Multicriteria Optimizationand Decision Making
Multicriteria Optimizationand Decision Making
Decision Making
1 Introduction 4
1.1 Viewing MOO as a task in system design and analysis . . . . . 6
1.2 Formal Problem Definitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
1.3 Pareto domination and incomparability . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
1.4 Formal Definition of Pareto Dominance . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12
1
4.3 Equality Constraints . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48
4.4 Inequality Constraints . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
4.5 Multiple Objectives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
5 Scalarization Methods 57
5.1 Linear Aggregation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 58
5.2 Nonlinear Aggregation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 60
5.3 Multi-Attribute Utility Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61
5.4 Distance to a Reference Point Methods . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67
2
Preface
3
Chapter 1
Introduction
4
• What are our goals? What makes it difficult to state goals? How do
people define goals? Can the process of identifying goals be supported?
• Which different strategies are used by people to come to decisions?
How can satisfaction be measured? What strategies are promising in
obtaining satisfactory decisions?
• What are the cognitive aspects in decision making? How can decision
support systems be build in a way that takes care of cognitive capabil-
ities and limits of humans?
• How do groups of people come to decisions? What are conflicts and how
can they be avoided? How to deal with minority interests in a demo-
cratic decision process? Can these aspects be integrated into formal
decision models?
Moreover, decisions are always related to some real world problem. Given
an application field, we may find very specific answers to the following ques-
tions:
• What is the set of alternatives?
• By which means can we retrieve the values for the criteria (experi-
ments, surveys, function evaluations)? Are there any particular prob-
lems with these measurements (dangers, costs), and how to deal with
them? What are the uncertainties in these measurements?
• What are the problem-specific objectives and constraints?
• What are typical decision processes in the field, and what implications
do they have for the design of decision support systems?
• Are there existing problem-specific procedures for decision support and
optimization, and what about the acceptance and performance of these
procedures in practice?
In summary, this list of questions gives some kind of bird eye’s view of the
field. However, in this book we will mainly focus on the structural aspects
of multi-objective optimization and decision making. On the other hand, we
also devote one chapter to people-centric aspects of decision making and one
chapter to the problem of selecting, adapting, and evaluating MOO tools for
application problems.
5
1.1 Viewing MOO as a task in system design
and analysis
The discussion above can be seen as a rough sketch of questions that define
the scope of multicriteria optimization and decision making. However, it
needs to be clarified more precisely what is going to be the focus of this
book. For this reason we want to approach the problem class from the point
of view of system design and analysis. Here, with system analysis, we denote
the interdisciplinary research field, that deals with the modeling, simulation,
and synthesis of complex systems.
Beside experimentation with a physical system, often a system model
is used. Nowadays, system models are typically implemented as computer
programs that solve (differential) equation systems, simulate interacting au-
tomata, or stochastic models. We will also refer to them as simulation models.
An example for a simulation model based on differential equations would be
the simulation of the fluid flow around an airfoil based on the Navier Stokes
equations. An example for a stochastic system model, could be the simula-
tion of a system of elevators, based on some agent based stochastic model.
! ! Modelling
! ? ! Identification
! ! Calibration
! ? Simulation
! ! ? Prediction
! ? Exploration
? ! Optimization
? ! ! Inverse Design
Control*
? !
*) if system (model) is dynamic
6
In Figure 1.1 different tasks of systems analysis based on simulation mod-
els are displayed in a schematic way. Modeling means to identify the internal
structure of the simulation model. This is done by looking at the relationship
between known inputs and outputs of the system. In many cases, the inter-
nal structure of the system is already known up to a certain granularity and
only some parameters need to be identified. In this case we usually speak of
calibration of the simulation model instead of modeling. In control theory,
also the term identification is common.
Once a simulation-model of a system is given, we can simulate the sys-
tem, i.e. predict the state of the output variables for different input vectors.
Simulation can be used for predicting the output for not yet measured input
vectors. Usually such model-based predictions are much cheaper than to do
the experiment in the real world. Consider for example crash test simula-
tions or the simulation of wind channels. In many cases, such as for future
predictions, where time is the input variable, it is even impossible to do the
experiments in the physical world. Often the purpose of simulation is also
to learn more about the behavior of the systems. In this case systematic
experimenting is often used to study effects of different input variables and
combinations of them. The field of Design and Analysis of Computer Ex-
periments (DACE) is devoted to such systematic explorations of a systems
behavior.
Finally, we may want to optimize a system: In that case we basically
specify what the output of the system should be. We also are given a
simulation-model to do experiments with, or even the physical system it-
self. The relevant, open question is how to choose the input variables in
order to achieve the desired output. In optimization we typically want to
maximize (or minimize) the value of an output variable.
On the other hand, a very common situation in practice is the task of
adjusting the value of an output variable in a way that it is as close as possible
to a desired output value. In that case we speak about inverse design, or if
the system is dynamically changing, it may be classified as a optimal control
task. An example for an inverse design problem is given in airfoil design,
where a specified pressure profile around an airfoil should be achieved for
a given flight condition. An example for an optimal control task would be
to keep a process temperature of a chemical reactor as close to a specified
temperature as possible in a dynamically changing environment.
Note, that the inverse design problem can be reformulated as optimization
problem, as it aims at minimizing the deviation between the current state of
7
the output variables and the desired state.
In multi-objective optimization we look at the optimization of systems
w.r.t. more than one output variables. Single-objective optimization can be
considered as a special case of multi-objective optimization with only one
output variable.
Moreover, classically, multi-objective optimization problems are most of
the time reduced to single-objective optimization problems. We refer to these
reduction techniques as scalarization techniques. A chapter in this book is
devoted to this topic. Modern techniques, however, often aim at obtaining
a set of ’interesting’ solutions by means of so-called Pareto optimization
techniques. What is meant by this will be discussed in the remainder of this
chapter.
In this definition the objective function f states the main goal of the
optimization. It can be evaluated for each search point x in the search space.
8
Here the search space is defined by a set of intervals, that restrict the range
of variables, so called bounds or box constraints.
Whenever inequality and equality constraints are stated explicitly1 , the
search space X can be partitioned in a feasible search space Xf ⊆ X and
infeasible subspace X − Xf . In the feasible subspace all conditions stated in
the mathematical program are satisfied. The conditions in the mathematical
program are used to avoid constraint violations in the system under design,
e.g., the excess of a critical temperature or pressure in a chemical reactor
(an example for an inequality constraint), or the keeping of invariance of
mass, an example for an equality constraint). The conditions are called con-
straints. Due to a convention in the field of operations research, constraints
are written in a standardized form such that 0 appears on the right side.
Equations can easily be transformed into the standard form by means of
algebraic operations.
Based on this very general problem definition we can define several classes
of optimization problems, by looking at the characteristics of the functions
f , gi , i = 1, . . . , ng , and hi , i = 1, . . . , nh . Some important classes are listed
in the table below:
Note, that for LP, with the Simplex algorithm there exists a powerful
solution technique that, except in rare degenerate cases, solves problems in
polynomial running time. For all other problem classes the solution of the
general problem is assumed to be intractable. However, in many cases the
problems can be solved efficiently if some special structure of the function
can be exploited and/or the size of the program or search space is limited. In
other cases metaheuristics, such as simulated annealing, evolutionary algo-
rithms or tabu-search, may serve as tools to approximate optimal solutions
1
We do not consider box-constraints as inequality constraints here, as they are usually
treated differently by the algorithms.
9
in practice. We will later give a detailed description of some of these solution
methods.
Note that there are also other types of mathematical programs. For
instance programs that introduce uncertainties (fuzzy programs, stochastic
programs, parametric programs) or programs that are dealing with dynamic
data structures, such as parameterized trees and graphs. Moreover, the char-
acteristics of the functions give rise to many definitions of programs, such as
semi-definite programs, convex programs etc..
Moreover, in some cases, the framework of mathematical programs is too
restrictive. This holds in cases where we optimize complex structures, such
as the network topology of recurrent artificial neural networks, or steel joint
constructions in bridges. Here the set of solutions can hardly be described as
a vector. Rather network models like graph rewriting systems are appropriate
to describe the sets of solutions.
In order to capture also these kind of problems a more general definition
of a general optimization problem can be used:
At this point in time it is not clear, how to deal with situations with conflict-
ing objectives, e.g. when the solutions that minimize f1 are different from
those that minimize f2 . Note that the problem definition does not yet pre-
scribe how to compare different solutions. To discuss this we will introduce
some concepts from the theory of ordered sets, such as the Pareto dominance
relation, first.
10
1.3 Pareto domination and incomparability -
An informal example
A fundamental problem in multicriteria optimization and decision making is
to compare solutions w.r.t. different, possibly conflicting, goals. Before we
lay out the theory of orders in a more rigorous manner, we will introduce
some fundamental concepts by means of a simple example.
Consider the following decision problem: We have to select one car from
the following set of cars: For the moment, let us assume, that your goal is
to minimize the price and maximize speed and you do not care about other
components.
In that case we can clearly say that the BMW outperforms the Lincoln
stretch limousine, which is at the same time more expensive and slower then
the BMW. In such a situation we can decide clearly for the BMW. We say
that the first solution (Pareto) dominates the second solution. Note, that
the concept of Pareto domination is named after Vilfredo Pareto, an italian
economist and engineer who lived from 1848-1923 and who introduced this
concept for multi-objective comparisons.
Consider now the case, that you have to compare the BMW to the VW
Beetle. In this case it is not clear how to make a decision, as the beetle
outperforms the BMW in the cost objective, while the BMW outperforms
the VW Beetle in the speed objective. We say that the two solutions are
incomparable. Incomparability is a very common characteristic that occurs
in so-called partial ordered sets.
We can also observe, that the BMW is incomparable to the Ferrari, and
the Ferrari is incomparable to the VW Beetle. We say these three cars form
a set of mutually incomparable solutions. Moreover, we may state that the
Ferrari is incomparable to the Lincoln, and the VW Beetle is incomparable
to the Lincoln. Accordingly, also the VW Beetle, the Lincoln and the Ferrari
form a mutually incomparable set.
11
Another characteristic of a solution in a set can be that it is non-dominated
or Pareto optimal. This means that there is no other solution in the set
which dominates it. The set of all non-dominated solutions is called the
Pareto front. It might exist of only one solution (in case of non-conflicting
objectives) or it can even include no solution at all (this holds only for some
infinite sets). Moreover, the Pareto set is always a mutually incomparable
set. In the example this set is given by the VW Beetle, the Ferrari, and the
BMW.
An important task in multi-objective optimization is to identify the Pareto
front. Usually, if the number of objective is small and there are many alterna-
tives, this reduces the set of alternatives already significantly. However, once
the Pareto front has been obtained, a final decision has to be made. This
decision is usually made by interactive procedures where the decision maker
assesses trade-offs and sharpens constraints on the range of the objectives.
In the subsequent chapters we will discuss these procedures in more detail.
Turning back to the example, we will now play a little with the definitions
and thereby get a first impression about the rich structure of partially ordered
sets in Pareto optimization: What happens if we add a further objective to
the set of objectives in the car-example? For example let us assume, we also
would like to have a very big car and the size of the car is measured by its
length! It is easy to verify that the size of the non-dominated set increases,
as now the Lincoln is also incomparable to all other cars and thus belongs to
the non-dominated set. Later we will prove that introducing new objectives
will always increase the size of the Pareto front. On the other hand we may
define a constraint that we do not want a silver car. In this case the Lincoln
enters the Pareto front, since the only solution that dominates it leaves the
set of feasible alternatives. In general, the introduction of constraints may
increase or decrease Pareto optimal solutions or its size remains the same.
12
Note, that in the bi-criteria case this definition reduces to: y1 ≺P areto
(1) (2) (1) (2) (1) (2) (1) (2)
y2 :⇔ y1 < y1 ∧ y2 ≤ y2 ∨ y1 ≤ y1 ∧ y2 < y2 .
In addition to the domination ≺P areto we define further comparison op-
erators: y(1) P areto y(2) :⇔ y(1) ≺P areto y(2) ∨ y(1) = y(2) .
Moreover, we say y(1) is incomparable to y(2) (in symbols: y(1) ||y(2) ),if
and only if y(1) P areto y(2) ∧ y(1) P areto y(2) .
For technical reasons, we also define strict domination as: y(1) strictly
(1) (2)
dominates y(2) , iff ∀i = 1, . . . , m : yi < yi .
For any compact subset of Rm , say Y, there exists a non-empty set of
minimal elements w.r.t. the partial order (cf. [Ehr05, page 29]). Minimal
elements of this partial order are called non-dominated points. Formally, we
can define a non-dominated set via: YN = {y ∈ Y|∄y′ ∈ Y : y′ ≺Pareto y}.
Following a convention by Ehrgott [Ehr05] we use the index N to distinguish
between the original set and its non-dominated subset.
Having defined the non-dominated set and the concept of Pareto domina-
tion for general sets of vectors in Rm , we can now relate it to the optimization
task: The aim of Pareto optimization is to find the non-dominated set YN
for Y = f (X ) the image of X under f , the so-called Pareto front of the
multi-objective optimization problem.
We define XE as the inverse image of YN , i. e. XE = f −1 (YN ) . This set
will be called the efficient set of the optimization problem. Its members are
called efficient solutions.
For notational convenience, we will also introduce an order (which we call
prePareto) on the decision space via x(1) ≺preP areto x(2) ⇔ f (x(1) ) ≺P areto
f (x(2) ). Accordingly, we define x(1) preP areto x(2) ⇔ f (x(1) ) P areto f (x2 ).
Note, the minimal elements of this order are the efficient solutions, and the
set of all minimal elements is equal to XE .
Exercises
1. How does the introduction of a new solution influence the size of the
Pareto set? What happens if solutions are deleted? Prove your results!
13
3. Find examples for decision problems with multiple, conflicting objec-
tives! How is the search space defined? What are the constraints,
what are the objectives? How do these problems classify, w.r.t. the
classification scheme of mathematical programming? What are the
people-centric aspects of these problems?
14
Chapter 2
15
binary relation and some common axiomatic properties of binary relations
that are relevant for in the context of orders.
A binary relation R on some set S is defined as a subset of S × S. We
write x1 Rx2 ⇔ (x1 , x2 ) ∈ R.
2.2 Preorders
Next we will introduce preorders and some properties on them. Preorders are
a very general type of orders. Partial orders and linear orders are preorders
that obey additional axioms. Beside other reasons these types of orders are
16
important, because the Pareto order used in optimization defines a partial
order on the objective space and a pre-order on the search space.
17
2.3 Partial orders
Pareto domination imposes a partial order on a set of criterion vectors. The
definition of a partial order is more strict than that of a pre-order:
Example
A pre-ordered set that is not a partially ordered set is the set of complex
numbers C with the following precedence relation:
Example
An example for a partially ordered set is the subset relation ⊆ on the power
set1 ℘(S) of some finite set S. Reflexivity is given as A ⊆ A for all A ∈ ℘(S).
Transitivity is fulfilled, because A ⊆ B and B ⊆ C implies A ⊆ C, for all
triples (A, B, C) in ℘(S) × ℘(S) × ℘(S). Finally, antisymmetry is fulfilled,
since A ⊆ B and B ⊆ A implies A = B for all pairs (A, B) ∈ ℘(S) × ℘(S)
18
2.4 Linear orders and anti-chains
Perhaps the most well-known specializations of a partially ordered sets are
linear orders. Examples for linear orders are the ≤ relations on the set of
real numbers or integers. These types of orders play an important rôle in
single criterion optimization, while in the more general case of multiobjective
optimization we deal typically with partial orders that are not linear orders.
Let us now clarify what essentially distinguishes a linear order from a partial
order.
19
Definition 2.5.1 Covers relation
We say x1 is covered by x2 , in symbols x1 ⊳ x2 :⇔ x1 ≺pre x2 and x1 pre
x3 ≺pre x2 implies x1 = x3 .
An equivalent reformulation of the above definition is as follows: x2 covers
x1 iff no element lies strictly between x1 and x2 .
As an example, consider the covers relation on the linearly ordered set
(N, ≤). Here x1 ⊳ x2 , iff x2 = x1 + 1.
Another example would be the subset relation ⊆. In this example a set
A is covered by a set B if B contains precisely one additional element. In
Fig. 2.1 we summarized the subset relation.
A good description of the algorithm to draw a Hasse diagram has been
provided by Davey and Priestly [DP90, page 11]:
There are many ways of how to draw a Hasse diagram for a given order.
Davey and Priestly note that diagram-drawing is ’as much an science as
an art’. Good diagrams should provide an intuition for symmetries and
regularities, and avoid crossing edges.
20
{1,2,3,4}
Figure 2.1: The Hasse Diagram for the set of all non-empty subsets partially
ordered by means of ⊆.
21
Let us now define these concepts formally:
{sn }∞
1 = {1, 3, 19, 219, 4231, 130023, 6129859, 431723379, . . . } (2.1)
22
(X, 1 ) a (X, 2 ) c (X, 3 ) a (X, 4 ) a
b c
b c b c
c b
d a
d d
and the number of equivalence classes, i.e. classes that contain only isomor-
phic structures, denoted with Sn , evolves as:
{Sn }∞
1 = {1, 2, 5, 16, 63, 318, 2045, 16999, ...} (2.2)
. See Finch [6] for both of these results. This indicates how rapidly the
structural variety of orders grows with increasing n. Up to now, no closed
form expressions for the growth of the number of partial orders are known
[6].
s + S 2 instead of {s} + S 2 .
23
Definition 2.7.3 Minkowski Product
The Minkowski product of a scalar α ∈ Rn and a set S ⊂ Rn is defined
as αS := {αs|s ∈ S}.
Among the many properties that may be defined for a cone, we highlight
the following two:
• convex, iff αd1 + (1 − α)d2 ∈ C for all d1 and d2 ∈ C for all 0 < α < 1
Now, let us turn to cones that define (weak, strict) Pareto domination.
For this we have to define special convex cones in R:
24
f2 f2
x′
x1 x4
dominated space dominated space
x2
x x3
non-dominated space non-dominated space
f1 f1
Exercises
1. In definition 2.1.1 some common properties are defined that binary
relations can have and some examples are given below. Find further
examples from real-life for binary relations! Which axioms from defi-
nition 2.1.1 do they obey!
25
2. Characterize incomparability (definition 2.2.4) axiomatically! What
are the essential differences to indifference?
3. Describe the Pareto order on the set of 3-D hypercube edges {(0, 1, 0)T ,
(0, 0, 1)T , (1, 0, 0)T , (0, 0, 0)T , (0, 1, 1)T , (1, 0, 1), (1, 1, 0)T , (1, 1, 1)T } by
means of the graph of a binary relation and by means of the Hasse
diagram!
5. Prove that the time cone C + is convex! Compare the Pareto order to
the order defined by time cones!
26
Chapter 3
27
0001 0011 0111
0101
0010 1011
0110
0000 1111
1o1o
0100 1101
1001
Figure 3.1: The ’binland’ example for a discrete partially ordered landscape.
The left figure visualizes the Hamming neighborhood on {0, 1}4 as adjacency
graph.
28
Figure 3.2: Hasse diagram of the Pareto order for the leading ones trailing
zeros (LOTZ) problem. The first objective is to maximize the number of
leading ones in the bitstring, while the second objective is to maximize the
number of trailing zeros. The preorder on {0, 4}2 is then defined by the
Pareto dominance relation. In this example all local minima are also global
minima (compare figure 3.8).
29
The Pareto front YN is defined as the set of non-dominated solutions in
Y = f(X ), i. e. YN = {y ∈ Y | ∄y′ ∈ Y : y′ ≺ y}. The efficient set is
defined as the pre-image of the Pareto-front, XE = f −1 (YN ).
Note, that the cardinality XE is at least as big as YN , but not vice versa,
because there can be more than one point in XE with the same image in YN .
The elements of XE are termed efficient points.
In some cases it is more convenient to look at a direct definition of efficient
points:
30
x2 f2
2 f
2
efficient non−dominated
1
weakly non−dominated
1
weakly efficient
non−dominated
efficient
0
0 0 1 2
1 x1 f1
Figure 3.3: Example for a solution set containing weakly efficient solutions.
Example In Fig. 3.3 we graphically represent the efficient and weakly effi-
cient set of the following problem: f = (f1 , f2 ) → min, S = X = [0, 2] × [0, 2],
where f1 and f2 are as follows:
2 + x1 if 0 ≤ x2 < 1
f1 (x1 , x2 ) = , f2 (x1 , x2 ) = 1+x1 , x1 ∈ [0, 2], x2 ∈ [0, 2].
1 + 0.5x1 otherwise
. The solutions (x1 , x2 ) = (0, 0) and (x1 , x2 ) = (0, 1) are efficient solutions
of this problem, while the solutions on the line segments indicated by the
bold line segments in the figure denote weakly efficient solutions. Note, that
both efficient solutions are also weakly efficient, as efficiency implies weak
efficiency.
31
f2 Maximal point y
Y = f(X )
f1
Figure 3.4: Ideal points, Nadir point, and maximal point for a multi-objective
optimization problem.
For the Nadir only points from the Pareto front YN are considered, while
for the maximal point all points in Y are considered. The latter property
makes it, for dimensions higher than two (m > 2), more difficult to compute
the Nadir point. In that case the computation of the Nadir point cannot be
reduced to m single criterion optimizations.
A visualization of these entities in a 2-D space is given in figure 3.4.
32
Definition 3.5.2 Level curves
L= (f (x̂)) = {x ∈ X : f (x) = f (x̂)} (3.3)
Definition 3.5.3 Strict level set
L< (f (x̂)) = {x ∈ X : f (x) < f (x̂)} (3.4)
Level sets can be used to determine whether x̂ ∈ X is (strictly, weakly)
non-dominated or not.
The point x̂ can only be efficient if its level sets intersect in level curves.
T Tm
Theorem 3.5.4 x is efficient ⇔ m k=1 L ≤ (fk (x)) = k=1 L= (fk (x))
Proof: x̂ is efficient ⇔ there is no x such that both fk (x) ≤ fk (x̂) for all
k = 1, . . . , m and fk (x) < f (x̂) for at least one k = 1, . . . , m ⇔ there is no
m
x ∈ X such that both
T Tm x ∈ ∩k=1 L≤ (f (x̂)) and x ∈ L< (fj (x̂)) for some j ⇔
m
k=1 L≤ (fk (x̂)) = k=1 L= (fk (x̂))
Theorem 3.5.5 The point x̂ can only be weakly Tm efficient if its strict level
sets do not intersect. x is weakly efficient ⇔ k=1 L< (fk (x)) = ∅
Theorem 3.5.6 The point x̂ can only be strictly efficientT if its level sets
intersect in exactly one point. x is strictly efficient ⇔ mk=1 ≤ (fk (x)) = {x}
L
Level sets have a graphical interpretation that helps to geometrically un-
derstand optimality conditions and landscape characteristics. Though this
intuitive geometrical interpretation may only be viable for lower dimensional
spaces, it can help to develop intuition about problems in higher dimensional
spaces. The visualization of level sets can be combined with the visualization
of constraints, by partitioning the search space into a feasible and infeasible
part.
The following examples will illustrate the use of level sets for visualization:
Example Consider the problem f1 (x1 , x2 ) = (x1 −1.75)2 +4(x2 −1)2 → min,
f2 (x1 , x2 ) = (x1 − 3)2 + (x2 − 1)2 → min, (x1 , x2 )⊤ ∈ R2 . The level curves of
this problem are depicted in Figure 3.5 together with the two marked points
p1 and p2 that we will study now. For p1 it gets clear from Figure 3.6 that
it is an efficient point as it cannot be improved in both objective function
values at the same time. On the other hand p2 is no level point as by moving
it to the region directly left of it can be improved in all objective function
values at the same time. Formally, the existence of such a region follows from
the non-empty intersection of L< (f1 (p2 )) and L< (f2 (p2 )).
33
x2
p1 p2
1
f2 ≡ 0.5
f1 ≡ 1 f2 ≡ 1
f1 ≡ 2 f2 ≡ 2
f1 ≡ 3 f2 ≡ 3
0 1 2 3 x1
x2
p1
1 L≤ (f1 (p1 )) L≤ (f2 (p1 ))
f1 ≡ 1 f2 ≡ 1
0 1 2 3 x1
Figure 3.6: The situation for p1 . In order to improve f1 the point p1 has to
move into the set L≤ (f1 (p1 )) and in order to improve f2 it needs to move into
L≤ (f1 (p1 )). Since these sets only meet in p1 , it is not possible to improve f1
and f2 at the same time.
34
x2
2 11111111111111111
00000000000000000
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
p2
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111 f2 ≡ 3
1 11111111111111111
00000000000000000
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
f1 ≡ 1
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
f2 ≡ 2
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
f2 ≡ 1
00000000000000000
11111111111111111 p1
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
f1 ≡ 2
00000000000000000
11111111111111111
00000000000000000
11111111111111111 x1
0 1 2 3
Example Consider the search space S = [0, 2] × [0, 3]. Two objectives
f1 (x1 , x2 ) = 2 + 13 x2 − x1 → min, f2 (x1 , x2 ) = 21 x2 + 12 x1 → max, In
addition the constraint g(x1 , x2 ) = − 23 x1 − x2 ≥ 0 needs to be fulfilled. To
solve this problem, we mark the constrained region graphically. Now, we can
check different points for efficiency. For p1 the region where both objectives
improve is in the upper triangle bounded by the level curves. As this set is
partly feasible, it is possible to find a dominating feasible point and p1 is not
efficient. In contrast, for p2 the set of dominating solutions is completely in
the infeasible domain, why this point belongs to the efficient set. The com-
plete efficient set in this example lies on the constraint boundary. Generally,
it can be found that for linear problems with level curves intersecting in a sin-
gle point there exists no efficient solutions in the unconstrained case whereas
efficient solutions may lie on the constraint boundary in the constrained case.
35
of nearest neighbors can be defined by means of some neighborhood function
N : X → ℘(X) with ∀x ∈ X : x 6∈ N(x). As an example consider the space
{0, 1}n of bit-strings of length n with the nearest neigbors of a bit-string x
being the elements that differ only in a single bit, i.e. that have a Hamming
distance of 1.
36
y 3 = 11 y 7 = 14 y 3 = 2, 1 y 7 = 2, 2
x(3) = 011 x(7) = 111 x(3) = 011 x(7) = 111
y 1 = 11 y 5 = 12 y 1 = 1, 2 y 5 = 5, 4
y 2 = 11 y 6 = 10 y 2 = 0, 3 y 6 = 1, 2
x(2) = 010 x(6) = 110 x(2) = 010 x(6) = 110
y0 = 0 y 4 = 15 y 0 = 2, 2 y 4 = 1, 5
x(0) = 000 x(4) = 100 x(0) = 000 x(4) = 100
Figure 3.7: Pseudoboolean landscapes with search space {0, 1}3 and the
Hamming neighborhood defined on it. The linearly ordered landscape on
the right hand side has three local optima. These are x(0) = 000, x(4) =
100, x(7) = 111. x(0) is also a global minimum and x(4) a global maximum.
The partially ordered landscape on the right hand side has locally efficient
solutions are x(1) = 001, x(2) = 010, x(3) = 011, x(6) = 110. The globally
efficient solutions are x(1) , x(2) and x(3)
37
3.7 Barrier Structures
Local optima are just one of the many characteristics we may discuss for land-
scapes, i.e. functions with a neighborhood structure defined on the search
space. Looking at different local optimal of a landscape we may ask ourselves
how these local optimal are separated from each other. Surely there is some
kind of barrier in between, i.e. in order to reach one local optimum from the
other following a path of neighbors in the search space we need to put up with
encountering worsening of solutions along the path. We will next develop a
formal framework on defining barriers and their characteristics and highlight
an interesting hierarchical structure that can be obtained for all landscapes
- the so called barrier tree of totally ordered landscapes, which generalizes to
a barrier forest in partially ordered landscapes.
For the sake of clarity let us introduce formal definitions first for land-
scapes with a one-dimensional height function as they are discussed in single-
objective optimization.
Definition 3.7.3 Let Px1 ,x2 denote the set of all paths between x1 and x2 .
Definition 3.7.4 Let the function value of the lowest point separating two
local minima x1 and x2 be defined as fˆ(x1 , x2 ) = minp∈Px1 ,x2 maxx3 ∈p f (x3 ).
Points s on some path p ∈ Px1 ,x2 for which f (s) = fˆ(x1 , x2 ) are called saddle
points between x1 and x2 .
Example In the example given in Figure 3.8 the search points are labeled
by their heights, i.e. x1 has height 1 and x4 has height 4. The saddle point
between the local minima x1 and x2 is x12 . The saddle point x3 and x5 is
x18 .
38
Figure 3.8: Example of a discrete landscape. The height of points is given
by the numbers and their neighborhood is expressed by the edges.
Lemma 3.7.5 For non-degenerate landscapes, i.e. landscapes where for all
x1 and x2 : f (x1 ) 6= f (x2 ), saddle points between two given local optima are
unique.
Note. that in case of degenerate landscapes, i.e. landscapes where there
are at least two different points which share the same value of the height
function, saddle points between two given local optima are not necessarily
unique anymore, which, as we will see later, influences the uniqueness of
barrier trees characterizing the overall landscape.
Definition 3.7.6 The valley (or: basin) below a point s is called B(s) :
B(s) = {x ∈ S|∃p ∈ Px,s : maxz∈p f (z) ≤ f (s)}
Example In the aforementioned example given in Figure 3.8, Again, search
points x1 , . . . , x20 are labeled by their heights, i.e. x4 is the point with height
4, etc.. The basin below x1 is given by the empty set, and the basin below
x14 is {x1 , x11 , x4 , x9 , x7 , x13 , x5 , x8 }.
Points in B(s) are mutually connected by paths that never exceed f (s).
At this point it is interesting to compare the level set L≤ (f (x)) with the
39
basin B(x). The connection between both concepts is: Let B be the set of
connected components of the level set L≤ (f (x)) with regard to the neighbor-
hood graph of the search space X , then B(x) is the connected component in
which x resides.
Theorem 3.7.7 Suppose for two points x1 and x2 that f (x1 ) ≤ f (x2 ).
Then, either B(x1 ) ⊆ B(x2 ) or B(x1 ) ∩ B(x2 ) = Ø.
Theorem 3.7.7 implies that the barrier structure of a landscapes can be
represented as a tree where the saddle points are the branching points and
the local optima are the leaves. The flooding algorithm (see Algorithm 2) can
be used for the construction of the barrier tree in discrete landscapes with
finite search space X and linearly ordered search points (e.g. by means of the
objective function values). Note, that if the height function is not injective
the flooding algorithm can still be used but the barrier tree may not be
uniquely defined. The reason for this is that there are different possibilities
of how to sort elements with equal heights in line 1 of algorithm 2.
Finally, let us look whether concepts such as saddle points, basins, and
barrier trees can be generalized in a meaningful way for partially ordered
landscapes. Flamm and Stadler [8] recently proposed one way of generalizing
these concepts. We will review their approach briefly and refer to the paper
for details.
Adjacent points in linearly ordered landscapes are always comparable.
This does not hold in general for partially ordered landscapes. We have to
modify the paths p that enter the definition.
40
Figure 3.9: A barrier tree of a 1-D continuous function.
41
Algorithm 2 Flooding algorithm
1: Let x(1) , . . . , x(N ) denote the elements of the search space sorted in as-
cending order.
2: i → 1; B = ∅
3: while i ≤ N do
4: if N(xi ) ∩ {x(1) , . . . , x(i−1) } = ∅ [i. e., x(i) has no neighbour that has
been processed.] then
5: {x(i) is local minimum}
6: Draw x(i) as a new leaf representing basin B(x(i) ) located at the
height of f in the 2-D diagram
7: B ← B ∪ {B(x(i) )} {Update set of basins}
8: else
9: Let T (x(i) ) = {B(x(i1 ) ), . . . , B(x(iN ) )} be the set of basins B ∈ B
with N(x(i) ) ∩ B 6= ∅.
10: if |T (x(i) )| = 1 then
11: B(x(i1 ) ) ← B(x(i1 ) ) ∪ {x(i) }
12: else
13: {x(i) is a saddle point}
14: Draw x(i) as a new branching point connecting the nodes for
B(x(i1 ) ), . . . , B(x(iN ) ). Annotate saddle point node with B(x(i) )
and locate it at the height of f in the 2-D diagram
15: {Update set of basins}
16: B(x(i) ) = B(x(i1 ) ) ∪ · · · ∪ B(x(iN ) ) ∪ {x(i) }
17: Remove B(x(i1 ) ), . . . , B(x(iN ) ) from B
18: B ← B ∪ {B(x(i) )}
19: end if
20: end if
21: end while
42
Figure 3.10: Different shapes of Pareto fronts for bi-criteria problems.
43
orthant, iff YN − Rm
≥ is a convex set.
44
Lemma 3.8.5 Dimension of the Pareto front
Pareto fronts for problems with m-objectives are subsets or equal to m−1-
dimensional manifolds.
Example For a problem with three objectives the Pareto front is a subset
of a 2-D manifold that can be represented as a function from the values of
the
45
Chapter 4
46
Figure 4.1: Level curves of a continuously differentiable function. Locally
the function ’appears’ to be a linear function with parallel level curves. The
gradient vector ∇f (x̂) is perpendicular to the local direction of the level
curves at x̂.
47
3)2 + y 2 + exp y the bound of the function is zero and every argument for
which the function reaches the value of zero must be a global optimum. As
the function is differentiable the global optimum will be also be one of the
stationary points. Therefore we can find the global optimum in this case by
looking at all stationary points. A more general way of looking at boundaries
in the context of optimum seeking is given by the Theorem of Weierstrass
discussed in [9]. This theorem is also useful for proving the existence of an
optimum. This is discussed in detail in [1].
For a rigorous proof of this theorem we refer to [1]. Let us remark, that the
discovery of this theorem by Lagrange preceded its proof by one hundred
years [1].
Next, by means of an example we will provide some geometric intuition
for this theorem. In Fig. 4.2 a problem with a search space of dimension two
is given. A single objective function f has to be maximized, and the sole
constraint function g1 (x) is set to 0.
1
Roughly speaking, a closed set is a set which includes all points at its boundary.
48
x2
−15
−14
−13
∇g1 (x∗ )
x∗
f ≡ const
∗
∇f (x )
g ≡ const
x1
Figure 4.2: Lagrange multipliers: Level-sets for a single objective and single
active constraint and search space R2 .
Let us first look at the level curve f ≡ −13. This curve does not intersect
with the level curve g ≡ 0 and thus there is no feasible solution on this curve.
Next, we look at f ≡ −15. In this case the two curve intersects in two points
with g ≡ 0. However, these solutions are not optimal. We can do better
by moving to the point, where the level curve of f ≡ c ’just’ intersects with
g ≡ 0. This is the tangent point x∗ with c = f (x∗ ) = −14.
The tangential point satisfies the condition that the gradient vectors are
collinear to each other, i.e. ∃λ 6= 0 : λ∇g(x∗) = ∇f (x∗ ). In other words, the
tangent line to the f level curve at a touching point is equal to the tangent
line to the g ≡ 0 level curve. Equality of tangent lines is equivalent to the
fact that the gradient vectors are collinear.
Another way to reason about the location of optima is to check for each
point on the constraint curve whether it can be locally improved or not.
For points where the level curve of the objective function intersects with
49
the constraint function, we consider the local linear approximation of the
objective function. In case of non-zero gradients, we can always improve the
point further. In case of zero gradients we already fulfill conditions of the
theorem by setting λ1 = 1 and λi = 0 for i = 2, . . . , m + 1. This way we can
exclude all points but the tangential points and local minima of the objective
function (unconstrained) from consideration.
In practical optimization often λ1 is set to 1. Then the equations in the
lagrange multiplier theorem boil down to an equation system with m + n
unknowns and m + n equations and this gives rise to a set of candidate
solutions for the problem. This way of solving an optimization problem is
called the Lagrange multiplier rule.
50
Example Consider the following problem:
g(x1 , x2 ) = x1 + x2 − 1 = 0 (4.5)
Due to the theorem of 4.3.1, iff (x1 , x2 )⊤ is a local optimum, then there exist
λ1 and λ2 with (λ1 , λ2 ) 6= (0, 0) such that the constraint in equation 4.5 is
fulfilled and
∂f ∂g
λ1 + λ2 = 2λ1 x1 + λ2 = 0 (4.6)
∂x1 ∂x1
∂f ∂g
λ1 + λ2 = 2λ1 x2 + λ2 = 0 (4.7)
∂x2 ∂x2
Let us first examine the case λ1 = 0. This entails:
λ2 = 0 (4.8)
2x1 + λ2 = 0 (4.11)
2x2 + λ2 = 0 (4.12)
51
f(x1,x2)
0.4
0.35
0.3
0.4 0.25
0.35 0.2
0.3
0.25 0.15
0.2 0.1
0.15 0.05
0.1 0
0.05 -0.05
0 -0.1
-0.05 -0.15
-0.1
-0.15
0.4
0.2
-0.4 0
-0.2 x2
0 -0.2
x1 0.2 -0.4
0.4
Figure 4.3: The level curves of x21 − x32 . The level curve through (0, 0)T is
cusp.
and hence x1 = x2 . From the equality condition we get: From the constraint
it follows x1 + x1 = 1, which entails x1 = x2 = 12 .
Another possibility to solve this problem is by means of substitution:
x1 = 1 − x2 and the objective function can then be written as f (1 − x2 , x2 ) =
(1 −x2 )2 + x22 . Now minimize the unconstrained ’substitute’ function h(x2 ) =
(1 − x2 )2 + x22 . ∂h
x2
= −2(1 − x2 ) + 2x2 = 0. This yields x2 = 12 . The second
∂2f
derivative ∂ 2 x2
= 4. This means that the point is a local minimum.
However, not always all candidate solutions for local optima are captured
this way as the case λ1 = 0 may well be relevant. Brinkhuis and Tikhomirov
[1] give an example of such a ’bad’ case:
Example Apply the multiplier rule to f0 (x) → min, x21 − x32 = 0: The
Lagrange equations hold at x̂ with λ0 = 0 and λ1 = 1. An interesting
observation is that the level curves are cusp in this case at x̂, as visualized
in Fig. 4.3.
52
4.4 Inequality Constraints
For inequality constraints the Karush Kuhn Tucker conditions are used as
optimality criterion:
Theorem 4.4.1 The Karush Kuhn Tucker conditions are said to hold for
x∗ , if there exist multipliers λ1 ≥ 0, . . . , λm+1 ≥ 0 and at least one λi > 0
for i = 1, . . . , m + 1, such that:
m
X
∗
λ1 ∇f (x ) + λi+1 ∇gi (x∗ ) = 0 (4.13)
i=1
Theorem 4.4.3 The KKT conditions are sufficient for optimiality, provided
λ1 = 1. In this case x∗ is a local minimum.
Note that if x∗ is in the interior of the feasible region (a Slater point), all
gi (x) < 0 and thus λ1 > 0.
The next examples discuss the usage of the Karush Kuhn conditions:
subject to constraints
g1 (x) = −x − 1 ≤ 0 (4.17)
g2 (x) = x − 3 ≤ 0 (4.18)
53
The existence of the optimum follows from Weierstrass theorem, as (1) the
feasible subspace [-1,3] is bounded and closed and (2) the objective function
is continuous.
The KKT conditions in this case boil down to: There exists λ1 ∈ R, λ2 ∈
R0 and λ3 ∈ R+
+
0 and (λ1 , λ2 , λ3 ) 6= (0, 0, 0) such that
∂f ∂g1 ∂g1
λ1 + λ2 + λ3 = −2λ1 x − λ2 + λ3 = 0 (4.19)
∂x ∂x ∂x
λ2 (−x − 1) = 0 (4.20)
λ3 (x − 3) = 0 (4.21)
.
First, let us check whether λ1 = 0 can occur:
In this case the three equations (4.19, 4.20, and 4.21) will be:
−λ2 + λ3 = 0 (4.22)
λ2 (−x − 1) = 0 (4.23)
λ3 (x − 3) = 0 (4.24)
.
and (λ2 , λ3 ) 6= (0, 0), and λi ≥ 0, i = 2, 3. From 4.22 we see that λ2 = λ3 .
By setting λ = λ2 we can write
λ(−x − 1) = 0 (4.25)
and
λ(x − 3) = 0 (4.26)
for the equations 4.23 and 4.24. Moreover λ 6= 0, for (λ, λ) = (λ2 , λ3 ) 6= (0, 0).
From this we get that −x − 1 = 0 and x − 3 = 0. Which is a contradiction so
the case λ1 = 0 cannot occur – later we shall see that this could have derived
by using a theorem on Slater points 4.4.3.
Next we consider the case λ1 6= 0 (or equivalently λ1 = 1): In this case the
three equations (4.19, 4.20, and 4.21) will be:
−2x − λ2 + λ3 = 0 (4.27)
,
λ2 (−x − 1) = 0 (4.28)
54
, and
λ3 (x − 3) = 0 (4.29)
We consider four subcases:
λ ≻ 0, υ ≻ 0 (4.30)
k
X m
X
λi ∇fi (x∗ ) − υi ∇gi(x∗ ) = 0. (4.31)
i=1 i=1
∗
υi gi (x ) = 0, i = 1, . . . , m (4.32)
55
Figure 4.4: Level curves of the two objectives touching in one point indicate
locally Pareto optimal points in the bi-criterion case, provided the functions
are differentiable.
56
Chapter 5
Scalarization Methods
• Can all solutions on the Pareto front be obtained by varying the (weight)
parameters of the aggregate function?
Section 5.1 starts with linear aggregation (weighted sum) and answers
the aforementioned questions for it. The insights we gain from the linear
case prepare us for the generalization to nonlinear aggregation in Section 5.2.
The expression or modeling of preferences by means of of aggregate functions
is a broad field of study called Multi-attribute utility theory (MAUT). An
overview and examples are given in Section 5.3. A common approach to
solve multicriteria optimization problems is the distance to a reference point
57
method. Here the decision pointer defines an desired ’utopia’ point and
minimizes the distance to it. In Section 5.4 we will discuss this method as a
special case of a scalarization technique.
Another question that arises is, whether we can find all points on the Pareto
front using linear aggregation and varying the weights or not. The following
theorem provides the answer. To state the the theorem, we need the following
definition:
58
Figure 5.1: The proper Pareto front for a bicriteria problem, for which in
addition to many proper Pareto optimal solutions there exist also two non-
proper Pareto optimal solutions.
Note, that in the bi-criterion case, the efficient points which are Pareto op-
timal in the Geoffrion sense are those points on the Pareto-front, where the
slope of the Pareto front (f2 expressed as a function of f1 ) is finite and non-
zero (see Fig. 5.1). The parameter M is interpreted as trade-off. The proper
Pareto optimal points can thus be viewed as points with a bounded tradeoff.
Example In Fig. 5.2 the Pareto fronts of two different bi-criterion problems
are shown. The figure on the right hand side shows a Pareto front which is
cone convex with respect to the positive orthant. Here the tangential points
of the level curves of w1 y1 + w2 y2 are the solutions obtained with linear
59
Figure 5.2: The concave (left) and convex Pareto front (right).
60
In order to discuss a scalarization method it may be interesting to an-
alyze where on the Pareto front the Pareto optimal solution that is found
by maximizing the utility function is located. Similar to the linear weight-
ing function discussed earlier, this is the point where the level curves of the
utility (looked upon in descending order) first intersect with the Pareto front
(see Fig. 5.4).
Example Consider you want to buy a car. Then you may focus on three ob-
jectives: speed, price, fuel-consumption. These three criteria can be weighted.
It is often not wise to measure the contribution of an objective function to
the overall utility in a linear way. A elegant way to model it is by specifying a
function that measures the degree of satisfaction. For each possible value of
the objective function we specify the degree of satisfaction of this solution on
a scale from 0 to 10 by means of a so-called value function. In case of speed,
we may demand that a car is faster than 80m/mph but beyond a speed of,
say, 180 km/h the increase of our satisfaction with the car is marginal, as we
will not have many occasions where driving as this speed gives us advantages.
It can also be the case, that the objective is to be minimized. As an example,
we consider the price of the car. The budget that we are allowed to spend
marks an upper bound for the point where the value function obtains a value
of zero. Typically, our satisfaction will grow if the price is decreased until a
critical point, where we may no longer trust that the solution is sold for a
fair price and we may get suspicious of the offer.
The art of the game is then to sum up these objectives to a single util-
ity function. One approach is as follows: Given value functions vi : R →
[0, 10], i = 1, . . . , m mapping objective function values to degree of satisfac-
tion values, and their weights wi , i = 1, . . . , m, we can construct the following
optimization problem with constraints:
61
Figure 5.3: Utility function for a bi-criterion problem. If the decision-maker
has modeled this utility function in a proper way, he/she will be indifferent
whether to choose y(2) and y(3) , but prefer y(3) and y(2) to y(1) .
Figure 5.4: The tangential point of the Pareto front with the indifference
curves of the utility function U here determines where the solution of the
maximization of the utility function lies on the Pareto front.
62
Figure 5.5: The components (value functions) of a multiattribute utility
function.
m
1 X
U(f(x)) = α wi vi (fi (x)) +β min wi vi (fi (x)), (5.4)
m i=1 i∈{1,...,m}
| {z } | {z }
common interest minority interest
(here: m = 3) (5.5)
s. t. vi (fi (x)) > 0, i = 1, . . . , m (5.6)
Here, we have one term that looks for the ’common interest’. This term can
be comparably high if some of the value functions have a very high value
and others a very small value. In order to enforce a more balanced solutions
w.r.t. the different value functions, we can also consider to focus on the value
function which is least satisfied. In order to discard values from the search
space, solution candidates with a value function of zero are considered as
infeasible by introducing strict inequality constraints.
A very similar approach is the use of desirability indices. They have
been first proposed by Harrington [13] for applications in industrial quality
management. Another well known reference for this approach is [14].
We first give a rough sketch of the method, and then discuss its formal
details.
As in the previously described approach, we map the values of the ob-
jective function to satisfaction levels, ranging from not acceptable (0) to to-
tally satisfied (1). The values in between 0 and one indicate the grey areas.
Piecewise defined exponential functions are used to describe the mappings.
They can be specified by means of three parameters. The mapped objective
function values are now called desirability indices. Harrington proprosed to
aggregate these desirability indices by a product expression, the minimization
of which leads to the solution of the multiobjective problem.
63
The functions used for the mapping of objective function values to desir-
ability indices are categorized into one-sided and two sided functions. Both
have a parameter yimin (lower specification limit), yimax (upper specification
limit), li , ri (shape parameters), and ti (symmetry center). The one-sided
functions read:
0,
yi < yimin
min
li
yi −yi
Di = min , yimin < yi < ti (5.7)
ti −yi
1, yi ≥ ti
The two plots in Fig. 5.6 visualize one-sided (l) and two-sided (r) desirability
indexes.
64
1.5 1.5
f(x) l=0.5
f(x) l=1
l=1.5 l=1.5
1 1
D(y)
D(y)
0.5 0.5
0 0
-0.5 -0.5
-1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5
y y
Figure 5.6: In the left figure we see and examples for one-sided desirability
function with parameters y min = −1, y max = 1, l ∈ {0.5, 1, 1.5}. The left
side displays a plot of two sided desirability functions for parameters y min =
−1.y max = 1, l ∈ {0.5, 1.0, 1.5}, and r being set to the same value than l.
The aggregation of the desirability indices is done by means of a product
formula, that is to be maximized:
k
Y 1
D = ( Di (yi )) k (5.9)
i=1
65
In literature many approaches for constructing non-linear utility functions
are discussed.
The Cobbs Douglas utility function is widely used in economy. Let fi , i =
1, . . . , m denote non-negative objective functions, then the Cobbs Douglas
utility function reads:
Ym
U(x) = fi (x)αi (5.10)
i=1
It is important to note, that for the Cobbs Douglas utility function the objec-
tive function values are to be minimized, while the utility is to be maximized.
Indeed, the objective function values, the values αi , and the utility have usu-
ally an economic interpretation, such as the amount of goods: fi , the utility
of a combination of goods: U, and the elasticities of demand: αi . A useful
observation is that taking the logarithm of this function transforms it into a
linear expression:
m
X
log U(x) = αi log fi (x) (5.11)
i=1
The linearity can often be exploited to solve problems related to this utility
function analytically.
A more general approach for construction of utility functions is the Keeney
Raiffa utility function approach [12]. Let fi denote non-negative objective
functions: m
Y
U(x) = K (wi ui (fi (x)) + 1) (5.12)
i=1
Here wi are weights for the objective functions between 0 and 1 and K denotes
a positive scaling constant. Moreover, ui denote functions that are strictly
increasing for positive input values. A general remark on how to construct
utility functions is, that the optimization of these functions should lead to
Pareto optimal solutions. This can be verified by checking the monotonicity
condition for a given utility function U:
This condition can be easily verified for the two given utility functions.
66
5.4 Distance to a Reference Point Methods
A special class of utility functions is the distance to the reference point (DRP)
method. Here the user specifies an ideal solution (or: utopia point) in the
objective space. Then the goal is to get as close as possible to this ideal
solution. The distance to the ideal solution can be measured by some distance
function, for example a weighted Minkowski distance with parameter γ. This
is defined as:
Xm
1
′
d(y, y ) = [ wi|yi − yi′ |γ ] γ , γ ≥ 1, w1 > 0, . . . , wm > 0 (5.14)
i=1
Here, wi are positive weights that can be used to normalize the objective
function values. In order to analyze which solution is found by means of
a DRP method we can interpret the distance to the reference point as an
utility function (with the utility value to be minimized). The indifference
curves in case of γ = 2 are spheres (or ellipsoids) around the utopia point.
For γ > 2 one obtains different super-ellipsoids as indifference curves. Here,
a super-ellipsoid around the utopia point f ∗ of radius r ≥ 0 is defined as a
set:
S(r) = {y ∈ Rm |d(y, f ∗) = r} (5.15)
with d : Rm × Rm → R+
0 being a weighted distance function as defined in Eq.
5.14.
Not always an efficient point is found when using the DRP method. How-
ever, in many practical cases the following sufficient condition can be used
in order to make sure that the DRP method yields an efficient point. This
condition is summarized in the following lemma:
67
Figure 5.7: Optimal points obtained for two distance to DRP methods, using
the weighted Euclidean distance (left) and the manhattan distance (right).
we can obtain all points on the Pareto front by optimizing the distance for
different weights wi . In more detail, the following condition is satisfied:
68
Figure 5.8: In the left figure we see and example for a utopia point which is
non-dominated by the image set but the corresponding DRP method does
not yield a solution on the Pareto front. In the right figure we see an example
where an utopia point is dominated by some points of the image set, but the
corresponding DRP method yields a solution on the Pareto front.
69
Figure 5.9: In the left figure we see and example where an non-dominated
point is obtained using a DRP with the Tschebychev distance. In the
right figure we see an example where also dominated solutions minimize the
Tschebychev distance to the reference point. In these cases a non-dominated
solution may be missed by this DRP method if it returns some single solution
minimizing the distance.
70
Chapter 6
This chapter will highlight two common approaches for transforming Mul-
ticriteria into Constrained Single-Criterion Problems. In Compromise Pro-
gramming (or ǫ-Constraint Method), m − 1 of the m objectives are trans-
formed into constraints. Another approach is put forward in the so-called
goal attainment and goal programming method. Here a target vector is spec-
ified (similar to the distance to a reference point methods), and a direction
is specified. The method searches for the best feasible point in the given
direction. For this a costraint programming task is solved.
71
Figure 6.1: Compromise Programming in the bi-criteria case. The second
objective is transformed into a constraint.
In figure 6.1 the method is visualized for the bi-criteria case (m = 2). Here,
it can be seen that if the constraint boundary shares points with the Pareto
front, these points will be the solutions to the problem in Eq. 6.2. Otherwise,
it is the solution that is the closest solution to the constraint boundary among
all solutions on the Pareto-front. In many cases the solutions are obtained
at points x where all objective function values fi (x) are equal to ǫi for i =
1, . . . , m. In these cases, we can obtain optimal solutions using the Lagrange
Multiplier method discussed in chapter 4. Not in all cases the solutions we
obtain with the compromise programming method are Pareto optimal. An
example for a problematic case is given in figure 6.2.
The compromise programming method can be used to approximate the
Pareto front. For a m dimensional problem a m−1 dimensional grid needs to
be computed that cover the m−1 dimensional projection of the bounding box
of the Pareto front. Due to Lemma 3.8.6 given m − 1 coordinates of a Pareto
front, the m-th coordinate is uniquely determined as the minimum of that
coordinate among all image vectors that have the m − 1 given coordinates.
As an example, in a 3-D case (see Figure 6.3) we can place points on a grid
72
Figure 6.2: Problematic case for the compromise programming method in
3-D. The cheese-like cylinder denotes the image set f(X ). The Constraint
boundaries are indicated by planes. Note that all objectives are to be max-
imized. Two of the infinitely many solutions in the image set that qualify
as solutions of the constrained problem are indicated by black points. The
black point on the right hand side f ∗ ′ dominates the black point on the left
hand side f ∗ .
73
Figure 6.3: Compromised Programming used for approximating the Pareto
front with 3 objectives.
stretching out from the minimal point (f1min , f1max ) to the maximal point
(f2min , f2max ) . It is obvious that, if the grid resolution is kept constant,
the effort of this method grows exponentially with the number of objective
functions m.
This method for obtaining a Pareto front approximation is easier to con-
trol than the to use weighted scalarization and change the weights gradually.
However, the knowledge of the ideal and the Nadir point is needed to com-
pute the approximation, and the computation of the Nadir point is a difficult
problem in itself.
74
6.2 Concluding remarks on single point meth-
ods
In the last two chapters various approaches have been discussed to reformu-
late a multiobjective problem into a single-objective or a constrained single-
objective problem. The methods discussed have in common that they result
in a single point, why they also are referred to as single point methods.
In addition, all single point methods have parameters the choice of which
determines the location of the optimal solution. Each of this methods has,
as we have seen, some unique characteristics and it different to give a global
comparison of them. However, a criterion that can be assessed for all single
point methods is, whether they are always resulting in Pareto optimal solu-
tions. Moreover, we investigated whether by changing their parameters all
points on the Pareto front can be obtained.
To express this in a more formal way we may denote a single point method
by a function A : P × C 7→ Rm ∪ {Ω}, where P denotes the space of multi-
objective optimization problems, C denotes the parameters of the method
(e.g. the weights in linear weighting). In order to classify a method A we
introduce the following two definitions:
75
Single Point Method Proper Exhaustive Remarks
Linear Weighting Yes No Exhaustive for convex Pareto
fronts with only
proper Pareto optima
Weighted Euclidean DRP No No Proper if reference
point dominates all
Pareto optimal points
Weighted Tschebyschev DRP No Yes Weakly non-dominated
points can be obtained,
even when reference
point dominates all
Pareto optimal points
Desirability index No No The classification of
proper/exhaustive is
not relevant in this case.
Goal programming No No For convex and concave
Pareto fronts with the method
is proper and exhaustive if the reference
point dominates all
Pareto optimal solutions
Compromise programming No Yes In two dimensional objective spaces
the method is proper.
Weakly dominated points
may qualify as solutions
for more than three
dimensional objective
spaces
76
Part I
77
Chapter 7
78
If certain conditions are met, systematic ways to generate neighboring
points can be derived. In all cases the connectedness of the Pareto front (in
the objective space) is assumed. In addition we assume that one connected
component of the efficient set will cover the Pareto front.
Next, we will discuss one particular continuation method which will pro-
vide all points of a convex 2-D Pareto front.
The idea is to first compute with a single-objective optimization method
the two extreme points on the Pareto front, say
and
x(1) = arg minn f2 (x) (7.2)
x∈R
, where
x(λt + ǫ) = arg minn (1 − λt − ǫ)f1 (x) + (λt + ǫ)f2 (x) (7.6)
x∈R
ṽ
and ǫ is an appropriately small positive number. The normalized v := ||ṽ||
is
used as the search direction.
79
Let F = (f1 , f2 ). We proceed to compute the step size h ∈ R+ along v
in the decision space xt+1 = xt + hv such that ||F (xt ) − F (xt+1 ||∞ = Θ∆
(where Θ ∈ (0, 1) is a safety factor). In case F is Lipschitz continuous we
know that there exists an L ≥ 0 such that
Combining 7.7 and 7.8, using h = ||xt − xt+1 ||, and assuming h is sufficiently
small, we obtain the following estimate:
Θ∆
h≈ (7.9)
Lxt
We can now state how to find the next Pareto optimal point xt+1 . Apply
the ǫ-constraint method where the constant ǫ is computed as the second
coordinate of the expression
From which we get: xt+1 := arg min f1 (x) such that f2 (x) = ǫ.
80
Bibliography
[9] Jozef Bialas and Namakura Shinshu: The Theorem of Weierstrass, Jour-
nal of Formalized Mathematics, Volume 7 (Online).
[11] A. Götz and J. Jahn: The Lagrange Multiplier Rule in Set-Valued Op-
timization: SIAM Journal on Optimization, Volume 10 , Issue 2 (1999)
81
Pages: 331 - 344 Year of Publication: 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers,
Boston, 1999.
[12] R.L. Keeney and H. Raiffa: Decisions with multiple objectives: prefer-
ences and value tradeoffs, Cambridge University Press, 1993
82