Montesquieu
Montesquieu
“Of all French political philosophers in the eighteenth century (other than
Rousseau) the most important was Montesquieu. Of them all he had perhaps the
clearest conception of the complexities of a social philosophy, and yet he too was
guilty of extreme over simplification.” (Sabine)
Montesquieu was born in 1689 at Chateau de la Bordeaux in a noble aristocratic family. His
father was an eminent French lawyer. At the age of twenty seven he became president of
Parliament of Bordeaux, the most important of parliaments in France except that of Paris.
For a long period of twelve years he continued as chief magistrate at Bordeaux, but he was
not satisfied with the job because he was an extensive reader of literature and history and
had deep sympathetic ties with the intellectual movements of his days. At last he left
presidency and moved to Paris. In 1728 he visited Austria, Hungary, Venice, Rome,
Switzerland, Holland and lastly England where he remained for above two years. During his
tour, he came across the leading politicians and political thinkers in England and he was
deeply impressed by the English conception of liberty and by the English system of
Government.
After his return he settled at La Brede and kept himself busy with the task of writing of
political philosophy. At that time France although under absolute control of King Louis XIV,
yet was more fertile for growth of political theory but Frenchmen were not satisfied with the
political situation, as were their fellows across the channel.
1.The Persian Letter: He published these letters in 1721. it embodied a brilliant satire on
the existing political, religious and social institutions in France.
2.Reflections and the causes of the Greatness and Decline of the Romans. This book
was published in 1734.
3.The Spirit of Law published in 1748. This book won a great fame and immortality for
Montesquieu because it came out after fourteen year unremitting labor and he made it a
masterpiece for all ages.
Montesquieu expounds his theory of separation of powers to set forth the governmental
organization in order to safeguard the political liberty. He believed that the separation of
powers among the different organs of the government is the best safeguard against
tyranny. He pleads that each power must be exercised by a separate organ and a system of
checks and balances should thus be established for solidarity and harmony of the state.
The theory of separation of powers among Legislative, Executive and Judicial branches of
government was best realized in the British Constitution. He came to realize that for
maintaining liberty, the separation of powers was absolutely essential. Montesquieu did not
rely upon observation. Locke and Harrington had taught him what to expect and for the rest
he adopted the myth which was current among the English
themselves. Bolingbroke said, “It is by this mixture of monarchial, aristocratically
and democratically power blended together in one system and by these three
estates balancing one another, that our free constitution of Government has been
preserved so long inviolate.”
1.By virtue of the legislative power, the prince or magistrate exerts temporary or
permanent laws and amends or abrogates those laws, which are contrary to the will of the
subject.
2.By virtue of the executive powers, he makes peace or war, sends or receives
Ambassadors, establish the public security and provide protection against invasions.
3.By virtue of the judiciary powers, he is vested with the powers to punish criminals and
also to safeguard the life and property of the individuals.
When the executive and legislative are united in the same person, there can be no liberty
because apprehensions may arise. If the judiciary power be not separated from the
legislative and the executive then again there will be no liberty. When it is combined with
the legislative, the existence and liberty of people would be exposed to arbitrary rule. When
it is combined with executive organ, then there will be violence and oppression in the
capacity of a mortal God.
It is quite obvious from all above cited discussion, that the separation of powers among the
three organs of governments fully ensures liberty and freedom, by imposing healthy checks
on the despotism of the government bureaucrats. Montesquieu was of the view that liberty
is an indispensable fundamental for human progress and glory. Everyone is born to enjoy it
without any distinction of color, creed and religion.
Criticism:
1.Montesquieu’s study of English constitution is not very correct until this day; there is no
full separation of powers between different governmental agencies. There the House of
Lords is a legislative as well as a judicial body. The Lord Chancellor partakes of all the three
functions of government.
2.If all the branches are made separate and independent of each other, each branch will
endeavor to safeguard its interests and possibly may jeopardize other’s interest.
4.Mill was of the view “the separation of powers will result in a clash between the
three different organs of the government because each one will take interest only
in its own powers.”
The classification of government of Montesquieu is base partly on the number of those who
hold political power and partly on the manner in which that power is exercised. He gives
more importance to the principle on which government is based than to its nature. He
assigned a particular basic principle to every form of government. The principle of
democracy was virtue, of an aristocracy virtue-cum-moderation, of monarchy honor while
that of despotism was fear. He enunciated the dangers attending each form of government
if it lost its basic principle.
1)Republic:
Montesquieu was of the view “A republican government is that in which the body or only a
part of the people, is possessed of the supreme power.” To him, when in a republic, the
body of the people is possessed of the supreme power it is called democracy. Sovereignty
rests with the people in democracy. In Republics, there can be no exercise of sovereignty
but by the votes of the people and these votes express their own will.
2)Monarchies:
Montesquieu remarks that monarchial government is that in which a single person governs
the state by fixed and established laws. He was of the view that the most intermediate
power is that of nobility. This in some measure seems to be essential to a monarchy, whose
fundamental maxim is no nobility no monarch, but there may be despotic process.
3)Despotism:
A despotic government is that in which a single person directs all functions of the
government with his own capricious will, without any law and without fixed rules. His own
words become laws of the land and complete subordination to these laws a expedient.
Montesquieu was of the view that certain religions had a definite affinity for certain types of
governments. Islam goes well with Democratic Republican form of government, wherein
fundamentals of religion i-e., equality, fraternity and freedom are deeply inculcated and
practiced for the security of mankind and glory of the state. Roman Catholicism is closely
affiliated with monarchial form of government with arbitrary rule and Protestantism even in
this modern age is deeply attached with despotism and cruel expansionism.
Republican form of government is possible only in a state of small size; monarchy suited the
moderate-sized state while a big country or an empire must have despotic government.
Real democracy is possible only ion small city-state. France of Montesquieu’s time was too
large for a republic form of government, Monarchy would suit her best. Montesquieu
declared monarchy, a worst form of government and he unlike Machiavelli discarded the
doctrine of aggrandizement and expansion.
Criticism:
1.It is quite wrong to assume, as Montesquieu does, that democracy and aristocracy are
sub-types of republican form.
2.It is a quite unfair to place despotic government at par with monarchial and republican
forms. Despotic state is not at all state because it is established by the absence of
established law, and hence it is a lawless state, which should not be included in the plan at
all.
3.Montesquieu’s scheme creates distinction between the republican and monarchic form
based upon the number of persons who possess the supreme power, the distinction
between the monarchic and despotic types depends upon the way in which the power of
governments are to be exercised.
1.Montesquieu follows the inductive and historical methods of Aristotle and like him, takes
keen interest in the practical political activities.
2.Like Aristotle, Montesquieu too pays his attention on the influence of physical
environment on the life of man and social institutions.
3.Montesquieu steps into the shoes of Aristotle, when he recognizes basic types of
government i-e, republican, monarchial and despotic.
4.Montesquieu closely follows Aristotle when he says that the fundamental types of political
constitutions are fixed once and for all but they are different to some extent under the
impact of the local conditions.
5.Montesquieu’s observation that the law of a society gives to its unique and particular
character, has its parallel in Aristotle’s statement that the constitution of a state determines
the very life and character of its people, if there occurs a change in the constitution, the
state itself becomes altogether a different state.
The classification of government of Montesquieu is base partly on the number of those who
hold political power and partly on the manner in which that power is exercised. He gives
more importance to the principle on which government is based than to its nature. He
assigned a particular basic principle to every form of government. The principle of
democracy was virtue, of an aristocracy virtue-cum-moderation, of monarchy honor while
that of despotism was fear. He enunciated the dangers attending each form of government
if it lost its basic principle.
1)Republic:
Montesquieu was of the view “A republican government is that in which the body or only a
part of the people, is possessed of the supreme power.” To him, when in a republic, the
body of the people is possessed of the supreme power it is called democracy. Sovereignty
rests with the people in democracy. In Republics, there can be no exercise of sovereignty
but by the votes of the people and these votes express their own will.
2)Monarchies:
Montesquieu remarks that monarchial government is that in which a single person governs
the state by fixed and established laws. He was of the view that the most intermediate
power is that of nobility. This in some measure seems to be essential to a monarchy, whose
fundamental maxim is no nobility no monarch, but there may be despotic process.
3)Despotism:
A despotic government is that in which a single person directs all functions of the
government with his own capricious will, without any law and without fixed rules. His own
words become laws of the land and complete subordination to these laws a expedient.
Montesquieu was of the view that certain religions had a definite affinity for certain types of
governments. Islam goes well with Democratic Republican form of government, wherein
fundamentals of religion i-e., equality, fraternity and freedom are deeply inculcated and
practiced for the security of mankind and glory of the state. Roman Catholicism is closely
affiliated with monarchial form of government with arbitrary rule and Protestantism even in
this modern age is deeply attached with despotism and cruel expansionism.
Republican form of government is possible only in a state of small size; monarchy suited
the moderate-sized state while a big country or an empire must have despotic government.
Real democracy is possible only ion small city-state. France of Montesquieu’s time was too
large for a republic form of government, Monarchy would suit her best. Montesquieu
declared monarchy, a worst form of government and he unlike Machiavelli discarded the
doctrine of aggrandizement and expansion.
Criticism:
1.It is quite wrong to assume, as Montesquieu does, that democracy and aristocracy are
sub-types of republican form.
2.It is a quite unfair to place despotic government at par with monarchial and republican
forms. Despotic state is not at all state because it is established by the absence of
established law, and hence it is a lawless state, which should not be included in the plan at
all.
3.Montesquieu’s scheme creates distinction between the republican and monarchic form
based upon the number of persons who possess the supreme power, the distinction
between the monarchic and despotic types depends upon the way in which the power of
governments are to be exercised.
1.Montesquieu follows the inductive and historical methods of Aristotle and like him, takes
keen interest in the practical political activities.
2.Like Aristotle, Montesquieu too pays his attention on the influence of physical
environment on the life of man and social institutions.
3.Montesquieu steps into the shoes of Aristotle, when he recognizes basic types of
government i-e, republican, monarchial and despotic.
4.Montesquieu closely follows Aristotle when he says that the fundamental types of political
constitutions are fixed once and for all but they are different to some extent under the
impact of the local conditions.
5.Montesquieu’s observation that the law of a society gives to its unique and particular
character, has its parallel in Aristotle’s statement that the constitution of a state determines
the very life and character of its people, if there occurs a change in the constitution, the
state itself becomes altogether a different state.
Baron de Montesquieu, Charles-Louis
de Secondat
First published Fri Jul 18, 2003; substantive revision Wed Apr 2, 2014
Montesquieu was one of the great political philosophers of the Enlightenment. Insatiably
curious and mordantly funny, he constructed a naturalistic account of the various forms of
government, and of the causes that made them what they were and that advanced or
constrained their development. He used this account to explain how governments might be
preserved from corruption. He saw despotism, in particular, as a standing danger for any
government not already despotic, and argued that it could best be prevented by a system in
which different bodies exercised legislative, executive, and judicial power, and in which all
those bodies were bound by the rule of law. This theory of the separation of powers had an
enormous impact on liberal political theory, and on the framers of the constitution of the
United States of America.
1. Life
2. Major Works
3. The Persian Letters
4. The Spirit of the Laws
o 4.1 Forms of Government
o 4.2 Liberty
o 4.3 Climate and Geography
o 4.4 Commerce
o 4.5 Religion
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
1. Life
Charles-Louis de Secondat, Baron de La Brède et de Montesquieu, was born on January
19th, 1689 at La Brède, near Bordeaux, to a noble and prosperous family. He was educated at
the Oratorian Collège de Juilly, received a law degree from the University of Bordeaux in
1708, and went to Paris to continue his legal studies. On the death of his father in 1713 he
returned to La Brède to manage the estates he inherited, and in 1715 he married Jeanne de
Lartigue, a practicing Protestant, with whom he had a son and two daughters. In 1716 he
inherited from his uncle the title Baron de La Brède et de Montesquieu and the office of
Président à Mortier in the Parlement of Bordeaux, which was at the time chiefly a judicial
and administrative body. For the next eleven years he presided over the Tournelle, the
Parlement's criminal division, in which capacity he heard legal proceedings, supervised
prisons, and administered various punishments including torture. During this time he was
also active in the Academy of Bordeaux, where he kept abreast of scientific developments,
and gave papers on topics ranging from the causes of echoes to the motives that should lead
us to pursue the sciences.
In 1721 Montesquieu published the Persian Letters, which was an instant success and made
Montesquieu a literary celebrity. (He published the Persian Letters anonymously, but his
authorship was an open secret.) He began to spend more time in Paris, where he frequented
salons and acted on behalf of the Parlement and the Academy of Bordeaux. During this
period he wrote several minor works: Dialogue de Sylla et d'Eucrate (1724), Réflexions sur
la Monarchie Universelle (1724), and Le Temple de Gnide (1725). In 1725 he sold his life
interest in his office and resigned from the Parlement. In 1728 he was elected to the
Académie Française, despite some religious opposition, and shortly thereafter left France to
travel abroad. After visiting Italy, Germany, Austria, and other countries, he went to
England, where he lived for two years. He was greatly impressed with the English political
system, and drew on his observations of it in his later work.
On his return to France in 1731, troubled by failing eyesight, Montesquieu returned to La
Brède and began work on his masterpiece, The Spirit of the Laws. During this time he also
wrote Considerations on the Causes of the Greatness of the Romans and of their Decline,
which he published anonymously in 1734. In this book he tried to work out the application of
his views to the particular case of Rome, and in so doing to discourage the use of Rome as a
model for contemporary governments. Parts of Considerations were incorporated into The
Spirit of the Laws, which he published in 1748. Like the Persian Letters, The Spirit of the
Laws was both controversial and immensely successful. Two years later he published
a Defense of the Spirit of the Laws to answer his various critics. Despite this effort, the
Roman Catholic Church placed The Spirit of the Laws on the Index of Forbidden Books in
1751. In 1755, Montesquieu died of a fever in Paris, leaving behind an unfinished essay on
taste for the Encyclopédie of Diderot and D'Alembert.
2. Major Works
Montesquieu's two most important works are the Persian Letters and The Spirit of the Laws.
While these works share certain themes -- most notably a fascination with non-European
societies and a horror of despotism -- they are quite different from one another, and will be
treated separately.
4.2 Liberty
Montesquieu is among the greatest philosophers of liberalism, but his is what Shklar has
called "a liberalism of fear" (Shklar, Montesquieu, p. 89). According to Montesquieu,
political liberty is "a tranquillity of mind arising from the opinion each person has of his
safety" (SL 11.6). Liberty is not the freedom to do whatever we want: if we have the freedom
to harm others, for instance, others will also have the freedom to harm us, and we will have
no confidence in our own safety. Liberty involves living under laws that protect us from
harm while leaving us free to do as much as possible, and that enable us to feel the greatest
possible confidence that if we obey those laws, the power of the state will not be directed
against us.
If it is to provide its citizens with the greatest possible liberty, a government must have
certain features. First, since "constant experience shows us that every man invested with
power is apt to abuse it ... it is necessary from the very nature of things that power should be
a check to power" (SL 11.4). This is achieved through the separation of the executive,
legislative, and judicial powers of government. If different persons or bodies exercise these
powers, then each can check the others if they try to abuse their powers. But if one person or
body holds several or all of these powers, then nothing prevents that person or body from
acting tyrannically; and the people will have no confidence in their own security.
Certain arrangements make it easier for the three powers to check one another. Montesquieu
argues that the legislative power alone should have the power to tax, since it can then deprive
the executive of funding if the latter attempts to impose its will arbitrarily. Likewise, the
executive power should have the right to veto acts of the legislature, and the legislature
should be composed of two houses, each of which can prevent acts of the other from
becoming law. The judiciary should be independent of both the legislature and the executive,
and should restrict itself to applying the laws to particular cases in a fixed and consistent
manner, so that "the judicial power, so terrible to mankind, … becomes, as it were,
invisible", and people "fear the office, but not the magistrate" (SL 11.6).
Liberty also requires that the laws concern only threats to public order and security, since
such laws will protect us from harm while leaving us free to do as many other things as
possible. Thus, for instance, the laws should not concern offenses against God, since He does
not require their protection. They should not prohibit what they do not need to prohibit: "all
punishment which is not derived from necessity is tyrannical. The law is not a mere act of
power; things in their own nature indifferent are not within its province" (SL 19.14). The
laws should be constructed to make it as easy as possible for citizens to protect themselves
from punishment by not committing crimes. They should not be vague, since if they were,
we might never be sure whether or not some particular action was a crime. Nor should they
prohibit things we might do inadvertently, like bumping into a statue of the emperor, or
involuntarily, like doubting the wisdom of one of his decrees; if such actions were crimes, no
amount of effort to abide by the laws of our country would justify confidence that we would
succeed, and therefore we could never feel safe from criminal prosecution. Finally, the laws
should make it as easy as possible for an innocent person to prove his or her innocence. They
should concern outward conduct, not (for instance) our thoughts and dreams, since while we
can try to prove that we did not perform some action, we cannot prove that we never had
some thought. The laws should not criminalize conduct that is inherently hard to prove, like
witchcraft; and lawmakers should be cautious when dealing with crimes like sodomy, which
are typically not carried out in the presence of several witnesses, lest they "open a very wide
door to calumny" (SL 12.6).
Montesquieu's emphasis on the connection between liberty and the details of the criminal law
were unusual among his contemporaries, and inspired such later legal reformers as Cesare
Beccaria.
4.4 Commerce
Of all the ways in which a country might seek to enrich itself, Montesquieu believes,
commerce is the only one without overwhelming drawbacks. Conquering and plundering
one's neighbors can provide temporary infusions of money, but over time the costs of
maintaining an occupying army and administering subjugated peoples impose strains that
few countries can endure. Extracting precious metals from colonial mines leads to general
inflation; thus the costs of extraction increase while the value of the extracted metals
decreases. The increased availability of money furthers the development of commerce in
other countries; however, in the country which extracts gold and silver, domestic industry is
destroyed.
Commerce, by contrast, has no such disadvantages. It does not require vast armies, or the
continued subjugation of other peoples. It does not undermine itself, as the extraction of gold
from colonial mines does, and it rewards domestic industry. It therefore sustains itself, and
nations which engage in it, over time. While it does not produce all the virtues -- hospitality,
Montesquieu thinks, is more often found among the poor than among commercial peoples --
it does produce some: "the spirit of commerce is naturally attended with that of frugality,
economy, moderation, labor, prudence, tranquility, order, and rule" (SL 5.6). In addition, it
"is a cure for the most destructive prejudices" (SL 20.1), improves manners, and leads to
peace among nations.
In monarchies, Montesquieu believes, the aim of commerce is, for the most part, to supply
luxuries. In republics, it is to bring from one country what is wanted in another, "gaining
little" but "gaining incessantly" (SL 20.4). In despotisms, there is very little commerce of any
kind, since there is no security of property. In a monarchy, neither kings nor nobles should
engage in commerce, since this would risk concentrating too much power in their hands. By
the same token, there should be no banks in a monarchy, since a treasure "no sooner becomes
great than it becomes the treasure of the prince" (SL 20.10). In republics, by contrast, banks
are extremely useful, and anyone should be allowed to engage in trade. Restrictions on which
profession a person can follow destroy people's hopes of bettering their situation; they are
therefore appropriate only to despotic states.
While some mercantilists had argued that commerce is a zero-sum game in which when
some gain, others necessarily lose, Montesquieu believes that commerce benefits all
countries except those who have nothing but their land and what it produces. In those deeply
impoverished countries, commerce with other countries will encourage those who own the
land to oppress those who work it, rather than encouraging the development of domestic
industries and manufacture. However, all other countries benefit by commerce, and should
seek to trade with as many other nations as possible, "for it is competition which sets a just
value on merchandise, and establishes the relation between them" (SL 20.9).
Montesquieu describes commerce as an activity that cannot be confined or controlled by any
individual government or monarch. This, in his view, has always been true: "Commerce is
sometimes destroyed by conquerors, sometimes cramped by monarchs; it traverses the earth,
flies from the places where it is oppressed, and stays where it has liberty to breathe" (SL
21.5). However, the independence of commerce was greatly enhanced when, during the
medieval period, Jews responded to persecution and the seizure of their property by
inventing letters of exchange. "Commerce, by this method, became capable of eluding
violence, and of maintaining everywhere its ground; the richest merchant having none but
invisible effects, which he could convey imperceptibly wherever he pleased" (SL 21.20).
This set in motion developments which made commerce still more independent of monarchs
and their whims.
First, it facilitated the development of international markets, which place prices outside the
control of governments. Money, according to Montesquieu, is "a sign which represents the
value of all merchandise" (SL 22.2). The price of merchandise depends on the quantity of
money and the quantity of merchandise, and on the amounts of money and merchandise that
are in trade. Monarchs can affect this price by imposing tariffs or duties on certain goods.
But since they cannot control the amounts of money and merchandise that are in trade within
their own countries, let alone internationally, a monarch "can no more fix the price of
merchandise than he can establish by a decree that the relation 1 has to 10 is equal to that of
1 to 20" (SL 22.7). If a monarch attempts to do so, he courts disaster: "Julian's lowering the
price of provisions at Antioch was the cause of a most terrible famine" (SL 22.7).
Second, it permitted the development of international currency exchanges, which place the
exchange rate of a country's currency largely outside the control of that country's
government. A monarch can establish a currency, and stipulate how much of some metal
each unit of that currency shall contain. However, monarchs cannot control the rates of
exchange between their currencies and those of other countries. These rates depend on the
relative scarcity of money in the countries in question, and they are "fixed by the general
opinion of the merchants, never by the decrees of the prince" (SL 22.10). For this reason "the
exchange of all places constantly tends to a certain proportion, and that in the very nature of
things" (SL 22.10).
Finally, the development of international commerce gives governments a great incentive to
adopt policies that favor, or at least do not impede, its development. Governments need to
maintain confidence in their creditworthiness if they wish to borrow money; this deters them
from at least the more extreme forms of fiscal irresponsibility, and from oppressing too
greatly those citizens from whom they might later need to borrow money. Since the
development of commerce requires the availability of loans, governments must establish
interest rates high enough to encourage lending, but not so high as to make borrowing
unprofitable. Taxes must not be so high that they deprive citizens of the hope of bettering
their situations (SL 13.2), and the laws should allow those citizens enough freedom to carry
out commercial affairs.
In general, Montesquieu believes that commerce has had an extremely beneficial influence
on government. Since commerce began to recover after the development of letters of
exchange and the reintroduction of lending at interest, he writes:
it became necessary that princes should govern with more prudence than they themselves
could ever have imagined; for great exertions of authority were, in the event, found to be
impolitic ... We begin to be cured of Machiavelism, and recover from it every day. More
moderation has become necessary in the councils of princes. What would formerly have been
called a master-stroke in politics would be now, independent of the horror it might occasion,
the greatest imprudence. Happy is it for men that they are in a situation in which, though
their passions prompt them to be wicked, it is, nevertheless, to their interest to be humane
and virtuous. (SL 21.20)
4.5 Religion
Religion plays only a minor part in the Spirit of the Laws. God is described in Book 1 as
creating nature and its laws; having done so, He vanishes, and plays no further explanatory
role. In particular, Montesquieu does not explain the laws of any country by appeal to divine
enlightenment, providence, or guidance. In the Spirit of the Laws, Montesquieu considers
religions "in relation only to the good they produce in civil society" (SL 24.1), and not to
their truth or falsity. He regards different religions as appropriate to different environments
and forms of government. Protestantism is most suitable to republics, Catholicism to
monarchies, and Islam to despotisms; the Islamic prohibition on eating pork is appropriate to
Arabia, where hogs are scarce and contribute to disease, while in India, where cattle are
badly needed but do not thrive, a prohibition on eating beef is suitable. Thus, "when
Montezuma with so much obstinacy insisted that the religion of the Spaniards was good for
their country, and his for Mexico, he did not assert an absurdity" (SL 24.24).
Religion can help to ameliorate the effects of bad laws and institutions; it is the only thing
capable of serving as a check on despotic power. However, on Montesquieu's view it is
generally a mistake to base civil laws on religious principles. Religion aims at the perfection
of the individual; civil laws aim at the welfare of society. Given these different aims, what
these two sets of laws should require will often differ; for this reason religion "ought not
always to serve as a first principle to the civil laws" (SL 26.9). The civil laws are not an
appropriate tool for enforcing religious norms of conduct: God has His own laws, and He is
quite capable of enforcing them without our assistance. When we attempt to enforce God's
laws for Him, or to cast ourselves as His protectors, we make our religion an instrument of
fanaticism and oppression; this is a service neither to God nor to our country.
If several religions have gained adherents in a country, those religions should all be tolerated,
not only by the state but by its citizens. The laws should "require from the several religions,
not only that they shall not embroil the state, but that they shall not raise disturbances among
themselves" (SL 25.9). While one can try to persuade people to change religions by offering
them positive inducements to do so, attempts to force others to convert are ineffective and
inhumane. In an unusually scathing passage, Montesquieu also argues that they are unworthy
of Christianity, and writes: "if anyone in times to come shall dare to assert, that in the age in
which we live, the people of Europe were civilized, you (the Inquisition) will be cited to
prove that they were barbarians; and the idea they will have of you will be such as will
dishonor your age, and spread hatred over all your contemporaries" (SL 25.13).