Methods in Analytical Political Theory Compress
Methods in Analytical Political Theory Compress
This is the first book to explain how to use key methods in analytical
political theory. The methods discussed include contractualism, reflec-
tive equilibrium, positive political theory, thought experiments and
ideological analysis. Many discussions of political theory methods
describe and justify these methods with little or no discussion of their
application, emphasizing ‘what is’ and ‘why do’ over ‘how to’. This book
covers all three. Each chapter explains what kinds of problems in poli-
tical theory might require researchers to use a particular method, the
basic principles behind the method being proposed, and an analysis of
how to apply it, including concrete principles of good practice. The book
thus summarizes methodological ideas, grouped in one place and made
accessible to students, and it makes innovative contributions to research
methods in analytical political theory.
Methods in Analytical Political
Theory
Edited By
Adrian Blau
King’s College, London
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
4843/24, 2nd Floor, Ansari Road, Daryaganj, Delhi – 110002, India
79 Anson Road, #06–04/06, Singapore 079906
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107098794
DOI: 10.1017/9781316162576
© Edited By Adrian Blau 2017
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2017
Printed in the United Kingdom by Clays, St Ives plc
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Blau, Adrian, 1972– editor.
Title: Methods in analytical political theory / edited by Adrian Blau, King’s
College, London.
Description: New York, NY : Cambridge University Press, 2017.
Identifiers: LCCN 2016047820 | ISBN 9781107098794 (hardback)
Subjects: LCSH: Political science – Methodology. | Political science – Research –
Methodology.
Classification: LCC JA71 .M4225 2017 | DDC 320.01–dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016047820
ISBN 978-1-107-09879-4 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-107-49170-0 Paperback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of
URLs for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication
and does not guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Methods in Analytical Political Theory
This is the first book to explain how to use key methods in analytical
political theory. The methods discussed include contractualism, reflec-
tive equilibrium, positive political theory, thought experiments and
ideological analysis. Many discussions of political theory methods
describe and justify these methods with little or no discussion of their
application, emphasizing ‘what is’ and ‘why do’ over ‘how to’. This book
covers all three. Each chapter explains what kinds of problems in poli-
tical theory might require researchers to use a particular method, the
basic principles behind the method being proposed, and an analysis of
how to apply it, including concrete principles of good practice. The book
thus summarizes methodological ideas, grouped in one place and made
accessible to students, and it makes innovative contributions to research
methods in analytical political theory.
Methods in Analytical Political
Theory
Edited By
Adrian Blau
King’s College, London
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
4843/24, 2nd Floor, Ansari Road, Daryaganj, Delhi – 110002, India
79 Anson Road, #06–04/06, Singapore 079906
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107098794
DOI: 10.1017/9781316162576
© Edited By Adrian Blau 2017
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2017
Printed in the United Kingdom by Clays, St Ives plc
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Blau, Adrian, 1972– editor.
Title: Methods in analytical political theory / edited by Adrian Blau, King’s
College, London.
Description: New York, NY : Cambridge University Press, 2017.
Identifiers: LCCN 2016047820 | ISBN 9781107098794 (hardback)
Subjects: LCSH: Political science – Methodology. | Political science – Research –
Methodology.
Classification: LCC JA71 .M4225 2017 | DDC 320.01–dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016047820
ISBN 978-1-107-09879-4 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-107-49170-0 Paperback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of
URLs for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication
and does not guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Methods in Analytical Political Theory
This is the first book to explain how to use key methods in analytical
political theory. The methods discussed include contractualism, reflec-
tive equilibrium, positive political theory, thought experiments and
ideological analysis. Many discussions of political theory methods
describe and justify these methods with little or no discussion of their
application, emphasizing ‘what is’ and ‘why do’ over ‘how to’. This book
covers all three. Each chapter explains what kinds of problems in poli-
tical theory might require researchers to use a particular method, the
basic principles behind the method being proposed, and an analysis of
how to apply it, including concrete principles of good practice. The book
thus summarizes methodological ideas, grouped in one place and made
accessible to students, and it makes innovative contributions to research
methods in analytical political theory.
Methods in Analytical Political
Theory
Edited By
Adrian Blau
King’s College, London
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
4843/24, 2nd Floor, Ansari Road, Daryaganj, Delhi – 110002, India
79 Anson Road, #06–04/06, Singapore 079906
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107098794
DOI: 10.1017/9781316162576
© Edited By Adrian Blau 2017
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2017
Printed in the United Kingdom by Clays, St Ives plc
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Blau, Adrian, 1972– editor.
Title: Methods in analytical political theory / edited by Adrian Blau, King’s
College, London.
Description: New York, NY : Cambridge University Press, 2017.
Identifiers: LCCN 2016047820 | ISBN 9781107098794 (hardback)
Subjects: LCSH: Political science – Methodology. | Political science – Research –
Methodology.
Classification: LCC JA71 .M4225 2017 | DDC 320.01–dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016047820
ISBN 978-1-107-09879-4 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-107-49170-0 Paperback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of
URLs for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication
and does not guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Contents
v
vi Contents
Index 327
Contributors
vii
viii List of Contributors
I had the idea for this book in late 2008. The central concept has stayed
the same – a ‘how-to’ book with practical advice in bold type. But much
else has changed. I owe a great deal to early guidance from my former
colleagues at the Manchester Centre for Political Theory (MANCEPT),
especially Alan Hamlin, Jon Quong and Hillel Steiner. My Cambridge
University Press editor, John Haslam, and my anonymous reviewers
had invaluable advice about content and scope: they made this book far
better.
I have greatly enjoyed working with my contributors. I wanted every
chapter to give clear, concrete advice grounded in examples of good or
bad practice. It was a pleasure to see this take shape and I hope our
readers will benefit.
I dedicate this book to the memory of my father, Nat Blau, who passed
away in 2010 after a long and productive life. He was a doctor, researcher
and teacher. He would have approved of a book that seeks to be helpful,
practical and well exemplified.
My father had a strong sense of our intellectual limits: for example, he
sometimes said that ‘if a theory explains all the facts, the theory must be
wrong, because some of the facts are wrong.’ This book is written not in
the expectation that our arguments and tips are right, but in the hope that
enough of them are right that we can advance the debate – and that
readers’ challenges to our arguments and tips will do so further.
This is the first book of its kind. It must not be the last.
ix
1 Introduction: A ‘How-to’ Approach
Adrian Blau
1 Introduction
This is the first ‘how-to’ handbook in political theory. It describes
different methods (‘what is method X?’), justifies them (‘why do method
X?’), and explains what to do (‘how should I do method X?’). ‘How-to’
guidance is our main aim. Political scientists have hundreds of such
handbooks, from general overviews on research design to textbooks on
specific techniques. Philosophers have dozens of handbooks on logic and
critical thinking. But political theorists have no handbook on how to apply
the methods we use.
Existing books on political theory methods typically describe and
justify methods without much detail on implementation – ‘what is’ and
‘why do’ more than ‘how to’. For example, Quentin Skinner’s book on
methods in the history of political thought contains relatively little prac-
tical guidance (Skinner 2002: 40–2, 75–6, 79–80, 114–20). If you want to
interpret texts like Skinner, you will learn more from his actual research.
Similarly, there is little advice on how to implement the methods and
approaches covered in the fine volume edited by Leopold and Stears
(2008).
When we praise or criticize work in political theory, ‘how-to’ principles
are often implicit. For example, if you find that some definitions are
clearer than others, you have already grasped some principles of concep-
tual clarity, consciously or subconsciously. But you will struggle to find
much published guidance on defining terms clearly. Our book aims to
make such implicit principles explicit and adds new how-to principles as
well.
Much of our focus, then, is on the logic of inference – on how best to draw
robust conclusions, on how to justify our conclusions against actual or
potential critics. ‘It came to me in a dream’ is not typically considered
good methodology in political theory. Rather better is ‘I carefully distin-
guished freedom and autonomy, used thought experiments to test their
relative importance, and engaged with comparative political thought to
1
2 Chapter 1
how-to principles will hopefully clarify the issues, stimulate debate, and
advance research in political theory.
4 Historical Reflections
Of course, debates over methods have always been important in political
theory. Plato’s Republic can be read as highlighting the weaknesses of
Socrates’s method and the strengths of Plato’s new method, ‘dialectic’
(Reeve 1988: 4–9, 21–3). Machiavelli scorns abstract Platonic theorizing:
we should ‘concentrate on what really happens’, because a prince who
follows ‘theories or speculations’ will ‘undermine his power rather than
maintain it’ (Machiavelli 1988: ch. 15, 54). In other words, empirical
observation gives us more guidance than theoretical conjecture about
what works and what does not.
Introduction: A ‘How-to’ Approach 5
the normative debates, but it has changed the picture and led to better
answers.
This brief historical overview does not imply that good methods ensure
universally accepted answers or that progress is impossible without
a how-to handbook. But methods have clearly been important in political
theory from the beginning, and a how-to handbook could thus bring this
key issue into sharper focus and foster further development.
Richard Rorty and Slavoj Žižek. There is huge variety within these camps,
of course; some writers, like Jürgen Habermas and Bernard Williams,
arguably fit in both camps; and not all of these names would classify
themselves like this. Nor do all authors in this book.
Miller and Dagger (2003: 446–9) outline five principles of analytical
political theory: (a) it is essentially separate from deep metaphysical ques-
tions about the meaning of human life, (b) it involves conceptual clarity
and argumentative rigour, (c) it is normative, (d) it addresses a plurality
of competing values, and (e) it ‘aims to serve as the public philosophy of
a society of free and equal citizens who have choices to make about how
their society will be organised.’
I do not believe we need principles (d) and (e). More importantly,
principle (c) only entails normative political theory, whereas this book is
wider. What did Locke mean by ‘man’? Why did Tocqueville write what
he wrote? These questions are essentially empirical. Was Hayek
a conservative? Does Arendt have a positive conception of liberty?
These questions are both empirical and conceptual: we infer Hayek’s
and Arendt’s beliefs, then compare them to criteria of conservatism and
positive liberty, respectively. What is equality? Do liberty and power
overlap? These questions are fundamentally conceptual. Do Hobbes’s
laws of nature follow necessarily from his premises? Would Rawls’s
principles of justice differ if we changed the motivations of people in the
original position? These questions could be normative, but are in essence
exercises in logic and conceptual clarity. I see no reason to exclude these
questions from analytical political theory.
But ultimately, it does not matter whether you agree with this view of
analytical political theory. Nor does it matter whether you see yourself in
the analytical and/or continental camp, or even as something different. All
that matters is whether some of this book’s guidance helps you.
Although I sought a wide coverage for this book, there are gaps.
We have nothing on international political theory, for example, or on
how political theorists should use empirical research in history and social
science. Such gaps will be criticized, and rightly so. I have some excuses
here, but not for the paucity of women authors – only four out of seven-
teen. When I started inviting authors, it was men who tended to spring to
my mind and to the minds of most of the men and women I sought advice
from. Only late in the day did I see the effects of this implicit bias. Around
the same time I was struck by a perceptive comment on the Feminist
Philosophers blog, which notes that while it might seem arbitrary to invite
a woman to speak at a conference just because she is a woman, it is also
arbitrary that many of us tend to think of men when we are asked who the
leading figures in a field are. I’ve tried to change my thinking and my
8 Chapter 1
actions after reading the Feminist Philosophers blog, the Being a Woman in
Philosophy blog, and the edited book Women in Philosophy (Hutchison and
Jenkins 2013). But this came too late to have much effect on the line-up of
authors. Mea culpa.
So the range of authors is not representative; we have not covered all of
political theory, or even all of analytical political theory; and the title is
a bit of a lie. But what we have is still an exciting venture that seeks to do
something new and important: the first book that seeks to explain how to
do much of political theory.
Contrast this view with John Dunn’s ‘contempt’ for political scien-
tists who do empirical research without considering norms: ‘an adult
and civically responsible human being’ would not study politics like
this (1996: 30–1). Dunn is right that we need more integration of
empirical and normative research. But we do not need or want
everyone to do this: normative researchers may need to draw on
empirical research involving meticulous case studies or exhaustive
statistical number-crunching conducted by scholars with no taste for
normative analysis and no skill in doing it. And those narrow empiri-
cal political scientists may in turn depend on even narrower metho-
dological research by political scientists who are not even interested
in empirical research but merely the methodology of case studies or
of statistical analysis.
So, when Skinner is criticized for overlooking social and religious
contexts, or when Rawls is criticized for overlooking institutional details,
this might merely be a criticism of such oversights, not a recommendation
that Skinner and Rawls should actually have done such research. Let
Skinner be Skinner: why make him start new research projects in social
or religious history when authorities in social and religious history can do
that themselves, building on Skinner’s expertise, filling in his gaps, and
seeing how his conclusions would differ? Let Rawls be Rawls: why make
one of the world’s great political philosophers learn political science when
we can add that to his philosophizing while he concentrates on doing what
he does best? Of course it could be that Skinner or Rawls could spend
a few weeks reading up on other people’s research, and that this would
change their conclusions; but we should not forget that the individual and
the collective ideal are not always identical.
So, we probably want a diversity of approaches – methods-driven and
problem-driven research, specialist and pluralist research. We want peo-
ple who see deeply and people who see widely. So, political theorists
should play to their strengths while recognizing the inevitable limita-
tions of any approach, narrow or wide, and while being aware that
political theory is a collective enterprise where we all stand on each other’s
shoulders, so to speak.
I want to finish with some brief comments on how methodology of
political theory benefits you, and most importantly, with some meta-
reflections on how to do methodology of political theory. There are two
main benefits of thinking about political theory methods. First, good
methods can improve your arguments – the central aim of this
book. Second, and less obvious, methodological reflection can give
you extra publications, e.g. a journal article early in a PhD, or a spin-off
article from a substantive project. This helps your academic career, gives
16 Chapter 1
you a wider audience than you might otherwise get and lets you poten-
tially make a significant contribution to the discipline.
But be careful of writing highly abstract methodological analyses. If this
book convinces you of anything, it is hopefully that methodological
publications should ideally be practical and well exemplified, by
showing what practical guidelines follow from one’s methodological
principles and by illustrating how these ideas have been or should be
implemented. Jubb’s chapter is significant partly because realist political
theory is often very negative: its practical implications have been hard to
grasp. My own chapter reflects my feeling that little methodological
discussion in the history of political thought has actually helped me to
interpret ambiguous passages in texts or to resolve apparent contradic-
tions between different parts of the same text. Indeed, every chapter has
sought to show the value of a practical and well-exemplified approach to
methods in political theory.
This suggests that studying methodology should also be practical
and well exemplified. If using this book to teach methods, one could for
example set students a chapter to read and a substantive application (good
or bad) of the relevant method. This encourages students to think
through the methodological issues and apply them to a substantive issue
or study – which can in turn help us think through the methodological
issues.
So, methodological insights often come from substantive research.
Although methodological developments can happen at a very theoretical
level, or by borrowing from methods in other fields, often one simply reflects
on actual research in political theory and makes inferences about what is
done well or less well. We hope that by reflecting on our methodological
recommendations, and by reflecting on actual research in political theory,
you can contribute to the continuing development of methods in
analytical political theory. That is the spirit in which we have written
this book.
Acknowledgements
For comments and criticisms on earlier versions of this chapter, I thank
Kimberley Brownlee, Alan Hamlin, and my anonymous Cambridge
University Press reviewers.
References
Bentham, Jeremy, 1843. The Works of Jeremy Bentham, volume III, ed.
John Bowring. Edinburgh: William Tait.
Introduction: A ‘How-to’ Approach 17
Robert E. Goodin
1) Show your work. When you are thinking through a problem, you
naturally start by thinking up some plausible line, then considering things
that might be wrong with that, and often rejecting what was superficially
a promising line. Instead of just erasing all of that as a ‘mistake’ or ‘false
start’, write it all out (the original idea, why it was tempting, why it is
wrong). That’s what counts as argument in analytical philosophy.
2) Clean kill/clear clutter. Once you’ve identified your main
argument, clear away superfluous clutter that doesn’t speak to that
argument directly. KISS (‘Keep It Simple, Stupid.’). Remember, ‘clear’
is the highest term of praise in analytical philosophy.
3) Organization = argument. Use the structure of the paper to show
the structure of the argument, wherever possible. If you’ve got several
separate arguments, or complex sub-arguments, put them into new (sub)
sections whenever you can. Let the structure of section breaks do a lot of
work for you.
4) Layer. Once you have a nice clear main line of argument, feel free to
add layers of texture within subsections.
5) Revise, revise, revise. Leave it in the bottom drawer for a month
(maybe while it’s out for comment) and come back to it and revise again.
It’s surprising what you’ll see upon revisiting it with a fresh eye.
6) Let weight on the page be proportional to the weight the
proposition bears in your argument. If something is important,
signal clearly that fact (‘And here’s the crucial point: . . . ’). If it’s
important, go on about it at appropriate length, even at the risk of
redundancy and just rephrasing the same point in other words.
7) Distinctions = arguments. Simply pointing out a distinction –
drawing attention to the fact that this is different from that (with which
it might naively be confused or conflated) – is the most typical way of
making arguments in analytic philosophy.
8) Introduce key devices early. Where there is some important dis-
tinction or device that you’re going to need later, particularly at multiple
points in the paper, it can be a good idea to introduce it early. If it’s
important, and you want people to notice it, don’t just sneak up on it
18
How to Write Analytical Political Theory 19
1
This is what James G. March (1976: 76–81) celebrates as ‘the technology of foolishness’.
20 Chapter 2
the revisions can sometimes pull the paper all out of shape. If they’re really
important, you might want to rewrite the whole paper (or whole section of
the paper) afresh. But often retrofitting them to the existing structure just
doesn’t work.
14) Placement. Every paper has a ‘natural home’. It’s just a case of
matchmaking, knowing the personality of a journal and whether this
paper would be a good fit.
Acknowledgements
These notes grew out of discussions with Chiara Lepora during our time
together at the National Institutes of Health, 2009–10.
Reference
March, James, 1976. ‘The technology of foolishness’, in James March and
Johan Olsen, eds., Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations. Bergen:
Universitetsforlaget, 69–81.
3 Thought Experiments
1 Introduction
A thought experiment is, in one sense, just what its name suggests – an
experiment in thinking. But it is thinking of a distinctive, imaginative
kind that offers a potentially powerful investigative and analytic tool in
mathematics, science, and philosophy. In science, thought experiments
are a well-accepted, uncontroversial mechanism for testing hypotheses,
and in mathematics, they are one of the principal tools for valid reason-
ing. They can build and destroy arguments (Brown 1986). In negative
terms, they can (1) expose a contradiction, (2) undermine a key pre-
mise, (3) reveal a conflation of concepts or principles, or (4) highlight
the counterintuitive implications of an argument. In positive terms, they
can (1) demonstrate the consistency or coherence of a set of principles/
concepts, (2) highlight congruities and similarities between different
claims, (3) reveal the scope of the application of a given principle, and
(4) bring forth intuitions not previously considered, amongst other
things.
In philosophy, some thought experiments are highly influential, even
famous. In moral and political theory, famous examples include the
following:
1. Philippa Foot’s/Judith Jarvis Thomson’s Trolley Problem:
A runaway trolley is hurtling towards five people who are working on
the railroad track up ahead. The driver can either continue onto the
track ahead, thereby killing the five, or steer onto a second track off to
the side on which only one man is working, thereby killing the one. Is it
permissible to turn the trolley? (Foot 2002: 23; Thomson 1985:
1395).
This thought experiment serves various purposes. Some argue, for exam-
ple, that it is permissible to turn the trolley because the negative duty not
to kill the five outweighs the negative duty not to kill the one. This
experiment is discussed in a variety of political theory contexts, including
in just war theory on the legitimacy of defensive harm.
21
22 Chapter 3
2 Definitions
Thought experiments have been characterized variously as devices ‘of the
imagination used to investigate the nature of things’ (Brown and Fehige
2014), picturesque arguments (Norton 1996: 334), purely mental proce-
dures that aim to reveal something about the relationship between two or
more variables (Sorensen 1992: 186, 205), and judgements about what
would be the case if the particular state of affairs described in some
Thought Experiments 25
1
We do not mean to settle the debate between expressivists/non-cognitivists on the one
hand and cognitivists on the other. Even if normative judgements are ultimately entirely
a matter of affective states (and hence are not mental-state-independent), we mean to
signal that thought experiments aim to provide answers that at least appear to be partly
mental-state-independent.
26 Chapter 3
2
One might worry that an expressivist or non-cognitivist would reject this as a false
distinction. But a sufficiently sophisticated version of non-cognitivism presumably accepts
that, even if moral judgement is ultimately a matter of affective states, there is nonetheless
a plausible distinction to be drawn between raw affective states and ‘gardened’ or reflective
ones.
28 Chapter 3
3
Paradigmatically, complex thought experiments involve pairwise comparisons.
Thought Experiments 29
states of mind of all human beings that ever lived, and suppose this man wrote all
he knew in a big book, then this book would contain the whole description of the
world; and what I want to say is, that this book would contain nothing that we
would call an ethical judgment or anything that would logically imply such
a judgment. (Wittgenstein 1965: 6)
Wittgenstein’s scenario presupposes that there are no facts in the
world of the kind that he aims to deny and hence his hypothetical
does not test the claim that this is the case. Any other conclusion
about the book’s content would be contradictory. This would be
a fatal problem for a thought experiment testing whether ethical
judgements are facts. However, the example would be acceptable as
a descriptive hypothetical that merely aims to elucidate what
Wittgenstein means by facts.
that your sibling is healthy, but you can finance similar life-saving medical
treatment for a stranger. If you accepted that you must save your sibling, must
you not also save the stranger?
This thought experiment can be readily translated into a fallacious
argument:
p1: We can save our sibling at high cost to ourselves.
p2 : We have a duty to save our sibling.
p3 : The best explanation for why we have a duty to save our sibling is because this
is our sibling.
c1 ( t h e h y po t h e s i s ) : We have a duty to save our sibling even when this
involves a high cost to ourselves.
p4 : Saving strangers would involve high costs.
p5 : The costs of saving the strangers would be identical to those of saving our
sibling.
c 2 : We have a duty to save strangers even when this involves a high cost to
ourselves.
This argument is invalid because, even were the premises all true, the
conclusion need not be true: it does not follow from the fact that we have
a duty to save a sibling at high cost to ourselves that we necessarily have
a duty to do other things that are equally costly.
The condition of philosophical respectability has the virtue of
demystifying the status of thought experiments. If thought experi-
ments can be represented as conventional arguments that meet the
standards of valid reasoning, then it is unsurprising that they can act
as solutions to philosophical problems. As we argued, this is the case
with all complex thought experiments and with at least some simple
thought experiments. To be genuinely well-posed, however, thought
experiments should also be analytically useful to us and not corrupt
our reflections. This is addressed by the second condition, the con-
dition of argumentative relevance.
instance, the Sibling and the Stranger could be translated into a valid
argument that fails to meet this condition:
p1: We can save our sibling at high cost to ourselves.
p2 ’: The best explanation for why we have a duty to save our sibling is because
we have a duty to save others even at a high cost to ourselves.
c 1 ’ ( t h e h y po t h e s i s ) : We have a duty to save others even when this involves
high cost to ourselves.
p3 : Saving strangers would involve high costs.
p4 : The costs of saving the strangers would be identical to those of saving the
sibling.
c2: We have a duty to save strangers even at a high cost to ourselves.
The argument is valid, but ridiculous: P2’ misidentifies the principle to be
derived from considering the case of the sibling. Similarly, looking at
a simple thought experiment, if, in the Transplant Case, we forbid the
doctor to kill the one person to save the five on the grounds that a doctor
may never kill, then we are not testing what the experiment is meant to
test, which, among other things, is whether there is a normatively
significant difference between killing and letting die (see likewise Rivera-
Lopez 2005). By prohibiting the doctor from killing, we block the relevant
test, as we allow her status as a doctor to infect our reflection on the
scenario.
All in all, if we want to use our thought experiments as evidence for or
against a given hypothesis (premise), we need to make sure that the results
of the experiment actually support or challenge the argumentative move in
question. The key question is whether it is possible to make this condition
of testing the relevant hypothesis more concrete beyond prohibiting
obvious shifts in focus. We argue that the condition of argumentative
relevance translates into two weak constraints on the design of thought
experiments. The first requires that the experiment allow for rudimentary
alternatives (the Rudimentary Alternatives Constraint). The second
requires that the experiment not encourage narrative-framing bias (the
Moderate Narrative-Framing Constraint). These two weak constraints
can be contrasted with more demanding variants, which we reject.
Unwilling Rock: Assume that a large rock is not willing to move, but still moves.
Is the rock to blame when it kills someone?
The ancient philosopher who holds that willing is a necessary condition
for moving should not run this thought experiment – without some extra
stipulations – because he is pre-committed to the view that the object that
moved must have been willing to move. He should stipulate instead
a rudimentary alternative for how the object moved; for example, the
object moved because it fell just like a human being might fall if pushed
by a gust of wind.
Unwilling Rock 2: Assume that a large rock is not willing to move, but still
moves, pushed by a gust of wind (against its will). Is the rock to blame when it kills
someone?
Although we endorse the Rudimentary Alternatives Constraint, we
reject the more demanding Fleshed-Out Alternatives Constraint, which
holds that allowed alternatives must be fully fleshed out and rendered
comprehensible to us given what we know about the world (Wilkes
1988: 43ff.). Returning to the ancient philosopher, unlike the
Rudimentary Alternatives Constraint, the Fleshed-Out Alternatives
Constraint would require him to explain how a large, heavy rock can
be pushed by a gust of wind. We acknowledge that a fully fleshed-out
alternative would protect us from certain biases, but the protection is too
restrictive. It is implausible to hold that we really need a fleshed-out,
clear statement of the alternative to the ruled-out feature of the scenario,
in order to prevent the ruled-out feature from determining our
conclusions.
All in all, then, we accept that unconscious bias is real bias. But the
possibility of bias is not a reason to abandon theorizing that might be
subject to it. It is a reason to guard against it within the parameters of the
case. We think that the Rudimentary Alternatives Constraint allows us to
do so.
other theories. But even this suggestion should be resisted. That is,
even applied theories that carry support need a method to discern
whether the considerations brought to bear on a given problem (to
reach an all-things-considered judgement) are relevant from the moral
point of view. For example, we need to ask whether it is relevant to
consider such things as ‘this is my house,’ or ‘this is extremely
demanding,’ or ‘she is a woman,’ or ‘it’s repellent,’ or ‘I would not
do it myself.’ Thought experiments offer an efficient way of testing the
salience of such considerations (which is not to say that such testing
would amount to a proof. On the fact that thought experiments alone
do not deliver transparent data, see Kagan 1988).
require a full character brief in the way that actors would if they were
required to play a given part and to react ‘in character’.
experiments ask us to do. They ask us, instead, to judge how our current,
familiar concepts behave when exposed to new situations. To see this,
first return to the paint analogy. The thought here is that we are not asked
to use the British paints to paint the African landscape; we are asked
instead to use the African light to rule, say, on whether two identical-
looking British colours really are identical. When we cannot easily tell if
the colours are the same against the British light, we may benefit from
examining them under the African light. We examine the value of equality
by asking if we still value equality in such a context. If not, then we have
reason to suspect that what matters to us in our ordinary context is not
simply equality, but absolute levels of deprivation.
Second, consider another illustration of the application of our ordinary
concepts to new situations. In Rich and Superrich, we do not ask what we
would think if we were living in such a privileged society. Instead, we ask
whether we consider the inequality present in that privileged society too
unfair by our own, current standards. Pointing out that in a world with
only the rich and the superrich, no one would care about equality (and
that they may not even have a sense that they are unequal) is irrelevant to
the question of whether we now see the inequality as problematic. (There
is a wrinkle here. We may have a conception of unfair inequality according
to which inequality is only unfair if the people subject to it consider it
unfair; if this is so then, indeed, we may be unable to tell whether unfair
inequality characterizes the hypothetical scenario, but that is not because
the thought experiment is hypothetical and wacky, but because we do not
have the relevant empirical data about the people we are investigating.)
To conclude this section, we want to emphasize that wacky thought
experiments are not, in fact, used solely to advance academic debates,
which some might consider esoteric in any case. Testing how our
familiar concepts behave when exposed to new situations is
a common, undisputed, and powerful strategy in many fields, includ-
ing one closely aligned with normative theory, namely, law. It is
routine practice in law schools to hold moot courts revolving around
wild and wonderful cases so as to train law students in the application
of key legal concepts. And the application of such legal concepts as
theft and property is viewed as no less legitimate when the parties are
Martians stealing magic from Venusians. Moreover, in broad terms,
real court cases are exercises in thought experimenting since both
ordinary court procedures and norms of due process necessarily
yield an abstracted and idealized presentation of the facts of the case.
Ultimately, wacky thought experiments are not undermined by our
inability either to imagine all of their elements or to anticipate how the
concepts we are exploring would evolve in hypothesized worlds.
42 Chapter 3
a special box for him, thinking it well worth it. He earns $250,000
this way, a much larger sum than the average income. Is he entitled
to keep all of it?
This thought experiment is used to show that people’s exercises of
personal freedom, such as choosing to pay twenty-five cents to go to
Chamberlain’s games, will disrupt a patterned principle of distributive
justice, such as the principle that everyone should have equal resources.
Acknowledgements
We thank Adrian Blau, Cécile Fabre, Fay Niker, Jonathan Quong, Victor
Tadros, and Lea Ypi for their very helpful feedback on this chapter.
We also thank Fay Niker for her research assistance. We thank the
participants of the Oxford Political Theory Seminar (June 2010) and
the Manchester Centre for Political Theory Seminar (October 2010) for
their comments.
References
Brown, James Robert, 1986. ‘Thought experiments in the scientific revolution’,
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1: 1–15.
Brown, James Robert, and Fehige, Yiftach, 2014. ‘Thought experiments’, in
Edward Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016
Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/thought-experiment/.
Carson, Tom, 1993. ‘Hare on utilitarianism and intuitive morality’, Erkenntnis 39:
305–31.
Cohen, G. A., 2009. Why Not Socialism? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Coleman, Stephen, 2000. ‘Thought experiments and personal identity’,
Philosophical Studies 98: 53–69.
Cooper, Rachel, 2005. ‘Thought experiments’, Metaphilosophy 36: 328–47.
Crisp, Roger, 2003. ‘Equality, Priority, and Compassion’, Ethics 113: 745–63.
Foot, Philippa, 2002. ‘The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect’,
in Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 19–32.
Gendler, Tamar Szabó, 1998. ‘Galileo and the indispensability of scientific
thought experiment’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49: 397–424.
Haggqvist, Sören, 1996. Thought Experiments in Philosophy. Stockholm: Almqvist &
Wiksell International.
Hare, R. M., 1981. Moral Thinking. Oxford University Press.
Kagan, Shelly, 1988. ‘The Additive Fallacy’, Ethics 99: 5–31.
Martin, C. B., 1958. ‘Identity and exact similarity’, Analysis 18: 83–7.
Mulhall, Stephen, 2002. ‘Fearful thoughts’, The London Review of Books 24 (16):
16–18.
Thought Experiments 45
Norton, John, 1996. ‘Are thought experiments just what you thought?’, Canadian
Journal of Philosophy 26: 333–66.
Nowell-Smith, P. H., 1954. Ethics. London: Penguin Books.
Nozick, Robert, 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Oxford: Blackwell.
O’Neill, Onora, 1986. ‘The power of example’, Philosophy 61 (235): 5–29.
Parfit, Derek, 1986. Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press.
Putnam, Hilary, 1975. ‘The meaning of “meaning”’, in Keith Gunderson (ed.),
Language, Mind, and Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
131–93.
Rawls, John, 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Raz, Joseph, 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford University Press
Rivera-Lopez, Eduardo, 2005. ‘Use and misuse of examples in normative ethics’,
The Journal of Value Inquiry 39: 115–25.
Singer, Peter, 1972. ‘Famine, affluence, and morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs
1: 229–43.
Sorensen, Roy, 1992. Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press.
Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 1971. ‘A defense of abortion’, Philosophy and Public Affairs
1: 47–66.
Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 1985. ‘The trolley problem’, Yale Law Journal 94:
1395–1415.
Unger, Peter, 1982. ‘Toward a Psychology of Common Sense’, American
Philosophical Quarterly 19: 117–129.
Walzer, Michael, 1973, ‘The problem of dirty hands’, Philosophy and Public Affairs
2: 160–80.
Williams, Bernard, 1960. ‘Bodily continuity and personal identity’, Analysis 20:
117–20.
Williams, Bernard, 1973. ‘A critique of utilitarianism’, in J. J. C. Smart and
Bernard Williams (eds.), Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge University
Press, 75–150.
Wilkes, Kathleen, 1988. Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Winch, Peter, 1965. ‘The universalizability of moral judgments’, The Monist 49:
196–214.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1965. ‘A lecture on ethics’, The Philosophical Review
74: 3–12.
4 Reflective Equilibrium
Carl Knight
1 Introduction
The method of reflective equilibrium focuses on the relationship between
principles and judgments. Principles are relatively general rules for compre-
hending the area of enquiry. Judgments are our intuitions or commit-
ments, ‘at all levels of generality’ (Rawls 1975: 8), regarding the subject
matter. The basic idea of reflective equilibrium is to bring principles and
judgments into accord. This can be achieved by revising the principles
and/or the judgments. For instance, if I am considering the principle that
it is always wrong to lie, but have the judgment that it would not be wrong
to lie in order to save a life, I can reach equilibrium by revising either the
principle or the judgment.
Reflective equilibrium is the most widely used methodology in con-
temporary moral and political philosophy (Sinnott-Armstrong et al.
2010: 246; Varner 2012: 11). It has even been suggested that it is ‘the
only defensible method’ (Scanlon 2003: 149). Its popularity is undoubt-
edly strongly influenced by John Rawls’s use of it in his seminal A Theory
of Justice, published in 1971.1 However, the method precedes this, and
extends to other fields. For instance, Nelson Goodman wrote regarding
induction that ‘[t]he process of justification is the delicate one of making
mutual adjustments between rules and accepted inferences; and in the
agreement reached lies the only justification needed for either’ (Goodman
1965: 64). Some fields, by contrast, do not seem as amenable to the
method of reflective equilibrium. Within linguistics, for instance, native
speakers’ judgments of grammaticality cannot generally be replaced as
moral judgments can (Daniels 1996: ch. 4). Although most writers
treat reflective equilibrium as unproblematic within empirical sciences
(Daniels 1996: 31–3; Cummins 1998; Welch 2014: 4; see also
McDermott 2008), adjustment of empirical judgments also seems to be
1
Jo Wolff (2013: 808) notes that, of the papers collected in the first two series of Politics,
Philosophy, and Society, Rawls’s was unique in aiming to defend a substantive position, and
in deploying a distinctive methodology to positive effect.
46
Reflective Equilibrium 47
2 Judgments
The starting point for reflective equilibrium is our judgments. We cannot,
however, use just any judgments. For instance, judgments made ‘in the
heat of the moment’ would not be a reliable basis for equilibrium.
Considered judgments are what we need. These are ‘those judgments in
which our moral capacities are most likely to be displayed without distor-
tion’ (Rawls 1999: 42).
Most writers, including Rawls (1999: 42), suppose that, in order to
count as considered, judgments should be held with confidence. Indeed,
Rawls often uses ‘convictions’ as a synonym for ‘judgments’ (Rawls 1975:
8; 2005: 24, 26, 28, 151, 156). This ‘confidence constraint’ seems to me
quite gratuitous (Knight 2006: 207–8). If I have the firm conviction that
the state should protect its citizens from terrorism, and also believe, less
firmly, that individuals have a right to privacy, a right to not be subject to
pre-trial detention beyond a certain duration and a right to a public trial,
the confidence constraint would seem to require that my numerous but
less firmly held concerns about individual rights be set aside. But this is to
give free reign to the one firm conviction, with the upshot that the
principle(s) arrived at in reflective equilibrium will allow almost any
breach of civil rights in the name of public protection. This is in
48 Chapter 4
4 Challenges
As the most widespread approach to theory selection in moral and poli-
tical philosophy, the method of reflective equilibrium has faced its share
of critical attention. In this section I consider a couple of the more
significant challenges.
A common complaint with the method is that it relies entirely on the
quality of the judgments that form a central part of the equilibrium
(Brandt 1979: 20; Williamson 2007: 244–6). Advocates of the method
typically build their examples around highly plausible judgments, such as
Rawls’ convictions about the wrongness of religious intolerance and racial
subordination. But if someone starts with implausible or even repugnant
judgments, there is, critics claim, nothing to stop the method from gen-
erating implausible conclusions. The point is put clearly by Thomas Kelly
and Sarah McGrath (2010: 346–7):
It is a good objection to a method if it turns out that impeccably following that
method could lead one to views that are unreasonable. It follows from this that if
beginning from all and only one’s considered judgments, and from there achiev-
ing wide reflective equilibrium without making any ‘downstream’ mistakes, is
sufficient for impeccably executing the method of reflective equilibrium, then the
method is not correct. The problem is that something might very well qualify as
a considered judgment, when that notion is understood in anything like the way it
is understood in the broadly Rawlsian tradition, and yet be utterly lacking in
rational credibility.
This is illustrated with the observation that there is nothing to stop ‘[o]ne
is morally required to occasionally kill randomly’ from counting as
2
Welch even defends a radical version of reflective equilibrium in which ‘there are no
considered judgments to consider’ (Welch 2014: 14).
Reflective Equilibrium 53
3
Kelly and McGrath seem to concede a similar point regarding empirical sciences – see the
lengthy quote given two paragraphs later.
54 Chapter 4
So suppose that the baseless beliefs about fruit flies are the following: fruit
flies originate from specific acts of divine creation; these acts occurred
within the past 10,000 years and are described in scripture; it is a matter of
religious duty to disregard all countervailing evidence regarding the ori-
gins of fruit flies. I think it highly plausible that these views are unreason-
able, and that ‘devot[ing] oneself to the study of fruit flies, and
impeccably follow[ing] the best scientific procedures we have for arriving
at accurate views about their nature’ does not stop these views from being
unreasonable. The lesson to draw from this is that neither the method of
reflective equilibrium nor the scientific method is guaranteed to rid people
of unreasonable beliefs. But that doesn’t change the fact that both are
more likely than alternatives to provide individuals with reasonable
beliefs, by exposing them to the most compelling evidence available in
their respective fields.
This leads us to the second challenge. Several writers have claimed
not that reflective equilibrium struggles with implausible idiosyncratic
judgments, like the random killing judgment, but with the fact that
our judgments are systematically undermined (Brandt 1979: 21–2;
Hare 1981: 12). Peter Singer emphasizes that our moral judgments
have largely arisen through an evolutionary process. For example, the
commonsense idea that we have stronger duties towards relatives can
be explained on the basis that the corresponding genes ‘are more likely
to survive and spread among social mammals than genes that do not
lead to preferences for one’s relatives that are typically proportional to
the proximity of the relationship’ (Singer 2005: 334; see also Singer
1974). It is no surprise, then, that brain scans suggest that our moral
judgments often do not seem to be informed by reason, but are rather
an immediate emotional response (Singer 2005: 339–42). Individuals
will stick to their judgment even where they end up rejecting the
reasons they initially give for it (Singer 2005: 337–8). This modern
scientific understanding of ‘how we make moral judgments casts ser-
ious doubt on the method of reflective equilibrium’, according to
Singer (2005: 348):
There is little point in constructing a moral theory designed to match considered
moral judgments that themselves stem from our evolved responses to the situa-
tions in which we and our ancestors lived during the period of our evolution as
social mammals, primates, and finally, human beings. We should, with our
current powers of reasoning and our rapidly changing circumstances, be able to
do better than that.
Suppose, for the sake of argument, that the evolutionary picture that
Singer paints is correct. I would not see this as a threat to the method of
Reflective Equilibrium 55
Here Singer claims that reflective equilibrium would have to rely not just
on the moderate, revisable foundationalism referred to earlier, but rather
on a stronger ‘special foundationalism’ (Harman 2003: 415) that identi-
fies certain ethical truths as unchallengeable. Were that true, it would
certainly be the case that reflective equilibrium had been stripped of its
distinctive features (in particular, mutual adjustment of judgments and
principles). But it is not true. Singer says that the interpretation should be
‘truly wide enough to countenance the rejection of all our ordinary moral
beliefs’. Reflective equilibrium is this wide (Sandberg and Juth 2011:
222). However, Singer’s conclusion implicitly assumes that countenan-
cing the rejection of ordinary moral beliefs will result in (1) their whole-
sale rejection and (2) the adoption of some mysterious ‘indubitable
starting point’, rather than a set of revised moral beliefs subject to reflec-
tive equilibrium’s usual ongoing epistemic tests. Both of these assump-
tions are quite gratuitous. A more likely result of considering Singer’s
background theory is a reduction in the weight we are willing to assign to
judgments that have a vividly personal quality, such as judgments favour-
ing family members or judgments assigning special opprobrium to harms
inflicted in a direct physical way, as these are likely to have evolutionary
origins (Tersman 2008: 397–8). There may be a corresponding increase
in the weight we are willing to assign to universal or impartial judgments,
4
Singer later seems to make this concession; see de Lazari-Radek and Singer (2012: 29–31).
56 Chapter 4
which have less (or possibly no) evolutionary baggage. Reforming our
judgments in this way would not mean that ‘the “data” that a sound moral
theory is supposed to match have become so changeable that they can
play, at best, a minor role in determining the final shape of the normative
moral theory’ (Singer 2005: 349). On the contrary, shifting judgments
play a full role as part of a ‘dynamic dialectical process’ (Brink 2014: 688).
5
It might be objected that this requirement seems incompatible with my rejection of the
‘epistemic constraint’ in Section 2. This objection misses the importance of the distinction
between constraints on the contents of judgments (such as the epistemic constraint) and
constraints on the circumstances of judgments. The former type of constraint is otiose, as
what it attempts to do (for instance, justification) is done more thoroughly by wide
reflective equilibrium. The latter type of constraint is essential as its functions cannot be
replicated by wide reflective equilibrium proper. For instance, a logical impossibility
should be cleared from our judgments once we consider relevant background theory,
provided we are reasoning in favourable circumstances. But the effects of unfavourable
circumstances, such as being drunk or ignorant of relevant political theory, will not be
cleared by reflective equilibrium, as the epistemic value of the process is fatally undercut
Reflective Equilibrium 57
4) The desire to reach the correct decision. The individual must be motivated
to arrive at justified principles. People (almost?) invariably come to
political theory with a set of preconceived ideas about politics. This is
fine provided that the individual is open-minded, willing to alter his or
her views in response to arguments. The fact that one is on record
defending a position should be no barrier to rejecting that position,
even where this might prove inconvenient or embarrassing.6
In short, the first step is to make sure that you undertake the process of
reflective equilibrium in the Rawlsian ‘conditions favorable for delibera-
tion and judgment in general’. The conditions established in the first
step must be maintained throughout the process.
The second step is to draw up a list of the main contending
principles on whatever topic you are considering. If you can think
of any compelling new principles, these should also be added to the list.
There is no specific number of principles that you should aim for, but as
a general rule and time permitting, more is better. Remember that, while
it is usually impractical in a work of political theory of 5,000 or 10,000
words to discuss a large number of principles, there is no ‘word limit’
when it comes to considering principles prior to or during the actual
writing process. Even if you only discuss two or three principles in detail
in the final product, you may have considered and rejected many more
during the process of reaching equilibrium. Presumably Rawls himself
did – in the ‘Presentation of Alternatives’ section of A Theory of Justice he
names more than a dozen ‘conceptions of justice’, several of them con-
taining multiple principles and one of them the extremely open-ended
‘list of prima facie principles (as appropriate)’ (Rawls 1999: 107). While it
would not be usual to provide such a lengthy list in writing, it is often
useful to mention in passing your reasons for rejecting some of the
principles that do not receive full discussion.
The third step is to begin reflective equilibrium in earnest. You
go through each principle, checking its prescriptions against your
judgments. Ask yourself: what are the central cases for my topic?
And what are the hard cases for this principle? The literature is, of
course, an invaluable resource for finding such cases, but you will also
come up with your own. Consider whether you can accept the impli-
cations of the principle in each of these cases. It may be that initially
6 An Example
I will now work through an example of reflective equilibrium on the topic
of distributive justice, using the aforementioned step-by-step guide and
my own considered judgments. I can obviously give only the scantest
indication of my reasoning here, summarizing years of work in a few
paragraphs. It is likely, furthermore, that the reader will disagree with
me at numerous points. The example should nevertheless illustrate one
way of reaching reflective equilibrium.
The first step is to make sure that my judgments are considered.
As I write this, it is 9.32 am, I had a good night’s sleep, I am aware of
the danger of conflicts of interest when discussing the societal allocation
of goods and am willing to counteract any resulting bias, and I have the
motivation and desire to reach the correct decision. So it seems that, right
now, I am making my judgments in suitable conditions. But as this test
must be taken each time you use the method of reflective equilibrium, it
must be repeated many times – indeed, many thousands of times in my
case!
60 Chapter 4
For the second step I have to draw up a list of the main principles within
this topic. Here’s my list:
– The principle of utility
– Rawls’s two principles of justice
– Equality of outcome
– Luck egalitarian principles (Arneson 1989; Cohen 1989)
– Democratic egalitarian principles (Anderson 1999)
– The principle of priority (Parfit 2000)
– The principle of sufficiency (Frankfurt 1987)
– Right libertarian principles (Nozick 1974: ch. 7)
– Left libertarian principles (Steiner 1994)
– The benefiting principle (Butt 2007)
– The principle of need
– The principle of desert
– Communitarian principles (Sandel 1982)
– Contractarian principles (Gauthier 1986)
– Egoist principles
The list is eclectic, and by design – the point at this stage is to avoid
missing anything important, not to construct the most elegant inventory
possible. Even so, other people’s lists would no doubt contain additional
principles.
With the third step I begin the reflective process by testing the princi-
ples and judgments against each other. Many principles can be set aside
quite quickly. I find nothing of merit in ‘free for all’ egoist principles, and
view the results of contractarian principles for people with low bargaining
power as utterly unacceptable, for instance. I do, by contrast, feel the pull
of the principle of sufficiency, as I am very concerned by those who are
very badly off in absolute terms. But I do not accept its implication that
those who are just below the threshold of ‘having enough’ get absolute
priority over those marginally above the threshold, who are only slightly
better off (Arneson 2006: 28). I therefore conclude that the principle of
priority better accommodates my concern with the absolutely badly off.
Similarly, I am attracted to equality of outcome and democratic equality,
as I am also concerned about inequality. But I am unhappy with demo-
cratic equality’s implication that large unchosen inequalities do not mat-
ter as long as individuals have equal social standing, and equality of
outcome’s implication that, where some squander their equal share of
resources, for instance by deliberately developing ‘expensive tastes’
(Dworkin 2000: 48–59), they should be ‘compensated’ to restore equal-
ity, at society’s expense. I find that luck egalitarianism, which avoids such
problems, fits with my judgments here better, but it has its own appar-
ently objectionable implication that those who make bad choices that
Reflective Equilibrium 61
For simplicity, I leave aside the fifth step. This brings us to the sixth
step. I have found luck egalitarianism and prioritarianism to be in accord
with my judgments. Now we need to decide on a rule to regulate conflicts
between these principles. It seems that neither the ‘eliminate involuntary
disadvantage’ (Cohen 1989: 916) goal of luck egalitarianism, nor prior-
itarianism’s concern with increasing absolute advantage (in particular,
that of the worst off), should be assigned lexical priority, as I would be
willing to give up a small improvement in either of these dimensions for
a large improvement in the other. So my conception of justice is a version
of ‘responsibility-catering prioritarianism’ (Arneson 1999; see also
Knight 2009: ch. 6), where luck egalitarianism and prioritarianism are
balanced against each other. Exactly what weighting, however, to give
each of these principles is a rather tricky question, to be tested through
considering a large number of cases, which I cannot do here.
Suppose, though, that I find a favoured weighting, and reach the
seventh and final step. Even then I cannot assume that weighting, or
even the selection of principles, to be settled for all time, as we can
reconsider any aspect of the process at any point. As Rawls (2005: 97)
cautions, ‘[t]he struggle for reflective equilibrium continues indefinitely.’
References
Ackerman, Bruce, 1980. Social Justice in the Liberal State. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Anderson, Elizabeth, 1999. ‘What is the point of equality?’, Ethics 109, 287–337.
Arneson, Richard, 1989. ‘Equality and equal opportunity for welfare’, Philosophical
Studies 56, 77–93.
Arneson, Richard, 1999. ‘Equality of opportunity for welfare defended and
recanted’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 7, 488–97.
Arneson, Richard, 2006. ‘Distributive justice and basic capability equality’, in
Alexander Kaufman, ed., Capabilities Equality. Abingdon: Routledge, 17–43.
Brandt, Richard, 1979. A Theory of the Good and the Right. Oxford University Press.
Brink, David, 1989. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge
University Press.
Brink, David, 2014. ‘Principles and intuitions in ethics’, Ethics 124, 665–95.
Butt, Daniel, 2007. ‘On benefiting from injustice’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy
37, 129–52.
Cohen, G. A., 1989. ‘On the currency of egalitarian justice’, Ethics 99, 906–44.
Cummins, Robert, 1998. ‘Reflection on reflective equilibrium’, in Michael DePaul
and William Ramsey, eds., Rethinking Intuition. Lanham, MD: Rowman and
Littlefield, 113–28.
Daniels, Norman, 1996. Justice and Justification. Cambridge University Press.
DePaul, Michael, 1986. ‘Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism’, American
Philosophical Quarterly 23, 59–69.
Reflective Equilibrium 63
Rawls, John, 2005. Political Liberalism, expanded edition. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Sandberg, Joakim and Juth, Niklas., 2011. ‘Ethics and intuitions: a reply to Singer’,
Journal of Ethics 15, 209–26.
Sandel, Michael, 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge University
Press.
Scanlon, T. M., 2003. ‘Rawls on justification’, in Samuel Freeman, ed.,
The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. Cambridge University Press, 139–67.
Scanlon, T. M., 2014. Being Realistic about Reasons. Oxford University Press.
Scheffler, Samuel, 2003. ‘What is egalitarianism?’, Philosophy and Public Affairs
31, 5–39.
Singer, Peter, 1974. ‘Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium’, The Monist 58,
490–517.
Singer, Peter, 2005. ‘Ethics and intuitions’, Journal of Ethics 9, 331–52.
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, Young, Liane and Cushman, Fiery, 2010. ‘Moral
intuitions’, in John Doris and The Moral Psychology Research Group, eds.,
The Moral Psychology Handbook. Oxford University Press, 246–72.
Steiner, Hillel, 1994. An Essay on Rights. Oxford: Blackwell.
Tersman, Folke, 2008. ‘The reliability of moral intuitions’, Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 86, 389–405.
Varner, Gary, 2012. Personhood, Ethics, and Animal Cognition. Oxford University
Press.
Walden, Kenneth, 2013. ‘In defense of reflective equilibrium’, Philosophical Studies
166, 243–56.
Welch, John, 2014. Moral Strata: Another Approach to Reflective Equilibrium.
Dordrecht: Springer.
Williamson, Timothy, 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.
Wolff, Jonathan, 2013. ‘Analytic political philosophy’, in Michael Beaney, ed.,
The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University
Press, 795–822.
5 Contractualism
Jonathan Quong
1 Introduction
Are you a contractualist? People sometimes ask this question in the same
way you might ask someone, are you Muslim or are you a Utilitarian?
They ask as if contractualism is a deep substantive commitment – as if it’s
an exclusive doctrine that competes with other normative theories.
I believe that this way of thinking about contractualism is flawed.
Contractualism is a method or a tool, not a first-order moral theory.
Asking a philosopher if she is a contractualist is thus a bit like asking
a carpenter if she is a ‘Hammerist’, that is, someone who uses a hammer to
the exclusion of all other tools of the trade.
For the purposes of this chapter, I will assume that contractualism is
a method used to answer some first-order normative question in moral or
political philosophy, according to which we should consider what a group
of idealized agents would or could accept under certain specified con-
straints. I will refer to the idealized agents as the contractors, and I will refer
to the general choice situation in which they are placed as the contractual
scenario. Obviously many different forms of contractualism are possible
since different assumptions can be made regarding who the contractors
should represent, how they should be idealized, what question they
should be tasked to answer, what constraints they should face, and what
alternatives they should confront in the event of non-agreement.
In this chapter I defend three main claims. First, like any good tool or
method, contractualism is a helpful way to tackle some problems, but not
others. Second, there are very different types of contractualism, and these
different types are designed to address different normative questions.
Finally, and relatedly, work in moral and political philosophy sometimes
goes wrong due to the failure to carefully distinguish these different forms
of contractualism.
The remainder of this chapter is organized as follows. Section 2 argues
that we can usefully distinguish three different forms of contractualism:
consent contractualism, fairness contractualism, and rationality contractualism.
65
66 Chapter 5
2 Why Contractualism?
Why ask what suitably situated contractors would or could accept? Why
not just ask what real people do in fact accept?
It’s not always possible to ask the relevant people what they would
accept. Sometimes this is because we are deciding whether to surprise
someone, whether to reveal information to someone, or whether to lie
to someone. Seeking the person’s consent would make it impossible to
surprise the person, avoid giving the person the information, or lie to
the person. Other times the problem is that the relevant people don’t
currently exist: we cannot directly talk to past or future generations.
Even when we can communicate with the relevant people, we may have
good reasons to disregard the answers they will provide. If the question
that interests us is what P would agree to if she were perfectly rational,
then asking the real P, who is far from perfectly rational, is not a good way
to answer the question. Similarly, we might want to know what political
principle persons would accept if everyone had exactly equal bargaining
power. Because real people do not have exactly equal bargaining power,
we cannot pose our question directly. We might also have good reasons to
ask what persons would accept if they had somewhat different aims or
motives – for example, what moral rules people would accept if they did
not already have various firm beliefs about rightness and wrongness, or
what political rules people would accept if they all shared a few particular
ideals, but diverged in many other ways.
In sum, it may be either impossible or undesirable to ask what real
people would accept. Under these conditions contractualism may be an
appropriate method for tackling certain moral or political questions. But
when exactly is it an appropriate method for doing so? What questions is
contractualism well suited to help us answer?
To begin, contractualism can be a useful way of trying to understand
whether some presumptively wrongful act or rule, ϕ, is in fact permissible
or legitimate when we think that permissibility or legitimacy depends on
whether persons would freely consent to ϕ if they could. For example, it is
presumptively wrong to cut someone open and operate on him without
his consent, but if the person freely consents to the surgery, the consent
typically renders the surgery permissible. But sometimes we cannot
obtain the person’s consent, and yet there are powerful reasons to proceed
Contractualism 67
1
Some refer to the narrow self-interested form of rationality contractualism as contractar-
ianism and contrast it with the contractualism of Rawls and Scanlon.
70 Chapter 5
3 Designing Contractualism
Having identified three of the main reasons to use contractualism, we can
consider in greater detail how contractualist scenarios should be designed
to best address a given problem. It will be helpful to distinguish five key
questions.
i. Constituency: Who do the contractors represent?
ii. Primary Question: What question do the contractors confront?
iii. Motives and Interests: What are the motives and interests of the
contractors?
iv. Information: How much information should be provided to the
contractors?
v. Non-agreement: What will happen to each contractor in the event of
non-agreement?
These are not the only questions that matter in designing a model of
contractualism, but they are central questions that heavily shape how the
model will work and what it can achieve. Let’s now consider how each of
these questions might be addressed from the perspective of the different
forms of contractualism.
2
In this example the identity of future persons is not what is at issue. Whether contrac-
tualism can also be used to address the so-called non-identity problem (where the choice
of policy will affect the identity of the future persons) is a further question. For an example
where contractualism is used in this way, see Reiman (2007).
72 Chapter 5
to all the relevant facts. Suppose, for example, we want to know whether an
unconscious patient would consent to an emergency procedure that has
a 5 per cent risk of death, or whether she would opt against the procedure,
in which case there is a 95 per cent chance she will suffer permanent
paralysis of her upper body. In cases like this it’s clearly acceptable if the
contractors know only the probabilities. After all, this is all the information
we have, and what we want to know is how the real person would choose
given the probabilities, not how she would choose if she knew the outcome.
Finally, we can turn to the issue of non-agreement in consent contrac-
tualism. If contractors are being asked whether they can accept the
imposition of ϕ, clearly a crucial feature of their decision will be informa-
tion regarding what will happen in the event that ϕ is not imposed. Other
things being equal, the worse the non-agreement point is for a given
contractor, the more likely she is to accept the imposition of ϕ. As we
did when considering how much information the contractors should be
given, we should be guided by the aim of ensuring that the choice made by
each contractor reflects the will of the real person being represented as
closely as possible. Thus, as a general rule, the non-agreement point
should be designed to accurately reflect what would happen to someone
in the event that ϕ is not imposed.
In some simple cases, the non-agreement point is clear. For example, in
the case just presented, if the doctor does not proceed with the surgery,
then no surgery is performed, and the patient faces a 95 per cent chance of
paralysis. In other cases, however, determining the non-agreement point
is more difficult. For example, suppose the question being posed is
whether citizens would consent to the coercive authority of the state if
given the choice. What should we assume is the non-agreement point?
Many philosophers have adopted some version of the state of nature as
the non-agreement point, but accounts of the state of nature vary wildly
from Hobbesian to Rousseauian.
The problem runs deeper than the mere fact that philosophers disagree
about what a state of nature might look like. Real citizens in contemporary
liberal democratic societies do not face the stark choice that some philo-
sophers ask their contractors to make: live in a state of nature or under the
authority of a state. Thus, even if we had a clear picture regarding what
the state of nature might look like, we should be wary of inferring anything
about the will or consent of real citizens from the hypothetical consent of
contractors confronting the huge question of whether the state is prefer-
able to the state of nature. Given the aims of consent contractualism, it’s
preferable to focus on questions that can be answered by confronting the
contractors with roughly the same options as those faced by the real
persons they represent.
74 Chapter 5
with the contractualist device here. Why not consider the question
directly? I want to set aside this objection for now, but I address it in
Section 4.4.
Let’s move on to the motives and interests of contractors in fairness
contractualism. Contractors must be partly driven by self-interest, at
least in the broad sense described earlier. That is, they must have their
own distinct plans that they wish to pursue. They will thus be motivated
to prefer rules that are more likely to advance their plans. But fairness
contractualism can also allow the motives and interests of contractors to
depart quite radically from the real-world persons that they represent.
The reason is simple: fairness contractualism does not aspire to accurately
reflect the will or prudential rationality of real people. Instead the aim is to
design a contractual scenario in such a way that whatever emerges as
a decision is guaranteed to constitute a just or fair decision. One way to
achieve this result is to stipulate that contractors are, in addition to being
self-interested, partly motivated by a desire to justify themselves to others,
and thus will only reject proposals on reasonable grounds, where ‘reason-
able’ is a partly moralized notion, one that requires contractors to take
due account of the interests and status of others affected by a proposed
rule or its rejection (see Scanlon 1998: 189–247).
There are two important and related objections to attributing to the
contractors moral motives that constrain the pursuit of their self-interest.
First, sceptics complain that the appeal to what contractors could reason-
ably reject will leave the results of the contractual device radically inde-
terminate. The problem is that the ordinary or everyday notion of
reasonableness is indeterminate or contested. Of course, there are some
attitudes and behaviours that we can all agree are unreasonable, for
example, viewing oneself as exempt from general moral rules that every-
one else must follow, or behaving as if one’s claims to resources or
advantages carry greater weight than those of similarly situated others.
But the cases in which we agree are too few to yield a precise account of
the concept, such that it can be reliably deployed to evaluate whether the
exercise of a veto is reasonable or unreasonable. Suppose, for example,
the question is whether those who fare worst under some distributive
scheme, D1, can reasonably reject D1 in favour of D2, where they would
be marginally better off, but everyone else would be significantly worse off
than under D1, though still better off than the worst off. The ordinary
sense of reasonableness does not provide an obvious answer to this ques-
tion, or to countless other questions where different considerations
appear to pull in different directions. If the notion of the reasonable is
so imprecise, our contractual device will be of no use for reaching deter-
minate results in most cases. This objection need not be limited to
76 Chapter 5
I won’t attempt a survey of the many objections that have been pressed
against Rawls’s use of the veil of ignorance. Instead, I want to consider
how much information should be excluded from what the contractors
know when designing a contractual scenario in which contractors are
purely self-interested.
The answer to this question might, at first glance, seem very straight-
forward. We should exclude any information that would give a contractor
an incentive to veto proposals for what we deem morally irrelevant rea-
sons. For example, if contractors knew the race of the person they repre-
sent, they would be inclined to veto proposals that fail to discriminate in
favour of members of their racial group. Since we don’t believe race is
a morally relevant basis for allocating resources, we prevent contractors
from having this information. But things aren’t so simple. Suppose we did
allow each contractor to know the race of the person she represents. This
won’t yield a morally problematic result, where some people are given
a greater share of resources merely on account of race, because any
proposal to benefit a particular racial group will be vetoed by contractors
representing people from other races. The only proposals that look cap-
able of evading a veto are those that disregard race as a relevant consid-
eration for the distribution of resources – any proposal that takes race into
account will be vetoed by at least one contractor. The rationale for
excluding information such as a person’s race thus cannot be that this is
the only way to avoid principles that wrongly allow race to serve as a basis
for the distribution of advantages and disadvantages.
You might protest that allowing contractors to know the race of the
person they represent will still prove problematic because it will lead to
a null set, that is, the contractors will be unable to agree on anything. Even
if racist proposals will be successfully vetoed, won’t non-racist policies
also be vetoed by contractors who will only consent to policies that give
priority to the racial group of the person they represent? Once contractors
have some specific information about which policies would be guaranteed
to maximally benefit the person they represent, won’t they refuse to
consent to anything less?
This problem can be avoided if the non-agreement point for each con-
tractor is less attractive than some of the proposals being considered.
Suppose, for example, contractors are asked to choose amongst potential
principles of distributive justice, and they know that if they cannot agree
on any proposed principles, the non-agreement point is roughly like the
Hobbesian state of nature. Faced with this option, contractors will readily
accept a principle of justice that ignores race as a basis for distribution
even if the contractors know the race of the person they represent and are
purely self-interested. Of course each contractor would prefer a principle
78 Chapter 5
of justice that favours his own race, but each knows the others can veto
any such principle, and each is strongly motivated to reach some agree-
ment to avoid the Hobbesian state of nature. The underappreciated point
is this: imposing a thick Rawlsian veil of ignorance is not necessary to
avoid the sort of partiality and prejudice that is incompatible with fairness,
even when contractors are strictly self-interested. Principles that unfairly
favour a particular race, gender, or religion can be avoided with
a combination of contractors’ vetoes and a non-agreement point that is
equally unappealing for all the contractors.
Some critics have complained that fairness contractualism cannot sim-
ply stipulate a non-agreement point that is sufficiently bad that contrac-
tors will prefer at least one of the proposals being considered. These
critics suggest that genuine contractualism depends on showing that the
agreed principles will be mutually beneficial, where the ‘benefit’ must be
measured according to a benchmark of how well off the real people being
represented could expect to be in the event of non-agreement (Cohen
1995: 225; Nozick 1974: 192–7). We cannot simply stipulate that all
contractors face the same very unappealing non-agreement point. This
stipulation will, in many cases, be false – for example, sometimes some
subset of the real people being represented will do better in the event of
non-agreement than they would under some fair set of distributive prin-
ciples. If so, argue the critics, then the would-be contractualist must
admit her contractualism is a sham in the sense that it fails to deliver
mutually advantageous principles.
But this objection misunderstands the aims of fairness contractualism
(Quong 2007: 77–82). As I’ve already emphasized, fairness contractual-
ism, properly construed, doesn’t aspire to track the wills of real people,
nor does it purport to establish that the principles selected are instrumen-
tally rational for real people given their current aims. The goal is rather to
construct a scenario where self-interested agents must come to an agree-
ment regarding a rule or set of rules, but the scenario is designed in such
a way that the agreement that emerges is guaranteed to be fair. In this
version of contractualism, nothing turns on showing that some real per-
son would benefit from the agreement relative to the status quo or relative
to a realistic non-agreement point.
Let’s return to our earlier observation that depriving the contractors of
all specific information about the persons they represent is inessential to
ensuring that the principles remain untainted by prejudice or wrongful
partiality. If this is true, why does Rawls impose a thick veil of ignorance
on the contractors? I think the answer to this question is, at least in part,
because doing so is a better heuristic for taking up the perspective of
others. Asking ‘what rules would I choose to regulate this domain if
Contractualism 79
they are. Instead, the theorist might wish to ‘clean up’ people’s existing
aims and interests – correcting for obvious inconsistencies, and discard-
ing those plans individuals have formed that are instrumental to achieve
one objective, but that are not the most effective means of pursuing
a more fundamental objective. There are varying degrees to which the
contractors can be idealized in this way. A moderate form of idealization
might seek to eliminate only obvious inconsistencies and clearly fallacious
inferences made by real persons, while leaving all the person’s central
commitments untouched.3 More radical forms of idealization are possi-
ble, however. In principle, all of a person’s plans or beliefs, apart from her
final ends, could be subject to revision.
How much information should be given to the contractors? There are
two main approaches to this question. On the one hand, the theorist may
want to know what would be instrumentally rational for persons given the
evidence available to them, even if that evidence does not include all the
relevant facts. For example, there are important questions regarding what
it is instrumentally rational to do given that we do not know how long we
are going to live, or whether we will be afflicted by illness or injury in the
future. Some governments require citizens to participate in compulsory
forms of collective insurance, and we may wish to know whether rational,
self-interested contractors representing all citizens would agree to such
schemes. But sometimes, as theorists, we want to know what rational and
self-interested agents would do if they had access to all the facts. For
example, we might want to know exactly what employment contracts an
employer and employee would accept if each party knew exactly what its
alternatives were. It is often valuable to know how fully informed and
rational contractors would act, even if their real-world counterparts are
neither fully informed nor fully rational.
Finally, how does rationality contractualism handle the issue of the
non-agreement point? Because the aim is often to understand what bargain
or agreement self-interested agents would reach, it’s typically crucial that
the non-agreement point be specified by reference to how well-off persons
would actually be in the absence of agreement. In this way rationality
contractualism differs sharply from fairness contractualism. In the latter,
the non-agreement point can be stipulated in any way the theorist chooses
if doing so serves the goal of making the resulting agreement fair. But
stipulating unrealistic non-agreements points will defeat the central pur-
pose of most forms of rationality contractualism, namely, discovering
what it would be rational for some group of people to accept given the
actual alternatives. Of course, we can stipulate an unrealistic or false non-
3
For a detailed account of moderate idealization, see Gaus (2011: 276–91).
82 Chapter 5
4
The final four sentences in this paragraph are taken, with slight modification, from Quong
(in press).
5
For a related discussion of contractualism as applied to this case, see Thomson (1990:
181–95).
84 Chapter 5
trolley is not that the one person would have consented ex ante from
behind a veil of ignorance, but rather the fact that turning the trolley can
avert a sufficiently great harm. The ‘consent’ of the one person is only
achieved by placing that person behind a veil of ignorance that deprives
the person from the most important piece of information relevant to the
decision, namely, that turning the trolley involves killing him for the
benefit of others. The consent obtained in this way is too far removed
from the interests and will of the actual person to carry the required
normative weight.
Perhaps this simply shows that the type of contractualism best
suited to handle these cases is not consent contractualism, but rather
fairness contractualism. The point, one might argue, is that under
suitably fair conditions (i.e. behind a veil of ignorance) all six people
would agree that the trolley should be turned, and so this establishes
that turning the trolley is the fair and thus permissible course of
action.
There are several serious problems with this view. First, in these
cases the central question is what it is permissible to do, and at
most, what fairness contractualism could tell us is what would con-
stitute a fair distribution of some harm. But the fact that distributing
harm in one way is fairer than the alternative is not sufficient to
conclude that imposing the harm in this way is permissible. From
behind a veil of ignorance, six people might also agree that
a surgeon should cut up a healthy patient and distribute his organs
to five other patients who are dying and in need of organ transplants
to survive, but hardly anyone thinks this is a permissible course of
action. Second, an act being fair is not necessary to establish its
permissibility. Suppose, for example, the runaway trolley can be
turned either to a sidetrack to the left, where it will kill your spouse,
or to a sidetrack to the right, where it will an innocent stranger.
Many will agree you are permitted to turn the trolley to the right
(you don’t have to flip a coin), but this is not a fair distribution
since the person on the right is given no chance to avoid being
killed. Finally, cases such as these are not analogous to standard
problems of distributive justice where fairness contractualism is
often deployed. In cases like the one being considered, each person
cannot share in the burdens and benefits. Rather, some people will
be forced to bear all the burdens while others reap all the benefits.
Though this may be the right thing to do in certain circumstances,
it’s not plausible to say that the burdens and benefits have been
fairly distributed.
Contractualism 85
‘consent’ obtained is too far removed from the will of the relevant real
people.6 This, recall, is one of the problems with an attempt to use
contractualism to explain why it is permissible to turn a runaway trolley
away from five people and towards one person.
I don’t wish to defend the extreme thesis that hybrid models of
contractualism are always unsuccessful. One reason to develop
a hybrid model would be if one’s wider metaethical or normative
beliefs entail an identity (or at least extensional equivalence)
between the different questions associated with different forms of
contractualism. For example, if one independently believed that
moral rules must be co-extensive with individual self-interest, then
the distinction between rationality contractualism and fairness con-
tractualism collapses. Similarly, if one had independent reasons to
believe that social morality is whatever set of rules real persons
(suitably idealized) have sufficient instrumental reasons to endorse,
then the distinction between a version of fairness contractualism and
an expansive version of rationality contractualism blurs. But as
a general methodological principle, we do better to carefully distin-
guish the different varieties of contractualism.
Acknowledgements
I am very grateful to Adrian Blau and Rebecca Stone for comments on
earlier versions of this chapter.
References
Barry, Brian, 1989a. Democracy, Power, and Justice. Clarendon Press.
Barry, Brian, 1989b. Theories of Justice: A Treatise on Social Justice, Vol. I. University
of California Press.
Cohen, G. A., 1995. Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality. Cambridge University
Press.
Dworkin, Ronald, 1973. ‘The original position’, The University of Chicago Law
Review 40: 500–33.
Gaus, Gerald, 2011. The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in
a Diverse and Bounded World. Cambridge University Press.
Gauthier, David, 1987. Morals by Agreement. Oxford University Press.
Hobbes, Thomas, 1996. Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck. Cambridge University
Press.
Nozick, Robert, 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Basic Books.
Quong, Jonathan, 2007. ‘Contractualism, reciprocity, and egalitarian justice’,
Politics, Philosophy, & Economics 6, 75–105.
90 Chapter 5
Michael L. Frazer
1 Introduction
Scholars across a variety of disciplines have come to believe that eighteenth-
century luminaries such as David Hume and Adam Smith were correct to
see our normative judgements as sentiments – that is, as integrating both
affective and cognitive elements, both emotions and beliefs.
There are several ways to defend this thesis (Frazer 2013: 21–4).
Psychologists, neuroscientists, and other social scientists have gathered
considerable evidence that normative judgements depend on emotions
(e.g. Damasio 1994; Marcus et al. 2000; Haidt 2001; Westen 2007).
Philosophers have then explored the deeper implications of these empiri-
cal discoveries (e.g. Nichols 2004; Prinz 2007). Normative ethicists and
political theorists have argued that emotional engagements ought to be
appreciated as positive features of our ethical and political lives (e.g.
Walzer 2004; Hall 2005; Krause 2008; Frazer 2010; Slote 2010).
During the first half of the twentieth century, many analytic metaethicists
even argued that the very concept of affectless evaluation is incoherent
(Ayer 1936: 102–19; Stevenson 1944). Under a particularly strong ver-
sion of this metaethical view – often defended under such names as
emotivism, non-cognitivism or expressivism – moral judgements consist
only of emotion, and contain no cognitive content whatsoever. Among
metaethicists today, moderate, qualified, hybrid or ‘neosentimentalist’
views are more popular (e.g. Gibbard 1990; D’Arms and Jacobson 2000).
Given the long-standing centrality of emotion in analytic metaethics, it
is surprising that sentimentalism is only now gaining a foothold in Anglo-
American political theory. Some might see this as evidence of the irrele-
vance of metaethics to politics. Even though the view that metaethics is
normatively neutral has not been popular for nearly half a century
(Gewirth 1968, 1970; Solomon 1970), the view that normative political
theory ought to be metaethically neutral is still widespread. Following
Rawls (1996: 12–15), metaethics is often classified alongside religion,
metaphysics, and even comprehensive theories of normative ethics as an
91
92 Chapter 6
chopping playfulness of the ethicists of his own day. ‘It makes one
ashamed’, he writes, ‘that men of our advanced years should turn
a thing as serious as this into a game’ (Seneca 2004: 97).
common cause with those practising what is now called realist or non-
ideal theory, overcoming the barriers between political philosophy and
social science (see Jubb, Chapter 7 in this volume).
Much of the empirical work realists cite today is the sort of nomo-
thetic social science that still qualifies as philosophy in the eighteenth-
century sense, the kind of ‘general facts about human society’ that
Rawls allows to the otherwise ignorant agents in the original position
(Rawls 1999: 116). In order to integrate narrative and didactic ele-
ments in the manner Hume and Smith advocated, sentimentalists are
more likely to draw on idiographic work in history and ethnography.
They are particularly likely to be drawn to the work of social scientists
who favour interpretive rather than causal explanations of human
behaviour. In the interpretive tradition, tracing others’ narratives
allows us to identify their motivations, values and worldviews, hence
achieving empathetic understanding, what Weber (1978: 7–8) calls
Verstehen. Although Weber believed that Verstehen is compatible with
a commitment to value-neutrality, sentimentalists seek such empa-
thetic understanding insofar as it allows for accurate, affectively
laden normative judgements.
There is a growing awareness in the social sciences that accurate
accounts of particular incidents can serve as what Thacher (2006) calls
‘normative case studies’. A ‘phronetic’ social science of the sort Flyvbjerg
(2001) advocated considers such cases in order to help us develop the
skills of ethical judgement required to guide public decision-making for
the better. It is a friendly amendment to this agenda to understand the
ethical skills being developed to consist largely in emotional, empathetic
sensitivity.
In addition to joining forces with those seeking to challenge the
division between normative theory and social science, sentimentalists
may also ally themselves with those opposed to the division between
philosophy and the rest of the humanities – especially the movement
that Danto (1985: 63) calls ‘philosophy as/and/of literature’. To be
sure, turning from factual to fictional narratives poses the danger that
fictions will be designed manipulatively, artificially evoking inap-
propriate moral sentiments. While the particular challenges that
a sentimentalist faces when drawing on imaginative literature will be
discussed later in this chapter, this worry suggests a second objection
to the sentimentalist approach. Even if it is acceptable to challenge
reigning disciplinary distinctions, one might still worry that it is unac-
ceptable to evoke moral sentiments in one’s readers because doing so
is manipulative.
Moral Sentimentalism 99
allowing their needs and interests to become our own. Without this
engagement with another’s interests, we are likely to find ourselves left
both cold and bored.
Livy, for example, interests us because ‘we enter into all the concerns of
the parties and are almost as much affected with them as if we ourselves
had been concerned in them’ (Smith 1985: 17, ii.27, 95–6). Via sym-
pathy, their interests become our own. Livy and Tacitus lead us ‘so far
into the sentiments and mind of the actors that they are some of the most
striking and interesting passages to be met with in any history’ (Smith
1985: 20, ii.67, 113).
Well-written history is always interesting in this way, as are philosophi-
cal, didactic writings that make frequent use of well-written narratives.
This is probably one of the reasons historians and ethnographers still
regularly find an audience among the educated reading public, while
philosophers who are not also storytellers rarely do so.
simply tells it like he sees it. The immense popularity and influence of
Addison’s Spectator is evidence of the power of such straightforward
writing.
It is a striking fact of human psychology that this modest approach can
arouse even greater emotional reactions than those aroused by direct
appeals. Smith argues that it is a ‘general rule that when we mean to
affect the reader deeply we must have recourse to the indirect method of
description, relating the effects the transaction produced both on the
actors and the spectators’ (Smith 1985: 16, ii.7, 86–7). Creative writers
are taught the rule ‘show, don’t tell’, not to establish impartiality or to
avoid manipulation, but simply to maximize emotional impact. The fact
that the same technique is the best way to achieve these two very different
objectives is a happy coincidence of human psychology.
References
Applebaum, Arthur, 2000. Ethics for Adversaries: The Morality of Roles in Public and
Professional Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Aristotle, 1995. Poetics, ed. and tr. Stephen Halliwell. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Ayer, A. J., 1936. Language, Truth and Logic. New York: Dover Publications.
Bentham, Jeremy, 1962. ‘Introduction to the principles of morals and legisla-
tion’, in J. Bowring., ed., The Works of Jeremy Bentham. New York: Russell &
Russell.
Boo, Katherine, 2012. Behind the Beautiful Forevers: Life, Death and Hope in
a Mumbai Undercity. New York: Random House.
Box, M. A., 1990. The Suasive Art of David Hume. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Moral Sentimentalism 109
Coons, Christian and Michael Weber, 2014. ‘Introduction: investigating the core
concept and its moral status’, in Christian Coons and Michael Weber, eds.,
Manipulation: Theory and Practice. Oxford University Press, 1–16.
Damasio, Antonio, 1994. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain.
New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons.
Danto, Arthur, 1985. ‘Philosophy as/and/of literature’, in John Rajchman and
Cornel West, eds., Post-analytic Philosophy. New York: Columbia University
Press.
D’Arms, Justin and Daniel Jacobson, 2000. ‘Sentiment and value’, Ethics 110,
722–48.
Darwall, Stephen, 1995. ‘Hume and the invention of utilitarianism’, in
M A. Stewart and John Wright, eds., Hume and Hume’s Connexions. State
College: Pennsylvania State University Press, 58–82.
Fassin, Didier, 2013. Enforcing Order: An Ethnography of Urban Policing. Malden,
MA: Polity Press.
Flyvbjerg, Bent, 2001. Making Social Science Matter. Cambridge University Press.
Frazer, Michael, 2007. ‘John Rawls: between two enlightenments’, Political Theory
35, 756–80.
Frazer, Michael, 2010. The Enlightenment of Sympathy: Justice and the Moral
Sentiments in the Eighteenth Century and Today. Oxford University Press.
Frazer, Michael, 2013. ‘Sentimentalism without relativism’ in James Fleming, ed.,
NOMOS LIII: Passions and Emotions. New York University Press, 19–37.
Frazer, Michael, 2015. ‘Anatomist and painter: Hume’s struggles as a sentimental
stylist’, in Heather Kerr, David Lemmings and Robert Phiddian, eds., Passions,
Sympathy and Print Culture: Public Opinion and Emotional Authenticity in
Eighteenth-Century Britain. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Frazer, Michael, Forthcoming. ‘Interdisciplinary before the disciplines: sentiment-
alism and the science of man’, in R. Debes and Karsten Stueber, eds., Taking
Ethical Sentimentalism Seriously. Cambridge University Press.
Gewirth, Alan, 1968. ‘Meta-ethics and normative ethics’, Mind 69, 187–205.
Gewirth, Alan, 1970. ‘Metaethics and moral neutrality’, Ethics 78, 214–25.
Gibbard, Allan, 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Goffman, Alice, 2014. On the Run: Fugitive Life in an American City. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
Gross, Neil, 2013. Why Are Professors Liberal and Why Do Conservatives Care?
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Guenther, Lisa, 2013. Solitary Confinement: Social Death and Its Afterlives.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Haidt, Jonathan, 2001. ‘The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist
approach to moral judgment’, Psychological Review 108, 814–34.
Hall, Cheryl, 2005. The Trouble with Passion: Political Theory Beyond the Reign of
Reason. New York: Routledge.
Hume, David, 1985. Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller.
Revised Edition. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
110 Chapter 6
Hume, David, 2000a. A Treatise of Human Nature, eds. David Fate Norton and
Mary Norton. Oxford University Press.
Hume, David, 2000b. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed.
Tom Beauchamp. Oxford University Press.
Kingston, Rebecca, 2011. Public Passion: Rethinking the Grounds for Political Justice.
Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Krause, Sharon, 2008. Civil Passions: Moral Sentiment and Democratic Deliberation.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Marcus, George, Russell Neuman and Michael Mackuen, 2000. Affective
Intelligence and Political Judgment. University of Chicago Press.
Nichols, Shaun, 2004. Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral
Judgment. Oxford University Press.
Nussbaum, Martha, 1990. Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature.
Oxford University Press.
Nussbaum, Martha, 1995. Poetic Justice. The Literary Imagination and Public Life.
Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Prinz, Jesse, 2007. The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford University Press.
Prinz, Jesse, 2011. ‘Is empathy necessary for morality?’, in Amy Coplan and
Peter Goldie, eds., Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. Oxford
University Press, 211–29.
Rawls, John, 1996. Political Liberalism. Revised Paperback Edition. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Rawls, John, 1999. A Theory of Justice. Revised Edition. Cambridge, MA:
The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Seneca, 2004. Letters from a Stoic: Epistulae Morales ad Lucilium, tr.
Robin Campbell. New York: Penguin Classics.
Singer, Peter, 1972. ‘Famine, affluence, and morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs
1, 229–43.
Slote, Michael, 2010. Moral Sentimentalism. Oxford University Press.
Smith, Adam, 1984. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, eds. A. L. Macfie and
D. D Raphael. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Smith, Adam, 1985. Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres, ed. J. C. Bryce.
Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Solomon, R. C, 1970. ‘Normative and meta-ethics’, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 31, 97–107.
Stevenson, Charles, 1944. Ethics and Language. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Stewart, John, 2013. The Unity of Content and Form in Philosophical Writing:
The Perils of Conformity. New York: Bloomsbury.
Thacher, David, 2006. ‘The normative case study’, American Journal of Sociology
111, 1631–76.
Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 1971. ‘A defense of abortion’, Philosophy and Public Affairs
1, 47–66.
Vermeule, Blakey, 2010. Why Do We Care about Literary Characters? Baltimore,
MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Moral Sentimentalism 111
Walzer, Michael, 2004. Politics and Passion: Toward a More Egalitarian Liberalism.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Weber, Max, 1978. Economy and Society, eds. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Westen, Drew, 2007. The Political Brain: The Role of Emotion in Deciding the Fate of
the Nation. New York: Public Affairs.
Williams, Bernard, 1981. Moral Luck. Cambridge University Press.
7 Realism
Robert Jubb
1 Introduction
Contemporary normative analytical political theory tends to think of itself
as continuous with or at least an application of moral philosophy. For
example, in the Introduction to his Political Philosophy: A Beginner’s Guide
for Students and Politicians, Adam Swift describes the discipline he is
introducing as asking ‘what the state should do’, explaining that this
means asking ‘what moral principles should govern the way it treats its
citizens’ (Swift 2014: 5). Similarly, in the Introduction to his
Contemporary Political Philosophy, Will Kymlicka says that ‘there is
a fundamental continuity between moral and political philosophy’
(Kymlicka 2002: 5). This is because Robert Nozick was right to claim
that moral philosophy sets the limits to what ‘persons may and may not do
to one another’ including ‘through the apparatus of a state’ (Kymlicka
2002: 5). Nor is this only a feature of purportedly introductory texts.
Cecile Fabre’s Cosmopolitan War sees its attempt to articulate to integrate
cosmopolitan principles of distributive justice and just war theory as
uncomplicatedly an enquiry in ‘applied ethics’ (Fabre 2012: 3).
Equally, the very first sentence of Thomas Christiano’s The Constitution
of Equality: Democratic Authority and Its Limits introduces its investigation
into democratic authority by asking what ‘the moral foundations of
democracy and liberal rights’ are (Christiano 2008: 1).
Realism rejects this understanding of how normative political theory
should operate. This ‘moralist’ or ‘ethics first’ approach to normative
political theory is, realists claim, fundamentally mistaken. The precise
description of moralism’s sins varies from realist theorist to realist theor-
ist, but as realism’s reaction against moralism grows in strength, various
themes have emerged. This chapter treats Bernard Williams’s ‘Realism
and moralism in political theory’ as an archetypical piece of realism, using
it to suggest that realists share a common commitment to the idea that
politics is the contextually specific management of conflicts generated by
our inability to order our lives together around an agreed set of complete
112
Realism 113
1
See https://scholar.google.co.uk/scholar?cites=10056158126568575885&as_sdt=2005&
sciodt=0,5&hl=en and https://scholar.google.co.uk/scholar?cites=395693232102231110
5&as_sdt=2005&sciodt=0,5&hl=en.
114 Chapter 7
2
There is in this sense a link between practice-dependence and realism. See Sangiovanni
(2008) for a definition of practice-dependence and Jubb (2016) for discussion of the
relation between the two.
Realism 119
1981: 1–2; Williams 2011: 181). If modernity has left us with ‘fragments
of a conceptual scheme’ stripped of the ‘contexts from which their sig-
nificance derived’ in the place where integrated notions of the good life
ought to be, then Williams’s support for liberalism will seem, at best,
acquiescence in a cultural catastrophe of an unimaginably vast scale
(MacIntyre 1981: 2, 3). MacIntyre’s stance here is at least in tension
with realism because of the way in which it refuses to deal with the agents
with which it understands itself as being faced. For MacIntyre, we are
doomed by the complete disintegration of the traditional authorities that
made possible the Thomist virtues we need for decent lives. How does
that diagnosis of our problems tell us to structure our lives together?
It must absolutely reject not just those institutions and their associated
historical and sociological forms but with them, us.
In this sense, a realist political theory must be based on an inter-
pretation of our political situation that refuses both the related
consolations of utopian hope and unremitting despair. MacIntyre
believes that modernity makes it impossible for us to live decent lives. He
combines utopianism with despair by claiming that unless we undo all the
history of at least the past three centuries, we are doomed to live fractured,
empty lives. The rejection of everything there is prompts the search for
something beyond it. This is not to say that such interpretations or even
the commitments for which they serve as foundations are incorrect or
inappropriate. It is instead to point out that if any really achievable social
order destroys all but the most minimal human values, then it is hard to
understand the point or even the possibility of ‘securing order, protection,
safety, trust, and the conditions of cooperation’ (RMPT: 3). There will be
no political values for distinctively political thought to articulate. Whether
they are conservative or radical, realists must be able to say something that
can make sense of the value of politics as an activity. The temptation to
slip into moralist condemnation needs to be resisted.
Emphasizing this may cast some doubt on the credentials of some self-
proclaimed realists, at least if they intend their realism to involve ‘distinc-
tively political thought’ in Williams’s sense (RMPT: 3). Raymond Geuss,
for example, not only sees himself operating in the tradition of critical
theory typified by Theodor Adorno; he criticizes Williams for ‘paddling
about in the tepid and slimy puddle created by Locke, J. S. Mill and Isaiah
Berlin’ rather than adopting Adorno’s rejection of both the ‘self-serving
“liberalism” of the Anglo-American political world and the brutal prac-
tices of “really-existing socialism”’ (Geuss 2012: 150). He also sees
himself as a realist; his Philosophy and Real Politics is a relentless attack
on behalf of realism against what he calls ‘ethics-first’ political philosophy
(see for example Geuss 2008: 9). However, anyone taking their lead from
120 Chapter 7
Adorno may find themselves too pessimistic about our historical and
political situation to be able to do justice to what we can achieve through
politics.
Adorno argued that while ‘social freedom is inseparable from
enlightened thought,’ ‘[t]he only kind of thinking that is sufficiently
hard to shatter myths is ultimately self-destructive’ (Adorno and
Horkheimer 1979: xiii, 4). If as a result our civilization is in fact
a kind of ‘barbarism’, its social orders will presumably be little more
than ‘one lot of people terrorizing another lot of people’ in more and
less open ways (Adorno and Horkheimer 1979: xi; RMPT, 3). That
will make it difficult to understand how, for example, Williams’s first
political question could be answered satisfactorily. Geuss may then
not be a realist, at least in the sense I am using here. Following
Adorno, he insists both that living a decent life is impossible within
the ‘repressive, duplicitous and alienated’ social forms of late capitalist
modernity and that it is impossible for us realistically ‘to envisage any
fundamental change in our world we could bring about by our own
efforts’ (Geuss 2012: 154, 160). If our historical and political situation
means that our lives cannot avoid being ‘radically defective’, an
‘impossible situation’, then we will struggle to find, let alone imple-
ment or grasp the value of, ways of living together that do not betray
all our hopes (Geuss 2012: 154).
There are ways to reject Williams’s account of modernity that do not
see it as made up of ideas that are ‘misshapen, brittle, riven with cracks . . .
and very ill-suited to each other’, and so under which it is impossible to
live coherently (Geuss 2001: 9). We might, for example, question
whether Williams can be right about liberalism being the only way that
a modern political order can make sense to its members. One does not
have to subscribe to claims about the superiority of alleged Asian values to
see that various states in East Asia seem to be accepted by most of their
citizens yet are neither liberal nor underdeveloped compared to the North
Atlantic democracies Williams presumably had in mind when equating
liberalism and modernity. There are problems too for Williams’s claim
even in Europe, where we might assume it would be most apt given its
association with the Enlightenment and its supposedly demystifying
aftermath. Many European states, most obviously those of the former
Warsaw Pact, have been and in some cases remain modern and illiberal
without obviously failing to give a broadly acceptable account of them-
selves to their citizens, even in the medium term. Even if modernity is
disenchanted, it seems that there are a variety of ways of responding to
that disenchantment. The interpretation of the relevant political
situation on which a realist relies must not generate obviously
Realism 121
modern democratic life means they are not realist. Those political move-
ments did not draw on philosophical ideals to draw together and motivate
their supporters, but on shared experiences of hardship and solidarity
built up in the course of struggles against it. Realists must acknowledge
the importance of material interests and ideological and charis-
matic appeals, especially compared to philosophical reasoning,
when theorizing political goods to fit particular political
situations.
Rawls’s and Williams’s interpretations of modernity illustrate two
errors to which interpretations of a political situation may fall victim.
Complacency about the generality of an interpretation or about the
motivational and cognitive power of philosophy is not realistic.
However, we can avoid both of those problems by marrying Rawls’s
cultural and geographical circumspection to Williams’s emphasis on dis-
enchantment. Such an interpretation of modernity will neither apply
beyond the societies with which both theorists were familiar nor end up
depending on the power of reason alone. This leaves us with a roughly
liberal principle of transparency, which, rather than requiring a system
capable of being endorsed by all ‘in light of principles and ideals accep-
table to their common human reason’, builds on Williams’s idea of the
‘human point of view’ (Rawls 2005: 137; IoE, 103).
The human point of view is a perspective that, when considering some-
one’s else’s life, ‘is concerned primarily with what it is for that person to live
that life and do those actions’ (IoE: 103). It asks us to ‘respect and try to
understand other people’s consciousness of their own activities’, whether
they manage to do what they hoped and how they feel about failures they
suffer (IoE: 103). The human point of view can become a demand for
transparency and rule out, Williams claims, markedly unequal societies
because of the frustrations and resentments they will predictably gener-
ate. Once the idea that societies are human creations spreads, those
frustrations and resentments can no longer be justified because they will
no longer seem inevitable (IoE, 105). If relations between members of
those societies are not to be conducted on the basis of brute force or
systematic deception, neither of which can be acceptable from the human
point of view, then hierarchies cannot be too steep or pervasive (IoE:
104–5). If the hierarchies are too steep or pervasive, then the social and
political order that sustains them will seem too unsympathetic to the
‘intentions and purposes’ of those at the wrong end of those hierarchies
(IoE: 103). The terms on which that sympathy operates will need to be
thinner, to assume less about the commitments of those whom it is for,
than the terms on which it operated in ‘supposedly contented hierarchical
societies of the past’ (see for example Williams 2005f). It will be unable to
Realism 123
take for granted the set of commitments we all supposedly shared in those
societies. Those are gone, along with metaphysical or supernatural
explanations that sustained the idea that the associated hierarchies were
unavoidable. Still, that sympathy will need to be there if the political order
is to ‘make sense’ to its members, to avoid failing to meet the basic
legitimation demand for at least those particularly disadvantaged by it.
In understanding what this account of legitimacy in North Atlantic
democracies might judge acceptable, we should look to real political
motivations. These need not be drawn directly from reality, as long as it
is clear that they have some real-world counterparts (see for example Jubb
2015a). Our accounts of political legitimacy or any other political
good must be for actually existing agents, and we can best check
that there is a constituency that they address by showing that they
can capture and give form to political demands that animate
actual agents. If we were to develop an account of a political good that
could not be seen as an articulation of a hope or resentment that drives
a stance towards a political order real people actually adopt, then that
failure would count strongly against the account being genuinely realist.
For example, connecting an interpretation of Williams’s minimally ega-
litarian account of legitimacy to the resentments that seem to have moti-
vated the most widespread civil unrest in the United Kingdom in recent
decades strengthens that account by showing that it could well make
sense of those real political demands (see Jubb 2015b). A series of inter-
views conducted with hundreds of self-identified rioters found
a ‘pervasive sense of injustice’ (Lewis et al. 2011: 24). Barely half of the
rioters felt British, compared to more than 90 per cent of Britons on
average, understandably given that they felt victimized by the police and
excluded from a culture of consumption by their poverty (Lewis et al.
2011: 28, 19). These interviews seem to show then that a realist egalitar-
ianism focusing on the systematic frustration of the hopes and expecta-
tions of the least advantaged speaks to real political motivations.
Realism does not just demand that political goods are for actual agents.
Actual agents may of course make demands that are not properly political
and so realists will have to temper and limit them. Indeed, the intense
moralism of much democratic political debate, which is for example often
captivated both on the left and the right by nostalgia for supposedly lost
forms of ethical community, may be a serious problem for realists. Even if
that moralism can be contained within the boundaries of the properly
political for now, there is presumably always a risk that dissatisfaction
with the inevitable compromises of political life will break through those
limits and put various political goods at risk. Descriptions of political
goods meant for moralistic publics will have to explain in terms
124 Chapter 7
they can understand why they must satisfy themselves with less
moral unity than they would like. In this sense, realist political theory
needs to draw not just on an interpretation of a political situation, but also
on an interpretation that is capable of being publicly stated and accepted
without, for example, undermining itself. If an account of legitimacy
shows a population they share less than they thought, it may prevent
them from sharing even that.
This is just one of a number of risks that realist pieces of theorizing face
as a result of the constraints imposed by the need to remain political.
The most obvious of these is that the theorizing itself relies on contro-
versial moral values. Realist political theorizing would be moralistic in this
sense if it relied on value claims that, if they were acceptable to the
constituency the theory addresses, would eliminate its political problems.
Politics is in part constituted by our disagreement on values around which
to order our shared institutions. Consequently, realist political theory
must not appeal to values or interpretations of values whose con-
troversy is, at least as far as its interpretation of the relevant
political situation is concerned, a defining feature of that
situation.
For example, if we were to try to articulate an egalitarian theory of
legitimacy along the lines suggested by Williams’s idea of the human
point of view, we would need to avoid basing its appeal on an ideal of the
good of living as equals. While perhaps there have been some commu-
nities where such an ideal could exert enough power over most of its
members to distinguish between legitimate and illegitimate rule, our
society is not one. It is too divided to demonstrate the acceptability of its
massively coercive, structuring power by appealing to the idea that
relations of equality are central to a good life. Even if that ideal seems
attractive in the abstract, its acceptability in general will not decide how
it should be weighed against other ideals when it inevitably conflicts with
them. A solidaristic society may be all well and good for many citizens,
but only as long as it does not suppress individuality, undermine indi-
vidual responsibility, respect for one’s traditions or any number of other
ideals.
Instead, an egalitarian theory of legitimacy must be based on a less
demanding account of the value of equality. Rather than requiring
citizens to accept not just a moral ideal, but a particular ranking of that
ideal against other competing ideals, some more minimal explanation
of the value of equality and its connection to an entitlement to rule is
needed. For Williams, one of the virtues of Judith Shklar’s liberalism
of fear was that it tried to address ‘everybody’ by drawing on ‘the only
certainly universal materials of politics . . . power, powerlessness, fear,
Realism 125
itself that prevents it from making sense of the value of whichever political
projects it favours to those for whom it favours them. Still, being in
principle able to articulate a given political value to and for a particular
group of people does not mean that the articulation will satisfy or be
accepted by those people. Nor does it mean that they will actually be able
to organize themselves into a collective capable of achieving whatever it
demands or hopes. To move beyond generic and towards what we could
call full realism, a theory should not just eliminate barriers to providing an
account of a particular political value to those in a particular political
situation. A realist political theory should also show that its poli-
tical projects can capture and hold the allegiance of people against
the rival political projects that are bound to challenge them, and
that the supporters who can be attracted can collectively put them
into practice.
This will mean understanding the political, social and economic
dynamics operating in particular societies. For example, an egalitarian
realist theory of legitimacy seems to face at least three related questions
raised by the requirement that it show not only how it is generically, but
also fully, concretely realist (see Jubb 2015b for more detail on these
challenges for a realist egalitarianism). If a realist theory of legitimacy is to
sensibly demand that states restrict their levels of inequality or risk
becoming illegitimate, it needs to show, first, that enforcing limits on
inequality will not, as a matter of fact, undermine various other values.
After all, for example, equality is often associated with societies and
groups that tend to repress difference, and so we might find that however
desirable equality is in theory, in practice there is no way of achieving it
that does not compromise too many of our other commitments. Second,
it must be politically possible to fulfil the demands of an egalitarian realist
theory of legitimacy. If supporters of higher levels of equality cannot
dominate the political scene, or if their dominance would inevitably
bring about economic collapse caused by, say, capital flight, then we
will have to change our attitudes. Either we will have to understand
ourselves differently, as needing a different kind of explanation of what
our states must do for us, or, alternatively, we will have to see our state as
an alien, dominating force for at least some of its members. Third, we
need to have a reasonable expectation that a constituency can be united
around the indignities of inequality, and that they will not seek to deal
with the frustrations associated with inequality in other ways. Otherwise,
it would not be clear how the theory answered a real rather than imagined
problem.
Political theorists are often unlikely to be able to meet these require-
ments. Indeed, even scholars with empirical expertise may not often be
128 Chapter 7
able to meet them given the unpredictability of political life. In this sense,
political realism’s emphasis on politics as a distinctive sphere of life limits
the role of scholars, especially given the importance of action in that
understanding of politics. The deliberately modest understanding of
political theorists as ‘democratic underlabourers’ offered by Adam Swift
and Stuart White, for example, seems in fact inappropriate and over-
ambitious (Swift and White 2008: 54). The problem is not primarily, as
Swift and White worry, that offering philosophical arguments will bypass
the proper democratic process (Swift and White 2008: 55). It is instead
that philosophical arguments are dangerously unsuited to political pro-
blems. Nor will positivist empirical theories of political processes often be
any better off. Politics shapes the problems with which it has to deal by
shaping the agents, both individual and collective, whose motivations and
dispositions create its problems. A theory of politics capable of under-
standing all the processes relevant to its own applicability would be too
complex for humans to understand, and of course itself a tool that, were it
understood, it would have to include in its assessment of the relevant
dynamics.
Political theories are in this sense necessarily incomplete. Politics is
a sphere of judgement instead of scientific understanding, which will be
vindicated by the acts it recommends having the intended effects and so
after the fact, once the situation has been changed. No political theory can
show completely that it captures and deals appropriately with a particular
political situation, and so no political theory can be fully realistic. Like
judgements, though, political theories can be better and worse. Realists
believe that working with the guidelines they provide will at least make
them more likely to avoid failing by not being about politics at all.
Acknowledgements
I sent earlier drafts of this to Ed Hall, Enzo Rossi, Paul Sagar, Matt
Sleat and Patrick Tomlin, all of whom were kind enough to send very
helpful comments. Adrian Blau’s editorial suggestions also substan-
tially improved the piece. I am grateful to all of them, and even more
so to Adrian for asking me to contribute to this volume in the first
place.
References
Adorno, Theodor and Horkheimer, Max, 1979. The Dialectic of Enlightenment.
London: Verso.
Christiano, Thomas, 2008. The Constitution of Equality. Oxford University Press.
Realism 129
Cohen, G. A., 2009. Why Not Socialism? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Fabre, Cecile, 2012. Cosmopolitan War. Oxford University Press.
Galston, William, 2010. ‘Realism in political theory’, European Journal of Political
Theory 9: 385–411.
Geuss, Raymond, 2001. History and Illusion in Politics. Cambridge University
Press.
Geuss, Raymond, 2008. Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Geuss, Raymond, 2012. ‘Did Williams do ethics?’, Arion 19: 141–62.
Jubb, Robert, 2015a. Playing Kant at the court of King Arthur’, Political Studies 63:
919–34.
Jubb, Robert, 2015b. ‘The real value of equality’, The Journal of Politics 77:
679–691.
Jubb, Robert, 2016. ‘“Recover it from the facts as we know them”: practice-
dependence’s predecessors’, Journal of Moral Philosophy 13(1): 77–99.
Kymlicka, Will, 2002. Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction. Second
Edition. Oxford University Press.
Lewis, Paul, Tim Newburn, Matthew Taylor, Catriona Mcgillivray,
Aster Greenhill, Harold Frayman and Rob Proctor, 2011. Reading the Riots:
Investigating England’s Summer of Disorder. London: The London School of
Economics and Political Science and The Guardian.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981 After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press.
Marmot, Michael, 2004. Status Syndrome: How Your Social Standing Directly Affects
Your Health. London: Bloomsbury.
Rawls, John. 2005. Political Liberalism. 2nd edition. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Rossi, Enzo and Matt Sleat, 2014. ‘Realism in normative political theory’,
Philosophy Compass 9/10: 689–701.
Sangiovanni, Andrea, 2008. ‘Justice and the priority of politics to morality’, Journal
of Political Philosophy 16: 137–64.
Shklar, Judith. 1989. ‘The liberalism of fear’, in Nancy Rosenblum, ed., Liberalism
and the Moral Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 21–38.
Swift, Adam, 2014. Political Philosophy: A Beginner’s Guide for Students and
Politicians. Cambridge: Polity.
Swift, Adam and Stuart White, 2008. ‘Political theory, social science, and real
politics’, in David Leopold and Marc Stears, eds., Political Theory: Methods and
Approaches. Oxford University Press, 49–69.
Wilkinson, Richard and Kate Pickett, 2009. The Spirit Level. London: Allen Lane.
Williams, Bernard, 1997. ‘Forward to basics’, in J. Franklin, ed., Equality. London:
Institute for Public Policy Research, 47–57.
Williams, Bernard, 2002. Truth and Truthfulness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Williams, Bernard, 2005a. In the Beginning Was the Deed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
130 Chapter 7
David Schmidtz
1
See also Robert Jubb’s chapter on realism in this volume, and Sleat (2013).
131
132 Chapter 8
Realistically, not all problems have solutions, let alone ideal solutions.
Sometimes studying a problem helps us see what would solve it.
Sometimes we learn that the best we can do is mitigate. To introduce
the main bits of advice given in this chapter:
(a) Start with problems. We were taught to see sound theory as
grounding sound practice and therefore as needing to come first.
In practice, theories are answers; questions come first.
(b) Start with diversity. We need to coordinate on terms of engage-
ment that are apt even among people who do not agree that those
terms are apt. Theorizing does not help. We navigate the terrain
of respect for separate persons with a compass far older than any
theory.
(c) Start with injustice, not justice. In the real world, we have no
vision of ‘peak justice’ in mind when deciding how to act. When
deciding which car to try to drive home at the end of the day, we
never consult the theory of justice we spent all day perfecting, except
in self-mockery. Theory is not what teaches us how to avoid trigger-
ing people’s sense of injustice.
Finally, if I had a bit of meta-advice about how to handle my advice, it
would be: proceed with caution. Some of my advice will survive the test
of time and turn out to be good advice, but there is no substitute for
exercising your own judgement, being sceptical of contemporary theoriz-
ing about morality and justice, and taking your cue from the world rather
than from the literature.
2
I do not suppose this move solves all of deontology’s puzzles. It does, however, address
some ‘indeterminacy of description’ problems in articulating a maxim’s proper form as the
subject of the universalizability test.
134 Chapter 8
picking the outcome with the highest utility.3 Given that supposition, the
only thing to consider is which of our two options, give versus don’t give,
has more utility. If giving has more, then give. Keep giving until not giving
would have more utility.
But the essence of a strategic world is that it does not give us that
supposition. It is not an a priori truth that the action with the highest
number leads to the outcome with the highest number, and in strategic
situations it is a howling non sequitur. The numbers that count are not
numbers attached to available acts, but numbers attached to possible
outcomes, where outcomes are consequences not of particular acts, but
of patterns of cooperation. In a strategic world, someone who cares about
consequences aims to induce a response. If the ideal response is coopera-
tive, then an ideal move is a move apt to induce that cooperative response.
If consequences matter, then being moral in a strategic world is about
inducing cooperative responses, not per se choosing them. That means
being moral involves knowing when to walk away from the act with the
highest number. In strategic situations, if you want the best out-
come for all, don’t worry about other people’s payoffs; worry
about their strategies.
Scottish Enlightenment theorists focused on the nature and source of
the wealth of nations. They cared enough about consequences to study
what has a history of actually working. They observed that prosperous
societies are places where traders build partnerships around principles of
reciprocity. It mattered to them that, in our world, actions have more than
one consequence, more than the intended consequence, and the conse-
quence you don’t see coming will matter. The kind of act-utilitarianism
Peter Singer incarnated circa 1972 is remarkably inattentive to what has
any robust history of good consequences. It is useless not because it is
obsessed with consequences, but because it largely ignores them.4
When moral theory conceives our world in solipsistic terms, practi-
tioners living in a strategic world have to ignore it, because real morality
requires people to make choices apt for the strategic world they actually
3
In the terms of a Prisoner’s Dilemma payoff matrix, the empirical premise I am warning
against is the assumption that choosing a row (‘cooperate’) is the same thing as choosing
a cell in the matrix (‘mutual cooperation’). In a strategic world, it is nothing of the kind.
One unilaterally chooses an act, a row, not as a way of unilaterally choosing an outcome,
a cell, but rather as a way of working towards an outcome.
4
Amartya Sen identifies himself as within the tradition of Adam Smith. Sen earned his
Nobel Prize for his work on twentieth-century famines, showing that not one was caused
by lack of food. Famine is caused by eroding rights, not eroding soil. When local farmers
lose the right to choose what to grow or where to sell it, they lose everything, and that is
when people starve. This is what Scottish Enlightenment theorists studied: consequences
(that is, long-term cause and effect) not imagined best responses to potted thought
experiments.
Realistic Idealism 135
5
Singer himself is increasingly aware of such strategic considerations. See also Schmidtz
(2015).
136 Chapter 8
In effect, traffic managers set aside the problem. Or, instead of tackling
a real problem, traffic managers solved an idealized problem. Their job
was to optimize traffic flow, but they chose instead to do what would
optimize traffic flow if drivers were ideal. Beware of idealized pro-
blems. In general, doing what would be ideal – if only the problem
were the ideal problem! – is not a way of being a serious idealist.
Here is the kind of idealism that realistic idealists scorn:
‘My solution is a hammer; therefore, the problem ideally would be
a nail. Reality is not a nail, obviously, so no one is saying my hammer
is a real solution. Still, I just proved that the ideal problem is a nail!
Therefore, impractical though my hammer may be in the real world, it
remains an ideal.’
By contrast, to a realistic idealist, saying a traffic management system
would work for ideal drivers says nothing in its favour even as an ideal.
An ideal traffic manager works with an accurate picture of the real
problem.
Some idealizations approximate reality, so some ideal solutions are
approximate solutions to real problems. Tucson traffic managers blun-
dered into misconceiving their ideal solution as an approximate solution
to a real problem. That I am not alone but instead live in a strategic world
of separate agents who decide for themselves is not a distracting detail.
If a proposal stipulates that people will not react to our intervention in the
way human beings do react, then the intervention is not an approximate
solution, or even a real response. If Rawls is right to say ‘an important
feature of a conception of justice is that it should generate its own support’
(1999b: 119), then a serious investigator does not set aside whether
a conception of justice actually has that feature. A serious investigator
checks.
people need from each other more than anything is to create conditions
under which they can afford to trust each other.
G. A. Cohen’s objection to Rawls is that
[I]f we assume, following Rawls, that individuals are motivated to comply with
justice, then the need to trade off equality and well-being disappears. It only
arises in the first place because talented people demand incentive payments to
become more productive. But people who are motivated to realize justice fully
would not demand incentive payments but rather increase productivity with-
out them. (Hamlin and Stemplowska 2012: 57, paraphrasing Cohen 2008)
6
We can say, the true ideal here is not bare instituting, but rather a conjunction of instituting
and complying. So, the actual Carens ideal is a conjunction of ‘make sure work doesn’t
pay’ and ‘workers keep acting as if it does’. To Estlund, the fact that we should not
implement the first conjunct when the second is false has no bearing on whether the
conjunction as a whole is ideal – even if, in our strategic world, instituting the first conjunct
is a paradigm of what renders the second one false. All sides seem to agree on this much: (1)
The Carens incentive structure by itself is not ideal. (2) At best, it would be ideal only if we
Realistic Idealism 139
idealized problem. The lesson is not that we have no way to get there, but
that we have no reason to want to.
Some idealists think ignoring compliance problems is ignoring some-
thing analogous to whether a campground is reachable. Not so. Ignoring
what an incentive structure would drive people to do is like ignoring
whether a campground would be terrible.
could assume workers will comply. But (3) if we can safely assume anything about worker
compliance, it is the opposite.
What else needs to be said? Perhaps this: anything we have reason to regard as ideal
surely has at least some potential not to be catastrophically misleading as a basis for
practical proposals. There is no such potential in alleged ideals like ‘when work stops paying,
workers keep acting as if it does’.
7
By ‘discernible defect’ Estlund has something like blatant self-contradiction in mind.
Being unfit for people as they are evidently is not a discernible defect, but is instead
a defect of the people.
140 Chapter 8
we set aside whether our vision has a robust history of being a hideous
response to the human condition, we are working to make sure our vision
has no discernible defect, while doing nothing to make sure it has no defect.
I may imagine how ideal it would be to move my pawn to K4, but if I fail
to anticipate my partner’s response, then my so-called imagination is, to
chess players, the paradigm of failed imagination. It takes imagination to
be a realist. The player who anticipates what can go wrong is the one
whose imagination other chess players have reason to admire. Imagining
what would be ideal in a parametric world is no substitute for being able to
imagine what is ideal in a strategic world.
Estlund speaks of ‘motivational features that are themselves moral
defects’. Yet only some institutions elicit predictably defective behaviour,
whereas other institutions are exactly right as responses to characteristi-
cally human motivational features. If sexism were an underlying propen-
sity, switched on or off by institutional settings, then we have a duty to
choose institutions that switch it off. If we choose institutions that switch
sexism on, it is our choice of institutions that is reprehensible, not human
nature. When a theorist conceives of justice as answering to a vision rather
than to people, the defect is not in the people. If our vision is poisonous for
people as they are, the right response is to stop blaming people for being ill
equipped to survive what we want to give them, and to start wanting
something else.
Crucially, it is false that people ‘just aren’t good’. How good people are
is variable, sensitive to how their institutional structure handles their
separateness as decision-makers. When it comes to fostering society as
a cooperative venture, it is misleading to say people are not good. Rather,
people are not as good (not as cooperative, not as benevolent, not as
trusting) when operating within frameworks that make free-riding pay.
Pablo Gilabert says, ‘It is part of the job of political philosophy to keep
ambitious ideals clear and visible, and to criticize a political culture
when it becomes complacent and superficial’ (2015: ms). I agree. Yet
the phrase ‘ivory tower’ designates philosophy that is complacent and
superficial, not ambitious. Insisting on tracking evolving reality is one
way – I suspect there is no other – to keep ambitious ideals clear and
visible.
It was not an ambitious ideal that drove G. A. Cohen’s (2003) retreat into
‘feasibility is philosophically irrelevant’ mode, as communism fell apart
before his eyes. If you are discouraged and hate to admit that your case for
communism’s economic superiority has been tested and found wanting,
then you lean towards a particular kind of idealism. By contrast, if you want
to avoid complacency, don’t judge people according to whether they
fit your vision. Judge your vision according to whether it fits them.
Realistic Idealism 141
3 We Are Diverse
Theorizing about how political animals should live could start by obser-
ving the extent of disagreement and diversity in human society. One
implication of diversity: diversity is only one of many places to start, and
where we start matters.
Consider how idiosyncratic and incompatible our individual visions of
perfection are, thus how unfit they are to be a blueprint for a community.
Part of the essence of toleration, of mature adulthood and of being fit to
live in a community at all is acknowledging that our personal visions do
not obligate others – not even if we are so gripped by confirmation bias
that we can talk ourselves into believing that our visions cannot reason-
ably be rejected.
The most primordial political fact of all is the fact that I am not alone.
I live among beings who decide for themselves. I may feel that people
cannot reasonably reject my deepest convictions about justice. But
they can, and they know it. This fact makes politics what it is, and justice
what it is.
Honestly taking the fact of diversity into account comes down to
grappling with a question like this: ‘what terms of engagement are
8
Was Wilberforce overconfident in the justness of his cause? I think not, but that may be the
wrong question. As I understand, Wilberforce’s opponents were overconfident in the
justness of their cause, as majorities usually are. They talk themselves into feeling right-
eous when they bully those with minority views. To complicate things, majorities are not
always wrong, and may even be right most of the time. But when they are wrong, and are
holding back progress, they will be the last to know.
142 Chapter 8
appropriate for people who do not even agree on which terms of engage-
ment are appropriate?’ The question is not cute. It is the crux of the
human condition. Rushing to treat our own intuitions about perfect
justice as if our intuitions were rationally compelling would be
a paradigmatic way of failing to rise to the level of seriousness that justice
demands.
need to share (or even justify) a destination. No one must accept being
relegated to a category of persons whose destination is less important.
Thriving communities minimize our need to justify our destination to
others. Indeed, the utility of a traffic management system largely lies in
people not needing to justify themselves. We need not stop at intersec-
tions to justify our destinations. We stop only because it is someone else’s
turn. Underlying a healthy society is a logic of coordination rather than
unified agency. In a healthy society, people’s movements constitute a flow
of traffic that moves smoothly, by virtue of people reaching consensus not
on what their destinations should be so much as on who has the right of
way. No one needs to agree about that. It is enough that we simply expect
the people around us to adjust their expectations to fit with what they
think others expect of them.
Ideally, we want to be able to co-exist with all of our neighbours, not
only the ideal ones. Realistic idealism aims to identify what, if anything, is
observably enabling people to thrive under actual conditions, not merely
ideal ones. When disagreement is inevitable, our worthy ideal is to make
disagreement non-threatening – to make it safe to disagree. Aim not to
minimize disagreement but to minimize the need for agreement.
The ideal of a mature political animal is not to win debates, but to avoid
needing to win. Realistic idealism does not delude us into thinking other
people should be on the same page as we are, and therefore avoids cursing
us with the appearance of a mandate to bully those who see things
differently.
Is there any alternative to consensus as a political aspiration? Is there
a realistic ideal? Perhaps it would be something like balance of power. When
people do not feel that they can safely abuse those with different views and
values, society makes progress.9
It is (a not quite realistic) ideal that political power be justified to all
citizens. No one expects total victory on this front any more than we
expect a war on poverty to culminate in a poverty rate of zero. Respecting
this ideal in practice involves minimizing how unjustified a regime’s
exercise of power is. One legitimate way to do that is to minimize the
cost of exit (Pennington 2017). That is hardly a total victory, but approx-
imate success marks a society as genuinely liberal. Being 100 per cent
justified is not realistic, but it is entirely realistic that exit be a non-
appalling option for any citizen appalled to be subject to a given regime.
9
Of course, liberal politics does not simply leave things where they were. It manages traffic
(dictating that people get to choose their own religion, for example). It does not treat all
destinations as equally valuable. It does try to make sure no one (apart from dangerous
criminals) is left facing a light that never turns green.
144 Chapter 8
10
This is how I read Williams (2005).
Realistic Idealism 145
11
Our personal peaks will of course have positive content, and may have to do with, for
example, reciprocity, equality, need, or desert. I wrote on such things before (Schmidtz
2006), but did not then doubt that justice has an essence. Moreover, I do not currently
believe we can altogether dispense with these positive elements of justice. We may
exaggerate how compelling our own personal peaks can be to others, and thus may
exaggerate how central a place they can hold as organizing principles for a diverse polis,
but they might for all that remain in some way meaningful and relevant. Honestly, I do
not know.
146 Chapter 8
ideal response to ideal conditions, they are doing the right thing. Their
role is to resolve conflict.
Judges play a role in enabling communities to climb, but see that
climbing begins from where we are. It is natural but thoughtless to think
a judge’s job is to dream about how to do a reset from day one and rebuild
society from the ground up according to a vision of justice. If you buy
a house in the United States, you do a title search. The point is not to
ascertain whether ideals of distributive justice single you out as having the
most weighty claim, but simply to uncover any active dispute over title, or
any unsettled dispute within the past forty years or so. If nothing turns up,
we treat the deed as valid. No one needs reminding that there are no
primordially clean land titles. Ascertaining that no one has disputed a title
in forty years is not a way of giving up on justice; it is a way of getting on
with the kind of justice that can ground society as a cooperative venture.
To philosophers, forty years seems arbitrary, but it is property’s role that
dictates what works as a foundation for cooperative society. To coin
a phrase, foundation follows function. Judges try to formulate simple
rules, in a spirit of equality before the law, that enable litigants to get on
with their lives, knowing how to avoid or minimize future conflict.
Property rights, including rights of self-ownership, are essentially rights
to say no. The right to say no makes it safe to come to market and
contribute to the community, thereby promoting trade, thereby promot-
ing progress. When people have a right to say no and to withdraw, then
they can afford not to withdraw. They can afford to trust each other. They
can afford to live in close proximity and to produce, trade, and prosper
without fear.
However, a right to say no is not a weapon of mass destruction.
The operating idea is having a right to decline to be involved in
a transaction, not to forbid transactions among others. Consider a case
(see Schmidtz 2011b). In Hinman v. Pacific Air Transport (1936),
a landowner sues an airline for trespass, asserting a right to stop airlines
from flying over his property. The court’s predicament: because a right to
say no grounds a system of property that in turn grounds cooperation
among self-owners, it was imperative not to repudiate the right to say no.
On the other hand, much of property’s point is to facilitate commercial
traffic. Ruling that landowners can veto air transport is a red light that
would gridlock traffic, not facilitate it. In Hinman, a property system had
come to be inadequately specified relative to newly emerging forms of
commercial traffic. The plaintiff’s interpretation of our right to say no
implied a right to gridlock air traffic, so the edges of our right to say no
needed clarifying.
Realistic Idealism 147
In Hinman, Judge Haney ruled that the right to say no does not extend
to the heavens, but only so high as a landowner’s actual use. Navigation
easements subsequently were interpreted as allowing federal govern-
ments to allocate airspace above 500 feet for transportation purposes.
The verdict made the system a better solution to a particular problem
confronting Judge Haney’s court, leaving us with a system of rights that
we could afford.
If Hinman had a right to veto peaceful cooperation, he would have
a right to veto progress. If Hinman makes demands of people to whom he
is of no use, and works to be someone whom society would be better off
without, then Hinman’s neighbours will ignore him as best they can and
seek out contributors: partners less intent on making demands and more
intent on having something to offer.12
Property’s purpose in managing commercial traffic (the purpose at
stake in Hinman) has to condition the contours of what we call justice,
not the other way around. Taking justice seriously involves seeing justice
as something that comes second, not first, because taking justice seriously
involves seeing justice as something a society can afford to take
seriously.13
From a mediator’s perspective, the test of theory is how it works in
practice, and in practice there is no progress without negotiation and
compromise, aiming for what everyone can live with. It is one thing to
win. It is another thing to get a result about which no one feels
triumphant but to which all can adjust without feeling sacrificed on
the altar of a vision they do not (and no one honestly expects them to)
share.
Judges have to play fair with the cards they are dealt. Judges can
theorize about cards they ideally would have been dealt, and such
theorizing is not necessarily irrelevant. But the relevance of such theo-
rizing stems from its implications regarding how best to play their actual
cards. While a philosopher’s job involves reflecting on how the world
ought to be in the grand scheme of things, actual governance is the art of
compromise in a world that is not a blank canvas. The practical rele-
vance of political philosophy depends on how well we take our cue from
effective conflict mediators.
12
See Harrison Frye, ‘A Different Camping Trip: Offers, Demands, and Incentives’ (pre-
sentation at Chapman University, 10 July 2015) for the idea that there is a fine line
between an offer (to bring a particular service to market for a price) and what others
perceive as a demand (when they want the service but resent having to pay).
13
We cannot afford to think of justice in terms that will render it obsolete as a response to
tomorrow’s problems. See Rosenberg (2016).
148 Chapter 8
Some questions have no answers until judges sort out what will help
current and potential litigants in particular circumstances to stay out of
court. After judges settle a dispute, citizens go forward not with personal
visions of justice, but with validated mutual expectations about what to
count as their due. Judges get it right when they settle it – when they
establish mutual expectations that leave everyone with a basis for mov-
ing on.
Effective judges know this. To them, having personal convictions
about fairness is not good enough. Judges aim higher, and thereby
settle disputes in a way that philosophers and their theories almost
never do. Philosophers spend their days convincing themselves that
they have enough evidence for their view to justify ignoring the evi-
dence against. Judges spend their days giving litigants a way to get on
with their lives.
I have never been employed as a mediator, but after playing
football in high school, I coached and served as a referee. Our task
as referees was to interpret and apply the rules. With responsibility
came power. With power came a measure of discretion. Our calls
could determine a game’s outcome. Crucially, it was not our place
to prefer a particular outcome. Favouring a team would have been
corrupt. Neither had we any right to prefer games ending in a tie.
That too would have been incompatible with the unobtrusive impar-
tiality that defines successful refereeing. We had a duty not to aim
for any outcome, not even an equal one. It was not our place to win.
Our aim was to let the players play, and let their futures be of their
own making.
4.3 Corruption
Benjamin Barber notes Rawls’s lack of realism in a stinging remark:
‘When political terms do occasionally appear, they appear in startlingly
naive and abstract ways, as if Rawls not only believed that a theory of
justice must condition political reality, but that political reality could
be regarded as little more than a precipitate of the theory of justice’
(1989: 310). Robert Paul Wolff’s criticism is equally sharp. He sees in
Rawls ‘no conception of the generation, deployment, limitations, or
problems of political power’.
It would require very considerable political power to enforce the sorts of wage
rates, tax policies, transfer payments, and job regulation called for by the differ-
ence principle. The men and women who apply the principle, make the calcula-
tions, and issue the redistribution orders will be the most powerful persons in the
society, be they econometricians, elected representatives, or philosopher-kings.
Realistic Idealism 149
How are they to acquire this power? How will they protect and enlarge it once they
have it? Whose interests will they serve? (1977: 202)
It is indeed startling to see the work of the twentieth century’s most
influential political philosopher described as ‘startlingly naive’.14 And yet,
upon reflection, it is amazing that there is no contemporary philosophical
literature on the idea that power corrupts.
Imagine concentrated power in the hands of the worst ruler in living
memory. Assume what you know to be true: namely, concentrated poli-
tical power actually does fall into the hands of people like that. This has an
important implication. When formulating theories about what is
politically ideal, ask ‘ideally, how much power would be wielded
by people like that?’ and not ‘ideally, how much power would be
wielded by ideal rulers?’ Which of these questions is a genuine question
about the human condition?
One theoretical bottom line is this. The fact that power corrupts bears
on how much power we have reason to want there to be. When we ask
how much good an ideal ruler could do with absolute power, we obscure
this. We are working on an idealized problem, and gravitating towards
endorsing as much power as it takes to realize our vision of true justice.
Yet, among actual corruptible human beings, we ought to regard the raw
power to ram any vision of true justice down people’s throats as the
paradigm of what true justice forbids.
Ideal theory done well cannot be a question of how much power ideally
would be wielded by ideal rulers. Ideal theory done well has to be
a question about how much power ideally would be wielded by the sort
of human being who actually ends up acquiring power in human societies
as we know them (Schmidtz 2015).
14
It would be naïve indeed to suppose for example that, for the sake of fairness, university
resources should be distributed among departments in whatever manner is to the greatest
advantage of the least advantaged department. However, what Rawls actually says is: the
principle applies only to the basic structure. We could simply stipulate this, or we could
argue that the Principle more broadly applied often would fail self-inspection. For
example, would it be to the greatest advantage of the least advantaged to treat rules of
university budgeting as mere summary rules that answer case by case to the Difference
Principle? (Would we distribute grades so as to be to the greatest advantage of the least
advantaged student?) By the lights of the Difference Principle itself, ignoring empirical
aspects of such questions is precisely what we have no right to do when evaluating
society’s basic structure and when evaluating the proper scope of the Difference
Principle’s application. If this is Rawls’s view, then his view has none of the naïveté that
Barber and Wolff find in the Difference Principle. The Difference Principle informs one
and only one practice: namely the practice of judging the fairness of society’s basic
structure.
150 Chapter 8
5 Conclusion
This chapter offers several conjectures about what it takes to make
theorizing about political animals worthwhile. Formulated as practical
advice, my conjectures are:
(a) Theorize about players, not pawns. We are political animals
living in a strategic world. To theorize about which institutions are
realistically ideal for political animals, we need to theorize about
which incentive structures are ideal.
(b) Theorize about ideals, but beware of starting with ideals. From
what I observe, theorizing in actual practice spirals between our
articulating of problems and of solutions. Introspectively, it will
seem true that before we were reasoning about the one, there was
a previous stage of reasoning about the other. (See also Philp 2012.)
Inevitably, it will feel right to ask ‘to theorize about x, don’t you need
some conception of y?’ Perhaps observation inevitably is theory-
laden. (That very thought is so obviously a theory-laden observa-
tion.) However, it is just as true that some theories (including some
ideal theories) are observation laden, and those are the theories we
have reason to take seriously. Those are the theories that began life as
responses to something real.
(c) Avoid solving idealized problems. More generally, theorizing
about what would be ideal if reality were no constraint is a variation
on the idealist theme, but not a realistic one. Realistic idealism works
in the space of educated guesses about how the world works and how
the world could work.
(d) Set aside details and focus on what you see as a problem’s
essence. Acknowledge that you exercise judgment when you set
aside details. Even if you do not beg the question, others will think
you did. When you simplify, beware of the impulse to simplify with
prejudice by setting aside, as a ‘distraction’, what reveals that your
solution is not ideal.
(e) Acknowledge that your reasons for seeing the world as you do
are not compelling. Theorize about a world of people who do not
see it your way, and who are perfectly aware that there is no reason
why they should. Societies thrive not when they minimize disagree-
ment so much as when they minimize the need for agreement.
(f) Question the platitude that justice is the first virtue of social
institutions. In practice, what a theorist calls justice will be that
theorist’s personal vision. But in a world of people who see things
differently, the first virtue of social institutions is that they curb the
hunger to impose a vision. To do that, institutions need to manage
Realistic Idealism 151
Acknowledgements
My work on this chapter was supported by a grant from the John
Templeton Foundation. Opinions expressed here are mine and do not
necessarily reflect views of the John Templeton Foundation. Adrian
Blau’s advice was illuminating and helpful at every turn. The chapter
also benefited from comments by Sameer Bajaj, Harrison Frye, Michael
Huemer, Ellen Mease, Richard Miller, Jacob Monaghan, Joshua Ramey,
and Danny Shahar.
References
Barber, Benjamin, 1989. The Conquest of Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Cohen, G. A., 2003. ‘Facts and principles’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 31:
211–45.
Cohen, G. A., 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Cohen, G. A., 2009. Why Not Socialism? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Estlund, David, 2008. Democratic Authority. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Estlund, David, 2011. ‘Human nature and the limits (if any) of political
philosophy’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 39: 207–37.
Estlund, David, 2014. ‘Utopophobia’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 42: 113–34.
152 Chapter 8
Gilabert, Pablo, 2015. ‘Justice and feasibility: a dynamic approach’, in Kevin Vallier
and Michael Weber, eds., Political Utopia: Contemporary Debates. Oxford
University Press.
Hamlin, Alan and Zofia Stemplowska, 2012. ‘Theory, ideal theory, and the theory
of ideals’, Political Studies 10: 48–62.
Hope, Simon, 2010. ‘The circumstances of justice’, Hume Studies 36: 125–48.
James, Aaron, 2012. Fairness in Practice. Oxford University Press.
Mason, Andrew, 2010. ‘Rawlsian theory and the circumstances of politics’,
Political Theory 38: 658–83.
Pennington, Mark, 2017. ‘Robust political economy and the priority of the right to
exit’, Social Philosophy & Policy 34: forthcoming.
Philp, Mark, 2012. ‘Realism without illusions’, Political Theory 40: 629–49.
Rawls, John, 1955. ‘Two concepts of rules’, Philosophical Review 64: 3–32.
Rawls, John, 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls, John, 1999a. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Rawls, John, 1999b. Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rosenberg, Alexander. (2016). ‘On the Very Idea of Ideal Theory in Political
Philosophy,’ Social Philosophy & Policy 33: 53–75.
Schmidtz, David, 2011a. ‘Nonideal theory: what it is and what it needs to be’,
Ethics 121: 772–96.
Schmidtz, David, 2011b. ‘Property’, in George Klosko, ed., Oxford Handbook of the
History of Political Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 599–610.
Schmidtz, David, 2015. ‘Corruption’, in Subramanian Rangan, ed., Performance
and Progress: Essays on Capitalism, Business, and Society. Oxford University Press,
49–64.
Schmidtz, David. 2006. Elements of Justice. Cambridge University Press.
Schmidtz, David, 2016. ‘After solipsism’, Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 6:
145–65.
Singer, Peter, 1972. ‘Famine, affluence, and morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs
1, 229–43.
Sleat, Matt, 2013. Liberal Realism. Manchester University Press.
Smith, Adam, 1984. Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Williams, Bernard, 2005. In the Beginning Was the Deed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Wolff, Robert, 1977. Understanding Rawls: A Reconstruction and a Critique.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
9 Conceptual Analysis
Johan Olsthoorn
1 Introduction
Concepts are the constituents of thoughts – the basic building blocks of
whatever propositions we form. Conceptual analysis is the philosophical
study of those building blocks. It is one of the more powerful tools
philosophers and political theorists have at their disposal; indeed, for
much of the twentieth century, philosophy in the Anglophone world
was all but equated with doing conceptual analysis (Miller 1983: 35–9;
Wolff 2013: 797–801).
Analytical philosophy values above all rigour in argumentation and
clarity in thinking. The former is supported by logic, the latter by con-
ceptual analysis. ‘[T]he very excellence of analysis’, writes John Stuart
Mill, ‘is that it . . . enables us mentally to separate ideas which have only
casually clung together’ (Mill 1989: 114). Besides elucidating and dis-
ambiguating complex ideas, conceptual analysis helps us to sharpen our
thinking by refining and enriching our vocabulary, structuring our the-
ories and guiding moral judgement. Furthermore, conceptual analysis
diminishes risk of miscommunication by improving our grasp of language
and of the ideas we seek to express with it.
The term ‘analysis’ has more than one sense, and so does ‘concep-
tual analysis’. ‘Analysis’ can mean ‘the resolution or breaking up of
a complex whole into its basic elements or constituent parts’ (Oxford
English Dictionary). Conceptual analysis, so understood, aims to
elucidate complex notions by breaking them up into their simpler
component parts. Legal theorists have sought to clarify the enigmatic
concept of property by reducing it to a bundle of analytically separable
rights to a resource – rights to possess, use, manage, transfer, etc.
(Honoré 1987: 165–79; cf. Penner 1996). Social and political
theorists, similarly, have attempted to translate statements about com-
plex phenomena such as corporate personalities (e.g. the nation or the
state) into more lucid ones about the individuals comprising those
personalities.
153
154 Chapter 9
2 Concepts
This section explains what concepts are and what they are not by distin-
guishing concepts from terms (2.1) and from conceptions, principles and
criteria of application (2.2). It also explains what conceptual connections
are and what conceptual change consists in (2.3).
1
Not every word is a term. Some words, including connectives like ‘and’, ‘neither’ and
‘either’, are not used to express concepts. They serve a merely syntactical function and
hence lack semantic meaning.
156 Chapter 9
freedom-depriving. People too poor to buy a ticket are not free to board
a train; anyone doing so would be quickly forced out. Notice that Cohen
makes a conceptual claim – ‘a claim about how certain concepts [here
“lacking money” and “freedom”] are connected with one another’
(2011a: 168) – premised on a claim about the coercive nature of ‘prop-
erty’. His argument involves no normative statements, grounded in
principles. Which brings us to the distinction between concepts and
principles.
in everyday life (Dworkin 1986: 70–2). Rawls, however, uses the distinc-
tion primarily to explain moral disagreement – for instance, disagreement
over what is just. But when I claim that justice forbids inequalities that
disadvantage the worst off, I don’t just make a linguistic claim about how
the term ‘unjust’ is ordinarily used. I also advance a normative claim about
what I think is morally indefensible. Such normative propositions cannot
be validated by pointing to linguistic practices. They require normative
argument. Normative propositions, and the principles they are based on,
can be true or false.3 If a proposed principle of justice fails to adequately
reflect our considered moral judgements, then this evinces that the prin-
ciple is incorrect (see Knight’s chapter on reflective equilibrium in this
volume). Principles, unlike concepts, are truth-apt. Conceptions of nor-
mative concepts are therefore also truth-apt. They differ in this respect
from conceptions of non-normative notions like courtesy. The latter
cannot be false qua conceptions (although they can fail to capture the
ordinary meaning of the corresponding term).
3
Most analytical political theorists labour on the assumption that there is such a thing as
justice, and that the theories we develop articulate this ideal for better or worse (propo-
nents of a non-cognitivist metaethics will disagree). Those political theorists may, in turn,
disagree over whether ‘justice’ is a mind-dependent moral property. On moral (anti-)
realism and moral (non-)cognitivism, see Joyce (2015).
162 Chapter 9
link between ‘liberty’ and ‘arbitrary power’ through the idea of ‘non-
domination’ (Pettit 1997: 51–79; 2012: 26–74). ‘Liberty as the absence
of interference’ entails no such link. On the non-domination conception
of liberty, to know whether an individual is free requires exploring
whether she is subject to an arbitrary or uncontrolled power. This require-
ment is a conceptual one: it follows logically from conceptualizing free-
dom in this way. Proponents of rival conceptions are spared this
requirement – though possibly at the cost of linguistic and theoretical
plausibility (Section 3.3).
The way a concept is linked to other concepts is not static and unalter-
able: connections between concepts can be rearranged and change over
time. Even as entrenched a conceptual relation as that between claim-
rights and obligations is plausibly conceived differently. Building on his
interest theory of rights, Joseph Raz (1984) argues that claim-rights are
interests deemed sufficiently important to justify holding others under
a correlative duty (barring conflicting considerations). On this concep-
tion, claim-rights do not simply have corresponding obligations in others:
rather, they are the justificatory grounds for these obligations.
Conceptual change in political theory consists not in changing concep-
tions, but in alterations to the internal structure of the concept itself. Rival
conceptions of normative concepts gain and lose prominence over time.
The Rawlsian conception of justice as fairness seems more popular today
than the utilitarian conception of justice as efficiency (Section 3.4). Such
changing fates do not necessarily imply conceptual change: they may
merely reflect the shifting popularity of the normative principles accom-
panying different conceptions. Conceptual change has occurred when-
ever the concept itself has changed. Such change usually manifests itself
in a rearrangement of the cluster of concepts in which the concept is
embedded and through which it is understood.
For example, in the early modern period distributive justice was
generally regarded as (1) a virtue of individuals, (2) regulating the
division of common goods (including spoils of war and political jobs)
(3) according to merit. Today, we tend to think of distributive justice
as (1) a virtue of social institutions, (2) regulating, among other
things, societal divisions of resources, (3) to which people have
a right (Fleischacker 2004: 1–16). Early modern philosophers did
not simply defend alternative conceptions of the modern concept of
distributive justice. Rather, they conceptualized distributive justice
itself differently. Most of them followed Hugo Grotius (1583–1645)
in holding that distributive justice dealt with ‘merit’ or ‘worthiness’,
rather than with rights (De Iure Belli, 1.1.7–8). Distributive justice did
not endow individuals with (morally) enforceable titles (2.22.16).
Conceptual Analysis 163
3 Conceptual Analysis
This section explains how to elucidate complex concepts by identifying
and clarifying their simpler component parts (3.1); how to determine the
extension of a concept (3.2); how to explore and expose conceptual
connections between different concepts (3.3); and how to discover pos-
sibly relevant conceptual distinctions through disambiguation (3.4).
The section concludes with recommendations for concept forma-
tion (3.5).
4
Words denote (mean something), speakers refer to things (Donnellan 1966). A speaker may
legitimately use any word to refer to any object provided the audience understands and
accepts it, without changing the semantic meaning of the word.
Conceptual Analysis 167
to the natural condition, ‘after the original pact, the term “civil” shifts and
is used to refer not to the whole of “civil society” but to one of its parts’ –
namely the public realm, from which women were considered excluded
(1988: 11). Through this equivocation, contract theorists like Locke and
Kant could simultaneously grant and deny women a place in civil society
(1988: 55). Pateman’s conceptual analysis reveals how the natural/civil
antinomy seeped into the private/public one, thus expressing and
legitimizing sexist prejudices.
Finally, you could explore the concept’s internal structure – the
links to other concepts that it presupposes. If diverse usages of the
same term entail different conceptual linkages, then the term probably
expresses multiple concepts. For instance, I believe that two irreducibly
distinct concepts of justice are found in modern political philosophy.
What we may call ‘ordinary justice’ expresses a moral norm ordering
agents to respect moral rights (on pain of injustice). The rights it regu-
lates, including human rights, are logically prior to justice. Ordinary
justice does not deal with the distribution of rights (human rights are
not distributed; we have them by virtue of being human). Distributive
justice, by contrast, is a moral norm allocating rights, e.g. to a share of
societal wealth. Individuals have these rights by virtue of distributive
justice – i.e. because a particular distribution is fair. Rights are thus
logically posterior to distributive justice. Ordinary justice and distributive
justice implicate the concept of rights in divergent ways, which strongly
suggests that they are distinct concepts. My point here is not to convince
you that political theorists unwittingly employ two distinct concepts of
justice, but to illustrate a method for disambiguation.
5
Bernard Williams’s (1985: 129–30) distinction between ‘thin’ ethical concepts (which
lack descriptive content) and ‘thick’ ones (which have both evaluative and descriptive
components) captures roughly the same idea more obscurely: ‘thickness’ and ‘thinness’
are matters of degree, whereas ‘essentially’ and ‘non-essentially’ are not (Carter 2015:
287–9; cf. Dworkin 2011: 180–4; Scheffler 1987: 417–21).
174 Chapter 9
(Miller 1983: 40–1). While people strongly disagree over what the proper
criteria are for institutions to qualify as just (i.e. over the standards of
justice), disagreement over what makes something count as a standard of
justice (rather than of prudence, good taste or efficiency) is unlikely to run
as deep. This is because recognizing a norm as a norm of justice requires
no normative judgement itself. We can recognize that ‘divide the social
surplus according to need’ is a principle of justice by reflecting on what
the principle aims to achieve (a fair distribution of societal resources).
We do not in addition need to morally evaluate whether the principle
succeeds, in our view, in capturing the true criteria for a fair distribution,
such that it successfully identifies all fair distributions and only those.
This discussion suggests that the extension of concepts like ‘justice’ is
ambiguous. It could either consist of everything in the world that meets
the standards of justice. Or it could consist of all these standards, princi-
ples and norms themselves. When analysing essentially evaluative
concepts like justice, do not conflate the set of objects it evaluates
positively with the set of evaluative standards that fall under the
concept.
An analysis of essentially evaluative concepts can take two forms. First,
reflection on linguistic use may reveal that essentially evaluative
terms are systematically used to refer to distinct kinds of objects.
As Aristotle observed long ago, ‘justice and injustice are spoken of in more
than one way, but because the different senses of each are close to one
another, their homonymy passes unnoticed’ (2000: 81–2). According to
Aristotle, ‘justice’ is used to refer to several different ideas: (1) justice of
persons and (2) of actions; (3) justice as the whole of other-regarding
morality vs. (4) justice as a special virtue; (5) distributive justice; (6)
corrective justice; and (7) justice in exchange. Each constitutes
a distinct concept falling under the umbrella notion of justice.
Disambiguating ‘justice’ in this way is illuminating even amidst intract-
able disagreement over which things in the world are just and unjust.
Second, we can explore the basic conceptual structure of justice
by identifying the elements of justice and their conceptual lin-
kages. These elements constitute linguistic criteria for counting as an
instance of justice. An excellent example is Mill’s analysis of the elements
of justice in Utilitarianism (Gaus 2000: 182–5). After summarizing the
various ways in which ‘justice’ is used, Mill identifies a number of ele-
ments common to each of these usages. This requires analysing con-
ceptually related notions like ‘rights’, ‘desert’, ‘duty’ and ‘impartiality’.
Justice, Mill claims, essentially deals with rights (whether moral or legal)
(Mill 1969: 241–2). ‘Impartiality’ is implicated in justice only insofar as it
is required by ‘the more general obligation of giving to every one his right’
176 Chapter 9
(1969: 243). Try to identify those elements that mark it off from
‘neighbouring’ concepts. How does justice differ from related concepts
like ‘morality’ and ‘expediency’? Unlike expediency, Mill contends, jus-
tice and morality govern duties – things that ‘may be exacted from
a person, as one exacts a debt’, whether by penal sanctions or moral
blame (1969: 246). Justice, in turn, differs from morality in dealing
exclusively with duties with correlative claim-rights: ‘Justice implies
something which it is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but
which some individual person can claim from us as his moral right.’
By contrast, while we have a duty to act benevolently, ‘[n]o one has
a moral right to our generosity or beneficence’ (1969: 247). Observe
that Mill’s analysis is reconstructive: in everyday language, we do not
always distinguish as clearly between justice and morality.
Conceptual clarification often requires a degree of reconstruction
(for a defence, see Oppenheim 1981: 177–202). The merits of recon-
structive analyses nevertheless depend primarily on their linguistic plau-
sibility, not on their conformity to reflectively endorsed normative
judgements.
5 Normative Implications
What follows normatively from a successful analysis of concepts?
Conceptual analysis, I shall argue, is no substitute for normative argu-
ment. It does, however, have important indirect implications for norma-
tive theorizing. Concepts frame our theories and guide moral judgement.
They can also have a distorting effect, however – rendering certain lines of
argument salient while side-lining others.
Normative arguments, and moral judgements generally, need concep-
tual guidance. Conceptual analysis helps normative judgements
target the right propositions, such that they don’t spill over into
adjacent conceptual territory (where they don’t hold true). Mill notes
that proponents of laissez-faire often make arguments ‘far outstretching
the special application made of them’ (Principles 5.11.1). Laissez-faire
advocates object not to government intervention as such, but to coercive
government intervention. Their arguments against government meddling
do not challenge ‘unauthoritative’ state interventions, such as the public
provision of goods the government considers too important to entrust
solely to the care of the market. To avoid argumentative spillover,
consider what is at stake normatively.
Another example is found in Cohen’s article ‘How to do political
philosophy’ (2011b: 227). Cohen urges political theorists not to conflate
the following three questions:
1. What is justice?
2. What should the state do?
3. Which social states of affairs ought to be brought about?
Even if justice is ‘the first virtue of social institutions’ (Rawls 1999: 3), it
does not follow, Cohen argues, that the concept ‘what the state should do’
is equivalent to ‘justice’. Justice is the primary but not the only virtue of
180 Chapter 9
does not show why the concept of self-ownership is incoherent, i.e. why
it is logically impossible for persons to own themselves. Even if he did
succeed in showing this, it is better to let moral judgements and
arguments rather than conceptual legerdemain do the norma-
tive weightlifting. Thus if we believe, like Kant, that prostitution is
morally unacceptable, then we should put forth normative arguments in
support rather than claiming that it is conceptually impossible for per-
sons to commodify their body.
Do not mistake the conceptual possibility of a notion with the
actual existence or normative desirability of what it denotes.
Proving a concept to be coherent is one thing; proving that it has real-
world application and/or denotes something normatively desirable is
something else. Proponents of the concept of self-ownership should do
more than dislodge the Kantian objection of incoherency. They should
also show that it is morally true that we own ourselves, e.g. by appealing
to the widespread intuition that ‘we – and not others – are morally in
charge of our bodies and persons’, and by showing that other property
rules like trusteeship or guardianship cannot satisfactorily account for
that intuition (Vallentyne, Steiner and Otsuka 2005: 208). As Cohen
puts it: ‘the concept of self-ownership is not identical with the thesis of
self-ownership: the latter might be false, while the former, being
a concept, cannot be false’ (Cohen 1995: 209).
When analysing evaluative concepts, separate the questions
‘what is X’ and ‘what makes X morally valuable/objectionable’.
A conceptual analysis of racism cannot by itself explain what is morally
objectionable about racism: normative judgement is needed as well.
However, the more refined our grasp of this concept, the easier it becomes
to determine which features make racism wrong. Conversely, if our
analysis focuses exclusively on those features of racism we deem morally
objectionable, then, constricted by our moral judgements, we are in
danger of arriving at an impoverished account of racism.
Section 2.2 pointed out that conceptions of normative notions gener-
ally include normative principles. Consequently, disputes over rival
normative conceptions cannot normally be settled by conceptual
arguments alone. Normative arguments are needed as well. Take
Galston’s (1995) distinction between conceptions of liberalism based
on ‘autonomy’ and ‘diversity’. Galston does not argue that one of these
conceptions captures more accurately the ‘true meaning’ of liberalism –
wisely, as the dispute is not solely about linguistic intuitions. Instead he
argues that the diversity conception better captures what we (ought to)
find valuable in liberalism.
182 Chapter 9
6
Stevenson opts for the term ‘emotive meaning’ because of his non-cognitivist metaethics.
His point applies to evaluative notions generally and does not depend on a particular
metaethical position.
Conceptual Analysis 183
6 Analysing Conceptualizations
As political philosophers, we do not just analyse political concepts them-
selves, as if they were free-floating entities (‘what is justice?’). We also try
to understand, if only preliminarily, how people have conceptualized these
notions (‘what did Rawls mean by justice?’). This section provides con-
crete advice on how to best reconstruct conceptualizations advanced in
the literature. My advice, partly modelled on Extensional Analysis
(Section 3.2), may be especially welcome when studying the history of
political philosophy. Today’s theorists usually try to advance conceptua-
lizations that match our linguistic intuitions (indeed, they are well-
advised to do so!), rendering the task of figuring out what they mean
with a term comparatively easy. This task becomes harder the further we
go back in history. The conceptual landscape has changed dramatically
since Locke wrote the Two Treatises. As a result, his notion of ‘property’
may well depart significantly from ours. Reading historical texts is, in
many ways, an exercise in translation.
How can we best reconstruct conceptualizations advanced in political
texts? The first and perhaps most important tip is to read with an open
mind. Do not simply assume that what Locke meant by ‘property’ is the
same as what you think it means. This also holds for contemporary texts:
G. A. Cohen’s conception of ‘justice’ may well be miles apart from what
you and I think the term signifies. Do not read into the text what is not
there. In Leviathan, Hobbes declares that ‘[t]he notions of Right and
Wrong, Justice and Injustice have . . . no place’ in the condition of ‘warre
of every man against every man’, as it exists outside the state (Leviathan
13.13). Hans Morgenthau, doyen of the realist school in international
relations theory, consequently attributes to Hobbes the ‘extreme dictum’
that ‘the state creates morality as well as law and that there is neither
morality nor law outside the state’ (Morgenthau 1952: 34). But Hobbes is
speaking only about justice. Justice and morality (‘natural law’) are not
the same thing for Hobbes; indeed, natural law exists and is to a limited
extent operative outside the state (Olsthoorn 2015: 20). The distinction
between justice and morality may be irrelevant for Morgenthau’s pur-
poses; it is not for Hobbes.
Read the text, as far as possible, in the original language. This
advice should not be taken to extremes: if your Latin is as rusty as mine,
reading modern editions is likely to be vastly more profitable than sweat-
ing over the original. Remember that you are reading a translation
(when doing so). Even critical editions may translate terms in
a misleading or inconsistent manner. Cross-checking the original can
save you much time and confusion. I have spent ages trying to make
184 Chapter 9
sense of Hobbes’s comment that ‘by natural law, one is oneself the judge’
(De Cive 1.9) – only to discover eventually that Tuck and Silverthorne
(1998) had mistranslated the original Latin: ‘by natural right’ (jure natur-
ali). (For Hobbes, ‘right’ and ‘law’ are opposites – e.g. De Cive 14.3;
Leviathan 14.3, 26.44.)
Stick as far as possible to the original terms. Substituting your
own terms is potentially distorting. Translation inevitably leads to loss
or change of meaning. Even if terms have roughly the same extension –
i.e. when they refer to the same objects – their meaning may differ.
What early moderns called ‘natural law’ picks out roughly the same
objects as our ‘morality’, but the conceptual linkages of the two
notions differ considerably. To highlight one salient difference, early
modern natural laws are moral norms applying to us by virtue of the
kind of beings we are. Modern ‘morality’ lacks such an explicit
grounding in human nature. While substituting your own terms
increases the risk of overlooking conceptual changes, sticking to the
original terms is no panacea: serious historical research is needed to
recover lost connotations and conceptual connections of notions like
‘natural law’. If you are using an original term whose meaning
has changed over time, then describe its meaning in present-
day terms as well as you can.
Be attentive to unexpected usages of the term. We are inclined to
think of ‘property’ as a general term for rules governing access to and
control of material resources (Waldron 1988: 31). Undiscerning readers
of the Second Treatise may assume that Locke was primarily concerned
with safeguarding citizens’ existing rights to material resources against the
State. But Locke uses the term ‘property’ in a far more expansive manner
as including ‘Lives, Liberties, and Estates’ (Second Treatise §123). Such
unexpected usages – lives as property? – should be red flags, indicators of
conceptual change.
What is the best way to systematically reconstruct what a particular
philosopher meant by a term? A good first step is to collect explicit
definitions and descriptions. Locke declares that it is of the nature of
property ‘that without a Man’s own consent it cannot be taken from him’
(Second Treatise §193). Notice that this is not, strictly speaking,
a definition, but rather a description of an essential feature of Lockean
property. Elsewhere, Locke writes: ‘the Idea of Property, being a right to
any thing’ (Essay Concerning Human Understanding 4.3.18). We may for-
mulate a provisional definition: ‘property is the exclusive moral control
over a material or immaterial object.’ To further improve the definition,
consider assembling contextual evidence. The Oxford English
Dictionary often lists earliest possible usages of senses of a term still in
Conceptual Analysis 185
7 Conclusion
This chapter has provided a range of advice, from the obvious to the
controversial, on how to do conceptual analysis in political theory. Rather
than reiterating my main recommendations, I will conclude by
Conceptual Analysis 187
Acknowledgements
Donald Bello Hutt, Adrian Blau, Benjamin De Mesel, Alex Douglas,
Robin Douglass, Cressida Gaukroger, Siba Harb, Michael Jewkes and
especially A. P. Martinich provided very helpful comments on previous
versions of this chapter. I would also like to thank the KU Leuven
research group in political philosophy (RIPPLE) for a stimulating discus-
sion of an earlier draft.
References
Aristotle, 2000. Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Roger Crisp. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Austin, John, 1998. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Indianapolis, IN:
Hackett.
Beaney, Michael, 2015. ‘Analysis’, in Edward Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/analysis. Accessed
1 September 2015.
Bell, Duncan, 2014. ‘What is liberalism?’, Political Theory 42: 682–715.
188 Chapter 9
Bentham, Jeremy, 1838–43. The Works of Jeremy Bentham, 11 vols., ed. J. Bowring.
Edinburgh: W. Tait.
Berlin, Isaiah, 2002. Liberty: Incorporating Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University
Press.
Carter, Ian, 2004. ‘Choice, freedom, and freedom of choice’, Social Choice and
Welfare 22, 61–81.
Carter, Ian, 2011. ‘The myth of “merely formal freedom”’, The Journal of Political
Philosophy 19, 486–95.
Carter, Ian, 2015. ‘Value-freeness and value-neutrality in the analysis of political
concepts’, Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy 1: 279–306.
Cohen, G. A., 1995. Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality. Cambridge University
Press.
Cohen, G. A., 2011a. ‘Freedom and money’, in On the Currency of Egalitarian
Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 166–92.
Cohen, G. A., 2011b. ‘How to do political philosophy’, in On the Currency of
Egalitarian Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philosophy. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 225–35.
Connolly, William, 1983. The Terms of Political Discourse. 2nd edition. Oxford:
Martin Robinson.
Donnellan, Keith, 1966. ‘Reference and definite descriptions’, The Philosophical
Review 75, 281–304.
Dummett, Michael, 2010. The Nature and Future of Philosophy. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Dworkin, Ronald, 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Dworkin, Ronald, 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Fleischacker, Samuel, 2004. A Short History of Distributive Justice. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Frazer, Michael, 2010. ‘The modest professor: interpretive charity and interpretive
humility in John Rawls’s Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy’,
European Journal of Political Theory 9, 218–26.
Freeden, Michael, 1996. Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Freeden, Michael, 2005. ‘What should the “political” in political theory explore?’,
The Journal of Political Philosophy 13, 113–34.
Gallie, W. B., 1956. ‘Essentially contested concepts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 56, 167–98.
Galston, William, 1995. ‘Two concepts of liberalism’, Ethics 105, 516–34.
Gardner, John, 2001. ‘Legal positivism: 5½ myths’, American Journal of
Jurisprudence 46: 199–227.
Gaus, Gerald, 2000. Political Concepts and Political Theories. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
Gerring, John, 1999. ‘What makes a concept good? A criterial framework for
understanding concept formation in the social sciences’, Polity 31, 357–93.
Grotius, Hugo, 2005. The Rights of War and Peace, ed. Richard Tuck. Indianapolis,
IN: Liberty Fund.
Conceptual Analysis 189
Mill, John Stuart, 1974. Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volumes VII and VIII,
ed. J. M. Robson. University of Toronto Press.
Mill, John Stuart, 1989. Autobiography, ed. J. M. Robson. London: Penguin.
Miller, David, 1983. ‘Linguistic philosophy and political theory’, in David Miller
and Larry Siedentop, eds., The Nature of Political Theory. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 35–51.
Morgenthau, Hans, 1952. American Foreign Policy: A Critical Examination.
London: Methuen & Co.
Murphy, Gregory, 2002. The Big Book of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Olivecrona, Karl, 1975. ‘The term “property” in Locke’s Two Treatises of
Government’, Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 61, 109–15.
Olsthoorn, Johan, 2015. ‘Why justice and injustice have no place outside the
Hobbesian state’, European Journal of Political Theory 14: 19–36.
Oppenheim, Felix, 1981. Political Concepts: A Reconstruction. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Outhwaite, William, 2010. Concept Formation in Social Science. London:
Routledge.
Pateman, Carole, 1988. The Sexual Contract. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Penner, J. E., 1996. ‘The “bundle of rights” picture of property’, University of Los
Angeles Law Review 43, 711–820.
Pettit, Philip, 1997. Republicanism. A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Pettit, Philip, 2012. On the People’s Terms. A Republican Theory and Model of
Democracy. Cambridge University Press.
Phillips, Anne, 2013. Our Bodies, Whose Property? Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Rawls, John, 1999a. A Theory of Justice. Revised edition. Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press.
Rawls, John, 1999b. Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 47–72.
Rawls, John, 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press.
Rawls, John, 2005. Political Liberalism. Expanded edition. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Rawls, John, 2007. Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Raz, Joseph, 1984. ‘On the nature of rights’, Mind 93: 194–214.
Russell, Bertrand, 1923. ‘Vagueness’, Australasian Journal of Psychology and
Philosophy 1, 84–92.
Sartori, Giovanni, 1970. ‘Concept misformation in comparative politics’,
American Political Science Review 64: 1033–53.
Sartori, Giovanni, 1984. Social Science Concepts: A Systematic Analysis. Beverly
Hills, CA: SAGE Publications.
Scheffler, Samuel, 1987. ‘Morality through thick and thin: a critical notice of
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy’, The Philosophical Review 96, 411–34.
Conceptual Analysis 191
Alan Hamlin
1 Introduction
This chapter is organized around two questions: what is positive political
theory, and how can it be used effectively to address research questions?
While positive political theory may apply in any substantive area of
politics, these questions will be addressed in the context of the analysis
of democratic institutions and political behaviour and, specifically, the
study of referendums, elections and voting.
The next section locates positive political theory relative to its
normative counterpart and indicates the range of positions that exist
within positive political theory. Section 3 provides an extended example
of positive political theory in the setting of the analysis of democratic
elections, so as to develop a more detailed understanding of the
component elements of any exercise in positive political theory.
Section 4 offers a ‘how-to’ guide for the development of positive political
analysis. While no such guide can guarantee success, the claim is that
detailed, systematic and explicit consideration of the processes involved
in constructing and using positive political theories can only enhance
political debate. Section 5 illustrates the ‘how-to’ guide by using its
principles as a guide to reading two journal articles.
192
Positive Political Theory 193
3 An Extended Example
At this point it is useful to provide an example, to illustrate the various
points made. The example begins with an extremely simple model of
a referendum in the broadly rational choice tradition, and shows some of
the ways in which that model has developed over time. While our focus
here is on the positive theory, note that the ultimate goal here, as is almost
always the case, is normative – we study referendums and elections not
just to understand them, but so as to be able to improve the design and
performance of our political institutions. Yet the normative concern for
improvement requires a relatively detailed positive understanding.
In keeping with the ideas of abstraction, simplification and idealiza-
tion, we will begin by identifying the minimal necessary ingredients for
a positive model of a referendum: a set of voters, some issue over
which the voters disagree, two alternative policy positions with respect
to that issue, and a voting rule. A referendum, in this simple model
200 Chapter 10
L X Y R
world, is simply the choice of one of the policy positions by the set of
voters acting through the voting rule. To be specific, and to idealize
features of any real-world referendum, assume that the voting rule is
simple majority voting (note that with just two alternatives, almost all
plausible voting rules converge on simple majority voting) and that the
issue at stake can be described as choosing a point along a left-right
spectrum. Left-right here does not need to carry any particular political
significance; it might, for example, be the level of public spending on
a particular activity, or the tax rate to impose in a particular context.
Assume also that each individual voter identifies an ideal point on the
spectrum at issue and would like the outcome to be as close as possible
to that ideal point. This adds an element of motivation to the
individuals in the model and is what makes this a model in the broadly
rational choice tradition: we assume that each individual acts in the
way that she believes will contribute to bringing about the best
available outcome seen from her own perspective. This does not
amount to an assumption of self-interest. The individual may choose
her ideal point because she believes it to be in the public interest, or
because she believes it is morally best, or for any other reason. All that
‘rationality’ requires here is that the individual identifies a relevant
ideal point and acts so as to bring about the closest possible approx-
imation to that ideal. This is essentially the model of democratic
decision-making introduced by Downs (1957) and may be illustrated
diagrammatically.
In Figure 10.1, the L-R line represents the policy issue at stake, with
points along the line representing different possible positions that might
be chosen. X and Y are the two specific policy positions that are ‘candi-
dates’ in this referendum, and the voters may be thought of as spread
along the L-R line with each voter positioned at his or her ideal point.
If we define point P to be the point halfway between X and Y, and we
assume that everyone votes (note the idealization here), it should be clear
that all voters whose ideal points lie to the left of P will vote for X and all
Positive Political Theory 201
those to the right of P will vote for Y. Given the simple majority voting
rule, X will win if a majority of voters lie to the left of P, Y will win if
a majority of voters lie to the right of P.
So far this model does nothing more than articulate the idea of majority
voting in a simple setting. To animate the model further we might add
another element. Consider the strategic choice of X and Y on the
assumption that these policy positions are chosen by political parties
whose choice is guided by the desire to maximize the probability of their
proposal winning the referendum. Note that we are here introducing
a second element of motivation, and again we are making that motivation
as simple and stark as possible, even though this may be unrealistic.
If, in the initial position depicted by Figure 10.1, X would win the
election, the political party controlling Y would face an incentive to shift
Y leftward. By doing so, the position of point P will move to the left, more
voters will support Y and fewer will support X. But similarly, the party
controlling X will face an incentive to move rightward, so increasing its
vote, and reducing its rivals. This suggests that the two party platforms
will converge under competitive pressure; but where might this process
stop? One aspect of the answer is that in the absence of any further
argument, there is nothing to stop the two platforms converging to
a single point, so that we might expect the two parties to offer the same
policy.
But this is only half the answer. Imagine that both parties offer policy
Y in Figure 10.1, and that more than half of the voters’ ideal points lie to
the left of Y. It is straightforward to argue that each party now faces an
incentive to move leftward. If either party succeeds in positioning itself
just to the left of its rival, it will win the referendum. But if both parties
face this same incentive, we might expect both to react (one of the
simplifying features of the model is that the two parties are essentially
identical). Similarly, if both parties chose a policy platform such that the
majority of voters’ ideal points were to the right of that policy, then both
would face an incentive to move rightward. So the model tells us not
only that the two parties will converge on the same policy, but that there
is a unique policy point at which the two parties will settle: the policy
that is the ideal point of the median voter, the point at which exactly
half of the voters’ ideal points lie to the left and half lie to the right. This
is the ‘Median Voter Theorem’ that says that in a two-candidate contest
of the type described, both candidates will offer a policy platform aimed
at the median voter’s ideal point.
This is a very simple model, and its simplicity generates both a clarity of
argument and a range of suggestions for further work. And these two
things are closely related. It is precisely because we can see the mechanics
202 Chapter 10
of the model clearly, and understand the forces at work, that we can
pinpoint important limitations of the model and identify further research
questions. A series of questions interrogates the robustness of the model.
What would be the impact of relaxing the assumption that all citizens
vote? What would be the impact of introducing a third political party?
What would be the impact of assuming that political parties had ‘ideal
policies’ of their own that tempered their motivation to win the vote at all
costs? What would be the impact of allowing the vote to operate on more
than one political issue (so that it becomes a model of an election rather
than a single-issue referendum)? How might we compare different voting
system in this framework? How might the model be reformulated to
capture the idea of electing representatives rather than making direct
policy choices?
Some of these questions are relatively simple to address, others require
considerable detailed work, but all of these questions, and many more,
have been explored in the literature that has developed since Downs
(reviewed in Mueller 2003). For example, the issue of abstention opens
up the question of identifying the factors influencing turnout (Aldrich
1993; Blais 2000; Bendor et al. 2003). One possibility is that voters
abstain when they are essentially indifferent across the alternatives on
offer; another possibility is that voters abstain when the policy platforms
are too far from their own ideal points (voter alienation). These
possibilities have different implications. If political parties converge on
identical policy platforms, and individual citizens abstain when they are
essentially indifferent between the platforms on offer, the theory will
generate predictions of low turnout. One branch of the literature intro-
duces the idea that individuals might participate in the vote out of a sense
of civic duty, even if they still vote for whichever platform is closer to their
ideal (Riker and Ordeshook 1968; Ferejohn and Fiorina 1974). This
opens up the idea that the factors that drive turnout may be rather
different from the factors that drive which option to vote for.
A second example relates to animating individual voters. The initial
idea in play here is just that individuals vote instrumentally to bring about
whichever outcome they see as ‘best’ regardless of exactly how they define
‘best’. But perhaps voting behaviour might be modelled differently: in
terms of habitual voting, retrospective voting or expressive voting.
The idea of habitual voting could be incorporated by assuming that an
individual’s vote in any particular election is partly determined by his or
her votes at earlier elections (Fowler 2006). This might allow parties to
pursue non-convergent platforms if they felt that their habitual vote was
secure. The idea of retrospective voting is that voters may be backward-
looking when choosing how to vote, rewarding good (or punishing bad)
Positive Political Theory 203
OUTCOME
PARTY VOTING
ISSUES CITIZENS
PLATFORMS RULE
VOTERS
OUTCOME
positive model will play a key role, ensuring that you move back and
forth between considering the features of the basic positive model
and the intended purpose of the proposed research in an iterative
and flexible process.
The next step is to animate the model and be explicit about
motivational and causal aspects of the model. In the case of the
basic Downsian model we noted two such aspects: the assumed
motivation of the voters in deciding how to vote and the assumed
motivation of the political parties in setting their platforms. Clearly
many other motivational assumptions are possible even within this very
simple structure. At this early stage, motivations and causal forces should
be as explicit and as simple as possible. One way of thinking about this is
to consider each of the arrows in a figure such as Figure 10.2 or 10.3, and
draft a clear statement of the nature of the relationship represented by that
arrow. The exercise of drafting such an explicit statement will almost
always bring three points to the fore. The first is that apparently simple
statements of a causal or motivational relationship often leave open
a considerable range of interpretation, so that detailed thought is required
to construct a clear, explicit statement of the relationship you have in
mind. The second is the requirement for some degree of coherence or
consistency as between the various relationships within the model.
The third is that there are almost always many quite different ways of
identifying a particular relationship, each of which carries at least some
degree of plausibility, so that many different, but related, theoretical
models could be constructed.
The first point is an example of the role of theory construction in
the process of conceptual clarification. By setting yourself the task of
thinking explicitly about the relationship between two parts of your
model and specifying that relationship as clearly and concisely as
possible, you should think carefully and clearly about the
concepts involved. Constructing and understanding your model,
albeit a simplified, abstract and idealized model, involves considerable
investment in the ideas and concepts that are basic to your research.
At this point the style and formality of a theory or model may come
under scrutiny. As your understanding of the model and its
component parts deepens, you will need to find a means of
communicating the nature of the model to others that reflects
its structure and the detailed specification that you have
decided on. There is no uniform answer to how best to present
a theory/model, but you should at least be aware of a variety of
options and make a conscious choice of presentational strategy
that fits with the overall research plan. It may be that an entirely
208 Chapter 10
5 Application
This approach to developing and using positive political theory is
intended to provide a flexible structure for thinking about a wide variety
of political questions and issues. Clearly it needs to be fine-tuned and
adapted to fit any specific purpose. While it has been presented as a way of
approaching research, it can also provide a way of reading the literature
and, to illustrate its use in this way, this section considers two articles in
the general area of democracy and voting that are published in the same
issue of The British Journal of Political Science.
Before turning to these articles, one important point should be
stressed. There is a crucial difference between the work done in
a research project and the report of that work in a final document.
In some contexts (a PhD thesis or monograph) it may be both
appropriate and important for the final document to explicitly display
almost all of the process of research – the consideration of variations
on a theme, the zooming in and zooming out and so on. In other
contexts, such as a journal article, the final document will typically
focus on a relatively small part of the overall research, presenting just
the key message and argument. Much of the research process will be
implicit in the way the article refers and relates to the literature and in
the way in which claims and results are framed.
With this thought in mind, consider two recent articles that relate to
models of democratic behaviour. One is theoretical and normative, while
the other is empirical but, despite this difference, I will point up the extent
to which both depend on underlying positive political theory and how the
approach outlined earlier helps us to read these articles and understand
the broader research programmes of which they form part.
The more theoretical article, by Annabelle Lever (2010a), is focused on
the normative question ‘should voting be compulsory?’ (See also Hill
2010; Lever 2010b.) Lever is clear from the outset that her approach
requires consideration of the differential impacts of compulsory and
voluntary voting systems, so that a positive account of each system is
a required input to the normative debate. Lever identifies a general chain
of argument in support of compulsory voting that proceeds through
Positive Political Theory 211
we should control for the potential impact of that issue. So, being explicit
about the issues we abstract from in our theoretical work helps us to
identify the variables we will need to control for when we turn to
quantitative work.
By considering a range of different positive models, Timmons
exemplifies the idea of searching across models and considering variations
on a theme. But the mismatch between the rather narrowly focused
models considered and the broadly specified empirical investigation
might suggest that the theoretical models are rather ‘zoomed in’ on the
study of micro issues that arise within a democracy, while empirical work
has been rather ‘zoomed out’ on the macro questions that arise in com-
paring democracies with non-democracies. This in itself points to useful
directions for further work on both the theoretical and empirical fronts.
6 Conclusion
No ‘how-to’ guide to the practice of positive political theorizing can
guarantee that the theories/models generated will be useful, valuable
and interesting. But the steps outlined in the previous sections capture
and spell out the benefits of thinking carefully and explicitly about the
positive theory/model element of any political analysis.
Early in this chapter I suggested that positive political theory had some
of the characteristics of prose, in that we use it all the time without always
being conscious of that fact. This is a metaphor that extends a little
further: just as the explicit study of grammar, syntax and punctuation
can improve our prose, whether as readers or writers, so the explicit study
of the more detailed structure of positive political theories and models
and the motivating and causal forces that they analyse can improve our
political debate and understanding, as both readers and writers. Just as
there are no perfect prose sentences, there are no perfect positive political
theories/models. But there are ways in which we can clarify meaning and
develop greater understanding, both in our prose and in our political
analysis.
References
Abrams, Samuel, Torben Iversen and David Soskice, 2011. ‘Informal social
networks and rational voting’, British Journal of Political Science 41, 229–57.
Aldrich, John, 1993. ‘Rational choice and turnout’, American Journal of Political
Science 37, 246–78.
Austen-Smith, David, and James Banks, 2000. Positive Political Theory I: Collective
Preference. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
214 Chapter 10
Austen-Smith, David and James Banks, 2005. Positive Political Theory II: Strategy
and Structure. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Bendor, Jonathan, Daniel Diermeier and Michael Ting, 2003. ‘A behavioral model
of turnout’, American Political Science Review 97, 261–80.
Berggren, Niclas, Henrik Jordahl and Panu Poutvaara, 2009. ‘The looks of
a winner: beauty and electoral success’, Journal of Public Economics 94, 8–15.
Besley, Timothy and Stephen Coate, 1997. ‘An economic model of representative
democracy’, Quarterly Journal of Economics 112, 85–114.
Blais, Andre, 2000. To Vote or Not To Vote? The Merits and Limits of Rational Choice
Theory. University of Pittsburgh Press.
Brennan, Geoffrey and Alan Hamlin, 1998. ‘Expressive voting and electoral
equilibrium’, Public Choice 95, 149–75.
Brennan, Geoffrey and Hartmut Kliemt, 1994. ‘Finite lives and social institutions’,
Kyklos 47, 551–71.
Brennan, Geoffrey and Loren Lomasky, 1993. Democracy and Decision. Cambridge
University Press.
Buchanan, James, 1984. ‘Politics without romance: a sketch of positive public
choice theory and its normative implications’, in James Buchanan and
Robert Tollison, eds., The Theory of Public Choice II. Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 11–22.
Downs, Anthony, 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York:
Harper & Row.
Duverger, Maurice, 1965. Political Parties: Their Organization and Activity in the
Modern State. London: Wiley.
Elster, Jon, 1989. Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge University Press.
Ferejohn, John, 1986. ‘Incumbent performance and electoral control’, Public
Choice 50, 5–25.
Ferejohn, John and Morris Fiorina, 1974. ‘The paradox of not voting: a decision
theoretic analysis’, American Political Science Review 68, 525–36.
Fiorina, Morris, 1981. Retrospective Voting in American National Elections. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Fiorina, Morris, Samuel Abrams and Jeremy Pope, 2003. ‘The 2000
US presidential election: can retrospective voting be saved?’, British Journal of
Political Science 33, 163–87.
Forbes, Donald, 2004. ‘Positive political theory’, in Gerald Gaus and
Chandran Kukathas, eds., Handbook of Political Theory. London: Sage
Publications, 57–72.
Fowler, James, 2006. ‘Habitual voting and behavioral turnout’, Journal of Politics
68, 335–44.
Friedman, Jeffrey, ed., 1996. The Rational Choice Controversy: Economic Models of
Politics Reconsidered. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Gordon, Scott, 1993. The History and Philosophy of Social Science. London:
Routledge.
Green, Donald and Ian Shapiro, 1994. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory:
A Critique of Applications in Political Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Positive Political Theory 215
Hamlin, Alan and Colin Jennings, 2004. ‘Group formation and political conflict:
instrumental and expressive approaches’, Public Choice 118, 413–35.
Hamlin, Alan and Colin Jennings, 2007. ‘Leadership and conflict’, Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization 64, 49–68.
Hamlin, Alan and Colin Jennings, 2011. ‘Expressive political behaviour: founda-
tions, scope and implications’, British Journal of Political Science 41, 645–70.
Hill, Lisa, 2010. ‘On the justifiability of compulsory voting: reply to Lever’, British
Journal of Political Science 40, 917–23.
Hindmoor, Andrew, 2006. Rational Choice. London: Palgrave.
Hindmoor, Andrew, 2011. ‘“Major combat operations have ended”? Arguing
about rational choice’, British Journal of Political Science 41, 191–210.
Kincaid, Harold, 1998. ‘Positivism in the social sciences’, in Edward Craig, ed.,
The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, 558–61.
Krehbiel, Keith and John Wright, 1983. ‘The incumbency effect in congressional
elections: a test of two explanations’, American Journal of Political Science 27,
140–57.
Lever, Annabelle, 2010a. ‘Compulsory voting: a critical perspective’, British
Journal of Political Science 40, 897–915.
Lever, Annabelle, 2010b. ‘Democracy and voting: a response to Lisa Hill’, British
Journal of Political Science 40, 925–9.
Mueller, Dennis, 2003. Public Choice III. Cambridge University Press.
Müller, Wolfgang and Kaare Strøm, eds., 1999. Policy, Office, or Votes? How
Political Parties in Western Europe Make Hard Decisions. Cambridge University
Press.
Ordeshook, Peter, 1986. Game Theory and Political Theory: An Introduction.
Cambridge University Press.
Panebianco, Angelo, 1988. Political Parties: Organization and Power. Cambridge
University Press.
Riker, William and Peter Ordeshook, 1968. ‘A theory of the calculus of voting’,
American Political Science Review 62, 25–42.
Riker, William and Peter Ordeshook, 1973. An Introduction to Positive Political
Theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Satz, Debra and John Ferejohn, 1994. ‘Rational choice and social theory’,
The Journal of Philosophy 91, 71–87.
Shepsle, Kenneth and Mark Bonchek, 1997. Analyzing Politics: Rationality,
Behavior and Institutions. New York: Norton.
Strøm, Kaare, 1990. ‘A behavioral theory of competitive political parties’,
American Journal of Political Science 34, 565–98.
Tiebout, Charles, 1956. ‘A pure theory of local expenditures’, The Journal of
Political Economy 64, 416–24.
Timmons, Jeffrey, 2010. ‘Does democracy reduce economic inequality?’, British
Journal of Political Science 40, 741–57.
Van Evera, Stephen, 1997. Guide to Methods for Students of Political Science. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
216 Chapter 10
Ware, Alan, 1992. ‘Activist-leader relations and the structure of political parties:
“exchange” models and vote-seeking behaviour in parties’, British Journal of
Political Science 22, 71–92.
Zuckerman, Alan, Nicholas Valentino and Ezra Zuckerman, 1994. ‘A structural
theory of vote choice: social and political networks and electoral flows in Britain
and the United States’, The Journal of Politics 56, 1008–33.
11 Rational Choice Theory
1 Introduction
‘The theory of justice is a part, perhaps the most significant part, of the
theory of rational choice’, writes John Rawls (1999a: 15). In linking the
theory of justice to rational choice Rawls both continued an intellectual
tradition and began a new one. He continued an intellectual tradition in
the sense that rational choice theory was first formally introduced in von
John von Neumann’s and Oscar Morgenstern’s Theory of Games and
Economic Behavior (1944), which launched a research agenda that con-
tinues to this day. Rawls, James M. Buchanan (1962; see Thrasher and
Gaus forthcoming), and John Harsanyi (1953, 1955) led the way in
applying the idea of rational choice to the derivation of moral and political
principles; a later generation of political theorists applied game theoretic
analysis to a wide variety of problems of social interactions (e.g. Hampton
1986; Sugden 1986; Binmore 2005). David Gauthier’s Morals by
Agreement (1986) was perhaps the most sustained and resolute attempt
to apply models of utility maximization and decision theory to the deriva-
tion of social morality. Yet, despite the fact that some of the most respected
political theorists of the past fifty years extensively employed the tools of
rational choice theory, confusion still reigns about what these tools pre-
suppose and how they are to be applied. Many reject the entire approach by
a common refrain that ‘rational choice assumes that people are selfish’, and
since that is false, the entire line of analysis can be dismissed; a slightly
more sophisticated (but still misplaced) dismissal insists that rational
choice is about ‘preferences’, but political philosophers are interested in
‘reasons’, so again the entire approach can be set aside asserting that
rational choice theory assumes selfishness, denying that people are selfish,
and dismissing rational choice accordingly. A fundamental aim of this
chapter is to explain just what the tools of rational choice theory are –
and what presuppositions they make – and to provide some guidance for
those wishing to follow in Rawls’s footsteps, showing how rational choice
217
218 Chapter 11
Table: 11.1
Mangos 3 10 1,000
Bananas 2 5 99
Apples 1 0 1
1
Read ‘¬’ as ‘not’.
2
For simplicity’s sake, we state these in terms of the strict preference relation. A more
general statement would use the ‘at least as good’ relation. The intuitive ideas are clearer
with strict preference.
Rational Choice Theory 221
lottery and receiving his middle option (y) for sure. So if such a lottery
is L(x,z), we can say that for Alf [L(x,z)]∼y.
6. Better Prizes. When Alf is confronted with two lotteries, L1 and L2,
which (i) have the same probabilities over outcomes (for example, 0.8
chance of the prize in the first position, and so 0.2 chance of the prize
in the second position), (ii) the second position has the same prize in
both L1 and L2, and (iii) in the first position, L1’s prize is preferred by
Alf to L2’s, Alf must prefer playing lottery L1 to lottery L2 (L1≻L2).
7. Better Chances. When Alf is confronted with two lotteries, L1 and L2,
where (i) L1 and L2 have the same prizes in both positions (x and y,
where x≻y) and (ii) L1 has a higher chance (say 0.8) of winning x than
L2 (say 0.6), Alf must prefer playing lottery L1 to lottery L2 (L1≻L2).
8. Reduction of Compound Lotteries. Alf’s preferences over compound
lotteries (where the prize of a lottery is another lottery) must be
reducible to a simple lottery between prizes. Thus the value of winning
a lottery as a prize can be entirely reduced to the chances of receiving
the prizes it offers – there is no additional preference simply for
winning lottery tickets (say, the thrill of lotteries).
If Alf’s preferences obey these axioms, we can derive a cardinal utility
function in the following manner, originally proposed by von Neumann
and Morgenstern (1944: ch. 3). Consider Alf’s ordinal utility function,
represented in Table 11.1. We take Alf’s most preferred option, x, and
assign it an arbitrary value, say 1. We then take Alf’s least preferred
option, z, and assign it an arbitrary value, say 0. We then take an option
in between (y) and compare Alf’s preference between that option and
a lottery between x and z. We manipulate the probability of the lottery
until Alf is indifferent between that lottery and the middling option under
consideration (the Continuity axiom guarantees there will be such lot-
tery). Suppose Alf is indifferent between y and a lottery with p = 0.6
chance of winning x and, so, a 1-p (0.4) chance of z (the probabilities in
the lottery must sum to 1). Because indifference obtains at this specific
probability, we assign a numerical value of 0.6 to the state of affairs in
which Alf receives y, a banana. Alf’s new cardinal utility function, repre-
senting how much more he prefers certain outcomes to others, is shown in
Table 11.2.
Just how we are to understand this information is disputed. On a very
strict interpretation, all we have found out is something about Alf’s
propensity to engage in certain sorts of risks; on a somewhat – but not
terribly – looser interpretation we have found out something about the
ratios of the differences between the utility of x, y, and z, which can be
further interpreted as information about the relative intensity of Alf’s
three preferences. It is important that our (1, 0.6, 0) utility scale is simply
222 Chapter 11
Table: 11.2
μ function
Mangos 1
Bananas 0.6
Apples 0
and beyond her control. As far as the chooser is concerned, she has a fixed
preference ordering and confronts a set of outcomes mapped onto a set of
actions correlated with those outcomes. This is opposed to strategic
choice, examined in the next section. We can understand decision theory
as the study of rational parametric choice, game theory the study of
rational strategic choice.
In the simplest case of rational choice, the individual is choosing
under certainty. Here Betty not only knows her orderings of outcomes
(x⊱y⊱z) – an assumption we make throughout – but also that she knows
with certainty that, say, action α produces x, action β produces y, and
action γ produces z. Given this, she has no problem ordering her action
options α⊱β⊱γ, and so as a rational utility maximizer she chooses α out of
the set of options (α, β, γ). But we do not always choose under certainty.
Sometimes we choose under risk. When we are choosing under risk, the
outcomes of our action options are not certain, but we do know the
probability of different outcomes resulting from our choice act. Suppose
Alf faces the option between action α (choosing covered fruit bowl A)
and β (covered fruit bowl B). Bowl A might contain a mango or it might
contain an apple – Alf does not know which. Bowl B might contain
a mango or it might contain a banana. Once again Alf does not know
which. Alf does know, however, that if bowl A is chosen, then there is
a 0.5 chance of getting a mango and a 0.5 chance of getting an apple. Alf
also knows that if bowl B is chosen, then there is a 0.25 chance of getting
a mango and a 0.75 chance of getting a banana. Because Alf knows the
probabilities that each action will produce different outcomes, Alf is
choosing under risk. How does a rational person choose in risky
situations?
In such situations, rational agents use an expected utility calculus. With
an expected utility calculus, agents multiply the probability an action that
will produce an outcome by the utility one assigns to that outcome.
We assume that Alf knows all the possible outcomes that each action
will produce. Suppose Alf has a von Neumann and Morgenstern cardinal
function over outcomes as depicted in Table 11.2. With this cardinal
utility function, Alf’s expected utility calculus goes like this:
α: choosing bowl A: 0.5(1) + 0.5(0) = 0.5
β: choosing bowl B: 0.25(1) + 0.75(0.6) = 0.7
Since the expected utility of α (choosing bowl A) is 0.5 and since the
expected utility of β (choosing bowl B) is 0.7, Alf chooses what is the best
prospect for maximizing his preferences, which is β. Notice that this
does not ensure that, in the end, he will have achieved the highest level of
preference satisfaction: if he did choose α and it turned out to have the
mango while β produced the banana, α would have given him the best
224 Chapter 11
Prize 1 Prize 2
L1 0 n
L2 1/n 1
Betty
Heads Tails
α β
Heads 1 –1
α –1 1
Alf Tails –1 1
β 1 –1
By convention, Row’s (Alf’s) payoffs are in the bottom left of each cell,
Column’s (Betty’s) in the upper right. Note that the gains and losses in every
cell equal 0; any gain must come from the other player, so we have a zero-
sum game. John von Neumann (1928) proved that all zero-sum games with
finite strategies have equilibrium solutions. That is, there is a rational course
of action in all such games. Relating back to decision under uncertainty in
parametric choice, the equilibrium solution for zero-sum games is to play
one’s maximin strategy – to maximize one’s minimum. If both players
maximize their minimums, then neither player can gain from unilaterally
changing her strategy. If we accept that the equilibrium solution concept
models rationality, then, when playing zero-sum games, it is rational to
maximin.
Though the theory of games was first developed in zero-sum form, it
was quickly realized that zero-sum games are of limited applicability for
understanding most strategic interactions. Rarely are we locked into total
conflict; we often find ourselves in situations where we are competing and
cooperating. Consider, for example, Luce and Raiffa’s (1957: 90–1)
politically incorrect ‘Battle of the Sexes’ game. In this game, Alf and
Betty wish to go out with each other on a Friday evening; the worst
thing for each would be to not go out together. However, Alf would prefer
a date at the prizefights, Betty at the ballet. Figure 11.3 gives an example
of the game, using cardinal utility.
So we have two players, Alf and Betty, and each has the same two ‘pure’
strategies, {Alf α, Alf β}, {Betty α, Betty β}. We suppose that each knows
the information set S: they know each other’s utilities and what strategies
are open to the other, each has knowledge of the other’s rationality, and
they know that each must choose without knowing what the other has
chosen. Moreover they each know S': each knows that the other knows all
the facts in S. And indeed they know S": each knows that the others know
all the facts in S'. The common knowledge assumption is assumed to be
iterative – we can go on with higher and higher levels, where each knows
what the facts were at the previous level.
228 Chapter 11
Betty
Go to Go to
Fights Ballet
α β
Go to 1 0
Alf Fights 2 0
α
Go to 0 2
Ballet 0 1
β
If Alf goes to the fights, then Betty, given her own preferences, will do
best by also going to the fights; if Betty goes to the ballet, Alf will do best
by also going to the ballet. Neither knows what the other is doing, but
they wish to coordinate. So this is a game of cooperation. Yet it is also
a game of conflict: they disagree about the best outcome. The central
concept in game theory is that of Nash equilibrium. We can think of the
Nash equilibrium as the solution to a game insofar as when two players
are playing their equilibrium strategies each has made his/her best
response to the move of the other player, and so neither player has any
incentive to unilaterally change his/her strategy. The strategic
interaction, we might say, can come to rest there. In the ‘Battle of the
Sexes’ game, there are two Nash equilibria in pure strategies: both play α
or both play β. Players can also play a ‘mixed strategy’, which is
a probability distribution over their pure strategies. In Figure 11.2’s
game, this would mean Alf would play α with a p probability and β
with a 1-p probability. This game has a Nash equilibrium in mixed
strategies in which Alf plays α with a probability of ⅔ (and so β with
a probability of ⅓) and Betty plays β with a probability of ⅔. At this
point, no adjustment to the probability that they play each of their pure
strategies will allow a player to unilaterally improve her expected
payoffs. John Nash (1950a, 1951), in a fundamental theorem of game
theory, showed that all games in cardinal utility with finite strategies
have at least one equilibrium (sometimes only a mixed equilibrium).
Note that this theorem, because it requires mixed strategies, depends on
the expected utility property.
We should note a more general solution concept, correlated equilibrium
(Aumann 1987), which includes the Nash solution. Its attractions are
manifest in the game of Chicken:
Rational Choice Theory 229
Chevy
Swerve Don’t
α Swerve
β
Swerve 5 10
Ford α 5 0
Don’t 0 –5
Swerve 10 –5
β
Suppose that every Saturday and Sunday, two teenagers, one driving
a Chevy and the other a Ford, drive toward each other with the pedal to
the metal, and the first one to swerve is ‘chicken’. So the options are
between swerving (α) and not swerving (β). The best result is to keep
driving straight while the other swerves: the other chickened; you didn’t.
If both swerve, neither crashes; if neither swerves, they crash. In this
game, the two ‘pure equilibria’ are (Ford α, Chevy β) and (Ford β;
Chevy α). There is a mixed Nash equilibrium where each swerves half
the time, but this has the unfortunate result that ¼ of the time they crash!
Now consider a game where we add a strategy: on Saturdays Chevy
swerves, on Sundays Ford swerves. The game will not be terribly exciting,
but they will never crash, and each will have an expected payoff of 5, as
good as one could do against a rational opponent. But note that we
seemed to have changed the game: we have expanded the strategy set to
include a correlating device (the day and the make of car).
At least in their simpler forms, Chicken and the ‘Battle of the Sexes’
raise problems when we understand strategic rational choice as requiring
agents to play their equilibrium strategies. For in these games there are
multiple equilibria. What, then, do rational players do? Which equilibrium
do they play? Unfortunately there is no definitive good answer. People
have tried many ways to select one equilibrium from multiple Nash
equilibria. The oldest way of solving the equilibrium selection problem
is to a priori theorize about what rationality requires when faced with
multiple equilibria. This is known as ‘equilibrium refinement’ and was
pursued to its fullest by John Harsanyi and Reinhard Selten (1988). Some
refinements seem plausible: for instance, if one equilibrium strictly dom-
inates another (i.e., is better for all parties), then perhaps that equilibrium
is more rational. At best, this is a rather limited refinement. As we
230 Chapter 11
Betty
Don’t Confess
Confess β
α
Don’t x 1
Confess x 0
Alf α
Confess 0 y
β 1 y
Where 1>x>y>0
settle on. The status of bargaining theory is unsettled. There are several
competing bargaining theories. Nash’s (1950b) bargaining solution has
the widest support. And Ariel Rubenstein (1982) appeared to put
cooperative bargaining theory on a firmer footing by clearly showing
how it can be derived from non-cooperative game theory. Yet Luce and
Raiffa’s (1957: 119–20) worry remains – that such bargaining solutions,
though intellectually interesting, do not seem to model what purely
rational players would select in actual bargains. And some worry that
the very axioms of bargaining theory go beyond rationality to include
some criteria of fairness (Thrasher 2014).
or that moral considerations never move them. These are matters about
the nature of the deliberation that determine a person’s rankings – they
concern the basis on which Alf determines whether state of affairs x is to
be ranked above y. As we have stressed, rational choice theory is not
committed to any account about the basis of rankings. Recall also that
preferences are not desires, but rankings of outcomes, which determine
preferences over actions. This is important. Many experimenters, for
example, believe that they have shown that people cooperate in
Prisoner’s Dilemmas. In experiments in which people are confronted
with situations that mimic Figure 11.5, where the payoffs are monetary
and players are awarded sums of money where the size of the monetary
payoffs is exactly correlated with the utility payoff schedule in
Figure 11.5, we can observe people cooperating – an action that, for all
players, is dominated by confessing. However, unless the players rank the
outcomes only in terms of their monetary payoffs – unless their prefer-
ences are only over amounts of money, and thus, for example, have no
concern with fairness or simply not being a jerk – we cannot say that the
players are actually in a Prisoner’s Dilemma interaction, so rational
choice theory does not predict that they will defect.
Nevertheless, even when we are more careful, there is dispute over
whether rational choice theory is a good predictor. Perhaps the most
comprehensive critique of rational choice theory as a predictive tool is
Ian Shapiro and Donald Green’s (1996) Pathologies of Rational Choice
Theory (see also Amadae 2015), though there have been equally
comprehensive defenses of rational choice theory as a predictive tool
(see, for instance, the debate in Friedman 1996). Rational choice theory
is a model of human action: like all models, we build a simplified world so
that we can better understand some salient dynamics, and get some
predictive leverage in some contexts. As Michael Wesiberg (2007)
notes: ‘[w]hen faced with . . . complexity, theorists can employ one of
several strategies: They can try to include as much complexity as possible
in their theoretical representations. They can make strategic decisions
about which aspects of a phenomenon can be legitimately excluded from
a representation. Or they can model, studying a complex phenomenon in
the real world by first constructing and then studying a model of the
phenomenon.’ These models abstract from the complexity of reality to
analyze the interactions among key elements. In some contexts, the
models may abstract from too much of the complexity to give adequate
understanding of the phenomena, but in other contexts they can be
enlightening and accurate. In social science, no model or theory explains
most of the variance of interestingly complex phenomena, but this does
not mean the model is without predictive and explanatory power.
Rational Choice Theory 233
And thus the importance of our opening quote from Rawls (1999a: 15):
‘The theory of justice is a part, perhaps the most significant part, of the
theory of rational choice.’
Rawls, however, insists that the choice of moral principles is not simply
governed by the ‘rational’, but also the ‘reasonable’ – a concern with fair
cooperation (1993: 48ff). One way to model this is to select principles
behind a veil of ignorance, in which parties have drastically restricted
information sets, including information as to who they are, and what their
utility functions look like (Harsanyi 1955; Gaus and Thrasher 2015).
This restriction on information forces parties to choose fairly: hence non-
tuistic parties, i.e., choosers only concerned with maximizing their own
goals, are forced (via ignorance) to consider how the goals of each fare,
since once the veil is lifted, one may end up being any of these people.
236 Chapter 11
Your next decision is: what are the actor’s information sets?
Do they know everything, or only a little? And if one is modeling
strategic interaction, one must decide if what the parties know is the same,
or if some parties know more than others. This latter difference can be
crucial, again for both normative and explanatory rational choice models.
On the normative side, we again turn to contractarianism. One common
assumption in bargaining theory is the assumption that parties are ‘sym-
metric’ – that they have the same strategies available to them, the same
bargaining ability, and, importantly, the same information sets. This
assumption was originally introduced by Nash (1950b), but is common
in many bargaining models, including Gauthier (1986). Yet as John
Thrasher (2014) shows, this assumption can often be at odds with the
contractarian project – it amounts to importing fairness criteria into the
terms of the bargain, when really what the contractarian is trying to do is
derive fairness criteria from the bargain itself. For the reason the symmetry
assumption is often introduced is because once we admit things like
asymmetric information sets into the bargain, the resulting distribution
might not be so intuitively attractive when compared to the symmetrical
case. And from an explanatory standpoint, Zachary Ernst (2005) force-
fully argues that many explanatory models of the evolution of conventions
and fairness norms obscure more than they reveal when they assume
symmetry across parties, of which symmetrical information sets is one
such part. These sorts of considerations are highly relevant when deter-
mining the information sets of the parties – symmetrical information
might be clean and easy, but possibly problematic.
If you decide that you are concerned with a strategic choice, you
will need to learn a bit of game theory. There are a number of good
introductory texts (e.g., Maschler, Solan, and Zamir 2013). Do not be
too quick to focus on a particular game before you have
determined the preferences and the information sets of the
parties. Games are defined by the preferences, information sets, and
strategies of the players. It is all too common for even postgraduate
students (and, alas, professors!) to get fascinated by a game such as the
Prisoner’s Dilemma or Chicken, and then to try to find ways to apply it,
often forcing a case or situation into an inappropriate game. Once one has
made the previous decisions on our list, one can fruitfully think about
game theoretic representations.
A last lesson: when using rational choice theory, especially in
normative contexts, it is critical to realize its limits. Often our
disputes are not about what a rational person would do, but about the
correct preferences to ascribe to people, or the conditions for fair
bargains. Understanding moral and political principles as an object
Rational Choice Theory 239
of choice among rational choosers can clarify their basis, but we must
be very careful not to reduce all these to disputes about rationality.
Even experts can believe that their dispute is about rationality, rather
than the proper content of an agent’s concerns. A good example of
this is the Rawls-Harsanyi debate. Harsanyi (1953, 1955) and Rawls
pursued very similar contract-based normative projects, reducing the
problem of moral justification to one of rational choice behind the veil
of ignorance. Contra Rawls, however, Harsanyi believed that rational
parties choosing behind a veil of ignorance would select average
utilitarianism rather than Rawls’s two principles of justice. At first
blush the dispute between Rawls and Harsanyi reduced to an argu-
ment about rational choice under uncertainty. Rawls thought rational
parties, when faced with radical uncertainty, ought to adopt the max-
imin decision rule. Harsanyi thought rational parties, when faced with
radical uncertainty, ought to adopt the Laplacean principle of
indifference. The debate continued after both parties published their
seminal social contract contributions. Harsanyi (1974) continued to
point out the irrationality of the maximin decision rule, while Rawls
(1999b: 225–31) continued defending it.
Recent analysis of the Rawls-Harsanyi dispute, though, suggests that
the disagreement between the two cannot merely be reduced to a debate
about rational choice. Michael Moehler (2013) argues that Rawls’s and
Harsanyi’s disagreement over what rationality requires itself reduces to
a philosophical dispute about which moral values should be modeled in
the choice situation, and thus which moral values are important. Rawls
wanted to model impartiality in the original position. Harsanyi was
especially concerned with modeling impersonality. While impartiality
merely requires that agents do not unjustifiably favor their own interests
in making decisions, impersonality requires agents to make decisions only
on the basis of the common interest. This inclusion of impersonality,
which Rawls (1999a: 24) rejected, required Harsanyi to use the Laplacean
principle of indifference. And as Rawls (2001: 97–100) notes later on, the
use of maximin reasoning in the original position ultimately comes down
to a moral, not a rational choice. The putative debate between Rawls and
Harsanyi over the nature of rational choice theory reduces to
a disagreement over what is to be valued – impartiality versus imperson-
ality. This is an object lesson. Rational choice theory by no means
replaces philosophical analysis. Remember always that it is a tool,
and like all tools, is effective only when it is used to perform its
proper tasks in its proper ways.
240 Chapter 11
References
Amadae, S. M., 2015. Prisoners of Reason: Game Theory and Neoliberal Political
Economy. Cambridge University Press.
Aumann, Robert, 1987. ‘Correlated equilibrium as an expression of Bayesian
rationality’, Econometrica 55: 1–18.
Binmore, Ken, 2005. Natural Justice. Oxford University Press.
Binmore, Ken, 2009. Rational Decisions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Bosman, Ronald, Matthias Sutter, and Frans van Winden, 2005. ‘The impact of
real effort and emotions in the power-to-take game’, Journal of Economic
Psychology 26, 407–29.
Buchanan, James and Gordon Tullock, 2004. The Calculus of Consent: The Logical
Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Chung, Hun, 2015. ‘Hobbes’s state of nature: a modern Bayesian game-theoretic
analysis’, Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1, 485–508.
Ernst, Zachary, 2005. ‘A plea for asymmetric games’, Journal of Philosophy 102:
109–25.
Friedman, Jeffrey, ed., 1996. The Rational Choice Controversy: Economic Models of
Politics Reconsidered. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Gaus, Gerald, 2011. The Order of Public Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Gaus, Gerald and John Thrasher, 2015. ‘Rational choice and the original position:
the (many) models of Rawls and Harsanyi’, in Timothy Hinton, ed., The Original
Position. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 39–58.
Gauthier, David, 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Gauthier, David, 1991. ‘Why contractarianism?’, in Peter Vallentyne, ed.,
Contractarianism and Rational Choice. Cambridge University Press, 15–30.
Gintis, Herbert, 2009. The Bounds of Reasons: Game Theory and the Unification of the
Behavioral Sciences. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hamilton, W. D., 1964. ‘The genetical evolution of social behaviour I’, Journal of
Theoretical Biology, 7: 1–16.
Hampton, Jean, 1986. Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge
University Press.
Harsanyi, John, 1953. ‘Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of
risk-taking’, Journal of Political Economy 61: 434–5.
Harsanyi, John, 1955. ‘Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics and interpersonal
comparisons of utility’, Journal of Political Economy 63: 309–21.
Harsanyi, John, 1974. ‘Can the maximin principle serve as the basis for morality?’,
American Political Science Review 69: 594–606.
Harsanyi, John and Reinhard Selten, 1988. A General Theory of Equilibrium
Selection in Games. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hobbes, Thomas, 1994. Leviathan, ed. Edwin Curley. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett
Publishing.
Hubin, Donald, 1991. ‘Non-tuism’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21: 441–68.
Rational Choice Theory 241
Kalai, Ehud and Meir Smorodinsky, 1975. ‘Other solutions to Nash’s bargaining
problem’, Econometrica 43: 513–18.
Kliemt, Hartmut, 2009. Philosophy and Economics I: Methods and Models. Munich:
Oldenbourg.
Luce, Duncan and Howard Raiffa, 1957. Games and Decisions. New York: Dover
Publications.
Maschler, Michael, Eilon Solan, and Shmuel Zamir, 2013. Game Theory.
Cambridge University Press.
Moehler, Michael, 2013. ‘Contractarian ethics and Harsanyi’s two justifications of
utilitarianism’, Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 12: 24–47.
Nash, John, 1950a. ‘Equilibrium points in n-person games’, Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 36: 48–49.
Nash, John, 1950b. ‘The bargaining problem’, Econometrica 18: 155–62.
Nash, John, 1951. ‘Non-cooperative games’, Annals of Mathematics 54: 286–95.
Plamenatz, John, 1973. Democracy and Illusion. London: Longman.
Plott, Charles, 1996. ‘Rational choice in experimental markets’, in Robin Hogarth
and Melvin Reder, eds., Rational Choice: The Contrast between Economics and
Psychology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 117–43.
Rawls, John, 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls, John, 1999a. A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John, 1999b. Collected Papers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John, 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Rosenberg, Alexander, 1995. Philosophy of Social Science, 2nd edition. Boulder,
CO: Westview.
Rubinstein, Ariel, 1982. ‘Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model’, Econometrica
50, 97–110.
Schelling, Thomas, 1960. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Schwartz, Norbert, 2002. ‘Feelings as information: moods influence judgments
and processing strategies’, in Thomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin, and
Daniel Kahneman, eds., Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive
Judgments. Cambridge University Press, 534–47.
Sen, Amartya, 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Shapiro, Ian and Donald Green, 1996. Pathologies of Rational Choice: A Critique of
Applications in Political Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Skyrms, Brian, 1996. Evolution of the Social Contract. Cambridge University Press.
Skyrms, Brian, 2004. The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure.
Cambridge University Press.
Smith, John Maynard, 1975. The Theory of Evolution, 3rd edition. New York:
Penguin.
Smith, Vernon, 2002. Bargaining and Market Behavior: Essays in Experimental
Economics. Cambridge University Press.
242 Chapter 11
Sugden, Robert, 1986. The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Thrasher, John, 2014. ‘Uniqueness and symmetry in bargaining theories of
justice’, Philosophical Studies 167: 683–99.
Thrasher, John and Gerald Gaus, forthcoming. ‘James Buchanan and Gordon
Tullock, Calculus of Consent’, in Jacob Levy, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Classics
in Contemporary Political Theory. Oxford University Press.
Trivers, Robert, 1971. ‘The evolution of reciprocal altruism’, The Quarterly Review
of Biology 66: 35–57.
Vanderschraaf, Peter, 2006. ‘War or peace? A dynamical analysis of anarchy’,
Economics and Philosophy 22: 243–79.
von Neumann, John, 1928. ‘Zur Theorie der Gesellschaftsspiele’, Mathematische
Annalen 100: 295–320.
von Neumann, John and Oscar Morgenstern, 1944. The Theory of Games and
Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Weisberg, Michael, 2007. ‘Who is a modeler?’, British Journal for Philosophy of
Science 58, 207–33.
12 Interpreting Texts
Adrian Blau
243
244 Chapter 12
one to find the other. That fundamental point has not, I believe, been
made in previous methodological discussions.
Equally unfortunately, most methodological writings give the wrong
impression by talking about different ‘approaches’ or ‘schools of thought’,
like contextualism, Straussianism, Marxism and so on. These categories
have some value, and I cover them later. But mental categories can limit
our thoughts and actions, and I believe this has happened here: most
commentators imply that these categories are very different without add-
ing that there are principles of good interpretation that apply to all of us
(see especially Pocock 1971: 6–11; Rorty 1984: 49; Dunn 1996: 19; Ball
2004: 19; Richter 2009: 7–11; Schulz and Weiss 2010: 284–8). Despite
some marked differences in our interpretive aims, there is or should be
much overlap in our interpretive methods. Silence about these core
principles has not prevented excellent interpretations, but has permitted
more dubious scholarship than otherwise.
This chapter’s main aim is to make explicit these core principles of
good interpretation. You will find relevant principles in every section of
this chapter, even in sections you might think do not apply to you.
Three brief caveats. First, my examples are mostly historical, but the
principles also fit contemporary texts. Second, my examples mainly come
from well-known Western authors, like Machiavelli and Rousseau, but
the principles also apply to less well-known Western authors, and to
authors in other cultures. (See also the chapters in this volume by
Leader Maynard on ideological analysis, and by Ackerly and Bajpai on
comparative political thought.) Third, and most important, although
I cover both empirical interpretation (e.g. what Locke meant by ‘prop-
erty’) and philosophical interpretation (e.g. how well Locke’s defence of
property works), and although I link the two more than other commenta-
tors do, most of my how-to guidance involves empirical interpretation,
including using philosophical interpretation as part of empirical
interpretation. Other chapters in this volume will help more for readers
primarily interested in philosophical interpretation in itself (especially the
chapters by Knight on reflective equilibrium, and Brownlee and
Stemplowska on thought experiments). But you should still read this
chapter to the extent that you want to get historical or contemporary
authors right. And Olsthoorn’s chapter (especially Section 6) will help for
both empirical and philosophical interpretation.
Section 2 summarizes contextualism: despite its crucially important
focus on history and context, there are other secrets to contextualists’
success, and pitfalls we must all beware. Section 3 addresses
Begriffsgeschichte, conceptual history and genealogy, which combine tex-
tual and/or contextual analysis with conceptual comparison. Section 4,
Interpreting Texts 245
2 Contextualism
Contextualism is often called the ‘Cambridge School’ approach, albeit
misleadingly (Skinner 2012: 16–17). Contextualism has dominated
methodological debates about textual interpretation for half a century.
And contextualists have essentially won the battle, both through their
theoretical arguments and the high quality of actual contextual research.
Although their theoretical arguments sometimes remain controversial,
the core idea is widely accepted: place texts in their historical contexts.
Even scholars who do not themselves do historical research usually
consult such publications, to make misinterpretation less likely.
Contextualism has a long history (e.g. Allen 1928: xvii–xx), but started
its upsurge in the late 1940s and flowered in the 1960s, with the theore-
tical ideas and substantive interpretations of writers like Peter Laslett,
John Pocock, Quentin Skinner and John Dunn (Pocock 2006: 37–9).
Given diversity within and between these writers and their followers
(Boucher 1985: 151–272; Skinner 2012: 16–17), I focus mainly on
Skinner, who I see as the supreme methodologist in our field. I have
learned much from his methodological writings, but even more from his
substantive interpretations, which I find methodologically richer and
more impressive. By contrast, Mark Bevir only tackles Skinner’s metho-
dological writings (1999: 40–50, 327) and thus overlooks some of
Skinner’s most important methodological lessons (see also Stuurman
2000: 319; Skinner 2002a: 178–9). Treating Skinner as a practitioner,
not just a theorist, lets me sidestep his speech-act theorizing, which is
essentially separate to contextual analysis (Hutton 2014: 927), and which
I address elsewhere.1
1
Adrian Blau, ‘Extended meaning and understanding in the history of ideas’ (working
paper, 2016).
246 Chapter 12
Although Skinner does not say so, and although most commentators
emphasize his contextualism, the foundation of Skinner’s success is
actually close textual analysis. Indeed, he has taught history of political
thought to graduate students like this, such as eight weeks of close reading
of Leviathan in Cambridge. The first principle of contextualism, and all
sensible interpretation, is thus: read texts carefully.
This requires us to read passages in their textual contexts.
Consider Hobbes’s comment that ‘the Thoughts, are to the Desires, as
Scouts, and Spies, to range abroad, and find the way to the things desired’
(Hobbes 1991: 8.16, 53). Although this does not mention ‘reason’, many
scholars seem to equate ‘thoughts’ and ‘reason’, and treat Hobbes as
implying that reason is instrumental to the passions, or even the slave of
the passions. But in the context of the chapter as a whole, this comment is
surely not about reason: Hobbes is merely saying that our thoughts jump
to what we desire. If I like baseball and see a big stick, my mind might
think: ‘could I hit a baseball with that?’ (Blau 2016: 201–2).
We cannot always read much of an author’s output: inevitably, we
sometimes dip in, especially for authors who are not central to our
work. Being corrected on such grounds is an occupational hazard. But
ideally, we should read an author’s texts widely, to avoid overlooking
important passages elsewhere in the text and in other texts. Book 2
chapter 3 of Rousseau’s Social Contract makes more sense alongside
book 4 chapter 1, casting light on how Rousseau may have understood
the general will (which is not to say that this is what Rousseau had in
mind). ‘Non-political’ texts might also be relevant: Rousseau’s Emile,
ostensibly about education, might also be read into these passages (e.g.
Rousseau 1979a: book 4, p. 286): perhaps morally pure people can look
inside themselves and intuit the general will. That said, the draft of the
Social Contract implies that intuitionism is inappropriate in modern
society (Rousseau 1997a: 1.2.6–14, 154–7). Yet the exclusion of these
passages from the final version must give us pause for thought. You never
know when to read different ideas/texts into each other and when
they are not consistent. Consider different options.
Textual analysis alone is never enough: a key contextualist contribution
is to place texts in their linguistic contexts by reading other texts
from the similar time/place, or by reading the work of scholars
who have done this. This can let us understand words we no longer use,
like dehort (dissuade). It helps us spot ‘false friends’ – words that look
familiar but whose meanings once differed, like prejudice (pre-judgement,
not bias), or force, which in eighteenth-century French had a sense of
strength/energy that might not be recoverable from merely textual
analysis of Rousseau’s ‘forced to be free’ (Mason 1995: 135–6).
Interpreting Texts 247
or language (e.g. Skinner 2009: 325). You may need to consider words
not used, as well as words used, as with Josiah Ober’s analysis of
‘democracy’ and similar terms in ancient Greece (2008: 5, 7). And
distinguish the word from the idea (see Olsthoorn’s chapter in this
volume, Section 2.1).
The primarily conceptual part of the analysis involves conceptual
comparison: we stand back and compare authors’ understandings, e.g.
asking how similarly Bentham and Mill saw ‘utility’. Careful
conceptual analysis is vital, as with Skinner’s fine-grained genealogy
of liberty (2003: 22). By contrast, Isaiah Berlin’s (1969) confused and
confusing conceptual analysis undermines his conceptual history of
liberty (for a critique, see Cohen 1960). Conceptual history is not
just history: it is also conceptual – philosophical. Olsthoorn’s chapter
in this volume has many other tips to help rigorous conceptual analysis
in conceptual history.
Anachronistic conceptualizations may help, especially when com-
paring authors who used different terms. Anachronism is dangerous: it
can infect our efforts to recover authors’ meanings (Skinner 2002a:
49–51). For example, James Mill’s ‘middle rank’ does not mean
‘middle class’ (Ball 1992: xx–xxi). But if handled carefully, using
appropriately fine-grained distinctions, and preferably not until you
have first recovered authors’ meanings, anachronism lets us apply
conceptual frameworks that usefully highlight similarities and
differences between authors. For example, Rousseau’s Considerations
on the Government of Poland recommends that citizens elect deputies
every six weeks, on an explicit set of instructions, divergence from
which would see deputies being executed (Rousseau 1997b: 7.14–19,
201–3). This is an extreme example of the so-called mandate or
delegate conception of representation (Pitkin 1967: 145–7).
Rousseau did not use these terms: he even denies that this is ‘repre-
sentation’ (1997a: 3.15.5–6, 114). But what he says amounts to how
we use these terms. If we are to compare notions of representation
over time, we will almost certainly have to apply such anachronisms.
So, first try to work out what authors meant, then see how well
this fits your own conceptualization or an existing one.
Conceptual history is interesting and important, not only histori-
cally and politically, but also normatively: we see why some
conceptions won out, how new and old conceptions often differ, and
how old conceptions might revive contemporary discussions, as with
Skinner’s revealing conceptual histories of freedom and the state
(Skinner 2003, 2009). Be attentive to the normative implications
of your interpretations.
Interpreting Texts 251
4 Reconstruction
Reconstruction means testing and potentially supplying, supplementing,
modifying or removing presuppositions, definitions, links between com-
ments/ideas and steps in arguments, as with Skinner’s analysis of Hobbes
on representation (2002b: 177–208), John Gray’s account of Mill on
happiness (1996: 70–85) and A. J. Simmons’s testing of Locke’s moral
theory (1992: 14–67). Note that these scholars are, respectively,
a historian, a political theorist and a philosopher.
Reconstruction is often seen as a special, philosophical technique (e.g.
Rorty 1984: 49–53), but everyone reconstructs, simply to understand
what is said or written. Some degree and some kind of reconstruction
are inseparable from the very nature of interpretation, and necessary to
the understanding of our texts. Again, compartmentalizing approaches
into different categories has led us to overlook key unifying ideas.
Simplifying somewhat, I distinguish between three kinds of
reconstruction:
(a) empirical reconstruction – trying to work out what authors meant;
(b) systematic reconstruction – linking authors’ ideas, making implicit
distinctions explicit, assessing consistency and so on, whether or not
authors themselves saw these things;
(c) adaptive reconstruction – altering what authors wrote and perhaps
what they intended.
These are not alternatives. We almost always do all three simultaneously,
to greater or lesser extents. Even the simplest empirical reconstructions
add, subtract or amend words. Even the most extreme adaptive recon-
structions make some assumptions about what authors meant. And we
typically interpret authors with some kind of systematic reconstruction,
e.g. reading one idea into another even when the author does not specify
a link. (Strictly speaking, systematic reconstruction is not a separate
category, but a mix of empirical and adaptive reconstruction where we
might be agnostic about the extent to which authors were conscious of the
systematization we offer.)
Some historians, including Skinner (1964), worry about systematic
and adaptive reconstruction. My point is that we cannot avoid doing
either, so we should learn to do them well – as, indeed, with Skinner’s
virtuoso systematic reconstruction of Hobbes’s views on the state and
representation (2002b: 177–208), including carefully worded adapta-
tions of Hobbes’s views (2002c: 190; see likewise 2002b: 217, 235).
A key message of this section, and of this chapter, is thus that thinking
philosophically helps us reconstruct what authors meant, even if some
scholars baulk at altering or ‘improving’ the authors they study.
252 Chapter 12
I will start with the most minimal kinds of reconstruction that we all do,
every day. All communication involves resolving ambiguities and filling in
gaps: we cannot say everything we want to say (Searle 1978). If you ask,
‘Did you have a good day?’, you presumably mean, ‘Did you have a
good day [today]?’, not, ‘Did you have a good day [five weeks after you
were born]?’. Likewise, when Sidgwick (1981: ix) writes that he has made
‘numerous alterations and additions’ in preparing the second edition of
The Methods of Ethics, he presumably means ‘numerous alterations and
additions [to this book]’, not ‘numerous alterations and additions [to my
trousers]’, even though that is logically consistent with what he wrote, and
might have been a better use of his time.
During conversations, our brains reconstruct such comments in a flash.
When we read, the process is often slower and more conscious. For
example, Mill writes: ‘As it is useful that while mankind are imperfect
there should be different opinions, so is it that there should be different
experiments of living’ (1989: 3.1, p. 57). Is Mill commending experi-
ments of living only while mankind is imperfect, or even once perfected?
The latter, it turns out, fits better with what Mill later says about indivi-
duality and self-development. Of course, ‘fits better’ does not signify that
he meant this, or even that he was clear in his own head. We can easily
over-interpret authors and make them more consistent than they were: no
author is fully consistent (Skinner 2002a: 67–72). But thinking through
the implications of ideas, and probing their consistency with other
things they said or implied, gives us evidence about what authors
might have meant. Contextual analysis is all well and good – and it is
very, very good – but it goes hand in hand with more philosophical
analysis, even merely of the kind that probes consistency.
Another use of consistency involves testing authors’ definitions, or
testing possible definitions where authors do not provide them. For
example, Machiavelli never defines virtú, and contextual analysis only
tells us what Machiavelli was reacting against, not how he understood the
term. It takes a more philosophical cast of mind to stand back from
the text and reconstruct what Machiavelli means when he discusses
virtú: he generally means ‘those qualities, whether moral or
otherwise . . . most conducive to military and political success’ (Skinner
2002a: 48).
This is not to imply that a single notion must fit a term. C. G. Prado
(2006: 81–103) finds five kinds of truth in Foucault’s many writings.
It does not really matter how aware Foucault was of this: these ideas are
there, and we understand Foucault better by systematizing his comments
more neatly. Indeed, we should do this even if Foucault emphatically
insisted that he only had one notion of truth. We never fully control what
Interpreting Texts 253
we say or write. Mill’s ‘one very simple principle’ (1989: 1.9, 13) turns out
to be neither one nor very simple. We understand Mill better by distin-
guishing between what he says he will do, and what he does do. We should
be careful about taking authors at face value: to say that we must
recover authors’ motives in order to understand what they mean (Skinner
2002a: 103–7) should not mean that we are bound by those intentions
(Skinner 2002a: 110–11).
A more complex example involves an apparent error in On Liberty. Mill
emphatically argues that you can do as you like, even harm yourself or
cause offence, provided you do not harm others (especially 1989: 1.9, 13;
2.44, 54–5). But suddenly Mill says, briefly and without justification, that
you cannot do self-harming things in public if they cause offence (1989:
5.7, 98). This seems like an astonishing about-turn. To understand what
actions Mill thought permissible, we must think through these passages
and see if this apparent contradiction is resolvable. This could imply
a different notion of harm or offence than we had assumed, potentially
entailing a significant reinterpretation. If we cannot find such
a resolution, we might want to disregard this passing comment (as
recommended by Gray 1996: 102). We might still explain why Mill
wrote it, e.g. to protect himself from objections of libertinism, but we
risk misunderstanding Mill if we treat this apparently incidental passage
as his considered view of harm. When you find an apparent contra-
diction, consider how (if at all) to resolve it – including the possi-
bility that it is not a contradiction at all.
A still more complex example involves Hobbes’s ambiguous references
in De Cive to ‘the dictates of right reason’ (1998: e.g. 2.2, 34; 15.4, 173).
Does he mean that reason forces our passions to obey, or merely that it
tells us what we should do even if our passions then disregard this? Or has
he not fully thought this issue through? (See Blau 2016.)
In effect, simply to understand one phrase we may need to reconstruct
Hobbes’s account of reason, the passions, deliberation and their
interconnections – quite an enterprise. It is thus problematic that con-
textualists encourage us to place texts in their contexts without addressing
the value of thinking through texts philosophically. Both matter.
This example actually has two even trickier dimensions. First, although
Hobbes’s other writings might help us interpret these comments in De
Cive, his account of reason might have changed over time (Skinner 1996:
298–437). Understanding the De Cive passages may involve tackling this
much bigger issue. Second, and even worse, our judgement of the change-
over-time thesis itself rests partly on how we read the comments about
reason and the passions in De Cive and elsewhere. In other words, the
thesis that informs our interpretation of individual comments itself
254 Chapter 12
Careful readers will note that this section has not yet mentioned Leo
Strauss. Those who have read between the lines may already see what
I now state explicitly: we should not equate ‘esoteric’ and ‘Straussian’
interpretation. From the 1940s on, Leo Strauss and his followers made
esoteric interpretations of writers like Plato, Machiavelli, Rousseau and
Nietzsche. There is nothing wrong with esoteric interpretation, but much
wrong with Strauss’s esoteric interpretation – due not to its esotericism,
but to its naive and flawed methodology (Blau 2012; see also Blau 2015b
for some corrections to the original argument).
Unfortunately, our methodological lexicon has clouded the real
problems. We should not say that Strauss has a different hermeneutic
or particular techniques of reading texts. Rather, he has hypotheses
about the particular ways that authors hid messages, and inadequate
tests of these hypotheses (Blau 2015b: 32–40). Fortunately, Melzer’s
wonderful practical advice (2014: 288–99, 323–4) warns Straussians
not to infer esotericism too hastily. Unfortunately, Melzer’s own
handling of claims about esotericism may still encourage such hasti-
ness (Blau 2015a: 162–3).
The excesses of Straussian readings have helped and hindered the
cause of esoteric interpretation. They have helped it by highlighting
a largely forgotten kind of writing and offering evidence of esoteric
techniques. But they have hindered it through methodologically flawed
over-interpretations that have given esoteric interpretation a bad name –
‘Straussian’. Esoteric interpretation, like any empirical interpreta-
tion, is only a hypothesis. And the failure to provide fundamental
principles for testing hypotheses, through a flawed focus on supposedly
separate approaches, is one of the great tragedies of twentieth-century
methodological writings. Readers should not think that my critiques of
Straussians are aimed only at Straussians.
8 Conclusion
This chapter’s key guidance can be summarized as follows: Read widely
and carefully. Think contextually and philosophically. Embrace
uncertainty. See both sides. Think against yourself. Question
evidence and interpretations. Test. Retest. Be open. And be open-
minded. Such how-to guidance – sometimes obvious, sometimes not – is
largely absent from the existing methodological literature, because of the
tendency to discuss different approaches and schools of thought without
also emphasizing core principles of good interpretation. I do not mean to
deride our methodological literature, and would especially encourage
novice interpreters to pore over Skinner’s methodological writings – but
also his substantive interpretations. My final suggestion is thus: see
Interpreting Texts 265
Acknowledgements
For comments and criticisms on earlier versions of this chapter, I thank
Seebal Aboudounya, Richard Bourke, Emillie De Keulenaar, Robin
Douglass, John-Erik Hansson, Eva Hausteiner, Johan Olsthoorn,
Joanne Paul, Mustafa Rehman, Paul Sagar, Dave Schmidtz, Max
Skjönsberg, Bertie Vidgen and Sarah Wilford.
References
Allen, J. W., 1928. A History of Political Thought in the Sixteenth Century. London:
Methuen.
Armitage, David, 2013. Foundations of Modern International Thought. Cambridge
University Press.
Ball, Terence, 1992. ‘Introduction’, in James Mill, Political Writings, ed.
Terence Ball. Cambridge University Press, ix–xxviii.
Ball, Terence, 2004. ‘History and the interpretation of texts’, in Gerald Gaus and
Chandran Kukathas, eds., Handbook of Political Theory. London: Sage
Publications, 18–30.
Ball, Terence, 2011. ‘The value of the history of political philosophy’, in
George Klosko, ed., The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy.
Oxford University Press, 47–59.
Ball, Terence, James Farr and Russell Hanson, eds., 1989. Political Innovation and
Conceptual Change. Cambridge University Press.
Berlin, Isaiah. 1969. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University Press.
Bernasconi, Robert, 2003. ‘Will the real Kant please stand up: the challenge of
Enlightenment racism to the study of the history of philosophy’, Radical
Philosophy 117, 13–22.
Bernasconi, Robert, 2010. ‘The philosophy of race in the nineteenth century’, in
Dean Moyar, ed., The Routledge Companion to Nineteenth Century Philosophy.
London: Routledge. 498–521.
Bevir, Mark, 1999. The Logic of the History of Ideas. Cambridge University Press.
Blau, Adrian, 2009. ‘Hobbes on corruption’, History of Political Thought 30,
596–616.
Blau, Adrian, 2011. ‘Uncertainty and the history of ideas’, History and Theory 50,
358–72.
Blau, Adrian, 2012. ‘Anti-Strauss’, The Journal of Politics 74, 142–55.
Blau, Adrian, 2015a. ‘Philosophy between the lines, or through dubious signs?’,
Perspectives on Political Science 44, 162–5.
266 Chapter 12
Pocock, J. G. A., 1971. Politics, Language, and Time: Essays on Political Thought and
History. New York: Atheneum.
Pocock, J. G. A., 2006. ‘Foundations and moments’, in Annabel Brett and
James Tully, eds., Rethinking the Foundations of Modern Political Thought.
Cambridge University Press, 37–49.
Prado, C. G., 2006. Searle and Foucault on Truth. Cambridge University Press.
Rawls, John, 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Reeve, C. D. C., 1988. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato’s Republic.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Richter, Melvin, 1995. The History of Political and Social Concepts: A Critical
Introduction. Oxford University Press.
Richter, William, 2009. ‘Introduction: the study of political thought’, in
William Richter, ed., Approaches to Political Thought. Lanham, MD: Rowman
& Littlefield, 1–12.
Rorty, Richard, 1984. ‘The historiography of philosophy: four genres’, in
Richard Rorty, J. B. Schneewind and Quentin Skinner, eds., Philosophy in
History: Essays on the Historiography of Philosophy. Cambridge University Press,
49–75.
Rosenblatt, Helena, 1997. Rousseau and Geneva: From ‘the First Discourse to
The Social Contract, 1749–1762. Cambridge University Press.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1979. Emile or on Education, ed. Allan Bloom. New York:
Basic Books.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1997a. ‘ The Social Contract,’ in The Social Contract and
Other Later Political Writings, ed. Victor Gourevitch. Cambridge University
Press.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1997b. ‘Considerations on the Government of Poland’,
in The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings, ed. Victor Gourevitch.
Cambridge University Press.
Sapiro, Virginia, 1992. A Vindication of Political Virtue: The Political Theory of Mary
Wollstonecraft. University of Chicago Press.
Schotte, Dietrich, 2015. ‘The virtues and vices of Leo Strauss, historian.
A reassessment of Straussian hermeneutics’, in Winfried Schröder, ed.,
Reading Between the Lines: Leo Strauss and the History of Early Modern
Philosophy. Berlin: De Gruyter, 57–76.
Schulz, Daniel and Alexander Weiss, 2010. ‘Introduction: approaches in the
history of political thought’, European Political Science 9, 283–90.
Searle, John, 1978. ‘Literal meaning’, Erkenntnis 13, 207–24.
Sidgwick, Henry, 1981. The Methods of Ethics. Seventh edition. Indianapolis, IN:
Hackett.
Simmons, A. John, 1992. The Lockean Theory of Rights. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Skinner, Quentin, 1964. ‘Hobbes’s “Leviathan”’, The Historical Journal 7, 321–33.
Skinner, Quentin, 1981. Machiavelli. Oxford University Press.
Skinner, Quentin, 1989. ‘The state’, in Terence Ball, James Farr and
Russell Hanson, eds., Political Innovation and Conceptual Change. Cambridge
University Press, 90–131.
Interpreting Texts 269
Skinner, Quentin, 1990. ‘The republican ideal of political liberty’, in Gisela Bock,
Quentin Skinner and Maurizio Viroli, eds., Machiavelli and Republicanism.
Cambridge University Press, 293–309.
Skinner, Quentin, 1996. Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Cambridge
University Press.
Skinner, Quentin, 2002a. Visions of Politics. Volume I: Regarding Method.
Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Quentin, 2002b. Visions of Politics. Volume III: Hobbes and Civil Science.
Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Quentin, 2002c. ‘Interview with Quentin Skinner’, Finnish Yearbook of
Political Thought 6, 32–63.
Skinner, Quentin, 2003. ‘States and the freedom of citizens’, in Quentin Skinner
and Bo Stråth, eds., States and Citizens: History, Theory, Prospects. Cambridge
University Press, 11–27.
Skinner, Quentin, 2008. Hobbes and Republican Liberty. Cambridge University
Press.
Skinner, Quentin, 2009. ‘A genealogy of the modern state’, Proceedings of the British
Academy 162, 325–70.
Skinner, Quentin, 2012. ‘On politics and history: a discussion with Quentin
Skinner’, Journal of Intellectual History and Political Thought 1, 7–31.
Sreenivasan, Gopal, 2000. ‘What is the General Will?’, The Philosophical Review
109, 545–81.
Stuurman, Siep, 2000. ‘On intellectual innovation and the methodology of the
history of ideas’, Rethinking History 4, 311–19.
Svacek, Victor, 1976. ‘The elusive Marxism of C. B. Macpherson’, Canadian
Journal of Political Science 9, 395–422.
Townshend, Jules, 1999. ‘Hobbes as possessive individualist: interrogating the
C. B. Macpherson thesis’, Hobbes Studies 12, 52–72.
Tuck, Richard, 1993. Philosophy and Government 1572–1651. Cambridge
University Press.
Tully, James, 1995. ‘Property, self-government and consent’, Canadian Journal of
Political Science 28, 105–32.
Van Evera, Stephen, 1997. Guide to Methods for Students of Political Science. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
Waldron, Jeremy, 2002. God, Locke, and Equality. Christian Foundations of John
Locke’s Political Thought. Cambridge University Press.
Whatmore, Richard, 2006. ‘Intellectual history and the history of political
thought’, in Richard Whatmore and Brian Young, eds., Palgrave Advances in
Intellectual History. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 109–29.
Wolff, Jonathan, 2013. ‘Analytic political philosophy’, in Michael Beaney, ed.,
The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University
Press, 795–822.
Wootton, David, 1992. ‘The Levellers’, in John Dunn, ed., Democracy:
The Unfinished Journey. Oxford University Press, 71–89.
Zagorin, Perez, 1993. ‘Hobbes’s Early Philosophical Development’, Journal of the
History of Ideas 54:3, 505–18.
13 Comparative Political Thought
1 Introduction
Two features characterize the emerging field of comparative political
thought (CPT). The first is an interest in bringing Islamic, Indian,
Chinese, African and Latin American ethical-political thought to the
attention of Western audiences. The second is an interest in combining
the methods of political theorists with those of historians, political
scientists and anthropologists to enhance real-world relevance of political
theory. This chapter provides an overview of normative-analytic, histor-
ical, interpretive and critical approaches to CPT with examples of var-
iants within each category. It argues for a methodology-based definition
of CPT, and for a non-hierarchical pluralism in which multiple vocations
of political theory prevail. Recognizing the complexity of questions raised
by the topic of methods in political theory generally, our aims in this
chapter are first to provide an introduction to CPT, second to provide
a schematic of the four methodological strands within CPT and finally to
highlight the range of methods useful for CPT research, and, where these
have something in common with other practices of political theory, to
elaborate on how they are used in CPT. To underline, this is an argument
about the variety of methodologies and methods in CPT scholarship and
an appreciation of the value of this methodological pluralism for the field
overall.
Political theorists have been comparing across time, authors and con-
texts since the field began. In the twenty-first century, given the contribu-
tions of post-colonial, feminist and queer scholars, we would expect most
political theorists to attempt to be self-aware regarding the parochialism
and historical elitism of some political theory. However, today, the phrase
‘comparative political thought’ indicates to an Anglophone audience
a way to teach and practise political theory that is less Western-centric.
Obviously, non-Western-centric approaches to political thought have
long featured in teaching and writing in Asia, Africa, the Middle East
and Latin America. Today, the phrase ‘comparative political thought’ is
270
Comparative Political Thought 271
Or, does CPT require engagement with contemporary scholars who have
training, experience and imaginations developed in multiple traditions?
As all of these questions suggest, many scholars today feel the need to
broaden the tool-kit of political theory to include not only new languages,
but also new ways of thinking about the historical epistemology of con-
cepts. These are questions about methods.
CPT scholars use a range of methods and answer these questions
differently. Methods choices depend on the researcher’s ontology,
epistemology and methodology. Ontology is the worldview that deter-
mines what the theorist finds to be an interesting question; epistemology
is the theoretical distinction between fact and opinion and is behind
a theorist’s choice of methodology; methodology is the theory of how
research should proceed. Methods are the specific techniques or tools for
carrying out the research (Ackerly and True 2010: 9–10; 2012). Certain
methods – for example the close reading of historical texts – are used by all
methodologies of CPT. However, these methods are used differently
depending on the specific research question and overarching methodol-
ogy of the project.
In order to discuss the methodologies and methods of CPT, we have to
engage, but not embrace, two suspect premises: that the field of compara-
tive political thought is a subdiscipline with distinct methods and that
delimiting those methods strengthens the field. Perhaps because
comparative political thought is a relatively new field in political theory,
most participants in the field have spent significant time being explicit
about and defending their methods. Michael Freeden refers to ‘the
absence of considered approaches, and their attendant methodologies’
of CPT as ‘one of the great lacunae in the study of political thinking’
(2007: 1). For many political theorists, explaining and defending our
choice of and use of chosen methods is part of justifying our arguments
(Herzog 1985; Gaus 1990; Forst 2001). We believe that a discussion of
methodologies is useful in order to clarify the choices available and to
defend the intellectual case for all of the methods in the field. What the
field needs now is a pluralist account of those methodologies so that
rather than debating which methods and approaches the field should
privilege, we can build an inclusive field whose methodological attentions
focus on the importance of (1) choosing the approach or approaches
appropriate to the particular question at hand and (2) doing that
approach well.
In this chapter we discuss a range of normative, historical, interpretive
and critical approaches to comparative political thought. Not all of those
who participate in the field use all of these approaches, and some CPT
scholars would not recognize certain approaches as being appropriately
Comparative Political Thought 273
exception, see Goto-Jones 2011), the other two approaches seek to break
down that dichotomous construction of ‘comparison’ and the focus on
‘traditions’ that has often accompanied this.
4 How to Do CPT
In a CPT project, as in other subfields of politics, methodologies and
methods need to be chosen with respect to a particular question. CPT
scholars often use a mixed methodology, perhaps beginning in one meth-
odology and revising using another. In this light, it is best to think of the
four CPT methodologies as providing an initial guiding framework.
As with empirical social science, triangulation across methodologies and
methods can be more fruitful than relying on one. The key to avoiding the
potential for epistemological imperialism in political theory is to be ques-
tion-driven, attentive to methodological pluralism even if your own methods
tend towards one strand of the field, attentive to the potential of any
method to be self-centric due to the building blocks of scholarship, and
self-reflective about the best execution of the methods of your selected
approach or approaches. These are ‘meta-methods’ if you will. Many,
maybe even all of these, are or should be part of any political theory
practice. Post-colonial, feminist and other critical approaches have
made similar arguments. Nevertheless, we offer a CPT perspective on
research practices and outline their concrete instantiation in CPT
scholarship.
(a) Start with your research question rather than methodology
or method. Several scholars have called for more question-driven
research, in contrast with the emphasis on methods and models in poli-
tical theory and political science (on the general point, see Isaac 1995;
Comparative Political Thought 287
Shapiro 2005). CPT joins calls in the discipline for putting the question
before methods. It has the potential to enlarge research questions beyond
those traditionally addressed by political theorists to include those
informed by deep engagement with non-Western sources on the one
hand, and empirical social science on the other.
As with other forms of political theory, a CPT question can be based on
an empirical observation. These can be empirical problems (such as
violence, immigration, climate change, gender oppression and poverty)
that pose challenges for how we live together. Such an empirical problem
can also lead to a theoretical problem that needs to be addressed before
we can think about how we might address the empirical problem (and
others like it). As we saw earlier, CPT scholars have addressed questions
of governance, human rights, democracy and citizenship. A CPT ques-
tion can also come from a new way of reading a text that comes from the
reading of texts in and/or across traditions. In sum, a CPT question can
be grounded in a problem (e.g. poverty), a concept (e.g. human rights) or
texts (e.g. Confucian and Neo-Confucian texts). Be aware of the fact that
your question will influence your methodological commitments.
(b) Know your ontological perspective and be open to its revi-
sion. By your selection of a research project, you reveal to yourself and
the world the ontological perspective behind the inquiry. Some
differences among theorists can be ontological, but manifest themselves
methodologically. For example, Andrew March argues that the important
differences across historical traditions lie in the differences in their world-
views. In fact, March has a worldview (an ontological perspective) about
the differences in worldviews. By contrast, Roxanne Euben argues that by
familiarizing ourselves with seeming differences in worldviews, we can
gain better self-understanding and an appreciation that differences are
not as different as we might have thought. She has an ontological per-
spective on the inter-comparability and inter-compatibility of world-
views. In Enemy in the Mirror, she argues that ‘Qutb’s work must be
understood as a “dialectical response” to rationalism and
Westernization’, and that he is ‘participating in a conversation that we,
as Western students of politics, not only recognize, but in which we
participate’ (Euben 1999: 155).
Consider the ways in which the tensions among competing readings or
interpretations and seeming ‘discontinuities’ or irreconcilable differences
across time and geography reveal not just intra-disciplinary methodolo-
gical disagreements, but ontological differences. If you are doing CPT
well, you challenge yourself to revisit your ontological perspectives
throughout the research process.
288 Chapter 13
2
Mark Bevir, personal communication, May 2015.
Comparative Political Thought 289
theory and political science, where the tools of political theorists are used
for improving social science explanations.
Critical comparative political theorists have analysed non-elite texts and
even treated as texts the arguments that are embedded in the political actions
of non-elites who are seeking alternative political arrangements. Critical
CPT methods include observation of contemporary struggles (Beltrán
2009; Cabrera 2010; Clifford 2012; Forman and Cruz forthcoming), critical
rereading of historical struggles (Keating 2011) and even interviews with
actors in the struggle (Ackerly 2008). Sungmoon Kim’s Confucian
Democracy in East Asia utilizes historical, interpretive and critical methods
and normative-analytic argument in setting out the import of his project
(Kim 2014).
Be aware that the findings from different methods may conflict.
Methodological location and triangulation (see later) can help with the
resolution of such conflicts.
(e) Be aware of your own boundaries. It is important to recognize
that as a comparative political theorist, you both construct and decon-
struct boundaries as you work. Attentiveness to that construction and
reconstruction is a feature of CPT best practice.
Consider, for example, the political and theoretical debate in the 1990s
about ‘Asian Values’ and their (in)commensurability with political equality,
individual freedom and rights. In the Asian Values debate, some partici-
pants emphasized the distinctiveness of East Asian cultures (Zakaria 1994;
Bell 2000). Drawing on textual analysis and cross-cultural comparison,
they developed a reified dichotomy between Western and Asian traditions.
Participants in that same debate challenged those readings of historical
texts and offered competing interpretations of ‘the’ cultural tradition
(Kim Dae 1994; Chan 1997). The debate revealed great differences within
each of these intellectual and cultural groupings. The diversity within those
broad civilizational categories – and their political import for charting
possible ways of thinking about what ethical responsibility requires in the
face of contemporary challenges – is obfuscated by the overgeneralized
characterization of and sharp delineation between the dialogue partners.
(f) Acquire requisite language skills. CPT methods typically, but
not necessarily, require competency in the language of the texts.
Depending on the research question, the availability and quality of trans-
lations and knowledge about the politics and epistemology of a text’s
translators, some CPT can be done without fluency.
(g) Read texts closely and contextualize these. All CPT makes use
of close textual reading. Whether your reading is typical or a nuanced
rereading, be attentive to alternative readings of the texts (see also Blau’s
chapter in this volume). Debates from the time period, contemporary
290 Chapter 13
secondary literature and political history of the context can enhance the
reading. Whereas the focus in reading texts is often the substance of their
arguments, CPT scholars can also read texts for their insights into how to
do political theory (e.g. Jenco 2007).
(h) Consider the broad range of available sources. When your
research question relates to broad categories – such as culture or religion –
contextualize your account of any particular text or other evidence with
reference to a broad range of sources. Remember (or reconsider) your
ontological commitments when you identify your sources.
From a critical CPT perspective, it is especially important for you to
consider the status of the authors of your texts at the time and in history.
Much CPT broadens our sources, but you may not be able to include
non-elite sources, those either lost to time because they did not generate
texts that are available today or omitted because their texts are not
considered ‘theory.’
For example, in East Meets West, Daniel Bell broadens what counts as
a text for political theory by taking the political ideas of two leaders in the
Asian Values debate of the 1990s and articulating their views in the form
of fictionalized characters. However, the fictionalized protagonists of the
dialogue that he constructs between East and West are as elite as the
political leaders on whose ideas the text is based (Bell 2000). Neither
protagonist is engaged in a struggle for recognition and enjoyment of his
own human rights. This is a critical CPT assessment of Bell’s sources.
(i) Pick your qualitative methods carefully. Political practice can
be a source of CPT ‘text’ for analysis. Michael Freeden, in his call for
explicit methods for CPT, urges theorists to focus more on ‘real world
forms of political thinking’ rather than great thinkers and texts that are
unrepresentative of their contexts (2007: 2; see also Bajpai 2011). Godrej
(2011) calls on CPT work to be anthropological or ethnographic.
However, such work can also be qualitative without being ethnographic.
For example, Ackerly (2001) looks at the human rights practices of
activists to complement what they say about their work. Cabrera (2010)
looks at the actions of migrants and those near and crossing borders.
Be aware too that textual and written sources also encode practices and
ritual forms – the latter are not just to be found in the realm of ‘behaviour’.
(j) Attend to sources of bias. A narrow source list can be one source
of bias, but there are others. Because each methodological approach has
strengths and weaknesses, be attentive to and make explicit the biases in
your framing of the comparative project. For instance, does it frame
Islamic, Indian or Chinese traditions in terms of their orthodox variants,
or even their dominant heterodox strands? What alternative sources pro-
vide a counter-reading of the thinkers and traditions that are its focus?
Comparative Political Thought 291
5 Conclusions
In the twenty-first century, the field of political theory and comparative
political thought is global, not in the sense that any articulation of the
complex web of concepts would be globally agreed to or that such agree-
ment should be the goal, but rather that our interlocutors in this endea-
vour are not predetermined by our training, experience, geography or
imagination, but may come from any place, time or family of inquiry.
292 Chapter 13
CPT can help us do political theory better. The field’s internal discus-
sions of methodologies and method can help its practitioners – novice and
experienced – do their work better. One day the modifier ‘comparative’
will become associated with this time in the historical development of our
discipline because in fact what we learn from how we do comparative
inquiry improves how we do political theory (Dallmayr 2004; Euben
2006: see especially chapter 2; March 2009: 536–7; see also Leader
Maynard’s chapter in this volume). CPT enables us to deepen our reflec-
tions about what we mean by ‘we’ when ‘we’ as theorists engage in an
ethical and political reflection.
Political, economic and social empirical problems with normative
import are the important questions for political theorists. Because
many of these recur, the history of political thought is a likely source
for a wealth of reflective insights. Because these issues have been
relevant in the world and over time, the historical intellectual tradi-
tions that may provide insight may come from anywhere. Because
these issues are pressing now, contemporary theorists around the
world should draw on each other’s reflective insights in order to
broaden our understanding of the web of relevant concepts and help
clarify our articulations of them. The vastness of these ambitions
extends beyond the capacity of any individual’s life work. Therefore,
political theory relevant to the significant challenges posed by these
ambitious normative puzzles needs to be a collaborative enterprise.
Taken together, the range of methodological forms that CPT takes
enables political theory to ever improve its contributions to the study
and practice of politics.
CPT methods build a shared, though not necessarily common platform
across multiple domains of knowledge production. They challenge false
universalisms and dominant Western stereotypes. They situate political
theory in multiple contexts of resemblance and difference and expand the
notion of text to include debates and action. CPT is one of the subfields in
political theory that engages in constructive criticism of the ways in which
political theory can perform global politics, not just write about it. CPT
methods push political theory to become increasingly self-aware about
that possibility.
Acknowledgements
We are grateful to participants in the London Comparative Political
Thought seminar, and to Adrian Blau, Humeira Iqtidar, Leigh Jenco,
Sungmoon Kim and Tejas Parasher for their comments on earlier
versions.
Comparative Political Thought 293
References
Ackerly, Brooke, 2001. ‘Women’s human rights activists as cross-cultural theor-
ists’, International Feminist Journal of Politics 3, 311–46.
Ackerly, Brooke, 2005. ‘Is liberalism the only way toward democracy?
Confucianism and democracy’, Political Theory 33, 547–76.
Ackerly, Brooke, 2008. Universal Human Rights in a World of Difference. Cambridge
University Press.
Ackerly, Brooke and Jacqui True, 2010. Doing Feminist Research in Political and
Social Science. Palgrave Macmillan.
Ackerly, Brooke and Jacqui True, 2012. ‘Methods and methodologies’, in
Georgina Waylen, Karen Celis, Johanna Kantola and Laurel Weldon, eds.,
The Oxford Handbook of Gender and Politics. Oxford University Press, 109–33.
Angle, Stephen, 2002. Human Rights and Chinese Thought: A Cross-cultural Inquiry.
Cambridge University Press.
Angle, Stephen, 2005. ‘Decent democratic centralism’, Political Theory 33,
518–46.
Angle, Stephen, 2012. Contemporary Confucian Political Philosophy. Cambridge:
Polity.
Asad Talal, 1993. Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in
Christianity and Islam. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Bajpai, Rochana, 2002. ‘The conceptual vocabularies of secularism and minority
rights in India’, Journal of Political Ideologies 7, 179–97.
Bajpai, Rochana, 2011. Debating Difference: Group Rights and Liberal Democracy in
India. Oxford University Press.
Bajpai, Rochana, 2012. ‘Liberalisms in India: a sketch’, in Ben Jackson and
Marc Stears, eds., Liberalism as Ideology: Essays in Honour of Michael Freeden.
Oxford University Press, 53–76.
Bajpai, Rochana and Graham Brown, 2013. ‘From ideas to hegemony: ideational
change and affirmative action policy in Malaysia, 1955–2010’, Journal of Political
Ideologies 18, 257–80.
Bell, Daniel, 2000. East Meets West: Human Rights and Democracy in East Asia.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bell, Daniel, 2006. Beyond Liberal Democracy: Political Thinking for an East Asian
Context. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bell, Daniel, 2008. China’s New Confucianism: Politics and Everyday Life in
a Changing Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Beltrán, Cristina, 2009. ‘Going public’, Political Theory 37, 595–622.
Bevir, Mark and R. A. W. Rhodes, 2002. ‘Interpretive theory’, in David Marsh and
Gerry Stoker, eds., Theory and Methods in Political Science. Basingstoke: Palgrave,
131–52.
Browers, Michaelle, 2006. Democracy and Civil Society in Arab Political Thought:
Transcultural Possibilities. Syracuse University Press.
Cabrera, Luis, 2010. The Practice of Global Citizenship. Cambridge University
Press.
Chan, Joseph Cho Wai, 1997. ‘An alternative view’, Journal of Democracy 8, 35–48.
294 Chapter 13
Chan, Joseph Cho Wai, 2009. ‘Is there a Confucian perspective on social justice?’,
in Takashi Shogimen and Cary Nederman, eds., Western Political Thought in
Dialogue with Asia. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 261–77.
Chan, Joseph Cho Wai, 2015. Confucian Perfectionism: A Political Philosophy for
Modern Times. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Clifford, Stacy, 2012. ‘Making disability public in deliberative democracy’,
Contemporary Political Theory 11, 211–28.
Dallmayr, Fred, ed., 1999. Border Crossings: Toward a Comparative Political Theory.
Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Dallmayr, Fred, 2004. ‘Beyond monologue: for a comparative political theory’,
Perspectives on Politics 2, 249–57.
Euben, Roxanne Leslie, 1999. Enemy in the Mirror: Islamic Fundamentalism and the
Limits of Modern Rationalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Euben, Roxanne Leslie, 2006. Journeys to the Other Shore: Muslim and Western
Travelers in Search of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Forman, Fonna and Teddy Cruz, forthcoming. ‘Global justice at the municipal
scale: the case of Medellín, Colombia’, in Thomas Pogge and Luis Cabrera, eds.,
Institutional Cosmopolitanism. Oxford University Press.
Forst, Rainer, 2001. ‘Towards a critical theory of transnational justice’,
Metaphilosophy 32, 160–79.
Freeden, Michael, 1996. Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Freeden, Michael, 2007. ‘The comparative study of political thinking’, Journal of
Political Ideologies 12, 1–9.
Freeden, Michael and Andrew Vincent, eds., 2013. Comparative Political Thought:
Theorizing Practices. New York: Routledge.
Fricker, Miranda, 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford
University Press.
Fukuyama, Francis, 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. New York: Free
Press.
Gaus, Gerald, 1990. Value and Justification: The Foundations of Liberal Theory.
Cambridge University Press.
Geertz, Clifford, 1973. The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays. New York:
Basic Books.
Godrej, Farah, 2011. Cosmopolitan Political Thought: Method, Practice, Discipline.
Oxford University Press.
Gordon, Jane Anna, 2014. Creolizing Political Theory: Reading Rousseau through
Fanon. Bronx: Fordham University Press.
Goto-Jones, Chris, 2011. ‘A cosmos beyond space and area studies: toward com-
parative political thought as political thought’, boundary 2 38, 87–118.
Gunnell, John, 2010. ‘Professing political theory’, Political Research Quarterly 63,
674–79.
Herzog, Don, 1985. Without Foundations: Justification in Political Theory. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
Huntington, Samuel, 1996. The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World
Order. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Comparative Political Thought 295
Iqtidar, Humeira, 2011 ‘Secularism beyond the state: the “state” and the “market”
in Islamist imagination’, Modern Asian Studies 45, 535–64.
Isaac, Jeffrey, 1995. ‘The strange silence of political theory’, Political Theory 23,
636–52.
Jenco, Leigh, 2007. ‘“What does heaven ever say?” A methods-centered approach
to cross-cultural engagement’, American Political Science Review 101, 741–55.
Jenco, Leigh, 2011. ‘Recentering political theory: the promise of mobile locality’,
Cultural Critique 79, 27–59.
Kaufman-Osborn, Timothy, 2010. ‘Political theory as profession and as subfield?’,
Political Research Quarterly 63, 655–73.
Keating, Christine, 2011. Decolonizing Democracy: Transforming the Social Contract
in India. Pennsylvania State University Press.
Kim Dae, Jung, 1994. ‘Is culture destiny: the myth of Asia’s anti-democratic
values’, Foreign Affairs 73.
Kim, Sungmoon, 2014. Confucian Democracy in East Asia: Theory and Practice.
Cambridge University Press.
Laborde, Cécile, 2008. Critical Republicanism: The Hijab Controversy and Political
Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Mackey, Eva, 2005. ‘Universal rights in conflict: “backlash” and “benevolent
resistance” to indigenous land rights’, Anthropology Today 21, 14–20.
Mahmood, Saba, 2005. Politics of Piety: The Islamic Revival and the Feminist Subject.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
March, Andrew, 2009. ‘What is comparative political theory?’, The Review of
Politics 71, 531–65.
Marx, Karl, 1967. Writings of the Young Marx on Philosophy and Society, ed. Loyd
David Easton and Kurt Guddat. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
Medina, José, 2012. The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression,
Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations. Oxford University Press.
Mills, Charles, 2015. ‘Decolonizing Western political philosophy’, New Political
Science 37, 1–24.
Nelson, Matthew, 2011. In the Shadow of Shari, ah: Islam, Islamic Law, and
Democracy in Pakistan. Columbia University Press.
Parel, Anthony, 2006. Gandhi’s Philosophy and the Quest for Harmony. Cambridge
University Press.
Rothschild, Cynthia, Scott Long and Susana Fried, eds., 2005. Written Out: How
Sexuality Is Used to Attack Women’s Organizing. New York: International Gay
and Lesbian Human Rights Commission & The Center for Women’s Global
Leadership.
Shapiro, Ian, 2005. The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences. Princeton
University Press.
Tan, Sor-Hoon, 2003. Confucian Democracy: A Deweyan Reconstruction. Albany:
State University of New York Press.
Taylor, Charles, 1985. Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Cambridge University
Press.
Thomas, Megan, 2010. ‘Orientalism and comparative political theory’, The Review
of Politics 72, 653–77.
296 Chapter 13
Tripp, Charles, 2013. ‘Acting and acting out: conceptions of political participation
in the Middle East’, in Michael Freeden and Andrew Vincent, eds., Comparative
Political Thought: Theorizing Practices. New York: Routledge, 88–109.
Von Vacano, Diego, 2015. ‘The scope of comparative political theory’, Annual
Review of Political Science 18, 465–80.
Wedeen, Lisa, 2002. ‘Conceptualizing culture: possibilities for political science’,
American Political Science Review 96, 713–28.
Wedeen, Lisa, 2008. Peripheral Visions: Publics, Power, and Performance in Yemen.
University of Chicago Press.
Whitehead, Laurence, 2013. ‘Latin American approaches to “the political”’, in
Michael Freeden and Andrew Vincent, eds., Comparative Political Thought:
Theorizing Practices. New York: Routledge, 40–59.
Wolin, Sheldon, 1969. ‘Political theory as a vocation’, American Political Science
Review 63, 1062–82.
Yanow, Dvora and Peregrine Schwartz-Shea, eds., 2013. Interpretation and
Method: Empirical Research Methods and the Interpretive Turn. Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe.
Zakaria, Fareed, 1994. ‘Culture is destiny: a conversation with Lee Kuan Yew’,
Foreign Affairs 73, 109–26.
14 Ideological Analysis
1 Introduction
The past two decades have seen a proliferation of academic work on
ideology (Freeden et al. 2013: v). While the study of ideology is older
than this (Larrain 1979; McLellan 1995), recent developments have
made it increasingly appropriate to speak of ‘ideology studies’ or ‘ideolo-
gical analysis’ as a distinct interdisciplinary field of research within the
humanities and social sciences. Researchers of ideology have made sig-
nificant methodological, theoretical and empirical advances, in
disciplines as diverse as political theory (Freeden 1996), intellectual
history (Tully 1983; Skinner 2002b), political psychology (Rosenberg
1988; Jost and Major 2001; Haidt et al. 2009; Jost et al. 2009a), discourse
analysis (Howarth et al. 2000; Fairclough 2010), political science (Knight
2006; Carmines and D’Amico 2015), sociology (Boudon 1989) and
social and cultural studies (Eagleton 1991; Hall 1996; Shelby 2003).
Indeed, the biggest problem facing the contemporary study of ideology
is the fragmentation of work across disciplines – one thing this chapter
attempts to address (for existing interdisciplinary work, see Žižek 1994a;
van Dijk 1998; Freeden 2007; Freeden et al. 2013). But while problems
and lacunae remain, ideological analysis is currently at a high point of
sophistication, diversity and output (for guideline maps to such contem-
porary research, see Norval 2000; Leader Maynard 2013; Leader
Maynard and Mildenberger 2016).
The overwhelming bulk of this work has occurred within research
domains that could loosely be described as empirical. But that is not the
focus of this chapter. I contend that ideological analysis is also important
for the sort of conceptual and normative political theory covered in most
chapters of this volume. Some theorists, notably the leading ideology
scholar Michael Freeden, have argued for the relevance of ideological
analysis to political theory by advocating a broad conceptualization of the
latter: where political theory goes beyond conceptual and normative
analysis to include theoretical reflection about empirical features of
297
298 Chapter 14
politics (Freeden 2005b, 2006, 2008, 2013b: especially chs. 1 and 2).
There are merits to this argument, but this is also not my approach here.
Instead, I’m happy to limit the scope of political theory to a normative
form – though I assume that this encompasses a broad range of ‘ideal’ and
‘non-ideal’ theorizing (Valentini 2012; see too the chapters by Jubb and
by Schmidtz in this volume). I will show how ideological analysis can
support such normative political theory (although my discussion should
be useful for those engaged in empirical work too). In Section 1, I discuss
how to conceptualize ideology, before going on, in Section 2, to explain
how ideological analysis can be valuable for normative political theory,
arguing that political theorists need to attend to it more frequently.
Finally, in the more substantive Section 3, I offer an integrative account
of how to engage in rigorous ideological analysis.
At many points my comments are necessarily cursory. My objective here
is to offer the most practically useful guide to engaging in ideological
analysis for scholars and students. Offering the fullest justification for
every piece of advice I give would make it impossible to explain that advice
clearly. Instead, my bibliographical references should serve to link readers
to key texts that examine the corresponding issues in more depth.
Since (b) and (c) can pull us in opposite directions, striking a balance
between them is necessary.
So there needn’t be one single definition of ideology that all theorists
should use. But in this chapter I follow recent trends in ideological
analysis by suggesting that political theorists should use
a conception of ideology that is both broad and non-pejorative –
respectively, that it encompasses a large range of idea systems and
thought practices, and that it does not assume that ideology is necessarily
false, inflexible, poorly formulated or otherwise ‘bad’. Such a conception
is recommended by two of the most sustained conceptual investigations
into ideology, by Malcolm Hamilton (1987) and John Gerring (1997),
and has been favoured by many other leading theorists (Freeden 1996;
van Dijk 1998: 11–12; Jost 2006; Knight 2006). Following their advice,
I advocate the use of the following definition (closely resembling
Hamilton’s):
A political ideology is a distinctive overarching system of normative and/or reputedly
factual ideas, typically shared by members of groups or organizations, which shapes
their understandings of their political world and guides their political behaviour.
This definition is not so broad that all sets of ideas become indistinguish-
ably ideological, but it rejects assertions (by politicians or political
theorists) that certain political worldviews are ‘beyond ideology’ or ‘not
ideological but pragmatic’ (see also Bell 1960; Freeden 2005a; Coote
2014). Such claims frequently suggest exceptionalism, cryptonormativity
and an attempt at partisan and contestable political tactics rather than
sound conceptual distinctions (Žižek 1994b; Freeden 2005a; Worsnip
2015). In this broad and non-pejorative conception, ideologies denote
whatever distinctive idea systems people do in fact use to think about
politics. No human being can engage in some kind of perfectly rational
disembodied reflection about politics that simply ‘sees the world as it is’
uninfluenced by prior thinking. Instead, every individual’s political think-
ing occurs via networks of values, meanings, narratives, theories, assump-
tions, concepts, expectations, exemplars, past experiences, images,
stereotypes and beliefs about matters of fact already existing in their
mind (Geertz 1964; Berger and Luckmann 1967; Tversky and
Kahneman 1974; Wittgenstein 2001; Baurmann 2007). These networks
of ideas vary, at least somewhat, from person to person, group to group
and society to society, which is what makes them important objects of
study. In this conception, ideology is not reprehensible, but inescapable.
As Aletta Norval (2000: 316) writes: ‘It is this emphasis on the ubiquity of
ideology . . . that is at the heart of contemporary approaches to the
question of ideology.’
Ideological Analysis 301
analysis important to the degree that political theory moves away from
ideal-type theorizing and becomes ‘non-ideal’ (Valentini 2012) or ‘realist’
(Galston 2010). In such situations, ideological analysis is needed to
assess the likely real-world effects of certain moral or political
principles in practice, and consequently their viability and normative
attractiveness. Such forms of non-ideal normative political theory are
concerned not just with reflection on moral rightness in some ‘ultimate’
sense, but the actual application of political theory to the world, and the
design of political prescriptions and norms to guide policy. How real-
world agents – perceiving, thinking and acting under the influence of real-
world ideologies – would actually operationalize normative principles is
thus a key question. As Jennifer Welsh (2010: 424) notes: ‘principles,
when adopted, always take on a life of their own. It is difficult to control
their meaning, or to avoid their misuse.’ Predicting how this ‘life of their
own’ will unfold ought to be a critical component of the assessment of
normative principles at the non-ideal level.
Ideological analysis supports these sorts of non-ideal and realist assess-
ments in four ways. First, it may provide contextual knowledge about
actually existing ideologies in particular circumstances. Failure to analyse
the nature and power of these extant ideologies can undermine normative
theorizing about the right way to approach injustice. For example, a range
of left-wing terrorist groups in the 1970s and 1980s believed that a few
symbolic acts of violence would expose the fragility of the capitalist order
and inspire a mass revolution, and acted accordingly (Tsintsadze-Maass
and Maass 2014). This legitimation of deadly political violence involved
a wildly naïve failure to appreciate the power and breadth and depth of
internalization of liberal, free-market ideologies in modern Western
societies. A parallel problem might be thought to exist in neoconservative
or neoliberal theories of why military intervention in countries to spread
democracy should be legitimate. Such theories carry many flaws, but
these include a fundamental blindness to the complex ideological terrain
of target states, and the radicalizing ideological consequences of militar-
ized action on both its victims and on the interveners themselves (Doris
and Murphy 2007; McCauley and Moskalenko 2011). The problem is no
less salient for other political strategies – one needs to know the ideologi-
cal context of a proposed policy to predict the normatively relevant
consequences. Normative political theorists have not been completely
blind to this. Members of the International Commission on
Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS), for example, advanced the
international norm of a ‘responsibility to protect’ in 2001 partly in the
belief that this concept would do a better job than the previous concept of
‘humanitarian intervention’ at reconciling competing attitudes and
Ideological Analysis 307
5 Conclusion
Ideological analysis is difficult, often tentative and always open to con-
testation and challenge. I have certainly not exhausted key methodologi-
cal precepts and techniques. Nor are the many points of advice or
empirical claims about human thinking that I have asserted immune
from criticism. What this chapter might do, I hope, is two things: to
show political theorists that ideological analysis matters to a far greater
extent than is generally appreciated, and to show them how they can do it
better. An expanded engagement with ideology in political theory is an
exciting direction for the discipline, and suggests a panoply of potential
research projects. But for it to be successful, political theorists need to
draw on interdisciplinary research on ideology more thoroughly, and to
reflect on how to study ideology more deeply.
References
Atran, Scott and Axelrod, Robert, 2008. ‘Reframing sacred values’, Negotiation
Journal 24, 221–46.
Ball, Terence, Farr, James and Hanson, Russell L., eds., 1989. Political Innovation
and Conceptual Change. Cambridge University Press.
320 Chapter 14
Howarth, David, Aletta Norval and Yannis Stavrakakis, eds., 2000. Discourse
Theory and Political Analysis: Identities, Hegemonies and Social Change.
Manchester University Press.
Huddy, Leonie, 2001. ‘From social to political identity: a critical examination of
social identity theory’, Political Psychology 22, 127–56.
Humphrey, Matthew, 2005. ‘(De)contesting ideology: the struggle over the mean-
ing of the struggle over meaning’, Critical Review of International Social and
Political Philosophy 8, 225–46.
Ipsos Mori. 2014. Perceptions Are Not Reality: Things the World Gets Wrong.
Available: www.ipsos-mori.com/researchpublications/researcharchive/3466/
Perceptions-are-not-reality-Things-the-world-gets-wrong.aspx. Accessed 9
May 2015.
Jost, John, 2006. ‘The end of the end of ideology’, American Psychologist 61,
651–70.
Jost, John, Christopher Federico and Jaime Napier, 2009a. ‘Political ideology: its
structure, functions and elective affinities’, Annual Review of Psychology 60,
307–37.
Jost, John, Jack Glaser, Arie Kruglanski and Frank Sulloway, 2003. ‘Political
conservatism as motivated social cognition’, Psychological Bulletin 129, 339–75.
Jost, John and Orsolya Hunyady, 2005. ‘Antecedents and consequences of
system-justifying ideologies’, Current Directions in Psychological Science 14,
260–65.
Jost, John, Aaron Kay and Hulda Thorisdottir, 2009b. Social and Psychological
Bases of Ideology and System Justification. Oxford University Press.
Jost, John and Brenda Major, 2001. The Psychology of Legitimacy: Emerging
Perspectives on Ideology, Justice and Intergroup Relations. Cambridge University
Press.
Kahneman, Daniel, 2012. Thinking, Fast and Slow. London: Penguin Books.
Knight, Kathleen, 2006. ‘Transformations in the concept of ideology in the twen-
tieth century’, American Political Science Review 100, 619–26.
Laclau, Ernesto, 2007. ‘Ideology and post-Marxism’, in Michael Freeden, ed.,
The Meaning of Ideology: Cross-disciplinary Perspectives. Oxford University Press,
98–109.
Larrain, Jorge, 1979. The Concept of Ideology. London: Hutchinson and Co.
Leader Maynard, Jonathan, 2013. ‘A map of the field of ideological analysis’,
Journal of Political Ideologies 18, 299–327.
Leader Maynard, Jonathan and Mildenberger, Matto, 2016. ‘Convergence and
divergence in the study of ideology: a critical review’, British Journal of Political
Science. FirstView early online edition.
Mann, Michael 2005. The Dark Side of Democracy: Explaining Ethnic Cleansing.
Cambridge University Press.
Mccauley, Clark and Sophia Moskalenko, 2011. Friction: How Radicalization
Happens to Them and Us. Oxford University Press.
Mclellan, David, 1995. Ideology. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Mill, John Stuart, 2008. On Liberty and Other Essays. Oxford University Press.
Mills, Charles, 1999. The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Ideological Analysis 323
Mullins, Willard, 1972. ‘On the concept of ideology in political science’, American
Political Science Review 66, 498–510.
Nelson, Eric, 2005. ‘Liberty: one concept too many?’, Political Theory 33, 58–78.
Norval, Aletta, 2000. ‘The things we do with words – contemporary approaches to
the analysis of ideology’, British Journal of Political Science 30, 313–46.
Opotow, Susan, 1990. ‘Moral exclusion and injustice: an introduction’, Journal of
Social Issues 46, 1–20.
Pinker, Steven, 1998. How the Mind Works. London: Penguin Books.
Price, Monroe, 2000. ‘Information intervention: Bosnia, the Dayton accords, and
the seizure of broadcasting transmitters’, Cornell International Law Journal 33,
67–112.
Rosen, Michael, 2000. ‘On voluntary servitude and the theory of ideology’,
Constellations 7, 393–407.
Rosenberg, Shawn, 1988. Reason, Ideology and Politics. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Rydgren, Jens, 2009. ‘Beliefs’, in Peter Hadström and Peter Bearman, eds.,
The Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology. Oxford University Press, 72–93.
Sagar, Paul, 2014. ‘A broken clock’, The Oxonian Review, 3 June. Available from:
www.oxonianreview.org/wp/a-broken-clock.
Sartori, Giovanni, 1976. Parties and Party Systems: A Framework for Analysis.
Cambridge University Press.
Searle, John, 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. London: Penguin.
Shelby, Tommie, 2003. ‘Ideology, racism, and critical social theory’,
The Philosophical Forum 34, 153–88.
Shenhav, Shaul, 2006. ‘Political narratives and political reality’, International
Political Science Review 27, 245–62.
Simonds, A. P., 1989. ‘Ideological domination and the political information
market’, Theory and Society 18, 181–211.
Skinner, Quentin, 1974. ‘Some problems in the analysis of political thought and
action’, Political Theory 2, 277–303.
Skinner, Quentin, 1998. Liberty Before Liberalism. Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Quentin, 2002a. ‘A third concept of liberty’, Proceedings of the British
Academy 117, 237–68.
Skinner, Quentin, 2002b. Visions of Politics. Volume I: Regarding Method.
Cambridge University Press.
Steger, Manfred, 2008. The Rise of the Global Imaginary: Political Ideologies from the
French Revolution to the Global War on Terror. Oxford University Press.
Swift, Adam, 2003. How Not to Be a Hypocrite: School Choice for the Morally
Perplexed Parent. London: Routledge.
Tajfel, Henri, 1974. ‘Social identity and intergroup behaviour’, Social Science
Information 13, 65–93.
Thagard, Paul, 2010. ‘Explaining economic crises: are there collective
representations?’, Episteme 7, 266–83.
Thagard, Paul, 2012. ‘Mapping minds across cultures’, in Ron Sun, ed., Grounding
Social Sciences in Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 35–62.
Thompson, John, 1984. Studies in the Theory of Ideology. Cambridge: Polity Press.
324 Chapter 14
The other chapters in this book describe and critique the standard
methods used in analytical political theory. Here we give a few pointers,
of the sort we give to our students, about doing a political theory PhD.
325
326 Chapter 15
Plan, but not too rigidly. You will need a plan for the whole thesis
from the start. But your structure and argument may well change, even
radically, before the end. Don’t worry. Just keep writing, and repackage
later.
Reading is the enemy of writing. At the beginning you will need to
read widely around the literature to get the lie of the land and situate your
work within it. That done, get on with writing; don’t chase up footnotes or
pursue everything written on the subject. Getting your own ideas down
and then seeing who has said something similar is a good way of
distinguishing what you want to say from others. That way you avoid
following the same ruts as the existing literature.
Let it go. Everything can be improved with a little more work, but don’t
let that stand in the way of submission. Plug the big holes and learn to live
with the problems (though plan a response in case someone else, espe-
cially your PhD examiner, spots them).
327
328 Index