William Ian Miller - Faking It (2005) (2005)
William Ian Miller - Faking It (2005) (2005)
Faking It
FA K I N G I T
Acknowledgments page xi
vii
contents
12 Passing and Wishing You Were What You Are Not 141
An American Tragicomedy 143
Passing 148
viii
contents
Notes 239
Works Cited 266
Index 279
ix
Acknowledgments
xi
one
1
faking it
that kid over there who is nodding off again. Don’t turn to write on
the blackboard because Ms. Simmons, the bombshell, will observe
the thinning of your hair in back, the beginnings of your tonsure.
While all these thoughts are going on, the me standing outside the
me going through the motions of lecturing gets a metathought of won-
derment: how remarkable human consciousness is that it can have
all these distracting thoughts while split in two and still let me speak
coherently on easements. How do I know the lecture is coherent?
Because as soon as I split in two the students dive for their pens and
the keyboard clacks increase to frenetic rates. They inevitably think
I am delivering the goods when they hear my father’s voice.1 When I
actually know what I am talking about they occupy themselves play-
ing solitaire on their laptops, or they ostentatiously look back at the
clock on the wall behind them (spiting their wristwatches) to make
sure I know how impatient they are for me to have done with it.
Funny how easy it is to do mental tasks with all the voices inside
your head critiquing you while you continue the performance, but
how hard it is to act convincingly when you become self-conscious of
your physical movements, such as whether you are walking naturally,
or blinking too much, or looking like a law-abiding driver when the
cop pulls up next to you at the stoplight. So though I feel that I am
faking it and fear the roof might come caving in on me at any moment,
since the physical demands are minimal and there is a barricade-like
lectern to provide cover for most of my body, the roof (almost always)
stays put. Within seconds the me standing outside me remerges with
the me putting on the show, and time is up and I am safe for another
day, unless, that is, I should overhear a student grumble to another
about what an awful class it was. But you never hear complaints after
a day of bluffing. You know you get your highest approval ratings
from the students when you keep it easy and falsely authoritative; as
long as they can take good notes, most of them feel they got their
money’s worth.
Is it the case that my experience of seeing myself as if outside myself
was generated by guilt over faking it? Is that me outside me, in other
words, my conscience? Or is it the form my conscience takes when
it really means business? That hardly seems right. For often that me
2
introduction
3
faking it
to play to pass for a properly socialized and sane person? And why,
when I happen to immerse myself joyously into a role, do I later –
not always, mind you, but often enough – wonder if I haven’t made
a fool of myself by overdoing it? And how do I manage to escape
being exposed as a fake as often as I do, unless it is all a setup?
To be a proper person behaving properly we must engage in a cer-
tain amount of self-monitoring. Most of such monitoring is routine
and hardly the stuff to generate great anxiety. I thus automatically
modulate the volume of my voice to the level appropriate to the occa-
sion (though my teenage girls are constantly shushing me in restau-
rants); without an anxious thought, I engage in minor gestures of
grooming to make sure my nose isn’t about to humiliate me, my nails
are clean, my zippers zipped and buttons buttoned. More anxiety-
provoking are the demands to display proper emotions at the right
time and place. Tears are a problem, often failing to appear when they
should and showing up when they shouldn’t. Just trying to display
interest when it is polite to do so, or to suppress signs of it when it
is impolite to show it, can make us uneasy about how poorly we are
playing it. It does not help, for instance, to let the fact that I cannot
take my eyes off the big zit on the chin of my interlocutor serve as a
substitute for my not being able to maintain the faintest modicum of
interest in his conversation.
But I must confess, and I would bet you could confess it too,
that I have found myself feeling quite pleased or relieved in the
midst of some emotional turmoil – a lover’s quarrel, a funeral, a
moving moment – that tears actually showed up. I cannot quite re-
press the “Thank God” of relief, or the “Way to go, Miller” of self-
congratulation. And who is saying that “Way to go”? Me? Or a fake
“me” that I pretend to be when I am trying to please? Or is it the voice
of a stranger, a father, a conscience, an intruder? Or all of the above?
Those internal conversations that make up much of what we think
of as thinking – are they monologues, dialogues, or sessions of the
Israeli Knesset?
This book is unified by the intrusive fear that we may not be what
we appear to be or, worse, that we may be only what we appear to be
and nothing more. It is about the worry of being exposed as frauds in
4
introduction
5
faking it
6
introduction
7
faking it
not linear, for the goal is not a particular end point of an argument or
a thesis but a descriptive travelogue that intends to give the traveler
a feel for, an expansive familiarity with, the custom of the country.
Some of the views are scenic, others will make us lament the lot of the
natives, but the pictures are all identifiably about some aspect borne
by the notion of “faking it,” as we employ that term colloquially.
At the beginning of William Langland’s Piers Plowman, Will, the
narrator, has a vision of a fair field full of folk going about their
chicanery and hypocritical fourteenth-century existences; the William
who narrates Faking It offers a twenty-first-century revisitation of
that vision: a world of posing and shams, anxieties of exposure, and
a fear that the genuine may be just another sham whose cover is too
tough to be blown. The first stop is a logical one: the vice of hypocrisy.
The next three chapters show how falseness and fakery lie at the heart
of many of the nice things we say and do, and how inextricably vice
and virtue are bound together in their eternal pas de deux and not
necessarily in a bad way.
8
two
9
faking it
10
hypocrisy and jesus
Ostentatious Alms
Hypocrisy comes in all sizes and shapes, and I am not about to spell
them all out.5 I will organize the discussion around Jesus’ use of the
term. First:
11
faking it
Each of the two examples Jesus gives – ostentatious alms and pub-
lic prayers – presents a different issue. The alms do not, it seems, help
the soul of the giver, yet they are of considerable use to the bodies
of the recipients. But the prayers said for the purpose of impressing
people with piety, unlike the alms that help the poor, are apparently
useful to no one. Jesus elsewhere is explicit about it: “You hypocrites!
Well did Isaiah prophesy of you, when he said: ‘This people honors
me with their lips, but their heart is far from me; in vain do they
worship me . . .’ ” (Matt. 15.7–9; Mark 7.6–7). I wonder, however,
whether God doesn’t credit these hypocritical prayers to a certain
degree. From His perspective they are better than no prayers at all.
Hypocrisy is not apostasy; the hypocrite may not be honoring God
with his prayers, but he is honoring those who believe that honoring
God with prayer is a good thing. He is paying some kind of homage
to a social and religious order that believes in the virtue of prayer.
Jesus is well aware that it is no easy matter to keep your mind
free of the reputational and other advantages gained by doing good
deeds. He thus counsels self-deception: keep the left hand ignorant of
what the right is doing. But how do you blind yourself to the honor
that comes from good deeds or from a reputation for piety? How
can giving in secret, as Jesus urges, keep you from feeling the pride
of eschewing public recognition? If you insist that the pauper keep
quiet, might you not mistrust your motives for so insisting? It will
be considerably easier on your purse if he keeps his counsel about
where he is getting his goodies. And if the pauper keeps your secret,
does that mean you have chosen to give to an unworthy beggar who
himself lacks sufficient generosity to share his secret with other needy
folk? Is your generosity thus working to decrease rather than increase
the amount of generosity in the world? Yet if you think it a good idea
that word about your generosity gets out in a discreet fashion so that
other paupers can benefit, can you trust that you will not delight in
the fact that you now have a reputation for genuine unhypocritical
generosity? Or do you fear you still may be letting Jesus down, that
your left hand was peeking?8
Jesus knows he is not asking for something easy to achieve if the
right motive does not come naturally in the first place. He gives
12
hypocrisy and jesus
How can you say to your brother, ‘Let me take the speck out of
your eye,’ when there is the log in your own eye? You hypocrite,
first take the log out of your own eye, and then you will see clearly
to take the speck out of your brother’s eye.
(Matt. 7.4–5)
Pardon the Revised Standard Version with its logs and specks, rather
than the King James with its motes and beams. The latter is unfor-
tunately more likely to befuddle the modern reader as to why Jesus
would be so uncharitable to a twinkle in your eye, to say nothing of
a whole fortification system in the eye of the other.
In the first type of hypocrisy Jesus counseled self-deception: com-
partmentalize your knowledge so that half of you does not know what
the other half is doing. In the case of specks and logs he is arguing
against self-deception, albeit of a different sort. We deceive ourselves
incessantly, flattering ourselves as to our virtues and blinding our-
selves to our faults, while at the same time fancying ourselves to be
ever so astute about the faults of others.10 Jesus is not addressing here
13
faking it
Stoning Adulterers
14
hypocrisy and jesus
sin may be driving you to be not very particular as to the guilt or in-
nocence of the person you are stoning. But be careful not to be too
zealous a stoner, for the type who would seek to deflect suspicion from
his own guilt by aggressively hunting down similar sinners is himself
suspicious. Be somewhat reserved when you stone adulteresses.
It is not even clear that such conscious hypocrisy is morally worse
than the mote/beam situation of merely being blind to one’s own
faults. Take the ever-present anxiety regarding racism and accusa-
tions of it. Is the person who fears that deep down she might be a
racist, and aggressively blames others for their racism, worse than the
person who does not know he is one and blames others for theirs? The
academy is filled with the latter (I could a tale unfold . . . that would
harrow up thy soul), who sport giant I-beams protruding from their
eyes. The former, the person who fears her own racism, comes al-
most as a breath of fresh air. We can reasonably believe that her
blaming the speck in others’ eyes is, in part, a way of chastising her-
self. She is faking nothing. She hates racism in herself and in others,
and she knows that she is no less guilty than they; that she prefers
not to blame herself in the presence of others may only be because
the chances of such self-blame being read as sincere rather than as
a form of self-serving fakery are not very high. One would mistrust
such self-castigation as so much ingratiating herself with the victim
group, and also as trying to give herself a better warrant to blame
others.15 The truth is that there is almost no tasteful way to proceed
in this domain that does not subject one to doubts about posturing,
favor currying, and camp following.
To the cases of the person who is unaware of the beam in his own
eye and the adulterer who is painfully aware but casts stones anyway,
add this: suppose we have bad desires, but through force of will we
do not act on them. Do we then have a warrant to blame the lecher
for his lechery, or the glutton for his gluttony, without being called
a hypocrite when we are dying to do the same but use all the self-
command at our disposal to refrain? Perhaps our own bad desires
should incline us to be charitable to the person who gives way to his
bad desires. Yet all too frequently we are inclined to blame him with
special energy because of his having cashed in:
15
faking it
16
hypocrisy and jesus
his more expansive readings of the Law. Thus when Jesus heals a
crippled woman,
The ruler of the synagogue may have given up too easily, or Jesus
was better at making sure he argued the case before a friendly au-
dience. The woman had been crippled for eighteen years; she could
have waited until Sunday. Or if I am being too cavalier about her
suffering, then the ruler of the synagogue might have emphasized
that Jesus do his healing a day earlier, on Friday; otherwise Sunday
would be fine. There is some suspicion as to Jesus’ motives; he wants
to make a point not about healing, but about healing on the Sabbath.
The woman’s sufferings are not his chief interest; they take a back
seat to his desire to test the Law. He cannot really complain that those
who adhere to the customary understandings of Sabbath observance
should object; that is precisely what he wanted them to do. Nor is the
animal analogy apt, for there is no glory in feeding and watering an-
imals on the Sabbath, but plenty in healing the sick.19 And Sabbath
work prohibitions were never understood to include not eating or
not feeding those who could not feed themselves. You can’t make the
animals work on the Sabbath, but you can feed them within the rules
of Sabbath observance no less than you can set food out for humans.
There may be crazed amounts of fussiness and persnicketyness in
the rabbinic rules as to what is work and what not, but there is no
hypocrisy. If anything, the vice in the rules is the obsessive concern
to get it exactly right. The problem is one of having to draw the line
somewhere when you make a rule, and the rule that distinguishes
17
faking it
18
hypocrisy and jesus
because they have become habit and custom?21 Or that because not
doing them would bring blame? Or that the doing of them would
bring approbation?
Subject to some major anxieties I mean to expose in a later chapter,
one might argue that the function, if not the purpose, of successful
ritual is to finesse the issue of motives. The point of ritual is to have
as an acceptable motive nothing more elaborate than “that’s what
we do.” And that is satisfying in itself.
19
three
Of Hairshirts
20
antihypocrisy
are not fasting when you are (Matt. 6.16–18) – and it immediately
gives rise to its own styles of hypocrisy, vanity, and playing at virtue.
In one of Mark Twain’s burlesques of Heaven we find Sir Richard
Duffer, a butcher from Hoboken who died with a carefully cultivated
reputation for meanness; he was awarded a baronetcy in Heaven for
having secretly furnished the homes of “honest square people out
of work” with meat.2 Take the more famous cases of St. Thomas
à Becket and St. Thomas More, who secretly wore itchy hairshirts
underneath their sumptuous robes to punish themselves for the vanity
of their rich clothing and high office. Better to appear completely
given over to unapologetic luxury than to appear virtuously dressed
in unostentatious habit and be suspected of ostentatious piety. Yet it is
hard not to suspect Becket and More of smirking to themselves, vain
of their hairshirt secret, or congratulating themselves on the brilliance
of a move that turns their showy sumptuousness into fake showy
sumptuousness, all to get around the stricture against trumpeting
one’s virtue.3
Similarly, it is hard not to imagine the simpler Richard Duffer
undertaking considerable extra labor to keep his generosity secret.
We can see him delighting in his reputation for meanness, precisely
because it is false, taking no small pleasure in a smug contempt for
those fools who fall for his perfectly engineered deception, who are so
wrong in their opinion of him. The townspeople’s false blame purifies
his virtue and shoots him straight to Heaven, at least according to
this theory of obsessive hypocrisy avoidance.
There are certain false fronts that are not part of the niceties of
politeness and decorum but instead turn the people who are their
objects into fools: this is the sin of Frank Churchill in Emma, who by
keeping his engagement to Jane Fairfax secret is assumed by others,
namely Emma, to be available for flirtation. The unknowing are thus
entrapped into humiliating themselves by fancying they are being
attended to by Frank in ways they are not. When the sham is revealed
people resent it, and with good reason. It is not likely that the denizens
of Hoboken who disliked the falsely mean butcher will feel much
more charitable toward him once his secret is revealed. No one likes
being made a fool of, even (or especially?) in the interests of someone
21
faking it
22
antihypocrisy
It might be that the real cross to bear was not the hairshirt but the
suspicion, your own as well as that of others, that you were thought
vain no matter how hard you tried not to be. And for all your pride
in your self-mortification, in the end you fear that the actual suffering
too is a sham. If the hairshirt was hard to bear at first, it gets easier
with time, and eventually you may even come to find it pleasurable.
As Trollope says of Mrs. Prime: “Nice things aggravated her spirits
and made her fretful . . . She liked the bread to be stale . . . She was
approaching that stage of discipline at which ashes become pleasant
eating, and sackcloth is grateful to the skin. The self-indulgences of
the saints in this respect often exceed anything that is done by the
sinners.”8
In such a moral regime anxieties regarding the purity of motive
behind otherwise virtuous-looking deeds arise with aggressive insis-
tence. You become anxious about doing good; you start to question
your motives. Even when you satisfy yourself on that score you are
not sure that others will not see you as motivated by vanity. Should
you employ Duffer’s or Becket’s strategy of playing the part of a sin-
ner so as to avoid the imputation of being vain of your virtue, you
hardly feel yourself more authentically and purely virtuous. Instead
you worry that the very charade of hiding your virtue has become en-
tirely too self-conscious to be authentic; your last hope is that all your
self-torturing and labor will themselves serve as sufficient atonement
for whatever imperfections may stain your motives. Or, as in the case
of Benjamin Franklin, you throw in the towel on matters of humility:
“For even if I could conceive that I had compleatly overcome [pride],
I should probably be proud of my Humility.”9
That you find yourself canonized doesn’t settle the matter either,
for it will be suspected that you were angling for that honor, especially
if, as in Becket’s and More’s cases, you made sure you were martyred.
There is as much earthly (though posthumous) as heavenly glory in
sainthood, rivaling in every way the glory of conventional military
heroes who die in battle. The old Vikings made no bones about it:
posthumous earthly glory was the best we could hope for, a kind of
Heaven on Earth:
23
faking it
24
antihypocrisy
doesn’t feel guilt for reveling in the proceeds and can really sincerely
miss me when I am dead and gone?
How to escape such miserable thoughts! Thus the fashion of the
pastoral, with its central theme that in Arcadia the shepherds were
uncomplicatedly innocent and authentic in their desires and deeds; or
the cult of children; or the belief in the patient, humble peasant pure
in virtue, a belief that was quickly discounted because that virtuous
peasant never seemed to reside on your manor but in the next village,
or in literature as Chaucer’s plowman or poor parish priest.14 Why
weren’t those poor as meek and blessed as advertised?
The occasional vogue of the pastoral – Marie Antoinette dress-
ing up as a shepherdess at Versailles or suburban rich kids joining
hippie communes – speaks to the desperate need for the possibility
of unself-conscious virtue. The shepherd is conceived to be too sim-
ple to entertain the ironies of appearances and reality. But maybe
the shepherd has his own doubts: “Damn, I can’t seem to feel as
authentic as I’m supposed to. Am I just going through the motions
because some jaded aristocrat expects me to sport innocently with so
many Daphnes and Amaryllises in the shade? Am I motivated in part
by putting on a show for these rich guys who come around during
the spring and paint me? These people don’t understand the moral
paradoxes of shepherding and the complexity of maintaining a life
of simplicity and authenticity. Being authentic is hard work. It takes
so much effort I have dropped into last place among my comrades in
sheep-stealing.”15
We know that when the sophisticated try their hand at shepherd-
ing they make a mess of it, as the failures of Brook Farm attest.16 The
rustics with whom they hobnobbed thought them phonies or merely
comical; and the sophisticated came to suspect each other of hypo-
critical posturing. Truth be told, actually living with those crude and
constantly bickering soulful shepherds had even fewer charms than
tea and crumpets in Concord. Adding drugs or gurus from India, as
in twentieth-century versions of Brook Farm, doesn’t seem to work
either. And when someone insists his new brand of the authentic life
really is working, we often mistrust his intelligence or sanity, as with
adherents of new age spirituality.
25
faking it
26
antihypocrisy
donning masks of virtue and using veils to cover our honest feelings,
and then disguising from ourselves our less than honorable decep-
tion of others by various tricks of self-duping; thus in the end we
honor virtue, not by being errant hypocrites, but by coming to be-
lieve that our hypocrisies are virtuous. And as long as our hypocrisy is
of the first type Jesus exposed – of being moved by the desire for being
known as virtuous for the sake of self-advancement, for honor’s sake –
the poor get their alms.
This kind of hypocrisy is very sociable. It cares greatly what people
think, and, for the most part, to be well thought of one must do good
deeds. It means having to be reasonably respectful of others, engaging
in small acts of civility, cultivating tact, sparing others the pain of too
much truth whose only virtue would be to hurt them needlessly and
feed your own vanity for being a tough truth teller. Though at times
you may actually feel like a hypocrite, that confers larger moral stakes
on most of these routine matters than they deserve.
Some took the argument about the benefits of our vanity one
step further; if the vanity of wanting to be thought good could pro-
duce good, then, it was both seriously and satirically argued – most
famously by Mandeville in the early eighteenth century, but quite
frequently in the century before him – that our plain old vices them-
selves produced good even if we took no care to gloss them over.
Forget about working to appear virtuous. Vices created demand in
the economy that prompted virtues (in others) of hard work and en-
terprise to meet them. The vanity of wanting sumptuous clothing and
a fancy equipage did an inadvertent good. Never mind giving alms for
suspect motives. Why, lordy-be, spending it on yourself was a form of
almsgiving; it was the virtue of trickle-down economics.19 No need
to waste energy being a hypocrite: vice is one kind of virtue, though
surely Mandeville’s argument about the virtue of vice is its own form
of hypocrisy; it provides shameless spendthrifts and gluttons a con-
venient rationalization for why it is good to be as disgusting as they
are.
The usual hypocrisy of false good appearances thus gives way to a
new hypocrisy of shameless redescriptions of undisguised vice as gen-
erators of virtue, prompting in these new, complacent sinners what
27
faking it
28
antihypocrisy
the motive of salvation, heavenly glory for an eternity. How isn’t that
the ne plus ultra of glory seeking?
I cannot help suspecting that the claim Jesus is making is as much
an aesthetic one as a moral one. He dislikes the aggressive posturing:
too noisy, too much trumpeting and chest thumping. Jesus prefers
the look of modesty, the decorousness of private almsgiving rather
than public spectacle. To obtain a more tasteful form of almsgiving
he is willing to offer a bribe: a reward from the Father, much better,
because less evanescent, he claims, than vain earthly glory. Such an
open offer of a quid pro quo is itself, however, rather vulgar. Could
Jesus possibly believe the reward, the payoff of heavenly bliss, should
be the motive for giving alms?23 If so, almsgiving becomes no less
selfish than it was when it was being trumpeted about. This must
be why Jesus counseled keeping the left hand ignorant of the right
hand’s activities. The thing to be hidden from yourself is not just the
knowledge that your virtue will get you praised in the here and now
but the reward the Father is holding in escrow for you. I hope that
that is what Jesus means, for I cannot shake the belief that the truly
virtuous soul, one I would want to gain a Heaven worthy of housing
him, would be moved primarily by an honest desire to help a person
in need. He saw something that needed to be done and he did it.24
Neither did Calvinism’s doctrine of predestined salvation and
damnation resolve the problem of double thoughts, those worries
about the quality of one’s motives. In Calvin’s view you had already
been paid off in either gold or lead long before you did your good
deed – long before you were born, in fact – but that did not prevent
you from worrying about the moral status of your motives for do-
ing good. Wouldn’t a person predestined for salvation do good deeds
with the purest of motives? Could a soul predestined for Heaven be
so corrupt as to want praise for his virtue or for wanting to have the
reputation as one predestined for salvation?25 Mightn’t your less than
perfect motive be, God forbid, a sign of your predestined damnation?
We are conflicted, but not always. Sometimes we just do good and
don’t worry that it may be good business to do so. Yet at other times,
in a plague of self-conscious scrupulosity, we doubt our motives and
desperately want to have our doubts assuaged. We may find some
29
faking it
It has been found, that the virtuous are far from being indifferent
to praise; and therefore they have been represented as a set of
vainglorious men, who had nothing in view but the applauses of
others. But this also is a fallacy. It is very unjust in the world, when
they find any tincture of vanity in a laudable action, to depreciate it
upon that account, or ascribe it entirely to that motive . . . Vanity is
so closely allied to virtue, and to love the fame of laudable actions
approaches so near the love of laudable actions for their own sake,
that these passions are more capable of mixture, than any other
kinds of affection; and it is almost impossible to have the latter
without some degree of the former . . . To love the glory of virtuous
deeds is a sure proof of the love of virtue.27
30
four
31
faking it
32
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
the capacity to deliver when the crunch came. Honor societies knew
that. In them, modesty was suspect. Keeping modestly in the back-
ground looked more like excessive prudence, which was mistrusted
as so much cover for fearfulness.
So hard is it to be courageous that we are willing to let people
engage in all kinds of precommitment strategies to raise the costs to
themselves of failure if they fink out. We wink at most all the tricks of
self-deception they might employ to fool themselves into fearlessness,
and we still deem them courageous if they come through. We thus
understand why they make boasts and vows, why they drink them-
selves into confidence, why they work themselves into rages, why
they shame the coward. True, some people did have the option of not
boasting and vowing: those who had already proved unambiguously
their mettle or who were so big and strong that no one doubted they
could win any fight they got into. But most needed to buck themselves
up by whatever means necessary to feel they might actually have a
chance of delivering when the time came.
Courage is thus courage even if the doer of brave deeds trumpets
them about, or does them so that others will trumpet them about.
Courage is not like almsgiving and praying.1 We may prefer that
courage be motivated for the pure sake of the virtue, as it sometimes
is, but if we hold out for that we will get very little courage. We cannot
be so persnickety about motives when a person is knowingly risking
life and limb. Though courage is not immune to being faked, it is
often the case that faking legitimately qualifies as the real thing.2 Of
course, not everything goes. A person too stupid to perceive the risk,
or too insane to have any awareness of danger, is not courageous.
One must recognize the risk, even if that level of risk does not make
one fear.
A common sentiment expressed in war memoirs of combat sol-
diers, manifestly brave men, is that they felt themselves cowards de-
spite being cited for courage, felt they had faked it.3 They knew they
had done deeds that are commonly thought to take courage, but
these moral rigorists were hard, too hard, on themselves; they felt
more like cowards who were lucky that they had not been exposed
for their false seeming. They were not just being modest, though they
33
faking it
34
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
you drank it in order to forget why you drank it, and also of not car-
ing very much even if you don’t forget where your newfound courage
has come from; you will take it any way you can get it. Much boot-
strapping makes great use of the emotions to obscure rationality: the
exhortation speech, the rebel yell, the “Battle Hymn of the Republic.”
Except for congenital optimists, who need no rum to delude them-
selves into believing this is not their day to die, most of us need all
these techniques and more to find our courage, to fake ourselves out.
And, though imperfect, such courage is not, by reason of its imperfect
motivation, hypocritical.
Politeness
If courage is largely immune from hypocrisy, if because of the sheer
difficulty of being courageous we allow the courageous act to com-
pensate for or obviate its less than perfect motivation, that cannot be
our excuse for politeness. Politeness doesn’t need an excuse; fakery is
openly admitted to lie at the structural core of the virtue. Politeness is
immune to many forms of hypocrisy because a certain benign form of
hypocrisy is precisely its virtue. Thus politeness gets one of the very
few of Ambrose Bierce’s definitions that could almost be called sweet:
“the most acceptable form of hypocrisy.” An evocative eighteenth-
century definition – “Politeness may be defined a dextrous manage-
ment of our Words and Actions whereby we make other people have
better Opinion of us and themselves” – could serve equally well for
the vice of flattery as for the virtue of politeness.7 Dextrous manage-
ment indeed.
Politeness need not be so cynically construed. We could give it a
nicer spin by noting how, at relatively little cost, it saves people from
unnecessary pain in social encounters. It is a certain willingness to
disguise our true beliefs and engage in small flatteries, small pleas-
antries, and white lies. It is to pardon or ignore small annoyances
and inconveniences. It means having the tact to cover for the faux
pas of others or to state your own claims in ways that will not make
for discomfort. It means responding to the cues people give you to
reaffirm their self-esteem as regards variously their appearance, taste,
35
faking it
36
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
37
faking it
heard it. The engagement may not even be feigned, for the interest of
the audience energizes you to reexperience your pleasure in the tale.
Suffering for the faults and failures of team members is sometimes
a simple matter of corporate liability or guilt by association, but it can
be more complex. I offer this homely example of my wife playing –
to borrow from Jane Austen again – Elinor to my Marianne, for
whom it was impossible “to say what she did not feel, however triv-
ial the occasion; and upon Elinor therefore the whole task of telling
lies, when politeness required it, always fell.”11 My wife feels that
part of her role in being associated with me requires her to engage
in what I feel are excessive gestures of politeness to compensate for
what she feels are my failures to meet the minimum standards of
inoffensiveness, whereas I view my “failures” in this regard as ef-
forts to compensate for what I feel are her excesses of politeness.
The more penetrating of our guests must suspect that her displays of
excited interest in their tedious tales or her sympathy for their petty
disappointments are partly to compensate for my having wandered
out to do the dishes in the midst of the conversation. Most are not
so penetrating, but those who are give her credit for caring to make
atonement for my failures.
It’s disgusting, she says to me later, that we fall into such predictable
gender roles: politeness feminine, failures of it – certain scripted fail-
ures to be sure – masculine. How can you write about this stuff, she
says, pick it apart in such tedious detail, and then get it all wrong in
the flesh, and not see how rude you were to Mrs. Z? That is more
domestic revelation than it is permissible here to indulge, except to
say that when I get the vacuum cleaner out while a guest is still seated
and tell her not to mind me but to please pick up her feet for just a
second so that I can get the inordinate number of crumbs she has
dropped, it is really only a function of my compulsive disorder. It has
nothing, I assure her, absolutely nothing, to do with my wanting her
to decamp.
If the demands of politeness can cause occasional anxiety among
homogeneous suburbanites, imagine what adding class, race, and
ethnic difference to the mix does. Big-time faking is on the menu.
How do we get our attempts at politeness understood as polite rather
38
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
39
faking it
40
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
front. Those hates and peeves are true only in the sense that we have
them at this precise moment. But why give those passing vexations,
annoyances, irks, and frustrations so much moral and social force by
giving blustery vent to them, thereby letting them create a state of
affairs that will endure long after the impulses have subsided?
Backed now by Santayana’s assurances, I should feel less anxious
about faking my politeness. But he helps only a little. His tone does
not quite disguise his own inability to banish his feeling hypocritical
for suppressing some of these urges. Part of him, it seems, like part of
me, still feels that politeness, like prudence – both surely praiseworthy
in their proper place – are to be suspected as a way of giving a virtuous
name to our cowardice.
One of the reasons why so few people are to be found who seem
sensible and pleasant in conversation is that almost everybody is
thinking about what he wants to say himself rather than about
answering clearly what is being said to him. The clever and polite
think it enough simply to put on an attentive expression, while all
the time you can see in their eyes and train of thought that they are
far removed from what you are saying and anxious to get back to
what they want to say.
(M 139)
41
faking it
42
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
43
faking it
44
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
45
faking it
and feelings inside? Back in 1968 it took a very stoned and unself-
critical hippie to forget that he was acting, posing, and living life
as theatre. What was being a hippie except self-consciously putting
on costumes that one was not entitled to wear: the army surplus
clothing, the pea coats, the Indian – both North American and Indian
subcontinent – outfits. It was not, as I recall someone once saying,
about being against the war or getting back to the earth, but about
having Halloween 365 days a year. Only a few were aware that it
was not authenticity that was being sought, but an inauthenticity so
overdone as to play up the falseness of all poses. Any real feeling of
authenticity tended to be chemically induced.
Not all phoniness, of course, is on the side of emotion display and
letting it all hang out. When the style of sober gravity was in vogue
among Puritans in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, merry old
souls lampooned it mercilessly as phony and fashion following, as
errant hypocrisy and humbuggery.
Marianne’s style is also criticized as parasitical. It can be indulged
in only because Elinor is there to smooth things over after Marianne
gives offense, as my wife is there to let me behave less than graciously
to guests who are overstaying the limited duration of my welcome.
But Austen also hints that the parasitism is mutual. Elinor shines
because Marianne is there to make the scenes that put Elinor’s ex-
traordinary poise and tact on exquisite display. Each provides a foil
for and relief from the style of the other. They even encourage each
other to play out their allegory of sense and sensibility by taking such
clear delight in each other’s mastery of her particular defining trait.17
They know that they make a good team.
Marianne’s impetuosity and imprudence turn out to be not that
imprudent (she marries better than Elinor), whereas Elinor’s prudent
reserve almost costs her her dear Edward, whom she gets only by an
improbable marring of the plot. As properly as she has behaved, there
seems to be a lesson here. Her self-command needed more leakage
so that sufficient glimpses of the passions being hidden were still dis-
creetly discernible.18 Sometimes you need to let on that your disguises
are disguises. One needs to keep reminding people, too, for they for-
ever fall right back into believing the disguise. Your four-year-old can
46
virtues naturally immune to hypocrisy
watch you put on a monster mask and then be terrorized when you
say boo to him immediately after putting it on.
In sum: don’t think that because hypocrisy is a disgusting vice that
dissimulation, imperfect motive, and the feigning of views and opin-
ions are not necessary to the cause of virtue. But because virtue must
cavort with such suspect company, can we be blamed for mistrusting
the moral state of our soul when we are being little more than polite
company? And suppose you decide that you will damn all dissimu-
lation and pretense in the interest of unvarnished truth. I give you
next the ugly sight of naked truth. And when I have finished I suspect
we will all admit the virtue of those small hypocrisies – call them
reticences if you will – that make us civil.
47
five
So you think there are times when the demands of politeness, the
burdens of restraint are more than you can handle? You think it is
easy to shed the trappings of civility? Then why does it take alcohol,
exhaustion, or a dare to get you to let the truth about your desires
and feelings all hang out (for the daws to peck at)? Norbert Elias
would have us believe that it was the work of centuries to make us
think politeness was easier than directness. It took a lot of time, a
shifting of political and social arrangements, he argues, to make our
self-restraint feel more natural than our lack of restraint. But I doubt
there was ever a time when it was easier to be truthful than to put on
masks and veils, even if the kinds of masks and veils in other times
strike us as crude and vulgar now.
Yet there are some who chuck all veneers of civility, claiming
(though this is often a pose) to be under the sway of a strong emotion,
such as anger, or a strong desire, such as a sexual one. Others do not
offer the excuse of a strong desire as long as they have pals, drugs, or
booze urging them on to be more vulgar than mere “nature” would
ever let them be.
Suppose two people take one look at each other and immediately
desire to do the deed. Though it has been known to succeed in cer-
tain cultural settings and though it types me as a middle-aged hetero
white male of puritanical, uncool, and conventional propensities to
be revolted that it does, it usually is not (or at least was not) the
case that one says to the other by way of introduction or within min-
utes of being introduced, “Hey, wanna f***?” I know it is phonily
prissy of me not to write “fuck,” but it strikes me as even phonier
to assume fake boldness or a fake flip casualness and write it. That
48
naked truth
The New Republic, The Nation, and other respectable organs use
“fuck” hardly indicates that it does not involve its user in pretense:
the pretense of the weenie feigning coolness. No way to avoid pre-
tense either way. God knows, “Hey, wanna f***?” gets said more
than I want to believe, and I would guess the lumpenproletarian
biker or bathhouse visitor no guiltier on this score than upper-middle-
class affected hip types or any average – I cannot, father of teenage
girls, bear the thought – high school junior. If as an empirical matter
such directness has become common fare, then let what follows
stand for a piece of history rather than a discussion of contemporary
mores.
Few (I hope) have the nerve to cut to the chase like that even on
a dare. You may have misread the other’s desire; nor do you want
to think of yourself as that vulgar, even if you have the excuse of
doing it on a drunken dare. So problematic is the allure, and the
corresponding contaminating power of sex, so holy in a bizarre way,
that one must assume all kinds of lengthy ritualized behaviors that
avoid directly avowing the desire. So what do we do? We talk, we
perform, we engage in elaborate rituals. In short, we rewrite the three-
word question into pages and pages, reconstructing it as one elaborate
periphrasis.
Nor is the word “f***” to take all the blame. Were you to say,
“Would you like to fornicate with me?” you would do no better.
In fact you would instead decrease substantially your already low
chance of scoring by revealing yourself a vulgar priss rather than just
a vulgar yahoo. Clinical language would do what it did in junior
high health class: prompt guffaws and giggles. Trying a more roman-
tic tone might be worse, for it suggests that the person asking really
thinks he stands a chance, and shows him oblivious to the fact that
the constraints imposed by when he is asking leave him with “Hey,
wanna . . .” as pretty much his only option: A “Pardon me, you
wouldn’t by any chance like to make love?” should get him laughed
at by the yahoo as well as by the stickler for decorum.
Decorum, respect for others and oneself, and politeness almost
always involve saying things in more words than the most direct
and most efficient statement of the desire would accommodate. We
49
faking it
teach our children not to grunt “ice cream”; we discourage the use
of the imperative mood except in the most exigent of circumstances.
Politeness requires the indirect expression of reasonable desire, not
the complete suppression of it. So it is “May I have some ice cream,
please, if it wouldn’t be any trouble?” The child adds even more
words, mostly in justification, about having had no sweets that day
and having eaten a very good dinner, which is a lie, but no matter.
The more indirect, the more polite, the more likely it is that the child
will get the ice cream as soon as the modestly elongated request is
concluded.
Be indirect, and ye shall be served – not too indirect, though.
Cultural rules vary greatly on this. Excessive indirectness in the demo-
cratic West smacks of Eastern slavish groveling, yes-sahib kind of
stuff. People who are ever so hesitant about making even modest
requests provoke bursts of frustrated annoyance: damn it, out with it
already, OK? And ye shall also not be served all the time. This is the
lesson that hits the two-year-old hard when the magic word “please”
doesn’t work to get her candy anytime she says it. The power of the
“please” not to please as advertised may well be a child’s first sense
that the world is not as enchanted as claimed. Parents, not science
and technology, disenchant the world.
Eventually we hope to make such politeness second nature, so one
would never think of it as fakery to express the desire as “may I
have” rather than grunt “ice cream.” But our direct vulgar desirer
answers: “I don’t grunt ‘ice cream’; I ask nice like my mother taught.
I say, ‘Hey, can I have some ice cream if you got any?’ I even add a
please. I still get my ice cream when I want it, not much more than
a second later. But I don’t want to take three weeks of boring talk to
get what I want now from that babe; besides, in three weeks I may
not want to do it anyway.” Given his unwillingness to take risks on
the duration of his desires, and his desire to live very much in the
present, I suppose he makes sense.
Contrast this with the shy guy who is more than willing to take the
days, weeks, months (I leave “years” to those much more persevering
than I can imagine) to fulfill his dreams, but who feels ever so acutely
that his periphrases are transparent. He thus dies a thousand deaths
50
naked truth
before asking a woman out for a first date even though he has no
thought of doing anything except talking. He is sure that “Would
you like to go see Twelfth Night with me next Saturday?” will be
heard by her as a little hum in the background not quite covering the
“Hey, wanna f***?” she will impute to him – and that at some level,
not far beneath the surface, he imputes to himself.
Sex, quite often not as satisfying as ice cream, can be craved as
much at certain times in the presence of certain others. Yet people
go through elaborate performances in which they purport to be in-
terested in what the other person does, what books she likes, what
food, what movies. They act interested in aspects of the other’s soul
as well as body; they, mostly the men, fight a desperate battle against
the powerful gravitational forces that pull their eyes down to check
out body parts beneath the eyes. Even fixing the lips with a look that
endures more than a nanosecond is taken as not much different from
blurting out the most vulgar declaration of desire.
What is especially interesting in this ritual of faking is that it in-
evitably becomes more than mere fakery. It can lead to disgust for
one’s initial desire or to a total extinguishing of it, as when the soul of
the other turns out to be unignorably dim, shallow, mean, defective,
or boring. You find you don’t wanna do it with this person anymore.
A nicer consequence of faking interest in other things beside the thing
is that faking in this domain becomes, if not quite an end in itself,
then surely a process with considerable charm. Deferring gratifica-
tion has its own rewards, small pleasures that are sufficient – well,
not quite – unto themselves.
Beware of making the easy assumption that it is a sign of how
deep the desire is that one is willing to invest so much time in talk,
talk, talk, and more talk. The amount of time you put in can support
exactly opposite meanings; it can mean you really really want to do it
so much that you are willing to invest considerably in getting there,
or it can equally mean you really want to find a colorable excuse
for postponing the dark deed.1 Delay is more than just a rational
means to get where you thought at the start you wanted to go. It also
reveals to you and to the other that you are discounting somewhat
your belief in your own desire. You think you wanna do the deed,
51
faking it
but in fact you are scared of it, too – so much risk of humiliation or
of befuddlement. Part of you is willing to run away without actually
doing it as long as you get some assurance that the other desired you
or at least did not find you repulsive.
The faking of interest in other things besides the big desire lets
your ambivalence about sex and your doubts about your desire have
their say, giving you the chance to escape if you wish. The part of
you that wants to do it is, you fear or at least wonder, not you, or not
all of you, or not the real you. You have the feeling sometimes that
your desire exists independently of you, that it is an invader from
the outside. Or you experience it as your genitals engaging in a coup
d’etat that will not bring a stable regime into power. The new regime
will collapse about fifteen minutes after the takeover, if, that is, it has
not already failed attempting to storm the breach.
But also beware of thinking that blurting out an unadorned vulgar
desire is any indication of its strength or clarity. If avoiding sex is
vaguely a part of your complex set of desires, there is probably no
better way to accomplish it than by coming on with a “Hey, wanna
f***?” Even if you truly want to do it, coming on like that is a way
to defend yourself against the pain of rejection because you have
to go in expecting to be refused; you in fact are inviting refusal. If
you ask like that and do mean it, your question is dealt with as not
having been meant and, if you are lucky, is laughed off as a bad joke.
(Treating egregious violations of norms of propriety as merely failed
attempts at humor is one of the classic strategies of tact to salvage a
bad situation.)
Who possibly can expect such an offer to be accepted, assuming it
is a male making it to a female? Not so dumb, those vulgar yahoos;
their very vulgarity proves to be the perfect defense against the pain
of rejection, which, I am sure, these touchingly sensitive souls would
rather avoid. Their vulgarity, to be sure, is more than a defense against
rejection; the indecency of the come-on provides its own form of very
cheap erotic thrill. Bizarrely enough, though, the eminent refusability
of such an offer is politeness itself compared with offers made in such
a way that all avenues of polite refusal are closed off, the kind of offers
mere acquaintances and relatives make: you wouldn’t by any chance
52
naked truth
be free sometime this year to come over for dinner, would you? Let’s
pick a date right now.2
And those souls who in fact have an unambivalent desire and ex-
press it with vulgar directness seldom do so outside a cultural or social
setting where it stands some chance of success. The yahoo male will
be drawn to yahoo females in a place where yahoos congregate. And
once he is there, alcohol, drugs, and raucous conviviality will provide
an excusing plea should he misjudge. Even such direct expressers of
desire as then-Governor Bill Clinton did not abandon all decorum
when seeking the services of Ms. Jones. With pants down, he asked
if she would “kiss it.” Kiss it?! In the midst of the most vulgar of
come-ons delicacy pokes (sorry) its head up through the harsh soil
of raw desire. Could we expel euphemism from this domain even
if we wanted to? This may be the realm of the unnamable, where
euphemism must intrude.3
Direct vulgarity is a strategy more available to men than to women.
Should a woman come on like that to a man and be turned down,
it would leave her nearly defenseless, because the yes is assumed,
though, truth be told, the male “yes” really means, if not “no,” then
“Well, I guess I will if I have to.” We must distinguish, however,
between those males who actually stand a better chance coming on
like that – people whose best moment is the first no matter how
vulgar the first moment may be – and those for whom time works
small miracles. Charm needs time, and not all that much depending
on how much physical unattractiveness it needs to compensate for.
Funny thing about charm: it can be openly seen to be so much roguish
fakery by the object of it. That is often part of charm’s charm, but the
charming person need not feel as if he is faking it for being charming;
he may be fully immersed in wanting to be admired and liked for
his charm. And when he sees that his charm is working, why then,
he just may pop the question, “Hey . . .”: or better, the object of his
attention will spare him that burden and ask first.
One of central themes – if not the central theme – of a good portion
of nineteenth-century English novels of manners is how to get the
truth across despite the veils with which we clothe it, or equally how
to repair the damage when we let truth show a little too much skin.
53
faking it
54
naked truth
“But you are so hard on one, my dear, with your running after
honesty, that one is not able to tell the real facts as they are. You
make one speak in such a bald, naked way.”
“Ah, you think that anything naked must be indecent; even
truth.”
“I think it is more proper-looking, and better suited, too, for
the world’s work, when it goes about with some sort of garment
on it. We are so used to a leaven of falsehood in all we hear and
say, nowadays, that nothing is more likely to deceive us than the
absolute truth.”
55
faking it
56
naked truth
The core irony of the passage, it turns out, is that once truth enters
the social domain as a strategy to advance self-interest it is magically
transformed into a fake, a pose, an act, and it becomes more deceiving
than the standard deceptions and poses of politeness and civility: “We
are so used to a leaven of falsehood in all we hear and say, nowadays,
that nothing is more likely to deceive us than the absolute truth.” The
choice facing Mrs. Smith, in other words, is not between truth and
hypocritical niceties but between different social posturings: one of
small lies and indirection, which we can pretty much play by rote
and still get the message across, and the other, naked truth, which
requires dares, drink, or drugs to steel ourselves to perform.
The next two chapters examine certain ritual practices – prayer and
apology, itself a form of prayer – and explore how these are variously
infected with hypocrisy and the anxieties of faking it. These are fol-
lowed by a chapter – chapter 8 – devoted to more homely matters of
praise and flattery, both of which are also intimately involved with
prayer, if not so much with apology.
57
six
58
in divine services
59
faking it
60
in divine services
61
faking it
62
in divine services
63
faking it
can give rise to the anxiety of faking it, only some of them convict
you of serious faking. Others come close to the line, but one suspects
that these kinds of doubts have been widely experienced. How could
they not, given that everyone since you were a small child has been
lecturing you on the assumption that that is what was going on in
your head?
Some prayers more than others are likely to be faked or to en-
gender doubts about whether they are being faked. We can, for our
purposes, divide prayers into two main kinds that have consider-
able overlap with the mental/vocal categories the Catholics employ:
prayers that are likely to generate the anxiety that we are faking them
and those that do not. Certain kinds of prayers grab us more readily
than others – those, for instance, not said in divine services as part
of a scripted pageant but that we compose ourselves. These are the
prayers we find ourselves saying when we wish to mobilize the deity
quickly or thank him profusely, often when we are in the embrace of
some strong emotion such as fear or relief. To be sure, such prayers
follow predictable forms and arise in predictable settings, but they
have the authenticity of spontaneity.8 Not that spontaneous prayers
cannot be faked; I would imagine that in certain charismatic religions
one must fake them all the time.9
Prayers of petition, particularly for immediate delivery from ene-
mies, prayers in which in the biblical sense we “cry out” to or “cry
unto” God, are much less likely to be beset with anxieties of fakery
than prayers of thanksgiving, unless the gratitude is an expression of
the “phew” of relief, as when narrowly escaping death, shame, or
a visit from a Jehovah’s Witness. Thus prayers uttered in foxholes
are completely sincere, although some soldier memoirs take note of
the self-conscious form these prayers take when a nonbeliever finds
himself praying for the first time since his childhood.10 One soldier
began, “God, if you get me out of this scrape, I promise to believe in
you.” But a prayer taking that form is not faked – quite the contrary.
It is as sincere a form of asking God to reveal Himself as can be made.
The person praying may indeed sense the irony, if his fear allows any
room for irony, but he feels no anxiety on account of not being into
his prayer; he rightly does not feel that he is faking it.
64
in divine services
65
faking it
and corrupt humanity, how could you dare approach the font of
purity?
Some, though, felt their wormhood so sincerely that they despaired
of God’s grace and did not pray. No faking there at all. The theolo-
gians intervened to proclaim them guilty of the sin of despair, the sin
against the Holy Ghost. You must not abandon prayer. Your self-
esteem is not to be so low that you are ever to doubt God’s powers
regarding your salvation; if you are in your own sight as a grasshop-
per and think others see you the same way, you get hit with forty more
years in the desert (Num. 13.33). But there is reason to think that peti-
tionary prayer, surely the foxhole variety, is the surest sign of despair
there is, a giving up of all hope except the last very long-odds gamble
that God will pay heed to your cry for help. The Victorian schoolgirl
quoted earlier saw it that way; her routine prayers for chocolate pud-
ding or for illness to befall her teachers were never answered “so that
on the whole I thought Him incorruptible . . .” When she realized that
any God she could believe in would have to be impartial, prayers of
petition ceased to make sense to her: “It was as if you were trying
to bribe the judge.” “After that, prayer became synonymous for me
with giving up hope; if ever I prayed again, it was only in a final
frenzy of despair.”11 In that frenzy one is too distracted to indulge in
anxieties of fakery.
When the stakes were high and sincerity was of the utmost impor-
tance, as in a communal fast decreed to beg God to relieve a drought,
the Jewish oral law (the Mishnah) sought to reduce the risk that the
person chosen to lead the prayers would not be properly motivated.
He was thus to be a man “who has children and whose house is empty
(i.e., he is destitute) so that his heart will be perfect in the prayer.”12
Now there was a man who would mean his prayers; his humiliation
was not a ritual show put on for the occasion but instead was his
true lot in life, imposed upon him by his poverty and the desperate
need of his children. I must confess to taking some small pleasure in
seeing that my anxieties on this score are not postmodern nor even
modern but have been troubling people for millennia.
We don’t feel we are faking when we bark out those daily prayers
beseeching God to damn people and things. These precations are
66
in divine services
67
faking it
The Amidah
Once we get away from cursing, thank-yous for escapes from close
calls, cryings out to deliver us from enemies, pleas to God not to
expose us as fakes to our friends and enemies – once, that is, we
are beyond the immediately personal into the prayer service itself –
the anxiety of faking it is much more intrusive. Let me give one
example that comes from the Jewish liturgy, but that I would imagine
is not dissimilar to the experience of many Catholics during lengthy
litanies, and Protestants in charismatic sects when too many people
start speaking in tongues and it is time to go home for lunch.16
The standard Jewish liturgy contains a prayer called the Amidah,
quite possibly the most ancient prayer in the formal liturgy, nearly
2,500 years old.17 It is long and is to be read silently in Hebrew
while standing (the word “Amidah” comes from the root for “to
stand”). Depending on the holiday, it can run to some ten pages or
more. Given the limited facility many in the congregation have for
reading the Hebrew script (even fewer understand the Hebrew they
68
in divine services
are saying), it could easily take the scrupulous person fifteen minutes
to read. When finished, you can sit down. Once the congregants have
completed their silent devotion, the entire lengthy prayer – this is the
truth – is repeated out loud from the altar.
Ritual always involves repetition but not of this magnitude and
duration (the cantor at my synagogue last Rosh Hashanah managed
to burden each syllable with so many notes that the repetition of the
Amidah lasted eighty, yes, eighty excruciating minutes). One senses
a whiff of rabbinic cunning: the ancient sages suspected that many
would not resist the temptation to cheat at their silent devotion and so
decided to visit the sins of the fakers upon faker and nonfaker alike.
Maimonides, in the twelfth century, admits as much. The Amidah
is repeated, he says, “in order that anyone who has not recited the
prayer [silently] shall be regarded as having discharged his obliga-
tion.” Thus those who do not know the prayer, he says, finding a
pious reason, get the benefit of the presiding reader reading it for
them.18 But he is ruthless, for if you recite it without proper devotion
you are to recite it again, he says, this time devoutly.19 The Sages
meant it when they said you were to mean this prayer when you said
(or did not say) it.
In contemporary conservative congregations, most people, I would
guess, are faking, skimming at best, but mostly skipping whole big
sections. One can hear the buzz of fake Hebrew. People surrepti-
tiously look to see what page others are pretending to be on and then
decorously turn a page ahead of that. Finally a few people start to sit
down. I strategize as to when I, who could barely muddle through my
Bar Mitzvah portion, can plausibly sit down and not expose myself
as a cheat. I read a few sentences, then switch over to the English
translation on the opposite page for a few, then back to the Hebrew.
Then I skim a bit, then pretend two pages are stuck together, then just
gaze around. I sit down after about a third of the congregation has
already given up, mostly to set a good example for my kids. Within
a minute or two all but five or six people are seated. No more than
six minutes have passed since the congregation launched forth on its
silent prayer, not enough time for more than the gifted few to have
read it even in English.
69
faking it
70
in divine services
more zealously for who could daven the fastest than for who could
run fastest or catch the best.
Davening is praying, rocking back and forth as you half mumble,
half-hum the Hebrew you are pretending to read. Needless to say,
this too led to all kinds of anxieties, and I for one could never rock
back and forth during prayers without feeling a complete fool and
fraud. I always did so rather embarrassedly, botching the performance
horrendously. How did anyone overcome embarrassment to fake this
adequately? (Conservative Jews still engage in a modest rock, reform
Jews have gone completely, WASPishly still.) It was simply beyond
me, of an ilk with cheering with abandon at high school pep rallies,
with doing karate yells, or with saying “groovy” in 1968. To my mind
there was no way a self-respecting, self-monitoring person could do
or say these things without feeling like an idiot. I could never do
full-Megillah davening, even when I was the only one not doing it,
as was the case at this camp. I would be only too happy to claim this
willingness to stand thus apart as a kind of moral courage, but it was
no such thing: I was too self-conscious, more embarrassed in my own
eyes for doing it than I would be in their eyes for not.
Was my self-consciousness a pathetic form of incipient self-hatred,
seeing the world a little too much through Christian eyes, or did
young Jews growing up in the shtetl have the same anxiety about
davening, in their case experienced as faking being a pious adult? Or
was it only fearing that I would look so obviously hypocritical, trum-
peting self-evidently fake piety? I settled for a very mild sway, a mere
shifting of my weight from foot to foot. Given the long time a Jew is
asked to stand during prayer my small movements were thus explica-
ble as purely natural and thus, I fancied, not too hypocritical nor so
indecorous that I would be embarrassed if a Christian saw me. Thus
did I join the fray in a kind of lame fashion, starting light years be-
hind, being about the only kid in the camp not to come from a kosher
home. Keeping kosher in Green Bay would have meant vegetarianism
because there were too few Jews to support a butcher; and in those
days most intelligent people felt vegetarianism would lead to death
by malnutrition, if not by pretension. Pretentious vegetarianism still
lay a few decades in the future.
71
faking it
For half the summer I braved the looks of the faster readers waiting
for me to sit down, for in this camp the rabbi waited until all had
finished before beginning the repetition. I wish I could say I had coldly
calculated that, by standing and facing everyone’s hostility, I was
winning points in the piety game. Truth be told I had been skipping
paragraphs right from the start, and I was still the last kid standing;
I had been cheating too modestly. I was completely snookered by the
other kids, who I believed were not faking it in the least. I could not
believe that religious Jews would do such a thing or would need to
do such a thing.
Maybe these guys could really read their Hebrew at the speed of
sound, some apparently at the speed of light (a colleague remonstrates
that I should not seek to attribute to others my ineptitude at reading
Hebrew script). There was for me only one solution: give up on my
nickel and dime faking and fake wholesale. I developed the technique
of mumbling out a real Hebrew phrase here and there so that those
around me would hear the place on each page I was staking my false
claim to. Each day I sat down a little earlier, until I had risen to be in
the top third, now a really adept speed-reader myself.
Formal secular rituals generate similar anxieties, even a routine
“Star Spangled Banner” before a ballgame. Everyone knows that
you can start cheering during the last line of the anthem without
being sacrilegious, though it would be bad form, no matter how
big the game, to start yelling before “oh say does that star spangled
banner yet wave.” Knowing when to cheer does not present much
of a problem; it’s how to stand and whether to sing. Should I take
off my hat, do I put my hand over my heart, do I stop chewing my
gum? Do I sing robustly with all the signs of patriotic fervor, or do I
kind of hum along? Do I purposely sing an octave lower to outmacho
the guy next to me? While all this is going on, how are the feelings
of patriotic reverence supposed to be attended to? Unless there is a
flyover. Then I am moved to tears by the beauty of those jet fighters,
by the precision of the flight, by their sudden appearance and equally
sudden departure, by the noise. I have thoughts like, “Oh Lord, I will
accept a raise in taxes if it goes to making things that beautiful; yes,
72
in divine services
Cynical Ceremony
The Amidah, despite being widely faked, is part of ritual that peo-
ple take seriously. Consider, however, a culture of complete cynicism
with regard to its Rituals. That is how Stephen Greenblatt describes
Thomas More’s world, one “in which everyone is profoundly com-
mitted to upholding conventions in which no one believes.”21 What
do we make, for instance, of Richard III’s cynical farce, which fooled
absolutely no one, of rejecting the offer of the crown and then
“reluctantly” accepting its re-offer? What of the consecration of a
bishop that is a charade because everyone knows he bought his of-
fice? “The point,” Greenblatt says, “is not that anyone is deceived
by the charade, but that everyone is forced either to participate in
it or watch it silently.” The more you can make people swallow, the
“more outrageous the fiction, the more impressive the manifestation
of power.” The claim apparently is that these rituals are so fake that
they constitute an in-your-face challenge to hoot them down. When
those in attendance fail to do so, they then have to accept themselves
as cowards or, if not quite broken in spirit, at least safely docile in
the face of the usurping authority.
If we concede that such breaking of the spirit may be one of the
effects of the performance, it hardly should be conceded that its
73
faking it
74
in divine services
long enough and you will believe, if only after a fashion. Maybe such
beliefs are only “beliefs,” but they are not disbelief or rejections.
Belief comes in all degrees of intensity; very few in the West believe
so firmly in Heaven that they will seek martyrdom to achieve it. Most
have some small discount built into their beliefs without making their
belief no belief or reducing it to a mere “belief.” The appalling dis-
plays of dignity-destruction that were a frequent occurrence during
Stalin’s purges – in which people were made to profess belief in a new
orthodox position they did not understand and then had to deny that
belief weeks later and then reaffirm it weeks after that – are especially
horrifying because even these people came to believe, or ceased dis-
believing, the crazy and nonsensical claims being forced upon them.
Animal Farm and 1984 are not exaggerations, but understatements,
as the unnerving Gulag memoirs demonstrate.24
A strong-minded recusant could profess allegiance to an entity he
loathed and make his mental reservations while professing. As long
as the authorities did not ask him too frequently to profess allegiance
he could, with luck, maintain his initial commitments. But should
the authorities become more insistent and keep him under surveil-
lance and force him to speak against his beliefs again and again,
then it would take an extraordinary commitment and continuous
mental effort to keep up his faith. Eventually the mental reservation
itself might become a vehicle of self-deception in which you convince
yourself that a real you exists independently of all your words and
deeds, that you really are still a Catholic living a secret life in a hos-
tile Protestant regime, or a rational human being trying to muddle
through in the mass lunacy that characterized the totalitarian regimes
of the twentieth century.25
The converso Jews in fifteenth-century Spain were subjected to
surveillance and had to live outwardly as Christians, attend Mass,
pray to what they believed was a false Messiah. Those who actually
succeeded in secretly maintaining their Judaism must have devoted
incessant labor to it and must have given each other much mutual
support not eventually to become what they feigned to be, as no doubt
most did.26 But Kurt Vonnegut’s “We are what we pretend to be, so
we must be careful what we pretend to be” makes no allowance for
75
faking it
76
seven
Some emotions are easier to fake than others, and some are
easier to hide than others. La Rochefoucauld says that as a general
matter it is harder to disguise emotions we have than to pretend to
have those we do not.1 The truth of this matter seems to require
a big qualifying “it depends.” It depends on which feelings we are
trying to cover up and which we are trying to feign. It is much easier
to disguise what Hume called the calm passions than to disguise
the violent ones. I can cover up benevolence more easily than my
sense of disgust, my sense of satisfaction in a beautiful object more
easily than my grief.2 And though it is not hard to feign interest,
concern, amusement, and other emotions that are commonly feigned
in routine conversation, one can almost choke at times trying to feign
delight in the unexpected arrival of a visitor or in a colleague’s big
raise.
Some emotions are characterized by postures and facial expres-
sions that are easy to fake: joy, surprise, female sexual pleasure, anger,
disgust. Very few are impossible to fake in some way, and that is a
very good thing. If we had to rely on really feeling an emotion to
display it, most of us would have been murdered long ago by people
we offended.3 Imagine, as an evolutionary fantasy, that the signs of
our emotions and other inner states were unfakeable or unveilable.
How different human society, if even conceivable under such circum-
stances, would have to be. It is the susceptibility of our emotions to
being disguised or faked that diffuses the violence latent in so many
of our social interactions. We can thank the synergism of our own
acting ability and capacity for mimicry coupled with the ease with
which the bulk of humanity can be conned and duped.
77
faking it
78
say it like you mean it
79
faking it
the driver he is all right and to beg the driver’s forgiveness, claiming
correctly that it was 100 percent his fault for darting out. The driver,
white as a sheet, is in turn falling over himself, shaking, apologizing,
begging forgiveness from Larry. Both are sincere and profuse in their
apologies; one for causing the accident though he in the end is the
one who got hurt, the other for being a prop in an accident he did
not cause, but in which another got hurt. Larry knows that the driver
will blame himself for merely having been in the wrong place at the
wrong time. Larry is thus apologizing for the harm of making the
driver think he needs to apologize to Larry. The only faking going on
is Larry’s. He is pretending not to be hurt. In fact, he is so embarrassed
and apologetic that he has not yet processed how hurt he is. His very
adrenalin-motivated urge to apologize has intercepted the pain he
will begin to feel as soon as he limps away. It is hard to find mutual
apologies so sincere.
I add two qualifications. There are times when the impulse to
apologize for accidental harms is muted or intercepted. What if the
person we inadvertently smash into is someone whom we already do
not like? We will apologize readily, perhaps more readily, because
the other person, knowing our distaste for him, has special reason to
think it was no accident. Or if he does accept that the harm was not
intended he may doubt that we are really sorry. He suspects we will
be taking a small delight in the happenstance. He is probably right
too. “You know, this was a complete accident, I am so sorry.” Then
comes our mental reservation: “But as long as it happened, I hope it
really hurt.”
The second qualification requires that we make note of the kind of
insupportable person who never thinks anything he does is wrong and
who thus never feels he has reason to apologize. The harms he inflicts
are, to his mind, the fault of the other: “It is your fault for getting in
the way of my fist.” “You should’ve started out thirty seconds earlier
for work; it is your fault for being in the intersection when I went
through the light.”
Some cases mix intentional with accidental aspects. In these, it is
precisely the lesser amount of presumed intentionality that makes
the apology stand a better chance of being sincere. Take these two
80
say it like you mean it
81
faking it
82
say it like you mean it
apology for a harm you meant to inflict is faked. They are often sin-
cere gestures of commiseration and pity in a low-stakes routine way.
Sometimes they are so rote as only to mark that you acknowledge
having heard the complaint and are responding in a polite way that
is no less scripted than answering “fine” to a “How are you?” Yet
this kind of I’m sorry can on occasion mark remorse. When a mother
says she is sorry her child scraped his knee we are still in the realm of
low-stakes commiseration, but when she says she is so very sorry the
child gashed his forehead and requires fifteen stitches to close it, the
apology may reflect the mother’s remorse for her failure to protect
the child against the injury.
There are also compulsive apologizers, ever anxious about the
harms they believe they may have caused others. They sincerely mean
their apologies, but they seldom have anything to apologize for except
their accidental wrongs. They are truly remorseful.16 But such people
devalue the worth of their apologies by apologizing so readily that
their apologies become nervous tics. They find themselves apologizing
for harms they did not commit or, in an especially extreme variant,
apologizing to the person who harmed them. This latter style can be a
form of pathological cravenness, or its own kind of moral heroism –
the form it takes, for example, with Dostoyevsky’s Prince Myshkin.17
What does an apology mean coming from someone like this, however
sincere it might be, for whom real remorse seems to come too easily
or who seems to take a little too much pleasure from apologizing?
83
faking it
84
say it like you mean it
man had sinful intercourse with a woman, and after a time was alone
with her, his passion for her persisting, his physical powers unabated
while he continued to live in the same district where he had sinned
and yet he refrains and does not transgress, he is a sincere penitent.”21
This is more than monitoring the penitent’s future behavior; it is a
testing, a courting of temptation – dangling the goodies before his
eyes – and thus a tormenting and hence a continued punishment
of the penitent. The strictness of the sincerity test is lessened by a
corresponding duty in the wronged party to forgive, and evidently
to trust the penitent to alter his behavior. This from the tractate on
torts: “The injured person, however, is forbidden to be harsh and to
withhold forgiveness . . . But once the offender has asked forgiveness
and has entreated him a first and a second time, and he knows that
the offender has repented of his sin . . . he should forgive him.”22
85
faking it
dangers of glitches were real and people felt the emotional intensity
of the performance. This was Ritual, not mere ritual; one smirk from
anyone in the audience, and the agreement not to take blood could
vanish.25
Honor cultures make apology and forgiveness, even for accidents,
very dangerous stuff because both look as if they might be motivated
by cowardice. When the wrongdoer was a child or an old man or a
woman, I’m sorry’s could be accepted without much anxiety. But
for warrior-aged men the presumption was that harms were inten-
tional unless proven otherwise. The burden was on the harmer to
show he did not mean it, but that got him caught up in fearing to
look cowardly by looking too fearful to face the consequences of
claiming the harm to have been intentional even if he hadn’t meant
it. The apologizer, it was suspected, harbored a cowardly and ab-
ject heart. He was apologizing because he was scared of having the
damage he inflicted revisited upon him in revenge.26
But the person who readily accepted an apology was also sus-
pected of harboring a cowardly heart, revealing himself too scared to
hunt down and kill the person who knocked him down. His fear, it
was believed, biased him in favor of interpreting ambiguous harms as
unintended. Isn’t the connection between ready apology and forgive-
ness and cowardice still true today? My quick and ever so concerned
I’m sorry for inadvertently bumping into someone is more quickly
given if the offended person looks angry and big enough to avenge
himself on me. And I am cravenly eager to forgive the same big per-
son when he bumps into me. Cowardice makes these apologies and
forgivenesses sincere, but not more remorseful than regretful.
Because of its associations with cowardice, only the strong and
powerful could risk granting forgiveness (it was one of the preroga-
tives of power)27 – but not frequently, and they rarely apologized. Not
having to say you’re sorry is another prerogative of power. Because it
looked like weakness to apologize, some people felt they had to stand
by even the stupid things they said or did, posturing stubbornly until
they “reluctantly” acceded to the demands of reasonable people to
back down and make amends. A trivial accident between two people
with no prior enmity could easily explode, becoming the first incident
86
say it like you mean it
in a formal enmity that could last years. But “reluctantly” still de-
serves the scare quotes I gave it because the reluctance was no less
likely to be faked than the apology it was pretending to refuse to
make. The risk was that if you acted your reluctance to make peace
too well you would end up stuck nervously awaiting the avenger’s
axe for having refused to pay up.
The offer of sixty sheep shows that this apology was not cheap.
The injured man could accept them because it could be claimed that
the compensation set a high value on his honor. Being struck, even
accidentally, was a dishonor – not only because the motive behind it
always allowed for some ambiguity as to the degree of its intention-
ality, but also because others might be taking pleasure in the victim’s
pain, laughing at him in the way bystanders laugh when someone
has a pratfall. People often look foolish for being the butt of an acci-
dent. We have special demeaning names for such souls if they make a
habit of this particular kind of bad luck: sad sacks, schlemiels, losers,
people sadly without much honor.
The sincerity of X’s apology cannot be divorced from the com-
pensation payment, which plays two roles in the transaction: it is
compensation for the dishonor to Y of having been struck, and it is
proof that he is willing to pay more than lip service to the issue of
intentionality. The apologizer can be trusted at the minimum to feel
sorry for the loss of his sheep and thus also to be sorry, though indi-
rectly, for the harm done to the other. That much they could verify.
Any true remorse was unverifiable.
Move this into more familiar surroundings, less dramatic but rec-
ognizable to any parent with more than one child. You tell one kid
to apologize for some harm he did to the other. He refuses. You, in a
sterner voice, order the apology. Continued refusal. You threaten him;
in Ann Arbor, the threat might include Draconian measures such as
a timeout for which the threatened sentence of fifteen minutes in his
toy-filled bedroom is inevitably commuted to five minutes. The kid
still resists giving the apology until you take a menacing step toward
him, upon which he turns to his sibling, not completely frontally, but
45 degrees off center, and sneers an I’m sorry in the most unapolo-
getic tone mutterable. Then back to us sternly: “Say it like you mean
87
faking it
88
say it like you mean it
knows will not be the case in a professorial household. But if she had
to choose between having her brother forced to apologize and getting
a ten-minute timeout? Easy case: make him say, “I’m sorry.”
The kids who refuse until seriously threatened to spit out their
unfelt apologies are truly better destined for the world of honor than
the world of therapy to which they had the misfortune to be born.
Sometimes they simply will not say it; they will not apologize no
matter what. Smash their toys if you want; they won’t budge. Got
to admire them for it. Thus it is that to force an unfelt apology is
not completely unsatisfying, for it is not easy to overcome the nearly
infinite will to power of the average five-year-old. If our little tyke
has to say uncle, he will still say it defiantly – but he is beaten and he
knows it, his very defiance being the proof of his loss. In a strange
way this is a win-win outcome. The apologizer, by willfully exposing
the fake apology as a fake, gains the dignity of some kind of sullen
defiance, and the original victim gets the joy of how much it hurts
the apologizer to go through the motions of his fake apology. His
very dignity-preserving gesture of defiance is his admission as to how
much humiliation he is suffering.
Someone deeply committed to the rhetoric of forgiveness, apology,
healing, and restoration of relationships will think my account of
apology a travesty. He would say that the story of the unapologetic
child is not a story about apology; that I have committed an error of
categorization, confusing punishment with apology, merely because
the punishment takes the form of a farcical apology. But it matters
that the punishment takes the form of forcing an apology rather than,
say, imprisonment. The ritual, even if performed badly, pretends to
make some sort of amends to the wronged party, which the latter can
choose to accept or not.
A more pious message lurks in the parent’s orders: in the future,
little boy, you should do the groveling and humiliate yourself; your
conscience should prompt you to it; that is what remorse is. Right
now, because your conscience is treating you too favorably or is to-
tally undeveloped, we will do some playacting. We will dress up as
your conscience and make you grovel and beat your breast for you.
You must be made to lower yourself before the other and be beaten
89
faking it
Suppose that our now well-trained child has learned to say “I’m
sorry” when appropriate and to say it nicely. Not only that, but he
has come to accord his inner state with his words so that he is now a
fully moral being; he genuinely feels remorse when he says his sorries.
What about you, the wronged person? Are you going to accept his
apologies? Do you not fear that it may have come a bit too easily?
Won’t you make him stand in the snow for a few days anyway, make
90
say it like you mean it
him wear some sackcloth, eat some ashes, maybe even want to see
him crucified? Why should anyone believe a sincere apology could
dispense with punishment?
But our sincere apologizer answers, “I am punished; I have been
punishing myself with remorse; my sense of well-being will be de-
stroyed forever if you do not forgive me. Even with your forgiveness
I will be scarred by the memory of my transgression.” “Fine and
dandy,” you say, “but I still want sixty sheep.” You even believe him;
you accept him as being truly remorseful. Moreover, should he be
faking, he is faking with such skill that the performance alone merits
crediting; it would be tasteless and graceless not to reward such mas-
terful acting. As La Rochefoucauld would have it, “Some disguised
deceits counterfeit truth so perfectly that not to be taken in thereby
would be an error in judgment” (M 282). The implications of La
Rochefoucauld’s maxim are not easy. Apparently, the deceit is not
so masterful that it passes without being noticed as a deceit, even at
the moment it is working as a deceit. Deceits, it seems, can work in
more ways than by simply deceiving. They can elicit awe for their
chutzpah, or daring; how is it that snake oil salesmen sell their wares
though every one knows they are lying? As Trollope rightly notes,
“A man may lie in such a way as to deceive, though no one believe
him.”31
Yet do we really believe that people are as hard on themselves as
they should be even when they are feeling truly remorseful? Might
they not actually be pleasuring in their guilt, vain of their self-
punishing capacity, feeling rather self-congratulatory about it, and
oh so moral, proud that they have such a sensitive conscience?32
Whatever humiliation they suffer by apologizing feeds their self-
satisfaction. Where is the compensation to you in their pleasure?
Might they not, by feeling ever so guilty, come to believe they are
allowed, even entitled, to forgive themselves? We can’t let them get
away with that, can we? In the words of the diarist Victor Klemperer,
“If one settles accounts with oneself, forgiveness is self-deception.”33
Apologies, faked or real, are often accepted and repaid with for-
giveness. To forgive, however, is not to forget; it is not letting bygones
be bygones. Forgiveness is merciful when compared with the revenge
91
faking it
92
say it like you mean it
93
faking it
damn. But such small encounters can escalate if the ritual forms are
not given their due. Apologies are also often given and received by
people who love each other or who have absolutely no wish to find
reasons to establish enmity. Such people, if they are the wronged
party, wish to believe in the sincerity of the apology or, if they are the
wrongdoer, hope that forgiveness for their sincere apologies can really
restore relations to a peaceful state. For petty wrongs, no problem.
The little I’m sorry’s of day-to-day interaction are freely traded; your
screw-ups are not only compensated for by your apologies, but by
my screw-ups too. We content ourselves to trade screw-ups back and
forth, along with apologies. But for big wrongs? Hand over the sheep,
sixty of them.41
94
say it like you mean it
95
eight
Praise is a good thing, we are told. We are thus to extol God out
of gratitude; we are urged to praise our children to assist their self-
esteem and confidence. We praise virtue and excellence, the motive
varying, but partly because the very praiseworthiness of the person
or deeds elicits the response almost involuntarily, as when we burst
into applause at an amazing performance in art or athletics. Flattery,
in contrast, has been cursed by moralists from the earliest of times;1 it
is hard to find a vice more excoriated. It is felt to be cheating, getting
a step up on the competition by engaging in a form of bribery. The
unfairness of it wouldn’t quite justify the vehemence with which it is
cursed if it were not that flattery had such extraordinary powers. Few
are so virtuous as not to be seduced by it, and thus many are tempted
to flatter because they almost certainly stand to gain by doing so.
Mostly it was the special vice that undid rulers, or people wealthy
enough to have followers and entourages: the “monarch’s plague,”
Shakespeare called it.2 Men who ruled others needed counsel, and it
was much pleasanter to hear one’s praises sung than one’s errors and
vices admonished and blamed.
The flatterer was often pictured as a kind of pimp, a purveyor of
pleasure to the organs of our vanity. As with the allure of delights
of the flesh, the temptation is overpowering. Flattery is narcotic and
addicting. It preys on two desperate and inescapable desires: to be
thought well of by others and to think well of ourselves. The second
desire depends on the first more than the first on the second; in any
event, they are complexly intertwined. Nor is either of these desires
mere vanity: they are much of what makes us socializable; nor is either
entirely distinct from what we, flatteringly, call conscience. We desire
96
flattery and praise
97
faking it
Tainted Praise
The common view is that flattery is a fraud, a fake; the dictionary
view is that it is false or insincere praise. But what is the basis of
its falseness? That it is not meant? That cannot be true; flatterers
can sincerely believe what they are saying. That the praise is false?
Although much flattery is false, not all is. I can flatter handsome
persons by telling them how good-looking they are. A teacher loves
to think that students are telling the truth and that they are sincere
when they shamelessly flatter her by telling her that her course was
the best offered in the school. Can’t the poor teacher, desperate for
approbation, believe in the innocence of the students’ intentions if
they say so after she has submitted the grades and the ones saying
it are not the ones who got the A’s? Yes, and that is just how she
flatters herself, though the students may not be conniving flatterers
for having flattered.
So flattery can be sincere and can be true. Then what could possibly
distinguish it from praise, which is also both sincere and true? Might
it be that flattery does to praise what hypocrisy does to all virtue:
infects it so that the real thing can never be trusted? Let’s assume
now that we are dealing with praise, both sincere and true, and see
whether we can keep it from being infected with flattery’s vices. Praise,
no less than flattery, raises the problem of how to handle the benefits
that will come your way as a byproduct of the praise you give. Are
you blameless as long as you do not praise for the reason of getting
rewarded for your praise? How naı̈ve do you have to be not to know
that praise is often rewarded by the person praised? Isn’t that what
motivates a good portion of the praise we give our children and our
dogs (and God too)? We hope that praise will move them to do what
we want them to do in the future, not merely build their self-esteem.
Dog-training manuals are richer than self-help books on this theme.
Praise, even more than flattery, should prompt rewards. The person
flattered might suspect the flattery is false or that it was motivated
primarily to be rewarded, and thus dismiss it if he possesses a steely,
virtuous soul. Praise, on the other hand, to the extent that it is not
flattery, is itself something of a virtue and should be rewarded. It is,
98
flattery and praise
after all, a kind of gift. And gifts demand recompense. The praised
person who does not reward sincere praise looks like an ingrate and
eventually may come to be blamed as one.5 But balanced against
the praised person’s desire to reward the praiser is a concern that
rewarding praisers will encourage flatterers, and the praised person
doesn’t trust that he will always be able to discern the difference.
Leave it to La Rochefoucauld to suspect that there is no difference
between praise and flattery. For him, praise is merely a sophisticated
form of flattery:
We dislike praising, and never praise anybody except out of self-
interest. Praise is a subtle, concealed, and delicate form of flattery
which gratifies giver and receiver in different ways: the latter ac-
cepts it as the due reward of his merit, the former bestows it so as
to draw attention to his own fairness and discrimination.
(M 144)
La Rochefoucauld is not dealing with low-level, on-the-make flatter-
ers. His praisers are no less vain than the people whose vanity they
flatter by praising them. They praise to be praised in return for prais-
ing astutely, for their penetrating taste and intelligence. This is much
subtler than seeing a flatterer as praising because he suspects it will
be rewarded by some material advancement. Here the act of praising
is itself its own unsavory reward in a world in which vanity, vanity,
all is vanity. We expect, however, that praise will elicit more than
admiration for praising well. How often have you seen people tell
others how nice they look in order to be told the same? Because we
cannot ask to be praised, we often fish for compliments, and praise
is sovereign bait for catching praise.
Is flattery any different? We indeed flatter to get credit for dis-
cernment, as when we pay homage to trendy positions we strongly
suspect are vacuous but fear that we will be seen as vacuous if we
do not flatteringly pay our respects. It is the emperor’s new clothes
all over again. And we surely flatter to be flattered in return. We are
always told to spurn flattery when we are its object, but in fact we
love it, even when we know it is flattery, when we know the person is
sucking up (pardon the vulgarity, but the behavior tends to invite dis-
gusting imagery). It all depends on how he does it. If he smarms and
99
faking it
100
flattery and praise
101
faking it
102
flattery and praise
103
faking it
104
flattery and praise
105
faking it
Observe the little habits, the likings, the antipathies, and the tastes
of those whom we would gain; and then take care to provide them
with the one, and to secure them from the other; giving them,
genteelly, to understand, that you had observed they liked such a
dish, or such a room for which reason you had prepared it: or on the
contrary that having observed they had an aversion to such a dish, a
106
flattery and praise
dislike to such a person, etc., you had taken care to avoid presenting
them. Such attention to such trifles flatters self-love much more
than greater things, as it makes people think themselves almost the
only objects of your thoughts and care.
This passage goes a long way to confirming Samuel Johnson’s dev-
astating description of Chesterfield’s letters as teaching “the morals
of a whore, and the manners of a dancing master.”15 This is an in-
struction in fawning, sedulousness, officiousness, and conniving, es-
pecially when you shamelessly collude against some absent person
by mentioning the care you took not to invite him. But Chesterfield’s
son is a bastard and must please others to advance or even to hold
his own; he must learn to crook the pregnant hinges of the knee,
as indeed must many an employee in various job hierarchies in our
world. Ugly business, and what do we suppose to be the inner state
of Mr. Stanhope, the bastard son, as he carries out this advice? It
is a role he is being instructed to assume, but can he possibly play
it without a bad taste in his mouth, without some bit of distancing
himself from the lines he must say? According to Diderot, whom we
will encounter more fully later, he need merely learn how to crook the
knee without any according of his sentiment to the role: it is about
mimicry; he can make mental reservations as he says his oily lines.16
Yet Johnson’s suspicion is that this is what makes the whore a whore,
and a dancing master a dancing master, and nothing more. Shake-
speare suggested via the bastard Edmund that playing such a role for
the sake of advancement may generate all kinds of resentments and
vengeful bitterness in the bastard boy. But it is no less likely that peo-
ple will come to enjoy the safety and advantages of their serviceable
roles and live rather happily and productively as slimy insinuators.
Chesterfield, to give him credit, is hardly confusing praise with
flattery. He acknowledges that it is flattery he is teaching, and if his
boy learns his lesson he will come to get praised for his complaisance,
his charm, his manner and manners. If you are loathsome as a flatterer
to the object of your flattery it means only that you are no good at
it. If you are loathsome to those who resent, envy, or begrudge your
advancement, you can dismiss them as losers at a game you beat them
at. Your successful flattery prompts vices in them; they entertain mean
107
faking it
thoughts, they tattle on you, and gossip. But that only makes them
look like enviers of your talent for advancement, and that is praise
indeed, though a skillful flatterer would also find a way to assuage
the resentments of his competitors even as he triumphed over them.
And then they will emulate you.
Chesterfield accepts as a given, and there is little reason to doubt
him, that adept flattery will please all but the most stony superior,
and even he will not welcome being told the truth. Our desire to
be flattered will make flatterers of our friends out of kindness, of
our underlings out of fear and desire for getting a leg up on the
competition, and of our superiors out of a desire better to get us to
do their bidding. There is no getting rid of the vice, and a good thing
too, or many more of our days would be ruined than already are.
108
nine
109
faking it
Talking to Hamlet
The mere mention of Hamlet in a book about faking and feeling like
a fake is a temptation to dive in and drown. Consider the plight of
Ophelia and Gertrude, who must pretend that they are having normal
conversations with Hamlet but know they are staging it for eaves-
droppers hiding behind arrases and elsewhere. Bad enough, as I have
been supposing, to have to attend to the colleague you are talking to
and worry about what you are going to say next. But imagine if that
colleague were Hamlet. A reptile on a cold day would be a nervous
wreck talking with him.1 How do you converse with Hamlet and not
walk away feeling humiliated unless, like Horatio, you have culti-
vated a stoical disposition? Hamlet is so much smarter than you, and
he delights in never letting you forget it. He makes each conversation
a contest to see whether you can follow his speed-of-light access to
startlingly original images juxtaposed in difficult and fantastic ways.
He tests to see whether you can fathom his incessant punning, his
playing with words only a tenth of which you grasp at the moment;
and while you are figuring out how to respond to them, another
hundred whiz right by you, ones that future editors of Hamlet’s con-
versations will spend years parsing. When you finally steel yourself
to open your mouth, he plays with your words, turning them against
you or making you not only feel stupid but look it too. Now add that
Gertrude and Ophelia have to perform not just for Hamlet but for
the eavesdropping Polonius or Claudius and know that by so doing
they are betraying Hamlet. It is amazing they don’t give up imme-
diately under the stress of the duplicitous conditions in which they
are being asked to converse and perform as genuine interlocutors.
No wonder Gertrude can continue discussions with Hamlet quite
rationally in the presence of Polonius’s bloody corpse. For her, the so-
cial situation has become infinitely simpler now that she is not being
overheard and can attend fully to her son’s whirling words. To credit
Ophelia’s and Gertrude’s attempts to act naturally when they know
they are being overheard, recall how hard a time Hamlet has convers-
ing with his mother when he discovers the ghost is eavesdropping on
him.
110
hoist with his own petard
111
faking it
112
hoist with his own petard
they may miss you, tunneling five yards to the right or left; it is the
fourteenth-century version of the submarine movies I grew up with.
As Hamlet, the counterminer, says: “O, ’tis most sweet, When in one
line two crafts directly meet.” Craft here means stratagem; it is not
a shift to nautical imagery. The countermine to gain its end must be
dug so as to intercept the mine. The lines must meet. But if they miss?
The miner wins, the counterminer loses, for he bears the risk of loss,
the loss of his home base, if he fails to stop the miners.
Countermining is a defender’s strategy, but unlike the paradigmatic
defensive strategy of awaiting the advance of the enemy, it requires the
defender to move forward and intercept. The whole imagery of mines
and countermines is rich in its suggestiveness about strategizing and
identity, how so much of it must be carried out blindly or in very dim
light, secretly. How like our own interiors and subsurfaces, where we
hatch our plots and orchestrate our roles but also where we often
don’t see very well through the murk of vanity, stupidity, and smoky
passions; the space and place of operations are obscure. The space
is also spooky, magical, and it can turn things into their opposite –
hate to love, coldness to warmth – and it is often lethal to songbirds.
I offer one stunning example of the magic of the mine. By the rules
of fourteenth- and fifteenth-century warfare, should two enemies of
knightly rank meet and fight in a mine, they became brothers-in-arms
and one could no longer take the life of the other; one also had to
help pay the ransom of the other should he be captured or set him
free without ransom should they meet again on opposite sides above
ground.6 Talk about transformations of identity and role!
This is surely one of my frolics, but not quite a detour, for strategiz-
ing under the ground darkly brings me back to the idea of the roles
we play and the degree of our immersion in them. Precisely when
does faking it work such a transformation upon the faker that he is
more faked out than his audience? He is not always hoist with his
own petard when this happens. He is indeed if he is a seducer, the
“cunning fool”7 who finds he has fallen in love with his quarry and
now suffers all the anguish of a jilted lover when she dumps him.
But there are other times when we devoutly wish to be hoist with
our petard, to find that the role we are faking takes over and we end
113
faking it
114
hoist with his own petard
Ironists
The ironic pose is a common one and more complex than most. Those
who adopt it seem to feel that irony gives them some control over
feeling foolish about playing the various roles they are self-conscious
about playing. It is a style of making one’s less than full immersion in
various roles the substance, as well as the style, of one’s character. The
ironic style is made up usually of a few parts self-mockery, more parts
mockery, all devoted to constructing a distance, an ironic distance,
between role and self, so that whatever gaffes and screw-ups occur
will be cushioned by a certain deniability. To play up anxious self-
consciousness in this way helps inure the ironist to it or lets him take a
second-order delight in it. The ironical posture also helps improve his
chances of being the center of attention by altering the game subtly
into one in which he can star for not being as good at the real game
he thinks everyone else is playing more adeptly than he could. He
often is pleased by his irony, flattering himself with the belief that it
takes more intelligence to be so painfully aware and self-aware.
At the very least irony keeps him, or so he believes, from being hoist
with the petard of uncritical full immersion into the conventional
roles he is called on to play. But the irony is that instead of lowering
the stakes of failure he raises them. Though irony provides an excuse
that he wasn’t playing for real, in fact he is playing for keeps. He
is not about to refuse the benefits he gains in social and self-esteem
for being good company, nor will he fail to feel chagrin at the losses
he suffers when his shtick fails to gain him social credit. Unlike the
person who plays it dully straight and goes home to a good night’s
sleep, our ironist worries how his act went over.
Though this kind of ironic style is meant to call attention to itself as
a pose, it is still committed to good manners. Its practitioner means
only to amuse or to be amused by introducing a whiff of drollery
into simple encounters, not to make scenes or make everyone else
115
faking it
awkward. Yes, a little more risk is introduced into the setting, but
only in the interests of interestingness and of protecting himself from
the risks of nonironic social interaction. This is not the freshman’s
view of irony, in which words are used in the opposite of their literal
sense, and it is broader and subtler than merely saying one thing when
you mean another but with an intonation or wink so that there is no
blame for a lie or misrepresentation.8
This kind of irony can function as a fake fake, for it is hardly
the case that he is not still properly filling the roles he is pretending
to distance himself from. It is trite to observe that we suspect that
certain people might also adopt this style to cover a deep seriousness
that they think, at some level, it would be bad form or unsafe to
reveal. They thus pose as ironical when they are dead serious. Part
of the motive may be that they are shy or embarrassed by their own
seriousness or afraid to give up the defense their irony provides. And
what is one to do once the conventional markers of seriousness and
sincerity have been polluted beyond repair by those given to new-age
“I hear you”-style signs of concern, by politicians, by people who
believe themselves serious and sincere because they have learned to
look you in the eye, or into the television camera, and not smile,
except with unctuous empathy?
I do not mean to delve very deeply into the various styles of ironic
poses except to mention a few of the most common types.9 There is
the knowingly defensive ironist, anxious about his position. He can
be a high-status person desperate not to seem snobby; or she is the
anxious middling soul uncertain of precisely where in the hierarchy
she is; or they are those self-conscious occupiers of the marches and
border regions of full personhood, who are never quite sure whether
they are in or out: the Jew, the affirmative-action admittee, the fat
among the thin, and so on.
There is also an ironic style we associate with snootiness, usually
adopted by people who think themselves brighter than they are, and
hence their irony often becomes the failed irony of a would-be ironist.
Incompetent ironists have a moral failing we tolerate about as well
as we tolerate a completely humorless person. The latter we avoid as
a killjoy, the former we fantasize we might enjoy killing. The sins of
116
hoist with his own petard
the bad ironist are numerous: they insult us by their lamely hostile
comments, which are all the more offensive because they radiate su-
perciliousness, excessive self-regard, and contempt. If their irony is
a defense to cover various fears, those fears are buried deep indeed,
for these are usually very self-satisfied souls.
The ironist is not quite the licensed fool, the court jester, although
he runs the risk of becoming one if he cannot modulate his pose from
time to time. Unlike the ironist, the fool has a privilege to overstep
the bounds of propriety because he is already deemed a nonperson.
His privilege, ironically, comes from the fact that he has no other
privilege but to be a fool, and this means he must speak the truths
that politeness refuses even to the ironist. He is compelled not to fake
it, to tell the whole truth and nothing but that truth that Mrs. Harold
Smith found so hard to do even when freely resolved upon. He must
expose pretense, whether he wants to or not, and that is another rea-
son the fool is harmless – not only because he is counted no person,
but also because his truth is constrained, not freely told, and hence
dismissible as compelled and not meant. Contrast the constrained
truth of the jester with the constrained unfelt apology of the impeni-
tent wrongdoer. Coercion makes the apology work as compensation,
whereas coercion makes the jester’s truth a joke.
Cultivating an ironic sensibility as a way of handling one’s own
anxiety about faking roles, or failure to get into role, or one’s anxiety
about one’s own seriousness, or as a means to prevent getting hoist by
excessive immersion into one’s roles, is, ironically, a petard waiting
to explode in your face. For being an ironist is a pose. It too is a
role, an amusing one if played well and very conventionally within
the array of acceptable social roles. But the ironist takes on risks
that other presentations of self do not take on in the same degree.
He had better be good at it. It takes very fine adjustments to mock
without offending, to self-mock without self-aggrandizing, and to
assume ironic posturing without calling into question whether there
is any nonironic self that is left to be protected by the pose. It can
also become excruciatingly tiresome. The risk is that irony ends in
self-involved shallowness, irony all the way down, a chronic refusal
to take anything seriously. Ultimately there may be no there there.
117
faking it
But I wonder. If being an ironist is itself a role, like other roles, then
it can be taken off, if not quite at will, then stripped off involuntarily.
It is hard to be ironic all the time. One must eat, sleep; and one
complains and means it. More than anything one gets bored, not in
the style of ennui, which forms an unholy alliance with irony, but
plain old bored as when listening to people discourse on where their
kids are applying to college. Irony also beats the rats off the sinking
ship, long before life itself is threatened, when things are getting to
you. Furnaces break down, pipes burst, your spouse’s needy friend
just rang the doorbell, and you see no humor in it at all: nothing but
pure unaccommodated reality.
Most ironists in our day are not the kind of ironist a saga hero
was; he would joke in the face of his own violent death, and he could
do so because his irony worked in the service of his sense of honor.10
A saga character named Atli remarks dryly on the fashionableness
of the spear used to run him through; Hrapp congratulates the per-
son who chopped off his arm as doing the rest of mankind a service.
Honor was not a joking matter; but death was. Our kind of bemused
irony – “I am above losing my entire being in any role I play, I have
a proper critical perspective” – doesn’t have great staying power in
the face of serious humiliation or pain. It does fine with small-stakes
embarrassment, but not with bigger issues such as betrayal by some-
one you love or the discovery that you are physically revolting to
the person you have a crush on. You may put on a mask of irony
to hide the pain, but you are no longer an ironist when you do so,
for you are recoiling in misery, buying time until you figure out how
to reconstitute your being, desperately serious, hurt, vengeful, and
bitter.
118
hoist with his own petard
119
faking it
ready when someone calls us on it. But no one ever does, until one
day . . .
On bad days she cynically suspects it is an unwritten rule that no
one calls anyone’s bluff unless someone pretty much dares you to.
The whole world is faking it, and everyone is complicit in everyone
else’s frauds. That is not fair. She has acquired real judgment. She
knows she doesn’t know everything, but she knows something; she
sees people who indeed know much more than she knows, more than
she believes it is humanly possible to know; and she genuinely respects
and admires such people more than she fears them, but fear them she
does, for surely they must see through her. These are the people who
are “the real thing,” truly knowledgeable, who she imagines must feel
secure in their mastery of their subject, though perhaps they never do
either. She comes in the end to believe that her anxieties about faking
it and exposure are the very form her respect for mastery takes. On
good days she lets herself believe that she might not be faking it; she
is truly what she once had to fake being; she is one with the role, a
lawyer and a pretty good one at that.
The analogy with the lawyer is not quite apt, but it suggests that
if someone plays being an ironist long enough, a mocker, a person
who fancies he is deep and needs to protect his depths – with humor
when he is charming, but with sneers and superciliousness when he is
not – he eventually becomes his defensive system and nothing more.
A walled town, with everyone inside dead of the plague.12
No sooner do I write that than some part of me stands outside my-
self and says, come off it, Miller, what pretentious overdramatization.
You really are not ready to defend the implication that somehow the
nonironist has any more people alive inside her town. It is the letter,
remember, that slayeth, not irony. That metaphor about everyone
dead inside the walled town suggests there is a lively core housed
within that needs defense. Just what is at the core? One true self, a
town full of clamoring burghers, or nothing at all?
120
ten
121
faking it
122
the self, the double, and the sense of self
123
faking it
feature of sanity, is assuredly there. Whether the self that the sense of
self senses is there, too, is probably not susceptible of proof.
Most of us, even when sitting with 60,000 identical souls at a
football game or when packed into a subway car, except in brief
moments of dissociation, feel quite certain, self-deceiving though it
may be, that we have a uniquely indelible core – embattled perhaps,
but still special and our own. Me, a mere subject position? My foot.
But why my foot? Is that foot part of my self, or merely attached to
it? Would I cease to be me without it? Does my self need it? Surely if
I am a serious sprinter it does. And why did I utter “my foot” as an
expletive? Is it because it is even lower by one measure than the arse,
which stands halfway between foot and head but still is understood to
be the bottom – even named “bottom” or “bum” – spiritually lower
than the foot? And thus the foot, because physically the lowest, is
able to work as a euphemism for the lowly arse, which I, in a gesture
of politeness, substitute prissily for ass, opting for the English form as
against the American. And why is it that in biforms such as arse/ass,
curse/cuss, burst/bust, horse/Hoss, it is the short-voweled r-less form
that is lower in social status?
Desperate to distinguish my self from others I am thrown back
on the fact that whoever I am I cannot tickle myself. I am also the
only sighted person in the world who needs a mirror to observe the
progress of my hair loss, and I am thus the only person in the world
who can construct a self that forgets how thin my hair is in back
while still caring desperately about it. But that’s a start. Not even my
clone or double can say that. My self is intimately tied up with my
being embodied in a way that distinguishes me from others so that I
am aware that I see their bodies differently and more fully than I see
my own. That means the only full view I can get of myself requires
others, for how can I see myself whole unless I see myself as others
see me, a view I can guess at pretty reliably based on my experience of
how I see them? I also need human culture to manufacture mirrors,
because mere nature with its reflecting ponds will not do the trick of
letting me see the back of my head.
This also raises complex questions of whether my body needs to
be a particular type of body for me to be me. My view is that it does,
124
the self, the double, and the sense of self
for though I have been envious of other body types a good portion
of my life, I have not been all that envious, for I fear that a body
too different from what I got stuck with genetically would make it
impossible for me to have the same inner life, which, such as it is,
I would prefer to keep. Not because I find it all that interesting,
but because without it my self as I know it would cease to exist, or
so I fear.14
My self, then, to the extent I have one, seems to require some kind
of embodiment, and not just any kind. Is the same always true of
my sense of self, the feeling of being a thinking thing with thoughts
that are mine alone? It has been forcefully argued that the sense of
self is a purely mental phenomenon, for which the body is merely a
vessel:
The early realization of the fact that one’s thoughts are unobserv-
able by others, the experience of the profound sense in which one is
alone in one’s head – these are among the very deepest facts about
the character of human life, and found the sense of the mental self.
It is perhaps most often vivid when one is alone and thinking, but
it can be equally vivid in a room full of people. It connects with
a feeling that nearly everyone has had intensely at some time –
the feeling that one’s body is just a vehicle or vessel for the mental
thing that is what one really or most essentially is. I believe that the
primary or fundamental way in which we conceive of ourselves is
as a distinct mental thing – sex addicts, athletes, and supermodels
included.15
125
faking it
126
the self, the double, and the sense of self
127
faking it
form of show trials. Smith assumes for the most part here that these
internal trials of ourselves are not marred by overt deceptions and
self-deceptions, but he well knows that the impartial spectator is brib-
able, suborned by the various tricks of self-love, envy, and interest –
the log in the eye again.
128
the self, the double, and the sense of self
129
faking it
The individual who performs the character will be seen for what
he largely is, a solitary player involved in a harried concern for
his production. Behind many masks and many characters, each
performer tends to wear a single look, a naked unsocialized look,
a look of concentration, a look of one who is privately engaged in
a difficult, treacherous task.23
130
the self, the double, and the sense of self
131
eleven
So i ask again: where amidst all these roles lies the true self, that
core of authenticity, that real me behind the masks and veils, that
authentic Bill Miller, not the guy who signs this book William Ian
Miller? How I got the Ian long before that name became pretentiously
fashionable is a story in itself, an innocent one of my dad doing honor
to the Scotsman Ian McPhearson, who commanded the ship on which
my dad served in the war. I was named after William Isidore Miller,
my father’s dead father, really Velvel or Villkela Yitzhak Miller in
the Yiddish that was my namesake’s native tongue. When you are
Bill Miller there is always a good chance you will be sitting next to
another one on the airplane; you get the mail of several others on
your campus, and most recently you lost five years of accumulated
frequent flyer miles because some other William Miller in Ann Arbor
took a trip around the world on them. So you posture as William Ian
Miller purely as a practical matter. But had my middle name been
Seymour, I see you thinking, you would not be signing your books
William Seymour Miller, would you? Spelling out that Ian, latching
on to it as a veil of sorts, shows I know very well who and what I am
at the core.
132
at the core at last
not very funny, but given Freud’s usual fare not bad enough to pro-
hibit retelling:
The doctor, who had been asked to look after the Baroness at her
confinement, pronounced that the moment had not come, and sug-
gested to the Baron that in the meantime they should have a game
of cards in the next room. After a while a cry of pain from the
Baroness struck the ears of the two men: “Ah, mon Dieu, que je
souffre!” Her husband sprang up, but the doctor signed to him to sit
down: “It’s nothing. Let’s go on with the game!” A little later there
were again sounds from the pregnant woman: “Mein Gott, mein
Gott, what terrible pains!” – “Aren’t you going in, Professor?”
asked the Baron. –“No, no. It’s not time yet.” At last there came
from next door an unmistakable cry of “Aa-ee, aa-ee, aa-ee!”
The doctor threw down his cards and exclaimed: “Now it’s time.”1
133
faking it
the Baroness is trying so hard to pass. But the joke is that neither a
Jew nor a Jewish joke can be anything but what it is. Their cores are
ineradicable. No amount of culture will change the Jew; his Jewish-
ness will burst through at embarrassing moments. That is the surface
point of the unbowdlerized joke, and the deeper one of the bowdler-
ized version. All those parapraxes, those Freudian slips, are so many
lapses into Yiddish or into a telltale accent. The point of the joke is
that there is no risk that a Jew desiring to pass will ever fake so well
as to become one with his new role.
John Murray Cuddihy argues powerfully that Freud’s purpose is
to war against the goy, to rub his face in the uncivilizable Jew. Because
the Jew could never make a good civil Christian, show the Christian
instead that underneath his veneers, his politeness, civility, decorum,
restraint, and good manners, he is at his core nothing more than
what he thinks the Jew is: a bestial, filthy sexual thing, precultural,
neither civilized nor civilizable. The bowdlerized Jewish joke says that
at our core we are instinct and beast, prelinguistic and precultural
screamers.
But that aa-ee, aa-ee is also a mask for Yiddish, Jew talk. The sug-
gestion is that the first human sounds of agony are not just nonsense
syllables, that they are not a pure manifestation of unadorned nature
that comes with the purity of pain, but that those pure unadorned
natural vocalizations are Yiddish, or some kind of masked Jew talk.
Jew talk in the Western tradition was the ur-talk, the first talk, the
natural language of humankind, and the language of pain. The point
is not the humanist one that at root we are all mere forked animals,
but a more hostile one that at root gentiles are no better than a bunch
of Jews trying to cover it up with perfume and manners, a claim that
is a horror to Christians, too nauseating to contemplate.
Among the many hypotheses offered to explain anti-Semitism, at
least in part, has been a supposed Christian bitter envy of the Jews for
having been chosen as God’s people. This view would then propose
that the Christian could resolve the pain of his envy by making the
lot of the Jew unenviable; make it so unpleasant as to breathe a sigh
of relief that God had not chosen Christians like you to be tortured
by the likes of you. But the one thing that must have still stuck in
134
at the core at last
the craw was that during that period of history when God cared to
speak directly to human beings at all, He had chosen to speak to Jews.
No mediation, no translation necessary.3 Though Christians insisted
that from the time of Jesus God was veiled to the Jews, who in their
blindness could not see the One Way to the Lord,4 that loss did not
quite assuage the envy of the fact that the Jews could talk directly
to Him and He to them. He was a co-linguist of the Jews. The Jew
could hear God and understand Him, argue and bargain with him,
as Abraham, father of the Jews, did in Gen. 18.23–33. Christians,
however, had to secure translators to hear God or his son, for both
spoke in a Jewish tongue, whether Hebrew or Aramaic.5
Imagine, though, how to explain that God became man as a Jew.
You could argue that God chose the most telling way to humble
himself. Incarnating himself as Achilles or Socrates rather than as a
Judean would have carried a very different message. But God, like
pagan deities, cannot shake completely a habit of tricksterism; there
are more than a few ironies in choosing to enflesh Himself as a poor
Jew. Can we suppose a deep Christian anxiety that God, instead of
masking Himself as the Jew Jesus, in fact, was stripping Himself of
all His own veils and masks, revealing the naked truth about His own
core identity? It turns out that God’s indelible self, in the Christian
exegetical tradition, his core, is the Jew Jesus, harbored deep inside
His bosom until the time was ripe to loose him upon the world.6
Like man, like God: Jew at the core. “Aa-ee, aa-ee, aa-ee!” For the
anti-Semite, and for Freud, the Jew has a fixed self beneath his masks;
it is Western civilizing Christian culture that is the costumery of roles
and poses, fronts and fakes.
If there is a core that is the pure us, that purity is subject to con-
tamination. A researcher on disgust asks us to consider the effects
on a barrel of wine of adding a tablespoon of raw sewage compared
with the effects on a barrel of raw sewage of adding a tablespoon of
wine.7 The wine is magically transformed by the sewage, rendered
disgusting and undrinkable. The sewage, however, remains just what
135
faking it
136
at the core at last
137
faking it
138
at the core at last
139
faking it
140
twelve
141
faking it
Yet few would deny that the shades and taints of stigma linger; the
scars are discernible, and the people who bear them are occasionally
tempted by plastic surgeries, figurative and real.
I will stick mostly to Jews in this chapter, with a preamble about
Americans abroad, because I am a Jewish American and that gives
me some license to say truths that if said about other groups would
be deemed unprivileged. Truth is not accepted as a defense in such
cases; in fact, one of the chief themes of this book is that truth is
an offense, seldom, if ever, a defense. I especially want to get at the
moves we make to disavow certain identities for the nonce, not for
all time – small cowardices perhaps, but nothing major. It is about
roles again, and fitting in, and trying to avoid petty embarrassments.
Big shames and humiliations I put to one side.
Distancing oneself from others whom one is lumped with often
involves a set of motives we loosely call self-hatred, but it needn’t
be as grave as that. Self-hatred, like love, lumps together a lot of
different phenomena. The emotion directed against oneself may not
always be hatred but rather contempt, or disgust, guilt, or shame, or
simply a vague dissatisfaction, not even as bad as low self-esteem.
It may be more or less durable, no more than a passing moment at
one end or an immutable trait of character at the other. The loathing
can be for traits that are yours alone or yours only to the extent you
belong to a disfavored group.
Self-hatred can thus have different styles depending on what you
hate yourself for. You might hate yourself in one way for being short,
in another for being fat, in another for being skinny, black, Jewish,
crippled, blind, old, or cowardly. And because self-hatred often takes
its cast from the hatreds of those who hate you, it matters greatly by
whom and for what you are hated, and the ways, means, and his-
tory of that hatred. Presumably the self-hatred of American blacks,
to the extent they are self-haters, would not be structured in the same
way or take on the same style as the self-hatred of Jews, for whom
self-hatred seems to lurk at the very core of diasporan identity.2 Not
all the powerless and disfavored dislike themselves in the same way,
if they dislike themselves at all. Nor are sentiments of negative self-
assessment solely the curse of the powerless.3 I might feel embarrassed
142
passing and wishing
by privileges I have that I feel I hold unfairly or are not quite legit-
imate but that I am still not willing to relinquish: so-called liberal
guilt, a sentiment that can readily be blamed as merely sentimental,
no more moral than Claudius’s weak or self-indulgent guilt noted
earlier.
An American Tragicomedy
Take the case of a certain kind of American self-hatred that is moti-
vated by class and regional biases, and also by a snobbish antidemo-
cratic impulse. The fear is that one belongs to a people that proves
itself consistently to lack sufficient insight to loathe itself for its beer
bellies, for coming from the prairies, for utter obliviousness to pre-
tensions regarding coffee and wine, for enjoying tractor pulls and pro
wrestling, for bad sexual politics, for being drawn to drawing a bead
on furry creatures with beautiful brown eyes, for being more reli-
gious than is seemly, for having no culture, and, in a very restricted
and bad faith way, for being white, for this kind of self-hater is him-
self inevitably white. What he loathes, in other words, is that these
average people seem so damn authentic and at ease with what they
are, and he cannot believe they should be. Those sorts were supposed
to be shepherds playing flutes and lyres in Arcadia, and it turns out
they are tailgaters eating brats and blasting boomboxes in the parking
lot before the Packer game.
No self-hating American of the kind I am describing feels that
American blacks harm his amour-propre in the same way as does a
white frat guy or a yahoo tailgater. Not because he is not racist, but
because he feels he will never be held accountable for loud fat blacks
in the same way he will for loud fat whites. Indeed, he is willing to
concede with some sincerity that blacks have style.
There is no self-hatred, quite the contrary, for coming from
Berkeley, from Greenwich Village, from unproductively pleasant-
looking settings in Vermont or on Cape Cod, or from any other place
deemed suitable for a second home. This self-hatred, though distaste-
ful, is not as morally defective as, and should be distinguished from,
the self-hatred that characterizes much of the American left as when
143
faking it
144
passing and wishing
145
faking it
146
passing and wishing
147
faking it
So secure are Brits that they are barely embarrassed by their soccer
hooligans. I suspect they are just a little prideful that they can set the
standard in boorish and violent self-assertion as well as in matters
of poise, tact, and reserve. Since when did any Brit mind that one
of his countrymen beat the living daylights out of a Belgian or a
Frenchman? There are some groups that are seen as winners no matter
what, and one never hears of the problem of English self-hatred.8
Something about them makes others accept their mildly self-mocking
self-satisfaction as utterly justifiable, something most would agree
seems much less to be the case for the French, whose self-love seems
indecorous, it not possessing the boisterous and generous innocence
of the American version of the same. Funny too is that I feel no
inconsistency in being manifestly proud of being an American and
admitting how nervous those damn Brits make me about it.
Passing
I know I am making some cavalier, maybe offensive, assertions,
parading American anxieties and prejudices as if they were getting
at Truth, but they are getting at some kind of truth, one many of us
have to own up to, however grudgingly.
Take the case of passing, as in light-skinned blacks, closeted gays,
and delicately benosed, blondish Jews. Passing involves, whether in-
tentional or not, disguise and dissimulation. In one sense, all faking
it is a form of passing, but the idea of passing is properly reserved
for big fakes. It is not about being polite when you don’t want to
be. It is about faking what most people feel are essential aspects of
identity for which all would agree the stakes are high: thus a woman
going off to war as a man is passing, but not a sixteen-year-old boy
lying about his age, because the recruitment officer is trying to sign
up bodies, not expose and refuse kids eager to fight. It is about faking
gender, ethnic affiliation, sexual orientation, race, and religion. That
doesn’t quite capture all the cases either. Goffman would include any-
one whose natural identity is stigmatized in some way and manages
to conceal it. We might also want to consider that a spy must pass,
as must many an infiltrator the basis of whose passing is ideological
148
passing and wishing
and political, but it would seem an expanded use of the term to apply
it to an unfaithful spouse keeping an affair secret. Con men of the
more mundane sort seem to fall on the nonpassing side of the line,
too.
What makes passing full-fledged Passing is that it is undertaken
in relation to what is perceived to be a low-status default identity.
Motives can vary. Self-hatred need not play much of a part. Coleman
Silk in Roth’s The Human Stain is a purely opportunistic passer who
simply decides not to correct people’s mistaken assumptions about
his identity. Coleman harbors no special loathing for his people. Some
people, in other words, pass without trying to; they fake out others
without faking it. Consider the turmoil of self-blame this could lead to
for the very non–Jewish-looking Jew or very straight-acting gay who
fears he might look cowardly or self-hating if he took advantage of
not being immediately recognizable as a member of his pariah group.9
He may thus find himself searching for decorous ways and occasions
to leak out the information as “naturally” as possible.
Assimilation can be viewed as quasi-passing, as a willingness to
adopt the styles and manner of the favored group without disclaiming
the low-status identity.10 Even here the lines get fuzzy. The assimilator
does not see himself as a deceiver in the way a secretive passer is, yet
he may be seen as trying to pass, both by conservative members of
his original group and by hostile members of the favored group. In
other words, he will be blamed as a Passer or an attempted Passer.
Assimilation could be understood to be a strategy of passing at
the level of the genes rather than at the level of the individual; the
first generation assimilator will fool no one, nor does he mean to,
but his children and grandchildren will intermarry with the favored
group and eventually will merge with the nonstigmatized popula-
tion. The first-generation assimilator begins the process of identity
laundering.11
Many in the favored group fear assimilation as a plot ending in a
bastardization of their blood, while many in the assimilating group
fear the dilution of theirs. The two fearers thus share a common in-
terest, and one need not be too paranoid to imagine a despairing Jew,
sick at the thought of his people surviving so many persecutions only
149
faking it
Classifications based on skin color allow for passing, too, for wher-
ever one drew the line, at one drop or at one great-grandparent, there
were going to be many who fell just to the wrong side who were in-
distinguishable in looks from those who fell just to the right side.
Whatever race was conceived to be, it wouldn’t always be easy to
see.14
150
passing and wishing
The passer runs the risk of exposure that in some regimes could
have more serious consequences than being chucked out of a country
club, painful as such a humiliation would be.15 The passer is faking
it big time, and he must fake out others completely or else the jig is
up. It may be, however, that the anxiety of being discovered is more
than compensated for by the delights of knowing you are bamboo-
zling those on the inside, not to mention the obvious benefits of not
suffering the indignities of being an open member of your low-status
group.16 Not that the glee of putting one over need always run in the
passer’s favor. The dominant group may have set you up, letting you
believe you are passing though they have seen through you from the
start. It is their secret kept from you that they have let you believe
you have a secret kept from them. Your expulsion will come at a time
of their own choosing guaranteed to make a cautionary example of
you, which they (and your own) will regale themselves with from
beyond your grave.
Sometimes, strangely, the dominant culture abandons its surest de-
fenses against the passer. I was seven, the year 1953, in Green Bay. We
were one family in a small Jewish community of about thirty fami-
lies. I was the only Jew in my school class until fifth grade, when two
others joined me. The night before I was to attend my first swimming
lesson at the local YMCA, my father and his brother sat me down
for an earnest discussion to prepare me, they said, for what I would
face the next day. They hemmed and hawed, but the upshot was that
I would notice that I was different from the other boys, who, they
said, would “not have a ring around their penises” as I did.
That night I peered closely to inspect the ring that had heretofore
escaped my attention. Nothing I saw looked like a ring to me, but
then, not to worry, for once I had checked the other boys the next
day the matter would be resolved. At the Y I tried ever so discreetly
to catch a glimpse of the other boys as we undressed and then as we
swam naked. I saw short penises, long ones, skinny ones, fat ones
too; I saw crooked ones with a bend sinister, some dexter, some up,
most down, but I could not for the life of me discern what the ring
was that they didn’t have that I did. God knows I wouldn’t have
been such a close observer of these facts, nor would they have seared
151
faking it
themselves into my memory, but for Dad and Uncle Gene trying to
spare me trouble on this score; they meant well.
How could Dad and Uncle Gene have been so wrong? It is embar-
rassing to confess the number of years that passed before I discovered
what the ring really was, even more embarrassing that in deference
to my father and uncle I believed it to be the skin within a half-
millimeter of the urethra. Within the twenty-five years that separated
my father from me, Christians in Green Bay had exchanged Pauline
figural circumcision of the heart for Yahweh’s literal circumcision of
the flesh.17 Making circumcision the norm worked to deny male Jews
a stubborn sign of exclusivity while at the same time giving them a
kind of passe-partout, a foolproof means of evading ultimate detec-
tion if they had already managed to remain undiscovered with their
clothes on. Why would Christians give this up? Why would they so
easily cave in to their doctors? (This change took place long before
Jews had penetrated the medical profession in significant numbers.)
It has nothing to do with guilt over the Holocaust, for the practice
had already begun shifting in the late nineteenth century, apparently
taking its good-natured time getting to Green Bay, something it had
yet to do by my father’s boyhood there in the 1920s and 1930s.
Various voguish late–nineteenth-century medical theories argued for
circumcision as a health measure whose time had come; it promised
all kinds of benefits – cures for compulsive masturbation, for paralysis
too, to say nothing of the virtue of having cleaner and less odiferous
genitals.18
Science was also operating, it has been suggested, in response
to anxieties of Protestant America, which was concerned to distin-
guish and insulate itself from the filthy teeming masses streaming into
America, more of whom were Catholic – Irish, Italians, and Poles –
than were Jews. If there was a colorable argument that circumcision
was cleaner (and surely the elimination of smegma should clinch the
case for those inclined to be fastidious about such things), then the
circumcised Protestant could still feel he was not mimicking a Jew in
his heart, for his motives were secular. His conscious motive was hy-
gienic; his unconscious motive was social and anti-Catholic, albeit no
less hygienic for that. The advocates of circumcision took great care
152
passing and wishing
153
thirteen
It has been fashionable for some time in the humanities to argue for
various species of cultural and historical relativism. Suppose a pro-
grammatic cultural relativist or, as the more pretentious cant would
154
authentic moments
155
faking it
majesty of the sea moves them. They are not faking that, but there
are all the other status gains to be had by communing with the sea
that makes their refusal to have the same experience at Lake Superior
a form of vanity.
That is why I distrust those who claim too much for salt spray
because I suspect that some of what they like about it is the proof
it provides that they are on the coast and have not been tricked by
the Great Lakes; olfaction is needed to save their culturally imposed
ranking system for the sublime. Is there really anything inherently
more beautiful about a mountain than the plain, about the sea than
Lake Superior? If the flat infinite expanse of the ocean makes it, why
can’t the flat infinite expanse of the plains? There are ugly moun-
tains, too, and ones that are kitsch, that are less sublime than a field
of wheat, with the wind stirring the expanse into iridescent waves
stretching as far as the eye can see.
So why is the sense of infinitude a selling point for the sea, but a
reason to dismiss the plains? Is it because the sea and mountains are
scary in a mighty way, whereas the plains, to these sophisticated ap-
preciators of beauty, are scary only because they are believed to house
boring people? Yes, says Edmund Burke, who specifically addresses
the point and claims that the plains are not sublime like the sea be-
cause the plains do not generate terror. Laurence Sterne suggests that
the very commodiousness of a fertile plain can terrorize only the travel
writer, not travelers, because the absence of danger and risk makes
for few good stories: “There is nothing more pleasing to a traveller –
or more terrible to travel-writers, than a large rich plain.”2 Sterne,
living in the eighteenth century, assumes that the flatlands are prefer-
able to the scenic route to the extent they make getting from point
A to point B pleasant and easy, with their good inns and level roads
that don’t tax the horses exceedingly. “Pleasant,” notice, is not the
adjective one uses to describe the experience of the sublime. For us,
though, who do not have to worry about where we will sleep (there
are Motel 6s in every godforsaken place) or whether our horses will
founder on the next steep climb, sublime scenery along the route is
costless and safe as long as we are not so mesmerized as to go sailing
off into it after missing a turn in the road.
156
authentic moments
Fear for our lives, even fear as to whether we may run out of gas
before the next gas station, has a way of pushing our attraction to the
beautiful and sublime well off center stage. We must, as Kant says,
“see ourselves safe in order to feel this soul-stirring delight.”3 The
perception and appreciation of beauty in the fearsome, as Kant and
others have pointed out,4 requires our safety and well-being and even
is dependent in some nontrivial degree on pacification and reasonable
security, on political and social order. In other words, we cannot
really be afraid, except in a kind of virtual, fake way, if we are going
to be moved aesthetically.5 Even trivial interferences with our sense
of well-being can reveal just how fragile our willingness to be moved
aesthetically is: vistas of breathtaking fall foliage were insufficient to
overcome my kids’ sense of ruination brought on by the collapse of
the car’s CD player at the outset of the trip. And scenery, no matter
how sublime, cannot elicit much aesthetic attention when we are
beset with a desperate urge for a restroom.
The incredible lethal beauty and awesomeness of a volcano or
tornado or jet fighter is usually apparent to most of us safely on film,
and those of us who have actually witnessed them still worry first
about getting to a safe place from which to indulge our awe or, in
the case of the jet fighter, of making sure it is friendly. A soldier is
more likely to indulge his sense of the sublime at the vast array of
his own fleet behind him than of the enemy’s array in front of him.
But there is something to those suggestions of lethality. The plains
of wheat never seem to overcome the comfortable story implicit in
them of well-being, habitability, fertility, and subdued and defeated
nature.
The relativist wavers: here on the fjords with mountains coming
down to the sea, his experience, he knows, will definitely be im-
proved if he can suspend his disbelief and let himself be overcome by
the feeling that there is something essentially sublime in the setting,
something primordial, precultural and grand beyond all obsessive
human intellectualizing. Did the Vikings find the mountains coming
down to this fjord at sunset sublime, or did they merely look at them
as barriers to be sailed around and see the setting sun as a practical
indicator of tomorrow’s weather? Our cultural relativist finds it hard
157
faking it
to believe they did not experience the beauty – “Sophocles long ago/
Heard it on the Aegaean.” He is now even less sure that his rela-
tivism isn’t a pose and something of a position he adopts because of
the pleasure it gives him to assert it against philistines or the man on
street. And he is quite thankful the fjords overpowered his intellectual
commitments. These come back later to nag at him in the hotel room,
but they did not interfere with his experience when he was having it.
Though it provides small solace, he feels that his affectations do not
quite render him as obviously phony as those who think that when
it comes to the sublime Lake Superior must be inherently inferior to
the sea.
Anxious Experts
There are other sources of self-consciousness in the face of the beauti-
ful or sublime, as sufferable in a museum before a famous painting as
when dealing with sunsets or fall foliage. These latter add the frustra-
tion of our never being quite sure we have captured or can identify
the optimal moment when the sunset and leaves are at their most
glorious.6 With art we have the added anxiety as to whether we are
enjoying it properly and whether we can convince others we enjoyed
it properly without seeming either too simple or sillily pretentious.
For a painting this means enjoying it intelligently, whereas the in-
telligent enjoyment of natural beauty – say, a sunset – seems less a
matter of the essence of sunsets than of our own response to beauty.
There is no special expertise in observing a sunset. We wouldn’t think
someone a philistine who said that when it comes to sunsets he just
sits back and enjoys them.
But with a painting one knows that there are experts out there who
could tell you so much more about it; you may have read them or may
even be one of them, and still you are not sure your appreciation is the
finest appreciation possible. You still could do better. You start to feel
vaguely deficient for not knowing more or, if you do know more, for
needing a boost to make you feel the power as you once felt it or as you
think you are supposed to feel it. Though your knowledge may have
increased and the sophistication of your appreciation with it over the
158
authentic moments
years, the cold fact is you suspect that the painting moved you more
when you were younger and knew less. You are now reduced, if not
quite to feigning awe, to paying mere lip service to awe once felt.
Or are you playing the role of a melancholic, deriving more plea-
sure from present self-doubt than from any misremembered prior
ecstasy? You have reason to believe that your prior ecstasy might be
misremembered. You know it is not beneath you to have repressed
the memory of your anxieties as to your ignorance when young, anx-
ieties that you could dredge up if you wanted to. You suspect that
your recall of the earlier ecstasy is in fact something of an invention
fashioned more for the purpose of casting doubt on your present ex-
perience. For you suspect you were posturing back then, too, faking
feeling awed because you were afraid of being seen as too dumb and
dim not to feel it. But that is not fair either, for the memory of a prior
ecstasy is a pleasurable memory, and it has served you well when
it flashes upon your inward eye. So what if that purer ecstasy was
in fact constructed later, that it is really something of a fake? Fake
memories may enhance the authenticity of the present moment, and
we are never sure that there is not always a whole lot of faking going
on in even our truest memories.
Adam Smith (TMS I.i.2.2) observes, “When we have read a book
or poem so often that we can no longer find any amusement in
reading it by ourselves, we can still take pleasure in reading it to a
companion; . . . we enter into the surprise and admiration which it
naturally excites in him, but which it is no longer capable of ex-
citing in us.” Recapturing or reproducing all the emotions of your
best experience with a particular object often puts you to a kind of
parasitical appreciation, piggybacking vicariously on the joy you see
others experience when they first discover it, especially when as par-
ent, friend, or teacher you introduce them to it. Without that last
proviso their pleasure may simply cause you chagrin, as when you
suffer the view of the young in one another’s arms. Yet your pleasure
is more than just witnessing their pleasure, for you find yourself re-
experiencing your original zeal because you have worked yourself up
trying to convince them to feel the power. Nevertheless you need the
other person in order to feel the greatness of the work again. This is
159
faking it
one of the great services students provide their teachers, who might
otherwise feel as if they are faking their pleasure in their chosen field.
160
authentic moments
that they have no clothes on, which in fact they often don’t. Philistin-
ism is no great shakes either; it comes in varieties ranging from naı̈ve
to studied, and its charms tend to have a short life.
How long are you obliged to pay homage, to stay looking at the
Vermeer? There is the niggling worry about when we can declare
ourselves properly released from having to attend to it. The painting
stubbornly stays there, available to be admired or studied until the
museum closes or until your companion urges you to move on in no
uncertain terms. When can you say, “OK, enough” and feel you have
paid proper homage? The problem of release is especially acute in
certain social settings. It is the exhausting demand made upon us to
admire someone’s new home, or garden, or collection of butterflies.
Leave it to the always-insightful Jane Austen to capture the sentiment:
161
faking it
162
authentic moments
163
faking it
164
authentic moments
You know these are foolish thoughts, yet you still worry, especially
about when you can declare yourself released from paying attention
to the painting. That is more than a matter between you and the
painting. In a museum there are many other masterpieces housed
in the same building, in the same room even, jealous of your atten-
tion, getting impatient and insisting you attend to them. Not only
does your companion want you to move on, but the other pictures
are asserting their demands too. Then, when the day is done, you
feel somewhat defeated by the experience, by the fact that you were
cowed into granting your not-quite-sincere homage completely pre-
dictably, paying attention only to paintings you already knew were
to be admired.
You may be tempted to dismiss this as a highly personalized neuras-
thenic account, not worthy of being generalized. Sure, there are peo-
ple, you will say, who are this agonizingly self-conscious, and we will
even grant that many of us have experienced similar sentiments in
some settings. But most of us do not find nature and museums as ag-
onizing as you, Mr. Miller, would make them, nor the appreciation
of beauty as fraught with constant self-defeating self-monitoring as
often as you claim. A good number of us go to museums and are
wholly absorbed, not giving a damn about what others think, other
than looking around occasionally to see whether we have been oc-
cupying the best viewing position too long. Some of us know we are
posturing and love the posturing, love any offense it may give or any
status we may achieve by it. Posturing as an appreciator of art can
put us in the proper mood to be pleasured by it and to appreciate it;
posing as appreciative helps mark the moment as an appreciative one,
and what is wrong with that? Others of us like the fact that we are in
Florence or New York or Amsterdam or Madrid and love that what
it means to visit those places is go to the museums they are famous
for. So how, we say, do you get the right to use “we” or bully us with
that “you” with such a presumption of authority? If you, Mr. Miller,
can be so anxious about a trip to a museum or looking at the trees
in their autumn beauty, how can you be so complacently unanxious
about claiming universality for your inner states?
165
faking it
166
fourteen
The bulk of the vexations dealt with so far have been about
fears of not getting into our roles or experiences as deeply as we feel
we should be. There is perhaps a more compelling problem at the
other end of the scale: getting into them too deeply to get out.
Elster’s Alchemies
Some faking, we have seen, openly acknowledges that you are trying
to bootstrap yourself into a preferred disposition, set of beliefs, or
character traits by acting as if you had it or them. Such is the case
of Pascal’s wager, which has acquired a classic dignity because the
initial risk-averse bet to believe in God’s existence is relieved of its
actuarial small-mindedness by being a necessary first step to commit
yourself to a serious regimen of observance. The habit of acting as if
you believe ends, eventually, in belief.
Some faking has no goal other than for you to survive the moment
with dignity intact and to let others preserve theirs; this is the case of
routine politeness and tact. Even these scripted moments of faking
can bend the mind to play it up all the way, so that instead of faking
sorrow at your guests’ departure you actually end up feeling a twinge
of melancholy when they depart; or, as noted earlier, if you give what
you think is lip service to a position you are too cowardly to oppose,
you end up coming to believe the position.1
Jon Elster describes a variety of transmutations of motivation in
which the initial motive cannot be publicly avowed because of its
offensiveness or inappropriateness. You start with a conscious lie, a
hypocritical assertion of a noble motive. Then you begin to believe
167
faking it
the lie and think yourself (falsely) nobly motivated. And the last step:
the lie ends up becoming true as you actually come to be moved
as you initially had falsely claimed. The intervening false belief as
to your motivation might be a necessary middle step in the process
of transmutation from knowing hypocrisy to unknowing hypocrisy,
to an actual change of motivation. Elster seems right when he says,
“Durable and consciously hypocritical or cynical stances are proba-
bly quite rare.”2 Or in Orwell’s formulation: “He wears a mask, and
his face grows to fit.”3 More effort is sometimes needed for us to stay
separated from our roles than to merge with them.4
These transmutations of motive, of nasty passions into generous
ones, of self-interest into generosity, of sham sorrow into real sor-
row, are what Elster calls alchemies of the mind. “Transmutation”
is an alchemical term of art; it means the changing of base metals
into silver or gold, a transformation of essences from mean to noble,
from low to high. Elster, rightly, also reminds us that not all such
transmutations are upward. Some work in reverse, turning gold to
lead, as in the classic case of sour grapes, when we downgrade our
desires by imagining that the unattainable thing we desired was no
good anyway; or as in the case of congenital pessimism, such as char-
acterizes the spirit of my dear father. He finds a dark lining to every
fleecy fair-weather cumulus cloud and succeeds in metamorphosing
the fear that things might go wrong into the expectation that they
will.5
For Elster, alchemy provides an evocative metaphor, a way of con-
ceptualizing the transformation of mental, not metal, essences. The
alchemical image means to suggest that these transformations take
place in the world of deception, wishful thinking, and self-deception.
They are magical, at least appearing so, because they seem to be
effected by a mental sleight of hand, operating mostly “behind the
back,” as Elster says. The magic is not psychosexual; it involves a
mix of mechanisms, but the most crucial seem to work in service of
what moralists would call vanity: our desperate need to look good
to others and ourselves.6
I want to put the metaphor aside and treat the real thing, to look
at a tale of an alchemist when alchemy was practiced – a tale of
168
the alchemist
These people, even when perpetrating their frauds, are not stand-
ing outside the structure of beliefs they are manipulating to their own
advantage. It might be that “even when perpetrating their frauds”
should be changed to “especially when perpetrating their frauds.” It
is because they believe in it that they are so good at conning others.8 A
remarkable and perfectly insightful comment from an Icelandic saga
has the thirteenth-century Christian author remark that his tenth-
century pagan ancestors rigged judicial ordeals “because [they] felt
their responsibilities no less keenly when performing such ceremonies
than Christians do now when ordeals are decreed.”9 I did not mis-
copy that. The point is that pagans were just like Christians: both
rigged their ordeals because they feared they would reveal the un-
welcome truth if not rigged. This is something rather different from
169
faking it
170
the alchemist
171
faking it
172
the alchemist
173
faking it
next time the temptation arises. The yeoman suffers from a gambling
addiction that takes the form of believing that this time he will hit
the jackpot or, if not this time, then surely some time soon. Each time
the bug bites him, he thinks the future is very near at hand, that is, he
fails to discount adequately the probability of his hitting the jackpot
this time.
The yeoman, though, sees it differently. Let’s instead take him at
his word: he says it is the “futur temps” that causes him to succumb
to temptation. He is not some benighted medieval person devoid
of psychological sophistication. To his mind, he is not undone by
thinking the future is now. He is not a victim of his own bad math or
of irrational discount rates; his is not an ordinary case of weakness of
the will. He never forgets that the shot at Elixir is a long one, almost
an impossible one. He is not driven by a belief that this time will be
the lucky one but, on the contrary, by prospects he despairingly sees
as ever remoter, ever more postponed to some rapidly lengthening
future. And still he cannot stop.
He has a sophisticated theory of his addiction that is emotion-
based. It is less about the ordering of his preferences than about the
peculiar workings of particular set of emotions. These lines hold the
key:
174
the alchemist
175
faking it
thrive, not to despair and curse God. Hope keeps him in the fold,
keeps him faithful, on the long shot that somewhere in some other
world, in some eternity, he will see justice done. The yeoman sees
hope the way a lot of cultures did that weren’t as high on hope as
Christianity is. The ancient Greeks made it the evil of what was left
to humankind when Pandora’s box was opened. Nietzsche reminded
us of the proper meaning of that tale – hope is “blind and deceitful” –
but our pious cultural commitments to hope as a theological virtue
make the tale of Pandora baffling to us to this day.14
Consider the yeoman’s blaming “good hope” that creeps into his
heart. Why is the hope good? Hope is what he knows is ruining him,
destroying his sense of well-being. The “good” is there, it seems, as a
nervous gesture of piety or no more than a rote honorific that is unfelt,
as when one addresses a “right honorable sir” or, more pointedly, a
“my good man” in which the “good” often works as a mild form
of reprimand or admonition. The yeoman pays homage to hope as
a virtue in his cultural order just as he is about to curse it.15 Hope
ranks with the most energetic mechanisms of self-deception, not quite
beating out vanity and self-love but coming close. Vanity might stake
the claim to being the chief source of self-delusion of those who do
not have to worry about their basic needs, such as food, clothing, and
shelter. Hope takes over as the chief source of self-deception among
the poor and among victims of suffering beyond all reason.
The canon’s yeoman represents a limiting case, the other side of
the faking-it coin. The yeoman too is anxious about his relation to
the roles he plays, but in a different way from the cases we have
been dealing with, which mostly involve anxieties about inadequate
immersion into a role. The yeoman’s problem is that he is drowning
in his role; there is no self left over to let him regain the shore. Full
immersion in a role is a true delight as long as we can still come up
for air and choose when to dive in again. Though the yeoman might
appear to have regained dry ground in his lament to the pilgrims, it
is still the alchemist in him that is calling the shots. The lament is not
a respite or relaxation but a phase in a cycle he cannot escape.
What is especially interesting about this kind of addiction is that
it leaves enough of its victim’s critical capacity intact so that he can
176
the alchemist
177
fifteen
178
“i love you”
Toby will perform his role in the world of love as he did in the world
of arms. He will behave admirably. His inner disposition is beside the
point. He acts as if he loves the service, whether he does or does not,
and because love is not so much a sentiment as a situation, Toby will
acquit himself as a man of prowess.
The word “love” is not only an emotion term but also a term, as
Walter said, that indicates a certain situation. Love, that is, is a state
of affairs. No, dear reader, Walter does not mean that love is the
state of an affair; where doth the prurience of thy mind lead thee?
179
faking it
180
“i love you”
181
faking it
the other abstracted from the usual clutter, vaguely transfigured and
usually across a room or a table, or at some intermediate distance,
or just as often in the mind’s eye or when looking at a photo, the
person not being there to spoil the glow you now see emanating
from him or her. Usually you do not communicate the sentiment,
too embarrassing, or if you do it is via a smile, a hug, or certain
restricted forms of teasing. If it were taking place in the movies the
soundtrack would let the other know what was going on. But in real
life the communication of the sentiment often fails to register with
its object.
182
“i love you”
183
faking it
on or come from a family that made a habit of it, then all of a sud-
den to begin would elicit suspicion as well as discomfort. Those I
love you’s (not quite as meaningless as love-ya’s) are of an ilk with
those little pecks on the cheek, which are the equivalent of air kisses
between spouses. I must admit I never forgive anyone who gives me
an air kiss, or anyone who gives one to anyone else either; but why
should I not be able to return the favor without feeling awkward and
silly, given that these kisses are, like the apology, openly a fake? Why
is everyone else so good at faking these things, or really meaning
them?
Maybe I am attributing too much virtue to these others who seem
so good at playing the role of love. I do not have access to their self-
doubts. I may doubt another’s motives, but I cannot always know
that he doubts them; I know, however, when I doubt my own. Self-
doubt is more than doubt turned inward, for it not only undermines
my own performances but also seems to give everyone else the benefit
of the doubt. The effect of my blaming my own motives is that I flatter
theirs. Maybe to them I look pretty good. Says my wife in the margin:
don’t flatter yourself.
Is it the sheer conventionality of these rote I love you’s that brings
on the fit of self-consciousness? That can’t be, for conventions in
other domains don’t do so as readily. Might it be that love, even
when completely expunged of sex, makes as much a demand on our
capacity for reticence as it does on our capacity for expression? That
is why public displays of affection strike me as little different from
people not having enough shame to go off into a corner to talk on
their cell phones, and also why it might not always be easy to play the
part privately either. Yet there is surely a case to be made for these
trivial displays. They are small reaffirmations of one’s commitment
to Walter’s love as a situation.
But a certain embarrassed reserve and stiffness can have its own
charm. Especially now, when it comes as relief from our new-age
style of verbalizing invented feelings we are “getting in touch with”
in favor of suppressing verbal expressions of real emotions we are
completely in touch with. A friend’s father, described without con-
demnation as “an uptight and embarrassed Scot,” said to his Italian
184
“i love you”
185
sixteen
186
boys crying and girls playing dumb
Yet over the course of the next month, one by one, boy after boy
announced a big breakup with their various girlfriends in which they
had broken down in tears and had begged to be taken back. I could
see I would have to take my turn in this new rite of initiation; I either
had to make a confession of tears spilled for love or be forever cast
out among the uncool. Unfair, I thought, to keep changing the rules
of cool like this. Was Ron, the guy who started all this, just trying to
see how much of a trendsetter he could be; was he even telling the
truth? And if he was, could it be possible that all the other guys were
telling the truth? Had they really cried?
As I try to access what I truly felt through the distorted lens of
memory, it seems that whatever distrustfulness I had of Ron was
muted. In short I believed every outrageous tale these guys told, and
the consequences of my naiveté were that I often got into more trouble
than they did actually trying to do (and failing) what they only said
they had done. I was too uninformed and naı̈ve to lie about sex. My
lying was restricted mainly to how many beers I had downed, and in
another year I would add tales of how fast I had taken the corner in
the car, though I still accepted everyone else’s tall tales as gospel, and
probably even deluded myself into believing my own fabrications.
But maybe they did cry, and my retrospective suspiciousness is as
naı̈ve in its own way as my gullibility was back then.
My turn, I saw, had arrived. It is clear to me now, and I think it was
clear to me then, why I was the last to join the new emotion display
fashion. I was barely holding it together in my act as a would-be
tough guy. Pretending to be tough took all my energy and resolve; I
had no margin of error. These guys could afford to announce they
had cried, because no matter how hard they got hit in a game or
fight they would never shed a tear or show signs of fear. They could
actually benefit from the thought that people would mistrust their tale
of having shed a tear over a fight with their girlfriend, but should I tell
the same tale, they would believe it with no discount for whether or
not I was lying. Of course Miller cried. For I suspected they suspected
me of being a fake real guy. I leaked unacceptable truths about myself
more often than I would have liked. I couldn’t, for instance, disguise,
in junior year, much as I tried, my excitement over Hamlet, a guy
187
faking it
188
boys crying and girls playing dumb
also commenting on the new regime; unless, that is, Ron and every
other guy had made the whole thing up and no girl had seen any of the
boys in tears. Maybe she was faking going along with it too, knowing
only too well that I was playing a role. Besides, I had a distinct feeling
I was not playing convincingly any aspect of this postpubescent daily
trauma. Who was I playing this for anyway? Not for her, but for the
guys, but not the guys either, because I could have lied. It must have
been my homage to the dominant adolescent social order, and I was a
member of that audience, judging my competence in proper emotion
display.
If this was how emotions and courtship were to proceed
“naturally,” why didn’t nature operate a little more automatically?
Had any evolutionary psychologists – who blithely come up with
just-so stories to show why it is written in our genes that attractive
undergraduate women must inevitably find middle-aged male evolu-
tionary psychologists sexy – ever been teenagers? None of this was
coming naturally. I was learning a part that I only wish had been
better programmed into my genes (and jeans). We were acting; mim-
icking actors in the movies or enacting what the older kids lied about
doing when they were our age that they had got from the movies: life
imitating art.
I was utterly clueless, operating in a fog. As I dimly recall, the
whole game was played with alternating senses, alternating fast as a
strobe light, of an acute awareness of fumbling cluelessly through a
role not fully understood, and of being so totally immersed in it that
my parents started sending away for brochures from various military
academies as threats to get me to cool it with the fair Ellen.
I was thrown back on my first plan. Tell the guys I had had a big
fight with Ellen and that I couldn’t help it, but that I had broken
down and cried. That is what I did. I was lying through my teeth,
but no one called me on it, for there was in fact a real truth to my
lie. I had committed myself by it to the new order; I was giving it the
homage of paying it lip service.
189
faking it
190
boys crying and girls playing dumb
This woman has no doubts about her own intelligence; she is smart
enough to suspect she might be getting outsmarted occasionally. She is
alert to the risks of looking foolish in this kind of faking it. She doesn’t
like playing dumb in the first place; she wishes rather that the boys
were “her superior in all ways a man should excel so that she could
be her natural self.” She lives in the 1940s, so pardon her articulation
of her wish. Besides, she is not giving much away. She is asking only
that he be sufficiently smart and secure in his intelligence so that
she can be her natural, manifestly intelligent self, so that she can
give up this particularly contemptible role of playing dumb for him.
Demeaning as it is to have to play dumb, it is not as bad as being
dumb, like many of her dates, though we should not underestimate
how often boys have to play dumb too – before other, tougher boys to
be sure, but for the girls too. Being a dumb frat kid does not come as
naturally to some of them as to others; some guys have to work at it
and never succeed in playing the role without evident embarrassment.
Our girl though is pretty sure these guys are dumb, not just playing
at it. She wishes they were smarter, not that she were dumber. Except
sometimes “once or twice,” the guy, she suspects, is smarter than she
191
faking it
initially thought and sees through the act and thinks it demeaning
for her to put it on. For this perspicacious and self-reflective girl,
what could be worse? It is not just being seen as dumb for playing
dumb that is so humiliating, it is being exposed as thinking you are
outsmarting someone by playing dumb when you should have been
smart enough to have read the guy better. Now you fear he has real
contempt for you, contempt you would agree with him for having,
not the kind of stupid contempt that a stupid guy has for a “dumb”
girl who is making a fool of him. Yet we do not know whether these
guys have really seen through her either. She may be suffering a bout
of paranoia.
An even scarier thought: only one or two guys made her suspect
that her dumb act was unbecoming to them. What if others let her
continue to think she was getting away with her act and sat back and
played along, outplaying her at playing dumb, either because of some
pathological misogyny that makes them like it when smart girls play
dumb, or because they had too much contempt for her to signal she
should give it up? What if, that is, the joke had been on her seven or
eight times, when she thought it was so only once or twice?
What about the boys dating this girl? They would have to know
she has been getting straight A’s. How faked out are they; are they not
scared of her? Are they really unaware of the contempt she has for
them? This girl suspects they may have such an inkling. In one sense
they are in a less enviable position than even she is. The boy playing
smart and the girl playing dumb do not have the same risks when their
cover is blown. If the smart girl playing dumb has her cover blown,
she falls, if “falls” is the right verb, not very far for being revealed as
intelligent. The guy, though, if exposed, turns out to be revealed as
a dimwit. Neither playing it smart nor playing dumb is an especially
attractive pose, but the risks of the former are the great humiliation
of punctured pomposity; the risks of the latter are that the pose will
be believed or that you will be disapproved of for betraying your own
virtues.
Presumably it is easier to fake being dumb, most of us having
been so at various times, than to fake being smart if you don’t have
the equipment. Playing dumb is not easy though; it takes a certain
192
boys crying and girls playing dumb
193
faking it
194
seventeen
It was the philosophe and encyclopedist Denis Diderot who took the
strong position that acting is about mimicking gesture, posture, ex-
pression, about external representations of feelings and motives, not
about feeling.1 He even argued that it is better not to have the feelings
should you be able to generate them. The conventions of drama ask
for quicker shifts of sentiment than real feelings could possibly keep
up with; it is best to keep cool on the inside and perfect your mimetic
technique. Besides, the actor must perform the same role night after
195
faking it
night (in the theater), and for consistency’s sake technique is more
reliable than mustering feelings on demand.
Yet Walter’s comments also hint at anticipating the famous view
of emotions articulated by William James, which is usually (and a bit
unfairly)2 boiled down to this: “I do not weep because I am sad; rather
I am sad because I weep”; “I do not tremble because I fear, I fear be-
cause I tremble.” James’s view is that the feeling we call the emotion is
nothing more than our awareness of certain changes that occur in the
body in response to external stimuli. Diderot’s actor, by this account,
need not generate the feeling to represent the emotion on stage, but by
representing it he may trigger the feeling. Diderot, we have just seen,
would prefer that the actor not develop the feeling; it might interfere
with the performance.3 Though the James theory has problems (it is
making a comeback),4 it embodies a certain folk wisdom that some
experience seems to support. The put-on-a-happy-face doctrine is a
practical application of the theory.5 Postures of the body, expressions
of the face, by some mysterious mechanism, seem to push the senti-
ments to accord with the outward display. Toby may indeed come to
feel love if he acts as if he loves. Whatever the mechanism that ac-
complishes this accord between gesture and sentiment, it is hardly
foolproof, for it is not uncommon to feel completely dissociated
from one’s gestures and actions, to feel and know them to be fake.6
Like Diderot, Walter does not care about inner states. It is all form,
throwing oneself wholeheartedly into visible forms when propriety
demands it. That is what a man of prowess such as Toby does. It
leads to deeds of bravery on the battlefield and acts of kindness in
the drawing room. The bedroom is another matter, but there is hope
even there. Walter is not a cynic. How do we teach our children to
have the inner state of the emotions of sadness, guilt, regret, disgust?
We cannot verify that they really feel what they are supposed to. We
are satisfied that they have the proper sentiments if they are mak-
ing the proper facial expressions, adopting the right tone of voice,
making their bodies accord with how that sentiment is to be prop-
erly displayed, carrying out actions that such a sentiment properly
prompts, and last and most importantly, doing those things when
196
acting our roles
197
faking it
V. J. Parmley and Chevy Zinder saw it, and ratted me out. [The
teacher] called me into the hallway and asked me if it was true.
“What is truth?” I should have answered . . . But, in my naiveté, and
in the grip of my conscience, I thought that this was a crossroads
moment. I felt that there was a right and a wrong thing to do. And
there was, but telling the truth wasn’t it. I knew instantly that I
should have lied. Whether or not she suspected that I had done it,
she never expected me to own up to it. She was more outraged by
the fact that I had the audacity to admit my misdeed, than that I
had committed it.9
198
acting our roles
and the butcher become callous. I believe that that mistakes cause
for effect: it is rather that they are suited to play all roles because
they have no character.12
199
faking it
200
acting our roles
201
faking it
202
acting our roles
in it too, and not only in decadent Rome or Weimar Berlin. Like all
practices it is subject to a thick array of rules, some articulated, most
not. Makeup that calls and is meant to call aggressive attention to
itself tends to indicate an aspiration for, or the fact of, marginality:
the whore or actor or super-hip or gender-bending male or weirded-
out teenager. (Makeup that calls, but is not meant to call, aggressive
attention to itself is usually the curse of the bumbling teenager or
aging woman.) Long before that line was crossed, however, innocent
rouging provided a basis for misogynists to lambaste the false seem-
ing of womankind.14 The woman who does not make up, or put on
a face, is also sending a message variously ranging from indifference
to not giving a damn (not the same as indifference) to thinking she
is so beautiful she doesn’t need it to claiming a certain style of femi-
nism, and more. The woman who refuses makeup is no less making
up for a role than the one who puts it on. The exact meaning of the
positions changes roughly each decade or two but, again, very much
within predictable ranges.
There is an honesty to cosmetics: the woman putting them on is
not ashamed that she is doing so. Women in my mother’s generation
would pull out a compact and reapply makeup seated in a restau-
rant; not to do so was bad form. In that day a woman might never
be so inaccessible as when she was redoing her face in public. And
cosmetics work more magically for not being disavowed, for being
so open; it draws men and frightens them; it is all so mysterious. The
more makeup, the more it suggests a certain freedom from sexual
constraint, a mask for carnival, while also suggesting a seamless self-
involvement that blithely denies the existence of others present. The
coding is complex: certain styles of making up thus signal primness
and propriety better than would no makeup. I am speaking only very
generally; these rules vary by social class and ethnicity and geograph-
ical region, and most of us are quite fluent in the language, at least
in the dialect of our own generation.
Before Prozac and its ilk, before implants, Viagra, and Rogaine,
the world of faking and pretense was about donning clothing and
the vocal accent of a different class. Shakespearean comedy depends
on the magical transformation that changes of dress can work on
203
faking it
identity, and surely it was the case that clothes made the man and
woman, hence the myriad sumptuary laws to regulate who could
wear what, so leaky were the dikes separating the various social
ranks.15 You were to stay within gender confines too. Saga Iceland, for
instance, loved its women tough, capable, good-looking, and smart,
but they were not to dress like men, nor men like women. The penalty
most frequently visited on cross- or ambiguous dressers in the sagas
was immediate divorce, but the laws go farther and subject the person
to prosecution for lesser outlawry – loss of property and three year’s
exile – at the suit of anyone who wished to bring it.16
What of the status of Rogaine, Prozac, or implants? Is there a duty
to inform? A very bald friend suggested that Rogaine does not belong
on this list because “it just retards hair loss and I wouldn’t call that
‘faking’; how about liposuction?” But I am retaining Rogaine; it tries
to mask the truth of the disgrace that the course of nature has visited
upon us. To confess to using it is embarrassing and forces one into a
self-mocking mode to own up to it, for it is proof that our vanity has
reached pretty near the depths of pathetic foolishness. Something still
makes Rogaine more a form of deception, for instance, than using
toothpaste with whitener in it, which is more, we think, like using
soap. That aside, is there a duty to inform, say, that you have breast
implants or use Viagra? And if you don’t tell and the other finds out,
will he or she accept you as the real you or as a discounted “you” or
as a jacked-up YOU?
Would you not feel a little bit betrayed by a guy taking Viagra or
a woman with breast implants? Wouldn’t a guy, in the latter case,
feel embarrassed if he got aroused by them knowing they were fake?
He, however, would have a response to that: “Fake? What’s fake
and what’s real? I have been reading the fathers of the church and
various monastic writers, and they have always suggested that even
so-called real breasts are fake, a false appearance, for all they are is
skin covering disgusting goo, mostly fat.17 Would a bowl of fat turn
you on? No, it is only the location and the skin over the fat that
transforms the fat into a breast. So what is wrong with skin over
silicon or salt water? Rather better in fact.” And he is not a fetishist,
204
acting our roles
205
faking it
in it, but there is no way they could ever overcome feeling foolish for
giving it a try. They would sink even lower for having sunk so low.
But a little yellow pill?
Here then is the problem. Suppose you court a person and win him
or her over to love you because you are easy-going and sociable. True,
some people would have loved you as a depressed and occasionally
angry wit, but this person whom you love beyond belief loves you as
you are on Paxil. He or she bought the act hook, line, and sinker. What
if she should go up to the attic and find your true portrait? Should
anyone feel anxious about matters of authenticity in this vignette?
Should they treat the new, docile you as an amiable imposter, a new,
better Martin Guerre returning from the wars? Good riddance to the
old one, whom no one liked anyway. And though people know the
new one is a fake, they prefer not to think of him that way; it is so
much pleasanter to take the imposter as the real Martin.
Your old friends know that it is not the real you but may prefer the
more tractable fake you anyway. But what of the friends you have
made after you became Paxilman? Must you disclose? If you do, do
you risk losing them? Or will they stick with you because it would
make them look shallow to abandon you on such grounds?21 But
then you might suspect that the only reason they did not abandon
you was out of a sense of duty. Would they trust you to keep taking
your pills? Maybe they would love the old you too? Want to give it a
try? These same anxieties are mirrored in the other person, who may
want to live dangerously by finding out what the real you is really
like. Nor is it all that unlikely that the person who discovers that
your character is chemically maintained is also on an antidepressant
and so may be forgiving. Does this make the situation exponentially
falser or somehow truer and fairer?
Then there is hair. The rules are very different for men and women,
because the former are desperate to acquire it except on the ears,
back, and neck, and the latter are desperate to get rid of it, except
on the head. It is male hair loss I limit myself to, not waxing, bikini
lines, or electrolysis. Rogaine seems fair preparation for the public
presentation of self. If it grows hair, which it probably won’t, it is real
hair, your hair. And though this makes it seem analogous to Viagra,
206
acting our roles
which makes real erections, that is not the case, for she has no reason
to believe that your love and desire for her caused your hair to grow.
If Rogaine doesn’t grow hair, you are out the money and look foolish
only to yourself and to the check-out clerk in the pharmacy.
Rogaine is surely an acceptable preparation for presenting yourself
in public in a way that hair transplants, with plugs that change a
head into a doll’s head or, worse still, a toupee, which justifiably
subjects its wearer to infinite ridicule, is not. A toupee is by definition
a botched performance.22 You think you are playing in a serious
drama, and instead you are the star of a farce. Rogaine carries a
risk of humiliation too, though small. No one believes you want to
be bald; they will mostly amiably laugh away the silly vanity you
reveal for wanting to have more hair than you do. You give others a
chance to tease you gently: suppose you say to your significant other,
“Hey I think it’s actually working” and the response is, “Yup, as an
hallucinogen; just slip it into your students’ water and they will see
you with hair.” Oh, the trials and tribulations of maintaining dignity.
Surgical Masks
There is a tradition, often maintained ironically or with a sense of its
shock value, that it is only when masked that we can speak truly, or
if not truly, at least interestingly. This is Oscar Wilde’s view. But there
has always been a related belief that fiction is better at approximat-
ing truth than nonfiction and then, paradox upon paradox, that the
“truest poetry,” according to Touchstone in As You Like It, “is the
most feigning” (3.3.16).23 Real life often seems more fake than fic-
tion. And acting styles as well as characterizations and plots in novels
have always had to perform serious cosmetic surgery on true life to
satisfy our demands for verisimilitude and plausibility. In a different
vein, we know how to mobilize contrived fiction to flush out truth, as
when the play is the thing wherein we catch the conscience of kings, or
as when Polonius and law enforcement agencies entrap wrongdoers:
“Your bait of falsehood takes this carp of truth” (2.1.62).
But the truthfulness of masks is not categorical; some allow truth
to flourish, others suborn it utterly. It depends on what kind of masks,
207
faking it
when and where donned, and what kind of fictions. To play being a
polite person is to be a polite person. The mask is all that is asked for.
There is a truth there. Sincerity supposes, in contrast, masklessness,
but that presents an impossible bind stated succinctly by Andre Gide:
“One cannot at the same time both be sincere and seem so.”24 One
can play a role sincerely. I sincerely act out my role as a teacher. Play-
ing the role of the sincere person sincerely, however, rightly raises
suspicions. Recall the unverifiability of sincerity in displays of re-
morseful groveling. There is, as we have seen, more verifiable sincer-
ity in the coerced spat-out apology than in voluntary sackcloth and
breast-beating. In the latter case, but not the former, the apologizer is
trying to sell the other on his sincerity and hence falls afoul of Gide’s
law.
Where, though, is the truth in masks that are surgically applied or
achieved by ingesting pills, other than the truth that we are vain, ill,
neurotic, and sad? These are not masks that allow for much artistry
on the part of the wearer; all the art belongs to the surgeon or the
chemist. What a crabbed moralist I have become. Is it because I feel
conned by breast implants, Paxil, Rogaine, and Botox, but not by pre-
tenses of gratitude, amiability, and modest applications of makeup?
Or is there some deeper notion of fair play and cheating involved?
Some ways of cheating nature have a long and venerable tradition;
other ways look like crass innovations, part of an unrelenting move
toward the moral horror of designer babies, cloning, and obscenely
long life.
Is it that a breast implant suggests the mind of the whore, or a
similar kind of pathetic pandering to male foolishness? Or is it noth-
ing more than a slightly more expensive and invasive succumbing to
pathetic vanity on the order of the man driven to Rogaine? Neither
wants to be rejected as an object of desire because of having, in one
case, small breasts or, in the other, thinning hair. Both evidently would
prefer knowing they have been rejected on more substantial grounds,
such as their dullness, shallowness, or moral failings. Incredible, but
no small number of us, I bet, would rather find out another is turned
off by us because he thinks us morally defective than that he found us
so physically unappealing as to make sex with us either unthinkable
208
acting our roles
209
faking it
short half-life. The same person who might at first give you a black
mark for shallowness and vanity on account of your breast implants
is soon likely to be very forgiving. Better attractive fakery than ugly
truth. Besides, the fakery has its own kind of truth, the truth of beauty,
which moralists of a certain stripe forever claim, to little avail, is false.
Within a month, maybe even an hour, he will be putting the moves
on you, and you will not reject him as readily as you would have
months before Rogaine had its salutary effect on him, and, what
with his Viagra, to misuse Yeats dreadfully,
210
eighteen
False (Im)modesty
211
faking it
not being at me. But can’t the pretentious prof think he is a really
funny guy too, delivering what he thinks are fine jests?
Not all fakes are pretentious, and not all pretentious people are
fakes. But so obviously unpleasant and affected is the style that one
wonders why on earth anyone would adopt it outside the German
academy, where it appears to be a necessary and often sufficient
qualification of a professorship?2 There are various cultural rules
on this. In America, democratic norms should make a pompous pro-
fessor more seriously morally defective than his pompous German
or even English counterpart. Pomposity does have different national
styles: the pomposity of the French, who think themselves witty and,
more pathetically, sexy, is not the pomposity of a Herr Doktor who
prides himself on taking more words rather than fewer to say some-
thing. The pomposity of Oxbridge dons is itself such an arabesque
of affectations that it is hard to believe anyone can play the part
without being aware of its comic implications. It is badly restyled in
the American academy, the difference being that the English are se-
cure enough in their pomposity to engage in pompous self-mockery
about the pompousness of it all, whereas the Americans are sincerely
pompous, like the parvenu who cannot run the risk of self-mockery.3
So distasteful is the style, given democratic assumptions, why on
earth would any American adopt it?4 Here is one reason that tran-
scends the cultural: I have found over the years that students tend
to confuse pomposity with knowledge and nastiness with smarts.
Students thus force otherwise indifferently kind and modest teachers
into being mean windbags to get the respect they crave. It may be less
that pompous power generates toadies than that toadyism generates
pompous power.
Pretentious people seem to inhabit their role in a unique way. They
are fully immersed in their role, but not in the manner of people who
lose themselves in a role out of exuberance, dedication, addiction, or
simplicity. One of the peculiar forms of this pretentious style is that
though the person never puts his role aside, he also never seems to re-
lax into it. One imagines that they never cease thinking of themselves
as Herr Professor Doktor when they fornicate and defecate. Yet such
pompous souls, not uncommonly, believe themselves, in fact, to be
212
false (im)modesty
rather deft wits and ironists; they thus take great care to enter their
bons mots in their class notes for annual repetition. And it need not
be that the pretentious person thinks he is more important than he
is – he is often quite important. It’s that he wants to make you feel his
importance in an unbecoming way. He lacks what in the eighteenth
century was called the virtue of condescension; he does not know
when to give up on the privileges of his standing when he could gain
credit by doing so.5 Because he insists on extending his authority to
occasions and physical spaces where it has no business, we treat him
as if he were making fraudulent claims. And we are right, for his
authority is not always properly to be on center stage, but only when
the stage directions say it is.
There is no way to separate the sociological from the moral here.
Modesty is a virtue that has very little to do with intention and very
much to do with how you present yourself modestly. Like courage,
modesty is about delivering the goods. If others feel you lord it over
them, never letting them forget for a moment that you are pleased
to be their superior in a way that makes them resentful, well then,
despite all intentions, you got it coming. That is another of my over-
statements, so let me clip its wings in the interests of accuracy. If we
discern that the pompous person is otherwise decent, that when push
comes to shove he is kind and generous and comes through on im-
portant matters, we will tell ourselves things like, “He really is OK
once you get to know him.” In the interests of equity, we make the
moral move of distinguishing between his style, for which we want to
stone him, and his substance, for which we will commute his capital
punishment into merely complaining about him behind his back or
warning people who are about to meet him to cut him some slack.
Pomposity seems to be an occupational hazard of academics more
than most professions, and I fear I am not always vigilant enough not
to succumb myself. But is it really that the academy draws more than
its share of pompous people? Or is it that the peculiar kind of preten-
tiousness that thrives in the academy is one of gravity, gravity being
much more prevalent in the ivy-covered walls than other equally
annoying forms of oppressing people with self-satisfaction, such as
the tough guy who won’t let you forget he can kick the crap out
213
faking it
False Modesty
Pompous pretentiousness is one way of characterizing the vice op-
posed to the virtue of modesty. In the Middle Ages the opposed vice
would have been understood to be pride, but we have long since
reevaluated pride and blame only a pride that is too prideful, too
showy, too pompous. Quiet pride is in fact how we have come to
understand what modesty is. Not too quiet, though. What is more
pretentious than the friend who does not tell you about winning a big
award? So what if she is beside herself with anxiety about how to tell
you or whether to tell so that she doesn’t look as if she is bragging?
To choose silence is the wrong move.
Modesty is another one of those virtues in which the faked version
makes the real thing suspect, so common is fakery in this domain.
Whatever false modesty is, it is not hypocritical any more than po-
liteness is. False modesty is about taking care of others’ feelings on
the tricky terrain of envy. It is the concession we grant to a certain
justice in envy that we not too far outstrip others, lest they hate us or
we offend them. False modesty is thus an homage to envy, born not
only of fear but also of fellow-feeling.
True modesty may have no motive other than its own realization.
False modesty, though, is precisely what propriety often demands
in the service of reducing envy. For this reason, real modesty that
does the sociable work we ask false modesty to perform will get
not much more credit than if it were false to begin with. What is
being asked is that the fortunate person spare the feelings of others.
214
false (im)modesty
215
faking it
216
false (im)modesty
217
faking it
218
false (im)modesty
he also fears that he will only outsmart himself and opts instead to
stick with being his plain old modest self. Except that is now not so
easy. How did he act when he was unconsciously modest? Can he
reproduce it if he is self-conscious about it? Perhaps, just perhaps, he
will manifest sufficient embarrassment and fluster trying to present
himself as the modest person he truly is that his very embarrassment
will be exactly the right signal to sell his modesty. And if it works this
time, next time he can fake the fluster.9
219
nineteen
Mostly we live and let live with our faking it. I won’t call you
on yours if you won’t call me on mine. The agreement works quite
well in domains of small encounters and routine politeness. But what
if your faking is less about faking for a good cause – such as politeness,
apology, being a dad, a teacher, a friend – than for a bad cause? And
what counts as a bad cause? So much of our faking is done to satisfy
our vanity, the bad cause par excellence in one well-established moral
tradition: the sin of pride.
We have already seen that another nonnegligible moral tradition
winked at vanity, even blessed it as the chief motive behind making us
virtuous actors. The desire to gain the good opinion of others and the
equally great desire to think well of ourselves drove us to do good
deeds and cultivate virtue. Vanity of this sort, if not quite a good
cause, surely makes the world a better place to live in. To borrow
from Lord Chesterfield, why should we not wink at the small-stakes
vanities that help people get through the day a little happier; politely
flatter them so that they will politely flatter us, all to the advancement
of sociability and amiability?
Most – but not all – in the tolerant second tradition would agree
that it is a bad cause when our misrepresentations and self-delusions
claim more for ourselves than is fair. We draw a line at some magical
point when your attempt to fake it, to fool me – pardonable – makes a
fool out of me – absolutely unpardonable, unless I have it coming. But
we also find it unpardonable when you fool yourself to the point of
making a fool out of yourself. And that is precisely the circumstance
in which I can make a fool out of you, because you have done most
of the work and you have it coming. When your vanity so blinds
220
caught in the act
you that you feel yourself great and grand no matter how inept and
unbearable you are, then you deserve precious little quarter.
I must immediately make a clarification. Not all self-duping is
unpardonable, especially that kind of self-esteem that leads you not
to quit at the first failure and persevere instead, or that keeps you
performing at the highest level of your abilities. But when vanity
moves in the direction of pomposity or self-inflation or ineducability,
it dares us to pierce it with pin or pen. The implicit agreement not to
expose each other’s faking collapses in the face of our graceless and
baseless self-love.
Because these themes are rather central to some of the essays I
published in a book called Humiliation, I will take up only issues
not discussed there, or ones that looking through the lens of faking it
might lead to different observations. I want to deal with the earliest
stages of self-consciousness about faking it, and then treat of some
especially anxiety-provoking settings in which we feel exposed and
the risk of exposure is at its highest.
Faking Sleep
Insomnia is one of those states it is virtually impossible to defeat by
direct action, unless the direct action is to admit defeat and take a
knock-out pill. Some of us are so self-tormenting that we test the pill
once we have taken it by trying to stay awake to see whether we have
been duped with a placebo. I nod off all the time reading scholarly
articles, but if I read one in order to overcome my insomnia it loses
its power to knock me out because I know I am reading not to read,
but in order to fall asleep. I see through the trick.1
We have seen this problem before: it is not easy to have the left
hand act as if it doesn’t know what the right hand is doing. Yet people
do it all the time. Our vanity makes us gullible; there is no difficulty
in seeing ourselves prettier, smarter, and more interesting than in
fact we are. Indeed, some of us endure bouts of seeing ourselves as
dumber, uglier, and duller than we are. We, however, usually do not
think of underevaluation as self-deception, perhaps because we have a
hard time accounting for vanity, the usual culprit, driving it, though
221
faking it
222
caught in the act
faking sleep as a child: your eyes shut, Father looking on, examining,
detecting, you unable to see him but fantasizing and anticipating the
worst.
It is actually scarier with Mother looking on, because you know
she is better at discerning the fake, even if she is more inclined to let
you lie in. Father does not care whether it is a fake, except that if you
are faking, it deprives him of the added pleasure of actually waking
you up. In either case you feel they see through you. Why are you
even putting on the charade? When they let you lie there it is not, you
suspect, out of kindness or out of love of your cuteness, but that they
wish to torment you for an entire geological age. They are making you
squirm on purpose, to let you know that your transgression is allowed
by their grace alone and not by the virtue of your deceptiveness,
should they decide to allow it. It is only later, during adolescence,
that you realize how easy it is to trick parents when, though they
pretend otherwise, they are too scared to want to find out what you
are really up to anyway.
At night the child is more likely to have his faking excused than in
the morning; wanting to read late bodes much better for his character
development than wanting to sleep late. At night the torture your
parents deliver actually helps you. They will come to your bedside
and turn your lamp off and then kiss you as you “sleep.” For once
you actually welcome their kisses because it allows you to act as if
they awakened you.
When it comes time to be rousted out to go to services to pray,
there are no kisses; there is nothing cute about you. Still they test to
see whether you are sleeping or faking, for there is a moral difference
between morning and night. Bad enough that you have to be awak-
ened in the morning when your sense of responsibility should have
done it for you, but that you are faking sleep betrays a depraved and
willful turning of your back on Responsibility. Let his heart pound a
little harder until the kid fears it will surely explode and kill him if he
fakes another second; then rip the covers off and indicate how many
minutes he has to get ready. Little did they know that I was already
conducting my own prayer service, praying they would buy the act,
praying God to intervene and make them merciful; He, however, is
223
faking it
a jealous God and instead steeled their resolve to crush the whining
resistance they had yet to face.
224
caught in the act
225
faking it
226
caught in the act
us feeling very vulnerable to exposure. The risks are not evenly dis-
tributed across all social domains. They are especially high when we
gauge a big hunk of our self-esteem, as in our professional compe-
tence or in courtship and sex. Nor is feeling anxiously self-conscious
likely to be distributed equally up and down the relevant hierarchy.
Those who must please others to survive, low but not so low as to
have no hope of advancing, those on the make trying to rise, those
who come from pariah or disfavored groups who fear a false move
means pogroms, those others who are stigmatized in more personal
ways – for these souls the costs of screwing up are greater.7 The com-
placently secure can afford a duller inner life, but as I have written
elsewhere, once democratic norms become generally accepted, even
high-ranking people lose their complacency and come to worry they
may be being judged as fools by those beneath them and are disturbed
that they are being so judged.8
Performing before experts is one way of describing the agonies of
courtship. No matter that each person is a miserable wreck before
the other. That other is an expert of his or her own tastes as they
apply to you. You are judged either to pass muster or to have failed.
There is no disputing the expertise of the taste that condemns you.
At my age I experience vicariously the miseries of courtship watching
my teenagers. Both my wife and I were surprised to find we feel
more excruciating pain on behalf of the pathetic boys who call the
uninterested Bess for dates than we do for Bess having to figure out
how to turn them down. Appallingly, we almost end up siding with
the guy so that we can be spared witnessing his humiliation. Bess, this
guy has called three times; he wants to come to your play; aren’t you
going to call him back and tell him when it is? Dad, he is so dumb;
I mean do you want to hear the dumb jokes he thinks are funny?
She then tells me one, and well, I guess he’s got it coming. But the
agony.
I would never be a teenager again even if it meant having a full
head of hair. You perform and are judged a fool, and the very fact
that you are performing means you have judged the other desirable;
you have hung yourself out to dry. More pathetic, though, is that our
endless vanity never lets up. It is not only rejection by those we find
227
faking it
228
caught in the act
229
faking it
friendly other might see you. But what if instead of spreading our-
selves thin over many roles and even expanding into multiple selves
and voices, we found our self shrinking down to one part of our
body? Sexual desire might reduce us in such a way to our genitals.
Compare too the feeling of being taken over by a discrediting failing.
When you were a teenager and had an enormous zit prominently ex-
posed on your face, did you not feel as if that zit were you? There was
only a little of you that remained that wasn’t that zit; that was the
part of you that felt so ever keenly that all you were to yourself and
others was that zit. Whatever desperate attempts you made at dis-
guise, masking, faking only called more attention to it. You were not
making it up; people teased you, your brothers and sisters laughed
at you; you saw people avert their eyes and be equally unable to pre-
vent their eyes from fixing on it. A stain on your pants or dress can at
times take you over too. The problem with these discrediting failings
is that they feel as if you have finally been stripped of all poses. You
are stripped, naked, authentically a discredited being. Not faking at
all.
Not just discrediting bodily blemishes, but discrediting deeds
shrink a person to an unwelcome essence too. Do you remember
the kid who in third grade wet his pants, or picked his nose and
ate it? Sure you do. No matter what he became in later life, be it a
big CEO or a famous actor, that is what you remember about him.
He, I suppose, gets the benefit of not knowing that you see him that
way, but because you see him that way he should, you feel, go into
a witness protection program. A mistake or habit at nine years old
will never let him make satisfactory amends for the disgusting im-
age rooted in your mind. What if that person were you? Will it be
forgotten? Depends what it was. The girl, Robin, will forgive if not
forget that you crashed the car into a tree because you forgot to put
it in park before you grabbed at her in teeny-bop obligatoriness, not
in anything resembling passion. Surely every kid had gaffes like that;
they are the stuff of comedy, not soul-destroying in the least. As with
the zit, you can live them down; their power to discredit is of short
duration. But what about the especially egregious lapses, the ones
that were dignity-destroying, perhaps irremediably so? Not just the
230
caught in the act
231
Afterword
232
afterword
that anything goes, for it does not have a large number of different
meanings either. The range of relevance is constrained. Though I
cannot see by their looks how my kids are related to me, to the
outsider they look like Millers, even if looking like Millers means
they mostly look like my wife, a Koehler. Faking it thus offers a
family of topics, and though it defies reduction to a unified theory
the little fakelets have the resemblance that family members come
to have. All these faked “its” in the last sentence of the preceding
paragraph are united also at the practical level by fears about our
competence in playing both true and false roles truly and, at an airier
level, by our anxieties about the ultimate authenticity of any of these
“its.”
Do not read me as willing to martyr myself for faking it, or as
irremediably hostile to the idea of authenticity. But, like it or not, we
are stuck with faking it. If we try to avoid it by refusing to don masks
or strip our veils we are only playing a role that has a lengthy and
complex history, predating the cynics, and ever so susceptible to hyp-
ocritical and false forms. Some accommodation with faking it is in
order. And though quests for authenticity prompt some raillery from
me, not all such quests are silly, and some indeed are necessary or un-
avoidable. What, in effect, is that niggling self-doubt, that stream of
self-consciousness that colors the voice of this book, but constantly to
be worrying about, and holding oneself up to, a standard of genuine-
ness? From whence the chronic anxiety if there weren’t some deep
urge to be whole and true? The urge, though, is often self-defeating,
for it is what keeps us doubting the quality of our motives and makes
us wonder whether we are really getting there or aren’t just faking
it. Should that doubting cease, it is no more likely to be a sign we
have become one with our true selves than that we are in the throes
of seamless self-deception or Paxil.
We seem destined to recapitulate at the individual level various his-
torical movements of authenticity and purification. We thus find our-
selves driving the money changers from our temples every now and
then, stripping away the costumery of certain roles, junking whole
roles that have become too ornate, too in-your-face false. But the
attempts to get back to true basics mostly succumb to the vanity of
233
afterword
human wishes; they never quite measure up to the hopes we had for
them. We do not escape the anxieties of authenticity once we embark
on the quest or once we get to the Celestial City. Even there, doubt
exists or Satan would not have fallen.
Such movements have brought us Christianity, Protestantism
within Christianity, various civil rights and social justice movements
on behalf of pariah groups. Still, a gay out of the closet, a Jew out
of the ghetto, and Protestants of whatever sect, from the highest
Anglican to Shakers and Pentecostals, will hardly have resolved once
and for all the problems of faking it and authenticity. At best the
doubts are relocated, but I doubt they are any less intense, rather
more so in fact because of the pretension of the claim to have at-
tained the pure and the authentic.
Do not read me to be sidling toward the conclusion that the most
authentic persona might be a voice similar to this book’s narrator’s.
That voice’s anxious self-doubt, self-mockery, constant ironizing, and
occasional bitterness need not mean that this voice is meaningfully
self-examining or struggling for psychic unity and authenticity. A
possessor of such a voice may find the comedy of the process its
own reward, or as providing a topic for a book. And not all simple
pleasures or simple miseries need elude him.4
But do read me as suggesting that faking it partakes in a serious
way in the struggle to maintain one’s dignity and honor. The self-
watching internal eye that prompts the anxieties of faking it and
authenticity are very similar to the external eyes of an honor/shame
culture. In some deep respects it is all about measuring up, and mostly
about not quite measuring up. If the stakes are often not of the se-
riousness that lead to shame, they are surely the stuff of constant
embarrassment.
Some readers might wonder whatever happened to the uncon-
scious in my story. Freudians will be mystified at best, incredulously
dismissive at worst, especially considering that the master was given
only a cameo appearance as a bad comedian. The neglect is deliberate.
The unconscious, the existence of which I am not about to deny, plays
a different role in the world of fakery, largely one subsumed under
234
afterword
235
afterword
my preferred pair: knave and fool. This pairing lies at the heart of
faking it, appearing often as deception (knave) and self-deception
(fool). Some might reply that the more seriously intended pairings in
the preceding paragraph are not meant to get at something as trivial
as foibles or fakery, but at more gravely grounded issues of right,
justice, and salvation. Besides, there is a lack of high seriousness in
the word “foible.” Call it sin or evil, and then make the evil banal,
and then high theory can sneak foible, in disguise, into its country
club, but not in all its riotous and varied grotesquerie. Human foible
undoes much highfalutin theory: mere mortals, dull as we are, are
inevitably too complex for pairings as restrictive as man–woman,
white–black, gay–straight, capitalist–worker, and the theories such
oppositions support.
The knave–fool pairing differs from the others because it gets at
human behavior at its most interesting; it is as expansive as its neme-
sis, the self-interested-rational-actor model of human behavior, is
limiting and limited. It forces us to contemplate, sometimes mor-
dantly, sometimes even lovingly, the wondrous complexity of the
simplest face-to-face encounters, the comic pretensions of our hopes
and dreams, our postures and poses, all our various forms of fakery.
Knave–fool does not reduce us to one dimension but keeps all our
motives, desires, fears, and hopes, all aspects of us – as workers,
friends, sexual beings, parents, children, believers or unbelievers –
on the table for discussion and gentle raillery. It is a particularizing
dichotomy. It loves stories and details, mostly comic ones, but tragic
ones too. Is not Othello a fool–knave story no less than the standard
comic trickster tale?
The knave–fool distinction, historically and perhaps even neces-
sarily, is wedded to a misanthropic style. Some may thus find the dis-
tinction a distasteful one, unworthy of decent-spirited souls. But that
misanthropy need not be of a savage Swiftian sort; it is equally suited
to the more amiable moral vision of a Fielding. The knave–fool view
of human moral possibility desperately seeks human goodness and
even recognizes its possibility, but it sees the forces arrayed against
goodness as undefeatable. It laments the fragility and vulnerability
of human goodness. It fears that the good person will be eaten alive,
236
afterword
plundered, not just by knaves but by other fools too, and, worse, by
his own foibles.
Foibles, of course, are usually held to be the lot of the fool. But it
is not only the good person or the fool who is undone by foible; the
knave is undone by them too. As I tried to show in the discussions of
being hoist with one’s petard and of Chaucer’s alchemist, the knave
is often his own fool, even outsmarted by fools, just as the genre
of the slick urban knave cleaned out by his country cousin would
have it. The fool–knave distinction is porous indeed, with any single
person playing both roles quite frequently, sometimes shifting from
fool to knave and back again within the confines of a single social
interaction. Think of the motives, moves, stratagems, defenses, and
humiliations of a first date. Think too of poor Wile E. Coyote.
This book is a small effort in an ancient tradition of moral writing.
Its primary article of faith is that humankind is vain, inescapably vain,
comical and foolish, though nonetheless, both in spite of and because
of these traits, capable of extraordinary achievements. If this were not
the case, this moral tradition would have no motive. It ridicules us
for our boundless vanity because it aspires to more. Still, that is not
a reason to turn its back on the small virtue of muddling through,
even if it cannot pass up the opportunity to give muddling a heavy
dose of comic and satirical treatment. For the most part, this book
sides with those who see some virtue to our vanity. We are something
more than mere fools for wanting so badly to look good to ourselves
and to others, so badly that we actually end up delivering on some of
the goods we hope to be esteemed and praised for. The same impulse
that sends some to a plastic surgeon for an implant sends others to
deeds worthy of an epic hero.
Our vanity, though, is seldom so seamless that it succeeds in sup-
pressing all our doubts about faking it. Now come, like so many
Grendels in the night, those niggling anxieties that pierce through
the vain veneering. They disorient us in dizzying attempts to figure
out who we really are and where we really stand. But that sick feeling
in the pit of the stomach, real as it is, is also part of a pose, as I am
proving right now as I write this for public consumption. That does
not make it fake, however. Not all poses are false in the same way,
237
afterword
nor even false at all. Yet we often worry they are; and we, or if you
do not wish to be included in that “we” then I, suffer real bouts of
wondering when the other shoe is going to fall, the shamming ex-
posed to the light of day. But I am not sure whether the first shoe
has even fallen yet or whether both have. I think I may have lost
count.
238
Notes
One. Introduction
1. Robert Nozick (Philosophical Explanations 257) is willing to confess to
much more: “My departmental colleagues are meticulous intellects who
instill in students the importance of mastering all the details whereof they
speak; while I think it is important for students also to learn how and
when to fake things, to glide over topics with a plausible patina.”
2. See Miller, Bloodtaking and Peacemaking; “Clint Eastwood and Equity”;
“Deep Inner Lives.”
3. See Kerrigan’s superb Revenge Tragedy, making the argument for the nec-
essary linking of revenge and drama.
4. One still cannot quite say “woman on the street” without raising improper
suggestions.
5. Emerson, “The Comic,” 8.157.
239
notes to pages 11–15
5. On hypocrisy in general see Shklar, Ordinary Vices 45–86; the most astute
unraveling of the vice I know of is Melville’s in The Confidence Man.
The classic treatment of the religious hypocrite as con man is Moliere’s
Tartuffe.
6. The judgment of hypocrisy in this case is an external one, about ranking
the propriety of certain motives in displays of piety. Jesus’ hypocrite is
hardly being dishonest in the sense of failing to match words and deeds
or words and intentions; he likes giving alms because he wants the glory,
which he is noisily open about. What Jesus is complaining about is the
hijacking of a pious ritual for such unashamed glorying.
7. See Melville on strategies of maintaining self-respect under the burden of
gratitude; The Confidence Man chs. 3–4.
8. Jesus is not counseling giving anonymously, for that is not suggested here;
the pauper will still know the identity of his benefactors. Anonymous
giving does not solve the problem of playing to the glorious applause of
one’s internal audience. The pride of turning one’s back on the more ob-
vious public attempts at approbation is a frequent topic of seventeenth-
century moralists; see discussion in Lovejoy, Reflections 99–112. Even
earlier the friar in Chaucer’s Summoner’s Tale tells about his own
“private” self-mortifications lest they go unnoticed.
9. This is the standard conundrum at the core of the philosophical self-
deception problem; see ch. 4n6.
10. Many in the self-esteem movement would say that our psychic biasing is
more prone to see our own specklike faults as logs.
11. Jesus does not call those who are about to stone the adulteress in
John 8 hypocrites. He confines the word “hypocrite” to settings where
it can sensibly have its Greek meaning of theatrical actor, which is
precisely why the trumpeting almsgiver is to him the hypocrite par
excellence.
12. An aside on the mote–beam metaphor: how is one supposed to visualize
a log sticking out of an eye unless it be the eye of Polyphemus? I find the
image puzzling. How can we not know we have a log in our eye even if we
are blinded by it? Consider too the problem with specks in our own eyes;
they hurt so much we feel they must be logs. But ask someone to look in
there and they see nothing. The log–speck metaphor appears better suited
to describing how our own little pains seem so much greater than other
people’s big pains.
13. See Elster’s discussion, Alchemies 87–88, on the “double perversity of
amour-propre.” See also La Rochefoucauld, M 31.
14. See Hebb’s experimental evidence that we are much better at reading oth-
ers’ emotions than our own (“Emotion in Man and Animal”).
15. A similar case for going easy on the hypocrisy of blaming others for faults
one has oneself is made by Hazlitt (“On Cant,” 360): “We often see that
a person condemns in another the very thing he is guilty of himself. Is
this hypocrisy? It may, or it may not. If he really feels none of the disgust
240
notes to pages 16–19
241
notes to pages 20–26
Three. Antihypocrisy
1. Montaigne, 3.10, “On Restraining Your Will,” 1157–1158.
2. Twain, “Capt. Stormfield’s Visit to Heaven,” 854.
3. Is the person who pretends to vices he does not have a hypocrite? Does
culpable false seeming run only in the direction of falsifying upward –
pretending to virtue – rather than falsifying downward? What of the clean-
cut kid pretending to badness – the drinking, womanizing, drugging that
I mentioned earlier – in order to have the tough guys think him not so
contemptible? Do we call him a hypocrite because, given the frame of
reference, he is pretending upward toward the cool; or do we refuse to
“honor” him with the dignity of hypocrisy and instead think him merely
pathetic, a wannabe?
4. See Elster, Alchemies 93–94.
5. On unostentatious virtue as suspect because of the approbation of one’s
internal audience, see the discussion in Elster, Alchemies 92–94; and Love-
joy, Reflections 99–112.
6. One of the most insightful character studies of the pridefulness of humility
is Trollope’s Rev. Crawley in Last Chronicle of Barset.
7. On pus-drinking saints, see Bell, Holy Anorexia; also my discussion in
The Anatomy of Disgust 157–163.
8. Trollope, Rachel Ray ch. 5.
9. Franklin, Autobiography 90.
10. Hávámal st. 76, my trans.
11. Lovejoy, Reflections 153–193; see Smith, TMS VI.iii.46: “The great secret
of education is to direct vanity to proper objects”; also Hirschman, The
Passions 20–31.
12. Even La Rochefoucauld appreciates the good things that flow from our
vanity; see, for example, M 150, 200, 220.
13. The Idiot II.11.
14. Victor Klemperer in one of the many astute asides in his diaries captures
the hokum of the pastoral in this way: “When politicians idealize rural
labor, they are always being hypocritical” (I Will Bear Witness July 19,
1937, I.230).
15. On pastoral cultures and mandatory sheep rustling, see Herzfeld, Poetics,
and Campbell, Honour. Hampshire supposes that “the ideal of natural-
ness of feeling, uncorrupted by reflection” is unattainable “once we have
built up a sophisticated vocabulary of intentional states, of emotions, sen-
timents, attitudes” (“Sincerity,” 248–249). I have argued elsewhere that
lack of a specific and rich vocabulary of emotions need not prevent implicit
emotion talk of substantial subtlety. The feeling, with a description of the
context generating it, will do much to make up for a lack of a specific
emotion vocabulary. See Humiliation ch. 3.
16. See Hawthorne, The Blithedale Romance; Packer, Transcendentalists
466–470.
17. Raverat, Period Piece 214.
242
notes to pages 26–33
243
notes to pages 33–37
244
notes to pages 37–56
113, makes the case for Goffman’s world being a moral order precisely
because of the centrality of the virtue of tact.
10. Mansfield Park ch. 28.
11. Sense and Sensibility ch. 21.
12. Santayana, Soliloquies 133–134, quoted in Goffman, The Presentation of
Self 57.
13. See Lovejoy, Reflections 135–136. The seventeenth-century French moral-
ists viewed the chief motive behind vanity to be the desire for praise, not
the fear of shame. The two go hand in hand, but the inner lives of per-
sons whose primary motive is fear of shame are miles apart from those of
people whose primary motive is to seek praise.
14. Notice that the log in our own eye not only causes us to exaggerate the
faults of the other but also can just as easily construe his bad intentions
as good if seeing them that way serves the cause of our self-love.
15. Chesterfield, Letters March 9, 1748; the last sentence is from Oct. 19,
1748.
16. Sense and Sensibility ch. 7.
17. For example, ch. 4, where each plays up to the expectations of her type
and each is delighting in playing it up for the other.
18. Elinor states clearly that the demands of propriety, meeting the expecta-
tions of others, govern only in small matters. Thus to Marianne: “. . . but
when have I advised you to adopt their sentiments or conform to their
judgment in serious matters?” (ch. 17).
245
notes to pages 59–67
246
notes to pages 67–75
247
notes to pages 75–82
26. There is a large literature on the conversos and Marranos; see, for example,
Bodian (“Men of the Nation”) and Netanyahu (The Marranos of Spain
and Toward the Inquisition).
27. Vonnegut, Mother Night p. v.
248
notes to pages 82–90
249
notes to pages 90–94
250
notes to pages 96–101
have given you had I not asked you to forgive me in advance, a request
that you cannot deny given the rules of polite excusings. So expected is
your pardon that I am already pressing my body into the contested space
as I am saying my pardon me. Your conceding the space is pretty much
a given, or else I wouldn’t have presumed upon you in the first place. Yet
should I not give my little sorry in a properly pleasant tone, an unignorable
offense will have been given.
251
notes to pages 102–112
252
notes to pages 112–121
relations? Gauge exactly your financial means – “costly thy habits as thy
purse can buy” – and then you will not be false to any creditors? But then
“this above all” bursts the restraints of such a narrow reading, and we get
instead Delphic wisdom.
5. Hamlet means to delve under them to place an explosive charge to collapse
their mine. Countermines could also seek to gain entry to the mine by tun-
neling above and pouring in lethal substances, or by entering and fighting.
6. See Keen, Laws of War 48–50, for examples. In saga Iceland the formal
blood-brotherhood ceremony required passing under turf to reemerge as
brothers; see my “Ordeal in Iceland.”
7. This is the term the rake Willoughby uses in an access of self-castigation
in Sense and Sensibility ch. 44.
8. Alanis Morrissette, an unremarkable Canadian pop singer, had a 1996 hit
called “Ironic” in which most of her examples of irony involved no irony
at all. One of the many merits of the Internet is that it prompts people who
otherwise would not feel compelled to write about such things to do so.
Her mistaken ideas about the meaning of irony have spawned numerous
hostile and amusing commentaries.
9. Following Trilling, Sincerity and Authenticity 120: “Irony is one of those
words, like love, which are best not talked about if they are to retain any
force of meaning.”
10. Grettir’s saga ch. 45; Njáls saga ch. 92.
11. She has the added problem of being and looking young and having to
advise elders. Trollope has a nice treatment of a twenty-three-year-old
cleric giving his first sermon to graybeards (Barchester Towers vol. 2,
ch. 4).
12. The ironist doesn’t necessarily improve his ironic talents with practice.
One suspects that if you have to practice at it you are without the talent
for it in the first place.
253
notes to pages 121–123
254
notes to pages 125–133
14. For the average person it is very hard to separate body types from character
and the propriety of and eligibility for certain roles, though philosophers
might show we need not feel that way; see the discussion in Parfit Reasons
and Persons §89.
15. Strawson, “The Self,” 407.
16. Mead, The Individual 53–54.
17. The Individual 46.
18. Ford, Parade’s End 55; Small, Road to Richmond 185. Even a dualist
would admit that the body can distract the mind from its thoughts, but I
am inclined to claim more for the body’s necessary participation in think-
ing for reasons I suggest in the text because thinking as a conversation
implies certain organs of sense, and the language we think in would hardly
have a metaphor available to it without recourse to images implicit in be-
ing embodied. Notions that assume our embodiment pervade language at
every level; see generally Lakoff and Johnson, Metaphors We Live By.
19. These kinds of congratulations or cursings of oneself do not carry quite the
same meaning when uttered audibly as they do when said only internally;
at least this is the case if there are people present who are meant to overhear
you. Thus, when I damn myself for missing an easy shot in basketball I
do it out loud as a gesture of apology and placation to my teammates.
20. Even respectable scholars end up sounding like self-help books – for ex-
ample, Charles Taylor, The Ethics of Authenticity. His ambitious Sources
of the Self has some of the same failing as Whig history in that it assumes
the excellence of the development that leads to his book. Works such as
Taylor’s set up the man of honor with a shallow inner life as a strawman
that the West has managed to overcome. I defend the depth of the inner
life of people of honor in “Deep Inner Lives,” and I suggest there that for
real shallowness one need only look to the discourse of self that congrat-
ulates us on being deep, ending in self-esteem movements and new age
sentimentalism.
21. See Parfit (Reasons and Persons 277) for an image of persons as “nations,
clubs, or political parties.”
22. Cf. Giddens, “Erving Goffman,” 118.
23. Goffman, Presentation of Self 235.
24. Outside tropical zones clothing is surely more “natural” than naked-
ness. Thus Dennett, Consciousness 416: “Clothes . . . are part of the ex-
tended phenotype of Homo sapiens in almost every niche inhabited by
that species. An illustrated encyclopedia of zoology should no more pic-
ture Homo sapiens naked than it should picture Ursus arctus – the black
bear – wearing a clown suit and riding a bicycle.”
255
notes to pages 135–139
3. The days of the prophets officially ended with the death of the last of
Jesus’ disciples. From then on God spoke through the translators and
interpreters of His church. You can speak to God in your tongue, but
He would no longer speak directly to you in His. The Protestant sects
that accepted contemporary prophecy had to develop means of crediting
revelations as authentic. One might see in the practice of speaking in
tongues an attempt to prove the authenticity of the revelation by putting
it in a kind of incomprehensible tongue that could pass for God’s own
Hebrew. For an especially good account of the anxieties of authenticity
that faced self-styled Anglo-American prophets in the eighteenth century,
see Juster, Doomsayers.
4. For a brief but suggestive treatment of the theme of Moses’ veil and the veil
over the Holy of Holies as taken up in the Christian exegetical tradition,
see Cunningham, In the Reading Gaol 398.
5. Cuddihy (Ordeal of Civility 24) reads this joke in a slightly different way,
but his central claim strikes me as having much merit, or at least as being
very rich in its suggestive possibilities. Cuddihy jokes that for Freud the
id is Yid, the Yid, id.
6. For the Son as co-eternal with the Father see Heb. 1.2, where through the
Son God made the world; and so, too, John 1.1. See Milton’s rendition of
the role of the Son in the wars in Heaven: “Son of my bosom, Son who
are alone / My world. My wisdom and effectual might” (Paradise Lost
3.169–170).
7. Rozin and Fallon, “A Perspective on Disgust,” 32.
8. See the discussion in Shapiro, Shakespeare and the Jews ch. 1.
9. The online edition of the Catholic Encyclopedia, published in 1912,
in a hagiography of Torquemada, testifies to the endurance of a view
that ended in the destruction of European Jewish culture within three
decades: “At that time the purity of the Catholic Faith in Spain was
in great danger from the numerous Marranos and Moriscos, who,
for material considerations, became sham converts from Judaism and
Mohammedanism to Christianity. The Marranos committed serious out-
rages against Christianity and endeavoured to judaize the whole of Spain.”
10. Goffman, Relations in Public ch. 6.
11. A similar problem arose in America with regard to black blood; but the
courts were inclined to let sleeping dogs lie. By encouraging slander suits
for loss of white racial reputation they discouraged zealous efforts to inves-
tigate people’s racial backgrounds, something many astute racists knew
would risk their own claims to purity of blood; see Sharfstein, “Secret
History of Race.”
12. Eliot, Complete Poems “Burbank with a Baedeker: Bleistein with a Cigar,”
sts. 4–6.
13. Shylock is not mentioned directly, but his presence in the poem is suggested
by the allusions to The Merchant of Venice (“on the Rialto”).
14. See Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals Essay I.
256
notes to pages 139–147
15. Ressentiment is not sour grapes: in the sour grapes mechanism you still
value sweetness, it is just that you see the particular grapes that are be-
yond your grasp as not being sweet because you cannot have them; in
ressentiment you decide that sweetness itself is bad and that those who
enjoy it are inferior, evil, or damned.
16. As an aside I note that it is often the case that the charge of ressentiment
leveled at others is itself a form of ressentiment, hurled by losers at winners,
or if not quite by losers, by fearful dominators who see their grip slipping.
Max Scheler’s treatment of ressentiment, for instance, strikes me less as
an analysis than as an exemplar of it. Scheler, a Jew, was a convert to
Catholicism when he sought to defend Christianity against Nietzsche’s
charges of its being a religion of ressentiment.
17. See Miller, The Anatomy of Disgust chs. 9–10.
Twelve. Passing and Wishing You Were What You Are Not
1. That same person can be praised for attempting to “improve” himself by
rejecting his tainted people. It is part of the morality of authenticity to wel-
come or at least to accept certain aspects of ourselves, and to self-realize
and self-improve as part of the proper development of our authentic self.
But which aspects are to be welcomed and which rejected or improved
beyond recognition is part of the flux of political, social, and moral
clashes.
2. See Gilman (Self-Hatred 6–9) regarding the Jew as black in the Euro-
pean context of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. The
most provocative study is still Cuddihy’s Ordeal of Civility, though in a
perverse way I find von Rezzori’s Memoirs of an Anti-Semite stunningly
insightful from the other side.
3. It is also necessary to distinguish a self-hatred deriving from a general-
ized misanthropy and melancholia, as in the case of Hamlet or Pascal,
from those arising from more ressentiment-like settings, as is the case of
Underground Man, to Jewish self-hatred, which is only partly susceptible
to being understood as ressentiment. Groucho Marx – “I don’t want to
belong to any club that would accept me as a member” – hardly means to
transform the values of the dominant order. He has internalized their view
of his powers of contamination; so his presence ruins the attractiveness
of the desired object. He wishes desperately that it were otherwise. See
Scheler, Ressentiment 52, on self-hatred and ressentiment.
4. See Walzer, “Can There Be a Decent Left?”
5. Trollope, The Way We Live Now ch. 91.
6. The image of the intrepid middle- or upper-class traveler of the late
nineteenth or early twentieth century springs to mind – Edith Durham,
Margaret Hasluck – and Margaret Thatcher for a recent exemplar.
7. The English would tell a different story: that their whole style is cultivated
because they are the most embarrassable of people, and they contrast
257
notes to pages 148–151
themselves proudly on precisely this trait from the French, whom they see
as profoundly unembarrassable; see Ricks, Keats 5–6.
8. Compare the ready coupling of leftist politics and patriotism in England
(Orwell, E. P. Thompson, et al.) with the smug and embarrassed disap-
proval of patriotism on the American left; see Walzer, “Can There Be a
Decent Left?”
9. Goffman, Stigma 73–91.
10. See Yoshino, who discusses the burden of “covering” a stigma such as
homosexuality so that an individual “modulates her conduct to make
her difference easy for those around her to disattend her known stigma-
tized trait” (“Covering,” 837). Yoshino would prefer a world in which
such accommodations are unnecessary. I am not sure I concur if it means
abandoning reticence with regard to aspects of one’s identity that are not
relevant to the moment. Surely the Jewish kid who sings “Hatikvah” in
Hebrew, or the Protestant who sings “Onward Christian Soldiers” during
their auditions for the junior high play can be reasonably expected to do
a better job of “covering” aspects of their identity.
11. See I. J. Singer’s work, which is quite good on these matters: The Family
Carnovsky, also to a lesser degree The Brothers Ashkenazi.
12. See Herzog’s account (Poisoning 321–323) of Coleridge and the stinking
Jew.
13. Hilaire Belloc, “The Garden Party,” vv. 1–4, Complete Verse 219; on this
issue see also Smith, TMS I.iii.2.5: “Politeness is so much the virtue of
the great, that it will do little honor to any body but themselves. The
coxcomb, who imitates their manner, and affects to be eminent by the
superior propriety of his ordinary behavior, is rewarded with a double
share of contempt for his folly and presumption.”
14. The literature on passing, black and Jewish, is enormous. Some of it is
of value, but much of it is tainted with the complacent assumptions of
a naı̈ve social constructionism that holds that because something is so-
cially constructed it becomes less durable, less real, for that reason. Social
constructions, on the contrary, might well be more durable than certain
basic aspects of our biology. We will be able to engineer our genes to our
liking long before we will rid ourselves of social constructions such as
racism. I have found these works of interest: Jacobson, Whiteness; Hale,
Making Whiteness; Gilman, Self-Hatred and Smart Jews; and Sharfstein,
“Secret History.” None strike me as being as consistently perspicacious as
Goffman’s Stigma.
15. Not that he will be tossed out on his ear if he is discovered. Goffman
notes that when someone’s false identity is seen through in a forbidden,
out-of-bounds place, where exposure means expulsion, the people seeing
through him may choose to avoid making a scene by kicking him out,
“an eventuality often so unpleasant to all parties that a tacit cooperation
will sometimes forestall it, the interloper providing a thin disguise and the
rightfully present accepting it, even though both know the other knows
258
notes to pages 151–161
of the interloping.” The understanding is this: don’t ever let this happen
again, buddy, or I can’t promise you such a tactful response; Stigma 81.
See also Larsen, Passing 16: “It wasn’t that she was ashamed of being a
Negro, or even of having it declared. It was the idea of being ejected from
any place, even in the polite and tactful way in which the Drayton would
probably do it, that disturbed her.”
16. Larsen, Passing 55: “White people were so stupid about such things for
all that they usually asserted they were able to tell . . . They always took
her for an Italian, a Spaniard, a Mexican, or a gipsy.”
17. Gilman, Smart Jews 183, cites Terry Abrahamson as claiming to have been
an anomaly in his high school locker room in Amundsen, Illinois, in the
mid 1960s, but unless the three or four uncircumcised penises loomed
very large in his imagination it is hard for me to believe that Amundsen’s
practices were more retarded than Green Bay’s on this issue.
18. See Gollaher’s tendentious anticircumcision account, which nonetheless
tells the American medical historical tale (Circumcision ch. 4). One of the
burdens of living in a university town is to find flyers such as the following
at your friendly Whole Foods store: “Beautiful music for alternative Jewish
Baby Naming Ceremonies. Contact Brandy Sinco, Member of MUSIC
(Musicians United to Stop Involuntary Circumcision).” And then Brandy
gives a sample verse from a song:
259
notes to pages 163–169
260
notes to pages 169–191
261
notes to pages 193–198
2. Would she prefer that he see through her and excuse her? What if he
believes the dumb act but then finds her unappealing because he doesn’t
like dumb girls? In that case would she be even more chagrined for not
playing dumb with enough leakage so the smart guy would see through
the pose?
262
notes to pages 199–209
263
notes to pages 211–222
264
notes to pages 224–235
Afterword
1. I have been taken to task on my reluctance or inability to write conclusions
to my books; see Stark, “Courage.”
2. Austin, Sense and Sensibilia, especially ch. 7, on dimension words and
trouser words.
3. Austin, 64.
4. Moments of naturalness are available even to such a type, as they were
to Dostoyevsky’s Underground Man. Thus Underground Man, that most
self-conscious and self-torturing of souls, can report that he made a gesture
in “a surprisingly disengaged manner” though he immediately loses his
naturalness by being so taken with his having actually succeeded in making
an unstudied gesture II.3. He cannot help being surprised by his own
naturally engaged manner, thereby managing ex post facto to turn his
naturalness into a fake.
5. East–West is also one way of repeating, if not white–black, then
white–dark.
265
Works Cited
266
works cited
267
works cited
268
works cited
269
works cited
270
works cited
Keen, M. H. The Laws of War in the Late Middle Ages. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1965.
Kenny, Anthony. The Self . Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press, 1988.
Kerrigan, John. Revenge Tragedy: Aeschylus to Armageddon. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1996.
Klemperer, Victor. I Will Bear Witness. Translated by Martin Chalmers. 2 vols.
New York: Random House, 1998–1999.
Komarovsky, Mirra. “Cultural Contradictions and Sex Roles.” American
Journal of Sociology 52 (1946), 184–189.
Konstan, David. Friendship in the Classical World. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997.
Konstan, David. Pity Transformed. London: Duckworth, 2001.
Kroeber, A. L. The Nature of Culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1952.
Kruger, Justin, and David Dunning. “Unskilled and Unaware of It: How
Difficulties in Recognizing One’s Own Incompetence Lead to Inflated Self-
Assessments.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 77 (1999),
1121–1134.
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1980.
Langland, William. The Vision of Piers Plowman. Edited by A. V. C. Schmidt.
New York: E. P. Dutton, 1978.
La Rochefoucauld, François, duc de. Maxims. 1665. Translated by Leonard
Tancock. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1959.
Larsen, Nella. Passing. 1929. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1997.
Laxdæla Saga. Translated by Magnus Magnusson and Hermann Pálsson.
Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969.
Lazar, Ariela. “Deceiving Oneself or Self-Deceived? On the Formation of Beliefs
‘Under the Influence.’ ” Mind 108 (1999), 265–290.
LeDoux, Joseph. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of
Emotional Life. New York: Touchstone, 1996.
Levenson, Jon D. “The New Enemies of Circumcision.” Commentary 109
(March 2000), 29–36.
Levenson, Robert W., Paul Ekman, and Wallace V. Friesen. “Voluntary Facial
Action Generates Emotion-specific Autonomic Nervous System Activity.”
Psychophysiology 27 (1990), 363–384.
Lewis, Sinclair. Babbitt. 1922. New York: Library of America, 1992. 487–844.
Little, Graham. Friendship, Being Ourselves with Others. Melbourne: Mel-
bourne Text Publishing, 1993.
Little, Lester K. Benedictine Maledictions: Liturgical Cursing in Romanesque
France. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993.
Locke, John. The Reasonableness of Christianity. 1695. Edited by George
W. Ewing. Washington, D.C.: Regnery, 1997.
Lovejoy, Arthur O. Reflections on Human Nature. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
Press, 1961.
271
works cited
272
works cited
Miller, William Ian. “Sheep, Joking, Cloning and the Uncanny.” In Clones
and Clones: Facts and Fantasies about Human Cloning. Edited by Martha
C. Nussbaum and Cass R. Sunstein. New York: W. W. Norton, 1998.
78–87.
Milton, John. John Milton: Complete Poems and Major Prose. Edited by
Merritt Y. Hughes. New York: Odyssey Press, 1957.
Mischel, Walter. “Personality Dispositions Revisited and Revised.” In Hand-
book of Personality: Theory and Research. Edited by Lawrence A. Pervin.
New York: Guildford Press, 1990. 111–134.
Molière, Jean Baptiste Poquelin de. Le Tartuffe. 1669. Edited by Jean Serroy.
Paris: Gallimard, 1997. English translation: Richard Wilbur. Tartuffe. New
York: Harcourt, Brace, 1992.
Montaigne. Michel de Montaigne: The Complete Essays. Translated by M. A.
Screech. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1991.
Naipaul, V. S. The Mimic Men. 1967. New York: Vintage, 2001.
Nashe, Thomas. Christs Teares over Jerusalem. London: Printed by James
Roberts, 1593.
Netanyahu, Benzion. The Marranos of Spain: From the Late 14th to the Early
16th Century According to Contemporary Hebrew Sources. 3rd ed. Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1999.
Netanyahu, Benzion. Toward the Inquisition: Essays on Jewish and Converso
History in Late Medieval Spain. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press,
1997.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. 1886. Translated by Walter
Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1966.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality. 1881.
Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1982.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human. 1886. Translated by R. J.
Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morals. 1887. Translated by Walter
Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage, 1967.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. “On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense.” 1873.
Translated by Walter Kaufmann. In The Portable Nietzsche. New York:
Viking, 1954. 42–47.
Njáls saga. Translated by Magnus Magnusson and Hermann Pálsson.
Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1960.
Nozick, Robert. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1981.
Nyberg, David. The Varnished Truth: Truth Telling and Deceiving in Ordinary
Life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993.
Orwell, George. “Shooting an Elephant.” In The Collected Essays, Journal-
ism and Letters of George Orwell. Edited by Sonia Orwell and Ian Angus.
Vol. 1. An Age Like This: 1920–1940. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1968.
235–242.
273
works cited
274
works cited
275
works cited
276
works cited
Wilde, Oscar. The Critic as Artist. 1891. In Complete Works of Oscar Wilde.
London: Collins, 1948. 1009–1059.
Yoshino, Kenji. “Covering.” Yale Law Journal 111 (2002), 769–939.
Zimbardo, Philip G. “The Pathology of Imprisonment.” In Down to Earth
Sociology: Introductory Readings. 11th ed. Edited by James M. Henslin.
New York: Free Press, 2002. 272–277.
277
Index
abnegation, 65–66. See also prayer pride and avarice as vices of, 169.
absolution. See penance See also Chaucer; Elster; Nashe;
accents, 203; academic, 145; transmutation
American vs. English, 144–145; alchemists: curiosity of, 171;
Katherine Hepburn’s, 145; lapsing reputation of, 170
into a southern, 39; alcohol, 48; as bootstrapping aid, 34
self-consciousness about, 39–40 allegory, 123
accidents, 249. See also apologies; almsgiving, hypocrisy and, 11–12,
remorse 28
acedia, sloth, 62 Americans: craven self-hatred of,
acting: Diderot’s theory of, 195–196; 144; modest self-hatred of,
Mansfield Park and, 199; teaching 143–144, 147–148; patriotic pride
children emotion display and, of, 146–147, 148. See also
196–197; Walter Shandy’s theory English; self-hatred
of, 195, 196 Amidah, 68–72; on Rosh Hashanah,
actors: characterlessness of, 69
198–200; as doer and as fake doer, anger: fake, 262; self-command and,
7; making up, 202; vs. thin-lipped 44
moralists, 199–200; waitresses as, anti-depressants, 205–206;
200 compared to yoga, 205
addiction: alchemist’s theory of, anti-essentialism. See relativism
173–177; gambling and, 174; hope antihypocrisy: looking bad in order
and, 174–177 to be good, 20–23. See also
aesthetics: vs. moral, 208–209, 210; Becket; hypocrisy; More; Twain
posing and, 154; religious anti-Semite, -ism, 134, 139, 232;
conversion and, 68. See also fears of pollution of, 136; limpieza
anxiety; art; sublime de sangre and, 136; misogyny and,
affectations: of hipness, 49; of 138; 1912 Catholic Encyclopedia
prissiness, 48 and, 256; uncanny lunacy of, 150;
airs: giving none, 215; putting on, 43 visions of Shylock and, 137
alchemy: deception and anxiety, 4–7; passim; appreciating
self-deception and, 170–176; as art and beauty and, 155–156,
metaphor for mechanisms of 158–161; doubling and, 126;
transmuting motives, 167–168; experts failing and, 158–160
279
index
280
index
281
index
282
index
283
index
284
index
285
index
286
index
prof drawn to style, 212; reconciliation, rituals of, 90. See also
self-satisfaction and, 213 apologies; penance
Pound, Ezra, 172 recusants, burden of maintaining
praise: vs. flattery, 96–103. See also secret beliefs and, 75. See also
flattery; La Rochefoucauld conversos
prayer: abnegation and forgiveness regret, 82. See also remorse
and, 65–66, 74; Amidah, 68–72; relativism, cultural, experience of
bored in services and, 62; of natural beauty and, 154–158
confession, 65; curses and, 66–67, remorse, 78; easy fakeability of, 78;
246; despair and, 66; faking it for forgiveness and, 90–94; vs. regret,
the kids and, 63; in foxholes, 64; 81–83; self-indulgent forms of, 91;
hypocritical, 12; Lord’s, 58; Smith’s nuanced view of,
meaning them, 62–68; mental vs. 248–249; weak, 84–85, 91
vocal, 62; petitory, 64; Psalms, respect: flatteringly, 99; paying, 62
67–68; spontaneous, 64; of respectfulness, 63, 67, 182. See also
thanksgiving, 67 lip service; politeness
pretending, 200–202; vs. faking it, ressentiment, 139; accusations of,
200; kids and, 200–202 257; relation to self-deception,
pretense, pretensions. See 140; vs. sour grapes, 257
affectations; pretentiousness ritual, Big R, 58; apology and, 86;
pretentiousness, 71, 120, 130, 160, coronation and, 74; giggles and,
211–214; art appreciation and, 59–60; hijacked, 74; hocus-pocus
158, 160, 164, 165; images of gas and, 58–59; of humiliation, 88,
and, 211; vs. modesty, 214; 90; nakedness as, 130; primitive,
professors and, 1, 211–214; 61; purity of officiator and, 74; of
unique way of inhabiting role and, reconciliation, 90, 92; “Star
212 Spangled Banner” and, 72
pride: authentic experience of, 140; Rogaine, 204, 208–210; vs. dignity,
of excluded groups, 140, 153; 207; vs. Viagra, 206. See also
humility as, 22, 23, 222, 240; vanity
reevaluations of, 214, 220; as sin roles, 3–4, 5, 6–7, 9–10, 104, 211;
of alchemists, 169 passim; anxiety as by-product of,
primitivism, 61 10; fears of botching, 37; irony
Protestantism, circumcision and, and, 115; playing with leakage, 46,
151–153. See also Christianity; 214–215; pretentiously played,
prayer 212; problems of immersion, 3–4,
Psalms, 67–68 113–115. See also anxiety;
punishment. See apologies; penance authenticity; pretentiousness;
Puritanism, 46 self-consciousness
Romanticism, 45, 128
race, 38–39 Roth, Philip, The Human Stain, 149
racism, 15; self-hating American
and, 143; sham moral courage sagas, Icelandic, women of, 204.
and, 243–244 See also irony
raillery, 36 salvation: glory seeking and, 29
287
index
288
index
289
index
290