Organism
Organism
An organism is any living thing that functions as an individual.[1] Such a definition raises more problems
than it solves, not least because the concept of an individual is also difficult. Many criteria, few of them
widely accepted, have been proposed to define what an organism is. Among the most common is that an
organism has autonomous reproduction, growth, and metabolism. This would exclude viruses, despite the
fact that they evolve like organisms. Other problematic cases include colonial organisms; a colony of
eusocial insects is organised adaptively, and has germ-soma specialisation, with some insects
reproducing, others not, like cells in an animal's body. The body of a siphonophore, a jelly-like marine
animal, is composed of organism-like zooids, but the whole structure looks and functions much like an
animal such as a jellyfish, the parts collaborating to provide the functions of the colonial organism.
The evolutionary biologists David Queller and Joan Strassmann state that "organismality", the qualities or
attributes that define an entity as an organism, has evolved socially as groups of simpler units (from cells
upwards) came to cooperate without conflicts. They propose that cooperation should be used as the
"defining trait" of an organism. This would treat many types of collaboration, including the fungus/alga
partnership of different species in a lichen, or the permanent sexual partnership of an anglerfish, as an
organism.
Etymology
The term "organism" (from the Ancient Greek ὀργανισμός, derived from órganon, meaning 'instrument,
implement, tool', 'organ of sense', or 'apprehension')[2][3] first appeared in the English language in the
1660s with the now-obsolete meaning of an organic structure or organization.[3] It is related to the verb
"organize".[3] In his 1790 Critique of Judgment, Immanuel Kant defined an organism as "both an
organized and a self-organizing being".[4][5]
Samuel Díaz‐Muñoz and colleagues (2016) accept Queller and Strassmann's view that organismality can
be measured wholly by degrees of cooperation and of conflict. They state that this situates organisms in
evolutionary time, so that organismality is context dependent. They suggest that highly integrated life
forms, which are not context dependent, may evolve through context-dependent stages towards complete
unification.[24]
Boundary cases
Viruses
Viruses are not typically considered to be organisms, because they are incapable of autonomous
reproduction, growth, metabolism, or homeostasis. Although viruses have a few enzymes and molecules
like those in living organisms, they have no metabolism of their own; they cannot synthesize the organic
compounds from which they are formed. In this sense, they are similar to inanimate matter.[7] Viruses
have their own genes, and they evolve. Thus, an argument that
viruses should be classed as living organisms is their ability to
undergo evolution and replicate through self-assembly. However,
some scientists argue that viruses neither evolve nor self-
reproduce. Instead, viruses are evolved by their host cells,
meaning that there was co-evolution of viruses and host cells. If
host cells did not exist, viral evolution would be impossible. As
for reproduction, viruses rely on hosts' machinery to replicate. The
discovery of viruses with genes coding for energy metabolism and A virus such as tobacco mosaic
protein synthesis fuelled the debate about whether viruses are virus is not a cell; it contains only its
living organisms, but the genes have a cellular origin. Most likely, genetic material, and a protein coat.
There is an argument for viewing viruses as cellular organisms. Some researchers perceive viruses not as
virions alone, which they believe are just spores of an organism, but as a virocell - an ontologically
mature viral organism that has cellular structure.[25] Such virus is a result of infection of a cell and shows
all major physiological properties of other organisms: metabolism, growth, and reproduction, therefore,
life in its effective presence.[12][26]
Organism-like colonies
The philosopher Jack A. Wilson examines some boundary cases to demonstrate that the concept of
organism is not sharply defined.[8] In his view, sponges, lichens, siphonophores, slime moulds, and
eusocial colonies such as those of ants or naked molerats, all lie in the boundary zone between being
definite colonies and definite organisms (or superorganisms).[8]
Jack A. Wilson's analysis of the similar organism-like nature of siphonophores
and jellyfish[8]
Function Colonial siphonophore Jellyfish
Buoyancy Top of colony is gas-filled Jelly
Apolemia, a colonial
siphonophore that functions
as a single individual
Synthetic organisms
Scientists and bio-engineers are experimenting with different types
of synthetic organism, from chimaeras composed of cells from
two or more species, cyborgs including electromechanical limbs,
hybrots containing both electronic and biological elements, and
other combinations of systems that have variously evolved and
been designed.[27]
Synthetic organisms already take diverse forms, and their diversity will increase. What they all have in
common is a teleonomic or goal-seeking behaviour that enables them to correct errors of many kinds so
as to achieve whatever result they are designed for. Such behaviour is reminiscent of intelligent action by
organisms; intelligence is seen as an embodied form of cognition.[27]
References
1. Mosby's Dictionary of Medicine, Nursing and Health Professions (10th ed.). St. Louis,
Missouri: Elsevier. 2017. p. 1281. ISBN 978-0-3232-2205-1.
2. ὄργανον (https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus:text:1999.04.0057:entry=
o)/rganon). Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus
Project
3. "organism (n.)" (https://www.etymonline.com/word/organism). Online Etymology Dictionary.
Retrieved 11 April 2024.
4. Kant, Immanuel (1790). Critique of Judgment. Lagarde und Friederich. §65 5:374.
5. Huneman, Philippe (2017). "Kant's Concept of Organism Revisited: A Framework for a
Possible Synthesis between Developmentalism and Adaptationism?". The Monist. 100 (3):
373–390. doi:10.1093/monist/onx016 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fmonist%2Fonx016).
JSTOR 26370801 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/26370801).
6. Rosen, Robert (September 1958). "A relational theory of biological systems" (http://link.sprin
ger.com/10.1007/BF02478302). The Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics. 20 (3): 245–260.
doi:10.1007/BF02478302 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2FBF02478302). ISSN 0007-4985 (http
s://search.worldcat.org/issn/0007-4985).
7. Moreira, D.; López-García, P.N. (April 2009). "Ten reasons to exclude viruses from the tree
of life". Nature Reviews Microbiology. 7 (4): 306–311. doi:10.1038/nrmicro2108 (https://doi.o
rg/10.1038%2Fnrmicro2108). PMID 19270719 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/19270719).
S2CID 3907750 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:3907750).
8. Wilson, Jack A. (2000). "Ontological butchery: organism concepts and biological
generalizations". Philosophy of Science. 67: 301–311. doi:10.1086/392827 (https://doi.org/1
0.1086%2F392827). JSTOR 188676 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/188676).
S2CID 84168536 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:84168536).
9. Santelices, Bernabé (April 1999). "How many kinds of individual are there?" (https://linkingh
ub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S0169534798015195). Trends in Ecology & Evolution. 14 (4):
152–155. doi:10.1016/S0169-5347(98)01519-5 (https://doi.org/10.1016%2FS0169-5347%2
898%2901519-5). PMID 10322523 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/10322523).
10. Pradeu, T. (2010). "What is an organism? An immunological answer". History and
Philosophy of the Life Sciences. 32 (2–3): 247–267. PMID 21162370 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nl
m.nih.gov/21162370).
11. Bailly, Francis; Longo, Giuseppe (2009). "Biological Organization and Anti-entropy" (https://
www.researchgate.net/publication/247697945). Journal of Biological Systems. 17 (1): 63–
96. doi:10.1142/S0218339009002715 (https://doi.org/10.1142%2FS0218339009002715).
ISSN 0218-3390 (https://search.worldcat.org/issn/0218-3390).
12. Piast, Radosław W. (June 2019). "Shannon's information, Bernal's biopoiesis and Bernoulli
distribution as pillars for building a definition of life" (https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/p
ii/S0022519319301109). Journal of Theoretical Biology. 470: 101–107.
Bibcode:2019JThBi.470..101P (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/2019JThBi.470..101P).
doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2019.03.009 (https://doi.org/10.1016%2Fj.jtbi.2019.03.009).
PMID 30876803 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/30876803). S2CID 80625250 (https://api.
semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:80625250).
13. Bateson, Patrick (February 2005). "The return of the whole organism". Journal of
Biosciences. 30 (1): 31–39. doi:10.1007/BF02705148 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2FBF02705
148). PMID 15824439 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/15824439). S2CID 26656790 (http
s://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:26656790).
14. Clarke, E. (2010). "The problem of biological individuality". Biological Theory. 5 (4): 312–
325. doi:10.1162/BIOT_a_00068 (https://doi.org/10.1162%2FBIOT_a_00068).
S2CID 28501709 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:28501709).
15. Pepper, J.W.; Herron, M.D. (November 2008). "Does biology need an organism concept?".
Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 83 (4): 621–627.
doi:10.1111/j.1469-185X.2008.00057.x (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1469-185X.2008.0005
7.x). PMID 18947335 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/18947335). S2CID 4942890 (https://
api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:4942890).
16. Wilson, R. (2007). "The biological notion of individual". Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy.
17. Folse, H.J., III; Roughgarden, J. (December 2010). "What is an individual organism? A
multilevel selection perspective". The Quarterly Review of Biology. 85 (4): 447–472.
doi:10.1086/656905 (https://doi.org/10.1086%2F656905). PMID 21243964 (https://pubmed.
ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/21243964). S2CID 19816447 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:19
816447).
18. Queller, David C.; Strassmann, Joan E. (November 2009). "Beyond society: the evolution of
organismality" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2781869). Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences. 364 (1533):
3143–3155. doi:10.1098/rstb.2009.0095 (https://doi.org/10.1098%2Frstb.2009.0095).
PMC 2781869 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2781869). PMID 19805423
(https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/19805423).
19. Gardner, A.; Grafen, A. (April 2009). "Capturing the superorganism: a formal theory of group
adaptation" (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1420-9101.2008.01681.x). Journal of Evolutionary
Biology. 22 (4): 659–671. doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2008.01681.x (https://doi.org/10.1111%2
Fj.1420-9101.2008.01681.x). PMID 19210588 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/19210588).
S2CID 8413751 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:8413751).
20. Santelices, B. (April 1999). "How many kinds of individual are there?". Trends in Ecology &
Evolution. 14 (4): 152–155. doi:10.1016/s0169-5347(98)01519-5 (https://doi.org/10.1016%2
Fs0169-5347%2898%2901519-5). PMID 10322523 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/10322
523).
21. Lücking, Robert; Leavitt, Steven D.; Hawksworth, David L. (2021). "Species in lichen-
forming fungi: balancing between conceptual and practical considerations, and between
phenotype and phylogenomics" (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs13225-021-00477-7). Fungal
Diversity. 109 (1): 99–154. doi:10.1007/s13225-021-00477-7 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs1
3225-021-00477-7).
22. Hine, R.S. (2008). A Dictionary of Biology (6th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 461.
ISBN 978-0-19-920462-5.
23. Kelly, Kevin (1994). Out of control: the new biology of machines, social systems and the
economic world (https://archive.org/details/outofcontrolnewb00kell). Boston: Addison-
Wesley. pp. 98 (https://archive.org/details/outofcontrolnewb00kell/page/98). ISBN 978-0-
201-48340-6.
24. Díaz-Muñoz, Samuel L.; Boddy, Amy M.; Dantas, Gautam; Waters, Christopher M.;
Bronstein, Judith L. (2016). "Contextual organismality: Beyond pattern to process in the
emergence of organisms" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5132100).
Evolution. 70 (12): 2669–2677. doi:10.1111/evo.13078 (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fevo.130
78). ISSN 0014-3820 (https://search.worldcat.org/issn/0014-3820). PMC 5132100 (https://w
ww.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5132100). PMID 27704542 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.
nih.gov/27704542).
25. Forterre, Patrick (4 October 2012). "The virocell concept and environmental microbiology" (h
ttps://doi.org/10.1038/ismej.2012.110). The ISME Journal. 7 (2): 233–236.
doi:10.1038/ismej.2012.110 (https://doi.org/10.1038%2Fismej.2012.110). ISSN 1751-7362
(https://search.worldcat.org/issn/1751-7362). PMC 3554396 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/p
mc/articles/PMC3554396). PMID 23038175 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/23038175).
26. Bandea, Claudiu I. (1983). "A new theory on the origin and the nature of viruses". Journal of
Theoretical Biology. 105 (4): 591–602. Bibcode:1983JThBi.105..591B (https://ui.adsabs.har
vard.edu/abs/1983JThBi.105..591B). doi:10.1016/0022-5193(83)90221-7 (https://doi.org/10.
1016%2F0022-5193%2883%2990221-7). PMID 6672474 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/
6672474).
27. Clawson, Wesley P.; Levin, Michael (1 January 2023). "Endless forms most beautiful 2.0:
teleonomy and the bioengineering of chimaeric and synthetic organisms" (https://doi.org/10.
1093%2Fbiolinnean%2Fblac116). Biological Journal of the Linnean Society. 138 (1): 141.
doi:10.1093/biolinnean/blac116 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fbiolinnean%2Fblac116).
ISSN 0024-4066 (https://search.worldcat.org/issn/0024-4066).
External links
"The Tree of Life" (http://tolweb.org/tree/phylogeny.html). Tree of Life Web Project.
"Indexing the world's known species" (http://www.species2000.org/). Species 2000.