725837
725837
Pugh
The idea for this article originated at the 2017 Global Carework Summit in Lowell, MA; my
thanks to the organizers and audience there, as well as at the 2021 Social Life of Care confer-
ence at the University of Cambridge and the 2021 Sociology of Emotions Section Session on
“Emotions and Inequality” at the ASA annual meetings. Arlie Hochschild, Rachel Sherman,
Steve Lopez, and Carrie Lane have been helpful as this project has evolved, but their munifi-
cence should not be taken to presume their agreement with the arguments here. Thanks are
also due to the editors of the special issue, three anonymous reviewers, and to Miranda Out-
man for excellent editorial assistance, as well as to Ira Bashkow, Jennifer Cyd Rubenstein, and
Denise Walsh for comments on earlier drafts. Genevieve Charles, Jaime Hartless, and Allister
Pilar Plater provided vital research help. This project was supported by National Science Foun-
dation grant no. 1755419 as well as the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences
and the Berggruen Institute.
1
All names and some identifying details have been changed for confidentiality purposes.
Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, volume 49, number 1, Autumn 2023.
© 2023 The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. Published by The University of Chicago Press.
https://doi.org/10.1086/725837
142 y Pugh
Arlie Hochschild (2012) terms “emotional labor,” as when the wife is rude
on the phone but Betty “doesn’t take it in.” But we also hear something else:
Betty’s emotional fluency, her capacity to read the other’s feelings, to take
their perspective seriously—“so you better understand what really happen-
ing to them”—and to communicate it back to them, in her words and ac-
tions. Betty uses emotions as a sense-making tool, to understand the other
from clues both discursive and bodily (Otis 2011); from these raw materials
she then conveys to them that they are understood, through practices as sim-
ple as making peas and rice.
These interactions serve as a kind of witnessing, a mirroring of another
person that can generate dignity and be transformative, for the giver and
the given. To be sure, mirroring can also do harm, as when it communicates
misrecognition or stigma (Fleming, Lamont, and Welburn 2012). But Betty
let the wife know that she saw her from her perspective, a gift of visibility that
worked to calm the wife down. In seeing her, Betty helped to convey—and
in so conveying she helped to constitute—a shared humanity.
I define “connective labor” as the creating and sharing of an emotional ac-
knowledgment, through a process of seeing or reflecting another person, in
order to create value. While this kind of work can be found in many occupa-
tions beyond care, when it is deployed in care-work, the value created is in con-
tributing to the physical and mental well-being of another. Thus, connective
labor in care-work has a unique moral valence. Connective labor is made up of
four components: first, empathic listening, in which workers cultivate a shared
emotional understanding of someone else’s perspective (Clark 1997); second,
often, but not always, emotion management, because caregivers cannot al-
ways just let loose with their own visceral reactions in the clinic or the class-
room; third, witnessing, with which workers reflect back—through words
and/or actions—what they see of the other person; and, finally, acknowledg-
ment, or the receiving of this witnessing, since following Berenice Fisher and
Joan Tronto (1990), I consider these processes interactive, in which the client,
patient, or student helps to co-construct the meaning of the encounter. Con-
nective labor is both a skill and an interaction, then; it included not just Betty’s
capacity to read the other but also the collaboration between Betty and the
wife to create meaning out of their exchange.
Practitioners across a host of different occupations, from therapists to
teachers to physicians to sex workers, testify to the power of connective la-
bor.2 When one Oakland middle-school student known for behavior
2
I use data from this project primarily as illustration for theoretical argument and so do not
go into detail about methods and sampling here; please see Pugh (forthcoming) for more in-
formation on the project’s methodology.
S I G N S Autumn 2023 y 145
problems started acting out, for example, the school knew to call upon
Mutulu Acoli, a special education teacher there. “Usually, like if I see him
like that, I know I can go up to him and stop him, even if he’s, like, torn
through a couple other adults,” Mutulu told me. “I’m like, ‘nope. Look
at me. Who am I? You know I got you, so listen to me. What’s going on,
and let’s talk so we can get you back in class.’ ”
For Mutulu, “I got you” meant that he knew the boy well enough to be
aware of the backstory, to realize the boy had a rationale for acting out, even
as he worked to get him back on track. “Basically we have the trust that I’m
not trying to just say he did something bad without reasoning, and I’m also
going to be behind him in how he’s feeling,” Mutulu said. He saw the boy
as a whole person, not just as a problem kid, and he reflected that vision
back to the boy; because the boy felt seen, that meant Mutulu could reach
him when other people could not.
As part of this project, I also spent six months observing hospital chap-
lains in training. One day they were sharing with each other what it meant
to them to simply be present with patients. One chaplain, Erin, told the
others that she had been called to a patient’s bedside after he had been in-
tubated, “even though he really didn’t want to be intubated, and the doc-
tors were saying he would die if he was extubated, and that he might die
even if he was intubated,” she said. “And I was just sitting there with him
trying to be with him, reading his body signals, and he was full of anger,
and screaming ‘Why, why, why’ through his tube, and he couldn’t really
write because he was on too many pain meds.”
At that moment, Erin said, she grabbed a box of Kleenex and gave it to
him, telling him to throw it against the wall and that it would make him feel
better. “And then I reached out my hand, and I thought he was going to
hold my hand, and he ended up grabbing me by the arm and pulling me
in and holding on to me for fifteen minutes. And the next time I saw him
he was not intubated, and not dying,” she paused to make the sign of a prayer,
“and he said, ‘There is nothing like being in the worst moment of your life
and being met with comfort by someone you don’t even know, when you
feel like someone understands you.’ ”
Teachers and chaplains inhabit very different social locations than do sex
workers or home health-care aides—even highly valued ones like Betty.
Careful scholarly work (e.g., Cranford 2020) has documented the relevance
of those contexts for the care people are able to give. By drilling down to
the emotional components of connective labor, however, this project
chronicles some surprising similarities across these occupations, despite
their dramatic differences in power, autonomy, training, and pay. As I
argue below, we also gain a new vantage point on the role of inequality
146 y Pugh
3
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this point.
S I G N S Autumn 2023 y 147
Attachment
Some care-work scholars point to attachment as an integral part of care. For
example, Francesca M. Cancian and Stacey J. Oliker (2000, 2) define “care-
giving” as “feelings of affection and responsibility combined with actions that
provide responsively for an individual’s personal needs or well-being, in a face-
to-face relationship.” Attachment brings with it the motivation necessary for
148 y Pugh
care, some scholars argue (e.g., Himmelweit 1999). As Paula England notes
in her review (2005), scholars imply that care is better when the practitioner
harbors feelings of affection for their client or patient, instead of being wholly
motivated by money. Writes Susan Himmelweit (1999, 29): “A carer will
not succeed in delivering good care unless he appears to the person being
cared for (the caree) to be motivated by genuine concern for his well-being.”
Yet, we might posit that the issue here is not whether caregivers feel affec-
tion and love for their clients and patients, since such feelings often (but not
always) arise in care situations. As one home-care worker told Jane Aronson
and Sheila M. Neysmith (1996, 65), “They might say, ‘Well, try not to get
involved.’ Well, you cannot not get involved. If you’re going in there reg-
ularly and you’re seeing the situation, you become part of that person. It’s
very hard not to become . . . involved, you know.” Instead, it is how cen-
tral those feelings are to their work: does their care count as care, regardless
of their personal attachment to the care recipient? Even more important, what
is emotion in care if not attachment?
Emotional labor
The term “emotional labor” is dotted across the landscape of care-work re-
search, as scholars depict caregivers marshaling the “right” emotion within
themselves or eliciting it in their charges as part of their jobs (e.g., Milligan
2005). As Hochschild (2012, 7) defines it, emotion work “requires one to
induce or suppress feeling in order to sustain the outward countenance that
produces the proper state of mind in others”; she reserves the term “emo-
tional labor” for that work conducted for a wage, cautioning that workers
risk feeling alienated from their very selves when they control emotions for
their employers. “The funeral parlor director, the doctor, the complaints clerk,
the day-care worker all apply a sense of ‘should’ to the situated feelings that
emerge in the course of a week,” Hochschild writes (1979, 572). As a nor-
mative arena, replete with dictates about who ought to care and how they
ought to do it, there are plenty of “shoulds” in care-work, including how
people should feel.
Furthermore, many researchers argue that part of good care is “creating
in others feelings of well-being or affirmation” (Wharton 2009, 149); a nurs-
ing home resident can be clean and tidy, but if they do not feel like they are
and are anxious about that, care has on some level not been fully accom-
plished (Fisher and Tronto 1990). To the extent that caregivers actively con-
trol and modify their own emotions to generate feelings of well-being in
their clients, their efforts surely involve emotional labor.
While the original meaning of emotional labor was quite limited to this
sense of oft-alienated emotion management, it has since expanded dramatically
S I G N S Autumn 2023 y 149
for some scholars. Since writing The Managed Heart, Hochschild (2012,
2013) has sought to broaden the concept of emotional labor to mean all
kinds of work involving emotions, calling attention to its outsourcing and
what happens when it is performed for a wage. As Rachel Sherman (2015,
176 n. 2) notes, emotional labor “is now widely used to describe all kinds
of commodified emotional work, although this was not its original meaning”
(see also Lopez 2006; Cain 2013). While some scholars continue to deploy
the term in its initial definition (e.g., Kelly 2016), others’ expansion of the
term to mean a much broader range of emotional behaviors is surely an in-
dicator of how much researchers find they need to be able to think and talk
across that range. Yet while an umbrella term is useful, we must also expand
our retinue of concepts to specify practices within the range, of which emo-
tion management and attachment are but two components.4
4
For clarity, from this point forward I refer to the more limited definition as “emotion
management” and the umbrella term as “emotional labor.”
150 y Pugh
In her study of personal trainers, Jennifer Smith Maguire (2001, 393) writes,
“the ability to cultivate different styles and then to effectively intuit the most
appropriate style for the client are part of the relational adaptability of per-
sonal training.” Sometimes scholars seem to tiptoe around the notion of
emotional experiences not captured by existing terminology, offering up
lists such as “the emotions, the smiles and eye contact, the time for conver-
sations big and small, the gentle touches and gestures” but not organizing
the uses of emotion in a patterned way (Henry 2018, 342; see also Cain
2013). These scholars attempt to make a space for emotions not captured
by the two dominant approaches.
The reign of attachment and emotional management as paradigms gov-
erning how care scholars talk about feeling has led researchers to focus on
the presence and purity of that feeling, through registers such as motivation,
authenticity, and alienation (e.g., Grant, Morales, and Sallaz 2009). For ex-
ample, researchers have identified a prisoner of love framework (Folbre 2001)
in which the intrinsic rewards of altruism bind caregivers to jobs that are
undercompensated (Lightman and Kevins 2019). While altruism may be dis-
tinct from emotion, instead linked simply to a “concern for the well-being
of care recipients” (Folbre and Wright 2012, 1), the line between such
concern and feelings of care or love is actually a bit blurry in scholarship.
In England’s influential (2005) review, for example, her discussion of the
prisoner of love model ranges over both “altruistic preferences” and emo-
tional bonds that “put care workers in a vulnerable position,” which she
terms the “emotional hostage effect” (390). Research into emotion man-
agement and care has focused on its impact on worker alienation and engage-
ment. While interactive caring jobs do not always involve emotion manage-
ment (Wharton 2009), and emotion management does not always lead to
feelings of alienation or inauthenticity (Orzechowicz 2008), when they do,
such feelings are linked to depression (Erickson and Wharton 1997). These
long-standing areas of research have come under some criticism of late, how-
ever, leading some to eschew emotional analysis outright.
Yet while scholars have used these distinctions to analyze race- and
class-based pay gaps (Budig, Hodges, and England 2019) or track the ra-
cial/ethnic and gendered composition of these jobs (Duffy 2011), critics
have argued that these categories themselves foster inequality among women
(Roberts 1997). Distinctions between work that involves face-to-face nur-
ture and that involving backstage support sound impartial, but they are far
from race- or class-neutral; as Dorothy Roberts (1997, 71) contends, they
follow the separation of “spiritual” and “menial” labor or “dirty” work that
once characterized the unpaid work of privileged white women as house-
wives and the domestic labor done by nonwhite, immigrant, and working-
class women (Glenn 2010). Furthermore, these categories do not simply
reflect actual distinctions in the field, these scholars note, as care jobs often
resist such neat categorization, mixing cleaning and interacting, cooking and
nurture (Anderson and Hughes 2010; Lutz 2011). In contrast, for exam-
ple, Evelyn Nakano Glenn (2010) offers a tripartite definition: direct care
(which includes emotional and physical care), maintaining the physical sur-
roundings, and fostering people’s social connections.
Drawing symbolic boundaries may seem neutral or simply descriptive, but
it in fact enacts distinctions that rely on preexisting cultural notions suffused
with normative meaning. These cultural meanings amplify existing inequal-
ities of race/ethnicity, class, citizenship, ability, and age, among others. They
sometimes make for counterintuitive groupings (Budig, Hodges, and En-
gland 2019) while drawing firm boundaries that critics argue are not al-
ways so cut and dried. These differences are messier in actuality: Betty, the
home health aide, both cooks and connects emotionally. That the defini-
tional distinctions are not inevitable suggests that whatever their analytic
purpose, their accomplishment is in part the making and remaking of these
inequalities.
the one hand, these distinctions are important for policy considerations,
since society has an interest in subsidizing care that satisfies basic needs oth-
erwise unmet. Tronto (2013, 22), whose foundational—and very broad—
definition would include both types, argues that the distinction captures
important observations about unequal relations: “in service, the actors who
command the care work that is provided by care workers are the ones with
greater power, whereas in ‘care,’ the more powerful actors provide the care
work for less powerful or more vulnerable recipients. . . . The difference is
in who appears to be in command.”
The difference also appears to be rooted in normative commitments, as
scholars attempt to distinguish between care that allows life and that which
allows luxury. As Sherman (2015, 166) observes, in reference to the per-
sonal chefs and concierges she interviewed, compared to workers focused
on basic needs fulfillment, “the kind of attention [these] workers offer may,
in fact, seem unnecessary or excessive, simply enacting and reproducing the
class entitlements of consumers.” Yet when care is viewed as only that which
satisfies basic needs, scholars argue, it serves to reduce care recipients to pas-
sive, dependent burdens, and this holds for people living with disabilities
(Kröger 2009) as well as children and youth (Morrow 1996; Lee 2001; Pugh
2014). Some scholars object that people can be at once dependent and inde-
pendent, and thus scholars should recognize interdependence instead (Fine
and Glendinning 2005). Others include a coconstitutive element to their
definitions of care, including a role for caregiver and recipient, highlighting
the mutuality of care-work (Tronto 1993; Douglas, Rice, and Kelly 2017;
Kittay 2020). Nonetheless, critical disability researchers have advocated a
turn to a “personal assistance” model instead, considering care—with its
emotional emphasis—“conceptually contaminated” (Kröger 2009, 399).
These three critiques have led some scholars to disavow the role of emo-
tions in care-work, to urge care-work researchers to deemphasize emotions
in their analyses, and to prioritize other framings that they argue are bet-
ter able incorporate the intersectional politics of care-work (Watson et al.
2004; Romero and Pérez 2016). “By removing culpability from the po-
litical and placing care work in the realm of the personal and affective,
[dominant narratives of emotion and love] often bolster . . . essentialist
views, [and] ultimately they also reinscribe inequality,” write Romero and
Perez (185). Meanwhile, as Tom Shakespeare has written, for the disabil-
ity activist, care is “value-laden, contested and confused, particularly in the
way it combines an emotional component and a description of basic human
services” (cited in Watson et al. 2004, 338–39). Emotions, in this view, are
the problem.
154 y Pugh
Seeing politics
Connective labor is emotional work, but it is also a skill, one that is recog-
nized and trained when professional counselors do it, to achieve what is
called a “therapeutic alliance.” Its reflective mirroring is frequently taught
as part of motivational interviewing, an approach that involves a formal cur-
riculum and is increasingly common in medical settings. Reflective, empathic
acknowledgment of the other is behind many of the vignettes in Lopez’s
(2006) account of the “organized emotional care” he witnessed in nursing
homes (133), for example, when a caregiver accurately recognized, reflected,
and responded to the distress of a nonverbal client, whose “relief and grat-
itude . . . was palpable and, in the context of their relationship, constituted
an important intrinsic reward” (148). These examples counter the notions
that because it is emotional, connective labor cannot be recognized as skill.
I observed a graduate course for school counselors for one semester, and
one day, they did an exercise to “encourage listening skills,” in which they
were paired up, with one person assigned to share a story “that invokes an
emotion in you” for two minutes without interruption, and the “helper”
was assigned to retell the story back to them “as if it were your own.” After
the exercise, Karen, the teacher, asked “What was it like as ‘helper’ to have
to listen, knowing you had to share back the details of their story?” A young
S I G N S Autumn 2023 y 155
woman responded: “It made me realize that listening a lot takes a lot of
endurance.” She was not nearly this attentive normally, she said. “I mean
I love my mother, but when I listen to her, I’m getting the general gist.”
Karen agreed, adding that they needed “to be able to follow through all
the way to the end and keep track of it all while you’re doing that.” The
skill of listening, at its most basic, involved staying with the speaker, cog-
nitively, “all the way to the end.” Later in the semester, they observed pairs
of peers from behind a one-way mirror, evaluating their capacity to reflect
the other. Connective labor may be emotional, but some programs are act-
ing like it can be trained, evaluated, and improved.
Care scholars disagree about how much to enumerate the skills and
mechanisms of care-work. On the one hand, the more it is subject to ef-
ficiency pressures—regardless of the category of emotional activity—the more
it becomes emotion management, ginned up for a wage. Discussions of
care-work often retain a vague and mysterious quality about what counts
as care, intentionally so for some scholars who see it as a means to fend off
its further rationalization (e.g., Henry 2018). Others have argued that
we need to be much more specific about the processes of care in order to
make an argument for its value; when employers ignore it, they do not
systematize it but neither do they make time for it (Duffy 2011). “When
relationality is invisible, workers are not recognized and care is compro-
mised,” writes Duffy (2011, 138). “Describing and advocating for for-
mal recognition of relational labor as part of paid care work is critical to
addressing some of the problematic working conditions care workers now
face” (140).
Seeing inequality
Introducing connective labor also allows us to tackle some of the critiques
of inequality in care-work scholarship. First, and paradoxically, it disrupts
some of the distinctions that naturalize racial/ethnic and class differences
in care-work’s definitional debates. When we drill down into specific pro-
cesses of care, rather than classifying entire jobs as relational or nurturant
per se, we can identify work that involves more or fewer of these processes
(Pietrykowski 2017). This move helps to highlight the emotional compo-
nents of some jobs that might not be identified as relational in their entirety,
and it thereby decomposes seemingly fixed racial/ethnic binaries—the
white women’s nurturant labor and the women of color in reproductive
care—decried by critical race scholars. Depending on the context, for exam-
ple, hairdressers and waitresses can find themselves conducting substantial
connective labor on the job, yet both jobs have been dubbed reproductive,
or nonnurturant care, in some accounts.
156 y Pugh
me about what she considered one of her biggest failures, lecturing an obese
Black teenager “about not drinking sodas.” “That was pretty much what I
was doing at the end of the visit,” she recalled, “and he ended up in tears.”
After years of treating them, it was the last time she saw the family. “That
just—it was actually after a year of building up this trusting relationship with
this boy who had been so emotionally charged, I lost all trust with him.”
Traumatic as it was for the physician, we can imagine the visit was even more
so for the boy—disadvantaged by race, class, age, and other dimensions—
whose empathic listener had turned into judge.
Other times practitioners were the ones who experienced the vulnerabil-
ity. Whitney, the “sugar baby,” felt acutely disadvantaged by gender, age,
and income in her encounters. “I mean, there’s also kind of—at least for
me—this element of fear the whole time when you’re with these people,”
she said. “Like, I mean small-level things, like, ‘is somebody who I know
going to see me?’ to large-level things, like, ‘Is this person going to murder
me? Or, like, rape me?’ And that doesn’t really go away.”
Third, faced with the challenges inequality poses to their capacity to de-
liver meaningful connective labor, practitioners cultivate dignity practices—
to convince themselves and others of autonomy, safety, and equity, even
in its relative absence. Among those dignity practices was inviting aspects of
the “whole person” into the classroom or clinic. Ken Margolis, a middle-
school teacher in Oakland, had students handle attendance so he could walk
around the classroom. “You just notice aberrations, [like] if some kid is al-
ways bubbly and they’re not bubbly that day,” he said. “And you have to ask
very specific questions. So you say something like, ‘Is it a friend? Is it an en-
emy? Is it your stomach? Is it your head?’ Because they need to feel—every-
body needs to feel cared for. And respected, right?” Dignity practices are one
way practitioners fight the growing systematization of care, by disrupting the
boundaries around what counts as relevant information. They described it
as if they were finding the humane in themselves while insisting upon it
for others.
Seeing mutuality
Finally, the arguments of disability activists who attempt to ward off pater-
nalism by disavowing emotion appear to presume that love or attachment
are the only dimensions of emotions in care-work. But for connective labor
workers, emotions are a tool, a means of sensing the contours of the other,
their identity, their desires and dislikes, without which the care recipient is
standardized and the care-work is uniform; furthermore, feminists have de-
cried the denigration of gendered emotional work, which characterizes even
the work of personal assistants. The denial of emotional content, scholars
158 y Pugh
5
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for emphasizing this point.
S I G N S Autumn 2023 y 159
reveal the significance of their secrets (1978, 67). Yet such power had to be
participated in, acquiesced to, constituted by both the person with the se-
crets and the person listening to them; here we see a blurring of the “line
between coercion and consent” made manifest by someone’s refusal. The
video continued with the man saying to his wife, “you’ve been doing this
for fourteen years, making their goddamn lunches.” Refusing to be drawn
into the process by Kelsey’s attempts to reflect his point of view, the recalci-
trant client demonstrated that connective labor required an active participant.
Collaboration helps to create the meaning of the encounter. Wanda
Coombs, a sex therapist, told me that when she got it wrong, the sense of
something amiss was palpable. “When things are wrong or off, you feel it,”
she said. “Something halts and there’s kind of like silence or a dead air, and
that’s when I’m just like, what just happened here? And I’ll say it, you know,
‘I felt like maybe there was a shift here, does that feel like that resonates for
you or not,’ and invite them to come in to provide clarity.” Indeed, as
Noddings (2010, 392) argues, “without the reinforcing response of the
cared-for, carers suffer empathic exhaustion and burnout.” Connective la-
bor thus is not only defined by such mutuality, it is sustained by it (Fine
and Glendinning 2005).
Conclusion
Connective labor is a form of seeing and reflecting the other emotionally,
and as such, it is a particular kind of work involving the use of feeling as a
tool. While connective labor is prevalent in all manner of care-work, how-
ever, existing scholarship does not have the vocabulary to capture this and
other kinds of emotional work. Care-work scholarship has relied on two pri-
mary models of emotion—attachment and emotional labor—that have fo-
cused researchers’ attention on questions of motivation and alienation. The
dominance of these models has also left the field open to critiques by critical
race scholars and disability rights researchers, who argue that they gloss over
the politics of care-work and impede our capacity to reckon with its inter-
sectional inequalities. In this article, I have proposed connective labor as
one way to address these critiques, not by turning away from emotion but
by turning toward it to identify additional ways in which feelings are used
in care-work.
The naming of connective labor, and its differentiation from the two mod-
els, should not preclude the questions raised regarding attachment or emo-
tional labor—in particular, how their working conditions shape care. Yet
as shown, the term opens up other areas for research: how workers man-
age pastoral power and its tensions of affirming another’s uniqueness and
160 y Pugh
requiring their emotional legibility, the factors that shape the mutual co-
constitution of meaning in care-work interactions, how workers of varying
advantage conduct and experience connective labor, the cultural scripts and
contexts that generate recognition and misrecognition and their impact. I
hope that future research investigates the impact of care-work contexts on
the great variety of emotional skills that constitute care. These issues are just
some of the fertile expanse awaiting researchers.
Furthermore, there are many other appearances of emotions in care-work
as yet unidentified, and recognizing these instances could expand our ability
to explore and understand it. We might agree upon an umbrella term—the
latest version of emotional labor is fine, if we distinguish it sufficiently from
emotion management—to apply to the general notion of emotions at work,
of which attachment, emotion management, and connective labor are but
three variants. Such a project is beyond the scope of this article but is im-
plicated by it: by this point, I mean to underscore that connective labor is
not the whole of what is missing in care-work, but its inclusion makes room
for others to explore the terrain.
References
Anderson, Nickela, and Karen D. Hughes. 2010. “The Business of Caring: Wom-
en’s Self-Employment and the Marketization of Care.” Gender, Work, and Or-
ganization 17(4):381–405.
Armenia, Amy. 2018. “Caring as Work: Research and Theory.” In Handbook of
the Sociology of Gender, 2nd ed., edited by Barbara J. Risman, Carissa M. Froyum,
and William J. Scarborough, 469–78. Cham: Springer.
Aronson, Jane, and Sheila M. Neysmith. 1996. “ ‘You’re Not Just in There to Do
the Work’: Depersonalizing Policies and the Exploitation of Home Care Work-
ers’ Labor.” Gender & Society 10(1):59–77.
Budig, Michelle J., Melissa J. Hodges, and Paula England. 2019. “Wages of Nur-
turant and Reproductive Care Workers: Individual and Job Characteristics, Oc-
cupational Closure, and Wage-Equalizing Institutions.” Social Problems 66(2):
294–319.
Butler, Judith. 2011. Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of “Sex.” New
York: Routledge.
Cain, Cindy L. 2013. “Heart Work: Challenges and Adaptations of Hospice Care
Workers.” PhD dissertation, University of Arizona.
Cancian, Francesca. 2000. “Paid Emotional Care: Organizing Forms That Encour-
age Nurturance.” In Care Work: Gender, Labor, and the Welfare State, edited by
Madonna Harrington Meyer, 136–48. London: Routledge.
S I G N S Autumn 2023 y 161
Cancian, Francesca M., and Stacey J. Oliker. 2000. Caring and Gender. Lanham,
MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Clark, Candace. 1997. Misery and Company: Sympathy in Everyday Life. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Connolly, Julie. 2010. “Love in the Private: Axel Honneth, Feminism, and the Pol-
itics of Recognition.” Contemporary Political Theory 9(4):414–33.
Cook, Catherine, and Margaret Brunton. 2015. “Pastoral Power and Gynaecological
Examinations: A Foucauldian Critique of Clinician Accounts of Patient-Centred
Consent.” Sociology of Health and Illness 37(4):545–60.
Cranford, Cynthia J. 2020. Home Care Fault Lines: Understanding Tensions and
Creating Alliances. Ithaca, NY: ILR Press.
Diamond, Timothy. 2009. Making Gray Gold: Narratives of Nursing Home Care.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Douglas, Patty, Carla Rice, and Christine Kelly. 2017. “Cripping Care: Care Peda-
gogies and Practices.” Review of Disability Studies 13(4). https://rdsjournal
.org/index.php/journal/article/view/779.
Duffy, Mignon. 2005. “Reproducing Labor Inequalities: Challenges for Feminists
Conceptualizing Care at the Intersections of Gender, Race, and Class.” Gender
& Society 19(1):66–82.
———. 2011. Making Care Count: A Century of Gender, Race, and Paid Care
Work. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Dwyer, Rachel E. 2013. “The Care Economy? Gender, Economic Restructuring,
and Job Polarization in the US Labor Market.” American Sociological Review
78(3):390–416.
England, Paula. 2005. “Emerging Theories of Care Work.” Annual Review of So-
ciology 31:381–99.
Erickson, Rebecca J., and Amy S. Wharton. 1997. “Inauthenticity and Depression:
Assessing the Consequences of Interactive Service Work.” Work and Occupations
24(2):188–213.
Fanon, Frantz. 1967. Black Skin, White Masks. Translated by Charles Lam Mark-
mann. New York: Grove.
Fine, Michael, and Caroline Glendinning. 2005. “Dependence, Independence, or
Inter-Dependence? Revisiting the Concepts of ‘Care’ and ‘Dependency.’ ” Age-
ing and Society 25(4):601–21.
Fisher, Berenice, and Joan Tronto. 1990. “Toward a Feminist Theory of Caring.”
In Circles of Care: Work and Identity in Women’s Lives, edited by Emily K. Abel
and Margaret K. Nelson, 35–62. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Fleming, Crystal M., Michèle Lamont, and Jessica S. Welburn. 2012. “African
Americans Respond to Stigmatization: The Meanings and Salience of Confront-
ing, Deflecting Conflict, Educating the Ignorant, and ‘Managing the Self.’” Ethnic
and Racial Studies 35(3):400–417.
Folbre, Nancy. 2001. The Invisible Heart: Economics and Family Values. New York:
New Press.
162 y Pugh
Folbre, Nancy, and Erik Olin Wright. 2012. “Defining Care.” In For Love or Money:
Care Provision in the United States, edited by Nancy Folbre, 1–20. New York:
Russell Sage Foundation.
Foucault, Michel. 1978. The History of Sexuality, vol. 1: An Introduction. Translated
by Robert Hurley. New York: Pantheon.
———. 1982. “The Subject and Power.” Critical Inquiry 8(4):777–95.
Giordano, Cristiana. 2014. Migrants in Translation: Caring and the Logics of Dif-
ference in Contemporary Italy. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Glenn, Evelyn Nakano. 2010. Forced to Care: Coercion and Caregiving in America.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Grant, Don, Alfonso Morales, and Jeffrey J. Sallaz. 2009. “Pathways to Meaning: A
New Approach to Studying Emotions at Work.” American Journal of Sociology
115(2):327–64.
Henry, Caitlin. 2018. “The Abstraction of Care: What Work Counts?” Antipode 50
(2):340–58.
Himmelweit, Susan. 1999. “Caring Labor.” Annals of the American Academy of Po-
litical and Social Science 561(1):27–38.
Hochschild, Arlie Russell. 1979. “Emotion Work, Feeling Rules, and Social Struc-
ture.” American Journal of Sociology 85(3):551–75.
———. 2012. The Managed Heart: Commercialization of Human Feeling. Berke-
ley: University of California Press.
———. 2013. So How’s the Family? And Other Essays. Berkeley: University of Cal-
ifornia Press.
Honneth, Axel. 1996. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social
Conflicts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hopkins, Debra, Linda McKie, Nick Watson, and Bill Hughes. 2007. “The Prob-
lem of Emotion in Care: Contested Meanings from the Disabled People’s Move-
ment and the Feminist Movement.” In Emotions and Social Movements, edited
by Helena Flam and Debra King, 119–34. London: Routledge.
Illouz, Eva. 2007. Cold Intimacies: The Making of Emotional Capitalism. London:
Polity.
Kelly, Christine. 2016. Disability Politics and Care: The Challenge of Direct Fund-
ing. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.
Kittay, Eva Feder. 2020. Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Labor, and Dependency.
2nd ed. New York: Routledge.
Kröger, Teppo. 2009. “Care Research and Disability Studies: Nothing in Com-
mon?” Critical Social Policy 29(3):398–420.
Lee, Nick. 2001. Childhood and Society: Growing Up in an Age of Uncertainty.
Maidenhead: Open University Press.
Lightman, Naomi, and Anthony Kevins. 2019. “Bonus or Burden? Care Work, In-
equality, and Job Satisfaction in Eighteen European Countries.” European Socio-
logical Review 35(6):825–44.
Lopez, Steven H. 2006. “Emotional Labor and Organized Emotional Care: Con-
ceptualizing Nursing Home Care Work.” Work and Occupations 33(2):133–60.
S I G N S Autumn 2023 y 163
Lutz, Helma. 2011. The New Maids: Transnational Women and the Care Economy.
London: Zed.
Lynch, Kathleen. 2007. “Love Labour as a Distinct and Non-commodifiable Form
of Care Labour.” Sociological Review 55(3):550–70.
Maguire, Jennifer Smith. 2001. “Fit and Flexible: The Fitness Industry, Personal Train-
ers, and Emotional Service Labor.” Sociology of Sport Journal 18(4):379–402.
Martin, Graham P., and Justin Waring. 2018. “Realising Governmentality: Pastoral
Power, Governmental Discourse, and the (Re)constitution of Subjectivities.” So-
ciological Review 66(6):1292–308.
Mauldin, Laura, and Mamta Saxena. 2018. “Mutual Exchange: Caregiving and Life
Enhancement in Siblings of Individuals with Developmental Disabilities.” Jour-
nal of Family Issues 39(8):2232–64.
Mayes, Christopher. 2009. “Pastoral Power and the Confessing Subject in Patient-
Centred Communication.” Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 6(4):483–93.
Milligan, Christine. 2005. “From Home to ‘Home’: Situating Emotions within the
Caregiving Experience.” Environment and Planning A 37(12):2105–20.
Morrow, Virginia. 1996. “Rethinking Childhood Dependency: Children’s Contri-
butions to the Domestic Economy.” Sociological Review 44(1):58–77.
Nelson, Margaret K. 1990. “Mothering Others’ Children: The Experiences of Fam-
ily Day-Care Providers.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 15(3):
586–605.
Noddings, Nel. 2010. “Moral Education in an Age of Globalization.” Educational
Philosophy and Theory 42(4):390–96.
Oliver, Kelly. 2001. Witnessing: Beyond Recognition. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Oliver, Michael, and Colin Barnes. 1990. The New Politics of Disablement.
Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.
Orzechowicz, David. 2008. “Privileged Emotion Managers: The Case of Actors.”
Social Psychology Quarterly 71(2):143–56.
Otis, Eileen M. 2011. Markets and Bodies: Women, Service Work, and the Making
of Inequality in China. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Pietrykowski, Bruce. 2017. “The Return to Caring Skills: Gender, Class, and Oc-
cupational Wages in the US.” Feminist Economics 23(4):32–61.
Pugh, Allison J. 2014. “The Theoretical Costs of Ignoring Childhood: Rethinking
Independence, Insecurity, and Inequality.” Theory and Society 43: 71–89.
———. 2022a. “Constructing What Counts as Human at Work: Enigma, Emotion,
and Error in Connective Labor.” American Behavioral Scientist. Prepublished
online, September 25. https://doi.org/10.1177/00027642221127240.
———. 2022b. “Emotions and the Systematization of Connective Labor.” Theory,
Culture, and Society 39(5):23–42.
———. Forthcoming. The Last Human Job. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Ray, Raka, and Seemin Qayum. 2009. Cultures of Servitude: Modernity, Domesticity,
and Class in India. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
164 y Pugh