0% found this document useful (0 votes)
9 views23 pages

Chapter 2 - Consumer Theory

This document is a lecture on consumer theory from Bilkent University's Econ 101 course, focusing on the decision-making process of consumers regarding purchasing goods. It outlines the model of consumer behavior, including constraints based on income and prices, as well as preferences represented through various mathematical relations. The document also discusses the optimal bundle of goods a consumer can purchase given their constraints and preferences.

Uploaded by

ersoyderen
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
9 views23 pages

Chapter 2 - Consumer Theory

This document is a lecture on consumer theory from Bilkent University's Econ 101 course, focusing on the decision-making process of consumers regarding purchasing goods. It outlines the model of consumer behavior, including constraints based on income and prices, as well as preferences represented through various mathematical relations. The document also discusses the optimal bundle of goods a consumer can purchase given their constraints and preferences.

Uploaded by

ersoyderen
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 23

Bilkent University

Econ 101 - Fall 2023


Chapter 2: Consumer Theory

A. Arda Gitmez Nuh Aygün Dalkıran

September 19, 2023

Contents
1 A Very Brief Introduction 2

2 The Model 2
2.1 The Constraint . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
2.2 Preferences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
2.2.1 Indifference Curves . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5
2.2.2 Marginal Rate of Substitution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6

3 Optimal Bundle 8

A Proofs 12

B Optimal Bundle for Some Famous Preferences 13


B.1 Perfect Substitutes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13
B.2 Quasi-linear Preferences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16
B.3 Cobb-Douglas Preferences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
B.4 Perfect Complements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22

1
1 A Very Brief Introduction
This lecture introduces the first formal model of the decision made by an economic agent: a consumer.
We consider the simplest (and possibly the most widespread) form of economic interaction: the decision
to buy some goods and services. This is literally the model of a consumer who is deciding to buy some
goods in a supermarket. There are 𝑛 different goods, which have their own prices. The consumer observes
the prices and decides how much to buy from each good.
As we discussed in the previous lecture, an economic agent has (i) a constraint and (ii) preferences. This
economic agent is no different: the consumer has limited income, denoted by a number 𝐼 . This is the con-
sumer’s constraint: she cannot buy everything she wants. The consumer also has well-defined preferences
towards goods. We will discuss what “well-defined” means in a few pages.
Also, as discussed in the previous lecture, each economic model involves some simplifications. Here are a
couple of simplifications we assume throughout this document:
• This is a one-time interaction. The customer does not go to the store and say “let me buy this item
later”. There may be future considerations in her decision to buy some goods (i.e., if she is buying a
washing machine she realizes that she will most likely not need a washing machine in the near fu-
ture). Those are fine – the future considerations, concerns about the quality of the good, uncertainty
about its use, social concerns etc. are all captured by her preferences.
• The customer observes all the prices perfectly, and knows her income. She can easily calculate the
money required to buy a given group of items.
• The customer knows her preferences, and she acts according to her preferences. That is, she is ratio-
nal.
At the risk of being repetitive: do these assumptions sometimes violated? Of course. But we are building a
benchmark here.

2 The Model
There is a single consumer and 𝑛 different goods. The consumer decides how much to buy of each good,
i.e. she chooses quantities.
Here is the notation we will use:
• 𝑖 : Will be used to denote a generic good. We will use natural numbers to denote goods and to index
them. Thus, the set of all goods will be denoted by {1, 2, . . . , 𝑛}. Here 𝑛 denotes the 𝑛th good, and
also the total number of goods that is available for consumption.
• 𝑞𝑖 : Denotes the quantity of good 𝑖 . The case where the consumer is considering consuming 5 kg of
good 2 will be represented with 𝑞2 = 5 kg. The quantity can be kilograms, grams, liters, numbers...
Whatever the denomination is, we will say it is a unit. Note that for any good 𝑖 we must always have
𝑞𝑖 ≥ 0. 𝑞𝑖 = 0 is allowed, i.e. the consumer may choose not to buy a good.
• (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 , . . . , 𝑞𝑛 ): Denotes a consumption bundle (or simply a bundle). This is a list that represents how
much of each good a consumer is considering for consumption. As an example, consider a situation
where there are 4 possible goods that the consumer can consume (hence 𝑛 = 4). The consumption
bundle (8, 2, 0, 12) represents the situation where the consumer is considering 8 units of good 1,
2 units of good 2, none of good 3, and 12 units of good 4 for consumption.
• 𝑝𝑖 : Denotes the price of good 𝑖 per unit. Therefore, if the consumer buys 𝑞𝑖 units of good 𝑖 at price 𝑝𝑖 ,
she pays 𝑝𝑖 𝑞𝑖 for that good.
• 𝐼 : Denotes the income of the consumer (the total wealth of the consumer).

2
2.1 The Constraint
The constraint of the consumer specifies which bundles are affordable (i.e., feasible for the consumer) and
which bundles are not.
Definition 1. Given the prices 𝑝1 , 𝑝 2 , . . . , 𝑝𝑛 of the goods and the income 𝐼 of the consumer, a bundle (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 , . . . , 𝑞𝑛 )
is feasible if and only if
∑︁𝑛
𝑝 𝑖 𝑞𝑖 = 𝑝 1 𝑞 1 + 𝑝 2 𝑞 2 + · · · 𝑝 𝑛 𝑞 𝑛 ≤ 𝐼 .
𝑖 =1
The set of feasible bundles is also called the budget set. The set of feasible bundles that requires the use of all
the income, i.e., the bundles (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 , . . . , 𝑞𝑛 ) such that 𝑝1 𝑞1 + 𝑝2 𝑞2 + · · · + 𝑝𝑛 𝑞𝑛 = 𝐼 are said to be on the budget
line (they constitute the budget line).
When there are two goods (𝑛 = 2), the set of feasible bundles given the prices 𝑝1 , 𝑝2 and income 𝐼 are the
bundles (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) that satisfy:
𝑝 1 𝑞1 + 𝑝 2 𝑞2 ≤ 𝐼
They can be represented graphically with the orange region shown in Figure 1. The budget line is a line
with slope − 𝑝12 .
𝑝

q2

I
p2
Bu
dg
et
Li
ne

Budget
Set

I
q1
p1

Figure 1: A graphical representation of feasible bundles given prices 𝑝1 , 𝑝2 , and income 𝐼 .

2.2 Preferences
The preferences of the consumer specify the consumer’s ranking between any two bundles 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 , . . . , 𝑞𝑛 )
and 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ , . . . , 𝑞𝑛′ ). The consumer may strictly prefer one bundle over the other, or may feel indiffer-
ent between them. We capture the consumer’s preferences through a preference relation.
A preference relation is a relation that compares two pairs of bundles. It is defined on all pairs of bundles,
including (but not limited to) feasible bundles. Given two bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ , it contains three possible
scenarios.
• The situation where the consumer (strictly) prefers bundle 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 , . . . , 𝑞𝑛 ) to another bundle
𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ , . . . , 𝑞𝑛′ ) is represented by:
𝑞 ≻ 𝑞′

3
• If the consumer is indifferent between the bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ , then we will write:

𝑞 ∼ 𝑞′

• If, for the consumer, bundle 𝑞 is at least as good as bundle 𝑞 ′ (i.e., the consumer prefers 𝑞 to 𝑞 ′ or
she is indifferent between 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ ) we will write:

𝑞 ≿ 𝑞′

Therefore, for any pair of bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ , we have:

𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ ⇐⇒ (𝑞 ≻ 𝑞 ′ or 𝑞 ∼ 𝑞 ′ ) (1)

Note that when 𝑞 ≻ 𝑞 ′ , by definition, it is also true that 𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ . This is not really surprising: when a
consumer prefers 𝑞 to 𝑞 ′ , she also thinks 𝑞 is at least as good as 𝑞 ′ .
Similarly: when 𝑞 ∼ 𝑞 ′ , by definition, it is also true that 𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ . This is not surprising either: when a
consumer is indifferent between 𝑞 to 𝑞 ′ , she also thinks 𝑞 is at least as good as 𝑞 ′ .
What I want to point out that two of these scenarios can be satisfied at the same time. This is just like
comparisons of real numbers. For the complete analogy: ≻ is like the > sign, ∼ is like the = sign, and
≿ is like the ≥ sign. Now, as we know, 5 > 3 and 5 ≥ 3 are both correct. Similarly, 4 = 4 and 4 ≥ 4 are
both correct.
A “well-defined” preference relation satisfies the following three conditions:
1. For any pair of bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ ,

𝑞 ≿ 𝑞′ or 𝑞 ′ ≿ 𝑞. (2)

This condition states that the consumer is able compare any pair of bundles. A relation that satisfies
this condition is said to be complete.
Note that we could have equivalently stated the completeness condition as follows. For any pair of
bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ ,

𝑞 ≻ 𝑞′ or 𝑞 ∼ 𝑞′ or 𝑞 ′ ≻ 𝑞.

(You can verify this by writing down equation (2) and using the definition of “at least as good as”
relationship in equation (1).)
2. For any triple of bundles 𝑞, 𝑞 ′ , and 𝑞 ′′ ,

if 𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′ ≿ 𝑞 ′′ , then 𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′′ .

That is, for the consumer, if 𝑞 is at least as good as 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′ is at least as good as 𝑞 ′′ , then 𝑞 should be
at least as good as 𝑞 ′′ . A relation that satisfies this condition is said to be transitive.
There are several implications of transitivity condition, which you derive on your own. The first one
is that if the consumer is indifferent between 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ and if she is indifferent between 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′′ ,
then she must be indifferent between 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′′ . In other words,

if 𝑞 ∼ 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′ ∼ 𝑞 ′′ , then 𝑞 ∼ 𝑞 ′′ .

Another implication of transitivity is the following. If the consumer strictly prefers 𝑞 to 𝑞 ′ and if she
is indifferent between 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′′ , then she must strictly prefer 𝑞 to 𝑞 ′′ . In other words,

if 𝑞 ≻ 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′ ∼ 𝑞 ′′ , then 𝑞 ≻ 𝑞 ′′ .

4
3. For any pair of bundles 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 , . . . , 𝑞𝑛 ) and 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ , . . . , 𝑞𝑛′ ),
if 𝑞𝑖 < 𝑞𝑖′ for all 𝑖 ∈ {1, 2, . . . , 𝑛}, then 𝑞 ′ ≻ 𝑞.
This condition states that if the bundle 𝑞 ′ has more of each good than bundle 𝑞 has, then 𝑞 ′ is pre-
ferred to 𝑞. To put it simply, the consumer prefers more to less. A relation that satisfies this condition
is called monotonic.
Throughout this lecture, we assume that any preference relation is complete, transitive and monotonic,
i.e., it is well-defined.

2.2.1 Indifference Curves


A graphical representation of preference relation can be obtained by drawing curves through bundles that
the consumer is indifferent among. Figure 2 gives information about a preference relation in which the
consumer is indifferent between the bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ (they are on the same curve).
q2

q0
q 00

q 000

q1

Figure 2: A graphical representation of a preference relation.

The curve that passes through 𝑞 is called indifference curve through 𝑞. Since 𝑞 ′′ and 𝑞 ′′′ are not on the
indifference curve through 𝑞, the consumer is not indifferent between 𝑞 ′′ and 𝑞 and also is not indifferent
between 𝑞 ′′′ and 𝑞. Since 𝑞 ′′ contains more of the (two) goods than 𝑞 does, by the monotonicity of the
preference relation, 𝑞 ′′ is preferred to 𝑞. Similarly, since the bundle 𝑞 contains more of the goods than 𝑞 ′′′
does, by the monotonicity of the preference relation, 𝑞 is preferred to 𝑞 ′′′ . Extending this argument, we can
conclude that any bundle that lies “above” (in the north east side of ) the indifference curve through 𝑞 is
preferred to 𝑞 and 𝑞 is preferred to any bundle that lies “below” (in the south west side of ) the indifference
curve through 𝑞.
By now, you may have realized that it is possible to draw multiple indifference curves in the same graph.
Consider, for instance, the indifference curve passing through 𝑞 ′′ . See Figure 3.
• By definition, the consumer is indifferent between any bundle on this “higher” indifference curve
and 𝑞 ′′ . For instance, the consumer is indifferent between 𝑞 ′′′′ and 𝑞 ′′ :
𝑞 ′′′′ ∼ 𝑞 ′′

• Recall that, by monotonicity, the consumer prefers 𝑞 ′′ to 𝑞:


𝑞 ′′ ≻ 𝑞

5
• Once again, by definition, the consumer is indifferent between any bundle on the “lower” indiffer-
ence curve and 𝑞. For instance, the consumer is indifferent between 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞:
𝑞 ∼ 𝑞′

• Combining all these stetements and using transitivity, we conclude:


𝑞 ′′′′ ≻ 𝑞 ′

Note that this argument can be repeated for any 𝑞 ′′′′ on the “higher” indifference curve and any 𝑞 ′ on the
“lower” indifference curve. We conclude: any bundle on a “higher” indifference curve is preferred over any
bundle on a “lower” indifference curve.

q2

q0
q 00

q q 0000 “higher”
indifference curve

q 000
“lower”
indifference curve

q1

Figure 3: Multiple indifference curves. Any bundle on a “higher” indifference curve is preferred over any
bundle on a “lower” indifference curve.
There are a couple of other things I want to emphasize about indifference curves:
• Since the preference relation of a consumer is assumed to be monotonic, the indifference curves
must be downward sloping. Suppose, for a contradiction, that a part of an indifference is upward-
sloping. Then, there are two bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ on the same indifference curve such that 𝑞1′ > 𝑞1 and
𝑞2′ > 𝑞2 . By monotonicity, we must have 𝑞 ′ ≻ 𝑞. But then, 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ cannot be on the same indifference
curve! A contradiction.
• As long as transitivity and monotonicity are satisfied, indifference curves cannot cross. I am leaving
this as an exercise for you to show.

2.2.2 Marginal Rate of Substitution


We will now define a very important object based on the indifference curves. It will provide the very crucial
information on how much the consumer “values” good 1 over good 2 at a certain bundle.
The marginal rate of substitution of good 2 for good 1 at the bundle 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ), denoted MRS2,1 (𝑞), is the
rate at which good 2 must substitute for a “small” decrease in the consumption of good 1 in order to keep
the consumer indifferent to the initial bundle 𝑞. More formally (see Figure 4):
Δ𝑞2
MRS2,1 (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) = lim = |slope of ind. curve at 𝑞 | . (3)
Δ𝑞1 →0+ Δ𝑞1
(𝑞1 −Δ𝑞1 ,𝑞2 +Δ𝑞2 ) ∼(𝑞1 ,𝑞2 )

6
The marginal rate of substitution of good 1 for good 2 at the bundle 𝑞, denote MRS1,2 (𝑞), is similarly de-
fined:
Δ𝑞1 1
MRS1,2 (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) = lim = . (4)
Δ𝑞2 →0+ Δ𝑞2 |slope of ind. curve at 𝑞 |
(𝑞1 +Δ𝑞1 ,𝑞2 −Δ𝑞2 ) ∼(𝑞1 ,𝑞2 )

q2 q2

M
∆q2 R
S
2,
(q1, q2) 1(
q) (q1, q2)
∆q1 =

sl
op
e

q1 q1

Figure 4: Marginal rate of substitution of good 2 for good 1: Taking the limit of Δ𝑞2 /Δ𝑞1 as Δ𝑞1 goes to zero
in the figure on left we obtain the figure on the right.

MRS2,1 (𝑞) is a measure of how much the consumer “values” good 1 in terms of good 2 when he is endowed
with the bundle 𝑞. Assume that the consumer is endowed with the bundle 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ). If we ask the con-
sumer to give up a “small” amount of good 1, say Δ𝑞1 units, the consumer would require “approximately”
MRS2,1 (𝑞)Δ𝑞1 units of good 2, to compensate the reduction in the quantity of good 1 in order to be indiffer-
ent between the initial bundle and the bundle after the exchange. Similarly, if we asked to consumer to give
up a “small” amount of good 2, say Δ𝑞2 units, the consumer would require “approximately” MRS1,2 (𝑞)Δ𝑞2
units of good 1 to compensate the reduction in the quantity of good 2.
Generally speaking, there are four ways to interpret MRS2,1 (𝑞).
1. (Mathematical.) It is the limit of a ratio of two differences: see equation (3).
2. (Verbal.) It is a measure of how many units of good 2 the consumer must be given, so that she is left
indifferent to a decrease in good 1.
3. (Geometrical.) It is the (absolute value of ) the slope of the indifference curve: the steeper the indif-
ference curve is, the higher MRS2,1 (𝑞) is.
4. (Economical.) It is a measure of the value of good 1 in terms of good 2: the more valuable good 1 is,
the higher MRS2,1 (𝑞) is.
Let me now define two more properties on the preference, which are common features of many prefer-
ences in real life.
• Generally, when a consumer has more of a good (say, good 1), and less of another good (say, good 2),
then good 1 becomes less “valuable” for the consumer relative to good 2. We formalize this idea as
follows:
Let 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ be any two bundles that the consumer is indifferent between (i.e., they are on the same
indifference curve). We require preference relations to be such that, if 𝑞1 > 𝑞1′ , then MRS2,1 (𝑞) <
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ′ ). Also, if 𝑞2 > 𝑞2′ , then MRS1,2 (𝑞) < MRS1,2 (𝑞 ′ ).
Preference relations that satisfy this condition are said to have (strictly) diminishing marginal rate
of substitution. If a preference relation satisfies the diminishing marginal rate of substitution as-
sumption, the relative value of good 1 in terms of good 2 will be lower as the consumer has more of
good 1 and less of good 2. As a result, the indifference curve will get flatter as 𝑞1 increases along the

7
same indifference curve. This means: the indifference curves will be bowed toward the origin (Figure
5).
• A preference relation is said to be smooth if the indifference curves do not have any kinks. The first
two indifference curves displayed in Figure 6 are examples of smooth preference relations and the
next two are examples of preference relations that are not smooth. If a preference relation is smooth
then for any bundle 𝑞 with positive component (i.e., 𝑞1 > 0 and 𝑞2 > 0) we have
1
MRS1,2 (𝑞) = . (5)
MRS2,1 (𝑞)

𝑞2 𝑞2

𝑞
𝑞

𝑞′
𝑞′
𝑞1 𝑞1

Figure 5: The graph one the left displays a indifference curve on which the diminishing marginal rate
of substitution assumption holds. The graph on the right displays an indifference curve on which the
marginal rate of substitution of good 2 for good 1 increases as we move in the increasing 𝑞1 direction along
the indifference curve. Hence the diminishing marginal rate of substitution assumption does not hold for
the indifference curve on the right.

3 Optimal Bundle
Okay, now that we have a grasp of the consumer’s constraints and preferences, it is time to characterize her
choice. The following is a formal definition of the consumer’s “favorite bundle among the feasible ones”.
Definition 2. Given the prices 𝑝1 , 𝑝 2 , . . . , 𝑝𝑛 and income 𝐼 , a bundle 𝑞 ∗ = (𝑞1∗ , 𝑞 ∗ , . . . , 𝑞𝑛∗ ) is an optimal bun-
dle if and only if
• 𝑖𝑛=1 𝑝𝑖 𝑞𝑖∗ = 𝑝1𝑞1∗ + 𝑝2𝑞2∗ + · · · + 𝑝𝑛 𝑞𝑛∗ ≤ 𝐼 (𝑞 ∗ is feasible), and
Í

• for any bundle 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 , . . . , 𝑞𝑛 ), if 𝑖𝑛=1 𝑝𝑖 𝑞𝑖 ≤ 𝐼 (i.e., 𝑞 is feasible), then 𝑞 ∗ ≿ 𝑞 (i.e., 𝑞 ∗ is at least as
Í
good as any feasible bundle).
Thus, a bundle is optimal if and only if it is feasible and is at least as good as (for the consumer) any feasible
bundle. Alternatively, a bundle 𝑞 ∗ is optimal if and only if any bundle that is preferred to 𝑞 ∗ is not feasible.
We will now find the optimal bundle 𝑞 ∗ when there are two goods (the argument is generalizable to more
than two goods). A starting point to develop the intuition is as follows. The optimality conditions imply
that the consumer needs to find the highest indifference curve, given her budget constraint. Can you try
to draw a budget set, the indifference curves, and find the optimal bundle?
Now, let’s get more formal. Please note that all the statements below assume that the preferences are “well-
defined” (i.e., they satisfy completeness, transitivity and monotonicity). In what follows, I will posit some
claims – which are “Claims” in the mathematical sense, so they are correct statements under the assump-
tions we made. They are not “claims” in the colloquial sense. They have proofs. I am relegating the proofs
to the Appendix to make this document more readable. Check them out if you are interested.
Assume that there are two goods and 𝑞 ∗ = (𝑞1∗ , 𝑞2∗ ) ∈ ℝ2+ is an optimal bundle. Our first claim is that the the
optimal bundle must be on the budget line.

8
𝑞2 𝑞2

𝑞1 𝑞1
𝑞2 𝑞2

𝑞1 𝑞1

Figure 6: The indifference curves at the top are smooth and the indifference curves at the bottom have
kinks.

9
Claim 1. If 𝑞 ∗ is optimal, then 𝑝1 𝑞1∗ + 𝑝 2𝑞2∗ = 𝐼 .
Informally, Claim 1 means that the consumer must exhaust her budget under the optimal bundle. This is
intuitively due to monotonocity: more is always better than less, and there is no reason to keep the money
in the pocket, so you better just spend the money.
Our second claim is a subtle one that relates the marginal rate of substitution to the price ratio.
Claim 2. If 𝑞 ∗ is optimal and 𝑞1∗ > 0, then
𝑝1
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥ . (6)
𝑝2

Informally, Claim 2 says the following: if the consumer is buying good 1 in a strictly positive quantity, then
it must be the case that she likes good 1 enough. Otherwise, buying good 1 would not be optimal.
The consumer could also consider consuming a “little” less of good 2 (provided that 𝑞2∗ > 0). Arguments
similar to the above would yield the following claim.
Claim 3. If 𝑞 ∗ is optimal and 𝑞2∗ > 0, then
𝑝2
MRS1,2 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥ . (7)
𝑝1

Informally, Claim 3 says: if the consumer is buying good 2 in a strictly positive quantity, then it must be the
case that she likes good 2 enough. Otherwise, buying good 2 would not be optimal.
Now, it is time to combine everything we know and have the “big reveal” of consumer theory. That would
be the theorem below.
Theorem 1. Given the prices 𝑝1 , 𝑝2 and income 𝐼 , if 𝑞 ∗ is an optimal bundle, then 𝑝1 𝑞1∗ + 𝑝2𝑞2∗ = 𝐼 and
• if 𝑞1∗ > 0, then
𝑝1
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥ ,
𝑝2

• if 𝑞2∗ > 0, then


𝑝2
MRS1,2 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥ ,
𝑝1

• if 𝑞1∗ > 0, 𝑞2∗ > 0, and preference is smooth, then


𝑝1
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) = .
𝑝2

Figure 7 illustrates the optimal bundle when 𝑞1∗ > 0 and 𝑞2∗ > 0. Intuitively, it is the point where the indif-
ference curve passing through 𝑞 ∗ barely touches the budget line, i.e. it is tangent to the budget line.
Take a moment to appreciate the beauty of this result! In the optimal bundle, the marginal rate of substi-
tution is exactly equal to the price ratio. That is, suppose you go and ask the consumer in a supermarket:
“I see your shopping cart, which contains your optimal bundle. Let me ask you a hypothetical
question. At the optimal bundle, how much do you value good 1 in terms of good 2?”
And suppose her answer is:
“Five. You need to give me five units of good 2 for me to give up one unit of good 1.”
And then you go ask the cashier in the supermarket:
“How expensive is good 1 relative to good 2?”
Almost magically, her answer is:

10
q2

I
p2

q∗

I
q1
p1

Figure 7: The optimal bundle 𝑞 ∗ is on the budget line and satisfies MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) = 𝑝2 .
𝑝1

“Five. You can give up five units of good 2 and buy one unit of good 1 instead.”
Isn’t this amazing? What is more amazing is that this applies to every single consumer in the supermarket,
regardless of their preferences. Another customer may be a fan of good 1, i.e. her MRS2,1 may be higher
for every bundle. Fine, she keeps buying more of good 1 and less of good 2, until the marginal rate of
substitution decreases and she finds the bundle where the marginal rate of substitution equals the price
ratio.
In the appendix, I provide some examples of “famous” preferences and discuss the properties of the opti-
mal bundle under those preferences. You may want to take a look at them before you solve some exercises.

11
Appendix

A Proofs
Proof of Claim 1. Suppose, towards a contradiction, that 𝑝1𝑞1∗ + 𝑝2𝑞2∗ ≠ 𝐼 . There are two possibilities.
• If 𝑝 1𝑞1∗ + 𝑝2𝑞2∗ > 𝐼 , 𝑞 ∗ would not be feasible. This would contradict feasibility of 𝑞 ∗ .
• If 𝑝1 𝑞1∗ + 𝑝2𝑞2∗ < 𝐼 , the consumer can afford another bundle 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1∗ + Δ1 , 𝑞2∗ + Δ2 ), i.e. 𝑞 ′ is feasible.
Because the preference relation is monotonic, this is preferred to 𝑞 ∗ , i.e. 𝑞 ′ ≻ 𝑞 ∗ . This contradicts the
optimality of 𝑞 ∗ .
Since both cases lead to a contradiction, the proof follows. □

Proof of Claim 2. Assume that 𝑞1∗ > 0. Let Δ𝑞1 be a “small” positive quantity such that 𝑞1∗ − Δ𝑞1 ≥ 0. (Since
𝑞1∗ is positive, there is such a positive quantity).
The consumer is considering the bundle 𝑞 ∗ . If she consumes Δ𝑞1 units less of good 1 (i.e., consumes 𝑞1∗ −Δ𝑞1
units of good 1 rather than 𝑞1∗ units of it), then the consumer would require (approximately) MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ )Δ𝑞1
units of good 2 to substitute for good 1 (so that the she is indifferent between the final bundle and the initial
bundle 𝑞 ∗ ). But if the consumer buys Δ𝑞1 units less of good 1, she would have 𝑝1 Δ𝑞1 TL to spend on good 2.
With this money she can buy (𝑝1 Δ𝑞1 )/𝑝2 units of good 2. If
𝑝1 Δ𝑞1
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ )Δ𝑞1 < , (8)
𝑝2

then the consumer would become better off by consuming Δ𝑞1 units less of good 1 and (𝑝1 Δ𝑞1 )/𝑝2 units
more of good 2. That is, if (8) holds, then the bundle

𝑞1∗ − Δ𝑞1 , 𝑞 ∗ + (𝑝 1 /𝑝2 )Δ𝑞1




is feasible and is preferred to the bundle 𝑞 ∗ . But this contradicts with 𝑞 ∗ being optimal. Thus, if 𝑞 ∗ is opti-
mal, then (8) can not be true, which means that
𝑝1 Δ𝑞1
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ )Δ𝑞1 ≥
𝑝2

must be true. Since Δ𝑞1∗ is positive, dividing both sides of the above inequality with 𝑞1∗ we obtain:
𝑝1
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥ .
𝑝2

Proof of Claim 3 is very similar to that of Claim 2, so I am leaving it as an exercise.

Proof of Theorem 1. The proof of first two bullet points follow from Claims 2 and 3. For the last bullet point:
If preference is smooth and 𝑞 ∗ is an optimal bundle with 𝑞1∗ > 0 and 𝑞2∗ > 0, then Claim 2, (5), and Claim 3
imply:
𝑝1 1 𝑝1
≥ = MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥
𝑝2 MRS1,2 (𝑞 ∗ ) 𝑝2
Which in turn implies
𝑝1
MRS2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) = .
𝑝2

12
B Optimal Bundle for Some Famous Preferences
(This appendix is meant to be supplementary. It will hopefully serve as a guideline for future exercises.
Please take some personal time to go through these examples on your own.)
The preferences we consider throughout this appendix satisfy completeness, transitivity and monotonic-
ity. We will keep assuming that there are two goods for the sake of visualization, but once again the ideas
extend. We will keep the budget constraint the same across examples: a bundle 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) is feasible if
and only if 𝑝1 𝑞1 + 𝑝2 𝑞2 ≤ 𝐼 .

B.1 Perfect Substitutes


Suppose the consumer’s preferences are such that: for any 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) and 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ ),
𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ ⇐⇒ 𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 ≥ 𝑎𝑞1′ + 𝑏𝑞2′ (9)

where 𝑎 > 0 and 𝑏 > 0.

How do indifference curves look like? Recall that the consumer is indifferent between any two bundles
on an indifference curve. Therefore, if 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ are on the same indifference curve,
𝑞 ∼ 𝑞 ′ ⇐⇒ 𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′ ≿ 𝑞 (by definition of indifference)
⇐⇒ 𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 ≥ 𝑎𝑞1′ + 𝑏𝑞2′ and 𝑎𝑞1′ + 𝑏𝑞2′ ≥ 𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 (by the preferences in Equation (9))
⇐⇒ 𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 = 𝑎𝑞1′ + 𝑏𝑞2′

What does it mean? Consider the line defined by the equation:


𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 = 𝑐 (10)

with some 𝑐 ≥ 0. The consumer is indifferent between any two bundles 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ on this line, because
𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 = 𝑐 = 𝑎𝑞1′ + 𝑏𝑞2′

Let’s make sure that this is actually a line. Rearranging Equation (10), we arrive at:
𝑐 𝑎
𝑞2 = − 𝑞1
𝑏 𝑏
which is, geometrically, the equation for a line with intercept 𝑏𝑐 and slope − 𝑏𝑎 .
So the indifference curves in this case are parallel lines, each with slope − 𝑏𝑎 . A higher 𝑐 means that the
consumer is on a “higher” indifference curve, meaning that the consumer prefers the bundles on the in-
difference curves with higher 𝑐 to the bundles on the indifference curves with lower 𝑐 . You can verify this
using two alternative methods.
1. Take two indifference curves
𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 = 𝑐
𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 = 𝑐 ′
with 𝑐 ′ > 𝑐 . Just drawing these indifference curves, you will see that the second indifference curve is
higher than the first one (it is further away from the origin.)
Take a bundle 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) on the first indifference curve, and another bundle 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ ) on the sec-
ond indifference curve. By the equations defining the indifference curves, they following equalities
must hold:
𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 = 𝑐
𝑎𝑞1′ + 𝑏𝑞2′ = 𝑐 ′
But since 𝑐 ′ > 𝑐 , 𝑎𝑞1′ + 𝑏𝑞2′ > 𝑎𝑞1 + 𝑏𝑞2 . Then, by the preferences in Equation (9), 𝑞 ′ ≻ 𝑞.

13
2. Just pick two bundles 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) and 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ ) where 𝑞1′ > 𝑞1 and 𝑞2′ > 𝑞2 . Draw the indifference
curves that pass through 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ , and you will see that the one that passes through 𝑞 ′ is further away
from the origin. By monotonicity,
𝑞′ ≻ 𝑞
By the definition of an indifference curve, the consumer is indifferent between 𝑞 and any bundle 𝑞 ′′
on the indifference curve passing through 𝑞.
𝑞 ′′ ∼ 𝑞
Similarly, the consumer is indifferent between 𝑞 ′ and any bundle 𝑞 ′′′ on the indifference curve pass-
ing through 𝑞 ′ .
𝑞 ′′′ ∼ 𝑞 ′
By transitivity,
𝑞 ′′′ ∼ 𝑞 ′ ≻ 𝑞 ∼ 𝑞 ′′ =⇒ 𝑞 ′′′ ≻ 𝑞 ′′

q2
c0

c
slo
pe

q 00 q0
=−

q2
a
b

q 000

q1 q1

Figure 8: Indifference curves for preferences given in Equation (9).

Fine, but what do they mean? The interesting thing about lines is that their slopes are constant. Since
the (absolute value of the) slope of the indifference curve is the marginal rate of substitution, it means that
the marginal rate of substitution is constant.
𝑎
𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) = for all 𝑞
𝑏

Recall that 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) is a measure of how much the consumer values good 1 in terms of good 2 when she
is endowed with bundle 𝑞. When 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) is constant, this means that the relative value of good 1 does
not depend on the bundle 𝑞. No matter how many units of good 1 and good 2 the consumer considers, the
relative value is the same. You can always take away 𝑏 units of good 1 from the consumer, compensate
the consumer by giving 𝑎 extra units of good 2, and leave the consumer indifferent. That is, no matter
what the consumer is endowed with, 𝑎 units of good 2 can always perfectly substitute 𝑏 units of good 1.
That’s why good 1 and good 2 are perfect substitutes.

14
Examples? We typically consider the goods that are very similar in quality to be perfect substitutes. Take
Coca Cola and Pepsi, for instance. You may like Coca Cola more than Pepsi, which is fine. In that the, the
marginal rate of substitution of Pepsi for Coca Cola will be higher than one. What matters is that if you
are willing to substitute one Coca Cola for one Pepsi when you have 10 Pepsis and 0 Coca Colas, then you
should be willing to substitute one Coca Cola for one Pepsi when you have 9 Pepsis and 1 Coca Cola. So
and so on.

Is the diminishing marginal rate of substitution satisfied? No. The marginal rate of substitution is con-
stant.

Are the preferences smooth? Yes. The indifference curves do not have any kinks. Therefore, 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 1,2 (𝑞) =
1 1
𝑀 𝑅𝑆 1,2 (𝑞 ) = 𝑎/𝑏 = 𝑎 for all 𝑞.
𝑏

Depends on 𝑏𝑎 (marginal rate of substitution) and 𝑝21 (marginal rate of trans-


𝑝
What is the optimal bundle?
formation.)
• To begin, suppose 𝑏𝑎 < 𝑝12 and consider the optimal bundle 𝑞 ∗ = (𝑞1∗ , 𝑞2∗ ). That is, the indifference
𝑝

curves are flatter than the budget line. I claim that in this case, we must have 𝑞1∗ = 0. Why? Suppose
not, i.e., suppose 𝑞1∗ > 0. But then, by Theorem 1, we must have 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥ 𝑝21 . But recall that
𝑝

𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) = 𝑏𝑎 < 𝑝12 . This is a contradiction. Therefore, we cannot have 𝑞1∗ > 0. We conclude that
𝑝

𝑞1∗ = 0, and the consumer spends all her income on 𝑞2∗ . The optimal bundle is 𝑞 ∗ = (0, 𝑝𝐼2 ).
Intuitively, what is going on? 𝑏𝑎 being low means that the consumer does not value good 1 much.
Indeed, the relative price of good 1 in terms of good 2 is higher than the relative value of good 1 in
terms of good 2. The consumer can always buy 𝑏 units less of good 1. This will save the consumer
𝑏𝑝1 . With these savings, the consumer can buy an extra 𝑝21 units of good 2. Since 𝑝12 > 𝑏𝑎 , 𝑝21 > 𝑎.
𝑏𝑝 𝑝 𝑏𝑝

Thus, the consumer can buy more than 𝑎 units of good 2 with her savings. But remember that 𝑎 units
of good 2 would leave the consumer indifferent! Anything more than 𝑎 units of good 2 would make
the consumer strictly happier! As a result, the consumer keeps reducing her consumption of good 1
until she has no good 1 left in her bundle.
Geometrically, the following is going on:
It’s just the consumer finding the “highest” indifference curve subject to the budget constraint.
• Next, suppose 𝑏𝑎 > 𝑝12 , i.e. the indifference curves are steeper than the budget line. Consider the
𝑝

optimal bundle 𝑞 ∗ = (𝑞1∗ , 𝑞2∗ ). I claim that in this case, we must have 𝑞2∗ = 0. Why? Suppose not, i.e.,
suppose 𝑞2∗ > 0. But then, by Theorem 1, we must have 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 1,2 (𝑞 ∗ ) ≥ 𝑝12 . But recall that 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 1,2 (𝑞 ∗ ) =
𝑝

< 𝑝21 . This is a contradiction. Therefore, we cannot have 𝑞2∗ > 0. We conclude that 𝑞2∗ = 0, and the
𝑏 𝑝
𝑎
consumer spends all her income on 𝑞1∗ . The optimal bundle is 𝑞 ∗ = ( 𝑝𝐼1 , 0).

• Finally, consider the case 𝑏𝑎 = 𝑝12 . The indifference curves are parallel to the budget line! In this case,
𝑝

there are many optimal bundles. Indeed, any bundle on the budget line is optimal.
This is a somewhat knife-edge case (a consumer whose relative value exactly equals the relative price),
but not impossible to find. For instance, suppose 𝑎 = 𝑏 and 𝑝1 = 𝑝2 . This means the consumer is to-
tally indifferent between the goods (take away good 1, give good 2 in equal amounts, doesn’t matter),
and also the price are equal. This corresponds to cases where the brand of the item does not matter,
at all. I am thinking of something like bleach. Does the brand of the bleach matter at all? For many
people, no. When I need to buy bleach, I would just go ahead and buy the cheapest one. If the two
brands in the supermarket have the same price, I could buy either of them.

15
q2

q∗

slo
slope =

pe
=−
a
b
− p2
p1

q1

Figure 9: Optimal bundle when 𝑏𝑎 < 𝑝2 . The blue lines are indifference curves and the red line is the budget
𝑝1

line.

B.2 Quasi-linear Preferences


Suppose the consumer’s preferences are such that: for any 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) and 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ ),

𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ ⇐⇒ 𝑣 (𝑞1 ) + 𝑞2 ≥ 𝑣 (𝑞1′ ) + 𝑞2′ (11)

where 𝑣 (𝑥) is an increasing and concave function. That is, its first derivative is positive and decreasing (it
second derivative is negative). Think of 𝑣 (𝑥) = log 𝑥 or 𝑣 (𝑥) = 𝑥 𝛼 for some 𝛼 ∈ (0, 1).

How do indifference curves look like? If 𝑞 and 𝑞 ′ are on the same indifference curve,

𝑞 ∼ 𝑞 ′ ⇐⇒ 𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ and 𝑞 ′ ≿ 𝑞 (by definition of indifference)


⇐⇒ 𝑣 (𝑞1 ) + 𝑞2 ≥ 𝑣 (𝑞1′ ) + 𝑞2′ and 𝑣 (𝑞1′ ) + 𝑞2′ ≥ 𝑣 (𝑞1 ) + 𝑞2 (by the preferences in Equation (11))
⇐⇒ 𝑣 (𝑞1 ) + 𝑞2 = 𝑣 (𝑞1′ ) + 𝑞2′

What does it mean? Consider the curve defined by the equation:

𝑣 (𝑞1 ) + 𝑞2 = 𝑐 (12)

This is a typical indifference curve for quasi-linear preferences, where higher values of 𝑐 correspond to
“higher” indifference curves. You can rearrange this to get:

𝑞2 = 𝑐 − 𝑣 (𝑞1 ) (13)

Since 𝑣 (𝑥) is increasing, this curve is downward-sloping. Since 𝑣 (𝑥) is concave, this curve is convex. For a
higher 𝑐 , we shift this curve upwards.

Fine, but what do they mean? As you can guess by its name, quasi-linear preferences are “kind of” like
linear preferences. By “kind of”, we mean preferences are linear with respect to one good (in this case,
good 2) and not linear with respect to the other good (good 1).

16
q2

q∗ q1

Figure 10: Optimal bundle when 𝑝2 . The blue lines are indifference curves and the red line is the
𝑎 𝑝1
𝑏 >
budget line.

The marginal value that the consumer assigns to good 1 is decreasing in the amount of good 1 the con-
sumer has. It is, however, constant in the amount of good 2 that the consumer has. When the consumer is
endowed with more of good 1, she starts liking it less – this is like a usual good we consider. When the con-
sumer is endowed with more of good 2, her attitudes towards good 2 does not change – this is like “linear”
preferences.
You can see this feature by checking the marginal rate of substitution. Just take the derivative of Equation
(13) and take its absolute value to find the slope of the indifference curve:

𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) = 𝑣 ′ (𝑞1 ) for all 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 )

As you see, this depends on 𝑞1 but not on 𝑞2 . As long as 𝑞1 remains the same, you can increase 𝑞2 and
𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) does not change. This means if you compare two indifference curves and keep 𝑞1 constant,
their slopes are the same. Therefore, indifference curves are just shifted versions of each other in the 𝑦 -
axis.

Examples? Good 1 in this example is a standard consumption good, like apples. Good 2 in this example
is a good so that the consumer’s feelings towards it does not change no matter how much of it she has. Let
me give a somewhat radical example. Consider good 2 as money. The price of good 2 is 𝑝2 = 1. That is,
you can spend 1 TL and buy one unit of good 2, which is again 1 TL. Of course, this is just a representation:
we are not considering a consumer who spends money to buy money. Instead, we are thinking about a
consumer with a certain budget who decides how many apples to buy (𝑞1 ) and how much money to keep
in her pocket (𝑞2 ). The crucial thing is that 1 TL is always 1 TL, no matter how much money you have. So it
is reasonable to assume that consumers’ feelings towards money does not depend on how much money
they have already.1
1 This does not have to be universally correct: you can imagine people valuing the extra lira less if they have more money already.

That is, the preferences towards money can also satisfy diminishing marginal value. But especially for cash-constrained consumers,
having quasi-linear preferences with respect to money seems like a reasonable thing to do.

17
q2

q∗ q1

Figure 11: Optimal bundles when 𝑝2 .


𝑎 𝑝1
𝑏 =

I just want to point out: our earlier discussions made it look like the consumer has to spend all her income
when she goes shopping. Now you realize that this framework allows for more general outcomes. It is
possible to introduce money saved as another good and conduct the analysis as usual.
Another example: let 𝑞1 denote the time spent on studying for the economics exam, and 𝑞2 denote the time
spent on other activities (such as watching more episodes of Ask-i Memnu). 𝑣 (𝑞1 ) is the expected grade on
the economics exam when the student studies for 𝑞1 hours. The student has a very standard thing to do
when she does not study (the satisfaction you derive from Ask-i Memnu neither goes up nor goes down as
you watch more of it), so the value of the alternative activities does not change at all.

Is the diminishing marginal rate of substitution satisfied? Yes. Recall that 𝑣 ′ (𝑞1 ) is decreasing.

Are the preferences smooth? Yes, as long as 𝑣 (𝑥) is a smooth function (it does not have kinks).

What is the optimal bundle? The bottom line is that: the consumer keeps buying good 1 until the point
where her marginal rate of substitution is low enough, so she does not want to buy it any more. The ques-
tion is: what is the marginal rate of substitution if she, hypothetically, has spent all her income on good
1? At this point, she has bought 𝑝𝐼1 units of good 1. If this much is enough so that 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) is lower than
𝑝2 , that is more than enough. She should have stopped buying earlier and spend the remaining amount
𝑝1

on good 2. If 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) > 𝑝12 at this bundle, she spends all her income on good 1. If she had even more
𝑝

income she would buy even more of good 1, but she is constrained, so she stops here.
Formally, the optimal bundle depends on 𝑣 ′ ( 𝑝𝐼1 ) (marginal rate of substitution) and (marginal rate of
𝑝1
𝑝2
transformation.)
• If 𝑣 ′ ( 𝑝𝐼1 ) ≤ 𝑝2 , the optimal bundle is 𝑞 = (𝑞1∗ , 𝑞2∗ ) such that
𝑝1 ∗

𝑝1 𝑝1
𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) = =⇒ 𝑣 ′ (𝑞1∗ ) =
𝑝2 𝑝2

18
q2

sl o
pe
=
−v
0 (x
)

x q1

Figure 12: Indifference curves for preferences given in Equation (11).

𝐼 −𝑝1 𝑞1∗
and 𝑞2∗ = 𝑝2 It’s easier to see graphically; see Figure 13.

• If 𝑣 ′ ( 𝑝𝐼1 ) > 𝑝 2 , the optimal bundle is 𝑞 = ( 𝑝𝐼1 , 0). See Figure 14.
𝑝1 ∗

B.3 Cobb-Douglas Preferences


The following preferences are “invented” by Charles Cobb and Paul Douglas in the first half of 20th cen-
tury.2 Suppose the consumer’s preferences are such that: for any 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) and 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ ),

𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ ⇐⇒ (𝑞1 ) 𝛼 (𝑞2 ) 1−𝛼 ≥ (𝑞1′ ) 𝛼 (𝑞2′ ) 1−𝛼 (14)

where 𝛼 ∈ [0, 1] is a parameter that measures the “weight” that the consumer attaches to good 1 in her
preferences. If 𝛼 is higher, consumer has a higher inclination towards good 1.

How do the indifference curves look like? You can just imitate the arguments in the previous examples
to derive the equation for a typical indifference curve:

(𝑞1 ) 𝛼 (𝑞2 ) 1−𝛼 = 𝑐 (15)

Once again, higher values of 𝑐 correspond to “higher” indifference curves. You can rearrange this to get:
1 −𝛼
𝑞2 = (𝑐 ) 1−𝛼 (𝑞1 ) 1−𝛼 (16)

You can check that this is downward-sloping.


2 Fun fact: Paul Douglas later went on to serve as a senator ın the US for eighteen years! We, as economists, sometimes wish that

he pushed for a legislation that requires every preference to be Cobb-Douglas. :)

19
q2

sl o
pe
sl o

=
q2∗
pe

−v
0 (q 1
=

∗)
− p2
p1

q1∗ I
q1
p1

Figure 13: Optimal bundle when 𝑣 ′ ( 𝑝𝐼1 ) ≤ 𝑝2 .


𝑝1

Fine, but what do they mean? Not much in particular. Cobb-Douglas preferences are the standard pref-
erences used to capture preferences towards two standard consumption goods. As you will see (and as we
discussed in the lecture), these preferences satisfy all the nice properties of a typical preference relation.
As you will also see, the optimal bundle satisfies certain nice properties.
With a little bit of messy algebra (which you don’t need to know by heart), you can verify that:
𝛼 𝑞2
𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) = for all 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) (17)
1 − 𝛼 𝑞1

So, the marginal rate of substitution depends only on the ratio of 𝑞2 and 𝑞1 . Note that if 𝑞1 decreases and
𝑞2 increases, the marginal rate of substitution increases, i.e. good 1 becomes relatively more valuable to
the consumer. This is the diminishing marginal rate of substitution!
Also note that the marginal rate of substitution is higher when 𝛼 is higher, i.e., when the “weight” of good
1 is higher. This makes sense: if the weight of good 1 is higher, the consumer values good 1 more, which
translates into a higher 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞).
More importantly, as long as 𝑞12 remains the same, the consumer’s relative valuation of the good is the
𝑞

same. Suppose the goods are coffee and eggs. When the consumer is endowed with one cup of coffee
and three eggs, she has a relative value attached to coffee versus eggs. If the consumer has Cobb-Douglas
preferences, then she would have the same relative value when she has two cups of coffee and six eggs.

Examples? Usual consumption goods. Tea versus coffee. Apples versus bananas. White shirts versus
blue shirts. Sujuk versus Halloumi cheese.

Is the diminishing marginal rate of substitution satisfied? Yessss.

Are the preferences smooth? Yessss.

20
q2

q∗
q1
I
p1

Figure 14: Optimal bundle when 𝑣 ′ ( 𝑝𝐼1 ) > 𝑝2 . The consumer spends all her income on good 1.
𝑝1

What is the optimal bundle? Take my word for it when I say that in the optimal bundle 𝑞 ∗ = (𝑞1∗ , 𝑞2∗ ), the
consumer has 𝑞1∗ > 0 and 𝑞2∗ > 0. Why? If 𝑞2∗ = 0 and 𝑞1∗ > 0, the consumer would have 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) = 0. This
is inconsistent with 𝑞1∗ > 0, as we showed in Theorem 1.
Given that 𝑞1∗ > 0 and 𝑞2∗ > 0, Theorem 1 yields:
𝑝1
𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞 ∗ ) =
𝑝2

Use Equation (17) to substitute the left hand-side:

𝛼 𝑞2∗ 𝑝1
=
1 − 𝛼 𝑞1∗ 𝑝2

Rearrange to get:

𝑞1∗𝑝1 𝛼
=
𝑞2∗𝑝2 1 − 𝛼

What does this mean? 𝑞1∗𝑝1 is the consumer’s total expenditure on good 1. 𝑞2∗𝑝 2 is the total expenditure on
good 2. Combine this with the equation 𝑞1∗𝑝1 + 𝑞2∗𝑝 2 = 𝐼 to derive the following result:
“In the optimal bundle, the consumer spends 𝛼 fraction of her income on good 1, and 1 − 𝛼
(1−𝛼 )𝐼
fraction on good 2. Therefore, 𝑞 ∗ = ( 𝛼𝐼
𝑝1 , 𝑝2 ).”

Circling back to what we had before: recall that 𝛼 is the weight of good 1. If 𝛼 is higher, the consumer
allocates a larger share of her budget to good 1!

21
𝑞2

𝑞1

Figure 15: Indifference curves for preferences given in Equation (14). Note the interesting feature. If you
draw a ray passing through the origin, this ray intersects each indifference curve once. Along the ray, 𝑞21 is
𝑞

constant. Therefore, at those intersections, 𝑀 𝑅𝑆 2,1 (𝑞) will be the same.

B.4 Perfect Complements


I will not write this one in much detail. For perfect complements, usually a visual inspection suffices.
Suppose the consumer’s preferences are such that: for any 𝑞 = (𝑞1 , 𝑞2 ) and 𝑞 ′ = (𝑞1′ , 𝑞2′ ),

𝑞1 𝑞2 𝑞′ 𝑞′
𝑞 ≿ 𝑞 ′ ⇐⇒ min{ , } ≥ min{ 1 , 2 } (18)
𝑎 𝑏 𝑎 𝑏
where 𝑎 > 0 and 𝑏 > 0.
A typical indifference curve is defined by the following equation:
𝑞1 𝑞2
min{ , }=𝑐 (19)
𝑎 𝑏
Meaning? 𝑎 units of good 1 perfectly complement 𝑏 units of good 2. If the consumer has 𝑎 units of good
1 and more than 𝑏 units of good 2, the extra units of good 2 are useless. Examples? Left and right shoes,
coffee and sugar (if you are drinking coffee only with sugar and if coffee is the only thing you put sugar in).

Is the diminishing marginal rate of substitution satisfied? Not really.

Are the preferences smooth? Nope.

What is the optimal bundle? See Figure 17. Theorem 1 does not apply in this case because the prefer-
ences are not smooth. But a visual inspection suffices.

22
qsugar
q1 = 3q2

qcof f ee
1 2
Figure 16: An example of indifference curves for preferences given in Equation (18). Here, good 1 is coffee
(quantity is in cups) and good 2 is sugar (quantity is in cubes). The consumer consumes each cup of coffee
with three cubes of sugar (I know – she should reduce her sugar consumption.) Therefore, one cup of coffee
perfectly complements three cubes of sugar. Thus, 𝑎 = 1 and 𝑏 = 3.

qsugar
q1 = 3q2
10

6
q∗

qcof f ee
1 2 5
Figure 17: Optimal bundle. Suppose 𝑝1 = 5 TL, 𝑝2 = 2.5 TL and 𝐼 = 25 TL. The consumer could buy 5
cups of coffee, but it will be worthless without the sugar. She could buy 10 cubes of sugar (how expensive
is sugar, by the way???), but that would be worthless without the coffee. In the optimal bundle, she buys 2
cups of coffee with 6 sugars, which perfectly complement each other.

23

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy