Compte-Rendu Quand Faire C'est Croire
Compte-Rendu Quand Faire C'est Croire
REVIEW ARTICLE
clifford ando
J. SCHEID, QUAND FAIRE, C’EST CROIRE. LES RITES SACRIFICIELS DES ROMAINS.
Paris: Aubier, 2005. Pp. 348. isbn 2-70072298-1. €26.00.
In the volume under review, Scheid organizes several new papers and revises a number
previously published in order to present a detailed portrait of sacrificial practice at Rome,
as well as an analysis of its logic. The result is an important book in a number of respects.
It provides a clear statement of Scheid’s methods in the study of ritual; it gives a compel-
ling account of public sacrifice and commensality; and it extends the insights thus gleaned
to non-public rites at Rome, particularly funerary banquets. To students of Roman
religion in particular, it offers the opportunity to consider a number of developments in
Scheid’s own work and in the field more generally since he made his initial sustained
contributions to the study of ritual and Roman religion over a quarter century ago.1
Besides an introduction and conclusion, Quand faire, c’est croire contains nine chapters
in four parts, each part with its own introduction, and eight appendices. The parts concen-
trate on Roman sacrifice; sacrifice according to the so-called ‘Greek rite’; sacrifice in
private contexts (both domestic and funerary); and commensality, among human partici-
pants and between humans and gods — in the latter case, the question being how they
understood and performed the division of meat. The appendices provide French transla-
tions — often enough with Latin original, but never Greek — of the most significant
evidence for various phenomena discussed in the text. Notably for those without easy
access to Scheid’s edition of the Arval acta, this includes long selections from that text; as
well as extended passages from the acta of the Secular Games (and from Zosimus’ report
on the same); the instructions on sacrifice provided by Cato — and these are compared
with the Arval evidence in a chart; as well as comparisons between the Parentationes and
funerary honours for Lucius and Gaius Caesar; and evidence for the sacrificial banquet.
Part 1, ‘Facere. Le sacrifice, rite central de la religion romaine’, contains two chapters —
one new, one revised. The new chapter, ‘Sacrifices selon le rite romain’, offers a reasoned
reconstruction of votive and regular sacrifices, following above all the data recorded in the
acts of the Arval Brethren. As such, it condenses arguments set forth in detail in Romulus
et ses frères (1990), Part 3. The reconstruction has two objects: the actions themselves
taken in the course of a sacrifice, together with what we might term their immanent mean-
ing. By immanent meaning I intend such understandings of the importance and effects of
any given action in its place within the ritual as one would need to adapt that ritual to the
contingent circumstances of a particular performance; or likewise such understandings as
1
Scheid himself offers invaluable insight regarding his intellectual formation and current endeavours in an
interview conducted with Philippe Matthey, ‘Entretiens avec John Scheid’, Asdiwal 2 (2007), 125–30.
2
The term and definition are my own; for a formulation along the same lines by Scheid see, e.g., 184: ‘Rappelons
encore que dans une religion ritualiste, les gestes et les comportements construisent des représentations et des
énoncés sur le système des choses et des êtres, énoncés qui, à la manière des actes performatifs, pouvaient devenir
une réalité dans la conscience de ceux qui célébraient ces rites et de ceux qui y assistaient. Et comme toujours dans
la reconstruction des énoncés formulés par des gestes (de surcroît transmis par des sources indirectes), tous les
détails sont importants.’ (‘Recall again that in a ritualist religion, gestures and deportment constitute
representations and statements concerning the system of things and of being, statements which, in the same manner
as performative acts, could become a reality in the consciousness of those who were celebrating and those who were
attending the rites. And as always when reconstructing statements made through gestures (and especially those
transmitted by indirect sources), all details are important.’)
3
By ‘less fulsome’ I intend both more narrowly lexicographical sources such as Festus/Paulus, Nonius Marcellus,
Isidore, Donatus and Servius, as well as leges arae. Much light is shed on the religious terminology and ritual
background of statal and private acts referred to simply in passing by Livy, Terence and Seneca in particular.
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 173
4
On the function of (epigraphic) textualization in Roman religion see especially M. Beard, ‘Writing and ritual: a
study of diversity and expansion in the Arval Acta’, PBSR 53 (1985), 114–62; and R. Gordon, ‘From Republic to
Principate: priesthood, religion and ideology’, in M. Beard and J. North (eds), Pagan Priests: Religion and Power in
the Ancient World (1990), 179–98. See also J. Scheid, ‘Rituel et écriture à Rome’, in A.-M. Blondeau and K. Schipper
(eds), Essais sur le rituel II, Bibliothèque de l’École des Hautes Études, section des sciences religieuses 95 (1990),
1–15; M. Beard, ‘Writing and religion: Ancient literacy and the function of the written word in Roman religion’, in
Literacy in the Ancient World, JRA Supplement 3 (1991), 35–58; J. Scheid, ‘Les archives de la piété’, in S. Demougin
(ed.), La mémoire perdue. À la recherche des archives oubliées, publiques et privées, de la Rome antique, CNRS —
Série Histoire Ancienne et Médiévale 30 (1994), 173–85; J. North, ‘The books of the pontifices’, in C. Moatti, La
mémoire perdue. Recherches sur l’administration romaine, CÉFR 243 (1998), 45–63; J. Rüpke, ‘Acta aut agenda:
relations of script and performance’, in A. Barchiesi, J. Rüpke and S. Stephens (eds), Rituals in Ink (2004), 23–43;
and C. Ando, The Matter of the Gods (2008), 72–5.
5
‘The variety of funerary rites cannot at present be taken into account, either. These change from family to
family, from necropolis to necropolis, from city to city. Nor is it a question of their evolution. With such lacunose
and poorly-known documentation, complete reconstruction is, for now, elusive’ (163). ‘There was a great number
of variants in the sacrifical act, but the fundamental and first principle was that we have to give. It lay in the
construction of difference and separation between different beings, while stressing their association in the world’
(183).
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 174
6
Among a large recent literature see O. de Cazanove, ‘Some thoughts on the “religious Romanization” of Italy
before the Social War’, in E. Bispham and C. Smith (eds), Religion in Archaic and Republican Rome and Italy
(2000), 71–6; idem, ‘I destinatari dell’iscrizione di Tiriolo e la questione del campo d’applicazione del
senatoconsulto de bacchanalibus’, Athenaeum 88 (2000), 59–68; C. Schultz and P. B. Harvey, Jr (eds), Religion in
Republican Italy, Yale Classical Studies 33 (2006), especially the essays by F. Glinister (‘Reconsidering “religious
Romanization”’), V. Livi (‘Religious locales in the territory of Minturnae: some aspects of Romanization’),
P. B. Harvey, Jr (‘Religion and memory at Pisaurum’), and A. Cooley (‘Beyond Rome and Latium: Roman religion
in the age of Augustus’); and C. Ando, ‘Diana on the Aventine’, in H. Cancik and J. Rüpke (eds), Die Religion des
Imperium Romanum (2009), 99–113.
7
One might understand the problem thus: the political identity of citizens of liberal-democratic states is
established by their interpellation as rights-bearers. In such systems, fundamental binding aspects of communal
culture such as religion and often even language are understood not simply as non-statal — the object of individual
choice, while communities of individuals like-minded in respect to religion are constituted as private at law — but
those choices are often protected through precisely the state’s guarantee of individual right. Scholars whose self-
understandings are formed by their constitution within such states are predisposed to understand individuals as
more completely atomized and to view a wider array of constituents of identity as objects of choice and negotiation.
Citizens of republics, on the other hand, are bound to each other and the state by networks of entitlements,
obligations, and cultural commitments communally understood and jurally defined as entailed by citizenship. These
might be debated and revised in the public sphere, but they are not subject to individual negotiation at the same
level. It is the co-existence in France of Republican citizenship and individual rights that gives French jurisprudence
on the law on persons its distinctive flavour.
8
There are two significant exceptions to this claim: ‘Cultes, mythes et politique au début de l’Empire’, in F. Graf
(ed.), Mythos in mythenloser Gesellschaft. Das Paradigma Roms (1993), 109–27 (translated by P. Purchase in
C. Ando (ed.), Roman Religion (2003)), and ‘Aspects religieux de la municipalisation. Quelques réflexions
générales’, in M. Dondin-Payre and M.-T. Raepsaet-Charlier (eds), Cités, Municipes, Colonies. Les processus de
municipalisation en Gaule et en Germanie sous le Haut Empire romain (1999), 381–423. The former is concerned
with Roman attempts to devise rituals by which to reify and articulate in gesture on-going anxieties about the
(increasing) internal heterogeneity of the Roman community; the latter studies the reception and practice of Roman
religion in communities of Roman citizens notionally autonomous at the level of public law — in what were, in
Roman terms, the borderlands of Roman religion.
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 175
Needless to say, a number of Anglophone scholars in particular, even those who concur
with Scheid in viewing Roman religion as orthoprax, part company with him in their
estimation of the place of interpretation in religiosity at Rome. To state the matter as
baldly as possible, these argue that far from having elaborated an understanding of Roman
religion on the basis of all the evidence (whatever that would mean) and then developing
a rule of evidence on the basis of that understanding, Scheid has brought to bear upon
Roman material a dogmatic view of orthopraxic religion. From this perspective, Scheid’s
rules of evidence effect an a priori exclusion from the history of religion of much of what
was very precisely religious in the (intellectual) life of Romans.10
Another way to think about the distinction drawn by Scheid between the religious and
extra-religious, and likewise about the conversation between him and his interlocutors,
would be to frame the problem in cognitive, epistemic or ontological terms. At what point
in the passage from acts and the rules governing them to reflection on the meaning of acts
do we pass from the fundamental knowledge — the technological savoir-faire — necessary
to the continuance of praxis to individual, metaphysical, and existential speculation so
removed from praxis as to be a gloss upon it? Is there such a point? Scheid obviously
answers the latter question in the affirmative. Indeed, he has done so for many years, com-
mencing perhaps with an essay also carrying the title ‘Quand faire, c’est croire’, written
with Marc Linder and published in 1993 (Archives de sciences sociales des religions 81,
47–62) and continuing with ‘Religion romaine et spiritualité’ (ARG 5 (2003), 198–209) and
‘Les sens des rites. L’exemple romain’ (EntrHardt 53 (2006), 39–71).
Despite this continuity, three notable changes across this period are: first, the
definitional framing of Roman religion in relation to concepts like foi, croyance, and more
recently spiritualité; second, a shift from the exclusion of metaphysical speculation
(‘renvoyé dans l’espace privé, le savoir des raisons ultimes des choses n’est ni essential ni
contraignant du point du vue religieux’: Archives de sciences sociales des religions 81
(1993), 4911) to the bracketing and containment of peculiarly ancient forms of religious
speculation such as aetiological myth (ARG 5 (2003), 207; EntrHardt 53 (2006), 54–60,
speaking of ‘explications et justifications situées à l’extérieur du rite’); and third, the
striving after a model and language that might describe the diffusion of agency and
responsibility in rites as well as the location of authority in knowledge-construction and
its transmission (see now especially, ARG 5 (2003), 207 and Quand faire, 275–9, describing
Roman religion variously as ‘collective’ and ‘institutionnelle’, and in particular ‘la règle’ of
rites as ‘une construction humaine appliquée au mystère des relations avec les immortals’,
‘a human construction applied to the mystery of relations with immortals’).
About these developments in Scheid’s work I offer two reflections only. First, they have
been provoked by scholarship on Roman religion written simultaneously with his own and
by readings performed by Scheid on further orthopraxic religions. Where Roman religion
is concerned, the interlocutor most often identified by Scheid is not unexpectedly Mary
Beard, whose remarkable article on the Parilia gets due recognition in these pages. I note
in passing that Beard, too, articulates her agenda in terms of rules of evidence: literary
10
To clarify, I might gesture at three prominent and quite distinct reactions to interpretive models (like Scheid’s)
that understand religion as embedded and consequently assign (great) heuristic value to inferences from statal ritual:
in addition to Mary Beard’s essay on the Parilia, consider J. North’s ‘The development of religious pluralism’, in
J. Lieu et al. (eds), The Jews among Pagans and Christians in the Roman Empire (1992), 174–93; and W. J. Tatum’s
‘Roman religion: fragments and further questions’, in S. N. Byrne and E. P. Cueva (eds), Veritatis Amicitiaeque
Causa. Essays in Honor of Anna Lydia Motto and John R. Clark (1999), 273–91. Beard, North and Tatum, each in
her or his own way, foreground the interpretive, affective and cognitive acts made by (or assumed to have been made
by) individuals, whether as viewers of (state) ritual or practitioners of domestic cult: more than that, for on varied
grounds each understands those acts as essential components of a phenomenology of Roman religion.
11
‘Restricted to the private sphere, knowledge of the ultimate reasons for things was neither essential to, nor
restrictive of, a religious outlook’.
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 177
12
Several of the above are collaborating in a DFG-funded Kolleg-Forschergruppe, ‘Religiöse Individualisierung in
historischer Perspektive’, housed from 2009–2012 at Max-Weber Kolleg, Universität Erfurt. Scheid is treating the
topic in his lectures of 2008–2009 at the Collège, ‘La religion, la cité, l’individu. La piété chez les Romains’. Bendlin’s
arguments must for the moment be accessed in ‘Looking beyond the civic compromise: religious pluralism in late
republican Rome’, in E. Bispham and C. Smith (eds), Religion in Archaic and Republican Rome and Italy (2000),
115–35; ‘Sünde’, Handbuch religionswissenschaftlicher Grundbegriffe 5 (2001), 123–34; and ‘Gemeinschaft,
Öffentlichkeit und Identität: Forschungsgeschichtliche Anmerkungen zu den Mustern sozialer Ordnung in Rom’, in
U. Egelhaaf-Gaiser and A. Schäfer (eds), Religiöse Vereine in der römischen Antike. Untersuchungen zu
Organisation, Ritual und Raumordnung (2002), 9–40.
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 178
13
An English translation by Philip Purchase of the first published version of this chapter may be found under the
title ‘Hierarchy and structure in Roman polytheism: Roman methods of conceiving action’, in C. Ando (ed.), Roman
Religion (2003), 164–89.
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 179
14
Scheid has provided a further statement of his position in this matter in ‘Le statut de la viande à Rome’, Food
& History 5 (2007), 19–28. Alas, he does not there respond to the detailed scrutiny his arguments receive in the same
volume from Nicole Belayche, ‘Religion et consommation de la viande dans le monde romain: des réalitées voilées’,
Food & History 5 (2007), 29–43. Belayche focuses on several problems: the lack of evidence for ritual slaughter in
the private sphere, which is part and parcel, she argues, of the silence of extant evidence regarding banal ritual
gestures of all kinds; the existence of meat derived from the hunt (and so not ritually slaughtered) in butcher shops;
and the religious status of meals at which meat ritually rendered profane was then consumed. See also Valérie Huet’s
essay in that issue, ‘Le sacrifice disparu: les reliefs de boucherie’, Food & History 5 (2007), 197–223, which points
out that images of butchering in commercial contexts focus on pigs and the carving of them, not on their ritual
slaughter, but argues that the iconography of butchery developed to advertise the skill of the butcher, not his piety.
15
‘There need be no ambiguity about the historical relationship between Cato’s prayers and those of the Arvales
or quindecemviri of the Empire: the public rites of the Empire did not “descend” from Cato’s. They participate in
the same religious culture and demonstrate precisely that there was no great difference between public rites on the
one hand and private or domestic rites, at least those of a great family, on the other.’
16
This is a difficulty of method in respect to evidence that I have attempted to describe more fully in a review of
E. Meyer, Legitimacy and Law in the Roman World. Tabulae in Roman Belief and Practice (2004): Classical Journal
100 (2005), 413–17.
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 180
17
This problem is treated at length in the introduction to C. Ando and J. Rüpke, Religion and Law, to which essay
these remarks are indebted.
Review Article 1:Rev Art 09/10/2009 14:55 Page 181
University of Chicago
clifford.ando@uchicago.edu