Behavioral Economics Probability Payoffs
Behavioral Economics Probability Payoffs
Introduction AUTHORS
Finding securities with gaps between price and value is the Michael J. Mauboussin
foundation of generating excess returns in active investment michael.mauboussin@morganstanley.com
management.1 The difference between price and value,
commonly called “variant perception” or “edge,” comes from Dan Callahan, CFA
dan.callahan1@morganstanley.com
having a substantiated view that diverges from what the market
reflects.2 In theory, the size of an investment within a portfolio
maximizes the benefit of edge while considering risk.
This is all simple in principle but difficult in practice. One of the
main challenges is discerning the gap between price and value.
Price is the relatively easy part. Buying or selling securities incurs
transaction costs, and the magnitude of those costs depends on
factors such as the liquidity of the security.3 But price is
transparent and investors can estimate market impact.
Value is the hard part. This is because value is really “expected
value,” which represents a range of potential payoffs with
associated probabilities. Investing is an inherently probabilistic
activity. The concept of expected value raises lots of issues that
we will explore.
One of the most challenging aspects of understanding expected
value is that excess returns can be the product of high probability
events with relatively low payoffs, or low probability events with
relatively high payoffs.4 In other words, how often you are right is
not all that matters. What is vital is how much money you make
when you are right versus how much you lose when you are
wrong.
We have called this the “Babe Ruth effect.”5 Ruth is considered
one of the greatest baseball players of all time and yet was the
career leader in strikeouts, a measure of offensive failure, when
he retired. At the same time, his slugging percentage, which
assesses batting productivity, remains the highest in the history of
Major League Baseball. What was good in his results more than
offset what was bad. We will look at the frequency and magnitude
of payoffs across asset classes.
.
Some markets have seen a shift in appetite from high probability, low payoff opportunities to low probability, high
payoff ones. In betting on horse races, there has been a rise in “exotic” wagers, which can include several horses
and multiple races, versus simple win, place, and show bets. 6 In sports betting, parlay bets, also wagers on
multiple outcomes, have grown relative to simple point spread or over/under bets. 7 And there has been a surge
in the trading of short-dated options in equity options markets.8
In this report, we discuss some of the issues with the calculation of expected value, what the payoff picture
means for investing, the implications of volatility drag, the psychology of dealing with probabilities and payoffs,
and how these ideas can be helpful for investing in various asset classes.
We focus on equities primarily but the thinking applies to credit and derivatives as well.
A calculation of expected value requires a quantification of potential payoffs and the probability of each payoff
occurring. The sum of the probabilities must be 100 percent. The expected value is the sum of the product of
each payoff and its associated probability (see exhibit 1 for a simplified example of the expected value of a drug).
Expected value calculations span from the simple to the very complex. As Warren Buffett, chairman and chief
executive officer of Berkshire Hathaway, has said, “Take the probability of loss times the amount of possible
loss from the probability of gain times the amount of possible gain. That is what we’re trying to do. It’s imperfect,
but that’s what it’s all about.”9
Economists typically translate expected value into expected utility, an idea that Daniel Bernoulli, a
mathematician, introduced in 1738. Utility is a measure of satisfaction and varies from person to person based
on individual preferences. Most people exhibit risk aversion, meaning that the marginal utility of wealth
diminishes as wealth increases.10 Expected value is a key concept in decision-making under uncertainty, but
economists recognize that individuals make choices based on different utility functions, which lead to a range of
preferences.
Most teachers start their lessons about expected value using examples with set probabilities and payoffs. For
instance, the expected value of the toss of a fair coin that pays $2 for heads and $1 for tails is $1.50 ([0.50 × $2]
+ [0.50 × $1] = $1.50). But investing is vastly more complex than the toss of a coin, the roll of a die, or the turn
of a playing card. The mindset carries over but the math does not. Overapplying these simple cases to the more
complicated ones is called the “ludic fallacy”—ludus is Latin for game.11
During a press briefing in 2002, Donald Rumsfeld, then U.S. Secretary of Defense, answered a question by
distinguishing between “known knowns” (“things we know we know”), “known unknowns” (“we know there are
things we do not know”), and “unknown unknowns” (“the ones we don’t know we don’t know”). He added that
the unknown unknowns is the “category that tends to be the difficult one.” 13
Richard Zeckhauser, an economist and champion bridge player, writes, “The essence of effective investment is
to select assets that will fare well when future states of the world become known.” 14 He notes that the efficient
market hypothesis posits that probabilities and payoffs are established and, as a result, smart investing is an
exercise in optimization.
The key to financial success when dealing with unknowns and ignorance, a good description of most investing,
is the ability to assess probabilities and payoffs. Decision theory becomes more important than optimization.
With these thoughts as background, we will take a closer look at payoffs and probabilities, the determinants of
expected value.
Payoffs. Payoffs reflect the future states of the world and can range from the very simple to the highly complex.
A common mistake in decision-making is “overprecision,” a form of overconfidence that occurs when someone
is too confident in their views and therefore fails to consider a sufficiently wide range of alternatives.15 Here are
some points to keep in mind when assessing the likelihood that particular future states of the world will come to
pass:
• Consider the shape of the distribution of payoffs. Benoit Mandelbrot, a renowned mathematician, used
the terms “mild” and “wild” to distinguish between the ranges of future states.16 Mild states can generally
be captured with a normal, bell-shaped distribution. The distribution of the height of people, for instance,
is mild, with the ratio between the tallest and shortest humans on record being five-to-one (left panel of
exhibit 2). Statistical concepts such as mean (average) and standard deviation are useful in expressing
mild states.
Wild states are often power laws, where few very large outcomes have a disproportionate impact on the
distribution.17 Examples include the distribution of wealth and city size (right panel of exhibit 2). As a case
in point, the ratio between the population of the largest city (New York, New York) and the one-thousandth
(Dekalb City, Illinois) in the U.S. is 205-to-1. Mean and standard deviation are not useful in expressing the
outcomes of these systems.
8
Normal
Population (Log)
7 1,000,000
6
5
4
100,000
3
2
1
0 10,000
-4 -3 -2 -1 0 1 2 3 4 1 10 100 1,000
Standard Deviation Rank (Log)
Source: Statistics Online Computational Resource Human Weight/Height Dataset and U.S. Census Bureau.
Note: Height of 25,000 people; cities in the United States.
Nassim Taleb, an author, popularized the idea of a “black swan,” which he defines as an event that is an
outlier, is consequential, and that humans try to explain after the fact.18 Black swans are from the domain
of unknown unknowns.
Many outcomes that investors call black swans are really what he calls gray swans, or known unknowns.
For example, a large and devastating earthquake would be an outlier and consequential. But geologists
have a good sense of the distribution of earthquake magnitudes even if they do not know exactly when or
where an earthquake will occur.
The Stoics, ancient philosophers who believed in a life led well, advocated “premeditatio malorum”—the
pre-meditation of evils. Seneca, a Stoic, wrote the following about adverse events that are unanticipated:
“The fact that it was unforeseen has never failed to intensify a person’s grief. This is a reason for ensuring
that nothing ever takes us by surprise.”19 The point is to prepare for all eventualities.
• Be mindful of the “grand ah-whoom.”20 Phase transitions, where small changes in a cause lead to large
effects, are pervasive in complex systems such as businesses and markets. Think of cooling water that
starts at a temperature just above freezing. As the temperature drops below the point of freezing—ah-
whoom—the liquid turns into a solid. A modest change has a large impact.
Jay Forrester, a professor at Massachusetts Institute of Technology who taught system dynamics,
developed the beer game to illustrate how small decisions can amplify into big effects. There are four
teams (manufacturer, distributor, supplier, and retailer) and assumed lags between when the orders are
received and when the beer is delivered. The goal is to meet consumer demand while minimizing back
orders and inventory.
Bullwhip effects, where relatively small distortions in demand create inefficiency throughout the supply
chain, commonly emerge from playing the game. Bullwhip effects occurred in multiple supply chains during
and following the COVID-19 pandemic. One widely discussed case was toilet paper: an initial spike in
consumer purchases caused retailers to order much more product, which signaled high demand to
• Control and reversibility. Because payoffs reflect future states of the world, it is important to understand
when the payoffs are expected to happen (time horizon), whether the decision-maker can alter the payoffs
(control), and if the investment can be exited at an acceptable cost (reversibility).22 Reversibility is closely
tied to liquidity, the cost of turning cash into an asset or an asset into cash. That cost is low in liquid
markets and high in illiquid markets.
To illustrate, consider the differences between an investment made by a company and one made by an
equity investor. Investments by companies such as building a data center or acquiring another company
tend to be long-term because the cost of reversal is high. Offsetting that illiquidity is some control over the
potential payoffs. Companies can act if the potential payoffs appear to be following an unsatisfactory path,
including tweaking a product offering, changing the pricing, refining the marketing strategy, or replacing
the managers in charge of the business.
Public equity investors have much more liquidity but commonly have limited control over payoffs. Note
that even activist investors, who seek to improve the payoffs by promoting change at the companies they
invest in, often need to have a sizeable stake in the company to establish credibility. More control requires
less reversibility.
• Asymmetric payoffs. Fundamental investors commonly seek opportunities where the magnitude of
payoffs on the downside are smaller than those on the upside. In other words, there are more potential
gains than losses (naturally, the probability of the payoffs is also crucial). In some cases, certain measures
of valuation may suggest a limit to downside payoffs. These include cash balances, tangible book value,
and free cash flow yield.
While our focus is on equities, the upside payoffs are generally capped for bonds. The upside payoff for
a straight bond held to maturity is the present value of coupon payments plus the return of principal. For
this reason, equity investors tend to focus on upside payoffs and bond investors are inclined to dwell on
the avoidance of loss. This is why Benjamin Graham and David Dodd, authors of Security Analysis, called
bond selection “primarily a negative art.”23
Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, professors of psychology, developed “prospect theory” in part as
an effort to explain the observation that people suffer more from losses than they enjoy gains of
comparable size, leading to “loss aversion.” 24 Relative to a reference point, people tend to be risk-averse
in the realm of gains and risk-seeking in the realm of losses (see exhibit 3). Empirical data back the point
that prospect theory explains investor behavior better than classic expected utility theory does.25
Utility
Loss Gain
Utility
Source: Counterpoint Global based on Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision
under Risk,” Econometrica, Vol. 47, No. 2, March 1979, 263-292.
Note: Assumes utility of wealth equals the log of wealth, U(w) = ln(w), and a loss aversion coefficient of 2.0.
There are categories of investments where the payoffs have a low probability of a large positive or negative
outcome. Specifically, investors can buy investments with characteristics similar to a lottery (lose a little
and potentially make a lot) or sell those similar to insurance (make a little and potentially lose a lot).
Research shows that investors commonly overprice stocks with lottery characteristics because they
overweight the probability of a high payoff.26 Some financial economists have concluded that it is better to
sell, rather than buy, investments with lottery- and insurance-type payoffs.27
This thinking can be expanded from individual opportunities to investment strategies. Selling investments
with lottery or insurance payoffs means making a little money most days and losing lots of money from
time to time (blowup). Buying investments with lottery payoffs means losing a little money most days and
making lots of money every now and then (bleed).
Nassim Taleb believes in the bleed strategy and argues that extreme outcomes are underpriced. But he
concedes that a financial firm may prefer to make money steadily even at the risk of a blowup. 28 An
example is Long-Term Capital Management, a hedge fund, which had returns well in excess of the market
from 1993 to early 1998 but then plummeted.
• Internal versus external factors. When considering payoffs and probabilities for the stock of a company,
investors commonly and appropriately focus primarily on the drivers of value for that firm. For example,
an analyst may consider different scenarios for measures of corporate performance such as sales growth
and operating profit margins and estimate the payoff per share for each scenario.
One of the most important findings in finance is that changes in stock market prices are greater than what
is justified by changes in fundamentals.29 A pair of academic papers looked at the largest moves in the
Probabilities. Philosophers, statisticians, and mathematicians have debated the meaning of probability for
centuries. Some have argued that probability is a subjective assessment that fails to reflect a real quantity, and
hence does not really exist.33 That said, it is useful to consider probabilities in evaluating opportunities. Here are
some points to keep in mind when assessing the likelihood that particular future states of the world will come to
pass:
• Methods to set probabilities. There are broadly three approaches to setting probabilities: frequentist,
propensity, and degrees of belief (subjective).34 These camps do not always see eye to eye.35
The frequentist sets probabilities based on a large sample of outcomes for a particular reference class.
The likelihood of a six appearing with the roll of a die is one-in-six based on a huge number of observations
of die rolls.
The propensity approach judges probability based on the properties of the object under consideration.
The probability of rolling a six is 16.7 percent, reflecting the physical nature of a die as a perfect cube.
Degrees of belief measures the subjective probability an individual assigns to an outcome. This probability
can be quantified through an analyst’s willingness to bet.36 An analyst who believes the likelihood of rolling
a 6 is 16.7 percent and is neutral to risk would be indifferent between doing nothing and betting $1 on
rolling a 6 if the payoff was $6 ($1 = .167 × $6). Investment analysts deal mostly with subjective
probabilities. An initial degree of belief is called a “prior.” The prior that a die will show a six is based on a
person’s assessment before any new information is revealed.
One sensible approach for investors is to use base rates as a way to inform prior probabilities and then
update those probabilities as additional information becomes available. A base rate reflects the
probabilities and payoffs for a specific reference class. To illustrate, exhibit 4 shows the distribution of
three-year compound annual growth rates of sales for U.S. companies over the past 63 years.
35
30
Frequency (Percent)
25
20
15
10
0
<(12) (12)-(8) (8)-(4) (4)-0 0-4 4-8 8-12 12-16 16-20 20-24 >24
3-Year CAGR (Percent)
Source: FactSet, Compustat, and Counterpoint Global.
Note: Companies listed on the New York Stock Exchange, NASDAQ, and NYSE American stock exchanges, with a minimum
$1 million of sales in 1962 dollars; nominal growth; CAGR=compound annual growth rate.
One essential point is that probabilities and payoffs are dynamic. That means that new information will
justify a revision in prior probabilities. The formal way to do this is with Bayes’ Theorem, which tells you
the probability that a prior belief is true conditional on some event happening. While the math is useful,
what is more important is an openness to updating your views.37
Research suggests that confirmation bias, the tendency to dismiss, discount, or disavow new information
in favor of a prior view, can impede proper updating.38 It helps to think like a “fox”—one who knows a little
about a lot—rather than a “hedgehog”—one who knows one big thing. Foxes update their views more
readily than do hedgehogs, who prefer to fit the facts to their worldview. 39
Investors deal mostly with subjective probabilities. These are useful if set carefully and revised
appropriately. But there is an additional layer of nuance: confidence in probability.
• Confidence in probability. Probability and confidence are distinct concepts that often get combined,
unwittingly, in investment analysis. You can think of probability as an estimate of the chances of a payoff
and confidence as “the degree to which an analyst believes that he or she possesses a sound basis for
assessing uncertainty.”40 Psychologists call the probability assigned to a payoff “first order uncertainty.” A
reasonable range of probabilities for first order uncertainty is called “second order uncertainty.” It reflects
uncertainty about an uncertain payoff.
Jeffrey Friedman, a professor of government, and Richard Zeckhauser describe three dimensions to
confidence: reliability of available evidence, range of reasonable opinion, and responsiveness to new
information.
Reliability of available evidence answers the question, “Can I defend this estimate with a substantial
amount of information?” A large amount of relevant knowledge provides a sound basis for assessing risk
Confidence in probabilities can be important when making investment decisions. For instance, two
opportunities may have the same discount to expected value, but the confidence in the probabilities for
one may exceed that of the other. That insight may be important for position sizing within a portfolio or for
risk assessment.
Words to probability. A perceived variant perception motivates most investment decisions based on
fundamentals. The challenge is that the articulation of the variant perception relies too often on vague
words rather than numerical probabilities. Phrases such as “we believe,” “the chance is good,” and “there
is a real possibility” are examples of this type of communication. A better approach is to quantify the variant
perception.42
There are at least two problems with using words instead of probabilities. The first is that people assign
different probabilities to the same word or phrase. This introduces the potential for miscommunication.
Exhibit 5 shows some of the results of a survey of more than 3,000 respondents who were presented with
words or phrases, in random order, and asked to assign probabilities to each.
While some words translate into consistent probabilities, the variation is huge in other cases. For example,
the term “might happen” evoked a range between 10 and 70 percent (setting aside the lowest and highest
5 percent of the responses). The cognate words and phrases of “possible” are particularly nettlesome as
they are interpreted to express a wide range of probabilities.43
The second problem is that using words can allow an investor to skirt accountability when he or she is
wrong. The ambiguity in words provides an investor the opportunity to craft a narrative that explains the
wrong judgment. Examples include the close call (“I was almost right”), bad timing (“my prediction will be
right but the timing was off”), and the unexpected (“an unforeseen event messed up my forecast”). We tell
stories to ourselves and others to paper over our poor predictions. Barbara Mellers, a professor of
psychology at the University of Pennsylvania, says, “We find prediction really hard, but we find explanation
fairly easy.”44
Percentile
5th 25th 50th 75th 95th
Certainly
Likely
Frequently
Often
Probably
Real Possibility
Possibly
Might Happen
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Percent
Source: Counterpoint Global and www.probabilitysurvey.com.
• Feedback and calibration. Skill acquisition requires timely and accurate feedback. You need to know
where and how you were wrong to improve on the next try. The challenge with investing and business is
that the feedback can be noisy and come with a lag. This impedes learning.
A variant perception, or investment thesis, can almost always be distilled into outcomes that are objective,
within a specific time horizon, and occur with an estimated probability. (“The company will divest division
X for $1 billion or more by the end of the year with an 80 percent probability.”) These three ingredients
allow you to score the quality of a forecast. The appendix discusses the Brier score, a common way to
measure forecasting accuracy.
We have found that asking investors to assign probabilities to payoffs with the intention of keeping score
prompts useful introspection. Documenting decisions also allows for an audit of the investment process.
Some investments do well even when the thesis is wrong (bad process, good outcome) and others do
poorly when the thesis is solid (good process, bad outcome). Feedback and calibration help improve the
process, which is the best way to increase the chances of satisfactory outcomes over time. 48
90
Correct (Percent)
80
77
70
65
60 60
56 57
51
50
40
40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Confidence (Percent)
Source: www.confidence.success-equation.com.
Best practices. Now that we have discussed considerations surrounding the setting of payoffs and probabilities,
we touch on some best practices for translating these ideas into action.
• Use base rates. When modeling expected corporate results, investors commonly gather lots of
information (e.g., financial filings, communication with management, sell-side research, company financial
guidance, surveys, expert calls), which they combine with their own experience and judgment, and project
into the future.49 This practice introduces a number of potential biases, including confirmation,
overconfidence, recency, and availability.50
Integrating base rates overcomes some of the limitations of this approach. Rather than considering each
problem as unique, the base rate considers the results of a relevant reference class. Instead of asking,
“what do I think will happen?” the base rate approach asks, “what happened when others were in this
Our recommendation is to use the expectations infrastructure (exhibit 7), which creates a mapping of the
interactions between the value triggers—sales, operating costs, and investments—and the ultimate
operating value drivers. The crucial point is that the elasticity of operating profit to changes in sales differs
a great deal by industry and company. As a result, analyst earnings forecasts can be very inaccurate,
especially in the case of declining sales.59
A further suggestion is to use more than three scenarios. Additional complexity does have a cost but we
would argue that the insight gleaned from considering, say, five scenarios is a worthwhile trade-off. The
main benefit is offsetting the risk of overprecision. Thoughtful use of Monte Carlo methods, a form of
simulation that produces payoffs based on draws from a distribution, can also lead to a deeper
appreciation of potential probabilities and payoffs.60
2
Price and
Mix Operating
Sales Profit
3 Margin (%)
Operating
Leverage
Incremental
4 Investment
Economies Rate (%)
of Scale
5
Operating
Cost
Costs
Efficiencies
6
Investments Investment
Efficiencies
Source: Michael J. Mauboussin and Alfred Rappaport, Expectations Investing: Reading Stock Prices for Better Returns—
Revised and Updated (New York: Columbia Business School Publishing, 2021), 46.
• Margin of safety. Ben Graham, the father of security analysis, suggested that the secret of sound
investment could be distilled into three words, “MARGIN OF SAFETY” (capitalization original). 61 Margin
of safety is the difference between value and price, and the point is that you want to have a sufficient gap
to improve the odds of generating excess returns as that gap narrows as well as to compensate for
“miscalculations” in analysis or “worse than average luck.”62
Expected value is the best way to think about value. Graham allowed that even investments with an
attractive margin of safety only improve the chances of a profit but do not eliminate the possibility of a
loss. For this reason, Graham suggested that portfolio diversification is the “companion” to the principle of
margin of safety, reckoning that the more investments that have attractive gaps between value and price
the more likely that the overall portfolio will fare well.
Now that we have discussed some of the issues surrounding how to think about, and calculate, the inputs to
expected value we turn our attention to how these ideas apply under different considerations.
The process of estimating expected value through payoffs and probabilities provides a way to quantify variant
perception, or edge, and compels useful thought and analysis. The next question is how to translate that work
into action.
Harry Markowitz, an economist and recipient of the Nobel Prize in Economics, came up with one answer to this
based on mean/variance optimization.63 The idea, which fits with intuition and experience, is that risk and reward
are related in a linear fashion. The security market line (exhibit 8) shows this visually. The return is the mean, or
average, arithmetic return from an asset or portfolio. The risk is variance, a measure of how far points on the
distribution are spread from the average.
Risk (Variance)
Source: Counterpoint Global.
Markowitz’s basic point is that an investor who cares about risk will seek the highest return for a given level of
risk or the lowest risk for a particular level of return. For example, if two portfolios have the same return but one
has lower risk than the other, the investor will select the portfolio with the lower risk. Markowitz showed that the
portfolios with the best risk and reward characteristics fall along the “efficient frontier.”
In theory there is no universally optimal portfolio because investors differ in their preferences. But portfolios that
fall at a distance from the efficient frontier are suboptimal. Mean/variance optimization is useful because you
can find an appropriate portfolio if you know your appetite for risk. Modern portfolio theory holds that the “market
portfolio,” the market-weighted value of all investable assets, is mean/variance optimal.
An essential point is that mean/variance optimization generally assumes you are deciding based on one period.
But the approach is different if you consider multiple time periods and your goal is to maximize the likelihood
that you will have the most money at a date far in the future.
But the math changes if the winnings are reinvested from one period to the next. Instead of seeking the outcome
with the best arithmetic mean, the objective is to find the opportunity with the highest geometric mean. This is
called the Kelly criterion, or Kelly strategy. In this case, subjective preference does not determine risk. Rather,
there is a knowable amount of risk that provides the best results in the long run.
The arithmetic mean is the sum of the values divided by the number of values. For example, the annual arithmetic
mean return for the S&P 500 was 11.9 percent for the 20 years ended in 2024.
The geometric mean return represents the average rate of return per period, accounting for compounding. For
the 20 years ending in 2024, the annual geometric mean return for the S&P 500 was 10.4 percent.
The difference between the arithmetic mean, a simple average, and the geometric mean arises from the
variance, or volatility, in returns. If there is no volatility in the returns, the arithmetic and geometric means are
equal. However, as volatility increases, the arithmetic mean will always be higher than the geometric mean
because of the compounding effect of positive and negative returns.
An illustration can help demonstrate the difference between mean/variance optimization and geometric mean
maximization. We draw this example from Fortune’s Formula, a wonderful book by William Poundstone that tells
the story of Kelly’s research and its implications.
Exhibit 9 shows the probabilities and payoffs for three investment opportunities. Poundstone suggests thinking
of them as wheels of fortune, each with six outcomes, that you spin to determine your outcome.
A B C
Probability Payoff Probability Payoff Probability Payoff
50% $1.00 50% $2.00 50% $3.00
50% $2.00 17% $0.00 50% $0.50
17% $1.00
17% $3.00
The probabilities and payoffs allow us to calculate the arithmetic and geometric means. We can see that of the
three opportunities, the expected value, or arithmetic mean, is lowest for A, in the middle for B, and the highest
for C. If you bet the same amount every time you should maximize expected value. Markowitz would say that
the best choice is a function of an individual’s preference. But opportunity C is the most attractive, all else being
equal.
Opportunity B has a positive expected value but a geometric mean of zero. This is the financial version of
Russian roulette.66 You will lose all of your bankroll with this strategy given a sufficient number of trials because
one of the payoffs is nil. The lesson is that some strategies with positive expected value can still result in financial
disaster, especially since real probabilities and payoffs are more opaque than those in this illustration. 67
One way to think about this is that mean/variance optimization (Markowitz) focuses on diversification at a point
in time and geometric mean maximization (Kelly) considers diversification over time. 68 Markowitz was fully aware
of Kelly and related research and wrote favorably about it.69
Ergodicity economics, a field led by Ole Peters, a physicist, provides another way to think about this issue.70 A
process is ergodic if the ensemble average and the time average are the same. For instance, imagine 100
people flipping a fair coin simultaneously and recording the outcomes (ensemble). Now imagine flipping a fair
coin 100 times in a row (time average). This process is ergodic because the expected outcomes are the same.
Consider that you pay $1 for the flip of a fair coin that pays $1.10 when it comes up heads and costs $1 when it
comes up tails. This game has a positive expected value of $0.05 per dollar played ([0.50 × $1.10] + [0.50 ×
-$1.00] = $0.05), which leads to expected wealth of $1.05 [$1.00 + $0.05 = $1.05].
Assume that 100 people, each with $1, play simultaneously. Half will end up with $2.10 and the other half zero.
This game has a positive expected value of $5.00 in the aggregate [100 x $0.05 = $5.00], and the expected
wealth for the group is $105 ([50 × $2.10] + [50 × 0] = $105).
Now you alone start with $100 and play the game 100 times in a row. You will also see results split roughly
evenly between heads and tails, and your expected wealth is the same at $105.
Exhibit 10 shows 100 runs of this game along with the median outcome (the average is virtually identical). This
game is ergodic because the payoffs are arithmetic. The expected outcomes of the ensemble and time averages
are the same and continue to converge as the number of rounds increase.
130
125
120
115
Log Wealth ($)
110
105
100
95
90
85
80
75
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Rounds
Source: Counterpoint Global.
Let us now consider a process that Ole Peters uses to illustrate a non-ergodic process. You flip a fair coin that
increases wealth 50 percent when it comes up heads and decreases it 40 percent when it comes up tails. If you
play with $1, the game also has an expected value of $0.05 ([0.50 × $0.50] + [0.50 × -$0.40] = $0.05) and
expected wealth of $1.05 ([0.50 × $1.50] + [0.50 × $0.60] = $1.05).
Again we assume that 100 people, each starting with $1, play the game at the same time. About one-half of the
ensemble will land on heads and end up with $75 [$50 + (50 × $0.50) = $75], and the other half on tails and end
up with $30 [$50 + (50 × -$0.40) = $30]. The expected wealth of the ensemble is $105 [$75 + $30 = $105].
But the experience of one person playing 100 rounds is very different because the geometric mean multiplier is
less than 1 (√1.5 x 0.6 ≈ 0.95). Exhibit 11 shows that the median wealth goes down as this game is played over
time. The average wealth also declines in the long run. The process is non-ergodic because the payoffs are
multiplicative. The ensemble and time averages are totally different.
1,000,000
100,000
Log Wealth ($)
10,000
1,000
100
10
1
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Rounds
Source: Counterpoint Global based on Ole Peters.
That life outcomes are non-ergodic also helps explain the value of buying insurance.71 A personal setback such
as losing a home to a fire or a costly medical treatment can substantially damage an individual’s wealth and
wealth trajectory. Insurance improves the time average growth rate for the insured because the reduction in
wealth from paying premiums is more than offset by the prevention of financial disaster. Insurance is attractive
from the insurer’s point of view because spreading risk among a population makes ensemble averages relevant.
The Kelly criterion makes clear the importance of thinking about geometric means when investing. But it provides
two additional lessons for investors, even for those who do not apply the criterion formally.
Pretend that you can participate in a game with a biased coin where heads show up 60 percent of the time. The
payoffs are even money, which means if you bet $1 and win you get another $1, and if you are wrong you lose
your $1. You start with a $25 bankroll and can wager any amount of your available bankroll for each round. What
betting strategy will allow you to achieve the highest probability of the most money after 100 rounds?
Victor Haghani and Richard Dewey, professional investors, presented this game to 61 participants, including
college students studying finance and young professionals at financial firms. Haghani and Dewey promised to
pay them their final balance in cash (capped at $250).72 The participants played 119 rounds on average, and
heads turned up 59.6 percent of the time.
Their exercise showed that this group did not know how to approach the problem even though the probabilities
and payoffs were set. About one-third of the participants lost money and an astounding 28 percent went bust.
Twenty one percent earned the maximum amount, which means about half of the players earned an amount
below the maximum but above zero. The average ending bankroll was $75.
The Kelly criterion provides an optimal way to engage in this game. Betting nothing makes no sense because
the proposition has a positive expected value of $0.20 for every dollar bet on heads ([0.60 × $1] + [0.40 × -$1] =
$0.20). But betting it all is also foolish because you lose the entirety of your money if tails appears.
We can present the Kelly criterion multiple ways, but a common approach to calculate the fraction of the bankroll
to bet, f, is as follows:
Edge
f=
Odds
Edge is the expected value of the proposition, or $0.20 in this case. Odds is how much you win if you win, which
is $1.00. So Kelly says the optimal bet size is 20 percent of your bankroll. 73
The equation highlights the first lesson, which is never bet when you do not have an edge. If edge is zero, f is
zero. In other words, generating excess returns requires having a well-grounded view that is different than what
the market has priced into an asset. This is consistent with seeking opportunities where the expected value is
different than the price, as well as ensuring a margin of safety. A corollary is that more attractive investment
opportunities should be larger positions in a portfolio than less attractive ones.
What happens if you select a strategy other than what Kelly prescribes? Exhibit 12 shows the results of 1,000
simulations of various proportional betting strategies over 100 rounds. The x-axis is the proportion of the bankroll
bet in each round and the y-axis is the median multiple of the initial bankroll after all of the rounds.
© 2025 Morgan Stanley. All rights reserved. 4236776 Exp. 2/28/2026 18
Exhibit 12: The Kelly Criterion Reveals the Optimal Betting Strategy
8
7
Wealth (Median Multiple
of Original Bankroll)
6
5
4
3
2
1
0
0.00 0.10 0.20 0.30 0.40 0.50 0.60 0.70 0.80 0.90 1.00
Bet Size--Fraction of Bankfoll (f)
Source: Counterpoint Global.
The chart shows that 20 percent is the proportional bet size that leads to the greatest wealth and that betting too
little fails to take advantage of the available edge.
But the other crucial lesson from the Kelly criterion is that it is possible to wager too much. Beyond a certain
point bigger bets lead to less, not more, return. Several studies suggest that some of the largest failures of hedge
funds in history were the consequence of overbetting.74
A handful of academics have claimed that some of the best investors of all time, including John Maynard Keynes,
Warren Buffett, George Soros, and Edward Thorp, employed a version of the Kelly criterion.75 Thorp, trained as
a mathematician, is among the most articulate and successful users of the Kelly criterion. He developed a system
of card counting in blackjack, a casino game, that allowed players to know when the odds were in their favor.
He then paired the edge gained from his approach with the Kelly criterion to optimize potential winnings.76
Thorp also successfully applied the Kelly criterion to the stock market. In November 1969, Thorp co-founded a
hedge fund that was eventually called Princeton Newport Partners. From the time of its founding through May
1998, the fund produced a compound annual return of approximately 20 percent, a standard deviation of just 6
percent, and a correlation with the stock market of near zero.77
The Kelly criterion undoubtedly offers valuable lessons that some investors have used successfully. But the
approach has had plenty of vocal critics as well.78 Some of the concerns include the following:
• Large estimation risk. Our simple examples assume that we know the probabilities and payoffs and can
confidently calculate arithmetic and geometric means. The ability to forecast distributions in the real world
falls on a continuum. A Kelly strategy is difficult to use without reliable inputs.
• High volatility. A full allocation prescribed by Kelly, even in simple games such as the biased coin, can
result in a wild ride of volatility to the point of terminal wealth. That volatility deters investors, and those
who rely on those investors as agents, from staying the course. Practitioners commonly use fractional
Kelly allocations to dampen that volatility.
• The long run. A Kelly system offers the highest probability of the most wealth in the long run. But some
individuals may need access to funds in the near term and therefore are unable to invest for the long haul.
As a result, fluctuations in the short term can blunt the benefits of compounding in the long term.
© 2025 Morgan Stanley. All rights reserved. 4236776 Exp. 2/28/2026 19
• Dynamic opportunity set. The system assumes the investment probabilities and payoffs are relatively
constant and that the opportunity set is sufficient to support a growing asset base. It is harder to apply the
system when investment payoffs and opportunities are in flux.
• Portfolio construction. The Kelly criterion is effective for a single, repeated opportunity. But the
application is vastly more complex for portfolios with a mix of opportunities. Optimizing for Kelly while
constructing a portfolio with multiple assets and varying degrees of correlation is a challenge.
• Some chance of disappointment. Maximizing the geometric mean increases the chance of ending up
with more wealth than other strategies but by no means guarantees it. There is always a small chance an
investor will do poorly and violate his or her utility function.
The main takeaway from this discussion is that there is a crucial difference between selecting the opportunity
with the highest expected value for one period and reinvesting returns in opportunities over multiple periods.
Mean/variance optimization is built for the former and geometric mean maximization works for the latter.
The lesson from ergodicity economics is that the experience of many (ensemble) is often irrelevant for the
experience of one (time average). You lead just one life and many of your results are path dependent, where
past outcomes influence future outcomes. Buying insurance makes sense because avoiding a disastrous result
is vital in a multiplicative process.
The Kelly criterion is a formal way to select investments and to size them appropriately. We observe that few
members of the fundamental equity investment community use Kelly. But its lessons are relevant, including
always seek edge, make your best investments your biggest positions, and never bet too much.
We noted that the difference between an arithmetic and geometric average is the volatility of returns. This is
called volatility drag and can create a large gap between the two measures of average.
There is no volatility drag when there is no volatility. For instance, zero coupon bonds, which do not pay interest
but start at a deep discount and accrete value at a steady rate until maturity, are an example of an asset where
the arithmetic and geometric average returns are the same.
Volatility drag arises because of the compounding effect of gains and losses. Start with $100 and assume you
are up 100 percent in year one (to $200) and down 50% in year 2 (to $100). The arithmetic average is 25 percent
([1.00 + -0.50] ÷ 2 = 0.25) and the geometric average is zero ([√2 x 0.50] – 1 = 0). Geometric returns are key
over time since it is capital accumulation that builds wealth.
Exhibit 13 shows the stocks in the S&P 500 with the highest and lowest geometric returns from 2005 to 2024.
Our sample includes only those stocks that traded the whole time. Take note of the difference between the
© 2025 Morgan Stanley. All rights reserved. 4236776 Exp. 2/28/2026 20
arithmetic and geometric average annual returns. Lennox International, a provider of climate control solutions,
and Alphabet, a technology company that owns Google, had identical geometric returns (20.2 percent per year)
but Lennox’s average annual arithmetic return, 23.5 percent, was quite a bit lower than Alphabet’s 27.5 percent.
The other feature of this exhibit worth highlighting is the maximum drawdown, the largest decline from peak to
trough based on intraday prices, that each stock had over the 20 years. The average drawdown for the best
performing stocks was 69 percent, and a handful experienced drawdowns of more than 75 percent. Reaching
the peak of total shareholder returns almost always requires going through a valley.
Exhibit 13: Volatility Drag of Stocks with Highest and Lowest Returns in the S&P 500, 2005-24
TSR, Annual Average Standard Volatility Max
Name Arithmetic Geometric Deviation Drag Drawdown
S&P 500 11.9% 10.4% 17.3% 1.5% -55.3%
Top 20
1 NVIDIA 65.2% 39.2% 87.3% 26.0% -85.5%
2 Netflix 56.5% 36.5% 86.0% 20.0% -82.7%
3 Apple 41.8% 32.0% 52.3% 9.8% -61.5%
4 Booking Holdings 40.7% 30.7% 59.6% 9.9% -68.7%
5 Texas Pacific Land Corporation 36.0% 28.4% 45.3% 7.6% -74.3%
6 Monster Beverage 38.9% 28.0% 74.8% 10.9% -70.0%
7 Intuitive Surgical 42.4% 26.9% 73.7% 15.5% -76.4%
8 Amazon.com 37.2% 25.8% 56.9% 11.4% -65.7%
9 Salesforce 33.4% 24.4% 47.0% 8.9% -72.3%
10 Deckers Outdoor 38.8% 24.3% 61.7% 14.5% -77.6%
11 Regeneron Pharmaceuticals 31.4% 24.3% 50.6% 7.2% -58.9%
12 Monolithic Power Systems 32.0% 24.0% 44.6% 8.0% -76.1%
13 Tyler Technologies 28.6% 23.6% 36.0% 5.0% -49.6%
14 Fair Isaac Corporation 27.5% 22.3% 36.1% 5.3% -79.9%
15 Old Dominion Freight Line 25.8% 22.0% 31.2% 3.9% -53.9%
16 O'Reilly Automotive 23.6% 21.9% 21.0% 1.7% -48.5%
17 Domino's Pizza 29.6% 21.7% 41.0% 7.9% -92.7%
18 Quanta Services 24.6% 20.3% 32.7% 4.4% -70.2%
19 Lennox International 23.5% 20.2% 28.9% 3.4% -55.0%
20 Alphabet 27.5% 20.2% 41.9% 7.3% -66.9%
Top 20 Average 35.3% 25.8% 50.4% 9.4% -69.3%
Bottom 20
1 American International Group 5.9% -11.4% 40.7% 17.3% -99.6%
2 Citigroup 1.3% -7.1% 37.2% 8.4% -98.3%
3 Walgreens Boots Alliance 0.4% -4.3% 30.0% 4.6% -91.7%
4 Paramount Global Class B 4.4% -2.5% 37.4% 6.9% -96.1%
5 APA Corporation 4.5% -2.5% 41.0% 6.9% -97.5%
6 Carnival Corporation 5.6% -2.1% 41.6% 7.7% -91.6%
7 Viatris, Inc. 3.3% -0.8% 31.4% 4.1% -89.0%
8 KeyCorp 5.6% -0.1% 33.9% 5.7% -89.0%
9 PG&E Corporation 3.2% -0.1% 23.9% 3.3% -95.0%
10 MGM Resorts International 10.6% 0.0% 42.4% 10.5% -98.2%
11 Newmont Corporation 4.6% 1.0% 29.4% 3.6% -78.7%
12 Regions Financial Corporation 7.0% 1.1% 33.6% 6.0% -94.0%
13 Mohawk Industries 6.2% 1.3% 30.0% 4.8% -84.3%
14 Ford Motor Company 19.1% 1.4% 86.7% 17.7% -93.2%
15 Devon Energy Corporation 10.5% 1.4% 53.7% 9.1% -96.3%
16 Huntington Bancshares 6.5% 1.5% 33.1% 5.0% -96.1%
17 AES Corporation 6.5% 1.6% 30.6% 4.9% -80.2%
18 Bank of America Corp 9.4% 1.9% 39.2% 7.5% -95.4%
19 Intel Corporation 8.3% 2.0% 35.8% 6.3% -73.3%
20 Zimmer Biomet Holdings 4.5% 2.1% 23.1% 2.4% -67.5%
Bottom 20 Average 6.4% -0.8% 37.7% 7.1% -90.2%
Source: FactSet and Counterpoint Global.
Note: Based on companies in the S&P 500 as of 12/31/2024 that traded for the entire period; TSR=total shareholder return.
© 2025 Morgan Stanley. All rights reserved. 4236776 Exp. 2/28/2026 21
One extreme example of volatility drag is the GraniteShares 3x Long MicroStrategy Daily ETP (exchange-traded
product). This is a security that seeks to provide total return exposure equal to three times the daily performance
of Strategy (formerly called MicroStrategy Inc.), a software company that is a large holder of the cryptocurrency
Bitcoin.79 For example, if Strategy’s stock goes up 5 percent in a day, the security is designed to rise 15 percent
(excluding slippage from tracking error, fees, and “eventual market disruption events”).
In 2024, Strategy shares were up 358.5 percent and the GraniteShares 3x ETP, which trades on the London
Stock Exchange, were down 47.6 percent. At a high level, the reason is that the leverage factor is reset every
day. After days when the stock has gone up, the fund increases its exposure to maintain the three times leverage
ratio. And when the stock goes down it reduces its exposure. This “buy-high” and “sell-low” feature creates the
huge gap between the underlying asset and the fund.80
GraniteShares is clear about these risks in its product material, including the point that holding for longer than
one day will create a return gap between the fund and Strategy’s stock. But it does not seem natural that a fund
aiming to offer returns three times those of the underlying stock can go down a lot over a period when the stock
goes up a lot.
Volatility drag and drawdowns are reasons it is psychologically difficult to deal with probabilistic systems. There
are various challenges, including failing to accurately assess probabilities and payoffs, streaks of losses despite
making positive expected value investments, and the practical and mental challenge of drawdowns.
The psychology of surprise is the study of how we react when outcomes differ meaningfully from expectations.
You can assume that investors who lament that an adverse outcome was a “20-sigma event” or a “perfect storm”
misunderstand the underlying probabilities and payoffs.
One vivid example is the stock market crash in 1987. Roger Lowenstein, a journalist, summarized some
academic research on the crash: “Economists later figured that, on the basis of the market’s historical volatility,
had the market been open every day since the creation of the Universe, the odds would still have been against
its falling that much in a single day. In fact, had the life of the Universe been repeated one billion times, such a
crash would still have been theoretically ‘unlikely’.”81 The goal is to have sufficient humility when dealing with
unknown unknowns and to act accordingly.
Loss aversion is the idea that we suffer losses more than we enjoy gains of comparable size. Exhibit 3 shows it
visually. Daniel Kahneman, who won the Nobel Prize in Economics despite being a psychologist, suggested that
“loss aversion is certainly the most significant contribution of psychology to behavioral economics.”82
Academic research has found that the average loss aversion coefficient is about 2.0 and the median is 1.7.83
That means the negative utility of losing $1 is twice the positive utility of gaining $1. But it is important to
acknowledge that the loss aversion coefficient for a population is distributed rather than uniform.
Loss aversion coefficients also vary by age and gender. Loss aversion tends to follow the shape of a “U,” high
for young people aged 18-24, troughing in the age range of 35-44, and again rising for adults over 55 years old.
Women also have a loss aversion coefficient that is consistently higher, although only modestly so, than that of
men.84
Another important consideration is that our individual loss aversion coefficient, no matter what it is at baseline,
can change based on our recent financial experience. Specifically, we tend to suffer losses more after having
realized losses.85 That shift in aversion can alter decision-making.
To illustrate the point, scientists created an investment game that compared the results of normal participants,
recruited from the local community, with participants who had brain damage. 86 Importantly, those with brain
damage had normal intelligence and the parts of their brains that dealt with logic and reasoning were intact. The
damage made it so these participants did not have normal feelings of fear or anxiety.
Each person was endowed with $20 at the start of the game. In each round the players had to decide whether
or not to invest one dollar, and the game would last 20 rounds. If the player did not play, they would keep their
dollar and move on to the next round. If they played, the experimenter flipped a fair coin and paid $2.50 for tails
and nothing for heads. The scientists created an incentive to end up with as much money as possible by
promising a gift certificate in the amount that the participant won.
The game is analytically straightforward, with a certain value of $1 to not play and an expected value of $1.25
to play (0.50 × $2.50 = $1.25). The ideal strategy is to play every round.
The scientists tallied the results and found that the participants with brain damage ended up with 13 percent
more money, on average, than those with normal brains ($25.70 versus $22.80).
Overall, the patients with brain damage played in 45 percent more rounds than the normal players did, and they
invested in rounds following a loss at a rate double that of the normal players.
The pattern of play is telling. All of the participants played at a high rate in the first five rounds. This shows that
everyone understood that the expected value was positive for each round. But as the game went on, normal
people chose to play fewer rounds after having suffered losses. Loss aversion kicked in.
The patients with brain damage, immune from fear and anxiety, played at a high rate throughout the experiment.
Brain damage, while debilitating in day-to-day life, spared them the sense of loss aversion and allowed them to
focus on expected value.
Baba Shiv, a professor of marketing and one of the scientists running the study, observed that the normal
participants “know the right thing to do is invest in every single round, but when they actually get into the game,
they just start reacting to the outcomes of previous rounds.” 87
Stop a moment to consider the implication. Individuals are willing to pass over positive expected value
propositions after having suffered losses. In periods following large losses in the stock market, such as March
2009, the difficulty is not finding investment opportunities with attractive expected values but rather overcoming
the aversion to losing more money.
The certainty and magnitude of payoffs can vary for investment opportunities. How investment alternatives are
presented can alter how people choose between them. Importantly, individuals often show preferences that
disagree with expected utility theory.
Opportunity 1 Opportunity 2
Choice Probability Payoff Choice Probability Payoff
A 100% $1,000,000 C 89% $0
11% $1,000,000
or or
Maurice Allais, a physicist and economist who won the Nobel Prize in Economics, showed these opportunities
to participants and found that they generally selected choice A from the first opportunity and D from the second
one. Selecting A and C, or B and D, is consistent with theory. But picking A and D, certainty in the first case and
higher expected value in the second, demonstrates inconsistent preferences and violates the axiom of
independence.88
Time also plays a significant role in the psychology of investing. Richard Thaler, a winner of the Nobel Prize in
Economics, and Shlomo Benartzi are behavioral economists who introduced the concept of “myopic loss
aversion.”89 They combine loss aversion with myopia, or nearsightedness, to explain why some short-term
oriented investors may suffer more from loss aversion than long-term investors do.90
Here is how it works. The stock market tends to go up over time because investors expect a positive return to
compensate them for deferring consumption. But returns in the short term are negative some percentage of the
time. For example, using past results as a guide, we estimate the probability of a positive gain to be about 55
percent for 1 day, 59 percent for 1 week, 63 percent for 1 month, and 73 percent for 1 year. An investor who
looks at her portfolio frequently is more likely to see losses, and suffer from loss aversion, than the investor who
looks at her portfolio infrequently.
The implication is that valuation depends in part on time horizon, as short-term investors will demand a higher
risk premium to overcome their loss aversion than will long-term investors. A slew of follow-up research suggests
that myopic loss aversion is relevant for individual and institutional investors.91
Psychology also enters into an assessment of investment process. Results in the investment industry, similar to
any field with payoffs and probabilities, has a large dose of luck in the short term. That means that someone can
make good decisions and have bad outcomes.
Difficult periods of returns, which are inevitable as part of the process of building a successful long-term
investment record, cast doubt on the ability of an investment process to identify opportunities with attractive
expected value. This creates a psychological challenge of determining whether disappointing results are the
consequence of a good process with normal variance, which is acceptable, or a bad process, which is not.
Finally, we return to the challenging effect of large drawdowns. Hendrik Bessembinder, a professor of finance,
identified the stocks of companies that created the most wealth in the last century, including Apple, Microsoft,
For example, Amazon’s stock had a compound annual growth rate of 33.5 percent from the price of its initial
public offering to the end of 2024 and created more than $2 trillion in wealth net of Treasury bill returns. But from
December 9, 1999 to October 1, 2001, the stock suffered a drawdown of 95 percent based on intraday prices.
Large drawdowns create three challenges. The first is that it is hard for an institutional investor to hold a stock
through a large drawdown due to concerns of being wrong and skeptical queries from clients. Second, as exhibit
13 reveals, some stocks have large drawdowns and do not recover. Finally, drawdowns in institutionally-
managed portfolios commonly lead to investor outflows, forcing a portfolio manager to sell positions when they
are down. This is important because academic research shows that institutional investors select stocks
effectively when based on valuation but that decisions induced by investor flows tend to be deleterious to fund
results.93
Psychology is important because it helps explain what we expect to see, how we react to losses, and how our
preferences can change based on our recent experience. We now turn to the probability and payoff
characteristics of various asset classes.
There are multiple asset classes within equities, including public equities, buyouts, and venture capital. Each
has its own profile of probabilities and payoffs, which you can think of as the raw material for constructing a fund.
The differences are relevant for the portfolio managers and investors in each asset class.
Richard Grinold, a former Global Director of Research at Barclays Global Investors, developed what he called
the “fundamental law of active management:”94
The equation says that excess return (information ratio) equals skill (information coefficient) times the opportunity
set (square root of breadth). More formally, the information coefficient is the correlation between forecasts and
outcomes, and breadth is the number of independent opportunities for excess returns in a specified period.
Ronald van Loon, a portfolio manager at BlackRock, further breaks down information coefficient into batting
average, which is “the number of winning decisions as a proportion of total decisions,” and slugging ratio, “the
average return of the wins over the negative of the average return of the losses.” He also worked out a way to
deal with distributions of asset returns with fat tails.95
Skill shows up in the batting average and slugging ratio. Portfolio construction, how investments are weighted
in the portfolio, is also relevant. The pattern of returns for the underlying assets plays a substantial role in how
a manager reveals his or her skill.
The best way to think about opportunity set, or breadth, is dispersion. 96 The intuition is straightforward. We can
use stocks as an example. If the expected returns for all relevant stocks are very similar it is hard for an
investment manager to distinguish him or herself. If the expected returns are highly dispersed, a skillful manager
produces excess returns by selecting the ones that go up and avoiding the ones that go down.
Understanding the dispersion of the returns of the available investment opportunities is crucial. Think of it this
way: the dispersion of the fund returns in each asset class will mirror the dispersion of the investment returns.
Examining how the pool of potential investments performs gives a sense of the characteristics of the asset class.
We now look at the actual distribution of returns that comprise the opportunity set for public equities, buyouts,
and venture capital. To provide some grounding, we estimate that the assets under management (AUM) for
active and index funds that manage U.S. public equities are at least $40 trillion at the end of 2024. The AUM
was $2.7 trillion for the buyout industry and $1.3 trillion for the venture capital industry in the U.S. in mid-2024,
according to PitchBook, a financial data company that tracks private markets.97
Mutual funds generally own 50-100 stocks and there are about 4,000 public companies in the U.S. Buyout funds
normally hold between 10-20 companies and control around 12,000 companies in total. Venture capital funds
commonly make 10-50 investments per fund, with funds that invest in later stages on the low side and those
that invest in earlier stages on the high side, and own more than 58,000 companies in aggregate.98 There are
roughly 5.5 million companies in the U.S.99
Exhibit 15 shows about 34,000 observations of 5-year returns, measured as multiples of invested capital at the
beginning of the period, for stocks in the Russell 1000. We collected 35 increments of 5-year returns from year-
end 1985 through year-end 2024. We selected five years because that is similar to the historical average holding
period for a company in a private equity portfolio, with VC slightly longer and buyouts slightly shorter than 5
years on average. Note that 25 percent lose money, the modal outcome is a gain of between 1 and 1.5 times,
and there are few extreme values.
50
Frequency (Percent)
40
30
20
10
0
8.0-8.5
0.0-0.5
0.5-1.0
1.0-1.5
1.5-2.0
2.0-2.5
2.5-3.0
3.0-3.5
3.5-4.0
4.0-4.5
4.5-5.0
5.0-5.5
5.5-6.0
6.0-6.5
6.5-7.0
7.0-7.5
7.5-8.0
8.5-9.0
9.0-9.5
>10.0
9.5-10.0
Bessembinder collaborates with other researchers to show that long-term returns for mutual funds follow a
similar pattern.101 Both findings are consistent with the idea that the returns for stocks are non-ergodic.
Exhibit 16 shows more than 15,000 observations of returns, measured as multiples of initial invested capital, for
global buyout deals. Most of the returns are from transactions done from the mid-1990s to 2018. Twenty-seven
percent lose money, the modal outcome is a loss of 50 to 100 percent of invested capital, and the tails are fatter
than those for public equities.
Academics developed a measure called “public market equivalent” (PME) to make a direct comparison between
returns in private versus public markets. PME is generally reflected as a ratio between private equity and public
market returns, with a ratio above 1.0 suggesting relative outperformance.102
Studies show that buyout funds have generally had PMEs in excess of 1.0, although this finding is not without
challenge.103 This result shows that an asset class with a lower batting average can have a higher return than
one with a higher batting average because of the pattern of payoffs. Venture capital is a more extreme example.
50
Frequency (Percent)
40
30
20
10
0
5.0-5.5
7.0-7.5
9.0-9.5
0.0-0.5
0.5-1.0
1.0-1.5
1.5-2.0
2.0-2.5
2.5-3.0
3.0-3.5
3.5-4.0
4.0-4.5
4.5-5.0
5.5-6.0
6.0-6.5
6.5-7.0
7.5-8.0
8.0-8.5
8.5-9.0
>10.0
9.5-10.0
50
Frequency (Percent)
40
30
20
10
0
0.0-0.5
3.5-4.0
7.0-7.5
0.5-1.0
1.0-1.5
1.5-2.0
2.0-2.5
2.5-3.0
3.0-3.5
4.0-4.5
4.5-5.0
5.0-5.5
5.5-6.0
6.0-6.5
6.5-7.0
7.5-8.0
8.0-8.5
8.5-9.0
9.0-9.5
>10.0
9.5-10.0
Multiple of Invested Capital
Source: Based on Gregory Brown, Robert S. Harris, Wendy Hu, Tim Jenkinson, Steven N. Kaplan, and David Robinson,
“Private Equity Portfolio Companies: A First Look at Burgiss Holdings Data,” SSRN Working Paper, March 3, 2020.
The PMEs for venture capital have also been above 1.0, and higher than buyouts, over time. But the high PMEs
in venture have come in bursts, with long stretches of PMEs close to or below 1.0 interspersed with periods of
very high returns. Venture capital fund returns show that it is possible to have a batting average below 50 percent
and still have satisfactory returns if the slugging ratio is sufficiently high.
Exhibit 18 shows our estimate of the batting average and slugging ratio of a handful of asset classes within
equities. There is naturally a lot of variance for funds in each asset class. The point is that there are meaningfully
different paths to seeking excess returns. One study compared the returns of equity funds run systematically
(e.g., quantitative funds) to those run with human discretion (e.g., diversified mutual funds) and concluded,
“systematic and discretionary funds have historically had similar performance after adjusting for volatility and
factor exposures.”104
High Venture
capital funds
Buyout funds
Diversified
mutual funds
Slugging
Ratio
Quantitative
funds
1.0
Low
Low 0.5 High
Batting Average
Source: FactSet and Counterpoint Global.
Exhibit 19 shows how the dispersion of the opportunity set translates into the dispersion of fund performance by
asset class.105 As the underlying return data would suggest, venture capital funds have the highest dispersion,
followed by buyout funds. The dispersion for mutual funds that invest in large capitalization stocks is much lower.
Exhibit 19: Dispersion of Returns for Active Managers in Various Asset Classes
50%
Percentiles
40% 95th
75th
Dispersion from the Median
30%
25th
20%
5th
10%
0%
-10%
-20%
-30%
-40%
Venture Buyout Long/Short Large Cap Small Cap Taxable Bond
Capital Equity Equity Equity Mutual Funds
Hedge Funds Mutual Funds Mutual Funds
Source: Morningstar Direct, PitchBook, and Counterpoint Global.
Note: Venture capital and buyout: net internal rates of return since inception for vintage years 1980-2018; hedge funds and
mutual funds: trailing 5-year annualized returns net of expenses with income reinvested through 12/31/2019.
© 2025 Morgan Stanley. All rights reserved. 4236776 Exp. 2/28/2026 29
Here again access is relevant. The returns for the top venture and buyout funds have been very attractive,
whereas the performance of the bottom funds has been much worse than that of public equities. Investors who
were able to gain access to the funds in the top quintile had a markedly different experience than those exposed
to the bottom quintile.
Benchmarks are also important. Public equity investors can invest in an index fund at a low cost whereas
comparable benchmarks are not readily available in private markets (hence the development of PME as a
measure of comparison). Investors in bonds, an asset class with less volatility than that of equities historically,
also run into a benchmark problem.106
An appreciation of the probabilities and payoffs, as well as the opportunity set, across various asset classes can
be useful to an investor seeking to generate excess returns. The nature of the probabilities and payoffs for the
underlying investments also means that what constitutes skill, in terms of batting average and slugging ratio,
differs by asset class. Again, it is not how often you are right that matters, it is how much you make when you
are right versus how much you lose when you are wrong.
Conclusion
The prime task of an investor seeking to generate excess returns is to find opportunities where there are gaps
between price and value. This is commonly called variant perception, or edge. Price is relatively straightforward
but assessing value can be a challenge. The common approach is to consider expected value, which is the sum
of the products of various payoffs and their associated probabilities. The task then becomes coming up with
payoffs and probabilities in a thoughtful manner.
The Babe Ruth effect highlights that it is not only how often you are right that matters (probability) but how much
you make when you are right versus how much you lose when you are wrong (payoffs). Venture capital, as an
asset class, loses more frequently than it wins. But the gains are so large they offset the losses in the aggregate.
Expected values can be characterized in different ways. With risk, no one knows which outcome will occur but
all the possible outcomes can be identified in advance. With uncertainty, both the outcomes and the range of
possible outcomes are unknown. And then there is the domain of “unknown, unknowns,” where ignorance
prevents an assessment of what might happen.
Determining payoffs comes with a number of challenges, including identifying the shape of the distribution,
reflecting potential non-linearities, recognizing the relationship between control and reversibility, assessing
asymmetries, and acknowledging that exogenous and endogenous risks affect payoffs.
There are recognized approaches to setting probabilities, including frequentist, propensity, and subjective belief.
Most forecasts in investing are based on subjective beliefs, which follow the laws of probability but require
updating with new information. Probabilities also come with varying degrees of confidence—sometimes a belief
can be held but with low confidence. Using probabilities instead of words is essential for clarity of communication
and as a basis for feedback and learning.
Best practices in setting payoffs and probabilities include using base rates, applying sensitivity analysis and
simulation, and, above all, always insisting on a margin of safety. The margin of safety reflects the size of the
gap between price and value and allows for incorrect analysis and bad luck.
Assessing expected value through payoffs and probabilities is very useful, and in decisions beyond one period
it is optimal to find the highest expected value for an assumed risk appetite. But the situation changes when the
process shifts from arithmetic to multiplicative.
© 2025 Morgan Stanley. All rights reserved. 4236776 Exp. 2/28/2026 30
In systems that are ergodic, where the ensemble and time averages are the same, it almost always makes the
most sense to pursue the approach with the highest arithmetic mean. In systems that are non-ergodic, where
the ensemble and time averages are different, the best approach is usually to find the opportunity with the
highest geometric mean.
This is important because markets are largely non-ergodic. The experience of the group is not relevant to an
individual who goes through life but once. As a consequence, understanding and integrating an appreciation of
the geometric mean of an investment opportunity is central to building wealth in the long term.
The Kelly criterion is an investment guideline based on geometric mean maximization. The Kelly criterion offers
two useful lessons even for those who do not use the principle in practice. The first is that every investment
opportunity should include edge. The second is that it is possible to bet too much. Sometimes increasing the
size of an attractive opportunity leads to a lower, not higher, expected return.
Volatility creates the difference between an asset’s arithmetic and geometric returns. This is called volatility drag.
Many of the best investments over time are volatile and have large drawdowns.
There are psychological challenges in dealing with probabilistic realms. One example is loss aversion, the idea
that we suffer roughly twice as much from losses as we enjoy gains of comparable size. While the coefficient of
loss aversion is around two on average, there is a great deal of variation by individual. Perhaps more importantly,
our loss aversion coefficients tend to go up after we have suffered losses. This means that people may react
differently to a financial opportunity based on the circumstances.
Time horizon is also very important. Markets tend to go up in the long term, but losses are common in the short
term. Investors who evaluate their portfolios frequently are more likely to see losses and hence suffer from loss
aversion. This means that the appetite for risk depends to some degree on the investor’s time horizon.
Excess returns are a function of skill and opportunity set. Skill can be assessed through batting average, how
often you make money, and slugging ratio, how much you make when you are right versus how much you lose
when you are wrong. Dispersion is a useful way to look at investment opportunities.
The opportunity sets of public equities, buyouts, and venture capital vary substantially. For example, based on
the figures we used, 25 percent of public equity investments lost money over 5 years compared to 62 percent
of venture capital investments. Offsetting that average is the fact that venture had more very high return
investments than did public markets.
One consequence of the variation in opportunity sets is the dispersion of returns for managers in each asset
class. Dispersion is the highest in venture capital, followed by buyouts, and then public equities. As a result,
access is important. Owning venture capital funds in the top quartile of performance has provided handsome
excess returns whereas owning those in the bottom quartile has been a challenge.
Investing is an inherently probabilistic endeavor. The ideas surrounding payoffs and probabilities can help the
intelligent investor build a portfolio positioned to generate excess returns.
The Brier score is a common method used to measure the accuracy of probabilistic forecasts. The score was
created by Glenn Brier, a meteorologist, in the 1950s.107 A basic version of the Brier score measures the square
of the forecast error. For binary events, the value is 1 if the event occurs and 0 if it does not. A lower score is
better.
Brier’s original approach had a scale of 0 to 2 (other versions have a scale from 0 to 1). In this basic case the
calculation considers the squared forecast error for both the event and the non-event.
Exhibit 20 is an example based on a meteorologist’s forecast for rain over four days. Take Day 2 as an illustration
of the calculation. Our meteorologist forecasted a 90 percent chance of rain and, by definition, a 10 percent
probability it would not rain. It did rain, so mark a “1” in the outcome column below “Rain” and a “0” under “No
Rain.” Our meteorologist’s Brier score for that day was 0.02. ([0.9 – 1]2 + [0.1 – 0]2 = 0.01 + 0.01 = 0.02). An
overall Brier score is the average over multiple forecasts. The meteorologist’s Brier score over these 4 days is
0.15.
One nice feature of the scale from 0 to 2 is that random guesses have a Brier score of 0.50. Top forecasters of
political, economic, and social outcomes have Brier scores of around 0.20-0.25. The key is to communicate
using terms that a Brier score can measure. As Phil Tetlock and Dan Gardner write in their book,
Superforecasting, “Forecast, measure, and revise: it is the surest path to seeing better.” 108
founded view that was meaningfully different from the market consensus . . . Understanding market expectation
was at least as important as, and often different from, the fundamental knowledge.” Ed Thorp, a mathematician
and extremely successful investment manager, said, “There is a market inefficiency if there is a participant who
can generate excess risk-adjusted returns that can be logically explained in a way that is difficult to rebut.” See
Michael Steinhardt, No Bull: My Life In and Out of Markets (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2001), 129 and Ed
Thorp interview in Jack D. Schwager, Hedge Fund Market Wizards: How Winning Traders Win (Hoboken, NJ:
John Wiley & Sons, 2012), 217.
3 Ĺuboš Pástor and Robert F. Stambaugh, “Liquidity Risk and Expected Stock Returns,” Journal of Political
Wall Street and has done fine work on analytics for the investment industry, wrote a book called Moneyball for
the Money Set: Using Sports Analytics to Predict the Returns of Portfolio Managers with Startling Accuracy. Joe
worked for one of the largest multi-strategy hedge funds and had access to the performance data of the various
portfolio managers, which he analyzed in an effort to assess skill. He found that hit rate, or daily percentage of
stocks that outperformed an average of relevant stocks in the sector, was one of the most important signals. He
argues that a hit rate above 50 percent is a key to success. This is a reasonable measure of skill for this strategy.
Peta goes on to dedicate a chapter to “debunking the George Soros narrative.” The setup is that the former chief
investment officer of Soros Fund Management and current U.S. Secretary of the Treasury, Scott Bessent, is
quoted as saying that Soros’s hit rate was less than 50 percent. Peta goes on to suggest that a hit rate of less
than 50 percent was “impossible” given Soros’s track record.
What Peta misses is that there are strategies that do succeed with hit rates below 50 percent, including trend
followers. (See Michael Covel, “Trend Following Winners Are Not Lucky Monkeys,” Active Trader Magazine.)
Peta’s analysis appears valid for the investment approach he studies but is not universally applicable.
5 Michael J. Mauboussin, More Than You Know: Finding Financial Wisdom in Unconventional Places—Updated
and Expanded (New York: Columbia Business School Publishing, 2008), 24. For a list of great quotations about
batting average, see http://mastersinvest.com/battingaverage.
6 Steven Crist, Exotic Betting: How to Make the Multihorse, Multirace Bets That Win Racing’s Biggest Payoffs
Journal, January 25, 2025 and Flutter Investor Day, Management Presentation and Q&A, New York, September
25, 2024.
8 Gunjan Banerji, “Wall Street’s Hot New Trade Is Fueling Gambling Addictions,” Wall Street Journal, December
23, 2024.
9 Warren E. Buffett, Berkshire Hathaway Annual Meeting, 1989.
10 Daniel Bernoulli, “Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk,” Econometrica, Vol. 22, No. 1,
January 1954, 23-36. To express the point more formally, for someone who is risk averse, as the expected value
increases (x-axis), utility increases at a lesser rate (y-axis), and the resulting curve is concave. Simple equations
to capture this include U(x) = x0.5 or U(x) = log(x).
Keynes makes similar points in his book, A Treatise on Probability, also published in 1921.
13 Donald H. Rumsfeld (Secretary of Defense), “Department of Defense News Briefing,” February 12, 2002.
14 Richard Zeckhauser, “Investing in the Unknown and Unknowable,” Capitalism and Society, Vol. 1, No. 2, 2006,
Article 5.
15 Don A. Moore, Perfectly Confident: How to Calibrate Your Decisions Wisely (New York: Harper Business,
2020), 8.
16 Benoit B. Mandelbrot, Fractals and Scaling in Finance: Discontinuity, Concentration, Risk (New York: Springer,
1997), 117-125 and Benoit B. Mandelbrot and Nassim Nicholas Taleb, “Mild vs. Wild Randomness: Focusing
on Those Risks That Matter,” in The Known, the Unknown, and the Unknowable in Financial Risk Management:
Measurement and Theory Advancing Practice, Francis X. Diebold, Neil A. Doherty, and Richard J. Herring, eds.,
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010), 47-58.
17 A power law is a relationship between two variables where one varies as a constant power of the other. The
slope of the line that best fits the data is the exponent, or “power,” that defines the law.
18 Taleb, The Black Swan, xvii-xviii.
19 Seneca, translated by Robin Campbell, Letters from a Stoic (London: Penguin House, 1969), 178.
20 Philip Ball, Critical Mass: How One Thing Leads to Another (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2004), 80-
97. Ball takes the term “the grand ah-whoom” from Kurt Vonnegut’s book, Cat’s Cradle.
21 James Surowiecki, The Wisdom of Crowds: Why the Many Are Smarter Than the Few and How Collective
Wisdom Shapes Business, Economies, Societies, and Nations (New York: Doubleday and Company, 2004).
22 Peter L. Bernstein, “Risk, Time, and Reversibility,” The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, Vol. 24, No.
Vol. 47, No. 2, March 1979, 263-292. More accurately, these conclusions derive from “cumulative prospect
theory” (see Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation
of Uncertainty,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 5, No. 4, October 1992, 297-323.) Barberis and Huang
summarize the advance beautifully: “Under cumulative prospect theory, people evaluate risk using a value
function that is defined over gains and losses, that is concave over gains and convex over losses, and that is
kinked at the origin; and using transformed rather than objective probabilities, where the transformed
probabilities are obtained from objective probabilities by applying a weighting function. The main effect of the
weighting function is to overweight the tails of the distribution it is applied to. The overweighting of tails does not
represent a bias in beliefs; it is simply a modeling device that captures the common preference for a lottery-like,
or positively skewed, wealth distribution.” See Nicholas Barberis and Ming Huang, “Stocks as Lotteries: The
Implications of Probability Weighting for Security Prices,” American Economic Review, Vol. 98, No. 5, December
2008, 2066-2100 and Tobias J. Moskowitz and Kaushik Vasudevan, “Betting Without Beta,” Working Paper,
May 2, 2022.
25 Kimberly F. Luchtenberg and Michael J. Seiler, “Do Institutional and Individual Investors Differ in Their
Preference for Financial Skewness?” Journal of Behavioral Finance, Vol. 15, No. 4, 2014, 299-311.
26 Barberis and Huang, “Stocks as Lotteries” and Suk-Joon Byun, Jihoon Goh, and Da-Hea Kim, “The Role of
Psychological Barriers in Lottery-Related Anomalies,” Journal of Banking & Finance, Vol. 114, May 2020,
105786.
27 Antti Ilmanen, “Do Financial Markets Reward Buying or Selling Insurance and Lottery Tickets?” Financial
Analysts Journal, Vol. 68, No. 5, September/October 2012, 26-36. Perhaps not surprisingly, Nassim Taleb took
issue with Ilmanen’s conclusions. See Nassim Nicholas Taleb, “Do Financial Markets Reward Buying or Selling
Insurance and Lottery Tickets?: A Comment,” Financial Analysts Journal, Vol. 69, No. 2, March/April 2013, 17-
19.
28 Nassim Nicholas Taleb, “Bleed or Blowup? Why Do We Prefer Asymmetric Payoffs?” Journal of Behavioral
Portfolio Management, Vol. 15, No. 3, Spring 1989, 4-12 and Bradford Cornell, “What Moves Stock Prices:
Another Look,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 39, No. 3, Spring 2013, 32-38.
31 Cutler, Poterba, and Summers, “What Moves Stock Prices?” 9.
32 Jon Danielsson and Hyun Son Shin, “Endogenous Risk,” in Modern Risk Management: A History (London:
2002), 26-29.
35 Sharon Bertsch McGrayne, The Theory That Would Not Die: How Bayes’ Rule Cracked the Enigma Code,
Hunted Down Russian Submarines, and Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 2011).
36 Frank P. Ramsey, “Truth and Probability,” The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays, Richard
B. Braithwaite, ed. (London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., 1931), 156-198 and Annie Duke, Thinking in
Bets: Making Smarter Decisions When You Don't Have All the Facts (New York: Portfolio/Penguin, 2018).
37 Here’s an example of a problem that requires updating prior beliefs based on new evidence. It comes from
Daniel Kahneman, Thinking, Fast and Slow (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2011), 166:
“A cab was involved in a hit-and-run accident at night. Two cab companies, the Green and the Blue, operate in
the city. You are told that 85 percent of the cabs in the City are Green and 15 percent are Blue. A witness
identified the cab as Blue. The courts tested the reliability of the witness under the circumstances that existed
on the night of the accident and concluded that the witness correctly identified each of the two colors 80 percent
of the time. What is the probability that the cab involved in the accident was Blue rather than Green?”
The most common answer is 80 percent, likely reflecting the accuracy of the eyewitness, but the correct answer
is about 41 percent. The tendency is to place too much weight on the account of the witness and not enough
weight on the point that a large majority of cabs in the city are Green.
Here is how you get the answer. You need three quantities to solve for the new probability. First is a prior
probability. In this case, the prior probability (x) of a Blue cab getting into an accident would be 15 percent
(assuming Green and Blue cabs have an equal chance of an accident). Second, is an estimate of the probability
as a condition of the hypothesis being true (y). We have a witness who is 80 percent accurate claiming that a
Blue cab was in the accident. Finally, is an estimate conditional on the hypothesis being false (z), which is 20
percent (the complement of 80 percent).
Bayes’s Theorem tells us the revised probability =
xy .15 x .80 .12
= = = 41.4%
xy + z(1-x) .15 x .80 + .2(1-.15) .29
An easier way to think about this is to use natural numbers. Assume there are 1,000 cabs in the city. The
eyewitness, examining all of the green ones, would suggest with 20 percent accuracy that one was in the
accident (170) and looking at the blue ones would say with 80 percent accuracy that one was involved (120). So
the likelihood is 120/(170 + 120), or 41.4 percent. See Sanjit Dhami, Principles of Behavioral Economics:
Microeconomics & Human Behavior (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2025), 418-419.
38 Chetan Dave and Katherine W. Wolfe, “On Confirmation Bias and Deviations From Bayesian Updating,”
Working Paper, March 21, 2003. Notwithstanding individual bias, the impact on the market overall may be
modest. See Colin F. Camerer, “Do Biases in Probability Judgment Matter in Markets? Experimental Evidence,”
American Economic Review, Vol. 77, No. 5, December 1987, 981-997.
39 Philip E. Tetlock, Expert Political Judgment: How Good Is It? How Can We Know? (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
between subjective and objective probabilities. Resolution measures the ability to distinguish between high and
low probability events. For example, consider daily forecasts of rain in London, England. If you forecasted a 30
percent likelihood every day for a year, you would appear well calibrated (it rains about 30 percent of the days
in one year on average). But that does not help for planning picnics. Scoring high on resolution means accurately
predicting “no rain” for 70 percent of the days and “rain” for the other 30 percent.
46 Sarah Lichtenstein and Baruch Fischhoff, “Training for Calibration,” Organizational Behavior and Human
Performance, Vol. 26, No. 2, October 1980, 149-171 and Philip E. Tetlock and Dan Gardner, Superforecasting:
The Art and Science of Prediction (New York: Crown Publishers, 2015), 180-182.
47 Allan H. Murphy and Harald Daan, “Impacts of Feedback and Experience on the Quality of Subjective
Probability Forecasts: Comparison of Results from the First and Second Years of the Zierikzee Experiment,”
Monthly Weather Review, Vol. 112, No. 3, 1984, 413-423.
48 Mauboussin, More Than You Know, 9-14.
49 Shreenivas Kunte, “The Herding Mentality: Behavioral Finance and Investor Biases,” CFA Institute
Forecasting of Corporate Sales Growth,” Journal of Forecasting, Vol. 42, No. 5, August 2023, 1069-1085.
51 Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, “Evidential Impact of Base Rates,” in Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic,
and Amos Tversky eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press, 1982), 153-160 and Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky “On the Psychology of Prediction,”
Psychological Review, Vol. 80, No. 4, July 1973, 237-251. To amplify on the latter point, when an activity shows
high persistence—a strong correlation between sequential outcomes—then more weight is placed on
information and individual input. When persistence is low, more weight is assigned to base rates. The degree of
persistence is quantifiable for many measures of corporate performance, such as sales growth, operating profit
margins, and return on invested capital.
52 Aswath Damodaran, Narrative and Numbers: The Value of Stories in Business (New York: Columbia Business
Kahneman, Paul Slovic, and Amos Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 414-421.
55 Etienne Theising, “Distributional Reference Class Forecasting of Corporate Sales Growth With Multiple
with new commentary by Jason Zweig (New York: Harper Business, 2024), 505.
62 These are terms that Graham used.
63 Harry Markowitz, “Portfolio Selection,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 7, No. 1, March 1952, 77-91.
64 J. L. Kelly Jr., “A New Interpretation of Information Rate,” Bell System Technical Journal, 1956, 917-926.
65 William Poundstone, Fortune’s Formula: The Untold Story of the Scientific Betting System That Beat the
Casinos and Wall Street (New York: Hill and Wang, 2005), 200.
66 In Russian roulette, an individual puts a bullet into one of the six chambers of a revolver, spins the cylinder,
places the handgun in harm’s way, and pulls the trigger. The weapon fires the bullet one-sixth of the time when
the loaded chamber is lined up with the barrel.
67 Nassim Taleb writes, “[U]nlike a well-defined precise game like Russian roulette, where the risks are visible
to anyone capable of multiplying and dividing by six, one does not observe the barrel of reality. Very rarely is the
generator visible to the naked eye. One is thus capable of unwittingly playing Russian roulette—and calling it by
some alternative ‘low risk’ name. We see the wealth being generated, never the processor, a matter that makes
people lose sight of their risks, and never the losers. The game seems terribly easy and we play along blithely.”
See Nassim Nicholas Taleb, Fooled By Randomness: The Hidden Role of Chance in the Markets and in Life
(New York, Texere, 2001), 27-29.
68 Aaron Brown, Red Blooded Risk: The Secret History of Wall Street (Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, 2012),
73-99.
69 Harry M. Markowitz, “Investment for the Long Run: New Evidence for an Old Rule,” Journal of Finance, Vol.
31, No. 5, December 1976, 1273-1286. For an example of work that is similar to that of Kelly, see Henry Allen
Latané, “Criteria for Choice Among Risky Ventures,” The Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 67, No. 2, April 1959,
144-155.
70 Ole Peters, “The Ergodicity Problem in Economics,” Nature Physics, Vol. 15, December 2019, 1216-1221.
71 Ole Peters, “Insurance as an Ergodicity Problem,” Annals of Actuarial Science, Vol. 17, No. 2, July 2023, 215-
218.
72 Victor Haghani, and Richard Dewey, “Rational Decision Making under Uncertainty: Observed Betting Patterns
on a Biased Coin,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 43, No. 3, Spring 2017, 2-8 and Victor Haghani and
James White, The Missing Billionaires: A Guide to Better Financial Decisions (Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons,
2023), 15-25. You can find a version of this game at https://elmwealth.com/coin-flip/.
73 Another simple approach to Kelly for even money bets is f = 2p – 1. In this case p = 0.60, to f = 0.20 ([2 ×
0.60] – 1 = 0.20).
74 Rachel E.S. Ziemba and William T. Ziemba, Scenarios for Risk Management and Global Investment Strategies
(Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons, 2007), 95-122. Leverage commonly plays a role in overbetting. In his
paper, “Optimal Leverage from Non-Ergodicity,” Ole Peters considers optimal leverage assuming non-ergodicity.
75 Oliver Gergaud and William T. Ziemba, “Great Investors: Their Methods, Results and Evaluation,” in William
T. Ziemba, Great Investment Ideas (Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific, 2017), 175-212.
76 Edward O. Thorp, Beat the Dealer: A Winning Strategy for the Game of Twenty-One (New York: Blaisdell
MacLean, Edward O. Thorp, and William T. Ziemba, eds., The Kelly Capital Growth Investment Criterion: Theory
and Practice (Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific, 2011), 823.
78 See Paul A. Samuelson, “The ‘Fallacy’ of Maximizing the Geometric Mean in Long Sequences of Investing or
Gambling,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Vol. 68, No. 10, October 1971, 2493-2496;
Rubinstein, Mark, “No ‘Best’ Strategy for Portfolio Insurance,” Letter to the Editor in Financial Analysts Journal,
Vol. 43, No. 6, November/December 1987, 77-80; and Zeckhauser, “Investing in the Unknown and Unknowable.”
79 The reality is a little more complicated. GraniteShares 3x Long MicroStrategy Daily ETP tries to replicate the
performance of the Solactive Daily Leveraged 3x Long MicroStrategy Index, which in turn seeks total return
Random House, 2000), 72. Lowenstein is quoting Jens Carsten Jackwerth and Mark Rubinstein, “Recovering
Probability Distributions from Option Prices,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 51, No. 5, December 1996, 1612.
Jackwerth and Rubinstein note that assuming annualized volatility of 20 percent for the market and a lognormal
distribution, the 29 percent drop in the S&P 500 futures was a 27 standard deviation event, with a probability of
10-160.
82 Kahneman, Thinking, Fast and Slow, 300.
83 Alexander L. Brown, Taisuke Imai, Ferdinand M. Vieider, and Colin F. Camerer, “Meta-Analysis of Empirical
Estimates of Loss Aversion,” Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. 62, No. 2, June 2024, 485-516.
84 David Blake, Edmund Cannon, and Douglas Wright, “Quantifying Loss Aversion: Evidence from a UK
Population Survey,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 63, No. 1, August 2021, 27-57 and for a broader
overview see Olivier l'Haridon and Ferdinand M. Vieider, “All Over the Map: A Worldwide Comparison of Risk
Preferences,” Quantitative Economics, Vol. 10, No. 1, January 2019, 185-215.
85 Alex Imas, “The Realization Effect: Risk-Taking after Realized versus Paper Losses,” American Economic
Behavior and the Negative Side of Emotion,” Psychological Science, Vol. 16, No. 6, June 2005, 435-439.
87 Jane Spencer, “Lessons From the Brain-Damaged Investor: Unusual Study Explores Links Between Emotion
and Results; ‘Neuroeconomics’ on Wall Street,” Wall Street Journal, July 21, 2005.
88 The independence axiom states that if someone prefers A over B, they should prefer C over D when the latter
two are mixed with the same probability of a third outcome. (In this case, if you add an 89 percent chance of
making $1,000,000 to C and D, which should not change your preference, the options become identical and A
= C and B = D.) For more on the Allais Paradox, see Maurice Allais and Ole Hagen, eds., Expected Utility
Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox (Dordrecht, Holland: Springer Science + Business, 1979), 25-145; John A.
List and Michael S. Haigh, “A Simple Test of Expected Utility Theory Using Professional Traders,” PNAS, Vol.
102, No. 3, January 18, 2005, 945-948; and Floris Heukelom, “A History of the Allais Paradox,” The British
Journal for the History of Science, Vol. 48, No. 1, March 2015, 147-169.
89 The goal of their paper was to attempt to solve the puzzle of the equity risk premium. In short, equity returns
appeared to be higher compared to bonds than their relative risk justified. See Rajnish Mehra and Edward C.
Prescott, “The Equity Premium: A Puzzle,” Journal of Monetary Economics, Vol. 15, No. 2, March 1985, 145-
161.
90 Shlomo Benartzi and Richard H. Thaler, “Myopic Loss Aversion and the Equity Premium Puzzle,” The
Myopia and Loss Aversion on Risk Taking: An Experimental Test,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol.
112, No. 2, May 1997, 647-661; Nicholas Barberis and Ming Huang, “Mental Accounting, Loss Aversion, and
Individual Stock Returns,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 56, No. 4, August 2001, 1247-1292; and Michael S. Haigh
and John A. List, “Do Professional Traders Exhibit Myopic Loss Aversion? An Experimental Analysis,” Journal
of Finance, Vol. 60, No. 1, February 2005, 523-534.
92 Hendrik Bessembinder, “Extreme Stock Market Performers, Part I: Expect Some Drawdowns,” Working Paper,
July 2020.
93 Martin Rohleder, Dominik Schulte, Janik Syryca, and Marco Wilkens, “Mutual Fund Stock‐Picking Skill: New
Evidence from Valuation‐ versus Liquidity‐Motivated Trading,” Financial Management, Vol. 47, No. 2, Summer
2018, 309-347.
94 Richard C. Grinold, “The Fundamental Law of Active Management,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol.
15, No. 3, Spring 1989, 30-37. Also, see Richard C. Grinold and Ronald N. Kahn, Active Portfolio Management:
A Quantitative Approach for Producing Superior Returns and Controlling Risk, Second Edition (New York:
McGraw Hill, 2000), 147-169.
1998); Harindra de Silva, Steven Sapra, and Steven Thorley, “Return Dispersion and Active Management,”
Financial Analysts Journal, Vol. 57, No. 5, September/October 2001, 29-42; Richard C. Grinold and Mark P.
Taylor, “The Opportunity Set: Market Opportunities and the Effective Breadth of a Portfolio,” Journal of Portfolio
Management, Vol. 35, No. 2, Winter 2009, 12-24; Larry R. Gorman, Steven G. Sapra, and Robert A. Weigand,
“The Role of Cross-Sectional Dispersion in Active Portfolio Management,” Investment Management and
Financial Innovations, Vol. 7, No. 3, October 2010, 58-68; Anna Agapova, Robert Ferguson, and Jason Greene,
“Market Diversity and the Performance of Actively Managed Portfolios,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol.
38, No. 1, Fall 2011, 48-59; and Anna von Reibnitz, “When Opportunity Knocks: Cross-Sectional Return
Dispersion and Active Fund Performance,” Critical Finance Review, Vol. 6, No. 2, September 2017, 303-356.
97 Dry powder, capital committed by limited partners but unallocated by the buyout or venture firm, was $770
billion for buyouts and $300 billion for venture capital per Pitchbook.
98 James Thorne, “Private Markets Are Bigger than You Think—and Gaining Ground on Public Equities,”
PitchBook Quantitative Perspectives, October 2, 2022; Pitchbook, “Q3 2024 Quantitative Perspectives Report”;
and PitchBook-NVCA Venture Monitor, “Q4 2024 Data Pack.”
99 Business Dynamics Statistics, U.S. Census, see www.census.gov/data/tables/2019/econ/susb/2019-susb-
annual.html.
100 Hendrik Bessembinder, “Do Stocks Outperform Treasury Bills?” Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 129,
No. 3, September 2018, 440-457 and Hendrik Bessembinder, Te-Feng Chen, Goeun Choi, and K. C. John Wei,
“Long-Term Shareholder Returns: Evidence from 64,000 Global Stocks,” Financial Analysts Journal, Vol. 79,
No. 3, 2023, 33-63.
101 Henrik Bessembinder, Michael J. Cooper, and Feng Zhang, “Mutual Fund Performance at Long Horizons,”
Approach to the Risk-Adjusted Performance of the Buyout Fund Market,” Financial Analysts Journal, Vol. 72,
No. 4, July/August 2016, 36-48; Gregory W. Brown, Robert S. Harris, Steven N. Kaplan, Tim Jenkinson, and
David Robinson, “Private Equity: Accomplishments and Challenges,” Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, Vol.
32, No. 3, Summer 2020, 8-20; and Steve Kaplan, “Private Equity: Past, Present and Future,” Presentation at
EDHEC Business School, January 2024. For a challenge, see Ludovic Phalippou and Oliver Gottschalg, “The
Performance of Private Equity Funds,” The Review of Financial Studies, Vol. 22, No. 4, April 2009, 1747-1776
and Jeffrey C. Hooke, The Myth of Private Equity: An Inside Look at Wall Street’s Transformative Investments
(New York: Columbia Business School Publishing, 2021), 73-98.
104 Campbell R. Harvey, Sandy Rattray, Andrew Sinclair, and Otto Van Hemert, “Man vs. Machine: Comparing
Discretionary and Systematic: Hedge Fund Performance,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 43, No. 4,
Summer 2017, 55-69.
105 See also “Benefits of a Fund-of-Funds Strategy in Private Equity,” Vanguard Private Equity Perspectives,
May 2024; Kaitlin Hendrix and Mamdouh Medhat, “Understanding Private Fund Performance,” Dimensional
Fund Advisors Research, July 2024; and Victoria Ivashina and Josh Lerner, Patient Capital: The Challenges
and Promises of Long-Term Investing (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2019), 58.
106 For example, bond exchange-traded funds that track the Bloomberg U.S. Aggregate Bond Index have much
higher tracking error and active share, measures of how closely the returns and portfolios reflect the index, than
do ETFs that mirror the S&P 500.
107 Glenn W. Brier, “Verification of Forecasts Expressed in Terms of Probability,” Monthly Weather Review, Vol.
Aboody, David, Shai Levi, and Dan Weiss, “Operating Leverage and Future Earnings,” Working Paper,
December 7, 2014.
Agapova, Anna, Robert Ferguson, and Jason Greene, “Market Diversity and the Performance of Actively
Managed Portfolios,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 38, No. 1, Fall 2011, 48-59.
Allais, Maurice, and Ole Hagen, eds., Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox (Dordrecht, Holland:
Springer Science + Business, 1979), 25-145.
Ball, Philip, Critical Mass: How One Thing Leads to Another (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2004).
Barberis, Nicholas, Ming Huang, and Tano Santos, “Prospect Theory and Asset Prices,” The Quarterly Journal
of Economics, Vol. 116, No. 1, February 2001, 1-53.
Barberis, Nicholas, and Ming Huang, “Stocks as Lotteries: The Implications of Probability Weighting for Security
Prices,” American Economic Review, Vol. 98, No. 5, December 2008, 2066-2100.
Bernoulli, Daniel, “Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk,” Econometrica, Vol. 22, No. 1,
January 1954, 23-36.
Bernstein, Peter L., “Risk, Time, and Reversibility,” The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, Vol. 24, No. 2,
April 1999, 131-139.
Bessembinder, Hendrik, “Do Stocks Outperform Treasury Bills?” Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 129, No.
3, September 2018, 440-457.
_____., “Extreme Stock Market Performers, Part I: Expect Some Drawdowns,” Working Paper, July 2020.
Bessembinder, Hendrik, Michael J. Cooper, and Feng Zhang, “Mutual Fund Performance at Long Horizons,”
Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 147, No. 1, January 2023, 132-158.
Bessembinder, Hendrik, Te-Feng Chen, Goeun Choi, and K. C. John Wei, “Long-Term Shareholder Returns:
Evidence from 64,000 Global Stocks,” Financial Analysts Journal, Vol. 79, No. 3, 2023, 33-63.
Blake, David, Edmund Cannon, and Douglas Wright, “Quantifying Loss Aversion: Evidence from a UK
Population Survey,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 63, No. 1, August 2021, 27–57.
Boutros, Michael, Itzhak Ben-David, John R. Graham, Campbell R. Harvey, and John W. Payne, “The
Persistence of Miscalibration,” NBER Working Paper 28010, Oct. 2020.
Breiman, Leo, “Optimal Gambling Systems for Favorable Games,” Fourth Berkeley Symposium on Probability
and Statistics, 1961, 65-78.
Brier, Glenn W., “Verification of Forecasts Expressed in Terms of Probability,” Monthly Weather Review, Vol.
78, No. 1, January 1950, 1-3.
Brown, Aaron, Red Blooded Risk: The Secret History of Wall Street (Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, 2012).
Brown, Alexander L., Taisuke Imai, Ferdinand M. Vieider, and Colin F. Camerer, “Meta-Analysis of Empirical
Estimates of Loss Aversion,” Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. 62, No. 2, June 2024, 485-516.
Brown, Gregory, Robert S. Harris, Wendy Hu, Tim Jenkinson, Steven N. Kaplan, and David Robinson, “Private
Equity Portfolio Companies: A First Look at Burgiss Holdings Data,” SSRN Working Paper, March 3, 2020.
Brown, Gregory W., Robert S. Harris, Steven N. Kaplan, Tim Jenkinson, and David Robinson, “Private Equity:
Accomplishments and Challenges,” Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, Vol. 32, No. 3, Summer 2020, 8-20.
Buffett, Warren E., “Letter to Shareholders,” Berkshire Hathaway Annual Report, 2001.
Camerer, Colin F., “Do Biases in Probability Judgment Matter in Markets? Experimental Evidence,” American
Economic Review, Vol. 77, No. 5, December 1987, 981-997.
Carta, Andrea, and Claudio Conversano, “Practical Implementation of the Kelly Criterion: Optimal Growth Rate,
Number of Trades, and Rebalancing Frequency for Equity Portfolios,” Frontiers in Applied Mathematics and
Statistics, Vol. 6, October 2020, Article 577050.
Cornell, Bradford, “What Moves Stock Prices: Another Look,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 39, No. 3,
Spring 2013, 32-38.
Covel, Michael, “Trend Following Winners Are Not Lucky Monkeys,” Active Trader Magazine, 16-21.
Crist, Steven, Exotic Betting: How to Make the Multihorse, Multirace Bets That Win Racing’s Biggest Payoffs
(New York: DRF Press, 2006).
Cutler, David M, James M. Poterba, and Lawrence H. Summers, “What Moves Stock Prices?” Journal of Portfolio
Management, Vol. 15, No. 3, Spring 1989, 4-12.
Damodaran, Aswath, “DCF Myth 3.2: If You Don't Look, It's Not There!” Musings on Markets, May 23, 2016.
Dave, Chetan, and Katherine W. Wolfe, “On Confirmation Bias and Deviations From Bayesian Updating,”
Working Paper, March 21, 2003.
de Silva, Harindra, Steven Sapra, and Steven Thorley, “Return Dispersion and Active Management,” Financial
Analysts Journal, Vol. 57, No. 5, September/October 2001, 29-42.
DeMiguel, Victor, Lorenzo Garlappi, and Raman Uppal, “Optimal Versus Naïve Diversification: How Inefficient
is the 1/N Portfolio Strategy?” The Review of Financial Studies, Vol. 22, No. 5, May 2009, 1915-1953.
Dhami, Sanjit, Principles of Behavioral Economics: Microeconomics & Human Behavior (Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, 2025).
Diebold, Francis X., Neil A. Doherty, and Richard J. Herring, eds., The Known, the Unknown, and the
Unknowable in Financial Risk Management: Measurement and Theory Advancing Practice (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2010).
Duke, Annie, Thinking in Bets: Making Smarter Decisions When You Don't Have All the Facts (New York:
Portfolio/Penguin, 2018).
Fabozzi, Frank J., ed., Active Equity Portfolio Management (New Hope, PA: Frank J. Fabozzi Associates, 1998).
Friedman, Jeffrey A., War and Chance: Assessing Uncertainty in International Politics (Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press, 2019).
Friedman, Jeffrey A., Joshua D. Baker, Barbara A. Mellers, Philip E. Tetlock, and Richard Zeckhauser, “The
Value of Precision in Probability Assessment: Evidence from a Large-Scale Geopolitical Forecasting
Tournament,” International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 62, No. 2, March 2018, 410-422.
Friedman, Jeffrey A., and Richard Zeckhauser, “Analytic Confidence and Political Decision-Making: Theoretical
Principles and Experimental Evidence From National Security Professionals,” Political Psychology, Vol. 39, No.
5, October 2018, 1069-1087.
Gächter, Simon, Eric J. Johnson, and Andreas Herrmann, “Individual-level Loss Aversion in Riskless and Risky
Choices,” Theory and Decision, Vol. 92, Nos. 3-4, April 2022, 599-624.
Gompers, Paul A., and Steven N. Kaplan, Advanced Introduction to Private Equity (Cheltenham, UK: Edward
Elgar, 2022).
Gorman, Larry R., Steven G. Sapra, and Robert A. Weigand, “The Role of Cross-Sectional Dispersion in Active
Portfolio Management,” Investment Management and Financial Innovations, Vol. 7, No. 3, October 2010, 58-68.
Graeber, Thomas, Christopher Ross, and Florian Zimmerman, “Stories, Statistics, and Memory,” Quarterly
Journal of Economics, Vol. 139, No. 4, November 2024, 2181-2225.
Graham, Benjamin, The Intelligent Investor: The Definitive Book on Value Investing, Third Edition, Updated with
new commentary by Jason Zweig (New York: Harper Business, 2024).
Graham, Benjamin, and David L. Dodd, Security Analysis (New York: McGraw Hill, 1934).
Grant, James, The Great Metropolis: Second Series, Volume II (Philadelphia, PA: E.L. Carey & A. Hart, 1838),
55-56.
Grinold, Richard C., “The Fundamental Law of Active Management,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 15,
No. 3, Spring 1989, 30-37.
Grinold, Richard C., and Ronald N. Kahn, Active Portfolio Management: A Quantitative Approach for Producing
Superior Returns and Controlling Risk, Second Edition (New York: McGraw Hill, 2000).
Grinold, Richard C., and Mark P. Taylor, “The Opportunity Set: Market Opportunities and the Effective Breadth
of a Portfolio,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 35, No. 2, Winter 2009, 12-24.
Haghani, Victor, and Samantha McBride, “Return Chasing and Trend Following: Superficial Similarities Mask
Fundamental Differences,” SSRN Working Paper, January 29, 2016.
Haghani, Victor, and Richard Dewey, “Rational Decision Making under Uncertainty: Observed Betting Patterns
on a Biased Coin,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 43, No. 3, Spring 2017, 2-8.
Haghani, Victor, and James White, The Missing Billionaires: A Guide to Better Financial Decisions (Hoboken,
NJ: John Wiley & Sons, 2023).
Haigh, Michael S., and John A. List, “Do Professional Traders Exhibit Myopic Loss Aversion? An Experimental
Analysis,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 60, No. 1, February 2005, 523-534.
Harvey, Campbell R., Sandy Rattray, Andrew Sinclair, and Otto Van Hemert, “Man vs. Machine: Comparing
Discretionary and Systematic: Hedge Fund Performance,” Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 43, No. 4,
Summer 2017, 55-69.
Heukelom, Floris, “A History of the Allais Paradox,” The British Journal for the History of Science, Vol. 48, No.
1, March 2015, 147-169.
Higgins, Huong N., “Earnings Forecasts of Firms Experiencing Sales Decline: Why So Inaccurate?” Journal of
Investing, Vol. 17, No. 1, Spring 2008, 26-33.
Hooke, Jeffrey C., The Myth of Private Equity: An Inside Look at Wall Street’s Transformative Investments (New
York: Columbia Business School Publishing, 2021).
Hurst, Brian, Yao Hua Ooi, and Lasse Heje Pedersen, “A Century of Evidence on Trend-Following Investing,”
Journal of Portfolio Management, Vol. 44, No. 1, October 2017, 15-29.
Ilmanen, Antti, “Do Financial Markets Reward Buying or Selling Insurance and Lottery Tickets?” Financial
Analysts Journal, Vol. 68, No. 5, September/October 2012, 26-36.
Ivashina, Victoria and Josh Lerner, Patient Capital: The Challenges and Promises of Long-Term Investing
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2019).
Kahneman, Daniel, Thinking, Fast and Slow (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2011).
Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky “On the Psychology of Prediction,” Psychological Review, Vol. 80, No.
4, July 1973, 237-251.
_____., “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk,” Econometrica, Vol. 47, No. 2, March 1979, 263-
292.
_____., “Intuitive Prediction: Biases and Corrective Procedures,” in Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic, and Amos
Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press, 1982), 414-421.
Kaplan, Steve, “Private Equity: Past, Present and Future,” Presentation at EDHEC Business School, January
2024.
Kaplan, Steven N., and Antoinette Schoar, “Private Equity Performance: Returns, Persistence, and Capital
Flows,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 60, No. 4, August 2005, 1791-1823.
Kelly, J. L., Jr., “A New Interpretation of Information Rate,” Bell System Technical Journal, 1956, 917-926.
Keynes, John Maynard, A Treatise on Probability (London: Macmillian and Co., 1921).
Knight, Frank H., Risk, Uncertainty and Profit (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1921).
Latané, Henry Allen, “Criteria for Choice Among Risky Ventures,” The Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 67, No.
2, April 1959, 144-155.
Lee, Charles M.C., and Eric So, “Alphanomics: The Informational Underpinnings of Market Efficiency,”
Foundations and Trends in Accounting, Vol. 9, No. 2-3, 2014, 59-258.
l'Haridon, Olivier, and Ferdinand M. Vieider, “All Over the Map: A Worldwide Comparison of Risk Preferences,”
Quantitative Economics, Vol. 10, No. 1, January 2019, 185-215.
L’Her, Jean-François, Rossitsa Stoyanova, Kathryn Shaw, William Scott, and Charissa Lai, “A Bottom-Up
Approach to the Risk-Adjusted Performance of the Buyout Fund Market,” Financial Analysts Journal, Vol. 72,
No. 4, July/August 2016, 36-48.
Lichtenstein, Sarah, and Baruch Fischhoff, “Training for Calibration,” Organizational Behavior and Human
Performance, Vol. 26, No. 2, October 1980, 149-171.
List, John A., and Michael S. Haigh, “A Simple Test of Expected Utility Theory Using Professional Traders,”
PNAS, Vol. 102, No. 3, January 18, 2005, 945-948.
Lleo, Sébastien, Leonard C. MacLean, “Dual Dominance: How Harry Markowitz and William Ziemba Impacted
Portfolio Management,” Annals of Operations Research, 2024.
Lo, Andrew W., H. Allen Orr, and Ruixun Zhang, “The Growth of Relative Wealth and the Kelly Criterion,” Journal
of Bioeconomics, Vol. 20, No. 1, April 2018, 49-67.
Lowenstein, Roger, When Genius Failed: The Rise and Fall of Long-Term Capital Management (New York:
Random House, 2000).
Luchtenberg, Kimberly F., and Michael J. Seiler, “Do Institutional and Individual Investors Differ in Their
Preference for Financial Skewness?” Journal of Behavioral Finance, Vol. 15, No. 4, 2014, 299-311.
Mandelbrot Benoit B., Fractals and Scaling in Finance: Discontinuity, Concentration, Risk (New York: Springer,
1997).
Mandelbrot Benoit B., and Nassim Nicholas Taleb, “Mild vs. Wild Randomness: Focusing on Those Risks That
Matter,” in The Known, the Unknown, and the Unknowable in Financial Risk Management: Measurement and
Theory Advancing Practice, Francis X. Diebold, Neil A. Doherty, and Richard J. Herring, eds., (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2010), 47-58.
Markowitz, Harry, “Portfolio Selection,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 7, No. 1, March 1952, 77-91.
_____., Portfolio Selection: Efficient Diversification of Investment (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1959).
_____., “Investment for the Long Run: New Evidence for an Old Rule,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 31, No. 5,
December 1976, 1273-1286.
Mauboussin, Andrew, and Michael J. Mauboussin, “If You Say Something Is ‘Likely,’ How Likely Do People
Think It Is?” Harvard Business Review Blog, July 3, 2018.
Mauboussin, Michael J., More Than You Know: Finding Financial Wisdom in Unconventional Places—Updated
and Expanded (New York: Columbia Business School Publishing, 2008).
Mauboussin, Michael J., and Alfred Rappaport, Expectations Investing: Reading Stock Prices for Better
Returns—Revised and Updated (New York: Columbia Business School Publishing, 2021).
McGrayne, Sharon Bertsch, The Theory That Would Not Die: How Bayes’ Rule Cracked the Enigma Code,
Hunted Down Russian Submarines, and Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 2011).
Mehra, Rajnish, and Edward C. Prescott, “The Equity Premium: A Puzzle,” Journal of Monetary Economics, Vol.
15, No. 2, March 1985, 145-161.
Merkle, Christoph, “Financial Loss Aversion Illusion,” Review of Finance, Vol. 24, No. 2, March 2020, 381-413.
Miller, John H., and Scott E. Page, Complex Adaptive Systems: An Introduction to Computational Models of
Social Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007).
Moore, Don A., Perfectly Confident: How to Calibrate Your Decisions Wisely (New York: Harper Business, 2020).
Moskowitz, Tobias J., and Kaushik Vasudevan, “Betting Without Beta,” Working Paper, May 2, 2022.
Murphy, Allan H., and Harald Daan, “Impacts of Feedback and Experience on the Quality of Subjective
Probability Forecasts: Comparison of Results from the First and Second Years of the Zierikzee Experiment,”
Monthly Weather Review, Vol. 112, No. 3, 1984, 413-423.
Paleologo, Giuseppe A., Advanced Portfolio Management: A Quant’s Guide for Fundamental Investors
(Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, 2021).
Pástor, Ĺuboš, and Robert F. Stambaugh, “Liquidity Risk and Expected Stock Returns,” Journal of Political
Economy, Vol. 111, No. 3, June 2003, 642-685.
Peta, Joe, Moneyball for the Money Set: Using Sports Analytics to Predict the Returns of Portfolio Managers
with Startling Accuracy (2023).
Peters, Ole, “Optimal Leverage from Non-Ergodicity,” Quantitative Finance, Vol. 11, No. 11, November 2011,
1593-1602.
____., “The Ergodicity Problem in Economics,” Nature Physics, Vol. 15, December 2019, 1216-1221.
Phalippou, Ludovic, and Oliver Gottschalg, “The Performance of Private Equity Funds,” The Review of Financial
Studies, Vol. 22, No. 4, April 2009, 1747-1776.
Poundstone, William, Fortune’s Formula: The Untold Story of the Scientific Betting System That Beat the
Casinos and Wall Street (New York: Hill and Wang, 2005).
Ramsey, Frank P., “Truth and Probability,” The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays, Richard
B. Braithwaite, ed. (London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., 1931).
Rebonato, Riccardo, The Plight of the Fortune Tellers: Why We Need to Manage Financial Risk Differently
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007).
Rohleder, Martin, Dominik Schulte, Janik Syryca, and Marco Wilkens, “Mutual Fund Stock‐Picking Skill: New
Evidence from Valuation‐ versus Liquidity‐Motivated Trading,” Financial Management, Vol. 47, No. 2, Summer
2018, 309-347.
Roll, Richard, “R2,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 43, No. 3, July 1988, 541-566.
Rotando, Louis M. and Edward O. Thorp, “The Kelly Criterion and the Stock Market,” The American
Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 99, No. 10, December 1992, 922-931.
Rubinstein, Mark, “No ‘Best’ Strategy for Portfolio Insurance,” Letter to the Editor in Financial Analysts Journal,
Vol. 43, No. 6, November/December 1987, 77-80.
Samuelson, Paul A., “The ‘Fallacy’ of Maximizing the Geometric Mean in Long Sequences of Investing or
Gambling,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Vol. 68, No. 10, October 1971, 2493-2496.
Seneca, translated by Robin Campbell, Letters from a Stoic (London: Penguin House, 1969).
Shiv, Baba, George Loewenstein, Antoine Bechara, Hanna Damasio, and Antonio R. Damasio, “Investment
Behavior and the Negative Side of Emotion,” Psychological Science, Vol. 16, No. 6, June 2005, 435-439.
Spencer, Jane, “Lessons From the Brain-Damaged Investor: Unusual Study Explores Links Between Emotion
and Results; ‘Neuroeconomics’ on Wall Street,” Wall Street Journal, July 21, 2005.
Spiegelhalter, David, The Art of Uncertainty: How to Navigate Chance, Ignorance, Risk and Luck (Dublin:
Penguin Random House, 2024).
_____., “Does Probability Exist? Probably Not—But It Is Useful to Act As If It Does,” Nature, Vol. 636, No. 8043,
December 19/26, 2024, 560-563.
Sunstein, Cass R., “Knightian Uncertainty in the Regulatory Context,” Behavioural Public Policy, forthcoming.
Surowiecki, James, The Wisdom of Crowds: Why the Many Are Smarter Than the Few and How Collective
Wisdom Shapes Business, Economies, Societies, and Nations (New York: Doubleday and Company, 2004).
Taleb, Nassim Nicholas, Fooled By Randomness: The Hidden Role of Chance in the Markets and in Life (New
York, Texere, 2001).
_____., “Bleed or Blowup? Why Do We Prefer Asymmetric Payoffs?” Journal of Behavioral Finance, Vol. 5, No.
1, 2004, 2-7.
_____., The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable, Second Edition (New York: Random House,
2010).
_____., “Do Financial Markets Reward Buying or Selling Insurance and Lottery Tickets?: A Comment,” Financial
Analysts Journal, Vol. 69, No. 2, March/April 2013, 17-19.
Tetlock, Philip E., Expert Political Judgment: How Good Is It? How Can We Know? (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2005).
Tetlock, Philip E., and Dan Gardner, Superforecasting: The Art and Science of Prediction (New York: Crown
Publishers, 2015).
Tetlock, Philip E., Yunzi Lu, and Barbara A. Mellers, “False Dichotomy Alert: Improving Subjective-Probability
Estimates vs. Raising Awareness of Systemic Risk,” International Journal of Forecasting, Vol. 39, No. 2, April-
June 2023, 1021-1025.
Thaler, Richard H., Amos Tversky, Daniel Kahneman, and Alan Schwartz, “The Effect of Myopia and Loss
Aversion on Risk Taking: An Experimental Test,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 112, No. 2, May
1997, 647-661.
Theising, Etienne, “Distributional Reference Class Forecasting of Corporate Sales Growth With Multiple
Reference Variables,” ArXiv, May 6, 2024.
Theising, Etienne, Dominik Wied, and Daniel Ziggel, “Reference Class Selection in Similarity-Based Forecasting
of Corporate Sales Growth,” Journal of Forecasting, Vol. 42, No. 5, August 2023, 1069-1085.
Thorp, Edward O., Beat the Dealer: A Winning Strategy for the Game of Twenty-One (New York: Blaisdell
Publishing Company, 1962).
_____., “Optimal Gambling Systems for Favorable Games,” Review of the International Statistical Institute, Vol.
37, No. 3, 1969, 273-293.
Thorne, James, “Private Markets are Bigger than You Think—and Gaining Ground on Public Equities,”
PitchBook Quantitative Perspectives, October 2, 2022.
Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman, “Evidential Impact of Base Rates,” in Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic,
and Amos Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press, 1982), 153-160.
_____., “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty,” Journal of Risk and
Uncertainty, Vol. 5, No. 4, October 1992, 297-323.
van Loon, Ronald J.M., “Timing versus Sizing Skill in the Investment Process,” Journal of Portfolio Management,
Vol. 44, No. 3, Winter 2018, 25-32.
Vince, Ralph, The New Money Management: A Framework for Asset Allocation (New York: John Wiley & Sons,
1995).
von Reibnitz, Anna, “When Opportunity Knocks: Cross-Sectional Return Dispersion and Active Fund
Performance,” Critical Finance Review, Vol. 6, No. 2, September 2017, 303-356.
Zeckhauser, Richard, “Investing in the Unknown and Unknowable,” Capitalism and Society, Vol. 1, No. 2, 2006,
Article 5.
Ziemba, Rachel E.S., and William T. Ziemba, Scenarios for Risk Management and Global Investment Strategies
(Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons, 2007).
Ziemba, William T., Great Investment Ideas (Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific, 2017).
The views and opinions and/or analysis expressed are those of the author as of the date of preparation of this
material and are subject to change at any time due to market or economic conditions and may not necessarily
come to pass. Furthermore, the views will not be updated or otherwise revised to reflect information that
subsequently becomes available or circumstances existing, or changes occurring, after the date of publication.
The views expressed do not reflect the opinions of all investment personnel at Morgan Stanley Investment
Management (MSIM) and its subsidiaries and affiliates (collectively “the Firm”), and may not be reflected in all
the strategies and products that the Firm offers.
Forecasts and/or estimates provided herein are subject to change and may not actually come to pass.
Information regarding expected market returns and market outlooks is based on the research, analysis and
opinions of the authors or the investment team. These conclusions are speculative in nature, may not come to
pass and are not intended to predict the future performance of any specific strategy or product the Firm offers.
Future results may differ significantly depending on factors such as changes in securities or financial markets or
general economic conditions.
Past performance is no guarantee of future results. This material has been prepared on the basis of publicly
available information, internally developed data and other third-party sources believed to be reliable. However,
no assurances are provided regarding the reliability of such information and the Firm has not sought to
independently verify information taken from public and third-party sources. The views expressed in the books
and articles referenced in this whitepaper are not necessarily endorsed by the Firm.
This material is a general communications which is not impartial and has been prepared solely for
information and educational purposes and does not constitute an offer or a recommendation to buy or
sell any particular security or to adopt any specific investment strategy or product. The material contained
herein has not been based on a consideration of any individual client circumstances and is not investment
advice, nor should it be construed in any way as tax, accounting, legal or regulatory advice. To that end, investors
should seek independent legal and financial advice, including advice as to tax consequences, before making
any investment decision.
Charts and graphs provided herein are for illustrative purposes only. Any securities referenced herein are solely
for illustrative purposes only and should not be construed as a recommendation for investment.
The S&P 500® Index measures the performance of the large cap segment of the U.S. equities market, covering
approximately 80% of the U.S. equities market. The Index includes 500 leading companies in leading industries
of the U.S. economy. The Russell 1000® Index measures the performance of the 1,000 largest companies in
the Russell 3000® Index. The Russell 3000 Index measures the performance of the largest 3,000 U.S.
companies representing approximately 98% of the investable U.S. equity market. The Russell 3000 Index is
constructed to provide a comprehensive, unbiased, and stable barometer of the broad market and is completely
reconstituted annually to ensure new and growing equities are reflected. The indexes are unmanaged and do
not include any expenses, fees or sales charges. It is not possible to invest directly in an index. The indexes
referred to herein are the intellectual property (including registered trademarks) of the applicable licensors. Any
product based on an index is in no way sponsored, endorsed, sold or promoted by the applicable licensor and
it shall not have any liability with respect thereto.
This material is not a product of Morgan Stanley’s Research Department and should not be regarded as a
research material or a recommendation.
The Firm has not authorised financial intermediaries to use and to distribute this material, unless such use and
distribution is made in accordance with applicable law and regulation. Additionally, financial intermediaries are
required to satisfy themselves that the information in this material is appropriate for any person to whom they
provide this material in view of that person’s circumstances and purpose. The Firm shall not be liable for, and
accepts no liability for, the use or misuse of this material by any such financial intermediary.
The whole or any part of this work may not be directly or indirectly reproduced, copied, modified, used to create
a derivative work, performed, displayed, published, posted, licensed, framed, distributed or transmitted or any
of its contents disclosed to third parties without MSIM’s express written consent. This work may not be linked to
DISTRIBUTION
This communication is only intended for and will only be distributed to persons resident in jurisdictions
where such distribution or availability would not be contrary to local laws or regulations.
MSIM, the asset management division of Morgan Stanley (NYSE: MS), and its affiliates have
arrangements in place to market each other’s products and services. Each MSIM affiliate is regulated
as appropriate in the jurisdiction it operates. MSIM’s affiliates are: Eaton Vance Management
(International) Limited, Eaton Vance Advisers International Ltd, Calvert Research and Management,
Eaton Vance Management, Parametric Portfolio Associates LLC, and Atlanta Capital Management LLC.
This material has been issued by any one or more of the following entities:
EMEA
This material is for Professional Clients/Accredited Investors only.
In the EU, MSIM and Eaton Vance materials are issued by MSIM Fund Management (Ireland) Limited (“FMIL”).
FMIL is regulated by the Central Bank of Ireland and is incorporated in Ireland as a private company limited by
shares with company registration number 616661 and has its registered address at 24-26 City Quay, Dublin 2,
DO2 NY19, Ireland.
Outside the EU, MSIM materials are issued by Morgan Stanley Investment Management Limited (MSIM Ltd) is
authorised and regulated by the Financial Conduct Authority. Registered in England. Registered No. 1981121.
Registered Office: 25 Cabot Square, Canary Wharf, London E14 4QA.
In Switzerland, MSIM materials are issued by Morgan Stanley & Co. International plc, London (Zurich Branch)
Authorised and regulated by the Eidgenössische Finanzmarktaufsicht ("FINMA"). Registered Office:
Beethovenstrasse 33, 8002 Zurich, Switzerland.
Outside the US and EU, Eaton Vance materials are issued by Eaton Vance Management (International) Limited
(“EVMI”) 125 Old Broad Street, London, EC2N 1AR, UK, which is authorised and regulated in the United
Kingdom by the Financial Conduct Authority.
Italy: MSIM FMIL (Milan Branch), (Sede Secondaria di Milano) Palazzo Serbelloni Corso Venezia, 16 20121
Milano, Italy. The Netherlands: MSIM FMIL (Amsterdam Branch), Rembrandt Tower, 11th Floor Amstelplein 1
1096HA, Netherlands. France: MSIM FMIL (Paris Branch), 61 rue de Monceau 75008 Paris, France. Spain:
MSIM FMIL (Madrid Branch), Calle Serrano 55, 28006, Madrid, Spain. Germany: MSIM FMIL Frankfurt Branch,
Große Gallusstraße 18, 60312 Frankfurt am Main, Germany (Gattung: Zweigniederlassung (FDI) gem. § 53b
KWG). Denmark: MSIM FMIL (Copenhagen Branch), Gorrissen Federspiel, Axel Towers, Axeltorv2, 1609
Copenhagen V, Denmark.
MIDDLE EAST
Dubai: MSIM Ltd (Representative Office, Unit Precinct 3-7th Floor-Unit 701 and 702, Level 7, Gate Precinct
Building 3, Dubai International Financial Centre, Dubai, 506501, United Arab Emirates. Telephone: +97 (0)14
709 7158).
This document is distributed in the Dubai International Financial Centre by Morgan Stanley Investment
Management Limited (Representative Office), an entity regulated by the Dubai Financial Services Authority
(“DFSA”). It is intended for use by professional clients and market counterparties only. This document is not
intended for distribution to retail clients, and retail clients should not act upon the information contained in this
document.
ASIA PACIFIC
Hong Kong: This material is disseminated by Morgan Stanley Asia Limited for use in Hong Kong and shall only
be made available to “professional investors” as defined under the Securities and Futures Ordinance of Hong
Kong (Cap 571). The contents of this material have not been reviewed nor approved by any regulatory authority
including the Securities and Futures Commission in Hong Kong. Accordingly, save where an exemption is
available under the relevant law, this material shall not be issued, circulated, distributed, directed at, or made
available to, the public in Hong Kong. Singapore: This material is disseminated by Morgan Stanley Investment
Management Company and should not be considered to be the subject of an invitation for subscription or
purchase, whether directly or indirectly, to the public or any member of the public in Singapore other than (i) to
an institutional investor under section 304 of the Securities and Futures Act, Chapter 289 of Singapore (“SFA”);
(ii) to a “relevant person” (which includes an accredited investor) pursuant to section 305 of the SFA, and such
distribution is in accordance with the conditions specified in section 305 of the SFA; or (iii) otherwise pursuant
to, and in accordance with the conditions of, any other applicable provision of the SFA. This publication has not
been reviewed by the Monetary Authority of Singapore. Australia: This material is provided by Morgan Stanley
Investment Management (Australia) Pty Ltd ABN 22122040037, AFSL No. 314182 and its affiliates and does
not constitute an offer of interests. Morgan Stanley Investment Management (Australia) Pty Limited arranges for
MSIM affiliates to provide financial services to Australian wholesale clients. Interests will only be offered in
circumstances under which no disclosure is required under the Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) (the “Corporations
Act”). Any offer of interests will not purport to be an offer of interests in circumstances under which disclosure is
required under the Corporations Act and will only be made to persons who qualify as a “wholesale client” (as
defined in the Corporations Act). This material will not be lodged with the Australian Securities and Investments
Commission.
Japan
This material may not be circulated or distributed, whether directly or indirectly, to persons in Japan other than
to (i) a professional investor as defined in Article 2 of the Financial Instruments and Exchange Act (“FIEA”) or
(ii) otherwise pursuant to, and in accordance with the conditions of, any other allocable provision of the FIEA.
This material is disseminated in Japan by Morgan Stanley Investment Management (Japan) Co., Ltd.,
Registered No. 410 (Director of Kanto Local Finance Bureau (Financial Instruments Firms)), Membership: the
Japan Securities Dealers Association, The Investment Trusts Association, Japan, the Japan Investment
Advisers Association and the Type II Financial Instruments Firms Association.