OceanofPDF - Com Stakeholder Theory - Jacob Dahl Rendtorff
OceanofPDF - Com Stakeholder Theory - Jacob Dahl Rendtorff
Stakeholder Theory
A Model for Strategic Management
Maria Bonnafous-Boucher
Full Professor Paris Chamber of Commerce and Industry, Paris, France
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher,
whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the
rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation,
broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and
transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation,
computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or
hereafter developed.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice
and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date
of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a
warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein
or for any errors or omissions that may have been made.
Printed on acid-free paper
Maria Bonnafous-Boucher
Contents
1 From “The Stakeholder” to Stakeholder Theory
Definitions
Conclusion
Political Approaches
Conclusion
Conclusion
Conclusion
General Conclusion
Bibliography
Footnotes
1 The references between brackets refer to the bibliography at the end of the book.
© The Author(s) 2016
Maria Bonnafous-Boucher and Jacob Dahl Rendtorff, Stakeholder Theory, SpringerBriefs in Ethics,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-44356-0_1
Definitions
The term stakeholder (“partie prenante” in French) is used in different ways
by specialists and members of the public. For the wider public, it is a
generic term, equivalent to “citizen,” to anyone taking part in public life.
For specialists, it refers to people who are not shareholders. In fact, “partie
prenante” is an imperfect translation of the English stakeholder, literally the
“holder” of a “stake.” Less literally, stakeholder means he, or she, who has
a stake in something. More broadly, it means someone who participates or
“takes part” in something (“prendre partie,” hence “partie prenante”). In
English, the term stakeholder is a neologism which plays on the term
stockholder (designating those who share the profits, including the
shareholders). The term indicates that parties other than stockholders can
have a say and that their stakes and interests in the activities of the firm
should be recognized (Freeman and Reed 1983). It defines individuals and
groups of individuals indispensible to the survival of the firm and who are
either consulted or participate directly in decision-making processes or
arbitrage. But from which point of view is the question of survival to be
considered: from that of the firm or that of the stakeholder? It is for this
reason that some Francophone authors prefer the term “partie intéressée”
(“interested party”) (Benseddik 2006) or “ayant droit” (“rights holder”)
(Mercier 2006). Perhaps not surprisingly, for the Swedish administrative
research school of the 1960s, represented by Rhenman and Stymne (1965),
the notion of the stakeholder is seen as reciprocal relationship in which a
stakeholder is a group which depends on the firm in order to achieve its
own objectives and on which the firm depends for its survival.
Officially, the term “stakeholder” was first used in public at a
conference held at the Stanford Research Institute in 1963 to refer to “all
groups on which an organization is dependent for its survival.” But it was
only 20 years later that the term “stakeholder” was popularized by Freeman
(1984) who, at that time, used it to mean: “an individual or group of
individuals which can affect or be affected by the achievement of
organizational objectives.” Only those who cannot affect (due to an
incapacity to do so) and those who are not affected by the actions of an
organization (due to the absence of any form of relationship) are excluded
from this definition. It should also be noted that a stakeholder can be
affected by the corporation without being able to affect it in turn (and vice-
versa). Potentially, and alternatively, it can contribute to or threaten the
organization.
In the final analysis, while the term “stakeholder” is closely associated
with the private sector and the corporate world, it is also revealing in terms
of the relationship between the business world and public life: it illustrates
the difficulty of dissociating various interests, since the environment within
which corporations act is not only economic and legal, but also social,
political, cultural and ecological. In fact, the term “stakeholder” has crossed
the borders of corporate governance and is now frequently used by political
analysts, as evidenced by the White Book on European governance
(Candela 2006), and by numerous political scientists (Ackerman and
Fischkin 2004). Nevertheless, the decision-making processes of national
public organizations (states, public authorities), regional public
organizations (the European Union), and para-public organizations
(associations, international NGOs) has little to do with the corporate
governance model.
Consequently, it is difficult to determine a priori who is a stakeholder
and who or what is not. It depends on a concrete analysis of the precise
situation in which an organization or, more specifically, a corporation, finds
itself. Whether in public debates or in debates on corporate management,
the notion of the stakeholder is generally associated with that of the actor
concerned with a decision or a project. It seems to complement the notions
of the historical social actor (Bourdieu), the strategic actor (Crozier), the
identity-creating actor (Sainsaulieu), the group actor (Kaes, Anzieu), and
the impulse actor (Enriquez), a family of concepts traversing many of the
social sciences. Stakeholders are constantly implicated in collective, public
action in terms of both analysis and practice. It is as if, in order to govern,
or quite simply to win agreement to a reform, it is sufficient to be aware of
the interests and influence of various groups. Thus, in a neo-liberal context,
integrating stakeholders into an action framework takes the form of a
pertinent, actionable theory (Audier 2012) in which everything is negotiable
in a context in which decisions are made in function of events and their
impacts (Bonnafous-Boucher 2004). But who or what is a stakeholder and
who isn’t? If everything, either in an absolute or relative manner, is a
stakeholder, is the fact of acting tantamount merely to establishing degrees
of engagement or disengagement? In many regards, stakeholder theory
bears witness to a desire for change in approaches to governance, decision-
making, acting, feeling or wanting to be part of a project. It reflects a shared
aspiration to participate; it highlights the questionable nature of the
distinction between those who have rights and those who do not. It takes
into account the blind spot constituted by those who do not express an
opinion. That is why, although it undeniably derives from management
studies, it can also be regarded as a theory critical of neo-liberalism.
In a well known article, Mitchell et al. (1997) attempted to put an end to
the debate on the identity of stakeholders once and for all. The authors
suggested that the problematic should be reduced to the following question:
who really counts for the firm? Clearly, the authors consider stakeholder
theory exclusively from the point of view of usefulness to the corporation
(Table 1.1).
Table 1.1 What is a “stakeholder”? A chronology
Source Stake
Stanford “those groups without whose support the organization would cease to exist” (cited in
memo Freeman and Reed 1983; Freeman 1984)
(1963)
Rhenman “are depending on the firm in order to achieve their personal goals and on whom the
(1964) firm is depending for its existence”
Source Stake
Ahlstedt “driven by their own interests and goals are participants in a firm, and thus depending
and on it and whom for its sake the firm is depending” (cited in Näsi 1995)
Jahnukainen
(1971)
Freeman Wide: “can affect the achievement of an organization’s objectives or who is affected
and Reed by the achievement of an organization’s objectives”
(1983: 91) Narrow: “on which the organization is dependent for its continued survival”
Freeman “can affect or is affected by the achievement of the organization’s objectives”
(1984: 46)
Freeman “can affect or is affected by a business”
and Gilbert
(1987: 397)
Cornell and “claimants” who have “contacts”
Shapiro
(1987: 5)
Evan and “have a stake in or claim on the firm”
Freeman
(1988: 75–
76)
Evan and “benefit or are harmed by, and whose rights are violated or respected by, corporate
Freeman actions”
(1988: 79)
Bowie “without whose support the organization would cease to exist”
(1988a, b:
112, Note
2)
Alkhafaji “groups to whom the corporation is responsible”
(1989: 36)
Carroll “asserts to have one or more of these kinds of stakes” – “ranging from an interest to a
(1989: 57) right (legal or moral) to ownership or legal title to the company’s assets or property”
Evan and contract holders
Freeman
(1990)
Thomson et In “relationship with an organization”
al. (1991:
209)
Savage et “have an interest in the actions of an organization and … the ability to influence it”
al. (1991:
61)
Hill and “constituents who have a legitimate claim on the firm … established through the
Jones existence of an exchange relationship” who supply “the firm with critical resources
(1992: 133) (contributions) and in exchange each expects its interests to be satisfied (by
inducements)”
Source Stake
Brenner “having some legitimate, non-trivial relationship with an organization (such as)
(1993: 205) exchange transactions, action impacts, and moral responsibilities”
Carroll “asserts to have one or more of these kinds of stakes in the business” – may be
(1993: 60) affected or affect …
Freeman participants in “the human process of value creation”
(1994: 415)
Wicks et al. “interact with and give meaning and definition to the corporation”
(1994: 483)
Langtry “the firm is significantly responsible for their well-being, or they hold a moral or legal
(1994: 433) claim on the firm”
Starik “can or are making their stakes known” – “are or might be influenced by, or are or
(1994: 90) potentially are influencers or some organization”
Clarkson “bear some form of risk as a result of having invested some form of capital, human or
(1995: 5) financial, something of value, in a firm” or “are placed at risk as a result of a firm’s
activities”
Clarkson “have, or claim, ownership, rights, or interests in a corporation and its activities”
(1995: 106)
Näsi (1995: “interact with the firm and thus make its operation possible”
19)
Brenner “do or which could impact or be impacted by the firm/organization”
(1995: 76,
Note 1)
Donaldson “persons or groups with legitimate interests in procedural and/or substantive aspects of
and Preston corporate activity”
(1995: 85)
Russell L. Ackoff (1974, 1994) seems to have been the first to have
genuinely recognized the conceptual potential of the notion of stakeholders.
He oriented his research toward a representation of the corporation and
developed an embryonic form of stakeholder theory by defining the
objectives of organizations. According to Ackoof, the corporation should
reconcile the contradictory interests of groups to which it is directly linked,
adjusting its objectives with a view to satisfying the needs of those groups
in an equitable manner. Although profit is one of its objectives, it is not the
only one. But, with the exception of Ackoff and a number of authors
working between the late 1960s and the mid-1980s, the theory received
little attention in the fields of management, strategy and ethics. Indeed,
when Freeman presented an article on stakeholder for publication, the
evaluators suggested that he should perhaps use the term “stockholder”
instead.
The most all-encompassing version of stakeholder theory is the one
outlined in 1984 (republished in 2010) by Freeman in Strategic
Management: A Stakeholder Approach. In his book, Freeman suggests that
the generally separate concepts of the organization and the corporation
should be linked to produce a strategic, political and moral conception
which includes negotiation and communication. For the author, the
corporation is a wheel whose spokes represent particular interests (Aggeri
2008; Cazal 2011). This observation is based on the dependence of firms on
third parties, these last expressing requests concerned with risks engendered
by economic activity. It is in this context that Freeman’s key concept (1984)
acquires its full meaning: “Simply put, a stakeholder is any group or
individual who can affect, or is affected by, the achievement of the
organization’s objectives.” According to the American professor,
stakeholders include any group or individual who can either help or analyze
a corporation by calling its strategy into question. By focusing on these
groups and their wellbeing, whether they are internal or external to the
corporation, it should be possible for an organization to establish its
strategies by ensuring that they are consonant with societal expectations.
Nevertheless, this approach requires a theoretical framework in order to
deal with various groups, which are not merely aggregations of particular
interests. Thus, theoretical research into the role of stakeholders would
provide a concrete analytical context making it possible to examine in a
relevant way the relationship between the corporation and its internal and
external environment. With this in mind, Freeman starts by drawing up a
map of the stakeholders in a specific firm. He then analyzes potential
negotiation processes based on specific themes concerning particular
groups of stakeholders. Negotiation is, in this context, based on dialogue,
with a view to guaranteeing free and voluntary collaboration (Freeman
1984: 74). Later, Freeman (1984: 83) demonstrated that stakeholder theory
could be used to define the fundamental visions and aims of a corporation.
Analyzing stakeholders is the same thing as analyzing the values and social
problems by which the corporation is confronted. From the author’s point of
view, this analysis is a part of the value of the corporation, enabling it to
measure not just its financial value but also its social and societal
performance (Fig. 1.1).
Fig. 1.1 Impact of the corporation on stakeholders/Impact of stakeholders on the corporation
(Source: R.E. Freeman, Strategic Management, Pitman Publishing Inc, Boston, 1984)
There are other, less operational and less relevant classifications than
Mitchell et al.’s (1997). These classifications are based on an initial
distinction between primary and secondary stakeholders. Some of them are
content to distinguish between internal and external stakeholders. While
this distinction is a practical one, it is also simplistic in that it does not take
the relational content of the theory into account. It also fails to take account
of the ubiquity of stakeholders (Martinet 1984) in the shape of actors within
the corporation and outside it. In effect, an employee can also be a
consumer of the products he or she manufactures. Thus, the relationship
between the stakeholders and the corporation takes on a particular
importance for Cornell and Shapiro (1987), Freeman and Evan (1990), and
Hill and Jones (1992). All of these authors talk of contracting parties. It
could also be added that the analysis of the relationship between
stakeholders (and not only between the corporation and its stakeholders)
establishes a non-dual explanatory framework which does not refer the
corporation back to a faceoff with all that is external to it. Thus, in its
diagnostic and management approaches, the corporation has to deal with
unusual alliances or with the divergent interests of individual stakeholders.
Two years before Mitchell, Agle and Wood published their typology,
Clarkson (1995) distinguished between stakeholders who take on risk by
investing human or financial capital, and those who do not take any risk.
For the author, stakeholders fall into two categories: voluntary and
involuntary. In this sense, a stakeholder is someone who has everything to
lose and who will thus make legitimate claims based on the risks he or she
has run. In this case, shareholders are clearly considered stakeholders, as
are entrepreneurs. Indeed, why not? But surely this veers away from the
stakeholder approach which, from the outset, has made a distinction
between stakeholders and shareholders and presented an alternative to the
orthodox vision of corporate governance.
Other, secondary, typologies focus on different categories of actors:
public actors (Tichy et al. 1997); archetypal actors (shareholders,
employees, clients, suppliers); recognized actors (banks, insurance
companies, enterprise networks, unions, public authorities, international
organizations, civic associations, NGOs); controversial actors (competitors,
the media, activists, the natural environment) (Lépineux 2005). Mention
could also be made of tertiary stakeholders, those which do not have the
capacity to speak for themselves, for example natural elements (oceans,
mountains, animals), and future generations (Starik 1994). Some authors
have also talked of silent or mute stakeholders represented by third parties
(NGOs) who plead on their behalf.
Typologies and classifications, particularly that of Mitchell et al., are
useful in that they furnish an actionable model which can be used to make
decisions and negotiate for and with stakeholders. But, let’s not be naive,
they can also be used against them. The theory can always be
instrumentalized. Regardless of their degree of sophistication, the limit of
such typologies is to be found in the way in which they represent society as
a series of actors of varying value (or threat) to the corporation (and
particularly to the very large corporation). One of the key factors in Agle et
al.’s typology is the hierarchization of categories of actors in function of the
interests of the firm. In this sense, although stakeholder theory makes it
possible to represent the actors, the typologies developed do not focus on
the interests and issues that they bring to the fore. From this point of view,
stakeholder theory can be criticized on the grounds that it offers only a
partial conception of civil society, which it considers as a series of self-
centered, interest-based struggles. In our opinion, an analysis of the
controversies and arguments on which the motivations of stakeholders are
based would make it possible to take into account issues originating beyond
specific groups of actors. In terms of typologies, it should also be noted that
exhaustive investigations of lists of actors are of only limited value, even if
probability calculus is used.
References
Ackerman, B., and A. Alstot. 1999. The stakeholder society. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Ackerman, B., and J.F. Fischkin. 2004. Deliberation day. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Ackoff, R. 1994. The democratic corporation: A radical prescription for recreating corporate
America and rediscovering success. New York: Oxford University Press.
Aggeri, F. 2008. Régénerer les cadres de la stratégie. Mise en dispositif et exploration de nouveaux
espaces d’action stratégiques. HDR thesis defended at the University of Paris, Dauphine.
Aglietta, M., and A. Reberioux. 2004. La gouvernance … autrement? Paris: Albin Michel.
Ahlsted, L., and I. Jahnukainen. 1971. Ytritysorganisaatio yhteisaiminnan
ohausjaerjaerjestelmaenae. Helsinki: Weilin and Goeoes.
Akrich, M. 1987. Comment décrire les objets techniques? Techniques et Culture 9: 49–67.
Barnard, D. 1938. The functions of the excecutive. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Barnett, A. 1997. Towards stakeholder democracy. In Stakeholder capitalism, ed. G. Kelly, D. Kelly,
and A. Gamble. London: MacMillan.
Benseddik, F. 2006. Démoraliser la responsabilité sociale. In Décider avec les parties prenantes.
Approches d’une nouvelle théorie de la société civile, eds. M. Bonnafous- Boucher and Y. Pesqueux,
91–105. Paris: La Découverte, Recherches.
Blair, J.P. 1995. Local economic development: Analysis and practice. Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Bonnafous-Boucher, M., and S. Porcher. 2010. Stakeholder theory and theory of civil society.
European Management Review 7: 205–216.
[CrossRef]
Bowie, N.E. 1988b. Fair markets. Journal of Business Ethics 7(1–2): 89–98.
[CrossRef]
Brenner, S.N. 1993. The stakeholder theory of the firm and organizational decision-making. Some
propositions and a model. In Proceedings of the fourth annual meeting of the international
association for business and society, eds. J. Pasquero and D. Collins, 205–210. San Diego.
Brenner, S.N. 1995. Stakeholder theory of the firm. Its consistency with current management
techniques. In Understanding stakeholder thinking, ed. J. Nasi, 75–96. Helskinki: LSR Julkaisut Oy.
Caby, J. 2003. Valeur partenariale ou actionnariale. In Encyclopédie des ressources humaines, ed. J.
Allouche and I. Huault. Paris: Economica.
Callon, M. 1986. Some elements of a sociology of translation: Domestication of the scallops and the
fishermen of St Brieuc Bay. In Power, action and belief: A new sociology of knowledge, ed. John
Law, 196–233. London: Routledge and Keegan Paul.
Candela, J. 2006. Vers une notion intégrée de bonne gouvernance. In Décider avec les parties
prenantes, eds. M. Bonnafous-Boucher and Y. Pesqueux. Paris: Editions La Découverte, Recherche
series.
Carroll, A.B. 1989. Business and society. Ethics and stakeholder management, 2nd ed. Cincinnat:
South-Western.
Carroll, A.B. 1993. Business and society. Ethics and stakeholder management, 3rd ed. Cincinnati:
South-Western.
Caroll, A.B., and A.K. Buchholtz. 2000. Business and society. Ethics and stakeholder management.
Cincinnati: South-Western College Publishing.
Caroll, A., and J. Näsi. 1997. Understanding the stakeholder. Themes from a Finnish conference.
Business Ethics 6(1): 45–51.
Cazal, D. 2011. RSE et Théorie des parties prenantes: les impasses du contrat, Revue de la
régulation, Dossier: RSE, régulation et diversité du capitalisme 9, 1er semestre 2011.
Charreaux, G., and P. Wirtz. 2006. Gouvernance des entreprises, Nouvelles Perspectives. Paris:
Economica.
Clarke, T. 1998. The stakeholder corporation. A business philosophy for the information age. Long
Range Planning 31(2): 182–184.
[CrossRef]
Clarkson, M.B.E. 1995. A stakeholder framework for analyzing and evaluating corporate social
performance. Academy of Management Review 20(1): 92–117.
Clarkson, M.B.E. (ed.). 1998. The corporation and its stakeholders. Classic and contemporary
readings. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Cornell, B., and A.C. Shapiro. 1987. Corporate stakeholders and corporate finance. Financial
Management 16(1): 5–14.
[CrossRef]
Dodd, E. 1932. For whom are corporate managers trustees? Harvard Law Review 45(7): 1145–1163.
[CrossRef]
Dondaldson, T., and L.E. Preston. 1995. The stakeholder theory of the corporation: Concepts,
evidence, and implications. Academy of Management Review 20(1): 65–91.
Evan, W.M., and R.E. Freeman. 1988. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian
capitalism. In Ethical theory and business, ed. T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie, 97–106. Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Evan, W.M., and R.E. Freeman. 1990. Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. Journal
of Behavioral Economics 19: 337–359.
[CrossRef]
Evan, W.M., and R.E. Freeman. 1993. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian
capitalism. In Ethical theory and business, ed. T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie. Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice Hall.
Freeman, R.E. 1981. Business ethics. In The state of the art, ed. R. Edward Freeman. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Freeman, R.E. 1984. Strategic management, a stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman Publishing.
Freeman, R.E. 1994. The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics
Quarterly 4(4): 409–422.
[CrossRef]
Freeman, R.E. 1999. Divergent stakeholder theory. Academy of Management Review 24(2): 233–236.
Freeman, R.E. 2010. Stakeholder theory. The state of the art. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
[CrossRef]
Freeman, R.E., and W. Evan. 1990. Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. Journal of
Behavioral Economics 19: 337–359.
[CrossRef]
Freeman, R.E., and D.R. Gilbert. 1987. Managing stakeholder relationships. In Business and society:
Dimensions of conflict and cooperation, ed. S.P. Sethi and C.M. Falbe, 397–423. Lexington:
Lexington Books.
Freeman, R.E., and R.A. Phillips. 2002. Stakeholder theory. A libertarian defense. Business Ethics
Quarterly 12(3): 331–349.
[CrossRef]
Freeman, R.E., and D. Reed. 1983. Stockholders and stakeholders: A new perspective on corporate
governance. In Corporate governance: A definitive exploration of the issues, ed. C. Huizinga. Los
Angeles: UCLA Extension Press.
Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, and A.C. Wicks. 2007. Managing for stakeholders: Survival,
reputation and success. The Business Roundtable Institute for Corporate Ethics Series in Ethics
andLead. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, A.C. Wicks, B.L. Parma, and S. De Colle. 2010. Stakeholder theory:
The state of the art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[CrossRef]
Freeman, R.E., and J. Mcvea. 2001. A stakeholder approach to strategic management. In The
Blackwell handbook of strategic management, ed. M.A. Hitt, R.E. Freeman, and J. Harrison, 189–
207. Oxford: Basil Blackwel.
Gibson, K. 2000. The moral basis of stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics 26(3): 245–257.
[CrossRef]
Gioia, D. 1999. Practicability, paradigms, and problems in stakeholder theorizing. Academy of
Management Review 24(2): 228–232.
Goodpaster, K. 1991. Business ethics and stakeholder analysis. Business Ethics Quarterly 1: 53–73.
Hendry, J. 2001a. Missing the target: Normative stakeholder theory and the corporate governance
debate. Business Ethics Quarterly 11(1): 159–176.
Hendry, J. 2001b. Economic contracts versus social relationships as a foundation for normative
stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics 10(3): 223–232.
Hill, C.W.L., and T.M. Jones. 1992. Stakeholder-agency theory. Journal of Management Studies
29(2): 131–154.
[CrossRef]
Hitt, C.W.L., R.E. Freeman, and J.S. Harrison. 2001. The Blackwell handbook of strategic
management. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hosseini, J.C., and S.N. Brenner. 1992. The stakeholder theory of the firm: A methodology to
generate value matrix weights. Business Ethics Quarterly 2(2): 99–119.
[CrossRef]
Hummels, H. 1998. Organizing ethics: A stakeholder debate. Journal of Business Ethics 17(13):
1403–1419.
[CrossRef]
Hutton, C.W.L. 1995. The state we’re in. London: Jonathan Cape.
Jensen, M.C. 2000. Value maximization and the corporate objective function. In Breaking the code of
change, ed. M. Beer and N. Norhial, 37–58. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Jensen, M.C. 2001. Value maximization, stakeholder theory and the corporate objective function.
Business Ethics Quarterly 12(2): 235–256.
[CrossRef]
Jensen, M.C., and W.H. Meckling. 1976. Theory of the firm: Management behavior, agency cost and
ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics 3(4): 305–360.
[CrossRef]
Jones, T.M. 1995. Instrumental stakeholder theory: A synthesis of ethics and economics. Academy of
Management Review 20(2): 404–437.
Jones, T.M., and A.C. Wicks. 1999. Convergent stakeholder theory. Academy of Management Review
24(2): 206–221.
Knox, S., and C. Gruar. 2007. The application of stakeholder theory to relationship marketing
strategy. Development in a non-profit organization. Journal of Business Ethics 75: 115–135.
[CrossRef]
Kochan, T.A., and S.A. Rubinstein. 2000. Toward a stakeholder theory of the firm: The Saturn
partnership. Organization Science 11(4): 367–386.
[CrossRef]
Langtry, B. 1994. Stakeholders and the moral responsibilities of business. Business Ethics Quarterly
4: 431–443.
[CrossRef]
Laplume, A.O., K. Sonpar, and R.A. Lits. 2008. Stakeholder theory: Reviewing a theory that moves
us. Journal of Management 34(6): 1152–1189.
[CrossRef]
Lépineux, F. 2005. Stakeholder theory, society and social cohesion. Corporate Governance 5(2): 99–
110.
[CrossRef]
Martinet, A.-C. 1984. Management stratégique: organisation et politique. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Martinet, A.-C., and E. Reynaud. 2001. Shareholders, stakeholders et stratégie. Revue Française de
Gestion, (November–December), 12–25.
Marcoux, A.M. 2000. Balancing act. In Contemporary issues in business ethics, ed. Desjardins J. R.
et Mccall J. J. (dir.), 4e édition, 92–100. Wadsworth: Belmont.
Mercier, S. 2006. La théorie des parties prenantes: une synthèse de la littérature. In Décider avec les
parties prenantes, eds. M. Bonnafous-Boucher and Y. Pesqueux. Paris: Editions La Découverte,
Recherche series.
Mitchell, R.K., B.R. Agle, and D.S. Wood. 1997. Toward a theory of stakeholder identification and
salience: Defining the principle of who and what really counts. Academy of Management Review
22(4): 853–866.
Moore, G. 1999. Tinged shareholder theory: Or what’s so special about stakeholders? Business
Ethics: A European Review 8(2): 117–127.
[CrossRef]
Näsi, J. 1995. What is stakeholder thinking? A snapshot of a social theory of the firm. In
Understanding stakeholder thinking, ed. J. Näsi, 19–32. Helsinki: LSR-Julkaisut Oy.
Orts, E.W., and A. Strudler. 2002. The ethical and environmental limits of stakeholder theory.
Business Ethics Quaterly 12(2): 215–234.
[CrossRef]
Phillips, R. 2003b. Stakeholder theory and organizational ethics. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler,
Inc.
Phillips, R., R.E. Freeman, and A.C. Wicks. 2003. What stakeholder theory is not. Business Ethics
Quarrterly 13(4): 479–502.
[CrossRef]
Polanyi, K. 1944. The great transformation. New York: Farrar and Rinehart.
Rustin, M. 1997. Stakeholding and the public sector. In Stakeholder capitalism, ed. G. Kelly, D.
Kelly, and A. Gamble. London: MacMillan.
Savage, G.T., T.H. Nix, C.J. Whitehead, and J.D. Blair. 1991. Strategies for assessing and managing
organizational stakeholders. Academy of Management Executive 5(2): 61–75.
[CrossRef]
Starik, M. 1994. Essays by Mark Starik. Toronto conference: Reflections on Stakeholder Theory.
Business and Society 33:82–131.
Stewart, G.B. 1994. EVA: Fact and fantasy. Journal of Applied Corporate Finance 7(2): 71–84.
[CrossRef]
Thomson, J.K., S.L. Wartick, and H.L. Smith. 1991. Integrating corporate social performance and
stakeholder management: Implication for a research agenda in small business. Research in Corporate
Social Performance and Policy 12: 207–230.
Tichy, N.M., A.R. McGill, and L. Saint-Clair. 1997. Corporate global citizenship, doing business in
the public eye. San Francisco: The New Lexington Press.
van Buren, H.J. 2001. If fairness is the problem, is consent the solution? Integrating ISCT and
stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quarterly 11(3): 481–499.
[CrossRef]
von Bertalanffy, Ludwig. 1968. General system theory: Foundations, development, applications.
New York: George Braziller.
Wicks, A.C., D.R. Gilbert, and R.E. Freeman. 1994. A feminist reinterpretation of the stakeholder
concept. Business Ethics Quarterly 4(4): 475–497.
[CrossRef]
© The Author(s) 2016
Maria Bonnafous-Boucher and Jacob Dahl Rendtorff, Stakeholder Theory, SpringerBriefs in Ethics,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-44356-0_2
Fig. 2.4 Competing stakeholder networks (Source: R. E. Freeman and al, Stakeholder Theory. The
State of the Art, Cambridge University Press (2010: 118))
Conclusion
The advocates of stakeholder theory have always claimed that its origins are
to be sought in strategic management. In this section, we have examined the
most important currents in the discipline, both those with which stakeholder
theory has a number of affinities, and those with which it is not congruent.
Some of these currents are seen as extensions of the theory, while others are
regarded as complementary to it. Indeed, some authors, for example Sachs
and Rühli (2011), see the theory as a new paradigm in strategic
management that redefines the corporation and the organization (Post et al.
2002). In entrepreneurship, it is possible to demonstrate that activity is not
only dependent on groups or individuals, but also on rules implied by
legislation and norms. In this regard, stakeholder theory is similar to neo-
institutionalism.
In order to enter this paradigm, it is necessary to move beyond an
exclusively economic model based on the maximization of profit and take
into account the wealth, diversity and complexity of the social dynamics
surrounding and affecting the corporation. In this sense, stakeholder theory
is congruent with the view of Gioia and Pitre (1990), for whom strategic
management is deployed in a multitude of perspectives. Far from being an
obstacle to the measurement of corporate performance, stakeholder theory
proposes multi-level performance criteria which presuppose a long-term
vision (Freeman et al. 2010: 117). Nevertheless, for most authors associated
with the theory, the integration of stakeholders implies a cognitive
revolution in the corporation and its structure (Gersick 1991), as well as in
its instances of governance, and its decision-making and learning processes.
References
Abell, Derek F. 1980. Defining the business: The starting point of strategic planning. Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Aggeri, F. 2008. Régénerer les cadres de la stratégie. Mise en dispositif et exploration de nouveaux
espaces d’action stratégiques. HDR thesis defended at the University of Paris, Dauphine.
Aoki, M. 1984. The cooperative game theory of the firm. Oxford Oxfordshire/New York: Clarendon
Press.
Barney, J.B. 1989. Assets, stocks and sustained competitive advantage. Management Science 35:
1511–1513.
[CrossRef]
Baron, D.P. 1995. Business and its environment. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Baron, D.P. 2006. A positive theory of moral management: Social pressure and corporate social
performance. Stanford University, Graduate School of Business Research Paper No. 1940, Rock
Center for Corporate Governance, Working Paper No. 36.
Bingham, J.B., J.R. Dyer, W.G. Smith, and G.L. Adams. 2010. A stakeholder identity orientation
approach to corporate social performance in family firms. Journal of Business Ethics 99(4): 565–
585.
[CrossRef]
Brandenburger, A.M., and Nalebuff, B. 1995. The right game: Using game theory to shape strategy.
Harvard Business Review (July–August), 57–71.
Caby, J. 2003. Valeur partenariale ou actionnariale. In Encyclopédie des ressources humaines, ed. J.
Allouche and I. Huault. Paris: Economica.
Charreaux, G. 1997. Le gouvernement des entreprises: Corporate Governance, Théories et Faits.
Paris: Economica.
Charreaux, G., and P. Wirtz. 2006. Gouvernance des entreprises, Nouvelles Perspectives. Paris:
Economica.
Christopher, M., A. Payne, and D. Ballantyne. 1991. Relationship marketing: Bringing quality,
customer service and marketing together. Oxford: Butterworth-Heineman.
Cornell, B., and A.C. Shapiro. 1987. Corporate stakeholders and corporate finance. Financial
Management 16(1): 5–14.
[CrossRef]
D’Aveni, R. 2010. The age of temporary advantage. Strategic Management Journal 31(13): 1371–
1385.
[CrossRef]
Dery, J. 1996. Analyse bibliographique des écoles en stratégie. Actes de la journée Recherche en
gestion. FNEGE Paris, October 11.
Desreumaux, A.A., X. Lecocq, et V. Warnier. 2005, 2006. Stratégie. Harlow: Pearson Education.
Desreumaux, A., X. Lecocq, and V. Warnier. 2006. Stratégie. Paris: Pearson Education.
Dyer, J.H., and H. Singh. 1998. The relational view: Cooperative strategy and sources of
interorganizational competitive advantage. Academy of Management Review 23(4): 660–679.
Fisher, R., and W. Ury. 1981. Comment réussir une négociation. Paris: Seuil, 1982.
Freeman, R.E. 1984. Strategic management. A atakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman Publishing.
Freeman, R.E. 2010. Stakeholder theory. The state of the art. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
[CrossRef]
Freeman, R.E., and W. Evan. 1990. Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. Journal of
Behavioral Economics 19: 337–359.
[CrossRef]
Freeman, R.E., and D. Reed. 1983. Stockholders and stakeholders: A new perspective on corporate
governance. In Corporate governance: A definitive exploration of the issues, ed. C. Huizinga. Los
Angeles: UCLA Extension Press.
Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, and A.C. Wicks. 2007. Managing for stakeholders: Survival,
reputation and success. The Business Roundtable Institute for Corporate Ethics Series in Ethics and
Lead, Caravan Publisher.
Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, A.C. Wicks, B.L. Parma, and S. De Colle. 2010. Stakeholder theory:
The state of the art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[CrossRef]
Gioia, D.A., and E. Pitre. 1990. Multiparadigm perspectives on theory building. Academy of
Management Review 15(4): 584–602.
Gomez, P.-Y., and H. Korine. 2009. L’Entreprise dans la démocratie. Une théorie politique du
gouvernement des entreprises. Louvain-la-Neuve: De Boeck Université.
Hafsi, T., and A.C. Martinet. 2007. The strategic decision-making process in state owned enterprises.
Gestion 32(3): 88–98.
[CrossRef]
Heath, J., and A. Potter. 2004. The Rebel Sell. How the counterculture became consumer culture.
London: Capstone.
Hitt, C.W.L., R.E. Freeman, and J.S. Harrison. 2001. The Blackwell handbook of strategic
management. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hofer, C.W., and D.E. Schendel. 1996. Strategy formulation: Analytical concepts. Saint-Paul: West
Publishing.
Holt, D.B. 2002. Why do brands cause trouble? A dialectical theory of consumer culture and
branding. Journal of Consumer Research 29: 70–90.
[CrossRef]
Jarniou, J. 1981. L’entreprise comme système politique. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Jensen, M.C., and W.H. Meckling. 1976. Theory of the firm: Management behavior, agency cost and
ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics 3(4): 305–360.
[CrossRef]
Krippendorf, E. 1973. Peace research and the industrial revolution. Journal of Peace Research 10(3):
185–201.
[CrossRef]
Learned, E.P., C.R. Christensen, K.R. Andrews, and W.D. Guth. 1965. Business policy, text and
cases. Homewood: Irwin.
MacMillan, I.C. 1978. Strategy formulation: Political concepts. St. Paul: West.
Martinet, A.-C. 1990. Épistémologie de la stratégie. In Épistémologie et sciences de gestion, ed. A.-
C. Martinet et al. Paris: Economica.
Martinet, A.-C. 2006. Parties prenantes, management stratégique et politique. In eds. M. Bonnafous-
Boucher and Y. Pesqueux. Paris: Editions La Découverte, Recherche.
Martinet, A.-C., and E. Reynaud. 2001. Shareholders, stakeholders et stratégie. Revue Française de
Gestion, (November–December), 12–25.
Miller, R.L., and W.F. Lewis. 1991. A stakeholder approach to marketing management using the
value exchange model. European Journal of Marketing 25(8): 55–68.
[CrossRef]
Parrat, F. 1999. Le gouvernement d’entreprise: ce qui a changé, ce qui va évoluer. Paris: Maxime L.
du Mesnil.
Pasquero, J. 1980. L’entreprise face aux pressions sociopolitiques de son environnement. PhD thesis,
Université des sciences sociales de Grenoble, IAE.
Pasquero, J. 2008. Entreprise, Développement durable et Théorie des parties prenantes: esquisse d’un
arrimage socio-constructionniste. Management International 12: 27–47.
Penrose, E. 1959. The theory of the growth of the firm. Oxford: Blackwell.
Phillips, R., and R.E. Freeman. 2010. Stakeholders. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
[CrossRef]
Porter, M., and M. Kramer. 2002. The competitive advantage of corporate philanthropy. Harvard
Business Review 80(12): 56–68.
Porter, M., and M. Kramer. 2011. Creating shared value. How to reinvent capitalism – and unleash a
wave of innovation and growth. Harvard Business Review 89(1/2): 62–77.
Post, J.E., L.E. Preston, and S. Sachs. 2002. Redefining the corporation, stakeholder management
and organizational wealth. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Preston, L.E., and J.E. Post. 1975. Private management and public choice: The principle of public
responsibility. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Roper, S., and G. Davies. 2007. The corporate brand: Dealing with multiple stakeholders. Journal of
Marketing Management 23(1–2): 75–90.
[CrossRef]
Sachs, S., and E. Ruhli. 2011. Stakeholders matter. A new paradigm for strategy in society.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[CrossRef]
Schleifer, A., and R.W. Vishnhy. 1997, Jun. A survey of corporate governance. The Journal of
Finance 52(2): 737–783.
Tabatoni, P., and P. Jarniou. 1975. Les systèmes de gestion: politiques et structures. Paris: PUF.
Thuderoz, C. 2010. Qu’est-ce que négocier? Sociologie du compromis et de l’action. Rennes: Presses
universitaires de Rennes.
[CrossRef]
Venkataraman, S. 2002. Stakeholder value equilibration and the entrepreneurial process. In Ethics
and entrepreneurship, eds. R.E. Freeman and S. Venkataraman, 45–57. Charlottesville: Ruffin Series,
Philosophy Documentation Center.
Wernerfelt, B. 1984. A resource-based view of the firm. Strategic Management Journal 5(2) (April–
June): 171–180.
Wicks, A., R.E. Freeman, and P.H. Werhane. 2009. Business ethics: A managerial approach.
Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Wirtz, P. 2008. Les meilleures pratiques de gouvernance d’entreprise. Paris: La Découverte, Repères.
© The Author(s) 2016
Maria Bonnafous-Boucher and Jacob Dahl Rendtorff, Stakeholder Theory, SpringerBriefs in Ethics,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-44356-0_3
There have been so many studies on organization between the 1980s and
2010, borrowing from so many different sources, that it would be vain to
attempt to demonstrate how stakeholder theory has attempted to appropriate
or influence any given model. Nevertheless, 30 years were needed to
jettison the evolutionist notion of the “one best way” in organization
studies, a notion that can be traced from Max Weber to Henry Mintzberg.
Stakeholder theory has contributed to this process of deconstruction. In
effect, systemic approaches (other than Gestalt theory and theories related
to Michel Crozier’s “concrete action system”) have cast the organization,
and particularly the corporation, as an ensemble of independent parties
articulated with a single objective in mind. Thus, the vast majority of
studies produced in the field of organization studies have promoted an
essentialist view of an entity focused on its own mode of functioning,
describing a structure centered on determinants (Mintzberg 1979, 1983;
Mintzberg et al. 1998). In this regard, the objectifiable and finite character
of the organization suggests “a coordinating entity with identifiable
frontiers functioning in a sustainable manner while at the same time
attempting to achieve one or more objectives shared by the participants”
(Robbins 1987). But structure is not appropriate to a fluid (and
fundamentally plastic) conception of the organization based on
stakeholders. Far from being a fortress founded on structural determinants,
the organization is porous. And stakeholder theory dispenses with the
biological and engineering foundations of systemic analysis, reconstructing
the approach on properly managerial and political bases. With stakeholder
theory, the study of organizations turns its attention to the notions of
interest, the negotiation of issues, and the management of more or less
stable relations both within and outside the organization. In this sense, the
organization is a kind of “collectivity sharing one or more common interests
and engaging in shared activities.” It is thus “a coalition of groups with
variable interests which elaborates objectives by means of negotiation”
(Scott 1987).
Political Approaches
“Political analysis is a generic expression for the ensemble of organizational
analyses of the notion of power” (Rouleau 2007). It encompasses
theoretical approaches from the 1960s, including the analysis of coalitions
(Cyert and March 1963); the 1970s, including Crozier and Friedberg’s
strategic analysis; and the 1980s, including strategic contingency theories
(Hickson et al. 1971; Pfeffer and Salancik 1978, 1981). Stakeholder theory
is a major contribution to political approaches for which power is less an
attribute than a relationship.
Conclusion
Compared to the multiplicity of analytical perspectives developed in the
field of organization theory between 1980 and 2000, stakeholder theory is
relatively unified. It has manifestly been linked to many currents of thought
by dint of being contemporary to them or by having appropriated concepts
associated with research in the field of organization studies. But systematic
correspondences are still few and far between. It should nevertheless be
noted that stakeholder theory is part of a trend promoting systemic analysis:
it deconstructs the organization by focusing to a larger degree on a dynamic
conception of organized action which produces meaning. Secondly, it
enables researchers to more effectively analyze organizational, and more
particularly, inter-organizational contexts which are increasingly
international. It enriches the concept of the environment at the crossroads
between strategic management and organization theory. In fact, the plethora
of stakeholder maps including employees, clients and suppliers in the
managerial literature and within companies themselves not only suffer from
the drawback of not being applicable to all situations, but discourage
interpretations of the concept of the stakeholder from the perspective of
coalition analysis, strategic contingency theory, relational analysis, the
analysis of the type of pressure deriving from stakeholders or being applied
to them in view of achieving a result, analyses of the common good, and the
framework of negotiation, etc. It should also be noted that stakeholder
theory is linked to all currents of research focusing on factors of
coordination (economics), convention (economic sociology), negotiation
(international relations and political science), and theories of argumentation
(rhetoric and political philosophy).
References
Astley, W.G., and P.S. Sachdeva. 1984. Structural sources of intraorganizational power: A theoretical
synthesis. Academy of Management Review 9(1): 104–113.
Astley, W.G., and A.H. Van de Ven. 1983. Central perspectives and debates in organization theory.
Administrative Science Quarterly 28: 245–273.
[CrossRef]
Berger, P., and T. Luckmann. 1966. The social construction of reality. New York: Doubleday and
Company. French edition by Armand Colin, 1996.
Brunsson, N., and A. Goran. 2008. Meta-organizations. Northampton: Elgar Publishing USA.
Casey, C. 2002. Critical analysis of organizations. Theory, practice, revitalization. Thousand Oaks:
Sage Publications.
Chabaud, D., J.-M. Glachant, C. Parthenay, and Y. Perez. 2008. Les Grands auteurs en économie des
organisations. Paris: EMS Editions.
Clegg, S.R. 1979. The theory of power and organization. London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.
Clegg, S.R. 1981. Organization and control. Administrative Science Quarterly 26(4): 545–562.
[CrossRef]
Cyert, R., and J. March. 1963. A behavioral theory of the firm. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Desreumaux, A. 2005. Théorie des organizations, 2nd ed. Paris: Editions Management & Société.
Freeman, R.E. 1984. Strategic management. A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman Publishing.
Gioia, D.A. 1986. The state of the art in organizational social cognition: A personal view. In The
thinking organization, ed. H.P. Sims and D.A. Gioia, 336–356. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Granovetter, M. 1985. Economic action and social structure: The problem of embeddedness.
American Journal of Sociology 91: 481–510.
[CrossRef]
Hardy, C. 1985. The nature of unobtrusive power. The Journal of Management Studies 22(4): 384–
399.
[CrossRef]
Hardy, C. 1995. Managing strategic change: Power, paralysis and perspective. Advances in Strategic
Management 12: 3–31.
Hasenclever, A., P. Mayer, and V. Rittberger (eds.). 1983. Theories of international regimes.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hickson, D.J., C.R. Hinings, C.A. Lee, R.E. Schneck, and J.M. Pennings. 1971. A strategic
contingencies’ theory of interorganizational power. Administrative Science Quarterly 16: 151–196.
[CrossRef]
Jensen, M.C., and W.H. Meckling. 1976. Theory of the firm: Management behavior, agency cost and
ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics 3(4): 305–360.
[CrossRef]
Keohane, R.O., and J.S. Nye. 1977. Power and interdependence: World politics in transition. Boston:
Little Brown.
Meyer, J.W., and B. Rowan. 1977. Institutionalized organizations: Formal structure as myth and
ceremony. American Journal of Sociology 83(2): 340–363.
[CrossRef]
Mintzberg, H. 1979. The structuring of organizations: A synthesis of the research. Trans. 1982,
Structure et dynamique de organizations. Paris: Editions d’Organisation.
Mintzberg, H. 1983. Power in and around organizations. Trans.: Le Pouvoir dans les organizations.
Paris: Ed d’Organisation.
Mintzberg, H., B. Ahlstrand, and J. Lampel. 1998. Strategy safari. New York: The Free Press.
Narayan, V.K., and L. Fahey. 1982. The micro-politics of strategy formulation. Academy of
Management Review 7(1): 25–34.
Nicolini, D., S. Gherardi, and D. Yanow. 2003. Introduction: Toward a practice-based view of
knowing and learning in organizations. In Knowing in organizations. A practice-based approach, ed.
D. Nicolini, S. Gherardi, and D. Yanow, 3–31. London: Sharpe.
Pfeffer, J., and G.R. Salancik. 1978. The external control of organization: A resource dependence
perspective. New York: Harper and Row.
Pfeffer, J., and G.R. Salancik. 1981. Power in organizations. Marshfield: Pitman.
Powell, W.W., and P.J. DiMaggio (eds.). 1991. The new institutionalism in organizational analysis.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Robbins, S.P. 1987. Organization theory. Englewood Cliffs: Prenctice-Hall.
Schwenk, C.R. 1989. Linking cognition, organizational and political factors in exploring strategic
change. Journal of Management Studies 26(2): 177–187.
[CrossRef]
Scott, R.W. 1987. Organizations, rational, natural and open systems. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-
Hall.
Scott, R.W., and J.W. Meyer. 1994. Institutional environments and organizations: Structural
complexity and individualism. Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Somech, A., and A. Drach-Zahavy. 2002. Relative power and influence strategy: The effects of
agent/target organizational power on superiors’ choices of influence strategies. Journal of
Organizational Behavior 23(2): 167–178.
[CrossRef]
Tsoukas, H., and C. Knudsen. 2003. The Oxford handbook of organization theory. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
von Bertalanffy, Ludwig. 1951. General system theory. A new approach to unity of science
(symposium). Human Biology 23: 303–361.
Westwood, R., and S.R. Clegg. 2003. The problem of order revisited: Towards a more critical
institutional perspective. Debating Organization. Oxford: Blackwell.
© The Author(s) 2016
Maria Bonnafous-Boucher and Jacob Dahl Rendtorff, Stakeholder Theory, SpringerBriefs in Ethics,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-44356-0_4
Like Rousseau and Locke, the authors regard the social contract as being
supported by a form of pre-existing sociality. While the idea of a sociality
existing before the contract is difficult to grasp, it is nevertheless the source
of social theories of the contract. Faithful to the tradition of the
contractualist philosophers of the Enlightenment, Donaldson and Dunfee
present pre-contractual social relations as the basis and preliminary of the
real contract, a kind of metaphorical “handshake” (1999). This notion
enables the authors to highlight the fictive status of the contract: “If the
contract were something other than a ‘fiction,’ it would be inadequate for
the purpose at hand, namely revealing the moral foundations of productive
organizations.” It is useful to assume this fiction and the implicit agreement
between stakeholders as the foundation of liberal societies: “The social
contract is a powerful image which supports all forms of democratic
government. In order for it to do so, we call upon a mythical agreement
which provides legitimacy to a wide range of laws and institutions”
(Axelrod 1986). In this vein, stakeholder theory “models” social contract
theory and provides the pre-conditions for an agreement. Just as
contractualists elaborate the ideal conditions of government in order to
replace monarchy with a rational representative political system, in the
business world some conditions are more equitable than others in terms of
creating productive organizations and conducting trade. These more
equitable conditions are expressed in a maxim: “Corporations should be
able to do business, use natural resources and own shares, in exchange for
which they should have ethical obligations toward all members of society”
(Donaldson and Dunfee 1999). Thus, any profits taken should not outweigh
the inconveniencies caused to members of society. However, it should be
noted that the parties to the contract are rational, autonomous people who
have given their consent freely and who have economic and political
preferences. Donaldson and Dunfee even suggest that “hypernorms,” or, in
other words norms by which individuals are governed, make it possible to
judge the actions of contracting parties. They apply the ideas of Charles
Taylor (1989), for whom the greatest good is justice, and of Michael Walzer
(1992), for whom there are nine basic criteria which render life in society
possible, including the interdictions to kill, torture, oppress, and so on.
This initial level of sociality precedes the real social contract by which
agreement is underpinned. However, some authors, like Kim Lane
Scheppele (1993), do not believe that implicit consent is possible and
question the likelihood of everyone having equal knowledge of and equal
access to the financial markets (one thinks of the sub-prime market crisis of
2008).
Integrative Social Contracts Theory juxtaposes the macro and micro levels.
While the macro level reflects a hypothetical agreement between members
of the community, the micro level bears witness to a real agreement
between professions and/or trades and/or activities categorized into around
forty different communities. This is how lobby groups are constituted with a
view to developing ethical norms and principles for individual professions
(lawyers, accountants), and how they are backed up by other political or
economic networks (the European Community, the United States, federal
states), industries (chemicals, software manufacturers), corporations
(Canon, Microsoft, United Way of America), organizational units (human
resources departments), and informal communities within organizations
(networks of female managers, networks of Afro-American managers).
There is no doubt that ISCT renders plausible a minimal level of agreement
between individual interests which are, in many ways, divergent. It should
nevertheless be observed that the institutional context of this social contract
is very different from that of contractualist political philosophy in both its
classical (Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau) and contemporary (Rawls) versions. It
is informed by a crisis of the nation-state. A number of questions arise: will
this kind of contract enable firms to form a “pact” with non-shareholders by
creating a framework for dialogue and deliberation in which the
expectations of non-shareholding stakeholders, who are subject to the
activities of the firm, are taken into account and met? Donaldson and
Dunfee’s response to these questions is normative. They stipulate a kind of
implicit contract between the corporation and society where the corporation
has obligations to society which, in turn, has the right to monitor the
corporation; however, they do not call into question stakeholders’ capacity
for arbitrage. In effect, Donaldson and Dunfee return to an idea of the social
contract based on a more detailed description of society than the one
proposed by stakeholder theory, which describes a more fragmented reality.
References
Aoki, M., B. Gustafson, and O. Williamson. 1990. The firm as a nexus of treaties. Thousand Oaks:
Sage.
Argandona, A. 1995. The ethical dimension of financial institutions and the market. Berlin/New
York: Springer.
[CrossRef]
Axelrod, R. 1986. An evolutionary approach to norms. American Political Science Review 80(4):
1095–1111.
[CrossRef]
Beck, U. 2005. Power in the global age: A new global political economy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bonnafous-Boucher, M., and S. Porcher. 2010. Stakeholder theory and theory of civil society.
European Management Review 7(4): 205–216.
[CrossRef]
Cazal, D. 2011. RSE et Théorie des parties prenantes: les impasses du contrat, Revue de la
régulation, Dossier: RSE, régulation et diversité du capitalisme 9, 1er semestre 2011.
Crane, A., and D. Matten. 2007. Business ethics. Managing corporate citizenship and sustainability
in the age of globalization. New York: Oxford University Press.
Donaldson, T. 1989. The ethics of international business. New York: Oxford University Press.
Donaldson, T., and T. Dunfee. 1995. Contractarian business ethics: Current status and next steps.
Business Ethics Quarterly 5(2): 173–186.
[CrossRef]
Donaldson, T., and T. Dunfee. 1999. Ties that bind. A social contracts approach to business ethics.
Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Dunfee, T.W. 1991. Business ethics and extant social contracts. Business Ethics Quarterly 1(1): 23–
51.
[CrossRef]
Hegel, G.W. 1820. Elements of the philosophy of right. Cambridge: Cambridge Texts in the History
of Political Thought, 1991.
Hill, C.W.L., and T.M. Jones. 1992. Stakeholder-agency theory. Journal of Management Studies
29(2): 131–154.
[CrossRef]
Powell, W.W., and P.J. DiMaggio. 1983. The iron cage revisited: Functional isomorphism and
collective rationality in organizational fields. American Journal of Sociology 48(2): 147–160.
[CrossRef]
Rousseau, J.-J. 1762a. Émile ou De l’éducation. In Œuvres complètes IV. Paris: La Pléiade.
Rousseau, J.-J. 1762b. Du contrat social ou Essai sur la forme de la république. In Œuvres
complètes III. Paris: La Pléiade.
Rousseau, J.-J. 1771. Manuscrit de Genève. In Œuvres complètes III. Paris: La Pléiade.
Scheppele, K.L. 1993. It’s just not right: The ethics of insider trading. Law and Contemporary
Problems 56(3): 123–173.
[CrossRef]
Taylor, C. 1989. Sources of the self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Walzer, M. 1992. Moral minimalism. In The Twilight of probability: Ethics and politics, ed. W.R.
Shea and G.A. Spadafora, 3–14. Canton: Science History Publications.
Wartick, S.L., and P.L. Cochran. 1985. The evolution of the corporate social performance model.
Academy of Management Review 10(4): 758–769.
Williamson, O. 1985. The economic institutions of capitalism. New York: The Free Press.
© The Author(s) 2016
Maria Bonnafous-Boucher and Jacob Dahl Rendtorff, Stakeholder Theory, SpringerBriefs in Ethics,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-44356-0_5
Principle Managers should acknowledge and actively monitor the concerns of all legitimate
1 stakeholders, and should take their interests appropriately into account in decision-
making and operations
Principle Managers should listen to and openly communicate with stakeholders about their
2 respective concerns and contributions, and about the risks that they assume because of
their involvement with the corporation
Principle Managers should adopt processes and modes of behavior that are sensitive to the
3 concerns and capabilities of each shareholder constituency
Principle Managers should recognize the interdependence of efforts and rewards among
4 stakeholders, and should attempt to achieve a fair distribution of the benefits and burdens
of corporate activity among them, taking into account their respective risks and
vulnerabilities
Principle Managers should work cooperatively with other entities, both public and private, to
5 insure that risks and harms arising from corporate activities are minimized and, where
they cannot be avoided, appropriately compensated
Principle Managers should avoid altogether activities that might jeopardize inalienable human
6 rights (e. g., the right to life) or give rise to risks which, if clearly understood, would be
patently unacceptable to relevant stakeholders
Principle Managers should acknowledge the potential conflicts between (a) their own role as
7 corporate stakeholders, and (b) their legal and moral responsibilities for the interests of
all stakeholders, and should address such conflicts through open communication,
appropriate reporting and incentive systems and, where necessary, third party review
2. Recognize that stakeholders are real and complex people with names,
faces and values.
10. Act with purpose that fulfills commitments to stakeholders. Act with
aspiration towards fulfilling your dreams and theirs (Freeman and
Velamuri 2006: 7–9).
Freeman’s principles of company stakeholder management allow for a
thoroughgoing reappraisal of stakeholder theory. Instead of placing it in the
center of the diagram (Fig. 5.3), the firm could, here, be conceived of as
serving society and contributing to the common good. This conception of
stakeholder theory can be represented in the diagram below (Fig. 5.3).
Fig. 5.3 Freeman’s normative corporate stakeholder responsibility principles (Source: Rendtorff
(2009))
Conclusion
In this chapter, we have discussed the ethical foundations of stakeholder
theory. Our initial considerations focused on the way in which the theory
goes beyond economic conceptions of the firm like those of Friedman and
Jensen. Indeed, it also goes beyond a number of philosophical currents
dealing with economic activity (including the firm), namely pragmatism,
communitarianism, universalism and republicanism. In effect, these
currents contribute to the development of a foundation for stakeholder
theory by providing an alternative view of the activities of the firm. They
focus on the possibility of the firm acting in the same way as an honest
citizen. The approach, based on the philosophy of contract developed by
Rawls, Freeman and Phillips has served as a framework with which to
formalize this dominant perspective in stakeholder theory. However,
dominant ideas about stakeholder theory and business ethics are called into
question by a deconstructivist, poststructuralist critique. In our view, it is
possible to found corporate citizenship on the philosophy of difference
developed by Derrida, Nancy and Agamben. In fact, a stakeholder ethics
presupposes the definition of a strategy based on this approach the aim of
which is to ensure that the firm acts in a socially responsible manner, or, in
other words, in the way in which a democratic, republican citizen would act
in regard to the market and, more generally, within a democratic, republican
political society.
References
Agamben, G. 2011. The kingdom and the glory. For a theological genealogy of economy and
government. Trans. Lorenzo Chiesa (with Matteo Mandarini). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Bowie, N.E. 1999. Business ethics. A Kantian perspective. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell
Publishers.
Freeman, R.E. 1993. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian capitalism. In Ethical
theory and business, ed. T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
Freeman, R.E., and S.J. Velamuri. 2006. A new approach to CSR: Company stakeholder
responsibility. In Corporate social responsibility: From aspiration to application, eds. M. Morsing
and A. Kakabadse, 9–23. Basingstoke/Hampshire: Palgrave MacMillan Houndsmills.
Goodpaster, K. 1991. Business ethics and stakeholder analysis. Business Ethics Quarterly 1: 53–73.
Jensen, M.C. 2000. Value Maximization and the corporate objective function. In Breaking the code of
change, ed. M. Beer and N. Nohria, 37–58. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Phillips, R. 2003b. Stakeholder theory and organizational ethics. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler,
Inc.
Solomon, R.C. 1993. Ethics and excellence. Cooperation and integrity in business. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Ulrich, P. 2008. Integrative economic ethics: Foundations of a civilized market economy. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
[CrossRef]
Wheeler, D., and M. Sillanpää. 1997. The stakeholder corporation. The body shop blue print for
maximizing stakeholder value. London: Pitman Publishing.
General Conclusion
The essential objective of this book has been to gauge the scope of
stakeholder theory in terms of its heuristic capacity.
The heuristic capacity of the theory enables it to achieve a level of
generality encompassing the way in which the market and society are
represented, while dealing exclusively which the representation of the
corporation. Although a management theory, it possesses an interpretative
capacity: it places the corporation at the center of its analysis by taking into
account the porosity between the economy, society and politics (in the sense
of “the polity,” or living together). Stakeholder theory examines the
frontiers between the activity of the firm and other social activities.
This heuristic potential has been addressed by means of an exclusively
ethical approach to the theory. Readers coming to the end of the book might
well ask themselves why the authors decided to leave their analysis of
stakeholder theory’s contribution to business ethics to the last chapter. The
reason is that this is the most well known aspect of stakeholder theory,
which is generally considered to be a mainstay of research into corporate
social responsibility and business ethics (Anquetil 2011 ).
In sum, the task of analyzing the scope of the theory (and not only its
state of the art) is still far from complete. In this regard, more room should
be made for a constructive critique in that, as some authors (Acquier and
Aggeri 2008 ), have observed, the concept of the “stakeholder” has become
an ecumenical matter. And while the importance of a theory is often related
to the number of commentaries it attracts, in the case of stakeholder theory,
with a few, rare exceptions, commentators contributing to the academic and
management literature are content merely to illustrate rather than critique.
In this sense, the work of Orts and Strudler ( 2002 , 2009 ), and Cazal (
2011 ) provides a useful reference point. It can be demonstrated that:
– A sociological approach is required in order to make sense of a
constellation of fragmented interests, with neither history nor
context. This would make it possible to escape a holistic view of
stakeholders in which employees and shareholders represent
homogeneous groups; to better perceive coalitions struck between
stakeholders (Rowley 1997 ); and to take into account the American
ethnocentrism of the theory, according to which society is made up
of competing interests represented by lobbies.
– The theory is characterized by a kind of heliocentrism, with the
corporation at the center of a model displaying direct dyadic
relations between the corporation and its stakeholders. The literature
is full of figures and illustrations highlighting this heliocentric
approach. What has been described as a bicycle wheel could also be
seen as a galaxy with the firm at its center. From this point of view,
it could be asked whether the theory is an attempt to encourage the
corporation to play a better role in society or an effort to teach it
how to defend itself more effectively from counter-powers (Acquier
and Aggeri 2008 ).
– Freeman’s critique of the shareholder approach is reversible: the
theory encourages the extension of shareholder powers to everyone
(Bonnafous-Boucher 2004 ).
– The theory’s normative postulates are problematic. In effect, the
equality in law and fact of individual stakeholders (the intrinsic
value of each one of them) makes it hard to justify a negotiation
based on priorities which are not always those of the firm. In order
to encourage a pluralist approach, it would be worthwhile comparing
the arguments of Bowie, the major advocate of Kantian capitalism,
with those of Mitchell, Agle and Wood, who promote the idea that
stakeholders should be defined in terms of management priorities.
– Freeman’s oft-repeated contention that he and his school subscribe to
a basically pragmatic approach is counterbalanced by a kind of
idealism apparent in his work. In effect, the idea of consensus, the
cornerstone of the social contract, itself a founding institution of
society, is bereft of tensions and of an exteriority guaranteeing
individual freedoms. But stakeholder interests are egotistical
interests. Thus, public organizations, public administrations, and
political scientists should take a prudent approach to the notion of
the stakeholder in that its origins are to be found in a representation
of society in which the corporation is the basic social unit.
Certain authors, including Hatchuel and Segrestin ( 2012 ) maintain that
stakeholder theory is incapable of “refounding the corporation,” primarily
because it is situated within the perspective of corporate governance. In
effect, stakeholder theory is a theory of the corporation – more specifically
a theory of the multinational company. It is, therefore, a local theory in that
this type of company does not cover all forms of entrepreneurship.
Nevertheless, the multinational is of particular interest, especially when one
considers that, while in 1970 there were only 7000 such companies, in 2003
there were 64,000, with 870,000 subsidiaries employing over 55 million
people. In many ways, the ownership structures and governance systems of
listed companies reflect the profound transformations in the representations
of capitalism mirrored in original theories of power and conceptions of
corporate delegation and representation. But stakeholder theory is more
than just a particular conception of corporate governance: it proposes a
heterodox version of that conception. Indeed, it is also a theory of the value
of the corporation. It has become almost a cliché in Europe to say that value
is the result of cooperative action. In stakeholder theory, stakeholders
represent this collective in their capacity as owners of interests, and
although Hatchuel and Ségrestin ( 2012 ) deny that the theory is designed to
foster or construct the collective, it nevertheless represents the corporation
as the construction of a dynamic capability (Helfat et al. 2007 ). It affirms
that, to exist and survive, the corporation and corporate governance must
recognize and promote pluralism.
Last, the primary objective of this book has been to highlight the ways
in which a management theory has been able to exert influence beyond its
borders, a rarity in that management studies borrow more ideas than they
propose. Second – and this is also a rarity – it is a management model that
paints a critical picture of the corporation: the issues and interests of all
those who are not shareholders or investors are primordial in terms of its
survival beyond the mere ownership of capital. Third, we have focused
primarily on the theory’s heuristic function. In our view, this capacity can
be exploited with a view to ensuring that the contributions of management
science and management studies are more than strictly performative.
Bibliography
Abell, Derek F. 1980. Defining the business: The starting point of strategic planning . Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Ackerman, B., and A. Alstot. 1999. The stakeholder society . New Haven: Yale University Press.
Ackerman, B., and J.F. Fischkin. 2004. Deliberation day . New Haven: Yale University Press.
Ackoff, R. 1994. The democratic corporation: A radical prescription for recreating corporate
America and rediscovering success . New York: Oxford University Press.
Acquier and Aggeri. 2008. « Une généalogie de la pensée managériale sur la RSE ». Revue française
de la gestion 180(1): 131–157.
Agamben, G. 2011. The kingdom and the glory. For a theological genealogy of economy and
government . Trans. Lorenzo Chiesa (with Matteo Mandarini). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Aggeri, F. 2008. Régénerer les cadres de la stratégie. Mise en dispositif et exploration de nouveaux
espaces d’action stratégiques . HDR thesis defended at the University of Paris, Dauphine.
Aglietta, M., and A. Reberioux. 2004. La gouvernance … autrement? Paris: Albin Michel.
Akrich, M. 1987. Comment décrire les objets techniques? Techniques et Culture 9: 49–67.
Andriof, J., S. Waddock, B. Husted, and S.S. Rahman. 2002. Unfolding stakeholder thinking , vols. 1
and 2. Sheffield: Greenleaf Publishing.
Anquetil, A. 2011. Éthique des affaires: Marché, règles et responsabilité . Paris: Vrin.
Ansoff, I., and E. McDowell. 1984/1990. Implanting Strategic Management , 2nd ed. Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Aoki, M. 1984. The cooperative game theory of the firm . Oxford Oxfordshire/New York: Clarendon
Press.
Aoki, M., B. Gustafson, and O. Williamson. 1990. The firm as a nexus of treaties . Thousand Oaks:
Sage.
Argandona, A. 1995. The ethical dimension of financial institutions and the market . Berlin/New
York: Springer.
Astley, W.G., and P.S. Sachdeva. 1984. Structural sources of intraorganizational power: A theoretical
synthesis. Academy of Management Review 9(1): 104–113.
Astley, W.G., and A.H. Van de Ven. 1983. Central perspectives and debates in organization theory.
Administrative Science Quarterly 28: 245–273.
Axelrod, R. 1986. An evolutionary approach to norms. American Political Science Review 80(4):
1095–1111.
Barnard, D. 1938. The functions of the excecutive . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Barney, J.B. 1989. Assets, stocks and sustained competitive advantage. Management Science 35:
1511–1513.
Baron, D.P. 1995. Business and its environment . Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Baron, D.P. 2006. A positive theory of moral management: Social pressure and corporate social
performance . Stanford University, Graduate School of Business Research Paper No. 1940, Rock
Center for Corporate Governance, Working Paper No. 36.
Barnett, A. 1997. Towards stakeholder democracy. In Stakeholder capitalism , ed. G. Kelly, D. Kelly,
and A. Gamble. London: MacMillan.
Beck, U. 2005. Power in the global age: A new global political economy . Cambridge: Polity Press.
Benseddik, F. 2006. Démoraliser la responsabilité sociale. In Décider avec les parties prenantes.
Approches d’une nouvelle théorie de la société civile, eds. M. Bonnafous- Boucher and Y. Pesqueux,
91–105. Paris: La Découverte, Recherches.
Berger, P., and T. Luckmann. 1966. The social construction of reality . New York: Doubleday and
Company. French edition by Armand Colin, 1996.
Berle, A., and G. Means. 1932. The modern corporation and private property . New York:
Macmillan.
Bingham, J.B., J.R. Dyer, W.G. Smith, and G.L. Adams. 2010. A stakeholder identity orientation
approach to corporate social performance in family firms. Journal of Business Ethics 99(4): 565–
585.
Blair, J.P. 1995. Local economic development: Analysis and practice . Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Bonnafous-Boucher, M., and S. Porcher. 2010. Stakeholder theory and theory of civil society.
European Management Review 7(4): 205–216.
Bowie, N.E. 1988b. Fair markets. Journal of Business Ethics 7(1–2): 89–98.
Bowie, N.E. 1999. Business ethics. A Kantian perspective . Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell
Publishers.
Brandenburger, A.M., and Nalebuff, B. 1995. The right game: Using game theory to shape strategy.
Harvard Business Review (July–August), 57–71.
Brenner, S.N. 1993. The stakeholder theory of the firm and organizational decision-making. Some
propositions and a model. In Proceedings of the fourth annual meeting of the international
association for business and society, eds. J. Pasquero and D. Collins, 205–210. San Diego.
Brenner, S.N. 1995. Stakeholder theory of the firm. Its consistency with current management
techniques. In Understanding stakeholder thinking , ed. J. Nasi, 75–96. Helskinki: LSR Julkaisut Oy.
Brunsson, N., and A. Goran. 2008. Meta-organizations . Northampton: Elgar Publishing USA.
Caby, J. 2003. Valeur partenariale ou actionnariale. In Encyclopédie des ressources humaines , ed. J.
Allouche and I. Huault. Paris: Economica.
Callon, M. 1986. Some elements of a sociology of translation: Domestication of the scallops and the
fishermen of St Brieuc Bay. In Power, action and belief: A new sociology of knowledge , ed. John
Law, 196–233. London: Routledge and Keegan Paul.
Candela, J. 2006. Vers une notion intégrée de bonne gouvernance. In Décider avec les parties
prenantes, eds. M. Bonnafous-Boucher and Y. Pesqueux. Paris: Editions La Découverte, Recherche
series.
Carroll, A.B. 1989. Business and society. Ethics and stakeholder management , 2nd ed. Cincinnat:
South-Western.
Carroll, A.B. 1993. Business and society. Ethics and stakeholder management , 3rd ed. Cincinnati:
South-Western.
Caroll, A.B., and A.K. Buchholtz. 2000. Business and society. Ethics and stakeholder management .
Cincinnati: South-Western College Publishing.
Caroll, A., and J. Näsi. 1997. Understanding the stakeholder. Themes from a Finnish conference.
Business Ethics 6(1): 45–51.
Casey, C. 2002. Critical analysis of organizations. Theory, practice, revitalization . Thousand Oaks:
Sage Publications.
Cazal, D. 2011. RSE et Théorie des parties prenantes: les impasses du contrat, Revue de la régulation
, Dossier: RSE, régulation et diversité du capitalisme 9, 1er semestre 2011.
Chabaud, D., J.-M. Glachant, C. Parthenay, and Y. Perez. 2008. Les Grands auteurs en économie des
organisations . Paris: EMS Editions.
Chandler, A. 1962. Strategy and structure: Chapters in the history of the American industrial
enterprise . Cambridge: MIT Press.
Charreaux, G., and P. Wirtz. 2006. Gouvernance des entreprises, Nouvelles Perspectives . Paris:
Economica.
Christopher, M., A. Payne, and D. Ballantyne. 1991. Relationship marketing: Bringing quality,
customer service and marketing together . Oxford: Butterworth-Heineman.
Clarke, T. 1998. The stakeholder corporation. A business philosophy for the information age. Long
Range Planning 31(2): 182–184.
Clarkson, M.B.E. 1995. A stakeholder framework for analyzing and evaluating corporate social
performance. Academy of Management Review 20(1): 92–117.
Clarkson, M.B.E. (ed.). 1998. The corporation and its stakeholders. Classic and contemporary
readings . Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Clegg, S.R. 1979. The theory of power and organization . London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.
Clegg, S.R. 1981. Organization and control. Administrative Science Quarterly 26(4): 545–562.
Cornell, B., and A.C. Shapiro. 1987. Corporate stakeholders and corporate finance. Financial
Management 16(1): 5–14.
Crane, A., and D. Matten. 2007. Business ethics. Managing corporate citizenship and sustainability
in the age of globalization . New York: Oxford University Press.
Cyert, R., and J. March. 1963. A behavioral theory of the firm . Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
D’Aveni, R. 1994. Hypercompetition: Managing the synamics of strategic maneuvering . New York:
Free Press.
D’Aveni, R. 2010. The age of temporary advantage. Strategic Management Journal 31(13): 1371–
1385.
Dery, J. 1996. Analyse bibliographique des écoles en stratégie. Actes de la journée Recherche en
gestion. FNEGE Paris, October 11.
Desreumaux, A. 2005. Théorie des organizations , 2nd ed. Paris: Editions Management & Société.
Desreumaux, A., and P. Selznick. 2009. L’organization comme institution. In Les Grands Auteurs en
Management, eds. S. Charreire Petit and I. Huault. Cormelles-le-Royal: Editions EMS.
Desreumaux, A.A., X. Lecocq, et V. Warnier. 2005, 2006. Stratégie . Harlow: Pearson Education.
Desreumaux, A., X. Lecocq, and V. Warnier. 2006. Stratégie . Paris: Pearson Education.
Dodd, E. 1932. For whom are corporate managers trustees? Harvard Law Review 45(7): 1145–1163.
Donaldson, T. 1989. The ethics of international business . New York: Oxford University Press.
Donaldson, T., and T. Dunfee. 1995. Contractarian business ethics: Current status and next steps.
Business Ethics Quarterly 5(2): 173–186.
Donaldson, T., and T. Dunfee. 1999. Ties that bind. A social contracts approach to business ethics .
Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Dondaldson, T., and L.E. Preston. 1995. The stakeholder theory of the corporation: Concepts,
evidence, and implications. Academy of Management Review 20(1): 65–91.
Dunfee, T.W. 1991. Business ethics and extant social contracts. Business Ethics Quarterly 1(1): 23–
51.
Dyer, J.H., and H. Singh. 1998. The relational view: Cooperative strategy and sources of
interorganizational competitive advantage. Academy of Management Review 23(4): 660–679.
Evan, W.M., and R.E. Freeman. 1988. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian
capitalism. In Ethical theory and business , ed. T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie, 97–106.
Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Evan, W.M., and R.E. Freeman. 1990. Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. Journal
of Behavioral Economics 19: 337–359.
Evan, W.M., and R.E. Freeman. 1993. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian
capitalism. In Ethical theory and business , ed. T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie. Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice Hall.
Ferguson, A. 1996[1767]. An essay on the history of civil society . Cambridge: Cambridge Texts in
the History of Political Thought.
Fisher, R., and W. Ury. 1981. Comment réussir une négociation . Paris: Seuil, 1982.
Fisher, R., and W. Ury. 1982. Getting to yes. Negotiation agreement without giving in . London:
Hutchinson, 1981.
Freeman, R.E. 1981. Business ethics. In The state of the art, ed. R. Edward Freeman. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Freeman, R.E. 1984. Strategic management. A stakeholder approach . Boston: Pitman Publishing.
Freeman, R.E. 1993. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian capitalism. In Ethical
theory and business , ed. T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
Freeman, R.E. 1994. The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics
Quarterly 4(4): 409–422.
Freeman, R.E. 1999. Divergent stakeholder theory. Academy of Management Review 24(2): 233–236.
Freeman, R.E. 2010. Stakeholder theory. The state of the art . Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Freeman, R.E., and W. Evan. 1990. Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. Journal of
Behavioral Economics 19: 337–359.
Freeman, R.E., and J. Mcvea. 2001. A stakeholder approach to strategic management. In The
Blackwell handbook of strategic management , ed. M.A. Hitt, R.E. Freeman, and J. Harrison, 189–
207. Oxford: Basil Blackwel.
Freeman, R.E., and D.R. Gilbert. 1987. Managing stakeholder relationships. In Business and society:
Dimensions of conflict and cooperation , ed. S.P. Sethi and C.M. Falbe, 397–423. Lexington:
Lexington Books.
Freeman, R.E., and R.A. Phillips. 2002. Stakeholder theory. A libertarian defense. Business Ethics
Quarterly 12(3): 331–349.
Freeman, R.E., and D. Reed. 1983. Stockholders and stakeholders: A new perspective on corporate
governance. In Corporate governance: A definitive exploration of the issues , ed. C. Huizinga. Los
Angeles: UCLA Extension Press.
Freeman, R.E., and S.J. Velamuri. 2006. A new approach to CSR: Company stakeholder
responsibility. In Corporate social responsibility: From aspiration to application , eds. M. Morsing
and A. Kakabadse, 9–23. Basingstoke/Hampshire: Palgrave MacMillan Houndsmills.
Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, and A.C. Wicks. 2007. Managing for stakeholders: Survival,
reputation and success . The Business Roundtable Institute for Corporate Ethics Series in Ethics
andLead. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, A.C. Wicks, B.L. Parma, and S. De Colle. 2010. Stakeholder theory:
The state of the art . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gibson, K. 2000. The moral basis of stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics 26(3): 245–257.
Gioia, D.A. 1986. The state of the art in organizational social cognition: A personal view. In The
thinking organization , ed. H.P. Sims and D.A. Gioia, 336–356. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Gioia, D.A., and E. Pitre. 1990. Multiparadigm perspectives on theory building. Academy of
Management Review 15(4): 584–602.
Gomez, P.-Y., and H. Korine. 2009. L’Entreprise dans la démocratie. Une théorie politique du
gouvernement des entreprises . Louvain-la-Neuve: De Boeck Université.
Goodpaster, K. 1991. Business ethics and stakeholder analysis. Business Ethics Quarterly 1: 53–73.
Granovetter, M. 1985. Economic action and social structure: The problem of embeddedness.
American Journal of Sociology 91: 481–510.
Hafsi, T., and A.C. Martinet. 2007. The strategic decision-making process in state owned enterprises.
Gestion 32(3): 88–98.
Hardy, C. 1985. The nature of unobtrusive power. The Journal of Management Studies 22(4): 384–
399.
Hardy, C. 1995. Managing strategic change: Power, paralysis and perspective. Advances in Strategic
Management 12: 3–31.
Hasenclever, A., P. Mayer, and V. Rittberger (eds.). 1983. Theories of international regimes .
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hatchuel, A., and B. Segrestin. 2012. Refonder l’entreprise . Paris: Seuil, La République des Idées.
Hendry, J. 2001a. Missing the target: Normative stakeholder theory and the corporate governance
debate. Business Ethics Quarterly 11(1): 159–176.
Hendry, J. 2001b. Economic contracts versus social relationships as a foundation for normative
stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics 10(3): 223–232.
Heath, J., and A. Potter. 2004. The Rebel Sell. How the counterculture became consumer culture .
London: Capstone.
Hegel, G.W. 1820. Elements of the philosophy of right . Cambridge: Cambridge Texts in the History
of Political Thought, 1991.
Helfat, C., S.W. Finkelstein, M. Mitchell, M. Peteraf, H. Singh, D. Teece, and S. Winter. 2007.
Dynamic capabilities: Understanding strategic change in organizations . Malden: Blackwell
Publishing.
Hickson, D.J., C.R. Hinings, C.A. Lee, R.E. Schneck, and J.M. Pennings. 1971. A strategic
contingencies’ theory of interorganizational power. Administrative Science Quarterly 16: 151–196.
Hill, C.W.L., and T.M. Jones. 1992. Stakeholder-agency theory. Journal of Management Studies
29(2): 131–154.
Hitt, C.W.L., R.E. Freeman, and J.S. Harrison. 2001. The Blackwell handbook of strategic
management . Oxford: Blackwell.
Hofer, C.W., and D.E. Schendel. 1996. Strategy formulation: Analytical concepts . Saint-Paul: West
Publishing.
Holt, D.B. 2002. Why do brands cause trouble? A dialectical theory of consumer culture and
branding. Journal of Consumer Research 29: 70–90.
Hosseini, J.C., and S.N. Brenner. 1992. The stakeholder theory of the firm: A methodology to
generate value matrix weights. Business Ethics Quarterly 2(2): 99–119.
Hummels, H. 1998. Organizing ethics: A stakeholder debate. Journal of Business Ethics 17(13):
1403–1419.
Jarniou, J. 1981. L’entreprise comme système politique . Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Jensen, M.C. 2000. Value maximization and the corporate objective function. In Breaking the code of
change , ed. M. Beer and N. Nohria, 37–58. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Jensen, M.C. 2001. Value maximization, stakeholder theory and the corporate objective function.
Business Ethics Quarterly 12(2): 235–256.
Jensen, M.C., and W.H. Meckling. 1976. Theory of the firm: Management behavior, agency cost and
ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics 3(4): 305–360.
Jones, T.M. 1995. Instrumental stakeholder theory: A synthesis of ethics and economics. Academy of
Management Review 20(2): 404–437.
Jones, T.M., and A.C. Wicks. 1999. Convergent stakeholder theory. Academy of Management Review
24(2): 206–221.
Keeley, M. 1998. A social contract theory of organizations . New York: Notre-Dame University
Press.
Keohane, R.O., and J.S. Nye. 1977. Power and interdependence: World politics in transition .
Boston: Little Brown.
Knox, S., and C. Gruar. 2007. The application of stakeholder theory to relationship marketing
strategy. Development in a non-profit organization. Journal of Business Ethics 75: 115–135.
Kochan, T.A., and S.A. Rubinstein. 2000. Toward a stakeholder theory of the firm: The Saturn
partnership. Organization Science 11(4): 367–386.
Krippendorf, E. 1973. Peace research and the industrial revolution. Journal of Peace Research 10(3):
185–201.
Langtry, B. 1994. Stakeholders and the moral responsibilities of business. Business Ethics Quarterly
4: 431–443.
Laplume, A.O., K. Sonpar, and R.A. Lits. 2008. Stakeholder theory: Reviewing a theory that moves
us. Journal of Management 34(6): 1152–1189.
Learned, E.P., C.R. Christensen, K.R. Andrews, and W.D. Guth. 1965. Business policy, text and cases
. Homewood: Irwin.
Lépineux, F. 2005. Stakeholder theory, society and social cohesion. Corporate Governance 5(2): 99–
110.
MacMillan, I.C. 1978. Strategy formulation: Political concepts . St. Paul: West.
Martinet, A.-C. 1990. Épistémologie de la stratégie. In Épistémologie et sciences de gestion , ed. A.-
C. Martinet et al. Paris: Economica.
Martinet, A.-C. 2006. Parties prenantes, management stratégique et politique. In eds. M. Bonnafous-
Boucher and Y. Pesqueux. Paris: Editions La Découverte, Recherche.
Martinet, A.-C., and E. Reynaud. 2001. Shareholders, stakeholders et stratégie. Revue Française de
Gestion , (November–December), 12–25 .
Marcoux, A.M. 2000. Balancing act. In Contemporary issues in business ethics , ed. Desjardins J. R.
et Mccall J. J. (dir.), 4e édition, 92–100. Wadsworth: Belmont.
Mercier, S. 2006. La théorie des parties prenantes: une synthèse de la littérature. In Décider avec les
parties prenantes, eds. M. Bonnafous-Boucher and Y. Pesqueux. Paris: Editions La Découverte,
Recherche series.
Meyer, J.W., and B. Rowan. 1977. Institutionalized organizations: Formal structure as myth and
ceremony. American Journal of Sociology 83(2): 340–363.
Miller, R.L., and W.F. Lewis. 1991. A stakeholder approach to marketing management using the
value exchange model. European Journal of Marketing 25(8): 55–68.
Mintzberg, H. 1979. The structuring of organizations: A synthesis of the research . Trans. 1982,
Structure et dynamique de organizations . Paris: Editions d’Organisation.
Mintzberg, H. 1983. Power in and around organizations. Trans.: Le Pouvoir dans les organizations .
Paris: Ed d’Organisation.
Mintzberg, H., B. Ahlstrand, and J. Lampel. 1998. Strategy safari . New York: The Free Press.
Mitchell, R.K., B.R. Agle, and D.S. Wood. 1997. Toward a theory of stakeholder identification and
salience: Defining the principle of who and what really counts. Academy of Management Review
22(4): 853–866.
Moore, G. 1999. Tinged shareholder theory: Or what’s so special about stakeholders? Business
Ethics: A European Review 8(2): 117–127.
Narayan, V.K., and L. Fahey. 1982. The micro-politics of strategy formulation. Academy of
Management Review 7(1): 25–34.
Näsi, J. 1995. What is stakeholder thinking? A snapshot of a social theory of the firm. In
Understanding stakeholder thinking , ed. J. Näsi, 19–32. Helsinki: LSR-Julkaisut Oy.
Nicolini, D., S. Gherardi, and D. Yanow. 2003. Introduction: Toward a practice-based view of
knowing and learning in organizations. In Knowing in organizations. A practice-based approach , ed.
D. Nicolini, S. Gherardi, and D. Yanow, 3–31. London: Sharpe.
Orts, E.W., and A. Strudler. 2002. The ethical and environmental limits of stakeholder theory.
Business Ethics Quaterly 12(2): 215–234.
Orts, E.W., and A. Strudler. 2009. Putting a stake in stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quarterly
88: 605–615.
Parrat, F. 1999. Le gouvernement d’entreprise: ce qui a changé, ce qui va évoluer . Paris: Maxime L.
du Mesnil.
Pasquero, J. 1980. L’entreprise face aux pressions sociopolitiques de son environnement . PhD thesis,
Université des sciences sociales de Grenoble, IAE.
Pasquero, J. 2008. Entreprise, Développement durable et Théorie des parties prenantes: esquisse d’un
arrimage socio-constructionniste. Management International 12: 27–47.
Penrose, E. 1959. The theory of the growth of the firm . Oxford: Blackwell.
Pfeffer, J., and G.R. Salancik. 1978. The external control of organization: A resource dependence
perspective . New York: Harper and Row.
Pfeffer, J., and G.R. Salancik. 1981. Power in organizations . Marshfield: Pitman.
Phillips, R. 2003b. Stakeholder theory and organizational ethics . San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler,
Inc.
Phillips, R., and R.E. Freeman. 2010. Stakeholders . Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Phillips, A., and J. Reichart. 2000. The environment as a stakeholder? A fairness-based approach.
Journal of Business Ethics 23: 185–197.
Phillips, R., R.E. Freeman, and A.C. Wicks. 2003. What stakeholder theory is not. Business Ethics
Quarrterly 13(4): 479–502.
Polanyi, K. 1944. The great transformation . New York: Farrar and Rinehart.
Porter, M., and M. Kramer. 2002. The competitive advantage of corporate philanthropy. Harvard
Business Review 80(12): 56–68.
Porter, M., and M. Kramer. 2011. Creating shared value. How to reinvent capitalism – and unleash a
wave of innovation and growth. Harvard Business Review 89(1/2): 62–77.
Post, J.E., L.E. Preston, and S. Sachs. 2002. Redefining the corporation, stakeholder management
and organizational wealth . Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Powell, W.W., and P.J. DiMaggio. 1983. The iron cage revisited: Functional isomorphism and
collective rationality in organizational fields. American Journal of Sociology 48(2): 147–160.
Powell, W.W., and P.J. DiMaggio (eds.). 1991. The new institutionalism in organizational analysis .
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Preston, L.E., and J.E. Post. 1975. Private management and public choice: The principle of public
responsibility . Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Roper, S., and G. Davies. 2007. The corporate brand: Dealing with multiple stakeholders. Journal of
Marketing Management 23(1–2): 75–90.
Rousseau, J.-J. 1762a. Émile ou De l’éducation . In Œuvres complètes IV. Paris: La Pléiade.
Rousseau, J.-J. 1762b. Du contrat social ou Essai sur la forme de la république . In Œuvres
complètes III. Paris: La Pléiade.
Rousseau, J.-J. 1771. Manuscrit de Genève . In Œuvres complètes III. Paris: La Pléiade.
Rousseau, J.-J. 1775. Discours sur l’origine de l’inégalité parmi les hommes. In Œuvres complètes
III. Paris: La Pléiade.
Rowley, L. 1997. Moving beyond dyadic ties: A network theory of stakeholder influences. Academy
of Management Review 22(4): 887–910.
Rustin, M. 1997. Stakeholding and the public sector. In Stakeholder capitalism , ed. G. Kelly, D.
Kelly, and A. Gamble. London: MacMillan.
Sachs, S., and E. Ruhli. 2011. Stakeholders matter. A new paradigm for strategy in society .
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Savage, G.T., T.H. Nix, C.J. Whitehead, and J.D. Blair. 1991. Strategies for assessing and managing
organizational stakeholders. Academy of Management Executive 5(2): 61–75.
Scheppele, K.L. 1993. It’s just not right: The ethics of insider trading. Law and Contemporary
Problems 56(3): 123–173.
Schwenk, C.R. 1989. Linking cognition, organizational and political factors in exploring strategic
change. Journal of Management Studies 26(2): 177–187.
Scott, R.W. 1987. Organizations, rational, natural and open systems . Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-
Hall.
Schleifer, A., and R.W. Vishnhy. 1997, Jun. A survey of corporate governance. The Journal of
Finance 52(2): 737–783.
Smith, A. 1982[1759]. In The theory of moral sentiments, eds. D.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie.
London: Liberty Fund.
Solomon, R.C. 1993. Ethics and excellence. Cooperation and integrity in business . Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Somech, A., and A. Drach-Zahavy. 2002. Relative power and influence strategy: The effects of
agent/target organizational power on superiors’ choices of influence strategies. Journal of
Organizational Behavior 23(2): 167–178.
Starik, M. 1994. Essays by Mark Starik . Toronto conference: Reflections on Stakeholder Theory.
Business and Society 33:82–131.
Stewart, G.B. 1994. EVA: Fact and fantasy. Journal of Applied Corporate Finance 7(2): 71–84.
Tabatoni, P., and P. Jarniou. 1975. Les systèmes de gestion: politiques et structures . Paris: PUF.
Taylor, C. 1989. Sources of the self . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Thomson, J.K., S.L. Wartick, and H.L. Smith. 1991. Integrating corporate social performance and
stakeholder management: Implication for a research agenda in small business. Research in Corporate
Social Performance and Policy 12: 207–230.
Tichy, N.M., A.R. McGill, and L. Saint-Clair. 1997. Corporate global citizenship, doing business in
the public eye . San Francisco: The New Lexington Press.
Tsoukas, H., and C. Knudsen. 2003. The Oxford handbook of organization theory . Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Venkataraman, S. 2002. Stakeholder value equilibration and the entrepreneurial process. In Ethics
and entrepreneurship, eds. R.E. Freeman and S. Venkataraman, 45–57. Charlottesville: Ruffin Series,
Philosophy Documentation Center.
von Bertalanffy, Ludwig. 1951. General system theory. A new approach to unity of science
(symposium). Human Biology 23: 303–361.
von Bertalanffy, Ludwig. 1968. General system theory: Foundations, development, applications .
New York: George Braziller.
Walzer, M. 1992. Moral minimalism. In The Twilight of probability: Ethics and politics , ed. W.R.
Shea and G.A. Spadafora, 3–14. Canton: Science History Publications.
Wartick, S.L., and P.L. Cochran. 1985. The evolution of the corporate social performance model.
Academy of Management Review 10(4): 758–769.
Wernerfelt, B. 1984. A resource-based view of the firm. Strategic Management Journal 5(2) (April–
June): 171–180.
Westwood, R., and S.R. Clegg. 2003. The problem of order revisited: Towards a more critical
institutional perspective. Debating Organization . Oxford: Blackwell.
Wheeler, D., and M. Sillanpää. 1997. The stakeholder corporation. The body shop blue print for
maximizing stakeholder value . London: Pitman Publishing.
Wicks, A.C., and T.M. Jones. 1999. Convergent stakeholder theory. Academy of Management Review
24(2): 206–221.
Wicks, A., R.E. Freeman, and P.H. Werhane. 2009. Business ethics: A managerial approach .
Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Wicks, A.C., D.R. Gilbert, and R.E. Freeman. 1994. A feminist reinterpretation of the stakeholder
concept. Business Ethics Quarterly 4(4): 475–497.
Williamson, O. 1985. The economic institutions of capitalism . New York: The Free Press.