2018 Johnson Heiss Liberal Institutionalism
2018 Johnson Heiss Liberal Institutionalism
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
Chapter 9
Liberal Institutionalism
Liberal Institutionalism presumes that domestic and international institutions play central roles in
facilitating cooperation and peace between nation-states. But currently, this influential approach
to thinking and practice appear to be in jeopardy. The United Kingdom seeks to be the first state
ever to withdraw from the European Union (EU). The United States threatens to renegotiate or
leave several international arrangements that it has recently signed or long supported.
Meanwhile, China hints that it would be happy to take on greater global leadership if the United
conventional international relations theory, which held that powerful nation-states dominate
world politics and international institutions are inconsequential. And yet today, liberal
escape the clutches of formidable international institutions that supposedly demand too much.
Meanwhile, non-liberal authoritarian regimes are willing not only to stay, but to take on greater
burdens.
with historical events and competing theoretical views. Hence, the chapter begins by explaining
how this theoretical approach has developed in response to both the conceptual world and the
real world. In doing so, it tracks major critiques of Liberal Institutionalism, which have spread
1
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
countries to the general publics in North American or European liberal democracies. Then, the
chapter concludes with open questions about the survival of the contemporary world order—and
international relations, and therefore it cannot be understood without first grasping the broader
relations theory is often traced to Niccolo Machiavelli, the Florentine diplomat whose 1513
treatise The Prince advised rulers about using ethically questionable means to achieve their
goals.1 Rooted in pragmatism rather than ideology, this approach to governance has become
entwined with the paradigm of Realism. Realism eventually developed a particular set of
assumptions, including:
3) States are rational actors, selecting actions they expect will achieve their goals;
5) Accumulating power is a zero-sum game in which gains for one state necessitate losses
for another.
Under these assumptions, realists consider any inter-state cooperation to be only a temporary
2
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
that strongly challenges realists' premise that states are on an inevitable collision course in their
quest for power. Instead, Liberalism perceives high prospects for sustained cooperation. States
can surmount competition, conflict, and war by forming like-minded groups and binding
This rationale permeates Immanuel Kant’s 1795 essay Perpetual Peace, which offers
three linked prescriptions.2 First: internally, each state should embrace a republican form of
government in which legislative power and executive power are separated. Such domestic
institutions make war more difficult to wage because the citizenry, who bear much of the cost,
would need to approve it. Second: externally, these republican states should band together in a
pacific federation whose members renounce the right to wage war with one another. Such
international institutions facilitate trade and other linkages that would make war even more
damaging for its perpetrators. Third: universally, individual “citizens of the world” who conduct
themselves peacefully should be free to travel and do business in states other than their own.
Once states are restrained at the domestic and international levels, their citizens are more likely
to respect the rights of other states’ citizens, further reducing the impetus for inter-state conflict.
In theory, the Kantian system widens over time, as more states become republican and
therefore eligible to enter the pacific federation and reciprocal rights of “hospitality.” And as
more states subscribe to universalist values, which guide how all members of the in-group must
be treated, the in-group itself grows. Thus, political institutions lie at the core of Kantian
perpetual peace, for they are crucial pieces of an expanding system that discourages war.
This sunny perspective is at odds not only with Realism but also with Marxism. Far from
seeing capitalist institutions and economic relations as the underpinnings of peace, Marxists see
them as the sites of contestation between social classes and as vehicles for exploitation at both
3
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
the domestic and international levels.3 Marxism clashes with the Kantian premise that
This foreshadows one of Liberalism’s thorniest issues: until all states reciprocate an
identical set of universalist values, there will be an in-group and an out-group. Enhancements
for one can be threats to the other. Hence until the system is all-encompassing, peace will be
fragile, partial, and intermittent. It is difficult to know, then, how to interpret the outbreak of
wars: are these predictable bumps on the road to perpetual peace, or are they evidence that
underscored the dilemma. For instance, in his 1911 publication The Great Illusion, Norman
misinterpreted as a positive argument for why war in Europe could not happen, in fact it is a
normative argument for why war should not happen. The "great illusion" was governments'
continuing faith in military power. Angell asserted that war among inter-dependent
industrialized countries would be costly and self-immolating, because most of the material and
human resources sought through conquest could be obtained much more effectively through
other means.
Although World War I nevertheless ensnared states in Europe and elsewhere, Liberalism
would have another chance to guide international politics: US president Woodrow Wilson
incorporated liberal notions into the Fourteen Points he articulated for the post-war system.5 He
4
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
“pacific federation” in which states with shared values and linked economies could co-exist. The
League was created, but the United States itself never formally joined.
The League's many weaknesses—along with evidence of Japan’s imperial aspirations and
the renewed tensions in Europe—highlighted the ongoing conceptual tussle between the liberal
and realist paradigms. In the 1939 book The Twenty Years’ Crisis, E.H. Carr lambasted
“utopians” who had trusted transnational ties or institutions to overcome states’ innate attraction
to power, competition, and armed conflict.6 Carr acknowledged Liberalism’s normative appeal.
However, he ultimately argued that in the existing milieu of jostling nation-states, the realist
paradigm was a superior guide and predictor of political behavior. Indeed, later that year Hitler
After the war, the conceptual tussle persisted. Realism's tenets seemed to explain the
failure to prevent a second large-scale war among industrialized countries, and its assumptions
appeared to fit the burgeoning Cold War between the United States and the Soviet Union.
Nevertheless, Liberalism also thrived. In his 1941 State of the Union address, US president
Franklin D. Roosevelt had asserted freedom of speech, freedom of religion, freedom from want,
and freedom from fear as core values that could and should spread throughout the United States
and the world.7 Traces of these “four freedoms” pervade the United Nations (UN), the
intergovernmental organization that replaced the League of Nations in 1945. Similar values also
gird a host of other international institutions—including the Food and Agriculture Organization
(FAO), the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT), the International Monetary Fund
(IMF), and the World Bank—that the US government helped to design and fund at the end of
World War II. These values and institutions are the foundations of today’s liberal world order.8
In the middle of the twentieth century, unable to ignore the flurry of postwar institution-
5
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
building, realists sought to bring these institutions in conformity with their own paradigm. Some
epiphenomenal: if institutions merely reflect the balance of power among states, then it continues
to be expedient for theories to ignore institutions and look directly at states.9 Other work, such
early proponent of “hegemonic stability theory,” Kindleberger argued that the belligerence and
economic woes of the 1930s stemmed from that period’s lack of a single hegemonic state that
was powerful enough to keep the international system running smoothly. After World War II,
however, the United States saw that its own capabilities and aims fit the role. Hence, this
powerful state built a network of international institutions to help it provide economic stability
and other public goods for the international system. A confluence of liberal values was
unnecessary, because peace could be achieved by a hegemon who would self-servingly enforce
cooperation.
More recent work, such as G. John Ikenberry’s After Victory, bridges realist and liberal
international institutions and liberal values are too. Institutions are difficult to change or
dismantle once they begin operating. Therefore, a hegemonic state can use institutional rules to
restrain itself when it is at the height of its power but also to extend its influence into the future,
when its raw power has declined. If the hegemon injects liberal values into these institutions,
then the institutions themselves will perpetuate the rule of law and the sorts of universalist
principles that Kant envisioned. The hegemon’s initial self-restraint helps to convince other
states to join—and as a greater number of states become invested in the institution, the institution
is even more likely to persist and propagate. That helps to explain why the liberal world order,
6
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
initiated following World War II, has expanded and still exists today.
Liberalism had struggled to make sense of the two world wars, but it prospered afterward. From
a real-world standpoint, it aligned with the institution-building and relative peace of the latter
half of the twentieth century. From a conceptual standpoint, it rehabilitated and redeemed itself
Institutionalism from the 1970s onward. Repeatedly, the influence of Liberalism has soared after
its proponents are forced to wrestle with competing theoretical views or unexpected historical
events.
In the decades after World War II, the construction of global and regional institutions
continued, rejuvenating "functionalist" notions that had begun challenging core realist tenets in
the 1930s. Promulgated through writings such as David Mitrany's 1933 book The Progress of
by nation-states within sovereign territories. Instead, governance is a set of functions that can—
and perhaps should—be carried out across national borders by a mix of state and non-state actors
functional areas develop deep expertise and cooperate effectively to wield authority, nation-
states cede even more authority to international institutions. And in line with Liberalism, such
concrete. The path began in 1951 with the European Coal and Steel Community (ECSC), which
would manage coal and steel production in France, West Germany, Italy, Belgium, the
7
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
Netherlands, and Luxembourg. In 1967, the ECSC merged with two sister bodies to form the
encompass Denmark, Ireland, and the United Kingdom. Throughout this process, numerous
dependent that war among them would never again be a compelling option.
The European undertaking gave credence to liberal and functionalist notions, and it also
inspired a new line of "neofunctionalist" thinking about regional integration. Building upon
Mitrany's insights, works such as Leon Lindberg's The Political Dynamics of European
Economic Integration13 and Ernst B. Haas' Beyond the Nation-State14 argued that the architects
cooperating in economic matters, states were building institutions and trust that eventually could
Among the shortcomings of functionalism and neo-functionalism, one of the most serious
was the supposition of a steady march toward supranationalism. By the 1970s, the US was
thinking about rolling back its support for international institutions—and certainly not making
them broader and deeper. American officials questioned whether they could, or should, continue
to bear the largest costs for international public goods such as freer trade, collective defense, and
the United Nations system. Nevertheless, inter-dependence across the world proved difficult to
reverse. Not only states, but also firms, sub-national governments, and civil society groups were
In their 1977 book Power and Interdependence, Robert Keohane and Joseph Nye
explored this complexity, arguing that monolithic states do not dictate international affairs.
Instead bureaucrats, legislators, judges, international institutions, firms, civil society groups, and
8
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
others interact with each other domestically and internationally. Consequently, states’ fortunes
were now tied not only through conventional economic linkages but also through novel political
and societal ones.15 Keohane and Nye flirted with liberal views, without explicitly endorsing
them—and they concluded that the US government could not easily extricate itself from the
Yet realist Kenneth Waltz’s 1979 book Theory of International Politics took a different
tack.16 According to Waltz, the world’s ostensible complexity had a very simple cause: the
number of powerful states in the international system. Such structural realism contended that the
existing bipolar system, in which two great powers tried but failed to dominate one another,
would naturally look different from a unipolar system with a global hegemon or a multipolar
system with several evenly matched states. Thus the real action was not among businesses, or
international institutions, or civil society groups, or even among most states—instead, all could
be traced simply to the rivalry between Washington and Moscow. Realism reasserted itself, this
But liberal notions soon rematerialized, taking on the parallel name of "neo-Liberalism"
and building on Keohane and Nye's ideas of interdependence. In the 1980s, scholars amassed
evidence about the importance of domestic institutions, a “black box” rarely opened by realists.
Summarizing historical data, Michael Doyle noted that mature liberal democratic states do not go
to war against each other, but they do go to war against illiberal, non-democratic states. He
posited that this “democratic peace” is not maintained via a hegemonic overseer. Rather, it
results from liberal values, norms, and institutions within individual states aligning with those of
fellow democracies, thus producing a modern stepping-stone to Kantian perpetual peace.17 The
findings again underscored the interim existence of in-groups and out-groups: renouncing war as
9
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
a solution to problems was a “universal” principle that worked primarily within the groups of
states whose domestic democratic institutions made reciprocation of that principle more credible.
international institutions matter, too. Since the early 1970s, the United States had decried free-
riders in global affairs and had tried retreating from its hegemonic support of international
institutions and public goods. Yet institutions such as the FAO, GATT, IMF, UN, and World
Bank continued to facilitate aid, trade, financial stability, peace, and development. How could
this be, if realists were correct that institutions merely reflected the will of the most powerful
states?
John Ruggie and Robert Keohane offered somewhat different answers for why an
international institution can survive even if a hegemon retreats, declines, or disappears. In After
Hegemony, Keohane adopted the core realist assumptions of state-centrism, anarchy, and
rationality, but he rejected the premise that international politics is a zero-sum quest for power.
institutions can persist when they provide information, coordination, enforcement, or other
benefits that states could not provide on their own.18 By selectively tweaking realist tenets,
Keohane demonstrated much greater prospects for cooperation, even without a hegemonic
patron. In contrast, Ruggie did not work from realist tenets, and in his work on "embedded
liberalism" he diverged markedly from Realism by emphasizing social purpose: institutions can
endure when a larger community of states continues to share the values embodied in those
presaged the emergence of Constructivism, while Keohane linked the new "Liberal
10
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
Liberal Institutionalism was not universally embraced. Instead, the new strains of Realism and
Liberalism would engage in a so-called "neo-neo" debate for over a decade. For instance, Joseph
Grieco argued that international cooperation could not be as easy as Keohane and others
asserted. Attempting to reinstate the rejected realist premise, he argued that international politics
indeed is a zero-sum game, and therefore each state will fixate on relative gains rather than being
satisfied with absolute gains. Presented with any arrangement from which it derives some
benefits but another state derives even more, it will refuse to participate. Grieco concluded that
However, a variety of formal models countered this view. For example, Duncan Snidal
and Robert Powell concluded that a fixation on relative gains occurs only under particular
conditions. The fixation can dissipate in non-security issues21 or with increases in the number of
participating states,22 thus explaining why inter-state cooperation is often prevalent and lasting.
Moreover, Robert Axelrod acknowledged that numerous situations in international politics share
characteristics with a Prisoners' Dilemma game, in which each player's dominant strategy is to
defect rather than cooperate. However, in the real world many of these situations are repeated,
and iteration makes prolonged cooperation possible through reputation-building and other
means.23 Hence, formal models delivered a further departure from Classical Liberalism: it was
unnecessary to aim for world government, because cooperation could be sustained through
international institutions would be tested in the early 1990s, after the Soviet Union’s
11
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
disintegration officially ended the Cold War. Would international institutions crumble in a
unipolar world, where the United States did not need their assistance in its competition with the
Eastern bloc and might be disinclined to restrain newfound American dominance? Would inter-
state war become widespread again, since there were no longer two superpowers reining in the
smaller states in their respective blocs? Would the camaraderie of liberal democracies collapse,
Europe reacted by not only deepening but also broadening the region’s supranational
institutions. In 1993, the Maastricht Treaty formed the European Union (EU), an even bolder
form of economic and political integration. The EU expanded its membership to include
numerous Eastern European states, and eventually it developed a common currency for states
opting into its Euro-zone. In work such as Andrew Moravcsik’s 1998 The Choice for Europe,
scholars strived to determine whether Realism, Liberalism, or something else best accounted for
this institutional phenomenon.24 Meanwhile, policy practitioners toyed with the idea of
recreating the European experiment in other parts of the world; thus far, the African Union is the
institutionalists now believed the evidentiary trail was compelling enough to stop playing
defense.26 The interesting question was not whether institutions mattered—it was when, or how.
And numerous scholars unearthed answers. For example Jon Pevehouse, Edward Mansfield, and
Bruce Russert argued that international institutions spread both peace and democracy.27
Meanwhile, Helen Milner reasoned that democratic domestic institutions aid the diffusion of
technology.28
Despite this progress, since the 1990s Liberal Institutionalism has faced a new conceptual
12
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
affairs are socialized and influenced by their surroundings, and therefore their proclivities toward
conflict or cooperation are collectively constructed.29 Those who interact with others negatively
will generate a hostile realist system; those who interact with others more positively can create a
Kantian system in which self-interests meld with community interests. But as social
rationality, and anarchy.30 Since Liberal Institutionalism also adopted these premises, it too is
challenged by the constructivist confrontation with Realism. In fact, some observers conjoin the
two as “rationalist” views that greatly differ from Constructivism. Ironically—although many
liberals share constructivists’ appreciation for ideas, non-state actors, and goals other than
power—liberals can be painted with the same brush as the realists they had spent centuries
contesting.31
Today, many researchers (including the authors of this chapter) eschew strict allegiance
to a single paradigm and instead draw from multiple conceptual insights to thoroughly
investigate pressing real-world developments,. For instance, Tana Johnson’s 2014 book
about policy-related values, the pursuit for institutional legitimacy, and alliances with civil
society—to examine the staff members working within the UN and other intergovernmental
organizations.32 Meanwhile, Andrew Heiss’ research on “amicable contempt” considers the role
13
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
As Liberal Institutionalism grew more prominent, its critics grew more vocal. In fact, critiques
that now circulate among the general public in North American or European liberal democracies
have been swirling for years among non-liberal governments, feminists, and developing
While Kant’s great hope in liberal institutions was rooted in universality, the modern democratic
peace is non-universal and may even be non-Kantian. According to Kant, peace emerges
naturally when states and their citizens choose to embrace similar values and institutions,
domestically and internationally. Peace spreads as more people adopt these vehicles for
may deter liberal states from interfering or warring with each other—but it can allow, or even
In the pursuit of peace, there has been a strong temptation to impose liberal values and
Institutionalism itself. After all, spreading it through coercive means is “the propagation of
particularist law under a universal guise,” as “liberals disqualify non-liberals from choosing their
own laws.”34 If real Kantian peace comes from states’ spontaneous alignment of universal
political principles, then forced adherence cannot bring real peace. Instead, it makes Liberalism
operate illiberally.
Besides this problem with implementation, critics also denounce how Liberal
14
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
fascination with power, nation-states, and the international system. This runs the risk of creating
a body of knowledge that is based largely on the lives of power-seeking men—while neglecting
Western thinkers, generally arguing about Western states and institutions, dominated debates
between realists and liberals—and later, between neo-realists and neo-liberals.36 This
overlooked non-Western experiences and risked excluding states in the Global South from full
major inter-governmental organizations reflect the experiences and expectations of the former
Western bloc—a handful of North American and Western European states that were among the
first liberal democracies. To the many additional states that willingly adopted these standards
and organizations, the West still seems to have an edge, enjoying greater benefits from
Marxism, subaltern critiques argue that the structures of global governance privilege a small set
Non-liberal states, feminists, and the Global South have long felt mistreated in the liberal world
order. But now, the general publics in many Western liberal democracies bear grievances too. It
is not clear whether injecting feminine or non-Western perspectives into Liberal Institutionalism
would yield drastically different theoretical conclusions. The canon may look masculine and
15
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
Western because modern international relations itself has been dominated by men and the West.
However, even if the same conclusions would be reached, the reasoning process itself could be
more inclusive. After all, perceptions of Liberal Institutionalism’s exclusivity have grown in
recent years, fueling pushback against international institutions and the broader post-World War
Liberal Institutionalism’s future cannot be known without examining its past, and its past
cannot be understood without appreciating liberals’ interactions with rival theoretical views and
knotty historical events. As the discussion shows, liberals occupy a tough position. By adopting
many of Realism’s tenets, they become vulnerable to its shortcomings. At the same time, they
try to distinguish themselves: realists simply anticipate war, while liberals anticipate war but
strive for peace. Kantian perpetual peace is a goal more than a prediction; indeed, the path to
such peace will be punctuated by war, because tensions arise between in-groups and out-groups
as long as universalism is incomplete. Moreover, for values and institutions to generate long-
standing peace, they must be embraced voluntarily, rather than foisted upon unwilling
populations.39
Grievances, now trumpeted in the West in addition to other parts of the world, are not so
different from those of the 1970s, 1930s, and other periods. At times grievances were
surmounted; other times they were not. Therefore, several questions arise for international
relations scholars and policy practitioners. For instance, is Liberal Institutionalism on the cusp
of collapse, or merely experiencing growing pains on the path to perpetual peace? Can civil
society groups, firms, or other non-state actors bring more stability to global affairs? To what
extent does the survival of international institutions depend on the preservation of democratic
domestic institutions? Could the liberal world order, which was established by democratic
16
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
When placed within the historical context, these questions point to a core truth. The
future is fraught with danger. But for Liberal Institutionalism and liberal institutions, that has
Additional reading
Beyond the West,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 39, no. 3 (May 2011):
619–37.
2. Michael Doyle, “Liberalism and World Politics,” American Political Science Review 80,
3. Tana Johnson, Organizational Progeny: Why Governments Are Losing Control over the
5. Robert Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political
6. Lisa Martin and Beth Simmons, “Theories and Empirical Studies of International
7. J. Ann Tickner, “You Just Don’t Understand: Troubled Engagements Between Feminists
and IR Theorists,” International Studies Quarterly 41, no. 4 (December 1997): 611–32.
Notes
17
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
1
Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince, ed. Quentin Skinner and Russell Price (1513; reprinted,
Their Economic and Social Advantage, 3rd ed. (New York; London: G.P. Putnam’s Sons, 1911).
5
Woodrow Wilson, Woodrow Wilson’s Fourteen Points, 8 January 1918 (reprinted, New York:
A. Knopf, 1948).
10
Charles Kindleberger, The World in Depression: 1929–1939 (Berkeley: University of
18
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
12
David Mitrany, The Progress of International Government (New Haven: Yale Uniervsity
Press, 1933).
13
Leon Lindberg, The Political Dynamics of European Economic Integration (Palo Alto:
(Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1977). For a more recent argument that emphasizes the
importance of networks, see Anne-Marie Slaughter, A New World Order (Princeton, NJ:
Affairs 12, no. 3 (1983): 205–35; and “Liberalism and World Politics,” American Political
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984). Also see: Arthur Stein, “Coordination and
299–324; and Barbara Koremenos, Charles Lipson, and Duncan Snidal, eds., The Rational
19
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
21
Robert Powell, “Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory,” American
International Organization 60, no. 1 (2006): 137–67; and Jon Pevehouse and Bruce Russett,
Press, 1999).
30
Michael Barnett and Raymond Duvall, eds., Power in Global Governance (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2005); Margaret Keck and Kathryn Sikkink, Activists beyond
Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
20
Preprint version of chapter
Full version: Tana Johnson and Andrew Heiss, "Liberal Institutionalism," chap. 8 in International Organization and Global Governance, 2nd ed.,
ed. Thomas G. Weiss and Rorden Wilkinson (London: Routledge, 2018), 123–34, doi: 10.4324/9781315301914.
1998); and Michael Barnett and Martha Finnemore, Rules for the World: International
the Theory and Practice of International Politics, ed. Stanley Hoffmann (Boulder, CO:
Perspectives,” Global Change, Peace & Security 23, no. 1 (2011): 5–13; and Christine Sylvester,
Beyond the West,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 39, no. 3 (2011): 619–37.
38
B. S. Chimni, “International Institutions Today: An Imperial Global State in the Making,”
21