Article - Good and Bad Arguments
Article - Good and Bad Arguments
We now have all the ingredients to be able to tell when arguments are
good or bad. And it’s now quite simple: good arguments are either
cogent or sound, otherwise, they are bad. Easy.
Here’s the diagram we introduced in the previous video to help you while
judging arguments:
Let’s see how we can use the diagram with some concrete examples. There
are two kinds of arguments: deductive and non-deductive.
For example:
Secondly, all of the argument’s premises are true. Then the argument is
sound, and is, therefore, good.
For example:
For example:
I have a very strong feeling that my lottery ticket is the winning ticket, so
I’m quite confident I will win a lot of money tonight.
Firstly, the argument has false premises. In this case, the argument is not
cogent. Game over, the argument is bad. For example:
If you smoke pot, even only once in your life, you are very likely to start
using heroin. You do smoke pot, and therefore, you will probably start
using heroin.
Secondly, all of the argument’s premises are true. Then the argument is
cogent, and is, therefore, good.
For example:
About 97% of climate experts agree that humans are causing global
warming. Therefore, probably, humans are causing global warming.
As you may have noticed, every argument that has false premises is bad.
Example 1
If you are a confident driver and have never been in an accident, then
driving over the speed limit is not dangerous for you or others. You are a
confident driver and have never been in an accident. Doubtless, then,
driving over the speed limit is not dangerous for you or others.
Driving over the speed limit is not dangerous for you or others.
Is the argument deductive or non-deductive?
Yes, the argument is valid, since it’s impossible for the premises to be true
and the conclusion false.
Now we’re asking if the premises are true. But the first premise is false.
It’s not true that if you are a confident driver and have never been in an
accident, that driving over the speed limit is not dangerous for you or
others.
Example 2
We left our parrot in the house this morning. The nearest neighbour lives
one kilometre away. When we got home from work, the parrot was gone.
It’s most probable that our neighbour stole the parrot.
Not really. It’s a bit quick to accuse your neighbour of stealing the parrot.
Think of other things that could have happened… maybe it flew out the
window!
Example 3
Here’s a more tricky example:
If all the premises happen to be true, given the number of Arab countries
there are, we’ll say the argument is reasonably strong. You might not
agree with me, but here’s some explanation. If all premises are true, then
they provide evidence that there’s some political instability that is
spreading in that region of the world, and this makes it quite probable that
the spread won’t stop.
You may not agree with me, but for the sake of the exercise, accept for
now that the argument is (reasonably) strong.
That is, are all the premises true? And the answer is ‘no’, because:
So at least two premises of the argument are false. Hence, the argument is
not cogent, and is, therefore, bad.
Notice that if you didn’t agree that the argument was strong, then you
thought it was weak, and a weak argument is a bad argument, so you
would agree that the argument is bad, but we would have different reasons
for thinking that the argument is bad.