law is posited as
constitutive as well as reactive. From this perspective, law is
viewed as having a significant and positive role in creating and
sustaining the market. As a social and legal institution, the mar¬
ket does not exist independent of law. Even more fundamen¬
tally, the market relies on law, which is necessary in order for
markets to function. A system of background or default rules is
required in order that competitive and voluntary transactions—
contracting—can take place.29 ^
The notion of background conditions is simply the realiza¬
tion that all agreements are made in an historic context in which
certain preexisting structures and institutional arrangements are
assumed. Background conditions are essential to the process of
bargaining and contract. Established, predictable relationships
RECASTING the Social contract 231
P
can initiate new relations with other people even from a position
of alienation. ...31
CONTRACT
hand, the part of the Contract with America that appears to ex¬
plicitly address and support families—the Family Reinforce¬
ment Act—actually contained very few programs at all, and
nothing about social programs that would address the health
and welfare of children, especially those in low-income fami¬
lies.48
By promoting the family as the solution to the problem of
poverty, the Republican Contract with America is a proposal to
move caretaking and dependency responsibilities back into the
private institution of the family. This proposed solution would
not increase the likelihood of successfully meeting caretaking
needs (how could a single mother work thirty-five hours a week
and care for her dependent preschool-age children?), but these
caretaking needs would be seen as a private problem, not a pub¬
lic one, and not one that the government would have to address.
V. CONCLUSION
*
Chapter Nine
I. INTRODUCTION
the employer cannot stop her or him. But such freedom for the
individual employee is largely illusory, an abstract proposition
taken out of the context of power relations and economic ne¬
cessity that inform most employment relationships.
Employers can usually hire someone else easily. For the em¬
ployee, however, a new job may be hard to find, particularly if
the employee is older, less skilled, or trained for a specific set of
tasks for which there is not a robust employment market. In¬
creasingly, employers require truly specialized employees or
those with knowledge that might prove beneficial to a competi¬
tor to sign noncompetition contracts as a condition of employ¬
ment. These contracts further reduce the possibility of securing
new work, should the at-will employee decide to leave.
From the employers’ perspective legally, the employment-at-
will doctrine has generally meant there was never much security
for workers. Yet assumptions about employer responsibility to
employees (at least managerial and white-collar employees) and
the expectation that employment would secure some basic so¬
cial goods are widely perceived as having shifted in the past few
decades.2
A vision of progressive change in the workplace centered on
the individual worker is hard to articulate because there is no con¬
sensus about an idealized form of relationship to exemplify
equality between employee and employer. Such a vision was
supplied in the context of marriage by the idea of an equal part¬
nership between husband and wife, a metaphor that was trans¬
ferable in part because the relationship is between two
presumptively equal individuals. However, in the workplace we
deal with an individual, on the one hand, and quite often a large
entity or organization, on the other. Even with small businesses,
there is no accepted concept of parity and partnership between
employer and employee—the relationship is structured as inher¬
ently unequal.
THE AUTONOMY MYTH
244
»
s
II. THE TENUOUS WORKPLACE
Although she doesn’t use the term social contract, Stone ex¬
plores the notion of a “psychological contract” in her work.7 She
applies the ideas developed in organizational behavior theory to
discuss the beliefs that an individual forms about reciprocal ex¬
change agreements. She distinguishes this notion of reciprocity
from the unilateral experience of expectation, hope, or aspira¬
tion. Stone casts the psychological contract as “a subjective con¬
cept, expressing an individual’s belief in the existence of a
bilateral relationship such that when expectations are not met,
the employee feels ‘wronged,’ deceived and betrayed with per¬
vasive implications for the relationship.”8
Stone goes on to describe how employers have dismantled
this structure in recent years, creating new, more uncertain land¬
scapes for the employee. She uses the term “precarious employ¬
ment,” rather than contingent employment, for this evolving
dismantling of the implicit contract between employer and em¬
ployee because it encompasses all who do not have a long-term
attachment to a firm: those hired as temporary workers, those
hired as provisional or short-term workers, and those who have
steady, full-time jobs, but no longer have an implicit or explicit
promise of job security.9
248 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
4
ily life. At the same time, the report found insecurity was on the
rise, with 29 percent saying they were fearful of losing their jobs
compared with only 15 percent in 1977.15
In addition to job insecurity, it is significant to note that over
the past thirty years, the minimum wage has not been adjusted
to keep up with inflation. As a result, a person working for mini¬
mum wage full-time will earn under Si 1,000 a year, which is al¬
most 40 percent below the national poverty level.16 In order to
provide for the basic needs of a family, these minimum-wage
workers are forced to work long hours, sometimes at several
jobs. Indeed, increased working hours take time away from chil¬
dren, who must be taken care of by others or stay at home alone
because their parents cannot afford child care.17
From a historic perspective, real wages for workers have de¬
clined, and the idea of a family wage has been replaced by the
reality of a dual-earner couple. In response to this situation and
the well-documented inability of a family to take care of its
basic needs even if it receives full-time minimum-wage pay, liv¬
ing wage campaigns have emerged in several states. A living
wage is defined as “the wage required to raise a family of four
above the official poverty line.”18 These campaigns urge local
legislatures to mandate that public employers, and those who
contract with the city or state, provide a living wage for their
workers. They argue that such efforts are essential to reduce
poverty and dependence on social programs. The campaigns
have been successful in thirty-two cities, and there are seventy
more campaigns active in the United States.19
%
rv. UNIONS, EQUITY, AND MARKET DISTRIBUTION
OF SOCIAL GOODS
per se but broader worker influence over the terms and conditions
today.29
Prior to the early 1970s, the United States was becoming pro¬
gressively more egalitarian.31 Since that time, however, the re¬
verse has been true—by 1982, income inequality had reverted to
its 1947 level, and it has increased further ever since then.32 In
1968, the household at the ninety-fifth percentile had six times
the income of the household at the twentieth percentile, while in
1994, the difference jumped to 8.2 times the income.33 Between
1977 and 1999, the lowest twentieth percentile of American
households dropped 12 percent in average income, and by 1999
the top twentieth percentile was earning half of all the income
in the United States.34
A. Corporate Responsibility
Wage stagnation and the degree of income inequality that
America now experiences violate the spirit of any social con¬
tract designed to govern the expectations and relationships in a
society that values equality and democracy. This type of in¬
equality demands governmental intervention and some reme¬
dial measures directed toward leveling the playing field.
According to Anne Phillips, professor of gender theory at the
London School of Economics and Political Science, true equal¬
ity is achieved not through an equal share of income and
wealth, but through opportunities provided. She claims in re¬
gard to persons bound in situations in which they cannot help
themselves that the state does not have a responsibility to give to
them what they lack, but “[t]he state has a responsibility to en-
260 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
«
<x
sure that opportunities for self-advancement are made equally
available to every citizen, an obvious responsibility in the fields
of education and training, with perhaps some additional re¬
sponsibilities to assist lone parents back into the labour market,
or to make the feckless take out insurance policies to protect
them from future disaster.”66 It is the role of the government to
step in and regulate the market to make sure it is functioning
fairly to the best interest of society.
To that end, I argue in chapter ten for a “responsive state” and
for a “right to work.” This concept has many dimensions, includ¬
ing the idea that the state and the market have an obligation to
structure things so as to accommodate workers who also have
family responsibilities. There are other, far-reaching responsibil¬
ities the state should shoulder in regard to the workplace.
It is also important, however, that we as individuals change
the way we think about our own relationship with work and with
our coworkers and fellow citizens. Within the workplace, we are
isolated from others, encouraged to believe that provisions to
one group means sacrifice by another.67 From the perspective of
the arguments I have been making in this book, it may be that
those without care responsibilities fear that they will be required
to bear the burdens in the workplace if there is some accommo¬
dation for workers who have responsibilities for caretaking.
But it seems to me that this is the wrong focus. We should in¬
stead be questioning a set of employment relationships in which
it can be considered just or fair for employers confronted with a
demand that they accommodate one group of workers to
merely shift the burdens and cbsts associated with that accom¬
modation to another group of workers. In the case of accom¬
modation for caretakers, employers should not be permitted to
evade their responsibility for some of the costs of dependency,
even if it means some reduction- in profits or diminished returns
on capital.
THE TENTATIVE* WORKPLACE 261
r
B. Beyond Caretaking
To take the need for regulating the workplace even further, it is
also possible to expand ideas about the social contract and the
existence of social debt developed in this book well beyond care¬
taking labor (for others or for self). We could consider the situa¬
tion of the worker in general, the conditions of work, and the
structure of compensation.69 The idea of an egalitarian social
262 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
«
ft
contract can be the metaphor to bring nonmarket values, such
as norms of distributive justice and worker security, to bear on
our society as we confront the implications of change.
These norms are part of the scheme of expectations in other
industrialized democracies and can be implemented in ours
through a regulatory scheme of laws structuring the responsibil¬
ities of our workplaces. Particularly in the market context, we
need to be reminded that corporations, as abstract legal entities,
and those who run, direct, and profit from them cannot function
without the labor of others. Secretaries and truck drivers are
as essential to commerce as are highly paid CEOs and stock¬
holders.
The arguments made about exploitation in regard to caretak¬
ing are applicable to the situation of all those whose labor is un¬
dervalued but essential in providing for the needs, growth, and
maintenance of society and its institutions. My arguments based
on the need for recognition of caretaking can evolve into a gen¬
eral critique of our version of the ideology of free-market capi¬
talism and a claim for universal provision of basic social goods.
One’s positive contributions to society can thus be valued in a
public and egalitarian fashion based on nonmarket values. After
all, we are all in this together, and this realization should guide
the direction of our discourse about dependency and societal
responsibility, as well as actual public policy.
\
Chapter Ten
state is the only societal entity that can act for all. It is the only or¬
ganization in which membership is mandatory and universal
(we are all subject to the authority of the state). It is also uniquely
and expressly constituted to define the collective rights and re¬
sponsibilities of its members. Therefore, fulfilling the obligation
to caretakers requires a state that assumes an independent and
active regulatory role.
This obligation to caretakers can be perceived as one compo¬
nent of a more general state obligation to promote and ensure
the conditions of equality, wherein all individuals have an oppor¬
tunity to achieve security and exercise agency. The state has a re¬
sponsibility to mediate the structural inequality built into our
“free” market system. In regard to caretakers, the inequality is
found in the first instance among societal institutions the fam¬
ily assumes a disproportionate share of responsibility for care¬
taking and dependency. In the second instance, there lesults an
inequality among family members as responsibility within the
family is delegated to some individuals, depriving them of op¬
tions and opportunities available to less fettered family members.
While it may seem obvious that the national government and its
institutions are the only mechanisms with the capability to uni¬
formly regulate the excesses of society, particularly the market,
this realization does not alone generate the political will neces¬
sary for such regulation. Partly this is because of the corruption
visible in the existing system. Our current political climate
means that programs and policies that disturb vested interests
are stifled at inception or ridiculed if some politician is brave
enough to raise them. This situation is not too surprising given
the centrality of money to individual and party political success.
THE T E N A B^L E STATE 265
r
dom of speech, thought and faith, the right to own property and
to conclude valid contracts, and the right to justice”; political
rights include “the right to participate in the exercise of political
power, as a member of a body invested with political authority
or as an elector of the members of such a body”; and social
rights “range from the right to a modicum of economic welfare
and security to the right to share to the full in the social heritage
and to live the life of a civilized being according to the standards
prevailing in the society.”13 Each one has developed out of con¬
flicts arising from a society’s attempts to realize the earlier at¬
tempt. Marshall did not claim that his theory represented a final
and definitive description—because of the ongoing conflicts in¬
volved in implementing them, he believed that citizenship
rights, and the ways in which they could be realized, would con¬
tinue to evolve and develop. Marshall coined the term “social
citizenship” to describe the status conferred by such an ap¬
proach to state responsibility.14
Marshall’s vision can form the foundation for an argument
that the state must provide the “rights of autonomous citizen¬
ship” in order for Americans to actually effectively exercise our
civil and political rights. Without the autonomy that basic social
goods provide, the rights of citizenship are merely formal, not
substantive.
While it is possible to appreciate Marshall’s notions of citi¬
zenship, the current politics in the United States are such that
substantive equality arguments are likely to be banished to the
realm of utopian visions. Absent some vigorous democratic
movement for change based on outrage stemming from the
badly skewed and unequal distribution of material, political,
and social goods, those who control the American state are likely
to do no more than continue it in its current role as reactive fa¬
cilitator of the market and its institutions.
278 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
«
ernment the instrument of our united purpose to solve for the in¬
beginning to wipe out the line that divides the practical from the
ance of the abuse of power by those who betray for profit the ele¬
purpose.
and the lowest standard of living can be raised far above the level
of mere subsistence.
The test of our progress is not whether we add more to the abun¬
\
metaphor, can provide a way to reintroduce and reinforce
noneconomic values, such as norms of distributive justice or
provision of worker security, into contemporary American po¬
litical ideology. These concepts are realized in a consistent polit¬
ical and material way in other industrialized democracies. For
those who question the wisdom of starting from caretaking and
then expanding to the “larger” word of wage workers, I can only
respond that it is necessary to secure the foundation before we
rehabilitate all that is built upon it.
This argument can be carried to relationships that exist be¬
yond the borders of the United States. A consideration of the
international implications of rethinking the state’s responsibility
with regard to dependency and subsidy is beyond the scope of
this book. Future work, however, may fruitfully explore the
many ways in which our economic and material success is
grounded on the provision of subsidies from other nations:
goods and services that are appropriated through a system in
which Western domination is built on centuries of colonization
and exploitation that to some extent parallels the appropriation
of women’s labor in the family.
Just as the family performs essential but invisible work, and
some necessary tasks are undervalued in the market, various
countries and their citizens’ labor directly contribute to the well¬
being of American multinational corporations, and hence also
to the American state. Often this contribution to market and
state is accomplished at the expense of individual American
workers, as production is shifted abroad to take advantage of
labor systems that pay mere fractions of what homegrown
workers would demand.
The United States has a responsibility to monitor these rela¬
tionships and the corporations that create and exploit them. It
also has a responsibility to acknowledge and heed in fashioning
policy our dependence on the rest of the world.
THE T E N A B'T. E STATE 291
IT
V
WHAT PLAGE F OK FAMILY PRIVACY? 295
r
I. PRIVACIES
pendent entity with a mind and heart of its own, but an associa¬
child.11
was shielded from state intervention and control was not only
specific, weighty, intimate decisions, such as the decision to
beget or bear a child, but also mundane, day-to-day family in¬
teractions.
Although the Supreme Court has brought some aspects of
family privacy into constitutional law, the cases that are most rel¬
evant in discerning the characteristics of family privacy are
state, not federal, decisions.13 The task of the state family pri¬
vacy cases is not to pronounce grand principles or to figure out
how to mesh family privacy with other constitutional limita¬
tions. Instead, these cases address expectations and aspirations
for families, articulating in the process what might be character¬
ized as an ethic or ideology of family privacy. This ideology,
which is noninterventionist, is rooted in an idealization of the
family, and it references the perceived pragmatics of family rela¬
tionships as well as the acknowledged limitations of legal (par¬
ticularly judicial) systems as substitutes for family decision
making. The ideology expresses the norm of nonintervention in
ongoing families—a principle of state restraint because of the
needs of the functioning family.14
The facts of McGuire v. McGuire,15 a Nebraska state court
spousal support case, illustrate the contours of the common-law
doctrine of family privacy. Mrs. McGuire had asked the court to
intervene and require her husband to provide suitable mainte¬
nance and support for her. She did not want a divorce or legal
separation, but instead she sought the enforcement of the terms
of the state-defined marriage contract, which required husbands
to support their wives. Her complaints about her husband’s lack
of adequate support were rather compelling. For example, al¬
though her husband was a fairly wealthy man, she had not re¬
ceived money to buy clothing for several years. Further, she lived
in a house with no indoor bathroom, kitchen sink, or function¬
ing central heating. The Nebraska Supreme Court, while indi-
298 THE AUTONOMY MYTH
the home is maintained and the parties are living as husband and
wife it may be said that the husband is legally supporting his wife
vate parental rights not from explicit textual provisions, but from
the history and functioning of the family itself.19
the idea of stewardship. She uses the child advocates’ claim that
children must be treated a.s “people in their own right” to argue
for laws and policies that focus on children’s welfare.28
Although she does believe that children’s welfare might neces¬
sitate some monitoring of parental authority, Woodhouse
reaches for more than mere control over parents. With the ob¬
jective of children’s welfare as the organizing tool, she advocates
for a more extensive sense of children’s rights—“needs-based
rights.” These rights are not associated with children’s rights to
autonomy or independence, but are the basis for a positive claim
for basic nurture and protection.29 These rights create responsi¬
bility, not only for individual parents, but also for the larger com¬
munity, and require political responses.
To some extent, Woodhouse’s concern with basic-needs
rights reflects my own call for collective responsibility for de¬
pendency. However, the identity of the rights holder and the
source of the right are different in important ways. My claim is a
communal one—entity focused and based on a claim of entitle¬
ment or right originating as a result of the societal work per¬
formed by caretakers.30 Woodhouse’s model is not a
compensatory one, but is based on the status of the child as a fu¬
ture citizen. She positions the child as the claim holder and, in
doing so, conceptually breaks up the family into individual and
therefore potentially competing interests. This paves the way for
claims of collective supervision and monitoring of parental
stewardship.
V. CONCLUSION
Introduction
37. Jack Zipes has conducted extensive research on myths and fairy
tales and concludes that they play a significant role in educating, socializ¬
ing, and civilizing both children and adults. Jack Zipes, Fairy Tale as Myth:
Myth as Fairy Tale 8, 17, passim (University Press of Kentucky, 1994); Jack
Zipes, Happily Ever After: Fairy Tales, Children, and the Culture Industry (Rout-
ledge, 1997)- See also Cuthbertson, supra note at 197.
NOTES TO (*AGES 25-34
3>3
r
i3> !997>Ai5-
3. Even women on welfare themselves perpetuate a feeling of shame
and stigmatize their condition. George W. Bush used the statement of a
woman who had worked her way ofT welfare to illustrate the point: “the
success of it is my children see me go to work every day. And that makes
them go to school every day, because they see mama isn’t staying at home.
President Bush applauded this particular mother by stating, “The ability
3J4 NOTES TO PAGES 34~39
♦
11. See supra note 3 (referring to ideals of hard work and self-sufficiency).
12. Ibid.
13. See Nick Gillespie, “The Kids Are Alright: The White House In¬
vents a Child Care Crisis,” Reason, December 1997, available at http://
reason.com/9801/ed.nick.shtml (last visited June 1, 2003); Dearborn,
“Press Release: Libertarians Give Mixed Reviews to Day Care Reform
Proposals,” Libertarian Party of Michigan, at www.mi.lp.org/press/
112299.htm (last visited June 1, 2003).
14. See Gillespie, supra note 13. It seems as though Gillespie-type argu-
NOTES TO PAGES 39-43 3*5
r
merits are not challenging the mythological role of the family, but still en¬
visioning the individual ideal since it depends on the individual choice of
parents to result in a satisfactory solution.
16. See Kimberly Porrazzo, The Nanny Kit 12 (Penguin Books, updated
ed., 1999). (“Nannies’ salaries vary greatly from region to region. In the
northeast, nannies are often paid $400.$500 or more per week. In Cali¬
fornia, however, the average nanny’s weekly salary is closer to $300-^350
per week. Within Southern California, wages are higher in Los Angeles
County than in Orange County or San Diego County, probably because
Orange and San Diego counties are close to the Mexican border and a
large number of illegal immigrants are seeking domestic work and will ac¬
cept a lower salary.”)
17. See Katherine M. Frank, “Theorizing Yes: An Essay on Feminism,
Law, and Desire,” 101 Columbia Law Review 181, 183-7 (2001).
21. Deborah Belle, The After-School Lives of Children: Alone and with Others
While Parents Work 7 (Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1999). (“The U.S. pub¬
lic school day is substantially shorter than the full-time work day and
shorter than the school day in many other nations of the world. The
school year is also interrupted by frequent holidays, early release days, and
closings for inclement weather, and then concluded with a lengthy sum¬
mer vacation, all of which vastly exceeds the vacation allotments of most
employed parents. Nor are extended day or after-school programs avail¬
able in many communities or to many children who need them.”)
24. See Helburn and Bergmann, supra note 23. (When a family at or near
the poverty level is looking for child care, it will obviously look for the
cheapest available, which is most likely to be unlicensed care; furthermore,
if there are any questions as to the quality, many families in this situation
would resolve them in favor of cheapness.)
25. See Helburn and Bergmann, supra note 23. (Two parents working at
minimum wage, for fifty-two forty-hour weeks, with two preschool chil¬
dren earn $27,962 in disposable income—after taxes. With the official U.S.
poverty-line living expenses set at $17,493, the family only has $10,496 to
spend on child care estimated to cost between $9,980 and $11,870.)
26. See Helburn and Bergmann, supra note 23. (One parent, with two
preschool children, working at minimum wage for fifty-two forty-hour
weeks, with government benefits earns $15,736 in disposable income. With
official U.S. poverty-line living expenses set at $13,898, the mother has
only $1,838 to spend on care estimated to cost between $9,980 and
$11,870.)
31. See Victor R. Fuchs, Women’s Quest for Economic Equality 60-64 (Har¬
vard University Press, 1998) (discussing the hidden costs of children for
women in the workplace); Shultz, supra note 8, at 1881, 1894 (arguing that
women do not choose lower-paying, lower-status jobs because of their
heavier family obligations, but rather that the segregation of women into
these jobs forces women into household labor).
42. See “Making Hay,” New Republic, May 20, 2002, at 9 (pointing out
that President Bush is not keeping with his market-driven approach to
agriculture).
43. See Dick Lugar, “The Farm Bill Charade,” New York Times, January
21, 2002, at A15. (The majority of payments in most states go to the
top tenth of farmers. Farms in just six states will take almost half of the
federal payments. According to the Times, “Ineffective agricultural policy
has, over the years, led to a ritual of overproduction in many crops and
3l8 NOTES TO PAGES ^2~6l
1
its traditional form and function is certainly the goal of some political ac¬
tors.
g. Id. at 5.
10. Ibid, (quoting Andrew Kohut, Pew Research Center for the People
320 NOTES TO PAGES 7^6 79
%
and the Press, “Deconstructing Distrust: How Americans View Govern¬
ment” (1998).
11. Id. at 6.
12. Id. at 10.
13. Id. at 7 (citing Daniel Yankelovich, “How Changes in the Economy
Are Reshaping American Values,” Values and Public Policy [Henry J. Aaron
et al, eds., 1994]). This seems to be particularly ironic given that the impli¬
cations of current economic arrangements on civic health are not seri¬
ously considered in the Commission’s Final Report.
14. National Commission on Civic Renewal, supra note 2, at 20.
15. Council on Civil Society, supra note 1, at 7.
16. National Commission on Civic Renewal, supra note 2, at 13.
17. Id. at 24.
18. Id. at 13.
19. SeeLovingv. Virginia. 87 S.Ct. 1817 (1967) (holding that statues barring
interracial marriage violated the equal protection and due process clauses
of the Fourteenth Amendment). It is interesting to note, however, that
South Carolina and Alabama retained antimiscegenation clauses in their
state constitutions until 1998 and 2000, respectively, despite this Supreme
Court holding.
20. “No State, territory, or possession of the United States, or Indian
tribe, shall be required to give effect to any public act, record, or judicial
proceeding of any other State, territory, possession, or tribe respecting a
relationship between persons of the same sex that is treated as a marriage
under the laws of such other State, territory, possession, or tribe, or a right
or claim arising from such relationship.” Defense of Marriage Act, 28
USC1738C (1996).
21. National Commission on Civic Renewal, supra note 2, at 41.
22. Id.
v
23. This second objection gives rise to some confusion in considerations
of civil society— it is not always clear who is in and who is outside of civil
society. At one point, the Commission defines civil society as “meaning
free markets and private associations,” suggesting that all nongovernmen¬
tal institutions might be considered civil. Id. at 43, n. 16. At another point,
however, civil society is seemingly restricted to “the network of voluntary
associations and activities.” Id. at 39.
notes to pAsges 79-80 321
46. See Authur J. Norton and Louisa F. Miller, United States Depart¬
ment of Commerce, “Marriage, Divorce, and Remarriage in the 1990’s”
!-4 (1992).
5 1- U.
52. Id. at 16.
79. Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and Family 139 (Basic Books,
I9^9)-
80. Id.
85. Center for the Future of Children, “Executive Summary,” The Fu¬
ture of Children: Children and Poverty, Summer/Fall 1997, at 2—3.
93. Id. at 7.
94. National Commission on Civic Renewal, supra note 2, at 24.
95. See Brofenbrenner, supra note 84, at 56; Weinberg, supra note 83, at 1;
Doyle, supra note 83.
96. Kathryn Larin and Elizabeth McNichol, Center on Budget and
Policy Priorities, “Pulling Apart: A State-by-State Analysis of Income
Trends,” www.cbpp.0rg/pa-4.htm (visitedJune 1, 2003).
97. National Commission on Civic Renewal, supra note 2, at 24.
98. Brofenbrenner, supra note 84, at 66.
99. Id.
100. See Nina Bernstein, “Poverty Rate Persists Despite Boom: Twice as
High as Nation. Analysis of Data Shows,” New York Times, October 7,1999,
at Bi.
101. Jeanne Brooks-Gunn and GregJ. Duncan, “The Effects of Poverty
on Children,” The Future of Children: Children and Poverty, Summer/Fall 1997,
at55-
102. Center for the Future of Children, supra note 85, at 3.
103. Id.
104. Brooks-Gunn and Duncan, supra note 101, at 57. This report collects
and assesses the available research in regard to each of these dimensions of
the well-being of children in poverty. The authors conclude drat income
can substantially influence children’s well-being, finding that the associa¬
tions between income and child outcomes are more complex and varied
than is suggested in simple tables. “Family income seems to be more
strongly related to children’s ability and achievement-related outcomes
than to emotional outcomes. In addition, the effects are particularly pro
nounced for children who live below the poverty line for multiple years
and for children who live in extreme poverty.” Id. at 67-8.
106. Id.
107. Id. Even two-parent families are experiencing poverty, so revering
the two-parent family as an ideal economic unit is not the answer.
108. Kristin Downey Grimsley and Jacqueline L. Salmon, “For Working
Parents, Mixed News at Home: Children Praise Them but Note Stress,
Washington Post, September 27, i999> at Ai-
109. Id.
326 NOTES TO PAGES 92-98
«
no. Id.
hi. Id.
112. A recent study by Cornell sociologist Phyllis Moen reports that cou¬
ples that feel burdened by long work hours, demanding jobs, and conflict
between work and personal life report the lowest quality of life among
working couples surveyed. See “Working Couples Burdened by Time at
Work Say Their Lives Are Beset by Stress, Conflict and Overload, Cornell
Sociologist Reports,” Cornell University News, at www.news.cornell.edu/
releases/Jangg/AAAS.couples. strategies.html (last visited June 1, 2003).
113. Richard K. Caputo, “Economic Well-Being in a Youth Cohort,”
Families in Society: The Journal of Contemporary Human Services, January 1,1998,
at 83.
114. John Ehrenberg, Civil Society: The Critical History of an Idea 246 (New
York University Press, 1999), 240.
115. Id. at 247.
116. Id.
3. Trammel v. United States, 445 U.S. 40 (1980); see also Frances E. Olson,
“The Family and the Market: A Study of Ideology and Legal Reform,” 96
Harvard Law Review 1497, 1504-05 (1983). •' *
5. See McGuire v. McGuire, 157 Neb. 226 (Sup. Ct. of Neb. 1953), discussed
in Martha Albertson Fineman, “What Place for Family Privacy?” 67 George
Washington Law Review 1207, 1209 (1999).
6. See Lloyd Cohen, “Rhetoric, the Unnatural Family, and Women’s
Work,” 81 Virginia Law Review 2275, 2286 (1995). I think this argument
raises an important empirical question—do men crave intimacy, not only
sexual, but that of the connection with children? I believe they do, but are
hampered in acting on that need in today’s society, which assigns them to
the workplace as the economic provider.
7. See also Randy Thornhill and Craig Palmer, A Natural History of Rape:
Biological Basis of Sexual Coercion (MIT Press, 2000).
8. Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.S. 158 (1994). Note that most of the de¬
bate about the state’s interest in precluding same-sex couples from the in¬
stitution of marriage focused on the negative effect this would have on
children (this was true in both the Hawaii and Vermont cases). The other
arguments focused on the possibility that same-sex marriage would
weaken “real” marriage as an institution.
9. 127 U.S. 190, 205-6 (1888) (“[M]arriage, as creating the most impor¬
tant relation in life [has] more to do with the morals and civilization of a
people than any other institution . . .”).
10. 98 U.S. 145,165 (1878) (“Upon it society may be said to be built, and
out of its fruits spring social relations and societal obligations and duties,
with which government is necessarily required to deal”).
11. Benjamin Franklin: “only a virtuous people are capable of free¬
dom.” Samuel Adams: “neither the wisest constitution nor the wisest laws
will secure the liberty and happiness of a people whose manners are uni¬
versally corrupt.” John Adams: “our constitution was made only for a
moral and religious people. It is wholly inadequate to the government of
any other.” As quoted in Lynn Wardle, “The Bonds of Matrimony and the
Bonds of Constitutional Democracy,” draft of comments made at Hofstra
University, March 5, 2003 (on file with author), 3.
12. Id.
13. Id.
14. Baker v. State, 744 A.2d 864 (Vt. 1999) (holding that the State of Ver¬
mont may not exclude same-sex couples from the benefits and protections
that its laws provide to opposite-sex married couples).
15. As the Hawaii Supreme Court noted in Baehr v. Lewin, benefits asso¬
ciated with marriage may include (1) a variety of state income tax advan-
328 NOTES TO PAGES I O 5 ~ I I O
«
\
cages, including deductions, credits, rates, exemptions, and estimates; (2)
public assistance from and exemptions relating to the Department of
Human Services; (3) control, division, acquisition, and disposition of com¬
munity property; (4) rights relating to dower, curtsey, and inheritance; (5)
rights to notice, protection, benefits, and inheritance; (6) award of child
custody and support payments in divorce proceedings; (7) the right to
spousal support; (8) the right to enter into premarital agreements; (9) the
right to change of name; (10) the right to file a nonsupport action; (11) post¬
divorce rights relating to support and property division; (12) the benefit of
the spousal privilege and confidential marital communications; (13) the
benefit of the exemption of real property from attachment or execution;
and (14) the right to bring a wrongful death action. Baehr v. Lewin 74 Hawaii
530 (1993)-
16. Some of the critics of civil unions in Vermont, where it is now legal,
cite religious belief. See Julie Deardorlf, “Vermont Is Front Line of Gay
Marriage Fight,” Chicago Tribune, April 3, 2001, at 1. The use of history and
tradition is more common. See also Bowers v. Hardwick and state court deci¬
sions in the 1970s limiting marriages to heterosexuals often assumed mar¬
riage was by definition between a man and a woman; Martha Chamallas,
Introduction to Feminist Legal Theory 265-6 (Aspen Law & Business, 1999), cit¬
ing Baker v. Nelson, 191 N.W.2d 185 (Minn. 1971), Jones v. Hallahan, 501
S.W.2d588 (Ky. 1973), Singer v. Hara, 522 P.2d 1187 (Wash. Ct. App. 1974).
17. See also Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194 (1999); Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530
(i993)-
18. Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530 (1993).
21. John Demos, “Images of the American Family, Then and Now,” in
Changing Images of the Family 43-60 (Virginia Tufte and Barbara Myerhoff,
eds., 1979).
for Same-Sex Marriage,” 1996 BYULaw Review 1; Curt Pham. “Let’s Get
Married in Hawaii: A Story of Conflicting Laws, Same-Sex Couples, and
Marriage,” 30 Family Law Quarterly 727 (1996); Linda Nielsen, “Family
Rights and the Registered Partnership in Denmark,” 4 The International
Journal of Law and the Family 297 (1990).
23. Tavia Simmons and Martin O’Connell, “Married-Couple and
Unmarried-Partner Households: 2000,” Census 2000 Special Reports,
U.S. Census Bureau (issued February 2003); Jason Fields and Lynne M.
Casper, “America’s Families and Living Arrangements: March 2001,” Cur¬
rent Population Reports, 20-537 (2001). Commentators point out that this can
be the result of a number of factors, such as couples’ living longer after
their adult children have “left the nest,” many men and women delaying
marriage and children until they are older than in previous generations,
and the relatively more rapid growth of single-parent families over those
of married parents.
24. Families headed by single mothers account for nearly 7 percent of
all households. Single-mother families increased from 3 million in 1970 to
10 million in 2000. See Jason Fields, “Living Arrangments of Children,”
Current Population Reports (1996).
25. Simmons and O’Connell, supra note 23, at 1.
27. Id.
28. Simmons and O’Connell, supra note 23, at 1.
29. The categories of relatives include husband/wife, natural-born
son/daughter, adopted son/daughter, stepson/stepdaughter, brother/sis¬
ter, father/mother, grandchild, parent-in-law, son-in-law/daughter-
in-law, and “other relative—print exact relationship.” The categories of
nonrelatives include roomer/boarder, housemate/roommate, unmarried
partner, foster child, and other nonrelatives.
30. Id.
31. This book focuses on heterosexual marital relationships simply be¬
cause family law and our political sense of family have been organized
around that particular intimate configuration. Same-sex couples are or¬
ganizing around demands for access to marriage, and this is increasingly a
topic of scholarship.
32. See Simmons and O’Connell, supra note 28.
34. Feliciano v. Rosemar Silver Co., 514 N.E.2d 1095, 1097 (1987)-
35. Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act
of 1996, §101,1996 HR 3734 (1996).
36. Geraldine Sealey, “Marriage Proposal Debate Looms over Bush
Plan to Spend $300 Million Promoting Unions,” at abcnews.go.com/
sections/us/dailynews/marriageo20305.html (visitedJune 1, 2003).
37. Krause et al., supra note 2, at 47.
38. Id.
39. Krause et al., supra note 2, at 533 (on annulment); Lawrence M.
Friedman, A History of American Law 204-08, 498-504 (Simon and Schus¬
ter, 2d ed., 1988) (on desertion).
40. Krause et al., supra note 2, at 534.
41. Weisberg and Appleton, supra note 4, at 533. In any case, such a bill
would only have been available to the wealthiest members of society
42. Id. at 533-4.
43. “Cause” could include adultery (in New York this was the only
cause that justified divorce in 1787), as well as “impotence, adultery, intol¬
erable severity, three years’ willful desertion, and long absence with pre¬
sumption of death” (Vermont in 1798) and “gross misbehavior and
wickedness in either of the parties, repugnant to and in violation of the
marriage covenant” (Rhode Island). Id. at 534.
44. See Krause et al., supra note 2, at 534.
45. Muhammad v. Muhammad, 622 So.2d 1239 (Miss. 1993). See also Weis¬
berg and Appleton, supra note 4, at 549. The supposed special nature of
the marital family is also significant outside of family law. Many other
areas of law incorporate and utilize the concept of the family—tort, crim¬
inal, and property laws have historically distinguished family relationships
from those of “strangers” and established exceptions or alternatives to the
general rules for family members. Such exceptions include the marital
rape exemption and various spousal privileges—domestic violence, tort
immunity, fornication, adultery, cohabitation, etc. These exceptions and
alternatives are based on the belief that a family connection signifies a spe¬
cial relationship, one that justifies a different regulatory regime.
46. See Krause et al., supra note 2, at 534. See also Glenda Riley, Divorce: An
American Tradition 8-29 (University of Nebraska Press, 1991).
47. Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. I (19(47) (the trial judge’s opinion stated,
“Almighty God created the races white, black, yellow, Malay and red, and
NOTES TO PAGE? I I 7 ~ I 2 4 331
r
he placed them on separate continents. And but for the interference with
his arrangement there would be no cause for such marriages. The fact that
he separated the races shows that he did not intend for the races to
mix . . .”); Potter v. Murray City, 760 F.2d 1065 (10th Cir. 1985), cert, denied, 474
U.S. 849 (1988) (“monogamy is inextricably woven into the fabric of our
society. It is the bedrock upon which our culture is built”).
48. Bradwell v. Illinois, 83 US 130 (1873) (saying a woman cannot get ad¬
mitted to the Illinois bar).
49. Blackstone, Commentaries 442-5.
50. See generally Graham v. Graham, 33 F. Supp. 936, 938 (E.D. Mich. 1940)
(holding that a contract between spouses to change the roles of husband
and wife—the essential incidents of the marriage—is void).
51. Beatrice Gottlieb, The Family in the Western World: From the Black Death
to the Industrial Age 90-92 (Oxford University Press, 1993).
52. Krause et al., supra note 2, at 152.
53. See generally June Carbone and Margaret Brinig, “Rethinking Mar¬
riage: Feminist Ideology, Economic Change and Divorce Reform,” 65 Tu-
lane Law Review 953 (1991).
54. Lenore J. Weitzman, The Divorce Revolution 74, 164-7 (Free Press,
1985); Wirth v. Wirth, 38 A.D.2d 611 (App. Div. 1971).
5. “Law in Fifty States: Case Digests’^o Family Law Quarterly 811 (1997).
6. See D. Kelly Weisberg and Susan Frelich Appleton, Modern Family
Law: Cases and Materials 284-5. (Aspen, 2nd ed., 2002). See also Samuel v. Uni¬
versity of Pittsburgh, 375 F. Supp. n 19 (W.D. Pa. 1974), decision to decertify
class vacated (invalidating, on equal protection grounds, university resi¬
dency rules that assigned the husband’s domicile to the wife for determi¬
nation of tuition); Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws § 21 (Supp.
1988) (“rules for the acquisition of a domicile of choice are the same for
both married and unmarried persons”).
7. Stratton v. Wilson, 185 S.W. 522, 532 (1916).
8. Edwardson v. Edwardson, Supreme Court of Kentucky, 798 S.W.2d
941 (1990). See also Uniform Premarital Agreement Act (UPAA), 9C U.L.A.
35 (2001) (premarital agreements are valid unless they are “uncon¬
scionable”).
9. Simeone v. Simeone, 581 A.2d 162 (Pa. 1990).
10. Edwardson v. Edwardson, 798 S.W.2d 941 (1990) (quoting Clark v. Clark,
192 S.W.2dg68, 970 [1946]).
11. Button v. Button, 388 N.W.2d 546 (Wis. 1986).
12. In Re Marriage of Greenwald, 454 N.W.2d 34 (Wis. Ct. App. 1990).
13. American Law Institute, “Principles of the Law of Family Dissolu¬
tion: Analysis and Recommendations” (Tentative Draft No. 4, April 10,
2000) Chapter 7 (Agreements), Topic 2 (Requirements for an Enforceable
Agreement), §7.05 (Procedural Requirements), 88.
14. Id.
15. It also recognizes, however, that the state might want to reserve the
right to oversee and amend these agreements in conformance with public
policy to a much greater degree than is permitted with commercial con¬
tracts that arise in the public sphere of the market.
16. Marvin v. Marvin, 557 P.2d 106 (Cal. 1976).
17. American Law Institute, supra note 13, Chapter 6 (Domestic Part¬
ners), § 6.05 (Allocation of Domestic-Partnership Property), 55. (“Domes¬
tic-partnership property should be divided according to the principles set
forth for the division of marital property in § 4.15 and § 4.16.”)
18. Baker v. State, 744 A.2d 864 (Vt. 1999).
26. Id. at 3.
27. Id. at 4 (emphasis in original).
28. www.now.org/issues/right/promise/quotes.html (visited June 1,
2003).
29. Laura Sanchez, “The Implementation of Covenant Marriage
in Louisiana.” Virginia Journal of Social Policy and the Law, 9(1) 194 (Fall
2001).
30. La. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 91273(A).
36. There are some moves to do this in the context of divorce already.
See Ruprecht v. Ruprecht, 252 NJ.Super.230, 599 A.2d 604 (Ch. Div. 1991) (al¬
lowing for suit for intentional infliction of emotional harm without physi¬
cal injury in the context of a divorce). See also Hakkila v. Hakkila, 112 N.M.
172, 812 P.2d 1320 (App. 1991).
37. Other areas of law that would substitute for (or be supplemented by)
the abolition of marriage and divorce rules would include bankruptcy, fi¬
duciary responsibility, equity, and ethics.
41. More specifically, these areas were set aside and governed by special
rules regulating marriage.
42. Historically, reasons for annulment had to do with sex and repro¬
duction. Typical grounds included inability to consummate the relation¬
ship, lying about pregnancy or about fertility, having a venereal disease,
and so on. The ability to function in an appropriate manner sexually is
considered by the law to be an “essential” aspect of the marriage relation¬
ship. Without that ability, the courts could determine that a real marriage
had not taken place—it was void.
43. People v. Liberta, 474 N.E.2d 567 (N.Y. 1984), cert, denied, 471 U.S. 1020
(x9^5) (holding that the marital exemption for rape no longer applies).
44. I Hale P.C. 629, as quoted in Warren u. State, 336 S.E.2d 221 (1985).
45. These rules include not only the laws of marriage and divorce, but
also large areas of criminal and civil law that bolster the institution of mar¬
riage and penalize sexual affiliations that do not conform to the marriage
model, e.g., laws against prostitution fornication, adultery, and cohabita¬
tion, as well as inheritance and probate laws, property rules, and tax laws
NOTES TO PA&ES I37-I4.O 335
IT
95 b 954-7-
49. Levy v. Louisiana, Supreme Court of the United States, 1968, 88 S.Ct.
1509, 20 L.Ed.2d 436 (denial of damages to “illegitimate” children as a re¬
sult of the wrongful death of their mother is a violation of the Equal Pro¬
tection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment).
50. Gomez v. Perez, 409 U.S. 535, 93 S.Ct. 872, 35 L.Ed.2d 56 (1973) (non-
marital child has a right to paternal support); Weber v. Aetna Casualty &
Surety Co., 406 U.S. 164, 92 S.Ct. 1400, 31 L.Ed.2d 768 (1972) (state law that
denied worker’s compensation benefits to nonmarital dependent children
is a violation of the Equal Protection and Due Process clauses of the Four¬
teenth Amendment); Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U.S. 68 (1968).
51. Clark v. Jeter, 486 U.S. 456 (1988).
336 NOTES TO PAGES 146-152
t
%
Equality and Family
1. Harry D. Krause et al., Family Law: Cases, Comments and Questions 113
(4th ed., West Group, 1998).
2. Ferguson v. Ferguson, 639 So. 2d 921 (Miss. 1994) (en banc).
3. D. Kelly Weisberg and Susan Frelich Appleton, Modern Family Law:
Cases and Materials 663 (Aspen Law and Business, 2nd ed., 2002).
4. This is manifest in the historic designation of the “separate spheres”
in common law. The family and other institutions of care and altruism oc¬
cupied the private (female) sphere, while the market and state were in the
public (male) domain. See Bradwell v. Illinois, 83 U.S. (16 Wall.) 130, 132
(1873) (Bradley, J., concurring) (commenting “ [t] hat God designed the
sexes to occupy different spheres of action, and that it belonged to men to
make, apply, and execute the laws”).
5. A traditional family is typically imagined: a husband and wife—
formally married and living together—with their biological children. The
husband performs as the head of the household, providing economic sup¬
port and discipline for the dependent wife and children, who correspond¬
ingly owe him duties of obedience and respect.
6. Marriage has shaped women’s dependency responsibilities. Their
caretaking responsibilities often prevent them from being able to take ad¬
vantage of opportunities in the workplace. Traditionally the uncompen¬
sated tasks of caretaking are placed with women while men pursue careers
that provide economically for the family but also enhance their individual
career or work prospects.
7. Women’s Rights Convention, “Declaration of Sentiments,” 1848.
8. Frances E. Olsen, “The Myth of State Intervention in the Family,”
18 University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform 835 (1985).
9. See, e.g, Uniform Marriage and Divorce Act (UMDA) §§ 205, 207
(amended 1971 and 1973), 9A U.L.A. 181, 183 (1998) (limiting the ability of
minors to marry and prohibiting pjarriages between close relations—
siblings or parent and child, respectively)./ .
10. See, e.g, Uniform Marital Property Act § 4, 9A U.L.A. 116 (1998)
(classifying property of spouses).
14. See generally Martha Fineman and Roxanne Mykitiuak, The Public
Nature of Private Violence (Roudedge, 1994). Increasingly, such critiques have
been accepted, and intervention in certain domestic situations has become
more common. There has been a change in the way society reacts to
spousal violence, for example. Marital exemptions to rape statutes have
been successfully attacked and repealed in many states. Police are trained
to respond to domestic calls and to take them seriously or risk legal re¬
sponses. Sexual intimacy is no longer considered to carry with it a corre¬
sponding right to rape or batter. This change in societal perception about
male family prerogative is largely the result of the feminist movement and
its egalitarian premises. I do not mean to imply that there is now freedom
from abuse in intimate situations; rather I want to indicate that the ideo¬
logical underpinnings for such violence have been successfully challenged.
«
stating that feminism is ignored. One can find at least some token gesture
to a feminist perspective in liberal scholarship in virtually all academic
areas. But knowledge of feminism remains rudimentary. A few well-worn
ideas attributed to a few well-recognized names may be a marginal part of
the discourse, but beyond this, most legal scholars seem unfamiliar with
the rich and varied work that has been produced by feminists over the past
several decades.
2. Recent feminist literature in a variety of disciplines has focused on
this process. See Judith Buder, Gender Trouble xiv-xv (Roudedge, 1999).
3. There is no recognition that there may be more than two sexes, let
alone many variations and combinations of gender attributes.
7. 83 U.S. 130 (1873) (plaintiff denied admission to the bar solely be¬
cause of her sex).
12. Id. at 500 (noting also that “the least divisive issues in family law,
such as domestic violence, have been those that have been resolved by ref¬
erence to familiar principles outside of family law. By the same token, the
most visible conflicts outside family law, such as the debate among femi¬
nists over maternity leave, have related to gender roles”).
13. Id.
14. See id. at 475. Bartlett addresses the tensions within feminism in re¬
gard to the areas she does discuss. In doing so, she of necessity also touches
on marriage and the child-support system (which is the privatized solution
for economic dependency and, therefore, tied to any discussion of wel¬
fare). Perhaps this demonstrates how difficult it is to address any one area
of central concern in family law without bumping into others, because
they are related conceptually and politically as well as in practice.
15. Id.
16. This is not to suggest that there is no sex discrimination remaining
in the workplace. Rather, the nature or character of discrimination has
changed. It is not the fact of being a woman that typically places one in the
margins of the workplace, but the culturally and socially imposed conse¬
quences of sex (gender) that are incompatible with the culture of the work¬
force.
17. See Arlie Russell Hochschild, The Time Bind: When Work Becomes Home
and Home Becomes Work 117-21 (Metropolitan Books, 1997) (men who asked
for parental leave were seen as not dedicated to their career); see also Gene
Koretz, “Hazardous to Your Career: The Risks of Taking Unpaid
Leaves,” Business Week, January 17, 2000, at 26.
18. Marilyn J. Essex and Marjorie H. Klein, “The Wisconsin Parental
Leave Study: The Role of Fathers” in Parental Leave and Child Care: Setting a
Research and Policy Agenda (Janet Shibley Hyde and Marilyn J. Essex, eds.,
Temple University Press, 1991).
NOTES TO PAGES I 7 5 _ I 7 9
340
«
19. These concepts helped to make it clear that historically the law has
treated women unequally and unjustly in the contexts of divorce, repro¬
duction, and family violence, contexts in which women were victimized to
begin with. These contexts are also areas in which we are clear(er) about
our aspirations for society and its institutions in regard to women’s quest
for equality. Victor R. Fuchs, Women’s Quest for Economic Equality (Harvard
University Press, 1988), 72 (noting that despite equality, children are still
predominately the concern of women).
20. These concepts of unequal worth and unequal ability are very diffi¬
cult to discuss in noncondescending or -patronizing ways. See Barbara
Bennett Woodhouse, “The Dark Side of Family Privacy,” 67 George Wash¬
ington Law Review 1247, 1250, n. 21 (1999) (advocating use of the “steward¬
ship” model and the “notion of children’s ‘need-based rights’ ”).
21. Foundations of the Economic Approach to Law 410 (Avery Wiener Katz,
ed., 1998).
24. Id.
25. Id. Katz states that, due to the complexity inherent in the family,
some may see economic modeling as inappropriate. In this regard, he rec¬
ognizes there are “competing disciplines,” specifically psychology and bi¬
ology. Feminism is not mentioned as a competing discipline.
26. This does not mean that economists have not used their model to
predict and explain family behavior or to argue for policy (see, e.g, Gary
Becker). Id. at 410-39.
24. See Richard Collier, “Waiting Till Father Gets Home: The Recon¬
structing of Fatherhood in Family Law,” Social and Legal Studies 4(1), 8 (1995)
(“He [father] is marked by all the trappings of a benign and safe/domesti¬
cated masculinity—a masculinity pervaded by the dualism of a
public/private divide which legitimated his absence from childcare whilst
simultaneously maintaining the structural supports whence he derived his
economic power”).
25. The traditional male preoccupation with the workplace has also
been characterized as “breadwinner masculinity.” Men are seen as eco¬
nomic providers and women are seen as caretakers. The law sanctions the
philosophy of male physical absence from the family in order to make
money. See Collier, supra note 24, at 8.
26. See Parke and Brott, “Lazy Dads and Deadbeat Dads,” in Throw¬
away Dads, supra note 10, at 65-9.
44. See Sheldon, supra note 8, at 21. Sheldon further asserts that if advo¬
cates of men’s rights are serious about problems facing individual unwill¬
ing fathers, then they should also advocate that children be considered the
responsibility not just of their parents, but also of society as a whole.
picture of a girl playing soccer, asking her mom who is the “crazy guy” in
the stands cheering for her. Her mother replies that this is her father. The
advertisement pledges, “Promise Keepers wants to help you be the man
your family needs you to be.”)
47. See Fineman, supra note 46, at 221.
48. Institute for Women’s Policy Research, “Research-in-Brief” (March
1999) -
49. See the Honorable Evelyn Lynn, “Prepared Testimony of the Hon¬
orable Evelyn Lynn,” Florida House of Representatives on Behalf of the
National Conference of State Legislatures Before the Senate Committee
on Finance Subcommittee on Social Security and Family Policy (July 25,
2000) (LEXIS, Federal News Service) see also Fineman, supra note 46, at 217
(poor and unemployed men have trouble providing for themselves, much
less a family).
50. Institute for Women’s Policy Research, supra note 48, at 6.
\
7. Id.
8. David de Carvalho, “The Social Contract Renegotiated: Protecting
Public Values in the Age of Contracting,” 2, at www.sprc.unsw.edu.
au/nspc200i/NSPC%20200iPapers/deCarvalho.pdf (last visited June 1,
2003).
9. Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 17 (1979) (Requirement of a
Bargain—the formation of a contract requires mutual assent).
10. See generally Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Basic Books,
1974)-
11. An influential exposition of this perspective is found in George
Gilder, Wealth and Poverty 63 (Basic Books, 1981). Also illustrative
are the debates concerning the revision of the welfare system.
See Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act of
1996, Pub. L. No. 104-103, § 101, no Stat. 2105, 2110-12 (1996).
12. See generally ]o\m Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Belknap Press, 1971).
13. John Locke, “An Essay Concerning the True Original, Extent, and
End of Civil Government” (Chapter 11, No. 140) (George Bonham, 1798).
14. See Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender and the Family (Basic Books,
1989)-
15. Eva Feder Kittay, Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Depen¬
dency 76 (Routledge, 1998).
16. Martha L.A. Fineman, “Dependencies,” in Women and Welfare: The¬
ory and Practice in the United States and Europe (Nancy J. Hirschmann and Ul-
rike Liebert, eds., 2001); Martha L. A. Fineman, “Contract and Care”
(Symposium on the Structures of Care Work) 76 Chicago Kent Law Review
1403-40 (2001); Martha L.A. Fineman, ‘Why Marriage?’ Virginia Journal of
Social Policy and the Law 239-71 (2001); Martha L.A. Fineman, “Cracking
the Foundational Myths: Independence, Autonomy, and Self-Sufficiency”
(Symposium: Gender, Work and Family Project Inaugural Feminist Legal
Theory Lecture) 8 American University Journal of Gender, Social Policy and the
Law 13-29 (2000); Martha L.A. Fineman, “The Family in Civil Society”
(Civil Society Symposium) 75 Chicago Kpnt Law Review 531-54 (2000);
Martha L.A. Fineman, “What Place for Family Privacy?” 67 George Wash¬
ington Law Review 1207-24 (1999); Martha L.A. Fineman, “The Inevitabil¬
ity of Dependency and the Politics of Subsidy” (Symposium on Welfare
Reform) 9 Stanford Law and Policy Review 89-99 (1998); Martha L.A. Fine-
man, “The Nature of Dependenciesv and Welfare Reform” (Symposium
on Ethics, Public Policy, and the Future of the Family) 36 Santa Clara Law
NOTES TO PACES. 215 — 219 347
17. John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement 10-11 (Erin Kelly, ed.,
Harvard University Press, 2001).
21. Id.
«
members. Political power is given first ‘into the hands of the society, and
therein to the governors whom the society has set over itself, with this ex¬
press or tacit trust: that it shall be employed for their good and the preser¬
vation of their property’ ” (II, 171; see also II, 243). While the creation of the
“Legislative” (the “soul” of the commonwealth) is “the first and funda¬
mental act of society” (II, 212), the body politic is created “by barely agree¬
ing to unite into one political society” (II, 99). Consent to membership in
the body politic must be unanimous (“by the consent of every individual”
[II, 96]), for “only a person’s own consent can remove that individual from
the state of nature. But this consent entails, Locke believes, consent to rule
by the majority of the members in all subsequent matters (including, of
course, the creation of government)” (internal footnotes removed). A.
John Simmons, “Political Consent,” in The Social Contract Theorists, supra
note 1, at 127.
3. I find in the course of my teaching that law students are very at¬
tached to the idea of contract. Many would use it to resolve all sorts of dif¬
ficult social policy and economic resource issues. The idea of consent is
particularly potent (she or he “asked for it”). See generally Restatement
(Second) of Contracts §§1, 3 (1979) (contract, agreement, and bargain de¬
fined).
7. See, e.g., NLRB v. Burns International Security Services, Inc., 406 U.S. 272
(!972) (The Supreme Court emphasized the importance of freedom of
contract in its decision that it was improper to hold a successor employer
to the substantive terms of a collective bargaining agreement that it had
neither expressly nor implicitly assumed).
NOTES TO P A (3 E S -2 20-224
349
9. James Boyle, “Legal Realism and the Social Contract: Fuller’s Pub¬
lic Jurisprudence of Form, Private Jurisprudence of Substance,” 78 Cornell
Law Review 371 (1993).
13. Id. at 97. He proposes a “simple theory of inequality and the social
contract,” which is based on two mechanisms: redistribution receives “less
political support in an unequal society than in a more homogenous one
. . . [and a] lower rate of redistribution, in turn, increases inequality of fu¬
ture income due to wealth constraints on investment in human or physical
capital.” Id. at 119. He concludes that these mechanisms have produced
“two stable steady-states, the archetypes for which could be the United
States and Western Europe: one with high inequality yet low redistribu¬
tion, the other with the reverse configuration.” Id. He concludes his article
by stating: “the original question of why the social contract differs across
countries, and whether these choices are sustainable in the long run, re¬
mains an important topic for further research.” Id. It seems that this issue
is the one being played out in current European politics. See, e.g., Robert
Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies, “Recasting the European Welfare
State: Options, Constraints, Actors” (1998-99 European Forum), at
www.fue.it/RSCAS/Research/EuropeanForum/EF_1998-1999.shtml
(last visited June 1, 2003); Peter Flora, “Welfare State Analysis” (Research
Programme 1996-1999-Research Department I), at www.mzes.uni-
mannheim.de/res_prog_e/fb_abio6. html (last visited June 1, 2003).
18. See e.g., the relevantly named Personal Responsibility and Work Op¬
portunity Reconciliation Act, Pub. L. No. 104-103, § 101, no Stat. 2105,
2110—12 (1996). See also Linda McClain, in Homo Economicus, Fineman and
Dougherty (eds.) forthcoming (2004).
22. See Fineman, supra note 19, at 177 (“The Limits of Privacy—The
Public Family”).
23. See chapter one.
24. See, e.g, Owen Fiss, “The Autonomy of Law” 3-4, at www.
yale.edu/lawweb/lawfac/fiss/efiss.pdf (last visited June 1, 2003) (“any
well-functioning market needs law . . . [t]he market also needs an institu¬
tion that can interpret and implement relevant rules of law: a judiciary”).
25. See the Uniform Commercial Code (U.C.C.) § 2-302 (2000) (dis¬
cussing court treatment of an unconscionable contract or clause).
26. 1 he U.C.C., recognizes background conditions in several different
forms. U.C.C. § 1-205 (2000) (Course of Dealing and Usage of Trade: “A
course of dealing is a sequence of previous conduct between the parties to
a particular transaction which is fairly to be regarded as establishing a
common basis of understanding for interpreting their expressions and
other conduct. ... A usage of trade is gny practice or method of dealing
having such regularity of observance in a plaCo, vocation or trade as to jus¬
tify an expectation that it will be observed with respect to the transaction in
question”).
Doctrine of the U.C.C.,” 29 Duquesne Law Review 221 (1991) (arguing for a
broad interpretation of § 2-615, with greater consideration of background
conditions especially due to the relational nature of the relevant con¬
tracts). Jeremy Waldron argues that in order for agreements and transac¬
tions between individuals, or between an individual and the state, to be
operational, there needs to be a context of “rights” upon which the agree¬
ments are based—in other words, a fallback position. Jeremy Waldron,
“When Justice Replaces Affection: The Need for Rights,” in Liberal Rights:
Collected Papers, 1981-1991, 370-91 (Cambridge University Press, 1993).
Waldron’s “rights” represent the background conditions upon which indi¬
viduals can reasonably rely in the event that goodwill and affection fail in
interpersonal relation. Id.
(noting that the changes in the workplace are creating a situation in which
all workers are experiencing the problems and dilemmas that have tradi¬
tionally faced women).
40. But see id. at 1925 (noting the growing number of contingent and
temporary workers working without benefits).
42. Many of the ways in which the state has participated in changing
the historic premises of the social contract are discussed in chapter four.
They include increased legal recognition of and response to domestic
abuse and neglect; removal of common-law interspousal tort immunity,
which precluded one spouse from recovering from the other for negli¬
gently inflicted injuries; no-fault divorce statutes; changes in the workplace
that acknowledge women’s ability to bargain and conduct business; the
courts’ changing approach to the validity of prenuptial agreements; in¬
creased legal recognition of nonmarital relationships between sexual affil¬
iates; the legal entitlement of nonmarital children to benefits historically
reserved for their marital counterparts; and a growing acceptance of a
contractual view of marriage, based on the parties’ equal status. See chap¬
ter four.
49. See Eva Kittay, Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency
76 (Routledge, 1999); see also Victor R. Fuchs, Women’s Quest for Economic
Equality 60-4, 133-4 (Harvard University Press, 1988).
I996)-
39. See id. at 56.
40. See id. at 58.
41. Poverty may be increasing because of the change from blue-collar
NOTES TO PAGES 256-257
356
t
\
to white-collar jobs that took place between the 1970s and 1980s, a change
from which workers have not completely recovered. See Caplow, supra note
30, at 63. Caplow questions whether there even is a crisis of the family: he
argues that although Americans have been told the family is in crisis, they
tend to see their own families as happy and successful.
42. U.S. Department of Labor, “Futurework: Trends and Challenges
for Work in the 21st Century” (visited June 1, 2003), atwww.dol.gov/asp/
programs/history/herman/reports/futurework/report.htm
43. Id.
44. Id.
45. See Timothy M. Smeeding and Lee Rainwater, “Comparing Living
Standards Across Nations, Real Incomes at the Top, the Bottom, and the
Middle,” Luxembourg Income Study (February 2002); Jeanne Brooks-Gunn
and Greg J. Duncan, “The Effects of Poverty on Children,” The Future of
Children: Children and Poverty, Summer/Fall 1997, at 55.
46. See Center for the Future of Children, “Executive Summary,” The
Future of Children: Children’s Poverty, Summer/Fall 1997, at 3.
47. Ibid.
48. Brooks-Gunn and Duncan, supra note 45, at 57. This report collects
and assesses the available research in regard to each of these dimensions of
the well-being of children in poverty. The authors conclude that income
can substantially influence children’s well-being, finding the associations
between income and child outcomes are more complex and varied than
suggested in simple tables. “Family income seems to be more strongly re¬
lated to children’s ability and achievement-related outcomes than to emo¬
tional outcomes. In addition, the effects are particularly pronounced for
children who live below the poverty line for multiple years and for children
who live in extreme poverty.” Id. at 67-8.
49. See Louis Uchitelle, “The American Middle, Just Getting By,” New
York Times, August 1, 1999 at BUi (citing the U.S. Census Bureau, which
calculates the median family incornp between $46,500 and $50,000).
50. Ibid, at BU13 (citing the U.S. Census Bureau) (families were working
3,860 hours in 1997—up from 3,236 in 1979).
51. Ibid.
52. Ibid. See also Anne Phillips, Which Equalities Matter? 62-3 (Blackwell,
1999) (Phillips argues that television is a necessity in a society that derives
its culture from TV programs, and that if one does not have a car, one
lacks the means to access basic amenities).
NOTES TO PA feES -257-259 357
r
55- Id.
56. Id. Even two-parent families are experiencing poverty, so revering
the two-parent household as an ideal economic unit is not the answer. In¬
deed, two-parent families are working harder than before, when there was
only one breadwinner, but they are still getting paid the same. See Harriet
Johnson Brackey, “Survey: Workplace Is More Demanding,” Herald, Feb¬
ruary 7, 1998, iC.
57. See Schultz, supra note 10, at 1926 (discussing the incidence and ram¬
ifications of increasing wage inequality).
58. Id.; see also David Leonhardt, “Did Pay Incentive Cut Both Ways?”
New York Times, April 7, 2002, at Ci (revealing the exorbitant income—up
to $154 billion—that many chief executive officers of leading corporations
enjoy, even despite company failures).
2003)
62. Lee Rainwater and Timothy M. Smeeding, “Doing Poorly: The
Real Income of American Children in a Comparative Perspective,”
Maxwell School of Citizenship and Public Affairs (1995), 18.
65. Although voluntary charity and philanthropy are not the objects of
the social contract configuration with which I am dealing, it is important
to point out that they prove to be no substitutes for governmental man¬
dates when it comes to business responsibility. Inventors and investors have
accumulated huge fortunes, but such financial success has not make their
holders socially uncomfortable. Giving is relatively miserly and much
more narrowly directed than it was at the turn of the last century, which
was also an era of capital consolidation and transformation. Today, phi-
358 NOTES TO PAGES 259-267
*
-V
67. See generally Schultz, supra note 10, at 1922-23 (discussing how work¬
place restructuring trends can create worker competition and result in ha¬
rassment and discrimination).
68. See Clark Freshman, “Re-Visioning the Dependency Crisis and the
Negotiators Dilemma: Reflections on the Sexual Family and the Mother
Child Dyad,” 22 Law and Social Inquiry 97 (1997) (reviewing Fineman, The
Neutered Mother).
69. Schultz also argues for a living wage, the right to work, empowering
work conditions, and reduced hours for all workers. Schultz, supra note 10,
1942-57-
4. See Justin Fox, “Here We Go Again,” Fortune (May 12, 2003), 64-71
(calling Reagan’s policy of supply-side economics “dead wrong” and in¬
voking George H. W. Bush as critic of his son’s recent plans).
7. Joel Bakan, Just Words: Constitutional Rights and Social Wrongs 46 (Uni¬
versity of Toronto Press, 1997).
8. Ibid., 9-10.
9. See, e.g, Kathleen E. Mahoney, “The Constitutional Law of Equal¬
ity in Canada,” 44 Maine Law Review 229 (1992), at 230.
behind.”
13. For a brilliant analysis of how these ideas can be used by feminists in
the welfare context, see Martha T. McCluskey, Subsidized Lives and the
Ideology of Efficiency,” 8 American University Journal of Gender, Social Policy
average of 12.1 in 1982, when the national trend toward expansion ap¬
peared to level off substantially short of the recommended goals. During
this same period, writes McCluskey, benefits and coverage in many states
expanded as a result of changes in administrative and judicial interpreta¬
tions of statutes. Ibid,., at 684. The changes in aspirations for the state that
occurred during the Reagan era meant that in the 1990s, employers’ cries
that the expansion of benefits was a “crisis” fell on fertile ears. From 1989
to 1997, states heeded the demands of employers and insurers rather than
labor groups and other representatives of injured workers, and enacted
legislation that substantially limited workers’ compensation. McCluskey
describes the justification for this revamping as reducing costs for insurers.
Id., 700.
17. Sonya Michel, “A Tale of Two States: Race, Gender, and
Public/Private Welfare Provision in Postwar America,” 9 Tale Journal of
Law and Feminism 127 (1997).
18. United Nations General Assembly, December 10, 1948, G.A. Res.
217A, 3GAOR, Resolutions (A/810), at 71.
20. Adopted November 22,1969. 1144 U.N.T.S. 123; OAS Treaty Series
No. 36; Basic Documents Pertaining to Human Rights in the Inter-
American System, OEA/Ser.L.V/II.71, Doc. 6 rev. 1, at 25 (1988).
26. Ibid.
27. See, e.g., Protocol to the American Convention on Human Rights,
(San Salvador), November 17, 1988, OAS Treaty Series No. 69, 28 Interna¬
tional Legal Materials 156 (1989), Article 17, Protection of the Elderly
(“Everyone has the right to special protection in old age”), and Article 18, Pro¬
tection of the Handicapped (“Everyone affected by a diminution of his
physical or mental capacities is entitled to receive special attention designed to
help him achieve the greatest possible development of his personality”)
(emphasis added).
29. See, e.g, United Nations General Assembly, December 10,1948. G.A.
Res. 217A, 3GAOR, Resolutions (A/810), Article 25 (“Everyone has the
right to a standard of living adequate for the health and well-being of him¬
self and of his family, including . . . medical care and necessary social ser¬
vices, and the right to security in the event of. . . sickness [or] disability”).
34. /</.,§26.
35. See Ann-Marie Slaughter, “A Typology of Transjudicial Communi¬
cation,” 29 University of Richmond Law Review 99 (1994)-
36. Ruth Bader Ginsburg and Deborah Jones Merritt, “Affirmative Ac¬
tion: An International Human Rights Dialogue,” 21 Cardozo Law Review
39. See, e.g., National Child Benefit, “Canada Child Tax Benefit for July
2003,” at www.nationalchildbenefit.ca/ncb/govtofcan4.shtml (visited
June 1, 2003); Columbia University, “Tax Day: How Do America’s Child
Benefits Compare?” Clearinghouse on International Developments in
Child, Youth and Family Policies, Issue Brief, Spring 2002, at www.
childpolicyintl.0rg/issuebrief/issuebrief4.pdf (visited June 1, 2003);
Health Canada Online, “Canada’s Health Care System at a Glance,”
(November 28, 2002) at www.hc-sc.gc.ca/english/media/releases/2002/
health_act/glance.html (visited June 1, 2003); “International Forum on
Common Access to Health Care Services” (January 31, 2003) at
http://social, regeringen.se/forum/pdf/ftnal_statement.pdf (visitedJune
1, 2003); European Commission, Directorate-General XXII, Education,
Training and Youth, “Press Release: Financial Support for Students in
Higher Education in Europe,” at www.eurydice.org/News/Communique/
en/Question_ cles_EN.pdf (visited June 1, 2003); KAM International,
“Canadian Education,” aiwww.kaminternational.com/index.asp (visited
June 1, 2003).
43. See, e.g, Elinor Burkett, The Baby Boon: How Family-Friendly America
Cheats the Childless (The Free Press, 2002).
45. See generally Vicki Schultz, “Life’s Work,” 100 Columbia Law Review
[88i, 1942-57 (arguing for a living wage, the right to work, empowering
work conditions, and reduced hours for all workers).
NOTES TO PA6ES 293-295 363
at 189-91.
mental, Justice Goldberg noted that judges must look at the “traditions
and (collective) conscience of our people to determine whether a principle
is so rooted ... as to be deemed fundamental.” Id.., at 493. Although mar¬
ital privacy is not explicidy addressed in the Constitution, to the dismay of
Justice Stewart, it was embraced as a fundamental right. See id. (Justice
Stewart dissenting.)
7. Id. at 486.
8. Id. Justice Douglas, concerned that the use of contraceptives was
what was prohibited, asked, “[W] ould we allow the police to search the sa¬
cred precincts of marital bedrooms for telltale signs of the use of contra¬
ceptives? The very idea is repulsive to the notions of privacy surrounding
the marriage relationship.” Id.
9. Id. at 495.
10. Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972). Laurence Tribe has stated that
the “right of access to contraceptive technology affirmed in Eisenstadt”
was not limited to married couples. Indeed, in Eisenstadt, the court declared
that just such a distinction between married and single persons was uncon¬
stitutional. Tribe further asserted that the court’s decision could hardly be
said to have revolved around marriage or the family. See Laurence H. Tribe,
American Constitutional Law 1423 (2d ed., Foundation Press, 1988).
11. Eisenstadt, supra note 1 o, at 453.
12. The fact that the cloak, as it was spun out, had certain holes does not
detract from the basic point that it was tailored for individual and not entity
protection. See Planned Parenthood of Central Missouri v. Danforth, 428 U.S. 52
(t976)- (“The obvious fact is that when the wife and the husband disagree
on this decision [abortion], the view of only one of the two marriage part¬
ners can prevail. Inasmuch as it is the woman who physically bears the
child and who is the more directly and immediately affected by the preg¬
nancy, as between the two, the balance weighs in her favor.”)
(I991)-
14. The law claims to be absent in the private sphere and has histori¬
cally refused to intervene in ongoing family relations. Elizabeth M.
Schneider, “The Violence of Privacy,” 23 Connecticut Law Review 973, 976
(1991). See also Nadine Taub and Elizabeth M. Schneider, “Perspectives on
Women’s Subordination and the Role of Family Law” in The Politics of
Law: A Progressive Critique 121 (D. Kairys, ed., Pantheon Books, 1982).
15. McGuire v. McGuire, 157 Neb. 226 (1953).
16. Id. at 238. There are many other contemporary cases embodying
this principle of family privacy. Tort law has traditionally been held inap¬
plicable to injuries inflicted by one family member on another. Under doc¬
trines of interspousal and parent-child immunity, courts have consistently
refused to allow recoveries for injuries that would be compensatable but
for the fact that they occurred in the private realm. In the same way, crim¬
inal law has failed to punish intentional injuries to family members. This
principle can also be seen in common-law and statutory definitions of
rape that continue to carve out a special exception for a husband’s forced
intercourse with his wife. Furthermore, wife beating was initially omitted
from the definition of criminal assault on the ground that a husband had
the right to chastise his wife. See Schneider, supra note 14, at 976.
23. The contrived ties are those the law constructs between biological
strangers through such devices as marriage (which creates husband and
wife) or adoption (which creates parent [s] and child). Ties of a “natural”
nature are those of consanguinity, although only some of these family ties
are reinforced by law in modern societies. Interestingly, while parents have
a legal obligation to their minor children, adult children are not generally
responsible for their parents.
nard v. Hill, 125 U.S. 190 (1888). Marriage “is an institution in the mainte¬
nance of which in its purity the public is deeply interested, for it is the
foundation of the family and of society, without which there would be nei¬
ther civilization nor progress.” Id. at 211.
25. I am not asserting that this is how families actually operate; rather,
this image is aspirational or idealized. Law certainly reflects a bias for the
reproductive unit as the appropriate family form, as evidenced by the fact
that the basic family relationships in our jurisprudence are those of hus¬
band and wife and parent and child. Those outside of these specified rela¬
tionships will often analogize their intimate relationships to one of these
paradigmatic ones in order to argue for benefits conferred upon the tradi¬
tional family.
26. For a historical account of parental rights, see generally Barbara Ben¬
nett Woodhouse, “Who Owns the Child? Meyer and Pierce and the Child
as Property,” 33 William and Mary Law Review 995 (1992). For a discussion of
the modern trend in parental rights, see Woodhouse, “A Public Role in the
Private Family: The Parental Rights and Responsibilities Act and the Pol¬
itics of Child Protection and Education,” 57 Ohio State Law Journal 393
(1996).
27. In “Hatching the Egg: A Child Centered Perspective on Parents
Rights,” 14 Cardozo Law Review 1747 (1993), Barbara B. Woodhouse first ad¬
vocated this new approach to the parent-child relationship, terming it the
“generist perspective.” It is based on the view that the nurturing of the
next generation is the touchstone of the family. An adult s relationship
with children is one of trusteeship rather than ownership. Adults’ “rights”
of control and custody yield to the less-adversarial notions of obligation to
provide nurturing, authority to act on the child s behalf, and standing to
participate in the collaborative planning to meet the child s needs. For
more on the generist perspective, see Woodhouse, “ ‘Out of Children s
Needs, Children’s Rights’: The Child’s Voice in Defining the Family,” 8
Brigham Young University Journal of Public law 321 (1994)-
28. Woodhouse, “Out of Children’s Needs, Children’s Rights,” supra
29. Id.
30. The claim is that caretaking is society-preserving work and entitled
to subsidy for that reason. See Fineman, Neutered Mother, at 394.
32. This is the position of the nuclear family today. It is afforded pri¬
vacy, and for the state to intervene, it must provide sufficient justification.
For more on this, see Fineman, supra note 2, at 968.
34. For example, marital rape and domestic violence would be treated
under the same set of rules that would apply to legal strangers (which is
what they become without or outside the family label).
35. Perhaps this is why so many scholars neglect the family. This is also
an illustration of the way in which we are fixated on gender relations, the
way that ordering (symbolically or otherwise) the relationship of sexual af¬
filiates dominates our attention and distorts analyses in regard to other re¬
lationships.
36. I recognize that this will happen in some cases, but this realization
should not provide the operative assumption for parent-child relation¬
ships. If it becomes the operative assumption, it creates a culture for state
intervention and control.
V
Index
330n47 173
Apel, Susan B., 324n82 Bayevsky, Anne, 360^4
372 INDEX
employment-at-will, 242
health insurance, 251 Families and Work Institute, 248
family agreements
and child care, economic in 19th century, 102—103,113
15—16 H5
New Deals: The Chrysler Revival and
nonmarital births, 78, 79, hi, Okin, Susan Moller, 88, 215
3211126 Olsen, Frances, 150-151
nonmarital families. See also
marital family parental leave, 172, 339ni7,
and children, absence of harm 339oi8
to, 101-102, 198-199 patriarchy, 38, 118, 130, 177, 184,
stigmatization of, 113 i96> 34In5
nonmarital relationships Personal Responsibility and
anullment, 3341142 Work Opportunity
child dependency, civil Reconciliation Act of 1996,
benefits and protections, 113
H0, 335n5° Personal Responsibility, Work,
and child dependency, state and Family Promotion Act
interest in, 139 of 2002, 3181147
contract view of, 128-130, philanthropy, 357065
363013 321031
Roe v. Wade, 152 and marital family, 80,
state intervention in, 150-152 321027
and subordination of women, marriage as social policy,
152 80-81
private investment, 313m morality, decline of, 80,
Promise Keepers, 65, 130—131, 32in26
47-49 108,223
social goods, 28 relationship to market,
allocation of, 102 269-270, 282, 290
caretakers as producers, 47-49 social contract, alteration of,
delivery of, 105,123, 199-200, 237-239> 265-266, 267,
236,327ni5 3521142
34m3 312028
%
«
%
«
>>»
\
tS
o§o
Mi l
ISBN 1-56584-760-1
9 0 0 0 0
9 781565 847606