We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 19
UNIT ETHICS AND THE
|] MORALPERSON
cHapTeR J se Concepts
W; cannot but encounter moral questions and issues in our life, since the actions
that we do are bound to affect ourselves and other people cither positively or
negatively. We inevitably face choices that may benefit or harm other people. Our actions
may promote the welfare of other people, just as they may inftinge on theit rights and
violate their dignity.
Everyone of us at one time or another has experienced asking about what the morally
right thing to do is, or more generally about what things should be valued. Some of our
moral questions may be straightforwardly practical (Should we take away a scholarship
granc from an underprivileged student due to a low grade she incurred? Is it right to
deceive a friend to spare him from a certain risk2) or more abstract (What is the ultimate
good? What is justice? Is morality relative?) Some moral questions we have may concern
our own actions (Should I reveal the truth? Should I give to this charity?) or deal with the
actions of others (Was it morally permissible for the President to make those remarks?
Should the government legalize divorce?) These questions, which vary in kinds, are the
concerns of a particular branch of philosophy called ethics. This philosophical discipline
basically deals with humanity's inquiries about right conduct, the good life, moral values,
and other related issues.
As rational beings, we are capable of acting freely rather than merely driven by instinct.
(Our actions are preceded by an understanding of the value of such acts, their consequence,
and their rightness or wrongness. And because of our rationality, we are inclined to think
about and try to understand the basis of what we believe in, or what we should pursue in
life. We do not want to simply depend on what authorities say or what social conventions
and norms prescribe as right and wrong. As Socrates once said, “The unexamined life is
not worth living.” In the same spirit of this classical statement, it can also be said that the
‘morally examined life is truly worth living. Icis, indeed, worthwhile to engage in ethics for
it provides us with the opportunity to look into the reasons and justifications behind our
own actions and the actions of others, the bases and principles of our decision-making,
and the goals of our moral life in order to find clearer answers to the various moral issues
and problems that we encounter in life.
However, before we tackle the practical questions of ethics, we must first clarify the
fundamental concepts and issues we often encounter in moral discourses. Before we
venture into analyzing and resolving particular moral problems and cases, we need to be
ioe Theorie snd Appllons| Val 1fear regarding certain questions that underlie our moral views and judgments: What is
the nature of morality? What is the good and how will we know it Are sal principles
objective, or are they relative to culture or individual decision? What relationship does
morality have with religion, law, and etiquette? Addressing these questions will provide
usa basic framework for understanding the foundation and seructure of morality. Only
then can we proceed to profitably discuss the various moral issues affecting our life and
our world today.
A. What is Ethics?
Ethics has been understood by peopl in different ways. Its also sometimes confused
With morality, as these two concepts are often loosely interchanged with each other
‘Thus: i is important that we is clarify whae ethics means o that we ean nce hang
differs from morality, what particular questions are raised in ethics, and wha subject
areas are under or overlap with ethics.
Ethics and Morality
Lat us first attempr to inquire on the meaning of morality. When we speak of morality, we refer
to the set of standards a person has about what is tight and wrong, How we judge whether
an ac is good or bad, whether someone is virtuous or not, whether we ought to do this or
Hag, depends largely on these standards. Ie is fr this reason we can say that people can have
diferent morality; tha is, we can have diffrent standards, views, of perspectives by which
we understand what is right and wrong, Such differences =
«an be attributed to how our moral standards originate.
Asa child, each person has been taught and influenced
by his/her family, friends, and clders to accept some
actions of behaviors as right and some as wrong. The
church and the school the person went to, the books he!
she read, the films he/she watched, the organizations he/
she joined, contributed to the formation of one’s basic
ideas of morality. Since people vary in terms of the social
influences that we have in life, wealso differ in he morality
we espouse. Some people think that homosexual marriage
should be allowed, while others believe i is wrong, Some
{gard death penalty as immoral while others think iis morally justified. Our judgments and
bie on hese matters are influenced by the moral sandards that pervade in ou
[Lara however, pertains not just co person's standards, but toa particular socieeys
ht and wrong, As a socal, cultural, or religious group, people share
“ors that guide them in what they accept or practice. In
Islamic societies, Muslims refrain from eating pork; in some European soiree, homered
relationships are acceprable: in Eskimos communities, infanticide ik permisible Thee ve
Social norms that pervade in every society tha serve asthe basis ofits members wo decide ne
what ic right oF wrong,
Mother reading her cide
2 Chapter | ahi: Bae Conese ad uesGiven this understanding of wha morality is, how does ethics differ from morality?
‘Although sometimes used to refer to one’s set of moral beliefs and practices, strictly
speaking, ethics is the discipline that examines the moral standards of an individual or a
society. In a sense, ethics is a study of morality. It looks into the soundness, reasonableness,
and appropriateness of the moral standards a person or a society espouses. It is one thing to
accept or adopr a set of moral standards, it is another thing co reflect on and examine these
standards. Thus, a person engages in ethics when helshe reflects on the moral standards
he/she has imbibed from his/her family, church, and friends, and asks: “Are these standards,
reasonable? Are these practices morally permissible? Are we justified to do this or that?"
‘As mentioned above, morality begins to form in childhood, which isa time when we
usually unquestioningly and mechanically accepe what is taught co us with regard to what
is right and wrong. Thus, itis important that, as we mature in reason, we subject our moral
beliefs and practices to a reflective analysis. We ought to question those moral standards
that we simply acquired in the past without any critical inquiry. We need ro espouse only
those standards which are supported by good reasons. It is here where the enterprise of
ethics comes in, Just as what other philosophical disciplines do, it invites us to exercise
self-awareness and self-criticism with regard to our own fundamental views and beliefs
about morality
In guiding us in evaluating our own moral beliefs and standards, ethics aims to shed light
con the basic questions such as what is right conduct, what principles should govern our moral
decision-making, and what basically is a good life, Ethics is not limited to particular moral
actions and practices, but it concerns itself with the whole of moral ideals and behaviors.
Areas of Ethies
‘As a branch of philosophy that examines and reflects about morality, ethics is usually
categorized into three general subject areas: metacthics, normative ethies, and applied
ethics. Metaethies, also known as analytic ethics, looks into the nature, meaning, scope,
and foundations of moral values and discourses. The term “meta” means afier or beyond;
and, thus, metaethics involves an abstract and detached way of thinking philosophically
about morality. It ateempts to shed light on the basic ideas, concepts, and assumptions
that underlie our moral beliefs and judgments. If the other two areas focus directly on
the question what is moral, metaethics focuses on the more fundamental question what
‘morality ielf isin the first place. For this reason, meraethics is also occasionally referred
to as “second-order” moral theorizing, to distinguish it from che “Atst-order" level of
normative theory.
The first part of this book is devoted to metaethics as it inquires about fundamental
{queries on morality—What is the nature of moral claims? How is morality distinct from
‘other normative standards? Is morality objective or relative? Who have moral rights? What
docs it mean to be morally accountable? Metaethical positions respond ro these questions
by examining the basic meanings, ideas and connotations involved in moral discourse
They shed light on issues pertaining to the status of moral beliefs and judgments, the
conditions of moral personhood and accountability, and other concepts that lie underneath
the subject of morality.
able Thesis and Applian | Ue‘Normative ethics, ackled in the second part of the book, is concerned with the moral
standards to determine right from wrong conduct. It involves the formulation of moral
norms or rules that can serve as basis of the kind of actions, institutions, and ways of life
that we should pursue. Theories proposed to answer what moral standards should govern
sm, b)
the three aspects of an action that ate
human action usually fall into three broad categories, namely, a) consequent
deontology, and ¢) virtue ethics. These represe
often considered in judging an action’s moral rightness (or wrongness): its consequences,
the rule it follows (or violates), and the character of the person performing it.
‘The third area of ethics is applied ethics, which isthe subject of the third part of this book. Is
thrusts to examine the particular issues in both the personal and social spheres that are matters of
‘moral judgment. Focusing on the more practical concerns of ethics, it uses philosophical methods
10 determine the moral permissibility of specific actions and practices. By using the conceptual
tools of metaethics and normative ethics, applied ethics artemprs to analyze, cart and shed light
(on various ethical issues with the goal of guiding our moral judgment. Some issues in applied
ethics pertain to public policy and the professions. In recent decades, new specializations in
applied ethics have arisen in diverse fields business, medicine, environmental policies, law, and
the media. Other isues focus on personal concer in everyday life, such as those pertaining to
life, health, sex, and relationship.
Before we delve into the basic concerns of metaethics in this chapter, itis important to
note that chere is another study of morality known as descriptive ethics, however, this is not
considered an area of moral philosophy. Descriptive ethics endeavors to present to us what
people think about right and wrong, how they behave, or how they reason about ethics
‘As such, it incorporates researches from the fields of anthropology, psychology, sociology,
and history as part of the process of understanding the moral norms that people follow
ot believe in, But it is not considered a philosophical study of ethics since it does not aim
to establish what should be the case—what people ought to do, what moral standards
should regulate human acts, how we should view morality. Rather, descriptive ethics aims
to establish what the case is, It attempts co describe or explain the world rather than
prescribe what the world should be. For example, anthropologists tell us that some tribes
in India practice throwing babies from the temple roof 30 to 50 feet high to be caught in a
blanket held by a group of men on the ground. But anthropology, as such, does not try to
determine whether itwas morally right for these tribes to endanger the lives ofthese babies
by throwing them from the temple roof. Ethics, on the other hand, tries to answer the
question of whether such practice is right or wrong. It is not descriptive but normative—ie
asks how people should live, anthropology asks how people in fact live.
Like anthropology, sociology is interested in morality in so far as it wants to find out
the set of moral beliefs and practices that a particular group or society follows. It may
even compare the moral beliefs of one culture to that of another. But it does not seck to
cstablish whether this or that moral belief is sound or not. Psychology studies morality in
terms of its being a component of human development. It attempts to describe how the
person's sense of moral responsibility develops. But while it explains how a person makes
‘moral judgment and what factors affect it, it does not tackle the correctness, cogency, or
defensibility of moral judgments
4 Chaper | Bis: Be Conese lsB. Nature of Moral Statements
To better understand ethics’ normative character as a study of moray,
is important
to understand the nature of claims that pertain to morality which we will label moral
statements. Such clarification is important in understanding how these statements should
be justified or how they should be evaluated as acceprable or unacceptable. This will also
shed light on the difference of morality from law, etiquette, and religion.
Moral Statements as Normative Statements
Moral statements are categorized as normative statements rather than factual statements,
A normative statement expresses a value judgment, a kind of judgment that claims that
something ought to be the case as distinct from a factual judgment that claims that
something és the case. As such, when one makes a normative statement, he/she presents
‘an evaluative account of how things should be rather than what things ave. Thus, we assess
the correctness of normative statements by looking at certain criteria, standards or norms
instead of focusing on empirical data. However, as can be seen in the examples below, aside
from moral statements, there are various kinds of normative statements that have their
corresponding basis of assessment:
You ought to return the excess change to | Moral standard
the cashier. ee pe
There should be unity, balance, and | Aesthetic standard
contrast in your painting, _—_ |
You ought to use the preposition “in” | Grammatical standard |
rather than “on.
Legal standard
| Standard of etiquette
[Ieis illegal to m
Cover your mouth when you laugh.
‘As mentioned above, since a factual statement expresses a claim that something is
the case, its claim can be empirically assessed as true or false based on either research,
observation, or experiment. For example:
| The Philippine Independence day was | Historical research
| declared on June 12, 1946,
| Some tribes in India practice cannibalism, | Observation
The cause of the fish killin the river is | Scientific research - |
pollution from agricultural biotoxins. _| : |
A blue litmus paper will turn red when —_| Experiment |
dipped in an acid solution,
ice Theorie and Applicone| Uae) 5Normative statements differ from factual statements in the way they are justified,
confirmed, or assessed. We appeal to certain standards when we deal with normative
statements. On the other hand, we appeal to the results of research, experi
observation when we deal with factual statements. Itcan be noticed on the above examples
that normative statements are of various kinds, not only those pertaining to morality.
Some pertain to the standards of visual arts, grammar, law, etiquette, religion, exc. We will
elaborate on the distinction of moral statements from these other normative statements
in the next section. Here, we will focus mainly on the normative nature of moral claims.
Since a moral statement is a normative statement rather than a factual one, it cannot
be justified by merely appealing to facts, empirical evidences, or data. Although providing
facts may be significane in justifying a moral claim, this remains insufficient.
Consider the following argument:
According a study of ten countries that enforce the death penalty the rate of criminality
in these countries went down after it has been enforced. Therefore, itis morally right to enforce
the death penalty.
‘The premise supporting the above moral claim is a statement of fact. This statement
is established by gathering statistical data to arrive ata Factual claim, However, co make a
moral conclusion thatimposing the death penalty is right needs more than merely providing,
a factual starement or information. There is a need to connect the factual statement with
the moral conclusion by supplying certain moral standards or principles such as “An act is
right if it promotes the greater good of the people.” Thus, the moral argument should be:
Imposing the death penalty will lnver the rate of criminality in our society and thus will be
beneficial to the greater number of people.
‘An act is right if it promotes the greater good of the greater number.
Therefore, imposing the death penalty is right.
The moral principle (second statement) added as a premise in the argument is not
factual by nature. It was not derived from appealing to research or experiment. But
without citing this moral standard, the fact that death penalty has brought down the rate
of criminality in countries that have imposed it, cannot suffice to justify that death penalty
should be imposed.
This point can be explained
more by stating that though some
people may also accept or agree
with the fact that death penalty
can reduce the rate of criminality
in our society, they still hold that
it is morally wrong to impose the
death penalty as they believe that
the right to life of a human being is
sacred and inviolable. Thus, despite
the greater good to sociery that the
imposition of death penalty may
Peapleexprening ter send on the issue of dash penalty bring about, others would still
regard it as morally unacceptable.We can see here that determining the rightness or wrongness of imposing the
death penalty does not lie only on establishing certain facts but deciding what moral
standards or principles to follow—pursuing the greater good or respecting the human
rights of individuals. One accepts a moral claim not by looking at the facts alone. One
agrees or disagrees with a moral claim on the basis of the moral standard he/she follows
or believes in
Such distinction of factual and moral statements suggests that factual statements are
casier to settle than moral statements, since the basis of the later (for being true or false)
is objective. That is, if there is a disagreement between two people whether the rate of
criminality had gone down this year compared to last year, or whether a drug can cure
a particular disease, the results of scientific research can clearly determine who is correct
and who is mistaken. However, itis said that disagreements on moral claims—whether we
should allow homosexual marriage or not, whether euthanasia is permissible or not—are
more difficuly, if not impossible, o settle or to be given any final resolution. It is for this
reason that moral claims are said to be relative and their acceptability ies on one’s personal
opinion or cultural belief
Although this question of whether moral claims are relative or not will be extensively
discussed in a later section of this chapter, itis worth mentioning at this poine thac i is a
mistake to think chat moral statements are always difficule to justify, and their acceptabili
always subjective to the individual. The claim “Ic is morally wrong to torture a person for fun"
or the assertion “Ic is morally right to give aid to typhoon victims” is not difficult to justify.
Ik s also incorrect to think that issues dealing with factual claims are always easy to resolve or
uncontroversial. Certain factual statements like “Humans evolved from primitive primates.”
“Imposing the death penalty will decer murder,” and “Aliens from other planets have visited the
earth’ are controversial and their truth (or falsity) is not easy to establish. Therefore, we cannot
distinguish moral and factual statements in terms of the degree of difficulty disagreements
about them can be resolved. What is clear, however, isthe basis by which we determine the
acceptability of these statements—for factual statements we appeal to empirical data through
research and observation; for moral statements, like other normative statements, we appeal to
norms and standards.
Moral Statements and Moral Standards
After distinguishing moral from faccual statements, itis now easier to understand the
difference of moral statements from other normative statements. We have seen earlier
that aside from moral statements, there are other statements that are normative, that is,
those that are justified and accepted based on standards rather than facts. However, the
standards used to justify normative statements are not moral standards. The standards of
etiquette by which we judge manners as good or bad, the standards of law by which we
judge an action to be legally right or wrong, the standards of language by which we judge
‘what is grammatically right and wrong, the standards of aesthetics by which we judge
good and bad art, and the athletic standards by which we judge how well a basketball or
a football game is being played—these standards are not moral standards. So how can we
distinguish moral standards from non-moral standards? Addressing this question can shed
hie Thar and Applnions| Une 7light to how different moral statements are from other normative starements, as well as
how distinct morality is from etiquette, law, and rel
Ethicists have identified a number of characteristics that speak of the nature of moral
standards, Although each of these characteristics may not be unique to moral standards,
if taken together, they can distinguish moral standards from non-moral standards. First,
moral standards deal with matters that we think can seriously harm or benefit human
beings. The conventional moral norms against cheating, lying, and killing deal with
actions that can gravely hurt people. Whether human dignity is respected or degraded,
work conditions are safe or dangerous, and products are beneficial or detrimental to our
health are matters that affect human well-being. The standards that govern our conduct in
these areas are moral standards
Second, moral standards have universal validity. They apply to all who are in the
relevantly similar situation. IF it is morally wrong for a person A to do act X, then it is
wrong to do X for anyone relevantly similar to P. This characteristic is exemplified in
the moral rule: “Do not do unto others what you would not have them do unto you.”
If we believe that killing a person is morally wrong, then we expect that people in other
places follow the same belief, regardless of their culture or religion. In comparison, other
standards are only valid to a particular group governed by such standards. The rule on
fasting at certain times is observed in some religions but not to other religions or to non-
believers. Etiquettes such as not wearing red in a funeral or taking off your shoes when
entering a house are practiced in some cultures but not to others.
Third, moral standards are generally thought to have a particularly overriding
importance, that is, people fel they should prevail over other values. A violation of the
moral rule against killing or stealing is more important than a violation of the rules of
etiquette or of grammar. Similarly, a moral judgment weighs more than an aesthetic
judgment, Moral claims are also more important than claims pertaining to law. Thus, laws
are questioned when they are thought to be unjust or are contrary to moral standards.
Moreover, legislators determine what laws to enact on the basis of certain moral principles
such as common good, respect for human dignity, fairness, and justice. This point will be
claborated more in the next section when we discuss morality and law,
Fourth, moral standards are not established by the decisions of authoritarian bodies,
nor are they solely determined by appealing to consensus or tradition. While laws and legal
standards are established by the authority of the legislature, religious beliefs and practices
are taught by the Church fathers and scholars, rules of etiquette emanate from tradition
and consensus, moral standards, however, are not established by a particular authority.
Instead, the validity of moral standards lies on the adequacy of reasons that support or
justify them. So long as these reasons are adequate, the standards remain valid.
Guided by these characteristics of moral standards, let us look into how, in particular,
morality differs from law, etiquette, and religion. These three are often identified with
morality, since these are also institutions and customs that lay down certain norms that
serve as our basis in determining what we ought to do and not do.
8 Chapter | tice Bae Congr and antC. Morality and Other Normative Subjects
Morality and Etiquette
Etiquette refers to the set of rules or customs that determine the accepted behaviors in
a particular social group. Following these rules makes us show respect and courtesy to
others. In eating out, for example, one should wait until all the people on the table have
been served before he/she starts eating, Of course, chere ate vatious areas in our social life
where our courtesy to others is expected. Aside from dining, we have etiquette at certain
‘occasions such as baptism and funeral, we have etiquette on riding a public transportation,
doing business, and even communicating (thus, we need to also observe certain rules in
the more modern ways of communicating such as sending emails and posting in social
media.) But these so-called rules of etiquette vary from one culture to another. What may
be an accepted behavior in one culture may not be in another.
uette is differenc from morality in that the former is concerned with proper
behavior while the latter with right conduct. Etiquette is also more arbitrary and culeure-
based than morality. To get others’ approval of our action, to be thought of well by people,
and to show respect to them, we try to observe common rules of etiquette. Violating the
rules can lead society to consider you ill-mannered, impolite, o even uncivilized—but not
nccessarily immoral, Making loud slurping sound when taking noodles or not closing your
mouth as you chew your food may result to being called impolite or being perceived as
lacking in manner, but they are not basis for claiming that one is acting immorally.
In the same way, it does not necessarily mean that following what etiquette demands is
acting morally. Shaw (2002) pointed out that scrupulous observance of rules of etiquette can
camouflage moral issues, Before the laws against racial discrimination were enacted in the
America, it was thought that itis bad manners for blacks and whites to eat together of to sit
side by side in a bus. But for one who believed that such rule of etiquette is rooted in racial
discrimination and human degradation, promoting or simply conforming to such rule does not
amount to doing the moral thing. Such was the point shown by a 42-year-old black woman
named Rose Parks when she was asked to give up her seat for a white man and refused. Though
she may not comply with the social expectation, she stood her ground knowing that she has not
done anything immoral. On the contrary, she believed she was doing the morally right thing to
do as she fought for equality and fairness
Though morality and etiquette are not synonymous with each other, there is a
relationship between the two since both concern human action. For example, distegarding
or scorning etiquette can be considered immoral in certain circumstances. There can be
different ways of greeting a person among various cultures. In Japan people greet each
other by bowing, and their bows differ in angle and duration depending on the person
they are greeting, In Oman, men greet cach other by pressing their noses together. In
Thailand, people greet each other by pressing their hands together in the fashion of a
prayer and slightly bowing their heads. But as pointed out by Pojman (1999), once the
custom is adopted, the practice rakes on the importance of a moral rule, subsumed under
hice Theor and Appleton | Uniethe wider principle of showing respect to people. In Islamic societies, standards of modesty
call for a woman to cover her body, particularly her chest. Thus, some Muslim women
‘wear hijab ora scarf that covers the head and neck and falls below the level ofthe shoulders
to cover the upper chest area. Muslims who follow this practice believe that it protects
women's dignity and promote modesty. Although there is nothing immoral for a non-
‘Muslim woman to wear sleeveless blouse or skimpy clothes, appearing in such an outtit in
a Maslim community may well be so offensive that ic is morally insensitive or scandalous.
Morality and Law
Like etiquette, law also regulates human conduct, which is why it is often confused with
‘morality. We ought nor to exploit the weak, deceive another person, or take what is not
ous because these acts are morally and legally wrong. The moral imperative nor to kill a
person coincides with the legal imperative not to commit murder or homicide.
Law and morality, however, are different. Breaking the law is not always an immoral ac,
just as following the law is not necessarily doing what is morally right. Let us take an example to
illustrate this point. Suppose your mother suffered a heart attack and she needed to be brought
to the hospital immediately. You took her in your car and rushed her to the hospital driving
at a speed of 100 kph. Although you are prohibited by law to drive at more than 60 kph on
that road, it does not seem morally right for you to follow the law and drive at that speed limie
knowing that doing so will jeopardize th life of your mother. Driving the car at that speed may
break the law, buc is morally right.
It can also be said chat an action that is legal can be morally wrong. For instance,
abortion may be legal ina particular country, but the question whether itis morally right
to commit an abortion remains an issue; thus, some of its citizens may stage a protest
or demonstration urging the state to respect the right co life of the unborn. Or when
Janet Napoles, the alleged mastermind behind the Priority Development Assistance
Fund (PDAF) scams, repeatedly invoked the right to self-incrimination, thus evading the
questions and being mum on what she knew about the politicians who were involved
in corruption, It may be legal to remain silent rather than to tell the truth, but such act
jeopardizes truth and justice, and thus is morally questionable. In those cases, itis clear
thar certain actions may be in accordance to the law, but not morally right.
Despite their differences, how are law and morality related to each other? We can say
thac in many cases, laws are based on morality. We determine what laws to adopt or enact
‘on the basis of certain moral principles. RA 9211 or the Tobacco Regulation Act of 2003
which prohibits people from smoking in public places is based on the moral principle of
the greater good for the greater number. Since law is derived from morality, people tend
{to equate what is lawful with what is moral. To a significant degree, law codifies a society's
als and values. But we should not see whar is lawful and what is moral as identical
for, as pointed out by Shaw (2002), “law cannot cover the wide variety of possible individual
and group conduct, and in many situations it is too blunt an instrument to provide moral
guidance.” (p. 6). Laws may be enacted, amended, or repealed by legislators to protect their
vested interests, and may not really be beneficial to the general welfare. One may wonder
why the Anti-Political Dynasty bill which aims to remove che concentration of political
10 Chapter | eh: Bac Conceal oespower within a particular clan has been proposed in the Philippine Congress several times
already, but has not gotten the nod of the legislators. It can be surmised that enacting such
law will be detrimental to the interests of those political personalities in the Congress.
Morality and Religion
Despite their difference, morality is often identified with religion. In various societies
around the world, religion has so much influenced the moral life of the people so as to be
seen as indistinguishable from morality. A Christian forgiving those who offended him!
her mindfal of Christ's commandment of love; a Jew preparing and consuming food based
on the law of Kosher; a Muslim giving alms co the needy according to the fourth pillar of
Islam—these moral practices of most of humanity throughout the ages are testaments to
how morality has become identified with conformity to God’s command,
Indeed, religion, like law, is related to morality. But unlike law which is often based
‘on morality, religion is generally perceived to be the basis of morality. People tend to
think that what is right can be derived from religious beliefs and teachings. Because this
line of thinking is anchored on the idea that God is the source of goodness, living a
moral life, then, is achieved by adhering to God’ will, while acting immorally is basically
disobeying God.
But should morality be based on religion? This question was asked in as early as Plato's
the Euthyphro, in which Socrates asks the pious Euthyphto, “Do the gods love goodness
because it is good, or is it good because the gods love it?” Following the point of question
raised by Socrates, we want to know whether God commands what is good because it is
good, or whether the good is good because God commands it. Although religion gives
‘moral basis and direction to people, thinking that morality depends on religion raise some
problems.
First, he moral directives given by the world’s great religions are general and imprecise.
People encounter moral dilemmas in particular situations or contexts that demand specific
‘moral precept. For example, Christianity teaches its believers “Thou shale not kill.” Howeve
even with such directive, there remains a disagreement among Christians whether impos
death penalty is morally justified, or whether legalizing abortion is morally permissible, ot
whether administering euthanasia to 2 patient in an irreversible vegetative state is morally
right. These moral situations cannot be resolved by a general moral admonition not to kill.
There are certain specific issues and factors that must be considered which have a lot of
‘weight in determining whether an act is good or bad. The Bible fails to give unambiguous
answers to specific moral problems humanity confronts. What do religions say regarding
‘more complex yet specific moral issues of today’s world such as artificial reproduction,
genetic engineering or the use of animals in research? We will remain inquiring what God
expects us to do.
Second, can we really be certi
what God wants us to do? We know that there
are different religions the world over. These religions may vary in terms of their moral
doctrines and practices. There are cases when they have conflicting answers to certain
‘moral questions. If one depends on the moral teachings of the religion he/she belongs
to, how can he/she deal with the moral beliefs of people from other religions especially
hie Teas Aplccons| Uae 1when they conflice with his/her own moral belief? There should be a basis of morality
that transcends religious boundaries, lest we fail to carry out an objective rational moral
discussion with people from other religions.
Third, as rational beings we are doing ourselves a disservice if we simply base our
judgmenc of right and wrong on what our religion dictates. We ought not to think or
reason anymore if morality is dependent on the teachings of the Church, We merely have
to know what our religion says about a certain moral issue and conform to it. But are we
leading a rational life if this is how we view morality? What is our faculty of reason for?
‘This point becomes more pronounced when we find ourselves in certain times when what
wwe believe to be right (or wrong) does not conform to the church stand on the issue. In the
past, the Catholic Church’s stand on the persecution of heretics, the Crusade movement,
and the Inquisition have been questioned even by its own members. Its view on homosexual
relationship and artificial contraception may not find support to all Catholics. Although
‘we are not saying that the Church's teachings on these matters are unsound or wrong, it
is important ro understand that an authentic sense of morality must not merely rely on
religion. Indeed, religion can guide us in making moral judgment and leading a moral
life, bur morality should transcend religion. Ultimately, itis a matter of reason rather than
mere adherence to religion.
D. The Issue of Ethical Relativism
[As mentioned in the previous section, the moral beliefs and practices of people are greatly
influenced by the environment that surrounds them. How the individual was brought up
and the social and cultural elements that the person was exposed to contribute to his/her
understanding and judgment of what is right and wrong. Given such phenomena, can we
conclude that morality is relative, that is, what is right varies from one person to another
of from one culture to another? Or is morality objective, that is, what is tight is based on
universal principle that applies to all people regardless of culture, religion, of ideology?
‘This is one major meta-ethical issue in philosophy which this section will address.
‘The view which holds thar all moral principles are valid relative to a particular society ot
individual, is called ethical relativism. Its to be distinguished from ethical skepticism —which
claims that there are no valid moral principles at all (or at least we cannot know whether
there are any)—and from ethical objectivism which asserts that there are universally valid
‘moral principles binding on all people. According to the relatvist perspective, the rightness
lor wrongness of an act depends on the moral norms of society or the moral inclinations of
the individual, and no absolute standard exists by which differing rules or inclinations can be
judged. So, what is morally right for a Chinese society may be morally wrong in an American
society, just as what is morally right for Pedro might be morally wrong for Juan.
From this description, we can infer that there are two forms of ethical relativism:
cultural ethical relativism and individual ethical relativism. According to the former, also
known as ethical conventionalism, the rightness or wrongness of an action depends on
society's norms. According to the latter, also known as ethical subjectivism, the tightness
‘or wrongness of an action lies on the individual's own commitments. Of the «wo,
12 Chapter | hice Base Concept and ae