An Investigation of The Planarity Condition of Grötzsch's Theorem
An Investigation of The Planarity Condition of Grötzsch's Theorem
Abstract
The idea for this paper originated from Professor Lszl Babais challenge to find a triangle-free graph with chromatic number 4. Professor Babai gave the following hints: the graph would have eleven vertices, the graph would be five-fold symmetric, and the graph was called Grtzschs Graph. After independently discovering a graph which satisfied all the conditions, I checked with Professor Babai, who confirmed that it was indeed an isomorphism of Grtzschs Graph. Independent further research led me to Grtzschs Theorem, which I will state. The purpose of this paper is to demonstrate the need for the condition of planarity in Grtzschs Theorem, using Grtzschs Graph as an example. This paper is conducted from first principles; all terms will be defined along the way. No previous experience with graph theory is necessary.
Section 1: Preliminaries
Definition 1.1: A graph is a pair G = (V, E), where V is the set of vertices and E is the set of edges. Definition 1.2: An edge is an unordered pair of vertices. Definition 1.3: Two vertices are adjacent if they are joined by an edge. Two adjacent vertices are said to be neighbors. Definition 1.4: A walk of length k is a sequence of k + 1 vertices vo,,vk such that vi-1 and vi are adjacent for all i.
Definition 1.5: A closed walk of length k is a walk v0,,vk where vk = vo. Definition 1.6: A cycle of length k is a closed walk of length k with no repeated vertices except that vo = vk. Definition 1.7: A graph is triangle-free if it does not contain a cycle of length 3. Definition 1.8: A legal k-coloring of a graph is a function c: V [k] = {1,,k} such that adjacent vertices receive different colors. A graph is k-colorable if there exists a legal kcoloring. The chromatic number (G) of a graph is the smallest k such that G is kcolorable. Definition 1.9: A planar graph is a graph that can be drawn in the plane so that the lines representing the edges do not intersect except at their end vertices.
Proof: As noted above, we will need to consider three cases. The proof will follow by process of exhaustion. Case I: The cycle begins at a vertex on the outer boundary. Without loss of generality, let the cycle begin at vertex 1. From vertex 1, the cycle can proceed to vertex 2, 5, 7, or 10. From these vertices, the cycle can then proceed to vertex 3, 4, 6, 8, 9, or 11. However, observe that none of these vertices are adjacent to vertex 1; hence, a triangle cannot be formed. Case II: The cycle begins at a neighbor of the center vertex. Without loss of generality, let the cycle begin at vertex 6. From vertex 6, the cycle can proceed to vertex 2, 5, or 11. From these vertices, the cycle can then proceed to vertex 1, 3, 4, 7, 8, 9, or 10. Again, observe that none of these vertices are adjacent to vertex 6; hence, a triangle cannot be formed. Case III: The cycle begins at the center vertex. The first move will be to a neighbor of the center vertex. Since no two neighbors of the center point are adjacent, the second
move will be to a vertex on the outer boundary. Since no vertex on the outer boundary is adjacent to the center vertex, it follows that no triangle can be formed. As noted above, Grtzschs Graph is five-fold symmetric, so these three cases are exhaustive. Hence, Grtzschs Graph is triangle free.
Proof: We must find a subgraph of Grtzschs Graph that is homeomorphic to K5, the complete graph on five vertices. The subgraph that we are searching for is simply the subgraph where we omit the central vertex and all its associated edges (see Figure 4.7). Lets compare that with the complete graph on five vertices (see Figure 4.8). Clearly, our subgraph is a subdivision of K5, obtained by inserting a vertex onto each of the edges joining the outer points. K5 in turn is a subdivision of itself, which means that both our subgraph and K5 are subdivisions of K5, which by definition means that our subgraph and K5 are homeomorphic. Hence, by Kuratowskis Theorem, Grtzschs Graph is nonplanar.
My isomorphism is pictured below (see Figure 5.2). The vertices of my isomorphism are numbered so that they are a bijection of Grtzschs Graph using the numbered vertices from Figure 3.1. From this point forward I will refer to my isomorphism as G and refer to its vertices by number based off of Figure 5.2. Observe that G is five-fold symmetric and preserves the adjacency of Grtzschs Graph.
We will start by proving that G, and therefore Grtzschs Graph, is not 2-colorable. Theorem 5.4: Grtzschs Graph is not 2-colorable.
Proof: By contradiction. Using G, assume that G is 2-colorable. Fix the color of the center vertex (red in Figure 5.5). All the neighbors of the center vertex must be of a different color. Since we are assuming that we can completely color G with 2 colors, all the neighbors of the center vertex must be the same color (blue in Figure 5.5). Hence, vertices 1-5 cannot be blue, since they are all adjacent to blue vertices. We are assuming that G is 2-colorable; therefore, vertices 1-5 must be red. However, without loss of generality, let vertex 5 be red. This means that vertices 1 and 4 are adjacent to both red and blue vertices, and therefore can be neither red nor blue, which contradicts the assumption. Therefore, by contradiction, G is not 2-colorable. Since G is an isomorphism of Grtzschs Graph, it follows that Grtzschs Graph is not 2-colorable.
We will now prove that Grtzschs Graph is not 3-colorable. We will do this by assuming that Grtzschs Graph is in fact 3-colorable, fixing the color of the center vertex and exhausting the possible cases for color combinations of the neighbors of the center vertex, then showing that contradictions will follow in each case. We will use the isomorphism G in the proof. Since we are assuming that G is 3-colorable, there are four possible cases for the coloring of the center neighbors: all of the neighbors are the same color, four are of one color and one of is a different color, three consecutive neighbors are of one color and the other two are of a different color, and three neighbors of one color are split up by two neighbors of a different color. These cases are illustrated below (see Figure 5.6). Observe that it does not matter which specific vertices are assigned which colors, since G, and Grtzschs Graph, are five-fold symmetric.
Figure 5.6: The possible color configurations of the center and center neighbors under the assumption of 3-colorability (not specific to vertices). Theorem 5.7: Grtzschs Graph is not 3-colorable.
Proof: Assume that Grtzschs Graph is 3-colorable. Fix the color of the center vertex (red in all Figures). The proof will proceed by exhausting cases for the possible colors of the center neighbors. Each case will proceed by contradiction.
Case I: The five center neighbors are all the same color (blue in Figure 5.8). Observe that vertices 1-5 cannot be blue, since they are all adjacent to blue vertices. We are assuming 3-colorability, hence, vertices 1-5 must be either red or green. Without loss of generality, let vertex 5 be red. This forces vertices 1 and 4 to be green. Since vertices 2 and 3 are adjacent to vertices 1 and 4, respectively, neither vertex 2 nor vertex 3 can be green. Without loss of generality, let vertex 2 be red. But now observe that vertex 3 is adjacent to red, green, and blue vertices, so it must be a fourth color. But this is a contradiction. Now, without loss of generality, let vertex 5 be green. This forces vertices 1 and 4 to be red. By a similar argument to the above, letting vertex 2 be green forces vertex 3 to be a fourth color, again a contradiction. Hence, by contradiction, G is not 3-colorable in this case.
Case II: Four of the center neighbors are one color (blue in Figure 5.9), and one is of a different color (green in Figure 5.9). Without loss of generality, let vertex 9 be the green vertex. We are assuming 3-colorability; hence, vertices 5 and 3 must be red. This in turn forces vertices 1 and 4 to be green. But now observe that vertex 2 is adjacent to red, green, and blue vertices, so it must be a fourth color, which is a contradiction. Hence, G is not 3-colorable in this case.
Case III: Three consecutive center neighbors are of one color (blue in Figure 5.10), and the other two are of a different color (green in Figure 5.10). Without loss of generality, let vertices 7 and 9 be the green vertices. We are assuming 3-colorability; hence vertices 1 and 5 must be red. But this is a contradiction, as vertices 1 and 5 are adjacent and therefore cannot be the same color. Hence, G is not 3-colorable in this case.
Case IV: Three center neighbors are of one color (blue in Figure 5.11), and they are split up by two neighbors of a different color (green in Figure 5.11). Without loss of generality, let vertices 9 and 10 be the green vertices. We are assuming 3-colorability; hence vertices 1 and 5 must be red. But this is a contradiction, as vertices 1 and 5 are adjacent and therefore cannot be the same color. Hence, G is not 3-colorable in this case.
Figure 5.11: Attempted 3-coloring of G in case IV. The five-fold symmetry of G means that these four cases are exhaustive. All four cases result in contradictions of the main assumption, which is that G is 3-colorable. Hence, by contradiction, G is not 3-colorable. Since G is an isomorphism of Grtzschs Graph, and isomorphisms preserve adjacency, it follows that Grtzschs Graph is not 3-colorable.
Proof: Taking Figure 5.11 and adding a fourth color (yellow in Figure 5.13), we see that G can indeed be legally 4-colored. This, along with Theorems 5.4 and 5.7 imply by definition that G, and therefore Grtzschs Graph, has chromatic number 4.
Section 6: Conclusion
For reference, Grtzschs Theorem is reprinted here, along with the three key theorems of the paper. Theorem 2.1 (Grtzschs Theorem): Every triangle-free planar graph is 3-colorable Theorem 3.2: Grtzschs Graph is triangle-free. Theorem 4.6: Grtzschs Graph is non-planar. Theorem 5.12: Grtzschs Graph has chromatic number 4. Taking the validity of Grtzschs Theorem as a given, and having proven that Grtzschs Graph is triangle-free, non-planar, and has chromatic number 4 (i.e. is not 3-colorable), we have shown that planarity is a necessary condition to Grtzschs Theorem. Therefore, we have fulfilled the purpose of this paper.
Section 7: Acknowledgments
1) Definitions 1.1-1.9, Definitions 4.1-4.4, Theorem 4.5, and Definition 5.1 all come from Professor Lszl Babai, Discrete Mathematics: Lecture Notes, Incomplete Preliminary Version, 2003. An exercise posed in class, mentioned in the Abstract, was also the inspiration for this paper. 2) Grtzschs Theorem and Grtzschs Graph are both taken from the Wikipedia article on the Grtzsch Graph, <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Grotzsch_graph>. Last accessed July 16, 2007. 3) The idea that a graph is a subdivision of itself (mentioned in Definition 4.3) was not in Professor Babais definition. This property of subdivisions was confirmed by multiple articles following a Google search with the search prompt a graph is a subdivision of itself.