Nino, Some Confusions Around Kelsen's Concept of Validity
Nino, Some Confusions Around Kelsen's Concept of Validity
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/23679244?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Franz Steiner Verlag is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to ARSP: Archiv für Rechts- und
Sozialphilosophie / Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen's
Concept of Validity*
show how it deals with issues with which its notion of validity is errone
ously supposed to be primarily connected.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
358 Carlos Santiago Nino
justification of the law, with the following very general propositions: (a)
To predícate validity of a legalsystem, or a particular legal rule, was to
assert that it had binding force; that its prescriptions constitute conclu
sse reasons for action, (b) When the validity of a legal System, or of a
legal rule, was contested, this was tantamount to denying its existence,
since the lack of validity was taken to imply that the system, or the rule,
did not have the normative conséquences that it stipulâtes (for instance,
if the invalid rule prohibits a certain action, the action would not be,
thereby, prohibited; the rule would be as ineffectuai for establishing
normative relationships as if it had not been enacted). (c) Even when
the ascription of validity might be dépendent on certain facts (for some
conceptions, the effîcacy of the system was a necessary or even a suffi
cient condition for that ascription) the meaning of "validity" was not
descriptive but normative; to say that a system or a particular legal rule
was valid was to endorse it, to maintain that its application and observ
ance was obligatory and justified (this feature of the traditional notion
of validity permits us to hold that the différent authors whose views I
am taking into account, employed the same concept of validity, in spite
of their wide discrepancies on the criteria for ascribing validity).
It seems clear to me that these features are présent in Kelsen''s notion
of validity. The following paragraphs are directed to justify this con
tention, showing that Kelsen's theory, like traditional philosophical
accounts of law, equates the validity of the law with its binding force
and its existence, and that it conceives of the ascription of validity as a
normative judgement.
say that a norm is valid is to say that we assume its existence or — what
amounts to the same - we assume that it has force' for
thing 'binding
those whose behaviour it régulâtes." On the next page Kelsen distin
guishes legal norms from commands, asserting that only legal norms,
enacted by organs authorized to do so, oblige the individuáis to whom
they are directed.
On p. 8 of the Pure Theory ofLaws Kelsen says: "The legislative act,
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions aroundKelsen's Concept of Validity 359
which subjectively has the meaning of ought also has the objective
— that is the of a valid norm — because the constitu
meaning meaning
tion has conferred this meaning upon the legislative act. The act whose
meaning is the constitution has not only the subjective but also the ob
jective meaning of ought, that is to say the character of a binding norm;
if — in case — it is the historically firstconstitution, we présupposé in our
juristic thinking that we ought to behave as the constitution prescribes."
In the same work, on p. 15,Kelsen writes: "To say that the behaviour of
The first quotation of the foregoing section shows also this feature of
Kelsen's notion of validity; even more clearly, that phrase is preceded by
the following remark: "By validity we mean the specific existence of
norms." On p. 48 of the same work (the General Theory of Law and
State) Kelsen asserts: "The existence of legal norms is its validity; and
the validity of a legal norm, although not identical with certain facts, is
conditioned by them." Later on (p. 170) Kelsen says: "... normative
jurisprudence asserts the validity of a norm, and that means its existen
ce."
In the Pure Theory ofLaw there are similar remarks, but there is also
an interesting explanation of what is involved in the identification be
tween the binding force of a norm and its existence: "It is, however,
meaning, and only if the act of will has also the objective meaning of an
ought, is this ought called a 'norm'. If the ought is also the objective
meaning of the act, the behaviour at which the act is directed is regarded
as something that ought to be not only from the point of view of the in
dividual who has performed the act, but also from the point of view of
the individual to whose behaviour the act is directed, and of a third indi
vidual not involved in the relation between the two" (p. 7).
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
360 Carlos Santiago Nino
validity, for, until the normative character that Kelsen ascribes to this
instance, on p. 193 of the Pure Theory Kelsen says: "A norm referring to
the behaviour of a human being is 'valid' means that it is binding - that
an individual ought to behave in the manner determined by the norm. It
has been pointed out in an earlier that the question why a norm
contextj
is valid, why an individual ought to behave in a certain way, cannot be
answered by ascertaining a fact, that is by the statement that something
is, that the reason for the validity of a norm cannot be a fact. From the
circumstance that something is cannot follow that something ought to
be; and that something ought to be, cannot be the reason that something
M."
theory.
In Kelsen's theory the validity of a legal rule requires that its enact
ment must be authorized by another rule that is, itself, valid. The judge
ment that a certain raie is valid présupposés, therefore, a judgement that
another raie, which authorizes the création of the former, is valid. The
juristic judgements of validity, about raies which stand in a certain
relationship of "dérivation" between themselves (constituted by the fact
that one authorizes the enactment of other), stand also in a certain
juristic judgement that a raie is valid "derives" from the judgement that
another raie is valid when the former présupposés the latter. This can be
illustrated as two parallel chains of "dérivation", one of raies and the
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 361
i i
Rule y: 'If somebody does <pit 'Rule y is valid'
ought to be a sanction'
validity is the upper positive norm of a legal system, Kelsen states that its
validity or binding force is presupposed and that the formulation of that
presupposition is the basic norm of the system (p. 115 of the General
He also that "since the reason of the validity of a norm can
Theory). says
be another norm, the must be a norm; not one
only presupposition
which belongs to the chain of dérivation of rules, but one which is part
of the chain of dérivation of judgements of validity. In other words, the
basic norm is a judgement of validity; it is the primitive juristic judge
ment of validity on which all other judgements about the validity of
rules, whose création is directly or indirectly authorized by the constitu
to be
scribes). The ascription of validity to a rule (which comes, thereby,
conceived as a norm) habilitâtes, in Kelsen's theory, the passage from
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
362 Carlos Santiago Nino
II
particular legal norm, mainly features connected with the criteria for
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 363
tary legal system when we ascribe validity to them on the basis of one
and the same basic norm." Of course, the phrase between quotation
marks is not a paraphrasis of the basic norm or of any other norm, it
formulâtes a criterion of identification which points to the circumstance
that the same basic norm is presupposed when we ascribe validity to all
the norms of the same legal System. Therefore, authors like Aichourron
and Bulygin1 are mistaken when they criticize Kelsen'% basic norm on
the ground that what is needed for the identification of a legal system is
a criterion and not a norm. Kelsen's basic norm establishes the oblig
atoriness of a legal system; its identity is determined by a criterion which
takes into account the fact that the same basic norm is presupposed
when ascribingobligatoriness to all the norms of that system. However, as
a criterion of identity, the foregoing is vacuous, since the content of each
basic norm (and, consequently, their own identity) cannot be established,
in the context of Kelsen's theory, before circumscribing the norms
that belong in the legal system to which the basic norm ascribes binding
force8.
ship which is not very much in discussion in modem legal theory (of
course it should be completed with a clause dealing with the membership
of the primitive norms of the system; this clause is not successfully pro
vided by Kelsen). This genetic criterion of membership is quite independ
ent of the validity of the norms in question; nowhere in Kelsen's works
7
See Normative Systems, Wien-New York,1971, p. 73 ff., 2.
8
See this criticism in J. Raz, The Concept of a Legal System, Oxford,p. 102.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
364 Carlos Santiago Nino
by it, are mutually independent, both are based on the same notion of
which that basic norm applies. Kelsen is, obviously, much in favour of
maintaining this coextensivity (that which explains why many authors
have confused it with identity), and it is this feature of his theory which
genera tes many unwelcome results. The fact is that, while,in relation to
membership, the dérivation from one norm from another, in the sense
explained, seems a prima facie sound criterion, with regard to the "trans
mission" of validity, it is clearly insufficient. If we accept the validity
of certain set of legal norms we are committed to accept the validity of
some other norms, not only when their création was authorized by the
former but also when the norms, whose validity is accepted, "recognize"
or establish the duty to obey those other norms. Thus, it has been
alleged9 that a legal system could recognize as valid the rules of other
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 365
valid. But Kelsen considere a norm to be valid only when its enactment is
authorized by another valid norm and, so, he is compelled to adopt the
absurd thesis that voidable norms are, in fact, authorized by the perti
nent superior norms, since they have, besides its explicit content which
the voidable norm violâtes, a tacit clause which authorizes the création of
not only when the former authorize the création of the latter but also
when the former impose the duty to obey or apply the latter. A voidable
norm would, thus, be a norm which, not having been authorized by valid
norms of the system in question (and, therefore, not belonging in that
of Kelsen's theory and the source of the current confusion, among inter
III
Some authors, like Hart13 and Aichourron and Bulygin14, assume that
dicussing the matter. Other authors have considered the possibility that
See General Theory of Law and State, op. cit., pp. 153-162.
See a more extensive treatmcnt of the problem of confliet of norras of différent
levels in Kelsen's theory in my "El concepto de validez y el problema del con
flicto entre normas de diferente jerarquía en la Teoría Pura del Derecho", in:
Derecho Filosofía y Lenguaje. Homenaje a A. L. Gioja, edited by G. P. Carrio,
Buenos Aires 1976.
See The Concept of Law, Oxford 1961, p. 245 (notes) where Kelsen's basie
norm is compared with Hart's own rule of récognition assuming tlrat they have
the same role.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
366 Carlos Santiago Nino
Change"16.
Raz points out certain features which, in Kelsen's theory, are charac
teristic of norms, ail of which are linked with the double character of
norms as guides for conduct and as patterns for evaluating behaviour. But
Raz realizes that ail these features are common to norms and ordinary
commands, so he asks himself what would be the property on which, in
Kelsen's theory, the distinction between norms and commands is based.
gorial judgements that the norm in question is justified but mere hypo
thetical judgements that it is justified if the basic norm of the System
is justified.
(d) That "oughf'-statements do not mean that the norms to which
they refer are justified but when we use them we imply our belief that
positivistic outlook. Then he rejects together the second, fourth and fifth
interprétations in a not very clear passage which seems to contain mainly
these two arguments: (i) that Kelsen is clear in to
ascribing "oughf'
statements a descriptive — the second is
only meaning so, interprétation
false — and (ii) that Kelsen is not equipped with a linguistic theory which
See, op. cit., chapter VI, section 'The Basic Norm and Dynamic Justification'
In Cambridge Law Journal 29 (1971).
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 367
the foregoing considérations suggest that Kelsen only thinks of the basic
norm as a common link between all the norms of a legal System (serving
as a ground for resolving problems of identification and membership)
Kelsen, Raz says, seem to give support to the third of the interprétations
between the conditions for the existence of norms and the use that we
(the third one) cannot reflect Kelsen's posture, since it would imply,
given the équivalence between validity and existence, that the existence
basic norm, that which would contradict Kelsen's denial that legal norms,
like idéologies, have a mere conditional existence.
the arguments that Raz addressed against those interprétations are not
gical outlook just referred to gives some ground for the idea that, for
Kelsen, the existence of the norms is conditional, in certain sense of
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
368 Carlos Santiago Nino
ien outlook that Kelsen adopts, he would be ready to admit that condi
tion for the knowledge of legal norms is also a condition for their exist
in the article mentioned with the problem of the change of the Kelsen
ian basic norm, that which he connects with the problem of whether
judges are justified, after a révolution has taken place, to recognize the
(i) Kelsen maintains that his basic norm has these two functions: a) it
enables us to regard norms as objective "ought" as différent from simple
commands, and b) it permits us to interpret ail valid norms as a coherent
field of meaning.
(ii) But the first of the above functions is in fact not performed by the
basic norm, nor does it need to perform that function. For a norm can
(iii) Kelsen ascribes the first function to the basic norm as a result of
a logical error he commits; he confuses two différent senses of the word
things of norms: (a) that a norm conforms to a higher norm; (b) that a
norm is part of a consistent field of meaning; (c) that a norm is effica
cious; (d) that a norm has "an inherent claim to fulfilment". In defend
ing a pure science of law, Kelsen rejects (d); and when he distunguishes
between validity and efficacy, Kelsen also rejects (c). Kelsen uses "validi
ty" sometimes with the meaning (a) and sometimes with the meaning
(b), and frequently he confuses one with the orther. The sense (a) is
relevant to distinguishing between a command and a legal norm but it has
nothing to do with the basic norm. The converse is true with regard to
This quotation is madc by Harris in the article referred to in note 16; sec foot
note 16, p. 106.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 369
contradictory and that lower norms should derive from higher ones.
(v) To fulfíl this aim of legal science something like the basic norm
must be accepted.
ary System does not directly apply to them. But, if judges do not follow
the solutions of legal science, this would become ineffective, and, as legal
science must be useful, then judges should présupposé the basic norm
adopted by legal science. So judges have a reason, independent of any
political commitment, to accept the norms enacted by revolutionaries.
new law. However, this does not exclude the possible existence of moral
mistakes that I think Harris commits. The general observation is that the
reasoning at stake has the curious feature of starting from what appear to
tion (a conclusion which coincides with the ideology that Ross calis
"pseudopositivism", distinguishing it from the theoretical positivism that
he and others defend18). The pitfalls that I want to point out are the
following:
18
See "El concepto de validez y otros ensayos", op. cit. Buenos Aires 1969, p. 25.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
370 Carlos Santiago Nino
(a) Harris limits the relevance of the Kelsenmn basic norm to the fonc
tion of enabling jurists to see the law as a consistent corpus. Besides the
true that Kelsen once maintained19 that legal Systems are necessarily
consistent and that he seemed to attribute the fonction of preserving this
consistency to the basic norm. The adoption of this stränge thesis could
receive différent explanations; it may well be a conséquence of identify
ing validity with justification and seeing the basic norm as the expression
of that justification; there is, indeed, a case for saying that one cannot
the content of the Äe/seman basic norm (even when it could be a requisite
(b) Neither the context nor the dérivation from another rule is
enough, in Kelsen's theory, for distinguishing a norm from a command.
reject its relevance for identifying legal norms (my confidence is based on
the simple fact that nowhere in Kelsen's works any significance is given
to circumstances such as the purposes with which a prescription is given,
the factual way in which power is acquired, etc.). In relation to the déri
'
vation from another mie (the sense (a) of "validity" in Harris classifica
tion) as a criterion which would allow to distinguish norms from com
J. Finnis has called my attention to the fact that Kelsen had abandoned his
position about the necessary consistency of legal Systems, in the article "Law
and Logic", published in Philosophy and Christianity, Amsterdam 1965.
See this point in J. Raz, "Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm", American Jour
nal of Jurisprudence 19(1974),p.106.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 371
viously requires dérivation from a valid norm, and "valid" here cannot
merely describe the fact that this other rule derives from a further one,
ñor can it mean membership to a consistent System (since the command
of the gangster may well satisfy this condition). Curiously enough, Harris
suggests, in a footnote, a possible distinction between "subjective" and
"objective" normative meanings (which in Kelsen corresponds, respec
tively, to mere commands and valid norms) which points in the direction
that he refuses to follow up in the text: "Kelsen's distinction between
legal science and there could be a case for saying that this task should be
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
372 Carlos Santiago Niño
adopted, instead, other norms, legal science could still continue with "its
useful function", presenting those other norms as a consistent whole.
If legal science were as descriptive and evaluatively neutral as Kelsen
thinks it must be, it should limit itself to describe, and perhaps to impose
consistency upon, the norms that courts happen to accept (the effica
cious norms), without this activity bearing any conséquence upon the
matter of what norms courts should accept. The origin oí Harris' confu
justified and fully accepting that justifiability, and to say that courts
must présupposé the basic norm towards efficacious Systems amounts to
saying that they should act in the same way as they would act if they
believed that the system is justified. The mistake that Harris commits in
his characterization of positivism is exactly the same that R. Dworkin
commits when he says23 : "I have no answer to the argument that the
term 'law' can be used in such a way as to make the positivist's thesis
true by stipulation. It can be used in such a way that the speaker re
cognizes as 'legal' standards only those standards that judges and lawyers
"
As Ross maintains, see op. cit., p. 43.
23
"Social Rules and Legal Theory", Y aie Law Journal 81, 1972.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 373
cept of law now in general employment, which is, I take it, theconcept of
the standards that provide for the rights and duties that the government
has the duty to recognize and enforce, at least in principie, throughthe
familiar institutions of mies and police." The concept of law which
Dworkin does not object is,by and large, just the concept which positivists
adopt; the other one (which obviously présupposés a direct normative
sense, and not merely an "inverted commas" use, of the word "duty"
in the phrase . . the government has the duty to recognize and en
force. ..") is that which is put forward by natural law théories, including
the pseudo-positivistic ideology that Dworkin and Harris confuse with
theoretical positivism. In sum, despite his rejection of any association
between judgements of validity and the hypothetical assumption that the
system is justified, Harris ends up by accepting a close connection be
tween judgements of validity and a füll avowal of the justification of the
System, which, in so far as validity is considered to be definitory of
"law" and "legal norm", is inconsistent with the posture of Kelsen and
other positivists.
IV
For Kelsen to say that a legal system or a legal norm is valid (that is to
say, that they are just a legal system or a legal norm) is to say that they
are justified or obligatory. Legal science does not need to commit itself
to the moral posture that the legal system it describes is actually valid
Kelsen, as for natural law theorists, the only conceivable type of norma
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
374 Carlos Santiago Nino
white", instead of the uncommitted phrase "I (you, he) believe(s) that
the snow is white". Of course, the point of bringing forth this parallel is
that, in the same way that we do not need to accept or présupposé the
truth of a belief in order to describe it, we do not need to accept or
présupposé the justification of a norm in order to describe it.
But the matter is more complex than the foregoing conclusion
assumes. In the case of beliefs we need to distinguish between the mental
State or attitude of some person which we describe as "believing in
I am not sure about whether the idea of "describing a proposition" has any
sense at all when it is distinguished from the détermination of the truth-value of
the proposition and the display of its logical conséquences. If my doubts were
confirmed, this would be a décisive objection to the view assumed by some
juiists that the central task of legal science is to describe norms and that this
task can be distinguished from the empirical task of determining which norms
are efficacious, the evaluative task of assessing which norms are valid, and the
logical task of displaying the conséquence of norms.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Some Confusions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 375
mativity is not the only one available and that there is a "social" con
ception of normativity, according to which norms are a kind of social
practice, Kelsen would certainly answer that norms are not social prac
tices (in the same way that descriptive propositions are not the psycholo
gical states or attitudes which we call "beliefs") but are what may or may
not be (depending on the efficacy of the norm) the "ideal content" of
some social practices.
Raz seems to have lately27 oriented himself in this direction when he
asserts that the normative language used by jurists in describing law
cannot be analyzed as descriptive of certain practices, beliefs or attitudes,
since that language, without apparent change of meaning or force, is used
as well to describe hypothetical norms which are not in force, and that,
consequently, the use of that language must imply the adoption of some
normative point of view not very différent than that described by Kelsen
as typical of legal science. However, Raz does not think that norms can
norms. This position poses very complex and interesting problems which
I hope to discuss in another work.
26
In op. cit., note 24, p. 111.
27 and in "Legal
In Practical Reason and Norms, cited, p. 170 et seq. Validity"
unpublished.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
376 Carlos Santiago Niño
Summary
nature, which it shares with the notion of validity used by natural law
philosophers, has not been sufficiently grasped. Once this feature of the
Kelseni&n concept of validity is taken into account, many problems in
the interprétation of the Pure Theory vanish and some of its shortcomings
are brought to notice. Some wrongaccountsofÄefen's notion of validity
are discussed in the article. Finally, some hypothèses are suggested in
order to explain why Kelsen includes in his theory a notion of validity
which is apparently in consistent with its basic postulations.
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
So me Confissions around Kelsen 's Concept of Validity 377
Résumé
employée par des philosophes du Droit Naturel. Une fois qu'on voit ce
Zusammenfassung
Kelsens Begriff der Geltung der Rechtsnormen ist ein zentrales Diskus
die These vertreten, daß dieser Begriff oft irrtümlich gedeutet wir , in
dem man seine normative Natur verkennt: es handelt sich um einen
This content downloaded from 137.132.123.69 on Mon, 30 Nov 2015 19:42:44 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions