Defence Mechanisms Siegal1969
Defence Mechanisms Siegal1969
: RICHARD
S. SIEGAL,PH.D.
MECHANISMS?
Richard S. Siegal died on April 3. 1967 at the age of thirty-nine. This paper
was perhaps a draft short of what he might have wished. It was developed from
an earlier collaboration with Dr. Gerald Ehrenreich whose contributions Dr. Siegal
would have gratefully acknowledged in print as he did informally.
From the work of the Psychotherapy Research Project of T h e Menninger
Foundation. This investigation is currently supported by Public Health Service
Research Grant MH 8308 from the National Institute of Mental Health, and was
previously supported by the Foundations’ Fund for Research in Psychiatry and the
Ford Foundation.
785
Downloaded from apa.sagepub.com at OAKLAND UNIV on June 14, 2015
586 RICHARD S. SIEGAL
it prevented the patient from saying freely what came to her mind,
including the ideas connected with the positive feelings, ideas
which would be available were it not for the presence of this
anger, this behavior can be considered a form of resistance. Inso-
far as it prevented her from experiencing and/or expressing the
waded-off ideas and feelings it can be considered defensive.
Which defense mechanisms, however, are here being invoked?
Clearly, such a bit of behavior has other. meanings in the
analytic situation. One could infer, for example, a “testing” of
the relationship involved here and probably many other determin-
ing factors. T h e technical use made of the analyst’s recognition of
the defensive function of this feeling of anger will obviously de-
pend on the whole analytic context. It is quite likely he will feel
no need to attempt to infer the particular defense mechanisms
involved in this clinical incident, and certainly he will think
little about the actual processes involved except perhaps to note
and keep in mind that this woman defends herself against unac-
ceptable or threatening love feelings by experiencing the reverse
thoughts or feelings.
In the early days of psychoanalytic writing, some writers felt
satisfied if they could understand the unconscious dynamic mean-
ing of a thought, a bit of.behavior, or a slip of the tongue. Simi-
larly, with the popularization and spread, outside of psycho-
analysis, of defense mechanism concepts, some of us now permit
ourselves to bask in the glow of achievement secured from spotting
a possible defensive purpose of some bit of mental life. Because
it seems clinically adequate, we are satisfied to proceed on the
basis of a somewhat vague conception of defense mechanisms as
simply the defensive use of specific mental contents.
We could understand such a bit of behavior as reported above
as necessitating that we infer the functioning of several underly-
ing defense mechanisms, principally denial and reversal. One
reconstruction of what occurred intrapsychically might go some-
thing like this: the patient experienced thoughts and feelings of
a positive nature toward the analyst. For example, “I felt under-
stood and accepted in the last hour; in fact, I felt loved and I
loved you in return.” These thoughts and feelings may have
been associated with an inner threat, perhaps, for example, feel-
or not one owns the same old knife after he gets a new handle
for it and then replaces the old blade. T h e adult’s ego within
which and with which defending occurs is quite different from
his ego when he was an infant. Thus, the process of defending
must also, of necessity, be different (granting, of course, some
degree of similarity between infantile and adult egos and de-
fensive processes). T h e content defended with, and against which
defenses are arrayed, is also different. JVhat then remains un-
changed enough to make it reasonable to postulate the “precur-
sory” relationship? Clearly, since what is defended against, what
does the defending, and thus how it is done, are considerably
(though not completely) changed, it must be the outcome or
purpose, the state aimed at (whether it be unawareness, inability
to act, or a neutral affect state) which is least changed. T h e “old
knife” with new blade and new handle is “old” only in some
conceptual sense-that is, it belongs to the same organism and
fills the same purpose. Thus a precursor to a defense mechanism
implies a conceptual similarity in purpose between two con-
structs rather than concrete similarities in processes or contents.
T h e genetic point of view cannot be sufficient by itself to
help us understand and adequately conceptualize the phenomena
of adult defensive functioning since this approach too encounters
the empirical problem that it is rarely clear which processes com-
prise given defense mechanisms. Nor is there reason to assume
that all processes used in the service of defense develop out of a
matrix of conflict. Defense mechanisms do not, of course, spring
into existence full blown. Following Hartmann (5), it is clear
that some ego functions develop within the conflict-free sphere
of the ego and may not thus be implicated in conflict or defense
at the time of their development. They may be enlisted only
later in the service of defense. IVe here touch upon the crucial
question of the relationship between defense and adaptation
which is in the forefront of a good deal of psychoanalytic think-
ing these days. IVhile it is of great interest to classify defense
mechanisms and defensive functioning along some continuum
of contribution to adaptation, a prior necessity is the conceptual
separation of processes of defense from defensive outcomes or
purposes.
Summary
T h e archaic tendency to take a concept as a thing or a substance
leads to confusion and unclarity in the theory of defense mecha-
nisms, and inhibits the fullest understanding and classification
of them. Defense mechanisms are constructs, man-made abstrac-
tions, which may be taken to refer either to mental contents,
purposes, outcomes, or to certain processes. I n this paper the
BIBLIOGRAPHY