Vandenhaag 1986
Vandenhaag 1986
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Harvard Law Review Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Harvard Law Review.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
COMMENTARIES
THE ULTIMATE PUNISHMENT: A DEFENSE
Ernestvan den Haag*
In an average year about 20,000 homicides occur in the United
States. Fewer than 300 convicted murderers are sentenced to death.
But because no more than thirty murderers have been executed in
any recent year, most convicts sentenced to death are likely to die of
old age.' Nonetheless, the death penalty looms large in discussions:
it raises important moral questions independent of the number of
executions. 2
The death penalty is our harshest punishment.3 It is irrevocable:
it ends the existence of those punished, instead of temporarily impris-
oning them. Further, although not intended to cause physical pain,
execution is the only corporal punishment still applied to adults.4
These singular characteristics contribute to the perennial, impassioned
controversy about capital punishment.
I. DISTRIBUTION
Consideration of the justice, morality, or usefulness, of capital
punishment is often conflated with objections to its alleged discrimi-
natory or capricious distribution among the guilty. Wrongly so. If
capital punishment is immoral in se, no distribution among the guilty
could make it moral. If capital punishment is moral, no distribution
would make it immoral. Improper distribution cannot affect the qual-
ity of what is distributed, be it punishments or rewards. Discrimi-
natory or capricious distribution thus could not justify abolition of the
* The authors of these Commentaries have not seen drafts of each other's pieces. The
Commentary format is not meant to be a debate, but rather is meant to present different
perspectives on current issues of public importance.
** John M. Olin Professor of Jurisprudence and Public Policy, Fordham University.
1 Death row as a semipermanent residence is cruel, because convicts are denied the normal
amenities of prison life. Thus, unless death row residents are integrated into the prison popu-
lation, the continuing accumulation of convicts on death row should lead us to accelerate either
the rate of executions or the rate of commutations. I find little objection to integration.
2 The debate about the insanity defense is important for analogous reasons.
3 Some writers, for example, Cesare Bonesana, Marchese di Beccaria, have thought that life
imprisonment is more severe. See C. BECCARIA, DEI DELITTI E DELLE PENE 62-70 (I764).
More recently, Jacques Barzun, has expressed this view. See Barzun, In Favor of Capital
Punishment, in THE DEATH PENALTY IN AMERICA I54 (H. Bedau ed. I964). However, the
overwhelming majority of both abolitionists and of convicts under death sentence prefer life
imprisonment to execution.
4 For a discussion of the sources of opposition to corporal punishment, see E. VAN DEN
I662
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
i986] FOR CAPITAL PUNISHMENT I663
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
I 664 HARVARD LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:I662
II. MISCARRIAGES
OF JUSTICE
In a recent survey Professors Hugo Adam Bedau and Michael
Radelet found that 7000 persons were executed in the United States
between igoo and I985 and that 25 were innocent of capital crimes.11
Among the innocents they list Sacco and Vanzetti as well as Ethel
and Julius Rosenberg. Although their data may be questionable, I do
not doubt that, over a long enough period, miscarriages of justice will
occur even in capital cases.
7 The ideal of equality, unlike the ideal of retributive justice (which can be approximated
separately in each instance), is clearly unattainable unless all guilty persons are apprehended,
and thereafter tried, convicted and sentenced by the same court, at the same time. Unequal
justice is the best we can do; it is still better than the injustice, equal or unequal, which occurs
if, for the sake of equality, we deliberately allow some who could be punished to escape.
8 Equality, even without justice, may remain a strong psychological, and therefore political,
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
i986] FOR CAPITAL PUNISHMENT I665
III. DETERRENCE
Despite much recent work, there has been no conclusive statistical
demonstration that the death penalty is a better deterrent than are
alternative punishments.'3 However, deterrence is less than decisive
for either side. Most abolitionists acknowledge that they would con-
tinue to favor abolition even if the death penalty were shown to deter
more murders than alternatives could deter.14 Abolitionists appear to
value the life of a convicted murderer or, at least, his non-execution,
more highly than they value the lives of the innocent victims who
might be spared by deterring prospective murderers.
Deterrence is not altogether decisive for me either. I would favor
retention of the death penalty as retribution even if it were shown
that the threat of execution could not deter prospective murderers not
already deterred by the threat of imprisonment.15 Still, I believe the
death penalty, because of its finality, is more feared than imprison-
ment, and deters some prospective murderers not deterred by the
benefits gained by trucking or the practice of doing justice. We are, however, far from this
situation.
13 For a sample of conflicting views on the subject, see Baldus & Cole, A Comparison of the
Work of Thorsten Sellin and Isaac Ehrlich on the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment, 85
YALE L.J. 170 (1975); Bowers & Pierce, Deterrence or Brutalization: What Is the Effect of
Executions?, 26 CRIME & DELINQ. 453 (I980); Bowers & Pierce, The Illusion of Deterrence in
Isaac Ehrlich's Research on Capital Punishment, 85 YALE L. J. I87 (I975); Ehrlich, Fear of
Deterrence: A Critical Evaluation of the "Report of the Panel on Research on Deterrent and
Incapacitative Effects", 6 J. LEGALSTUD. 293 (I977); Ehrlich, The Deterrent Effect of Capital
Punishment: A Question of Life and Death, 65 AM. ECON. REV. 397, 4I5-I6 (I975); Ehrlich &
Gibbons, On the Measurement of the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment and the Theory of
Deterrence, 6 J. LEGALSTUD. 35 (I977).
14 For most abolitionists, the discrimination argument, see supra pp. I662-64, is similarly
nondecisive: they would favor abolition even if there could be no racial discrimination.
15If executions were shown to increase the murder rate in the long run, I would favor
abolition. Sparing the innocent victims who would be spared, ex hypothesi, by the nonexecution
of murderers would be more important to me than the execution, however just, of murderers.
But although there is a lively discussion of the subject, no serious evidence exists to support
the hypothesis that executions produce a higher murder rate. Cf. Phillips, The Deterrent Effect
of Capital Punishment: New Evidence on an Old Controversy, 86 AM. J. Soc. I39 (I980)
(arguing that murder rates drop immediately after executions of criminals).
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
i666 HARVARD LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:I662
16 H. GROSS, A THEORY OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE 489 (1979) (attributing this passage to Sir
James Fitzjames Stephen).
17 Weems v. United States, 217 U.S. 349 (1910), suggests that penalties be proportionate to
the seriousness of the crime - a common theme of the criminal law. Murder, therefore, demands
more than life imprisonment, if, as I believe, it is a more serious crime than other crimes
punished by life imprisonment. In modern times, our sensibility requires that the range of
punishments be narrower than the range of crimes - but not so narrow as to exclude the death
penalty.
18 Cf. Kaplan, Administering Capital Punishment, 36 U. FLA. L. REV. I77, I78, I90-9I
(I984) (noting the high cost of appealing a capital sentence).
19For an example of this view, see A. CAMUS, REFLECTIONS ON THE GUILLOTINE 24-30
(I959). On the limitations allegedly imposed by the lex talionis, see Reiman, Justice, Civiliza-
tion, and the Death Penalty: Answering van den Haag, I4 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. I15, II9-34
(I985).
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
I986] FOR CAPITAL PUNISHMENT I667
the murderer on death row suffers more than his victim suffered;
however, unlike the murderer, the victim deserved none of the suf-
fering inflicted. Further, the limitations of the lex talionis were meant
to restrain private vengeance, not the social retribution that has taken
its place. Punishment - regardless of the motivation - is not in-
tended to revenge, offset, or compensate for the victim's suffering, or
to be measured by it. Punishment is to vindicate the law and the
social order undermined by the crime. This is why a kidnapper's
penal confinement is not limited to the period for which he imprisoned
his victim; nor is a burglar's confinement meant merely to offset the
suffering or the harm he caused his victim; nor is it meant only to
offset the advantage he gained.20
Another argument heard at least since Beccaria21is that, by killing
a murderer, we encourage, endorse, or legitimize unlawful killing.
Yet, although all punishments are meant to be unpleasant, it is seldom
argued that they legitimize the unlawful imposition of identical un-
pleasantness. Imprisonment is not thought to legitimize kidnapping;
neither are fines thought to legitimize robbery. The difference between
murder and execution, or between kidnapping and imprisonment, is
that the first is unlawful and undeserved, the second a lawful and
deserved punishment for an unlawful act. The physical similarities
of the punishment to the crime are irrelevant. The relevant difference
is not physical, but social.22
L. REv. 706, 7I9 (I98I) (explaining why the desire for retribution, although independent, would
have to be satisfied even if deterrence were the only purpose of punishment.)
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
i668 HARVARD LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:I662
24 An explicit threat of punitive action is necessary to the justification of any legal punish-
ment: nulla poena sine lege (no punishment without [preexisting] law). To be sufficiently
justified, the threat must in turn have a rational and legitimate purpose. "Your money or your
life" does not qualify; nor does the threat of an unjust law; nor, finally, does a threat that is
altogether disproportionate to the importance of its purpose. In short, preannouncement legi-
timizes the threatened punishment only if the threat is warranted. But this leaves a very wide
range of justified threats. Furthermore, the punished person is aware of the penalty for his
actions and thus volunteers to take the risk even of an unjust punishment. His victim, however,
did not volunteer to risk anything. The question whether any self-inflicted injury - such as a
legal punishment - ever can be unjust to a person who knowingly risked it is a matter that
requires more analysis than is possible here.
25 2 THE WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM 105 (J. Bowring ed. 1972). However, I would be
more polite about prescriptible natural rights, which Bentham (lescribed as "simple nonsense."
Id. (It does not matter whether natural rights are called "moral" or "human" rights as they
currently are by most writers.)
26 THE DEATH PENALTY IN AMERICA 256-63 (H. Bedau ed.. 3d ed. i982) (quoting Furman
v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 286, 305 (I972) (Brennan, J., concurring).
27 Id. at 272-73; see also Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. I53. 230 (1976) (Brennan, J., dis-
senting).
28 Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 291 (1972) (Brennan, J., concurring).
29 Id. at 290.
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
i986] FOR CAPITAL PUNISHMENT I669
have had the death penalty, although it has been discarded in Western
Europe, where it is currently unfashionable probably because of its
abuse by totalitarian regimes.
By "degrading," Justice Brennan seems to mean that execution
degrades the executed convicts. Yet philosophers, such as Immanuel
Kant and G.F.W. Hegel, have insisted that, when deserved, execu-
tion, far from degrading the executed convict, affirms his humanity
by affirming his rationality and his responsibility for his actions. They
thought that execution, when deserved, is required for the sake of the
convict's dignity. (Does not life imprisonment violate human dignity
more than execution, by keeping alive a prisoner deprived of all
autonomy?)30
Common sense indicates that it cannot be death - our common
fate - that is inhuman. Therefore, Justice Brennan must mean that
death degrades when it comes not as a natural or accidental event,
but as a deliberate social imposition. The murderer learns through
his punishment that his fellow men have found him unworthy of
living; that because he has murdered, he is being expelled from the
community of the living. This degradation is self-inflicted. By mur-
dering, the murderer has so dehumanized himself that he cannot
remain among the living. The social recognition of his self-degrada-
tion is the punitive essence of execution. To believe, as Justice Bren-
nan appears to, that the degradation is inflicted by the execution
reverses the direction of causality.
Execution of those who have committed heinous murders may
deter only one murder per year. If it does, it seems quite warranted.
It is also the only fitting retribution for murder I can think of.
This content downloaded from 144.122.201.150 on Thu, 14 Jan 2016 04:07:00 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions