Shan Gao - PHD Thesis
Shan Gao - PHD Thesis
Shan Gao
THESIS
submitted for the degree of
Doctor of Philosophy
Unit for History and Philosophy of Science Centre for Time, SOPHI
Faculty of Science Department of Philosophy
University of Sydney
Sydney, Australia
March 2012
c Shan Gao 2011
All rights reserved
This thesis is copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to provisions of relevant collective
licensing agreements, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval
system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, without the prior written permission
of the author.
This thesis is dedicated to Erwin Schrödinger, who introduced the wave function,
discovered its equation named after him, and argued that quantum mechanics is in-
complete by his famous cat paradox.
Abstract
4
Acknowledgement
The idea of random discontinuous motion of particles came to my mind when I was a post-
graduate at the Institute of Electronics, Chinese Academy of Sciences in 1993. I am happy
that finally it has a more logical and satisfying formulation in this PhD thesis. During the
writing of the thesis, I have been supported financially by a University of Sydney Interna-
tional Scholarship and a Postgraduate Scholarship in Quantum Foundations provided by the
Unit for HPS and Centre for Time (SOPHI), as well as by two Lucy Firth Scholarships in
Philosophy provided by the Department of Philosophy.
I would like to express my deepest gratitude to my supervisors, Dean Rickles and Huw
Price, whose understanding, motivation and personal guidance was indispensable during my
PhD studies. I am deeply indebted to them for their continuous encouragement, stimulating
suggestions and healthy criticism which helped me greatly during my research and writing
of this thesis. Their professional approach and accuracy was particularly beneficial to my
study.
I wish to express my warm and sincere thanks to the head of the Unit for HPS, Ofer
Gal, the postgraduate coordinator, Hans Pols, and Debbie Castle. I am grateful for their
personal support and for their reassurance regarding technical conditions during my PhD
work. I would like to take this opportunity to thank all the other members of the Unit for
their help and encouragement throughout the years.
I would like to gratefully thank David Miller, Rod Sutherland, Hans Westman and Owen
Maroney for helpful discussions and useful suggestions. I owe a debt of gratitude to all the
PhD students here who I shared good times and had fun with.
My deepest gratitude goes to my parents, Qingfeng Gao and Lihua Zhao, who spared
no effort to provide the best possible environment for me to grow up in and their constant
support during my extended studies. They have always allowed me to have the freedom of
choice, and for that I am truly grateful. I am also thankful to my brother, Yuan Gao, and to
all my friends, as they have always been willing to share their thoughts with me and provide
alternative viewpoints which have helped me think in a more holistic fashion.
Finally, I am deeply indebted to my wife Huixia and my daughter Ruiqi for their un-
flagging love and support throughout my study; this dissertation would have been simply
impossible without them. Moreover, they have never let me forget the true values of life.
5
Publications
2. The wave function and quantum reality, in Proceedings of the International Conference on
Advances in Quantum Theory, A. Khrennikov, G. Jaeger, M. Schlosshauer, G. Weihs (eds),
AIP Conference Proceedings 1327, 334-338 (2011).
3. Meaning of the wave function, International Journal of Quantum Chemistry, 111, 4124-
4138 (2011).
4. Is gravity an entropic force? Entropy special issue “Black Hole Thermodynamics”, Jacob
D. Bekenstein (eds), 13, 936-948 (2011).
6
Contents
1 Introduction 10
7
CONTENTS
8
I think I can safely say that nobody understands quantum mechanics... Do not keep
saying to yourself, if you can possible avoid it, “But how can it be like that?” because
you will get ‘down the drain’, into a blind alley from which nobody has escaped. Nobody
knows how it can be like that. — Richard Feynman, 1964
1
Introduction
10
know what physical state the wave function of a quantum system describes, we need to mea-
sure the system in the first place, while the measuring process and the measurement result are
necessarily determined by the evolution law for the wave function. Fortunately, it has been
realized that the conventional measurement that leads to the apparent collapse of the wave
function is only one kind of quantum measurement, and there also exists another kind of mea-
surement that avoids the collapse of the wave function, namely the protective measurement
(Aharonov and Vaidman 1993; Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman 1993; Aharonov, Anandan
and Vaidman 1996). Protective measurement is a method to measure the expectation values
of observables on a single quantum system without disturbing its state appreciably, and its
mechanism is independent of the controversial process of wavefunction collapse and only
depends on the linear Schrödinger evolution and the Born rule, which are two established
parts of quantum mechanics. As a result, protective measurement can not only measure the
physical state of a quantum system and help to unveil the meaning of the wave function, but
also be used to examine the solutions to the measurement problem before experiments give
the last verdict. A full exposition of these ideas will be given in the subsequent chapters.
The plan of this thesis is as follows. In Chapter 2, we first investigate the physical
meaning of the wave function. According to protective measurement, the mass and charge
distributions of a quantum system as one part of its physical state can be measured as
expectation values of certain observables. It turns out that the mass and charge of a quantum
system are distributed throughout space, and the mass and charge density in each position
is proportional to the modulus square of the wave function of the system there. The key
to unveil the meaning of the wave function is to find the origin of the mass and charge
distributions. It is shown that the density is not real but effective; it is formed by the time
average of the ergodic motion of a localized particle with the total mass and charge of the
system. Moreover, it is argued that the ergodic motion is not continuous but discontinuous
and random. Based on this result, we suggest that the wave function represents the state
of random discontinuous motion of particles, and in particular, the modulus square of the
wave function (in position space) gives the probability density of the particles appearing in
certain positions in space.
In Chapter 3, we further analyze the linear evolution law for the wave function. It is shown
that the linear non-relativistic evolution of the wave function of an isolated system obeys the
free Schrödinger equation due to the requirements of spacetime translation invariance and
relativistic invariance. Though these requirements are already well known, an explicit and
complete derivation of the free Schrödinger equation using them seems still missing in the
literature. The new integrated analysis, which is consistent with the suggested interpretation
of the wave function, may be helpful for understanding the physical origin of the Schrödinger
equation. In addition, we also analyze the physical basis and meaning of the principle of
conservation of energy and momentum in quantum mechanics.
In Chapter 4, we investigate the implications of protective measurement and the sug-
gested interpretation of the wave function based on it for the solutions to the measurement
problem. To begin with, we argue that the two no-collapse quantum theories, namely the
de Broglie-Bohm theory and the many-worlds interpretation, are inconsistent with protec-
tive measurement and the picture of random discontinuous motion of particles. This result
strongly suggests that wavefunction collapse is a real physical process. Secondly, we ar-
gue that the random discontinuous motion of particles may provide an appropriate random
source to collapse the wave function. The key point is to realize that the instantaneous
state of a particle not only includes its wave function but also includes its random position,
momentum and energy that undergo the discontinuous motion, and these random variables
can have a stochastic influence on the evolution of the wave function and further lead to
the collapse of the wave function. Thirdly, we propose a discrete model of energy-conserved
11
wavefunction collapse. It is shown that the model is consistent with existing experiments
and our macroscopic experience. Lastly, we also give some critical comments on other dy-
namical collapse models, including Penrose’s gravity-induced collapse model and the CSL
(Continuous Spontaneous Localization) model.
In the last chapter, we briefly analyze the problem of the incompatibility between quan-
tum mechanics and special relativity in terms of random discontinuous motion of particles.
It is argued that a consistent description of random discontinuous motion of particles re-
quires absolute simultaneity, and this leads to the existence of a preferred Lorentz frame
when combined with the requirement of the constancy of speed of light. Moreover, it is
shown that the collapse dynamics may provide a method to detect the frame according to
the energy-conserved collapse model.
12
2
What does the ψ-function mean now, that is, what does the
system described by it really look like in three dimensions?
— Erwin Schrödinger, 1927
The physical meaning of the wave function is an important interpretative problem of quantum
mechanics. Notwithstanding more than eighty years’ developments of the theory, however, it
is still a debated issue. Besides the standard probability interpretation in textbooks, there are
also various conflicting views on the wave function in the alternatives to quantum mechanics.
In this chapter, we will try to solve this fundamental interpretive problem through a new
analysis of protective measurement and the mass and charge density of a quantum system.
The meaning of the wave function is often analyzed in the context of conventional impulse
measurements, for which the coupling interaction between the measured system and the
measuring device is of short duration and strong. As a result, even though the wave function
of a quantum system is in general extended over space, an impulse position measurement will
inevitably collapse the wave function and can only detect the system in a random position
in space. Then it is unsurprising that the wave function is assumed to be related to the
probability of these random measurement results by the standard probability interpretation.
However, it has been known that there exists another kind of measurement that can avoid the
collapse of the wave function, namely the protective measurement (Aharonov and Vaidman
1993; Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman 1993; Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman 1996).
Protective measurement also uses a standard measuring procedure, but with a weak and
long duration coupling interaction and an appropriate procedure to protect the measured
wave function from collapsing. Its general method is to let the measured system be in a
nondegenerate eigenstate of the whole Hamiltonian using a suitable protective interaction
(in some situations the protection is provided by the measured system itself), and then make
the measurement adiabatically so that the state of the system neither changes nor becomes
entangled with the measuring device appreciably. In this way, such protective measurements
can measure the expectation values of observables on a single quantum system, and in
particular, the mass and charge density of a quantum system as one part of its physical state,
as well as its wave function, can be measured as expectation values of certain observables.
According to protective measurement, the mass and charge of a quantum system are
distributed throughout space, and the mass and charge density in each position is propor-
tional to the modulus square of the wave function of the system there. The key to unveil
the meaning of the wave function is to find the physical origin of the mass and charge
distributions. Historically, the charge density interpretation for electrons was originally sug-
gested by Schrödinger when he introduced the wave function and founded wave mechanics
(Schrödinger 1926). Although the existence of the charge density of an electron can provide a
classical explanation for some phenomena of radiation, its explanatory power is very limited.
In fact, Schrödinger clearly realized that the charge density cannot be classical because his
equation does not include the usual classical interaction between the densities. Presumably
since people thought that the charge density could not be measured and also lacked a consis-
tent physical picture, this initial interpretation of the wave function was soon rejected and
replaced by Born’s probability interpretation (Born 1926). Now protective measurement re-
13
2.1. STANDARD QUANTUM MECHANICS AND IMPULSE MEASUREMENTS
endows the charge distribution of an electron with reality by a more convincing argument.
The question is then how to find a consistent physical explanation for it1 . Our following
analysis can be regarded as a further development of Schrödinger’s idea to some extent.
The twist is: that the charge distribution is not classical does not imply its non-existence;
rather, its existence points to a non-classical picture of quantum reality hiding behind the
mathematical wave function.
The charge distribution of a charged quantum system such as an electron has two possible
existent forms: it is either real or effective. The charge distribution is real means that it exists
throughout space at the same time, and the charge distribution is effective means that there
is only a localized particle with the total charge of the system at every instant, and its motion
forms the effective charge distribution. If the charge distribution is effective, then there will
exist no electrostatic self-interaction of the effective charge distribution, as there is only a
localized charged particle at every instant. By contrast, if the charge distribution is real,
then there will exist electrostatic self-interaction of the real charge distribution, as the charge
distribution exists throughout space at the same time. Since the superposition principle of
quantum mechanics prohibits the existence of electrostatic self-interaction, and especially,
the existence of the electrostatic self-interaction for the charge distribution of an electron
already contradicts experimental observations, the charge distribution of a quantum system
cannot be real but must be effective. This means that for a quantum system, at every instant
there is only a localized particle with the total mass and charge of the system, and during an
infinitesimal time interval at a given instant the time average of the ergodic motion of the
particle forms the effective mass and charge density in each position, which is proportional
to the modulus square of the wave function of the system there.
The next question is which sort of ergodic motion the particle undergoes. It can be argued
that the classical ergodic models, which assume continuous motion of particles, are incon-
sistent with quantum mechanics, and the effective mass and charge density of a quantum
system is formed by discontinuous motion of a localized particle. Moreover, the discontin-
uous motion is not deterministic but random. Based on this result, we suggest that the
wave function in quantum mechanics describes the state of random discontinuous motion of
particles, and at a deeper level, it represents the property of the particles that determines
their random discontinuous motion. In particular, the modulus square of the wave function
(in position space) determines the probability density of the particles appearing in every po-
sition in space. In the following, we will give a full exposition of this suggested interpretation
of the wave function.
14
2.1. STANDARD QUANTUM MECHANICS AND IMPULSE MEASUREMENTS
2. Physical properties
Every measurable property or observable of a physical system is represented by a Her-
mitian operator on the Hilbert space associated with the system. A physical system has a
determinate value for an observable if and only if it is in an eigenstate of the observable (this
is often called the eigenvalue-eigenstate link).
3. Composition rule
The Hilbert space associated with a composite system is the tensor product of the Hilbert
spaces associated with the systems of which it is composed. Similarly, the Hilbert space
associated with independent properties is the tensor product of the Hilbert spaces associated
with each property.
4. Evolution law
(1). Linear evolution
The state of a physical system |ψ(t)i obeys the linear Schrödinger equation i~ ∂|ψ(t)i ∂t =
H |ψ(t)i (when it is not measured), where ~ is Planck’s constant divided by 2π, H is the
Hamiltonian operator that depends on the energy properties of the system.
(2). Nonlinear collapse evolution P
If a physical system is in a state |ψi = i ci |ai i, where |ai i is the eigenstate of an
observable A with eigenvalue ai , then an (impulse) measurement of the observable A will
instantaneously, discontinuously, and randomly collapse the state into one of the eigenstates
|ai i with probability |ci |2 . This is usually called the collapse postulate, and the nonlinear
stochastic process is called the reduction of the state vector or the collapse of the wave
function.
The link between the mathematical formalism and experiments is provided by the Born
rule. It says that the probability of the above measurement of the observable A yielding the
result ai is |ci |2 .3 Note that the Born rule can be derived from the collapse postulate by
resorting to the eigenvalue-eigenstate link, but it does not necessarily depend on the postu-
late. Different from the controversial collapse postulate, the Born rule has been confirmed
by precise experiments and is an established part of quantum mechanics.
The conventional impulse measurements can be further formulated as follows. According
to the standard von Neumann procedure, measuring an observable A in a quantum state |ψi
involves an interaction Hamiltonian
HI = g(t)P A (2.1)
coupling the measured system to an appropriate measuring device, where P is the conjugate
momentum of the pointer R variable. The time-dependent coupling strength g(t) is a smooth
function normalized to dtg(t) = 1 during the interaction interval τ , and g(0) = g(τ ) = 0.
The initial state of the pointer is supposed to be a Gaussian wave packet of width w0 centered
at initial position 0, denoted by |φ(0)i.
For an impulse measurement, the interaction HI is of very short duration and so strong
that it dominates the rest of the Hamiltonian (i.e. the effect of the free Hamiltonians of
the measuring device and the measured system can be neglected). Then the state of the
combined system at the end of the interaction can be written as
i
|t = τ i = e− ~ P A |ψi |φ(0)i . (2.2)
By expanding |ψi in the eigenstates of A, |ai i, we obtain
3
For a continuous property such as position, P (x) = |hx|ψi|2 is the probability density at x, and P (x)dx
is the probability of obtaining a measurement result between x and x + dx.
15
2.2. WEAK MEASUREMENTS
X i
|t = τ i = e− ~ P ai ci |ai i |φ(0)i , (2.3)
i
where ci are the expansion coefficients. The exponential term shifts the center of the pointer
by ai :
X
|t = τ i = ci |ai i |φ(ai )i . (2.4)
i
This is an entangled state, where the eigenstates of A with eigenvalues ai get correlated to
measuring device states in which the pointer is shifted by these values ai (but the width
of the pointer wavepacket is not changed). Then by the collapse postulate, the state will
instantaneously and randomly collapse into one of its branches |ai i |φ(ai )i with probability
|ci |2 . This means that the measurement result can only be one of the eigenvalues of measured
observable A, say ai , with a certain probability |ci |2 . The expectation value of A is then
obtained P as the statistical average of eigenvalues for an ensemble of identical systems, namely
2
hAi = i |ci | ai .
Expanding Pthe initial state of the system |ψi in the eigenstates |ai i of the measured observable
A, |ψi = i ci |ai i, then after the interaction (2.1) the state of the system and the measuring
device is:
2 2
X
|t = τ i = (w02 π)−1/4 ci |ai ie−(x−ai ) /2w0 . (2.7)
i
The probability distribution of the pointer variable corresponding to the final state (2.7) is:
2 /w 2
X
Pf (x) = (w02 π)−1/2 |ci |2 e−(x−ai ) 0 . (2.8)
i
In case of a conventional impulse measurement, this is a weighted sum of the initial
probability distribution localized around various eigenvalues ai . Therefore, the reading of
16
2.3. PROTECTIVE MEASUREMENTS
the pointer variable in the end of the measurement always yields the value close to one of
the eigenvalues. By contrast, the limit of weak measurement corresponds to w0 ai for all
eigenvalues ai . Then we can perform the Taylor expansion of the sum (2.8) around x = 0
up to the first order and rewrite the final probability distribution of the pointer variable in
the following way:
|ci |2 ai )2 /w02
X P
Pf (x) ≈ (w02 π)−1/2 |ci |2 (1 − (x − ai )2 /w02 ) ≈ (w02 π)−1/2 e−(x− i (2.9)
i
This is the initial probability distribution shifted by the value i |ci |2 ai . It indicates that
P
the result of the weak measurement is the expectation value of the measured observable in
the measured state:
X
hAi ≡ hψ|A|ψi = |ci |2 ai . (2.10)
i
Certainly, since the width of the pointer wavepacket is much greater than the shift of
the center of the pointer, namely w0 hAi, the above weak measurement of a single system
is very imprecise4 . However, by performing the weak measurement√ on an ensemble of N
identical systems the precision can be improved by a factor N . This scheme of weak
measurement has been realized and proved useful in quantum optical experiments (see, e.g.
Hosten and Kwiat 2008).
Although weak measurements, like conventional impulse measurements, also need to
measure an ensemble of identical quantum systems, they are conceptually different. For
conventional impulse measurements, every identical system in the ensemble shifts the pointer
of the measuring device by one of the eigenvalues of the measured observable, and the
expectation value of the observable is then regarded as the property of the whole ensemble.
By contrast, for weak measurements, every identical system in the ensemble shifts the pointer
of the measuring device directly by the expectation value of the measured observable, and
thus the expectation value may be regarded as the property of individual systems.
17
2.3. PROTECTIVE MEASUREMENTS
HI = g(t)P A, (2.11)
where P is the momentum conjugate to the pointer variable X of an appropriate measuring
device. Let the initial state of the pointer at t = 0 be |φ(x0 )i, which is a Gaussian wave
packet of eigenstates of X with width w0 , centered around the eigenvalue R x0 . The time-
dependent coupling strength g(t) is also a smooth function normalized to dtg(t) = 1. But
different from conventional impulse measurements, for which the interaction is very strong
and almost instantaneous, protective measurements make use of the opposite limit where
the interaction of the measuring device with the system is weak and adiabatic, and thus the
free Hamiltonians cannot be neglected. Let the Hamiltonian of the combined system be
18
2.3. PROTECTIVE MEASUREMENTS
E
PA
where H = HS + HD + T . We further expand |φ(x0 )i in the eigenstate of HD , Ejd , and
write
i X E
|t = T i = e− ~ HT cj |En i Ejd , (2.15)
j
Let the exact eigenstates of H be |Ψk,m i and the corresponding eigenvalues be E(k, m), we
have
X X i
|t = T i = cj e− ~ E(k,m)T hΨk,m |En , Ejd i|Ψk,m i. (2.16)
j k,m
Since the interaction is very weak, the Hamiltonian H of Eq.(2.12) can be thought of as
H0 = HS + HD perturbed by PTA . Using the fact that PTA is a small perturbation and that
d , the perturbation theory gives
the eigenstates of H0 are of the form |Ek i Em
E
d
|Ψk,m i = |Ek i Em + O(1/T ),
d 1
E(k, m) = Ek + Em + hAik hP im + O(1/T 2 ). (2.17)
T
Note that it is a necessary condition for Eq.(2.17) to hold that |Ek i is a nondegenerate
eigenstate of HS . Substituting Eq.(2.17) in Eq.(2.16) and taking the large T limit yields
X − i (E T +E d T +hAi hP i ) E
|t = T i ≈ e ~ n j n j
cj |En i Ejd . (2.18)
j
For the special case when PE commutes with the free Hamiltonian of the device, i.e.,
[P, HD ] = 0, the eigenstates Ejd of HD are also the eigenstates of P , and thus the above
equation can be rewritten as
i i i
|t = T i ≈ e− ~ En T − ~ HD T − ~ hAin P |En i |φ(x0 )i . (2.19)
It can be seen that the third term in the exponent will shift the center of the pointer |φ(x0 )i
by an amount hAin :
i i
|t = T i ≈ e− ~ En T − ~ HD T |En i |φ(x0 + hAin )i. (2.20)
This shows that at the end of the interaction, the center of the pointer shifts by the expec-
tation value of the measured observable in the measured state. E
For the general case when [P, HD ] 6= 0, we can introduce an operator Y = j hP ij Ejd hEjd |
P
i i i i i
|t = T i ≈ e− ~ En T − ~ HD T − ~ hAin Y |En i φ(x00 ) = e− ~ En T − ~ HD T |En i |φ(x00 + hAin )i. (2.22)
7
Note that it may not always be possible to physically realize the operator Y , and an operator canonically
conjugate to Y need not always exist either. For further discussions see Dass and Qureshi (1999).
19
2.3. PROTECTIVE MEASUREMENTS
Thus the center of the pointer also shifts by hAin at the end of the interaction. This
demonstrates the generic possibility of the protective measurement of hAin .
It is worth noting that since the position variable of the pointer does not commute with
its free Hamiltonian, the pointer wave packet will spread during the long measuring time.
For example, the kinematic energy term P 2 /2M in the free Hamiltonian of the pointer will
spread the wave packet without shifting the center, and the width of the wave packet at
2 1
the end of interaction will be w(T ) = [ 21 (w02 + MT2 w2 )] 2 (Dass and Qureshi 1999). However,
0
the spreading of the pointer wave packet can be made as small as possible by increasing the
mass M of the pointer, and thus it will not interfere with resolving the shift of the center of
the pointer in principle8 .
20
2.3. PROTECTIVE MEASUREMENTS
impossible when the system is in an entangled state because neither particle is then in a
unique state that can be protected. If a protective measurement is made only on one of the
particles, then this would also collapse the entangled state into one of the eigenstates of the
protecting Hamiltonian. The right method is by adding appropriate protection procedure
to the whole system so that the entangled state is a nondegenerate eigenstate of the total
Hamiltonian of the system together with the added potential. Then the entangled state can
be protectively measured. Note that the additional protection usually contains a nonlocal
interaction for separated particles. However, this measurement may be performed without
violating causality by having the entangled particles sufficiently close to each other so that
they have this protective interaction. Then when the particles are separated they would still
be in the same entangled state which has been protectively measured.
21
2.4. ON THE MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY OF A QUANTUM SYSTEM
can only be the statistical properties of the ensemble. Next, if each system in the ensemble is
indeed identical as the standard view holds (this means that the quantum state is a complete
description of a single system), then obviously the expectation values of observables will be
also the properties of each individual system in the ensemble. Thirdly, even if the quantum
state is not a complete description of a single system and additional variables are needed as
in the de Broglie-Bohm theory (de Broglie 1928; Bohm 1952), the quantum state of each
system in an ensemble of identical systems is still the same, and thus the expectation values
of observables, which are calculated in terms of the quantum state, are also the same for
every system in the ensemble. As a result, the expectation values of observables can still be
regarded as the properties of individual systems.
Lastly, we stress that the expectation values of observables are instantaneous properties
of a quantum system (Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman 1996). Although the measured
state may be unchanged during a protective measurement and the duration of measurement
may be very long, for an arbitrarily short period of time the measuring device always shifts
by an amount proportional to the expectation value of the measured observable in the
state. Therefore, the expectation values of observables are not time-averaged properties
of a quantum system during a finite period of time, but instantaneous properties of the
system during an infinitesimal period of time or at a precise instant11 .
∂ψ(x, t) ~2 iQ 2
i~ = [− (∇ − A) + Qϕ]ψ(x, t), (2.23)
∂t 2m ~
where m and Q are the mass and charge of the system, respectively, ϕ and A are the electro-
magnetic potential. The electrostatic interaction term Qϕψ(x, t) in the equation indicates
11
Our later analysis of the mass and charge density of a quantum system will further show that the
expectation values of observables are the instantaneous properties of a quantum system during an infinitesimal
time interval, like the standard velocities in classical mechanics.
12
Quoted in Moore (1994), p.148.
22
2.4. ON THE MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY OF A QUANTUM SYSTEM
that the interaction exists in all regions where the wave function of the system, ψ(x, t), is
nonzero, and thus it seems to suggest that the charge of the system also distributes through-
out these regions. If the charge does not distribute in some regions where the wave function
is nonzero, then
R ∞ there will2 not exist an electrostatic interaction there. Furthermore, since
3
the integral −∞ Q|ψ(x, t)| d x is the total charge of the system, the charge density in space,
if indeed exists, will be Q|ψ(x, t)|2 . Similarly, the mass density can be obtained from the
Schrödinger equation of a quantum system under an external gravitational potential:
∂ψ(x, t) ~2 2
i~ = [− ∇ + mVG ]ψ(x, t). (2.24)
∂t 2m
The gravitational interaction term mVG ψ(x, t) in the equation also suggests that the (passive
gravitational) mass of the quantum system distributes throughout the whole region where
its wave function ψ(x, t) is nonzero, and the mass density in space is m|ψ(x, t)|2 .
23
2.4. ON THE MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY OF A QUANTUM SYSTEM
ψ(x, x0 , t) = aϕ1 (x0 , t)ψ1 (x, t) + bϕ2 (x0 , t)ψ2 (x, t), (2.28)
where ϕ1 (x0 , t) and ϕ2 (x0 , t) are the wave functions of the electron influenced by the electric
fields of the system in box 1 and box 2, respectively, the trajectory of ϕ1 (x0 , t) is deviated
by a maximum amount, and the trajectory of ϕ2 (x0 , t) is not deviated and still a straight
line. When the electron is detected on the screen, the above wave function will collapse to
ϕ1 (x0 , t)ψ1 (x, t) or ϕ2 (x0 , t)ψ2 (x, t). As a result, the detected position of the electron will be
either “1” or “0” in Fig.1, indicating that the system is in box 1 or 2 after the detection.
This is a conventional impulse measurement of the projection operator on the spatial region
of box 1, denoted by A1 . A1 has two eigenstates corresponding to the system being in box
1 and 2, respectively, and the corresponding eigenvalues are 1 and 0, respectively. Since the
measurement is accomplished through the electrostatic interaction between two charges, the
measured observable A1 , when multiplied by the charge Q, is actually the observable for
the charge of the system in box 1, and its eigenvalues are Q and 0, corresponding to the
charge Q being in boxes 1 and 2, respectively. Such a measurement cannot tell us the charge
distribution of the system in each box before the measurement.
24
2.4. ON THE MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY OF A QUANTUM SYSTEM
∂ψ(~r, t) ~2 2 e · |a|2 Q
i~ =− ∇ ψ(~r, t) − k ψ(~r, t), (2.29)
∂t 2me |~r − r~1 |
where me is the mass of electron, k is the Coulomb constant, r~1 is the position of the center
of box 1, and |a|2 Q is the expectation value of the charge Q in box 1. Correspondingly, the
trajectory of the center of the electron wave packet, r~c (t), will satisfy the following equation
by Ehrenfest’s theorem:
d2 r~c e · |a|2 Q
me = −k . (2.30)
dt2 |~
rc − r~1 |(~
rc − r~1 )
Then the electron wave packet will reach the position “|a|2 ” between “0” and “1” on the
screen as denoted in Fig.1. This shows that the result of the protective measurement is the
14
It is worth stressing that the added protection procedure depends on the measured state, and different
states need different protection procedures in general.
25
2.5. THE PHYSICAL ORIGIN OF MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY
expectation value of the projection operator A1 , namely the integral of the density |ψ(x)|2
in the region of box 1. When multiplied by Q, it is the expectation value of the charge Q in
the state ψ1 (x, t) in box 1, namely the integral of the charge density Q|ψ(x)|2 in the region
of box 1. In fact, as Eq. (2.29) and Eq. (2.30) clearly indicate, this is what the protective
measurement really measures.
As we have argued in the last section, the result of a protective measurement reflects the
objective property or physical state of the measured system. Thus the result of the above
protective measurement, namely the expectation value of the charge Q in the state ψ1 (x, t),
|a|2 Q, will reflect the actual charge distribution of the system in box 1. In other words,
the result indicates that there exists a charge |a|2 Q in box 1. In the following, we will give
another two arguments for this conclusion.
First of all, let’s analyze the result of the protective measurement. Suppose we can
continuously change the measured state from |a|2 = 0 to |a|2 = 1 (and adjust the protective
interaction correspondingly). When |a|2 = 0, the single electron will reach the position
“0” of the screen one by one, and it is incontrovertible that no charge is in box 1. When
|a|2 = 1, the single electron will reach the position “1” of the screen one by one, and it is
also incontrovertible that there is a charge Q in box 1. Then when |a|2 assumes a numerical
value between 0 and 1 and the single electron reaches the position “|a|2 ” between “0” and
“1” on the screen one by one, the results should similarly indicate that there is a charge
|a|2 Q in the box by continuity. The point is that the definite deviation of the trajectory of
the electron will reflect that there exists a definite amount of charge in box 1.15 Next, let’s
analyze the equation that determines the result of the protective measurement, namely Eq.
(2.30). It gives a more direct support for the existence of a charge |a|2 Q in box 1. The r.h.s
of Eq. (2.30) is the formula of the electric force between two charges located in different
spatial regions. It is incontrovertible that e is the charge of the electron, and it exists in the
position ~r. Then |a|2 Q should be the other charge that exists in the position r~1 . In other
words, there exists a charge |a|2 Q in box 1.
In conclusion, protective measurement shows that a quantum system with mass m and
charge Q, which is described by the wave function ψ(x, t), has mass density m|ψ(x, t)|2 and
charge density Q|ψ(x, t)|2 in space, respectively16 . Note that this conclusion is only based
on two established parts of quantum mechanics, namely the linear Schrödinger evolution
and the Born rule. In the above example, the linear Schrödinger evolution determines the
deviation of the electron wave packet, and the Born rule is needed to obtain the information
about the center of the electron wave packet detected on the screen.
26
2.5. THE PHYSICAL ORIGIN OF MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY
~2 2 |ψ(x0 , t)|2 3 0
Z
∂ψ(x, t)
i~ =− ∇ ψ(x, t) − Gm2 d x ψ(x, t) + V ψ(x, t), (2.31)
∂t 2m |x − x0 |
~2 2 |ψ(x0 , t)|2 3 0
Z
∂ψ(x, t) 2 2
i~ =− ∇ ψ(x, t) + (kQ − Gm ) d x ψ(x, t). (2.32)
∂t 2m |x − x0 |
Note that the gravitational self-interaction is attractive, while the electrostatic self-interaction
is repulsive. It has been shown that the measure of the potential strength of the gravitational
2
self-interaction is ε2 = ( 4Gm 2
~c ) for a free system with mass m (Salzman 2005). This quantity
17
That a real charge distribution has electrostatic self-interaction has been confirmed not only in the classical
domain but also in the quantum domain for many-body systems. For example, two charged quantum systems
such as two electrons have electrostatic interaction, and thus a real charge distribution containing these two
charges has electrostatic self-interaction. Thus it is reasonable to expect that this assumption also holds true
for individual quantum systems.
18
It has been argued that the existence of a gravitational self-interaction term in the Schrödinger-Newton
equation does not have a consistent Born rule interpretation (Adler 2007). The reason is that the probability
of simultaneously finding a particle in different positions is zero.
27
2.5. THE PHYSICAL ORIGIN OF MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY
represents the strength of the influence of the self-interaction on the normal evolution of the
wave function; when ε2 ≈ 1 the influence is significant. Similarly, for a free charged system
with charge Q, the measure of the potential strength of the electrostatic self-interaction is
2
ε2 = ( 4kQ 2
~c ) . As a typical example, for a free electron the potential strength of the electro-
2
static self-interaction will be ε2 = ( 4ke 2 −3
~c ) ≈ 1 × 10 . This indicates that the electrostatic
self-interaction will have a remarkable influence on the evolution of the wave function of a
free electron19 . If such an interaction indeed exists, it should have been detected by precise
interference experiments on electrons. As another example, consider the electron in the hy-
drogen atom. Since the potential of the electrostatic self-interaction is of the same order as
the Coulomb potential produced by the nucleus, the energy levels of hydrogen atoms will
be remarkably different from those predicted by quantum mechanics and confirmed by ex-
periments. Therefore, the electrostatic self-interaction cannot exist for a charged quantum
system such as an electron.
To sum up, the superposition principle of quantum mechanics requires that the mass and
charge distribution of a quantum system such as an electron is not real but effective; at every
instant there is only a localized particle with the total mass and charge of the system, while
during an infinitesimal time interval the time average of the ergodic motion of the particle
forms the effective mass and charge distribution20 , and the mass and charge density in each
position is proportional to the modulus square of the wave function of the system there.
28
2.5. THE PHYSICAL ORIGIN OF MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY
of time the electron spends in a given position, the electron must be in the left half of the
box half of the time and in the right half of the box half of the time. But it can spend no
time at the center of the box where the effective charge density is zero; in other words, it
must move at infinite velocity at the center. Certainly, the appearance of velocities faster
than light or even infinite velocities may be not a fatal problem, as our discussion is entirely
in the context of non-relativistic quantum mechanics, and especially the infinite potential
in the example is also an ideal situation. However, it seems difficult to explain why the
electron speeds up at the node and where the infinite energy required for the acceleration
comes from. Moreover, the sudden acceleration of the electron near the node may also
result in large radiation (Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman 1993), which is inconsistent
with the predictions of quantum mechanics. Again, it seems very difficult to explain why
the accelerating electron does not radiate here.
Let’s further consider an electron in a superposition of two energy eigenstates in two
boxes ψ1 (x) + ψ2 (x). In this example, even if one assumes that the electron can move with
infinite velocity (e.g. at the nodes), it cannot continuously move from one box to another
due to the restriction of box walls. Therefore, any sort of continuous motion cannot generate
the effective charge distribution e|ψ1 (x) + ψ2 (x)|2 . One may still object that this is merely
an artifact of the idealization of infinite potential. However, even in this ideal situation, the
model should also be able to generate the effective charge distribution by means of some sort
of ergodic motion of the electron; otherwise it will be inconsistent with quantum mechanics.
On the other hand, it is very common in quantum optics experiments that a single-photon
wave packet is split into two branches moving along two well separated paths in space. The
wave function of the photon disappears outside the two paths for all practical purposes.
Moreover, the experimental results are not influenced by the environment and experimental
setup between the two paths of the photon. Thus it is very difficult to imagine that the
photon performs a continuous ergodic motion back and forth in the space between its two
paths.
In view of these serious drawbacks of the classical ergodic models and their inconsis-
tency with quantum mechanics, we conclude that the ergodic motion of particles cannot be
continuous. If the motion of a particle is discontinuous, then the particle can readily move
throughout all regions where the wave function is nonzero during an arbitrarily short time
interval at a given instant. Furthermore, if the probability density of the particle appearing
in each position is proportional to the modulus square of its wave function there at every
instant, the discontinuous motion can also generate the right mass and charge distribution.
This will solve the above problems plagued by the classical ergodic models. The discon-
tinuous ergodic motion requires no existence of a finite ergodic time. Moreover, a particle
undergoing discontinuous motion can also move from one region to another spatially sepa-
rated region, no matter whether there is an infinite potential wall between them, and such
discontinuous motion is not influenced by the environment and experimental setup between
these regions either. Besides, discontinuous motion can also solve the problems of infinite
velocity and accelerating radiation. The reason is that no classical velocity and accelera-
tion can be defined for discontinuous motion, and energy and momentum will require new
definitions and understandings as in quantum mechanics.
In summary, we have argued that the mass and charge distribution of a quantum system,
which can be measured by protective measurement, is not real but effective. Moreover, the
effective mass and charge distribution is formed by the discontinuous motion of a localized
particle, and the probability density of the particle appearing in each position is proportional
to the modulus square of its wave function there.
29
2.5. THE PHYSICAL ORIGIN OF MASS AND CHARGE DENSITY
30
2.6. THE WAVE FUNCTION AS A DESCRIPTION OF RANDOM
DISCONTINUOUS MOTION OF PARTICLES
31
2.6. THE WAVE FUNCTION AS A DESCRIPTION OF RANDOM
DISCONTINUOUS MOTION OF PARTICLES
Since the sum of the measures of all such dense instant sets in the time interval ∆t is equal
to the length of the continuous time interval ∆t, we have:
27
Note that the propensity here denotes single case propensity. For long run propensity theories fail to
explain objective single-case probabilities. According to these theories, it makes no sense to speak of the
propensity of a single isolated event in the absence of a sequence that contains it. For a helpful analysis
of the single-case propensity interpretation of probability in GRW theory see Frigg and Hoefer (2007). In
addition, it is worth stressing that the propensities possessed by particles relate to their objective motion, not
to the measurements on them. By contrast, according to the existing propensity interpretations of quantum
mechanics, the propensities a quantum system has relate only to measurements; a quantum system possesses
the propensity to exhibit a particular value of an observable if the observable is measured on the system (see
Suárez 2004, 2007 for a comprehensive analysis). Like the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics,
these interpretations cannot be wholly satisfactory because of resorting to the vague concept of measurement.
28
However, there is an exception. When the probability density function is a special δ-function such as
δ(x−x(t)), where x(t) is a continuous function of t, the motion of the particle is deterministic and continuous.
In addition, even for a general probability density function it is still possible that the random position series
forms a continuous trajectory, though the happening probability is zero.
29
Recall that a trajectory function x(t) is essentially discontinuous if it is not continuous at every instant
t. A trajectory function x(t) is continuous if and only if for every t and every real number ε > 0, there exists
a real number δ > 0 such that whenever a point t0 has distance less than δ to t, the point x(t0 ) has distance
less than ε to x(t).
32
2.6. THE WAVE FUNCTION AS A DESCRIPTION OF RANDOM
DISCONTINUOUS MOTION OF PARTICLES
X
M∆x,∆t (xj , ti ) = ∆t. (2.34)
j
This quantity provides a strict description of the position distribution of the particle or the
relative frequency of the particle appearing in an infinitesimal space interval dx near position
x during an infinitesimal interval dt near instant t, and it satisfies the normalization relation
R +∞
−∞ ρ(x, t)dx = 1 by Eq. (2.34). Note that the existence of the limit relies on the continuity
of the evolution of %(x, t), the property of the particle that determines the probability density
of it appearing in every position in space. In fact, ρ(x, t) is determined by %(x, t), and there
exists the relation ρ(x, t) = %(x, t). We call ρ(x, t) position measure density or position
density in brief.
Since the position density ρ(x, t) changes with time in general, we may further define the
position flux density j(x, t) through the relation j(x, t) = ρ(x, t)v(x, t), where v(x, t) is the
velocity of the local position density. It describes the change rate of the position density.
Due to the conservation of measure, ρ(x, t) and j(x, t) satisfy the continuity equation:
∂ρ(x, t) ∂j(x, t)
+ = 0. (2.36)
∂t ∂x
The position density ρ(x, t) and position flux density j(x, t) provide a complete description
of the state of random discontinuous motion of a single particle30 .
The description of the motion of a single particle can be extended to the motion of many
particles. For the random discontinuous motion of N particles, we can define joint position
density ρ(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t) and joint position flux density j(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t) = ρ(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t)
v(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t). They also satisfy the continuity equation:
N
∂ρ(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t) X ∂j(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t)
+ = 0. (2.37)
∂t ∂xi
i=1
When these N particles are independent, the joint position density can be reduced to
the
QN direct product of the position density for each particle, namely ρ(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t) =
i=1 ρ(xi , t). Note that the joint position density ρ(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t) and joint position flux
density j(x1 , x2 , ...xN , t) are not defined in the real three-dimensional space, but defined in
the 3N-dimensional configuration space.
33
2.6. THE WAVE FUNCTION AS A DESCRIPTION OF RANDOM
DISCONTINUOUS MOTION OF PARTICLES
~ ∂ψ(x, t) ∂ψ ∗ (x, t)
j(x, t) = [ψ ∗ (x, t) − ψ(x, t) ]. (2.39)
2mi ∂x ∂x
Correspondingly, the wave function ψ(x, t) can be uniquely expressed by ρ(x, t) and j(x, t)
(except for a constant phase factor):
j(x0 ,t)
im x dx0 /~
p R
ψ(x, t) = ρ(x, t)e −∞ ρ(x0 ,t) . (2.40)
In this way, the wave function ψ(x, t) also provides a complete description of the state of
random discontinuous motion of particles. For the motion of many particles, the joint posi-
tion density and joint position flux density are defined in the 3N-dimensional configuration
space, and thus the many-particle wave function, which is composed of these two quantities,
is also defined in the 3N-dimensional configuration space.
Interestingly, we can reverse the above logic in some sense, namely by assuming the wave
function is a complete objective description for the motion of particles, we can also reach
the random discontinuous motion of particles, independent of our previous analysis. If the
wave function ψ(x, t) is a complete description of the state of motion for a single particle,
then the quantity |ψ(x, t)|2 dx will not only give the probability of the particle being found
in an infinitesimal space interval dx near position x at instant t (as required by quantum
mechanics), but also give the objective probability of the particle being there at the instant.
This accords with the common-sense assumption that the probability distribution of the
measurement results of a property is the same as the objective distribution of the values
of the property in the measured state. Then at instant t the particle will be in a random
position where the probability density |ψ(x, t)|2 is nonzero, and during an infinitesimal time
interval near instant t it will move throughout the whole region where the wave function
ψ(x, t) spreads. Moreover, its position density in each position is equal to the probability
density there. Obviously this kind of motion is random and discontinuous.
One important point needs to be pointed out here. Since the wave function in quantum
mechanics is defined at an instant, not during an infinitesimal time interval, it should be
regarded not simply as a description of the state of random discontinuous motion of particles,
but more suitably as a description of the intrinsic property of the particles that determines
their random discontinuous motion at a deeper level32 . In particular, the modulus square
of the wave function represents the property that determines the probability density of the
particles appearing in certain positions in space at a given instant (this means %(x, t) ≡
|ψ(x, t)|2 ). By contrast, the position density and position flux density, which are defined
during an infinitesimal time interval at a given instant, are only a description of the state
of the resulting random discontinuous motion of particles, and they are determined by the
wave function. In this sense, we may say that the motion of particles is “guided” by their
wave function in a probabilistic way.
We have been discussed random discontinuous motion of particles in real space. The
picture of random discontinuous motion may exist not only for position but also for other
31
Note that the relation between j(x, t) and ψ(x, t) depends on the concrete evolution under an external
potential such as electromagnetic vector potential. By contrast, the relation ρ(x, t) = |ψ(x, t)|2 holds true
universally, independent of the concrete evolution.
32
For a many-particle system in an entangled state, this property is possessed by the whole system. See
Chapter 5 for a detailed analysis of the physical picture of quantum entanglement.
34
2.6. THE WAVE FUNCTION AS A DESCRIPTION OF RANDOM
DISCONTINUOUS MOTION OF PARTICLES
dynamical variables such as momentum and energy, and thus the interpretation of the wave
function in position space may also apply to the wave function in momentum space etc. This
means that if a particle is in a superposition of the eigenstates of a variable, it will undergo
random discontinuous motion among the corresponding eigenvalues of this variable33 . How-
ever, we note that spin is a distinct property. Since the spin of a free particle is always
definite along one direction, the spin of the particle does not undergo random discontinuous
motion, though a spin eigenstate along one direction can always be decomposed into two
different spin eigenstates along another direction. But if the spin state of a particle is en-
tangled with its spatial state due to interaction and the branches of the entangled state are
well separated in space, the particle in different branches will have different spin, and it will
also undergo random discontinuous motion between these different spin states. This is the
situation that usually happens during a spin measurement.
33
Since the values of two noncommutative variables (e.g. position and momentum) at every instant are
random and mutually independent, the objective value distribution of every variable can be equal to the
modulus square of its respective wave function. Besides, it is worth stressing that for random discontinuous
motion the property of a particle in a superposition of the eigenstates of the property is indeterminate in the
sense of usual hidden variables, though it does have a definite value at every instant. This makes the theorems
that restrict hidden variables such as the Kochen-Specker theorem (Kochen and Specker 1967) irrelevant.
35
3
The motion of particles follows probability law but the proba-
bility itself propagates according to the law of causality.
— Max Born, 1926
After investigating the physical meaning of the wave function, we will further analyze the
linear evolution law for the wave function in this chapter. It is demonstrated that the
linear non-relativistic evolution of the wave function of an isolated system obeys the free
Schrödinger equation due to the requirements of spacetime translation invariance and rel-
ativistic invariance. In addition, we also investigate the meaning and implications of the
conservation laws in quantum mechanics.
Many quantum mechanics textbooks provide a heuristic “derivation” of the Schrödinger
equation. It begins with the assumption that the state of a free quantum system has the form
of a plane wave ei(kx−ωt) . When combining with the de Broglie relations for momentum and
energy p = ~k and E = ~ω, this state becomes ei(px−Et)/~ . Then it uses the nonrelativistic
energy-momentum relation E = p2 /2m to obtain the free particle Schrödinger equation.
Lastly, this equation is generalized to include an external potential, and the end result is the
Schrödinger equation.
In the following sections, we will show that the heuristic “derivation” of the free Schrödinger
equation can be turned into a real derivation by resorting to spacetime translation invariance
and relativistic invariance1 . Spacetime translation gives the definitions of momentum and
energy, and spacetime translation invariance entails that the state of a free quantum system
with definite momentum and energy assumes the plane wave form ei(px−Et)/~ . Moreover, the
relativistic invariance of the free states further determines the relativistic energy-momentum
relation, whose nonrelativistic approximation is E = p2 /2m. Though the requirements
of these invariances are already well known, an explicit and complete derivation of the free
Schrödinger equation using them seems still missing in the literature and textbooks. The new
integrated analysis may not only help to understand the physical origin of the Schrödinger
equation, but also help to understand momentum and energy and their conservation for
random discontinuous motion of particles.
1
There have been some attempts to derive the Schrödinger equation from Newtonian mechanics, one typical
example of which is Nelson’s stochastic mechanics (Nelson 1966). However, it has been argued that Nelson’s
derivation is problematic, and in particular, stochastic mechanics is inconsistent with quantum mechanics
(Glabert, Hänggi and Talkner 1979; Wallstrom 1994). Glabert, Hänggi and Talkner (1979) argued that the
Schrödinger equation is not equivalent to a Markovian process, and the various correlation functions used in
quantum mechanics do not have the properties of the correlations of a classical stochastic process. Wallstrom
(1994) further showed that one must add by hand a quantization condition, as in the old quantum theory, in
order to recover the Schrödinger equation, and thus the Schrödinger equation and the Madelung hydrodynamic
equations are not equivalent. In addition, Nelson (2005) also showed that there is an empirical difference
between the predictions of quantum mechanics and his stochastic mechanics when considering quantum
entanglement and nonlocality. For example, for two widely-separated but entangled harmonic oscillators,
the two theories predict totally different statistics; stochastic mechanics predicts that measurements of the
position of the first one at time T (oscillation period) and the position of the second one at time 0 do not
interfere with each other, while quantum mechanics predicts that there exists a strong correlation between
them.
36
3.1. SPACETIME TRANSLATION AND ITS INVARIANCE
∂
P = −i
. (3.3)
∂x
Similarly, a time translation operator can be defined as
∂ψ(x, t)
i = Hψ(x, t). (3.5)
∂t
where H is a to-be-determined operator that depends on the properties of the system. In
the following analysis of this section, we assume H is independent of the evolved state,
namely the evolution is linear2 . Then the time translation operator U (t) can be expressed
as U (t) = e−itH , and H is the generator of time translation. Note that we cannot determine
whether U (t) is unitary and H is Hermitian here.
Let’s now analyze the implications of spacetime translation invariance for the laws of
motion of a free system or an isolated system. First, time translational invariance requires
that H has no time dependence, namely dH/dt = 0. This can be demonstrated as follows
(Shankar 1994, p.295). Suppose an isolated system is in state ψ0 at time t1 and evolves for
an infinitesimal time δt. The state of the system at time t1 + δt, to first order in δt, will be
37
3.1. SPACETIME TRANSLATION AND ITS INVARIANCE
If the evolution is repeated at time t2 , beginning with the same initial state, the state at
t2 + δt will be
38
3.2. RELATIVISTIC INVARIANCE
p0 + E0 v/c2
p= p , (3.14)
1 − v 2 /c2
E0 + p0 v
E=p . (3.15)
1 − v 2 /c2
We further suppose that the particle is at rest in frame S0 . Then the velocity of the
particle is v in frame S.5 Considering that the velocity of a particle in the momentum
eigenstate ei(px−Et) or a wavepacket superposed by these eigenstates is defined as the group
velocity of the wavepacket, namely
dE
u= , (3.16)
dp
we have
39
3.3. DERIVATION OF THE FREE SCHRÖDINGER EQUATION
dE/dp = v. (3.18)
Eq.(3.17) means that E0 and p0 are independent. Moreover, since the particle is at rest in
S0 , E0 and p0 do not depend on v. By differentiating both sides of Eq.(3.14) and Eq.(3.15)
relative to v we obtain
dp v p0 + E0 v/c2 E0 /c2
= 2 + 1 , (3.19)
dv c (1 − v 2 /c2 ) 23 (1 − v 2 /c2 ) 2
dE v E0 + p0 v p0
= 2 3 + 1 . (3.20)
dv c (1 − v 2 /c2 ) 2 (1 − v 2 /c2 ) 2
Dividing Eq.(3.20) by Eq.(3.19) and using Eq.(3.18) we obtain
p0
p = 0. (3.21)
1 − v 2 /c2
This means that p0 = 0. Inputting this important result into Eq.(3.15) and Eq.(3.14), we
immediately obtain
E0
E=p , (3.22)
1 − v 2 /c2
E0 v/c2
p= p . (3.23)
1 − v 2 /c2
Then the energy-momentum relation is:
E 2 = p2 c2 + E02 , (3.24)
where E0 is the energy of the particle at rest, called rest energy of the particle, and p and E
is the momentum and energy of the particle with velocity v. By defining m = E0 /c2 as the
(rest) mass of the particle6 , we can further obtain the familiar energy-momentum relation
E 2 = p2 c2 + m2 c4 . (3.25)
In the nonrelativistic domain, this energy-momentum relation reduces to E = p2 /2m.
∂ψ(x, t) 1 ∂ 2 ψ(x, t)
i =− . (3.26)
∂t 2m ∂x2
6
According to the analysis given here, it seems that we can in principle avoid talking about mass in modern
physics from a more fundamental point of view (cf. Okun 2009).
7
This also means that the Klein-Gordon equation can be derived in the relativistic domain when assuming
that the wave function is a number function.
40
3.4. FURTHER DISCUSSIONS
It is worth noting that, unlike the free particle Schrödinger equation, the reduced Planck
constant ~ with dimension of action is missing in this equation. However, this is not a
problem. The reason is that the dimension of ~ can be absorbed into the dimension of the
mass m. For example, we can stipulate the dimensional relations as p = 1/L, E = 1/T and
m = T /L2 , where L and T represents the dimensions of space and time, respectively (see
Duff, Okun and Veneziano 2002 for more discussions). Moreover, the value of ~ can be set
to the unit of number 1 in principle. Thus the above equation is essentially the free particle
Schrödinger equation in quantum mechanics.
By using the definition of classical potential and requiring an appropriate expectation
value correspondence, dhP i/dt = −h∂V /∂xi, we can further obtain the Schrödinger equation
under an external potential V (x, t)8 :
∂ψ(x, t) 1 ∂ 2 ψ(x, t)
i =− + V (x, t)ψ(x, t). (3.27)
∂t 2m ∂x2
∂
The general form of a classical potential may be V (x, ∂x , t), and its concrete form is deter-
mined by the non-relativistic approximation of the quantum interactions involved, which are
described by the relativistic quantum field theory. Since the potential V (x, t) is real-valued,
the Hamiltonian H = P 2 /2m + V (x, t) is Hermitian, and as a result, the time translation
operator or evolution operator U (t) is also unitary.
41
3.4. FURTHER DISCUSSIONS
speaking, time translational invariance requires that dH/dt = 0, and the solution of the
evolution equation i ∂ψ(x,t)
∂t = Hψ(x, t) must assume the form ψ(x, t) = ϕE (x)e−iEt . Space
translational invariance requires [P, H] = 0, and this further determines that ϕE (x) is the
eigenstate of P , namely ϕE (x) = eipx . Thus spacetime translation invariance entails that the
state of an isolated system with definite momentum and energy assumes the plane wave form
ei(px−Et) . Furthermore, the relation between p and E or the energy-momentum relation can
be determined by the relativistic invariance of the momentum eigenstate ei(px−Et) , and its
non-relativistic approximation is just E = p2 /2m. Then we can obtain the form of the energy
operator for an isolated system, H = P 2 /2m, and the free Schrödinger equation, Eq.(3.26).
To sum up, this analysis may answer why the wave function must assume a complex form
in general and why there are the de Broglie relations and why the non-relativistic energy-
momentum relation is what it is.
So far so good. But how does the wave function ψ(x, t) in the thus-derived free Schrödinger
equation relate to the actual physical state of the system? Without answering this question
the above analysis seems vacuous in physics. This leads us to the problem of interpreting
the wave function. According to the standard probability interpretation, the wave function
in quantum mechanics is a probability amplitude, and its modulus square gives the proba-
bility density of finding a particle in certain locations. Notwithstanding the success of the
standard interpretation, our derivation of the free Schrödinger equation seems to suggest
that the wave function ψ(x, t) is a description of the objective physical state of a quantum
system, rather than the probability amplitude relating only to measurement outcomes. In
our derivation we never refer to the measurement of the isolated system at all. Moreover, the
derivation seems to further suggest that the wave function ψ(x, t) is a complete description
of the physical state of the system. As we have argued in the last chapter, ψ(x, t) can be re-
garded as an objective description of the state of random discontinuous motion of a particle,
and |ψ(x, t)|2 dx gives the objective probability of the particle being in an infinitesimal space
interval dx near position x at instant t. This objective interpretation of the wave function
is quite consistent with the above derivation of the free Schrödinger equation.
In addition, the derivation may provide another argument for the non-existence of con-
tinuous motion of particles from the aspect of the laws of motion. The continuous motion
of a particle can be regarded as a very special form of discontinuous motion, for which the
position density of the particle is ρ(x, t) = δ 2 (x − x(t)), where x(t) is the continuous trajec-
tory of the particle. However, such states are not solutions of the equation of free motion,
namely the free Schrödinger equation, though they satisfy the continuity equation. Accord-
ing to the free Schrödinger equation, an initial local state like δ(x − x0 ) cannot sustain its
locality during the evolution, and it will immediately spread throughout the whole space.
Thus the equation of free motion, which is derived based on the fundamental requirements of
spacetime translation invariance and relativistic invariance, does not describe the continuous
motion of particles. If the equation of free motion still describes the motion of particles as
we have argued in the last chapter, then the motion of particles cannot be continuous but
must be essentially discontinuous. Note that our derivation of the free Schrödinger equation
does not depend on the picture of discontinuous motion, and thus this argument for the
non-existence of continuous motion of particles is not a vicious circle.
As stressed earlier, our derivation of the free Schrödinger equation relies on the presuppo-
sition that the Hamiltonian H is independent of the evolved state, i.e., that the evolution is
linear. It can be reasonably assumed that the linear evolution and nonlinear evolution both
exist, and moreover, they satisfy spacetime translation invariance respectively because their
effects cannot counteract each other in general. Then our derivation only shows that the
linear part of free evolution, if satisfying spacetime translation invariance and relativistic in-
variance, must assume the same form as the free Schrödinger equation in the non-relativistic
42
3.5. ON THE CONSERVATION OF ENERGY AND MOMENTUM
domain. Obviously, our derivation cannot exclude the existence of nonlinear quantum evolu-
tion. Moreover, since a general nonlinear evolution can readily satisfy spacetime translation
invariance, the invariance requirement can no longer determine the concrete form of possible
nonlinear evolution.
dhAi ∂A
=h i − ih[A, H]i, (3.28)
dt ∂t
where hAi = ψ ∗ (x, t)Aψ(x, t)dx is defined as the expectation value of A, we have
R
dhHi
= 0, (3.29)
dt
and
dhP i
= 0. (3.30)
dt
This means that the expectation values of energy and momentum are conserved for the
evolution of an isolated system. Moreover, for arbitrary functions f (H) and f (P ), we also
have
dhf (H)i
= 0, (3.31)
dt
and
dhf (P )i
= 0. (3.32)
dt
This is equivalent to the constancy of the expectation values of the generating functions or
spacetime translation operators U (a) ≡ e−iaH and T (a) ≡ e−iaP
dhU (a)i
= 0, (3.33)
dt
and
dhT (a)i
= 0. (3.34)
dt
43
3.5. ON THE CONSERVATION OF ENERGY AND MOMENTUM
By these two equations it follows that the probability distributions of energy eigenvalues
and momentum eigenvalues are constant in time. This statement is usually defined as the
conservation of energy and momentum in quantum mechanics.
Now let’s analyze the implications of this derivation for the meaning of the conservation
of energy and momentum. First of all, we point out that the linearity of evolution is an
indispensable presupposition in the derivation. As we have stressed in the derivation of the
free Schrödinger equation, spacetime translation invariance does not lead to dH/dt = 0 and
[P, H] = 0 without assuming the linearity of evolution. Therefore, the common wisdom
that spacetime translation invariance implies laws of conservation only holds true for a
linear evolution. For a general nonlinear evolution H(ψ), energy and momentum will not be
conserved by Ehrenfest’s theorem9 :
dhP i ∂P ∂H(ψ)
=h i − ih[P, H(ψ)]i = −ih[P, H(ψ)]i = −h i=6 0. (3.36)
dt ∂t ∂x
We can see the violation of the conservation of energy and momentum more clearly by an-
alyzing the nonlinear evolution of momentum eigenstates ei(px−Et) and their superpositions.
If a nonlinear evolution can conserve energy and momentum for momentum eigenstates, then
the momentum eigenstates must be the solutions of the nonlinear evolution equation; other-
wise the evolution will change the definite momentum eigenvalues or energy eigenvalues or
both and lead to the violation of the conservation of energy and momentum. Some nonlin-
ear evolutions can satisfy this requirement. For example, when H(ψ) = P 2 /2m + α|ψ|2 , the
solutions still include the momentum eigenstates ei(px−Et) , where E = p2 /2m + α, and thus
energy and momentum are conserved for such nonlinear evolutions of momentum eigenstates.
However, even if a nonlinear evolution can conserve energy and momentum for momentum
eigenstates, it cannot conserve energy and momentum for the superpositions of momentum
eigenstates. The reason is obvious. Only for a linear evolution the momentum eigenstates
and their superpositions can both be the solutions of the evolution equation. For any nonlin-
ear evolution H(ψ), if the momentum eigenstates are already its solutions, then their linear
superposition cannot be its solutions. This means that the coefficients of the momentum
eigenstates in the superposition will change with time during the evolution. The change of
the amplitudes of the coefficients directly leads to the change of the probability distribution
of momentum eigenvalues and energy eigenvalues, while the change of the phases of the
coefficients leads to the change of the momentum eigenvalues or energy eigenvalues, which
also leads to the change of the probability distribution of momentum eigenvalues or energy
eigenvalues. In fact, a nonlinear evolution may not only change the probability distributions
of energy and momentum eigenvalues, but also change the energy-momentum relation in gen-
eral cases (e.g. in the above example)10 . These results are understandable when considering
the fact that the nonlinear evolution of a spatial wave function will generally introduce a
time-dependent interaction between its different momentum eigenstates, which is equivalent
to adding a time-dependent external potential for its free evolution in some sense. Therefore,
it is not beyond expectation that a nonlinear evolution violates the conservation of energy
and momentum in general.
9
In order to ensure that the nonlinear evolution is unitary and thus the total probability is conserved in
time, the Hamiltonian H(ψ) must be Hermitian. Besides, this property is also required to ensure that the
energy eigenvalues (which satisfy the equation H(ψ)ψ(x) = Eψ(x)) are real. When the Hamiltonian H(ψ) is
Hermitian, the Ehrenfest theorem holds true.
10
This will violate the relativistic invariance of momentum eigenstates.
44
3.5. ON THE CONSERVATION OF ENERGY AND MOMENTUM
Two points needs to be stressed here. First, energy and momentum are still defined as
usual for a nonlinear evolution in the above discussions. One may object that they should
be re-defined for a nonlinear evolution. However, this may be not the case. The reason is
as follows. Momentum is defined as the generator of space translation, and this definition
uniquely determines that its eigenstates are eipx . Similarly, energy is defined as the gener-
ator of time translation, and this definition uniquely determines that its eigenstates satisfy
H(ψ)ψ(x) = Eψ(x). Since these definitions are independent of whether the evolution of the
state is linear or nonlinear, they should have a fundamental status in a theory formulated in
space and time such as quantum mechanics. The second point is that the above argument
implicitly assumes that the nonlinear evolution H(ψ) is universal, i.e., that it applies to
all possible states. If the nonlinear evolution only applies to some special states, then the
evolution may still conserve energy and momentum. For example, suppose the nonlinear
evolution H(ψ) = P 2 /2m + α|ψ|2 applies only to the momentum eigenstates ei(px−Et) and
the linear evolution H(ψ) = P 2 /2m applies to the superpositions of momentum eigenstates,
then energy and momentum are still conserved during the evolution. On the other hand,
it has been argued that the universal nonlinear quantum dynamics has a serious drawback,
namely that the description of composite systems depends on a particular basis in the Hilbert
space (Czachor 1996). If a nonlinear quantum evolution only applies to certain privileged
bases due to some reason, then such nonlinear quantum dynamics may be logically consistent
and also conserve energy and momentum (Gao 2004).
The second implication of the above derivation of the conservation laws is that spacetime
translation invariance implies the conservation of energy and momentum for individual states,
not for an ensemble of identical states. As in the derivation of the free Schrödinger equation,
we only refer to an isolated system and never refer to an ensemble of identical systems
in the derivation of the conservation laws. Moreover, the transformations of spacetime
translation also apply to a single isolated system. Therefore, what the derivation tells us
is that spacetime translation invariance implies the conservation of energy and momentum
for the linear evolution of the states of an isolated system. The conservation of energy and
momentum for a single system means that the objective probability distributions of energy
eigenvalues and momentum eigenvalues are constant during the evolution of the state of the
system. As we have argued in the last chapter, the objective probability can be understood
according to the interpretation of the wave function in terms of random discontinuous motion.
Similarly, the above analysis of nonlinear evolutions also shows that a universal nonlinear
evolution violates the conservation of energy and momentum for individual systems.
This implication raises a further issue. It is well known that the conservation of energy
and momentum in quantum mechanics refers to an ensemble of identical systems, not to
individual systems, and its precise statement is that the probability distributions of the
measurement results of energy and momentum for an ensemble of identical isolated systems
are constant during the evolution of the systems in the ensemble. But as we have argued
above, the derivation of the conservation laws based on spacetime translation invariance is
for individual isolated systems, not for an ensemble of these systems. The derivation never
refers to the measurements of these systems either. Therefore, there is still a gap (which
may be very large) between the derivation and the conservation laws in quantum mechanics.
Undoubtedly we must analyze the measurement process in order to fill the gap. We will
postpone a detailed analysis of the measurement problem to the next section. Here we only
want to answer a more general question. If the conservation laws in quantum mechanics
are indeed valid as widely thought, then what are their implications for the evolution of
individual states?
First of all, the evolution of the state of an isolated system cannot contain a universal
deterministic nonlinear evolution, which applies to all possible states; otherwise the evolution
45
3.5. ON THE CONSERVATION OF ENERGY AND MOMENTUM
will violate the conservation of energy and momentum not only at the individual level but
also at the ensemble level. Next, the evolution may contain linear evolutions as well as
special deterministic nonlinear evolutions that apply only to certain privileged states. They
can both conserve energy and momentum for individual states11 . Lastly, the evolution may
also contain a (universal) stochastic nonlinear evolution, which applies to all possible states.
Although the evolution cannot conserve energy and momentum for individual states, it may
conserve energy and momentum for an ensemble of identical states. As we will see in the
next chapter, the dynamical collapse of the wave function may be such a stochastic nonlinear
evolution.
To summarize, we have analyzed the relationships between the conservation of energy
and momentum, spacetime translation invariance and the linearity of quantum dynamics. It
has been often claimed that the conservation of energy and momentum is a conservation law
resulting from the requirement of spacetime translation invariance. However, this common-
sense view is not wholly right. Only when assuming the linearity of quantum dynamics,
can spacetime translation invariance lead to the conservation of energy and momentum.
Moreover, the connection between invariance of natural laws and conservation laws is for
individual states, not for an ensemble of identical states. Although a nonlinear evolution of
the wave function can readily satisfy spacetime translation invariance, the invariance can no
longer lead to the conservation of energy and momentum, let alone determining the form of
the nonlinear evolution. Rather, a universal nonlinear evolution that applies to all possible
states will inevitably violate the conservation of energy and momentum.
Since the conservation of energy and momentum is required by spacetime translation in-
variance only for the linear evolution of the wave function of an isolated system, the principle
cannot exclude the existence of a possible nonlinear evolution that may violate it. In other
words, spacetime translation invariance is no longer a reason to require that the evolution
of the wave function of an isolated system must conserve energy and momentum. On the
other hand, the conservation of energy and momentum may still hold true for an ensemble
of identical isolated systems as claimed by the standard quantum mechanics. Therefore, a
(universal) stochastic nonlinear evolution of the wave function may exist. Although such
evolutions cannot conserve energy and momentum for individual states, it may conserve
energy and momentum at the ensemble level. However, unlike the linear evolution, which
is natural in the sense that its form can be uniquely determined by the invariance require-
ments, the stochastic nonlinear evolution must have a physical origin, and its form can only
be determined by the underlying mechanism. In the next chapter, we will investigate the
possible stochastic nonlinear evolution of the wave function.
11
For more discussions about the arguments for linear quantum dynamics see Holman (2006) and references
therein.
46
4
Was the wavefunction of the world waiting to jump for thousands of millions
of years until a single-celled living creature appeared? Or did it have to wait a
little longer, for some better qualified system ... with a Ph.D.? ... Do we not
have jumping then all the time?
— John Bell, 1990
47
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
problem before experiments give the last verdict (cf. Marshall et al 2003)1 .
In this chapter, we will first investigate the existing solutions to the measurement prob-
lem and then propose a new solution based on the implications of protective measurement
and the meaning of the wave function. It is first shown that the two quantum theories
without wavefunction collapse, namely the de Broglie-Bohm theory and the many-worlds
interpretation, are inconsistent with protective measurement and the picture of random dis-
continuous motion of particles. This result strongly suggests that wavefunction collapse is a
real physical process. Next, it is argued that the random discontinuous motion of particles
may provide an appropriate random source to collapse the wave function. Moreover, the
wavefunction collapse is a discrete process, and the collapse states are energy eigenstates
when the principle of conservation of energy is satisfied. Based on these analyses, we fur-
ther propose a discrete model of energy-conserved wavefunction collapse. It is shown that
the model is consistent with existing experiments and our macroscopic experience. Lastly,
we also provide a critical analysis of other dynamical collapse models, including Penrose’s
gravity-induced collapse model and the CSL (Continuous Spontaneous Localization) model.
48
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
always definite. It can be shown that the de Broglie-Bohm theory gives the same predictions
of measurement results as standard quantum mechanics by means of a quantum equilibrium
hypothesis (so long as the latter gives unambiguous predictions). Concretely speaking, the
quantum equilibrium hypothesis provides the initial conditions for the guidance equation
which make the de Broglie-Bohm theory obey Born’s rule in terms of position distributions.
Moreover, since all measurements can be finally expressed in terms of position, e.g. pointer
positions, this amounts to full accordance with all predictions of quantum mechanics3 . In
this way, it seems that the de Broglie-Bohm theory can succeed in avoiding the collapse of
the wave function.
However, although the de Broglie-Bohm theory is mathematically equivalent to quantum
mechanics, there is no clear consensus with regard to its physical interpretation. The physical
contents of the theory contain three parts: the Bohmian particles, the wave function, and
the interaction between them. We first analyze the Bohmian particles and their physical
properties. It is fair to say that what physical properties a Bohmian particle has is still
an unsettled issue, and different proponents of the theory may have different opinions. For
example, it has been often claimed that a Bohmian particle has mass, as the guiding equation
for each Bohmian particle of a many-body system obviously contains the mass of each sub-
system (Goldstein 2009). Yet it seems unclear whether the mass is inertial mass or (passive
or active) gravitational mass or both or neither. On the other hand, it has been argued that
the mass of a quantum system should be possessed by its wave function, not by its Bohmian
particles (Brown, Dewdney and Horton 1995). It was even claimed (without proof) that a
Bohmian particle has no properties other than its position (Hanson and Thoma 2011). In
the last analysis, in order to know exactly what physical properties a Bohmian particle has,
we need to analyze the guiding equation that defines the laws of motion for them.
In the minimum formulation of the theory, which is usually called Bohmian mechanics
(Goldstein 2009)4 , the guiding equation for the Bohmian particle of a one-particle system
with mass m and charge e in the presence of an external electromagnetic field is5
dx ∇ψt
m = ~=[ ] − eA(x, t), (4.1)
dt ψt
where x is the position of the Bohmian particle, ψt is the wave function of the system
that obeys the Schrödinger equation, A(x, t) is the magnetic vector potential in position x.
According to this equation, the motion of a Bohmian particle is not only guided by the wave
function, but also influenced by the external vector potential A(x, t). The existence of the
term eA(x, t) in the guiding equation indicates that the Bohmian particle has charge e, the
charge of the system, and the charge is localized in its position6 . Besides, the appearance
of the mass of the system in the equation may indicate that the Bohmian particle also has
the (inertial) mass of the system. Therefore, according to Bohmian mechanics, the Bohmian
particle of a one-particle system such as an electron has the mass and charge of the system.
For example, in the ground state of a hydrogen atom, the Bohmian particle of the electron
in the atom has the mass and charge of the electron, and it is at rest in a random position
near the nucleus.
3
Certainly, as Albert (1992) noted, no theory can have exactly the same empirical content as quantum
mechanics does, as the latter (in the absence of any satisfactory account of wavefunction collapse) does not
have any exact empirical content.
4
For a critical analysis of this minimal formal interpretation see Belousek (2003).
5
Note that this guiding equation applies only for spin 0 particles, and for spin 1/2 particles there is also
a spin-dependent term (Holland and Philippidis 2003).
6
That a Bohmian particle has no properties other than its position is possible only when the mass and
charge terms disappear in the guiding equation, but the resulting theory will contradict quantum mechanics
and experiments.
49
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
That the Bohmian particle of a one-particle system has the mass and charge of the system
can be seen more clearly from the quantum potential formulation of the de Broglie-Bohm
theory. By differentiating both sides of Eq. (4.1) relative to time and including an external
gravitational potential VG , we obtain
dẋ ∂A
m = −∇Q − m∇VG − e[∇A0 + − ẋ × (∇ × A)], (4.2)
dt ∂t
2
d ∂ ~ ∇ |ψt |
2
where dt = ∂t + ẋ · ∇, A0 is the electric scalar potential, and Q = − 2m |ψt | is the so-called
quantum potential. The electromagnetic interaction term −e[∇A0 + ∂A ∂t − ẋ × (∇ × A)]
indicates that the Bohmian particle has charge e, and the gravitational interaction term
−m∇VG indicates that the Bohmian particle also has (passive) gravitational mass m.
It can be seen that although a Bohmian particle has mass and charge, the functions of
these properties are not as complete as usual. For example, in Bohmian mechanics, a charged
Bohmian particle responds not to the electric scalar potential, but only to the magnetic vector
potential, and it has no gravitational mass but only inertial mass. This apparent abnormal-
ity is in want of a reasonable physical explanation. In addition, in the quantum potential
formulation, although the Bohmian particles of a quantum system respond to external grav-
itational and electromagnetic potentials, they don’t have gravitational and electromagnetic
influences on other charged quantum systems, including their Bohmian particles. Moreover,
the Bohmian particles of a quantum system do not have gravitational and electromagnetic
interactions with each other. Therefore, the (gravitational) mass and charge of a Bohmian
particle are always passive, i.e., a Bohmian particle is only a receptor of gravitational and
electromagnetic interactions. This characteristic may lead to some problems. For one, the
nonreciprocal interactions will violate the conservation of energy and momentum (except
that the Bohmian particles have no momentum and energy). At the worst, it already sug-
gests that the hypothetical Bohmian particles are redundant entities in the theory (and
their role in solving the measurement problem is ad hoc), since they have no any influence
on other entities in the theory such as the wave function. Note that these problems do not
exist for the wave function; the evolution of the wave function of a charged quantum system
is influenced by both electric scalar potential and magnetic vector potential, as well as by
gravitational potential, and the wave functions of two charged quantum systems also have
gravitational and electromagnetic interactions with each other.
Another suggestion of the non-existence of Bohmian particles concerns the mass and
charge distributions of a one-particle system such as an electron. As we have shown above,
the guiding equation in the de Broglie-Bohm theory requires that the Bohmian particle of
a one-particle system has the mass and charge of the system, and the mass and charge are
localized in a position where the Bohmian particle is. On the other hand, as noted before,
protective measurement shows that the mass and charge of a one-particle system such as an
electron are not localized in one position but distributed throughout space, and the mass and
charge density in each position is proportional to the modulus square of its wave function
there. Therefore, the de Broglie-Bohm theory is inconsistent with the results of protective
measurement concerning the mass and charge distributions of a quantum system7 . This
7
This conclusion relies on the common-sense assumption that an electron indeed has only one basic charge
(and one mass of the electron). The only way to avoid the inconsistency is to assume that an electron has
two basic charges: one for its wave function and the other for its Bohmian particle. In this case, since what
protective measurement measures is the mass and charge distributions relating to the wave function, not the
masses and charges of the Bohmian particles, the above inconsistency can be avoided. However, this theory
seems too clumsy and unnatural to be true. Moreover, it will introduce more problems. For one, there is
a dilemma concerning the electromagnetic interaction between the wave function and the Bohmian particle
of an electron. If they do have usual electromagnetic interaction, then the theory will be inconsistent with
quantum mechanics and experiments. If they have no electromagnetic interaction, then this will add more
50
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
51
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
Lastly, we analyze the hypothetical interaction between the Bohmian particles and the
wave function in the de Broglie-Bohm theory. It can be seen that the guiding responsibility
of the wave function assumed by the theory is inconsistent with the meaning of the wave
function. As noted above, the wave function represents the property of particles that de-
termines their random discontinuous motion. Accordingly, the wave function indeed guides
the motion of particles in some sense. However, the wave function guides the motion of the
particles not in a deterministic and continuous way as assumed by the de Broglie-Bohm the-
ory, but in a probabilistic and discontinuous way; the modulus square of the wave function
determines the probability density of the particles appearing in certain positions in space.
Moreover, the motion of these particles is ergodic. By contrast, the motion of the Bohmian
particles is not ergodic, and the time averages of the Bohmian particles positions typically
differ remarkably from the ensemble averages (Aharonov, Erez and Scully 2004).
Although one may assume that a quantum system contains additional Bohmian particles
besides its non-Bohmian particles that undergo random discontinuous motion, the motion of
the Bohmian particles cannot be guided by the wave function of the system. For the wave
function of the system represents the property of the non-Bohmian particles of the system,
and its efficiency is to guide the motion of these particles in a probabilistic way. In particular,
the wave function is neither a field-like entity distributing throughout space nor a property of
the Bohmian particles that may guide their motion, and at every instant there are only non-
Bohmian particles being in positions that are usually far from the positions of the Bohmian
particles. Note also that the non-Bohmian particles cannot have known interactions such as
gravitational and electromagnetic interactions with the Bohmian particles either; otherwise
the theory will contradict quantum mechanics and experiments. Without being guided by
the wave function in a proper way, the motion of the Bohmian particles will be unable to
generate the right measurement results in conventional impulse measurements.
In conclusion, we have shown that the de Broglie-Bohm theory is inconsistent with the
results of protective measurement and the meaning of the wave function implied by them
when considering its physical contents.
52
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
vented to explain the emergence of these results, e.g. the definite measurement result in
each world always denotes the result of a conventional impulse measurement. However, this
does not guarantee consistency for all types of measurements. Indeed, it can be seen that
the existence of the many worlds defined above is inconsistent with the results of protective
measurements. The reason is that the whole superposed wave function of a quantum system
including a measuring device can be measured by a protective measurement12 . The result
of the protective measurement indicates that all branches of the superposed wave function
of the measuring device exist in the same world where the protective measurement is made.
Therefore, according to protective measurement, the branches of the superposed wave func-
tion of a measuring device, in each of which there is a definite measurement result, do not
correspond to many worlds, in each of which there is only one such branch; rather, the
whole superposed wave function of the device, if it exists, only exists in one world, namely
our world. In this way, protective measurement provides a strong argument against the
many-worlds interpretation13 .
Four points are worth stressing. First of all, the above argument does not depend on
how the many worlds are precisely defined in the many-worlds interpretation. The key point
is that all branches of the superposed wave function of a measuring device can be detected
by protective measurement in our world, and thus they all exist in one world. Therefore,
according to protective measurement, it is impossible that there are many worlds, in each
of which there is only one branch of the superposed wave function of a measuring device.
Next, the above argument is not influenced by environment-induced decoherence. On the
one hand, even if the superposition state of a measuring device is entangled with the states
of other systems, the entangled state of the whole system can also be measured by protective
measurement in principle (Anandan 1993). The method is by adding appropriate protection
procedure to the whole system so that its entangled state is a nondegenerate eigenstate of
the total Hamiltonian of the system together with the added potential. Then the entangled
state can be protectively measured. On the other hand, environment-induced decoherence
is not an essential element of the many-worlds interpretation. Even when a measuring
device is isolated from environment (and the measured particle is absorbed by the device),
the interpretation also requires that each branch of the wave function of the measuring
device in which there is a definite measurement result corresponds to each world among the
many worlds; otherwise the many-worlds interpretation will not give the same predictions of
measurement results as standard quantum mechanics (so long as the latter gives unambiguous
predictions).
Thirdly, the above argument does not require protective measurement to be able to
distinguish the superposed wave function of a measuring device (in each branch of which
there is a definite measurement result) from one of its branches, or whether the superposed
wave function collapses or not during a conventional impulse measurement. Since the deter-
mination demands the distinguishability of two non-orthogonal states, which is prohibited
by quantum mechanics, no measurements consistent with the theory including protective
measurement can do this. What protective measurement tells us is that such a superposed
wave function, which existence is assumed by the many-worlds interpretation, does not cor-
respond to the many worlds defined by the many-worlds interpretation. In other words,
protective measurement reveals inconsistency of the many-worlds interpretation. Lastly, we
12
Note that protective measurement in general requires that the measured wave function is known before-
hand so that an appropriate protective interaction can be added. But this requirement does not influence our
argument, as the superposed wave function of a measuring device can be prepared in a known form before
the protective measurement.
13
This objection does not apply to the de Broglie-Bohm theory, according to which the wave function of a
measuring device does not collapse either, but it exists only in one world.
53
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
stress again that the principle of protective measurement is irrelevant to the controversial
process of wavefunction collapse and only depends on the linear Schrödinger evolution and
the Born rule. As a result, protective measurement can be used to examine the internal
consistency of the no-collapse solutions to the measurement problem, e.g. the many-worlds
interpretation, before experiments give the last verdict.
In the following, we will further show that the existence of many worlds is not consistent
with the picture of random discontinuous motion of particles either. In order to examine the
many-worlds interpretation, it is necessary to know exactly what a quantum superposition is.
No matter how to define the many worlds, they correspond to some branches of a quantum
superposition after all (e.g. the branches where measuring devices obtain definite results,
and in particular, observers have definite conscious experience). According to the picture of
random discontinuous motion of particles, a quantum superposition exists in a form of time
division. For a superposition of two positions A and B of a quantum system (e.g. the pointer
of a measuring device), the system randomly and discontinuously jumps between these two
positions. At some random and discontinuous instants the system is in position A, and at
other instants it is in position B. In this picture of quantum superposition, it is obvious that
there is only one system all along, which randomly and discontinuously moves throughout all
branches of the superposition, no matter the system is a microscopic particle or a measuring
device or an observer. In other words, there is only one world whose instantaneous state is
constantly changing in a random and discontinuous way.
This conclusion is also supported by a comparison between discontinuous motion and
continuous motion. For a quantum particle undergoing discontinuous motion, the position
of the particle changes discontinuously. For a classical particle, its position changes continu-
ously. There is no essential difference between these two kinds of changes. For both cases the
position of the particle is always definite at each instant, and the positions of the particle at
different instants may be different. Moreover, the discontinuous change, like the continuous
change, does not create the many worlds, because, among other reasons, the change happens
all the while but the creating process only happens once. Therefore, if there is only one
world in classical mechanics, then there is also one world in quantum mechanics according
to the picture of random discontinuous motion of particles, no matter how the many worlds
are precisely defined.
We have argued that there are no many (physical) worlds as claimed by the many-worlds
interpretation, and in particular, even if the physical state or brain state of an observer is in
a quantum superposition, there is still one physical observer. However, the argument does
not exclude the variants of the many-worlds interpretation that assume a distinct dynamics
for the evolution of an observer’s mental state, e.g. the many-minds theory (Albert and
Loewer 1988)14 . For example, although the superposed brain state of an observer does not
correspond to many physical observers, each of which has a definite measurement record, it
may correspond to many minds of a unique observer, each of which has the experience of
a definite measurement record, as assumed by the many-minds theory. Since what we can
immediately access is not the position of the pointer of a measuring device, but our immediate
conscious experience, it is indeed necessary to analyze the conscious experience of an observer
during a conventional impulse measurement. In the final analysis, the measurement problem
is the problem of explaining the apparent incompatibility of our determinate experience and
14
According to these theories, the physical state always evolves in a deterministic way and may be super-
posed and indefinite, while the mental state is always definite but evolves randomly. In some sense, these
theories can be regarded as hidden-variable theories like the de Broglie-Bohm theory. The latter assumes
the definite positions of Bohmian particles provide observers with definite measurement records, while the
former assumes the definite mental states of the observers, though which are non-physical parameters, directly
provide observers with definite measurement records.
54
4.1. THE REALITY OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
55
4.2. A CONJECTURE ON THE ORIGIN OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
(Ghirardi, Grassi and Benatti 1995; Ghirardi 1997, 2008; Allori et al 2008), is inconsistent
with the results of protective measurement and the picture of random discontinuous motion
of particles. For example, the existence of the effective mass and charge density of a quan-
tum system already excludes the mass density ontology, which claims that the mass density
is real (Ghirardi 2008). In addition, the existing dynamical collapse theories are still phe-
nomenological models, and they are also plagued by some serious problems such as energy
non-conservation etc (Pearle 2007, 2009). In particular, the physical origin of the wavefunc-
tion collapse, including the origin of the randomness of the collapse process, is still unknown,
though there are already some interesting conjectures (see, e.g. Diósi 1989; Penrose 1996).
In the subsequent sections, we will try to solve these problems and propose a new dynamical
collapse model in terms of the random discontinuous motion of particles. A more detailed
review of the existing dynamical collapse theories will be given in the last section.
56
4.2. A CONJECTURE ON THE ORIGIN OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
its stays at other instants in any direct way. Then the random stays of the particle can only
manifest themselves in the equation of motion by their influences on the evolution of the wave
function18 . This forms a feedback in some sense; the wave function of a particle determines
the probabilities of its stays in certain position, momentum and energy, while its random
stay at each instant also influences the evolution of the wave function in a stochastic way19 .
However, the existence of the stochastic influences on the evolution of the wave function
relies on an important precondition: the discreteness of time. If time is continuous and
instants are durationless, the random stays of a particle can have no stochastic influence
on anything. The reason is as follows. First, the duration of each random stay of the
particle is zero in continuous time. Due to the randomness of motion, when there are at
least two possible instantaneous states a particle can move between, the particle cannot stay
in the same instantaneous state throughout a finite time. For the joint probability of the
particle being in the same instantaneous state for all infinitely uncountable instants in the
finite time interval is obviously zero, and the total probability of the particle being in other
instantaneous states is not zero at any instant in between either. In other words, in order
that a particle stays in the same instantaneous state for a finite time, the probability of
the particle being in this instantaneous state must be one all the while during the entire
interval. This is possible only for the banal case where there is only one instantaneous state
the particle can stay and thus there is no motion and its randomness at all throughout the
duration20 .
Secondly, the influence of the random stay of a particle at a durationless instant is zero.
This can be readily understood. If a physical influence is not zero at each durationless instant,
then it may accumulate to infinite during an arbitrarily short time interval, which should
be avoided in physics. Lastly, the accumulated influence of the random stays during a finite
time interval, even if it can be finite21 , contains no randomness. For the discontinuity and
randomness of motion exist only at each durationless instant, during which the influence
of the random stay is zero, and they don’t exist during a finite time interval or even an
infinitesimal time interval. For example, the state of random discontinuous motion in real
space, which is defined during an infinitesimal time interval at a given instant, is described
by the position density and position flux density, and they are continuous quantities that
contain no discontinuity and randomness.
Therefore, if time is continuous and instants are durationless, then the random stays of a
particle can have no stochastic effects. This also means that the random stays of a particle
can influence the evolution of its wave function in a stochastic way only when instants are not
zero-sized but finite-sized, i.e., when time is discrete or quantized. Once the duration of each
random stay of a particle is finite, each random stay can have a finite stochastic influence
on the evolution of the wave function. It is worth stressing again that if time is not discrete
but continuous, a particle cannot stay in one of the infinitely many instantaneous states
all through for a finite time; rather, it can only stay there for one zero-sized instant. By
contrast, if time is discrete and instants are not zero-sized but finite-sized, even if a particle
18
In fact, since the random stays of a particle as one part of its instantaneous state are completely random,
the complete evolution equation of the instantaneous state of the particle is only about the evolution of the
wave function. Therefore, the random stays of the particle can only manifest themselves in the complete
equation of motion by their stochastic influences on the evolution of the wave function.
19
In other words, the wave function of a particle determines its random discontinuous motion, while the
motion also influences the evolution of the wave function reciprocally.
20
Unfortunately, this banal case does not exist. Due to the uncertainty relation between position and
momentum in quantum mechanics, there are always infinitely many different instantaneous states (with
definite position and momentum) where a particle can stay at any time.
21
Our analysis of a concrete model in the next section will show that under some reasonable assumptions the
accumulated influence of the random stays during a finite time interval is still zero when time is continuous.
57
4.2. A CONJECTURE ON THE ORIGIN OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
stays in an instantaneous state only for one instant, the duration of its stay is also finite as
the instant is finite-sized. In some sense, the discreteness of time prevents a particle from
jumping from its present instantaneous state to another instantaneous state and makes the
particle stay in the present instantaneous state all through during each finite-sized instant22 .
Since it has been conjectured that the Planck scale is the minimum spacetime scale23 , we
will assume that the size of each discrete instant or the quantum of time is the Planck time
in our following analysis24 .
To sum up, the realization of the randomness and discontinuity of motion in the laws
of motion requires that time is discrete. In discrete time, a particle randomly stays in an
instantaneous state with definite position, momentum and energy at each discrete instant,
with a probability determined by the modulus square of its wave function at the instant.
Each random, finite stay of the particle may have a finite influence on the evolution of its wave
function. As we will show in the next section, the accumulation of such discrete and random
influences may lead to the correct collapse of the wave function, which can then explain the
emergence of definite measurement results. Accordingly, the evolution of the wave function
will be governed by a revised Schrödinger equation, which includes the normal linear terms
and a stochastic nonlinear term that describes the discrete collapse dynamics. Note that
the wave function (as an instantaneous property of particles) also exists in the discrete time,
which means that the wave function does not change during each discrete instant, and the
evolution of the wave function including the linear Schrödinger evolution is also discrete.
58
4.2. A CONJECTURE ON THE ORIGIN OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
be the energy eigenstates of the total Hamiltonian of a given system25 . In the following,
we will give a more detailed analysis of the consequences of this assumption. Its possible
physical basis will be investigated in the next subsection.
As we have argued in the last chapter, for a deterministic evolution of the wave function
such as the linear Schrödinger evolution, the requirement of energy conservation applies to a
single isolated system. However, for a stochastic evolution of the wave function such as the
dynamical collapse process, the requirement of energy conservation cannot apply to a single
system in general but only to an ensemble of identical systems26 . It can be proved that only
when the collapse states are energy eigenstates of the total Hamiltonian for each identical
system in an ensemble, can energy be conserved at the ensemble level for wavefunction
collapse (See Pearle 2000 for a more detailed analysis). Note that for the linear Schrödinger
evolution under an external potential, energy is conserved but momentum is not conserved
even at the ensemble level, and thus it is not momentum conservation but energy conservation
that is a more universal restriction for wavefunction collapse.
The conservation of energy can not only help to solve the preferred basis problem, but
also further determine the law of dynamical collapse to a large extent. For each system in
the same quantum state in an ensemble, in order that the probability distribution of energy
eigenvalues of the state can keep constant for the whole ensemble (i.e. energy is conserved
at the ensemble level), the random stay of the system at each discrete instant can only
change its (objective) energy probability distribution27 , and moreover, the change must also
satisfy a certain restriction. Concretely speaking, the random stay in a definite energy Ei
will increase the probability of the energy branch |Ei > and decrease the probabilities of all
other energy branches pro rata. Moreover, the increasing amplitude must be proportional to
the total probability of all other energy branches, and the coefficient is related to the energy
uncertainty of the state. We will demonstrate this result in the next subsection.
A more important problem is whether this energy-conserved collapse model can explain
the emergence of definite measurement results and our macroscopic experience. At first
sight the answer appears negative. For example, the energy eigenstates being collapse states
seems apparently inconsistent with the localization of macroscopic objects. However, a
detailed analysis given in the subsequent subsections will demonstrate that the model can
be consistent with existing experiments and our macroscopic experience. The key is to
realize that the energy uncertainty driving the collapse of the entangled state of a many-
body system is not the uncertainty of the total energy of all sub-systems, but the sum of
the absolute energy uncertainty of every sub-system. As a result, the collapse states are
the product states of the energy eigenstates of the Hamiltonian of each sub-system for a
non-interacting or weakly-interacting many-body system. This gives a further collapse rule
for the superpositions of degenerate energy eigenstates of a many-body system.
59
4.2. A CONJECTURE ON THE ORIGIN OF WAVEFUNCTION COLLAPSE
wave function represents the physical state of a single system, e.g. the state of random
discontinuous motion of particles. An ensemble is not an actual system after all, and the
conservation of something for an ensemble seems physically meaningless. Moreover, since a
single system in the ensemble does not ‘know’ the other systems and the whole ensemble,
there must exist some underlying mechanism that can ensure the conservation of energy
for an ensemble. Then the conservation of energy for an ensemble of identical systems is
probably a result of the laws of motion for individual systems in the ensemble. Here is
a possible scheme. First of all, energy is conserved for the evolution of individual energy
eigenstates. Next, a superposition of energy eigenstates will dynamically collapse to one of
these energy eigenstates, and the probability of the collapse result satisfies the Born rule.
Then the wavefunction collapse will satisfy the conservation of energy for an ensemble of
identical systems.
In the following, we will further suggest a possible physical basis for this scheme of energy-
conserved wavefunction collapse. According to the picture of random discontinuous motion,
for a particle in a superposition of energy eigenstates, the particle stays in an instantaneous
state with a definite energy eigenvalue at a discrete instant, and at another instant it may
jump to another instantaneous state with another energy eigenvalue. It seems to be a reason-
able assumption that the particle has both the tendency to jump among the instantaneous
states with different energies and the tendency to stay in the instantaneous states with the
same energy, and their relative strength is determined by the energy uncertainty of the parti-
cle. This is satisfactory in logic, as there should exist two opposite tendencies in general, and
their relative strength is determined by certain condition. In some sense, the two tendencies
of a particle are related to the two parts of its instantaneous state; the jumping tendency
is related to the wave function, and it is needed to manifest the superposition of different
energy eigenstates, while the staying tendency is related to the random stays. These two
opposite tendencies together constitute the complete “temperament” of a particle.
It can be argued that the tendency to stay in the same energy for individual particles
may be the physical origin of the energy-conserved wavefunction collapse. For a particle
in a superposition of energy eigenstates, the particle stays in an instantaneous state with
definite energy at a discrete instant, and the staying tendency of the particle will increase its
probability of being in the instantaneous states with the present energy at next instant. In
other words, the random stay of a particle in an instantaneous state with an energy eigenvalue
will increase the probability of the energy eigenvalue (and correspondingly decrease the
probabilities of other energy eigenvalues pro rata). Moreover, the increase of probability
may relate to the energy uncertainty of the particle. By the continuity of the change of
staying tendency, the particle will jump more readily among the instantaneous states with
small energy uncertainty and more hardly among the instantaneous states with large energy
uncertainty (which can also be regarded as a restriction of energy change). Thus the larger
the energy uncertainty of the superposition is, the larger the increase of probability is during
each random stay. A detailed calculation, which will be given in the next section, shows
that such a random change of energy probability distribution can continuously accumulate
to lead to the collapse of the superposition of energy eigenstates to one of them.
It can be further argued that the probability distribution of energy eigenvalues should
remain constant during the random evolution of an ensemble of identical systems, and thus
the resulting wavefunction collapse will satisfy the Born rule. The reason is as follows. When
an initial superposition of energy eigenstates undergoes the dynamical collapse process, the
probability distribution of energy eigenvalues should manifest itself through the collapse
results for an ensemble of identical systems. At a deeper level, it is very likely that the
laws of nature permit nature to manifest itself, or else we will be unable to find the laws of
nature and verify them by experiments, and our scientific investigations will be also pointless.
60
4.3. A DISCRETE MODEL OF ENERGY-CONSERVED WAVEFUNCTION
COLLAPSE
This may be regarded as a meta-law. Since the collapse evolution of individual systems is
completely random and irreversible, the diagonal density matrix elements for an ensemble
of identical systems must be precisely the same as the initial probability distribution at
every step of the evolution. Otherwise the frequency distribution of the collapse results
in the ensemble cannot reflect the initial probability distribution, or in other words, the
probability information contained in the initial state will be completely lost due to the
random and irreversible wavefunction collapse28 . As a consequence, the collapse evolution
will conserve energy at the ensemble level, and the collapse results will also satisfy the Born
rule in quantum mechanics.
Certainly, there is still a question that needs to be answered. Why energy? Why not
position or momentum? If there is only one property that undergoes the random discon-
tinuous motion (e.g. position), then the above tendency argument for the unique property
may be satisfying. But if there are many properties that undergoes the random discontin-
uous motion, then we need to answer why the tendency argument applies only to energy.
A possible answer is that energy is the property that determines the linear evolution of the
state of motion, and thus it seems natural and uniform that energy also determines the
nonlinear collapse evolution. Moreover, energy eigenstates are the states of motion that no
longer evolve (except an absolute phase) for the linear evolution. Then by analogy, it is likely
that energy eigenstates are also the states that no longer evolve for the nonlinear collapse
evolution, i.e., that energy eigenstates are the collapse states. However, we may never be
able to reach (and know we reach) the end point of explanation. Another important task is
to develop a concrete model and compare it with experiments. We do this in the subsequent
sections.
where |Ei i is the energy eigenstate of the Hamiltonian of the system, P Ei is the corresponding
energy eigenvalue, and ci (0) satisfies the normalization relation m |c
i=1 i (0)| 2 = 1.
61
4.3. A DISCRETE MODEL OF ENERGY-CONSERVED WAVEFUNCTION
COLLAPSE
during a finite time interval much larger than tP , the probability of each branch will undergo
a discrete and stochastic evolution. In the end, the probability of one branch will be close to
one, and the probabilities of other branches will be close to zero. In other words, the initial
superposition will randomly collapse to one of the energy branches in the superposition.
Now we will give a concrete analysis of this dynamical collapse process. Since the linear
Schrödinger evolution does not change the energy probability distribution, we may only
consider the influence of dynamical collapse on the energy probability distribution. Suppose
the system stays in branch |Ei i at the discrete instant t = ntP , and the stay changes the
probability of this branch, Pi (t), to
Pj (t)∆Pi
Pji (t + tP ) = Pj (t) − , (4.5)
1 − Pi (t)
where the superscript i still denotes the staying branch. The probability of this random
stay at the instant is p(Ei , t) = Pi (t). Then we can work out the diagonal density matrix
elements of the evolution31 :
m
p(Ej , t)Pij (t + tP )
X
ρii (t + tP ) =
j=1
X Pi (t)∆Pj (t)
= Pi (t)[Pi (t) + ∆Pi ] + Pj (t)[Pi (t) − ]
1 − Pj (t)
j6=i
X ∆Pj (t)
= ρii (t) + Pi (t)[∆Pi − Pj (t) ]. (4.6)
1 − Pj (t)
j6=i
Here we shall introduce the first rule of dynamical collapse, which says that the probabil-
ity distribution of energy eigenvalues for an ensemble of identical systems is constant during
the dynamical collapse process. As we have argued in the last subsection, this rule is required
by the principle of energy conservation at the ensemble level, and it may also have a physical
basis relating to the manifestability of nature. By this rule, we have ρii (t + tP ) = ρii (t) for
any i. This leads to the following set of equations:
X Pj (t)∆Pj (t)
∆P1 (t) − = 0,
1 − Pj (t)
j6=1
X Pj (t)∆Pj (t)
∆P2 (t) − = 0,
1 − Pj (t)
j6=2
...
X Pj (t)∆Pj (t)
∆Pm (t) − = 0. (4.7)
1 − Pj (t)
j6=m
30
One can also obtain this result by first increasing the probability of the staying branch and then normal-
Pj (t)
izing the probabilities of all branches. This means that Pi (t + tP ) = Pi1+∆(t)+∆
and Pj (t + tP ) = 1+∆ for any
∆ ∆
j 6= i. In this way, we have ∆Pi = 1+∆ (1 − Pi (t)) and ∆Pj = 1+∆ Pj (t) for any j 6= i.
31
The density matrix describes the ensemble of states which arise from all possible random stays.
62
4.3. A DISCRETE MODEL OF ENERGY-CONSERVED WAVEFUNCTION
COLLAPSE
By solving this equations set (e.g. by subtracting each other), we find the following relation
for any i:
∆Pi
= k, (4.8)
1 − Pi (t)
where k is an undetermined dimensionless quantity that relates to the state |ψ(t)i.
By using Eq. (4.8), we can further work out the non-diagonal density matrix elements of
the evolution. But it is more convenient to calculate the following variant of non-diagonal
density matrix elements:
m
X
ρij (t + tP ) = p(El , t)Pil (t + tP )Pjl (t + tP )
l=1
X
= Pl (t)[Pi (t) − kPi (t)][Pj (t) − kPj (t)]
l6=i,j
+Pi (t)[Pi (t) + k(1 − Pi (t))][Pj (t) − kPj (t)]
+Pj (t)[Pj (t) + k(1 − Pj (t))][Pi (t) − kPi (t)]
= (1 − k 2 )ρij (t). (4.9)
Since the usual collapse time, τc , is defined by the relation ρij (τc ) = 21 ρij (0), we may use a
proper approximation, where k is assumed to be the same as its initial value during the time
interval [0, τc ], to simplify the calculation of the collapse time. Then we have:
63
4.3. A DISCRETE MODEL OF ENERGY-CONSERVED WAVEFUNCTION
COLLAPSE
Since k is invariant under the swap of any two branches (Pi , Ei ) and (Pj , Ej ) according to
Eq. (4.8), the most natural definition of the energy uncertainty of a superposition of energy
eigenstates is32 :
m
1 X
∆E = Pi Pj |Ei − Ej |. (4.12)
2
i,j=1
∆E = P1 P2 |E1 − E2 |. (4.13)
It seems a little counterintuitive that k contains the energy uncertainty term that relates
to the whole energy distribution. The puzzle is two-fold. First, this means that the increase
of the probability of the staying branch relates not to the energy difference between the
staying branch and all other branches, but to the energy uncertainty of the whole state.
This is reflected in the formula of ∆E in the existence of the energy difference between
any two branches, |Ei − Ej | for any i and j. Next, the increase of the probability of the
staying branch relates also to the energy probability distribution that determines the energy
uncertainty. This is reflected in the formula of ∆E in the existence of Pi Pj . In fact, these
seemingly puzzling aspects are still understandable. The first feature is required by the first
rule of dynamical collapse that ensures energy conservation at the ensemble level. This can
be clearly seen from Eq. (4.8). If the increase of the probability of the staying branch relates
to the difference between the energy of the staying branch and the average energy of all other
branches, then Eq. (4.8) will not hold true because the swap symmetry of k will be violated,
and as a result, the first rule of dynamical collapse will be broken. The second feature can
be understood as follows. In the picture of random discontinuous motion, the probability
distribution contains the information of staying time distribution. An energy branch with
small probability means that the system jumps through it less frequently. Thus this energy
branch only makes a small contribution to the restriction of energy change or the increase of
the staying tendency. As a result, the increase of the probability of the staying branch and
k will relate not only to energy difference, but also to the energy probability distribution.
Then after omitting a coefficient in the order of unity, we can get the formula of k in the
first order:
~EP
τc ≈ , (4.15)
(∆E)2
where EP = h/tP is the Planck energy, and ∆E is the energy uncertainty of the initial
state33 .
Here it is worth pointing out that k must contain the first order term of ∆E. For
the second order or higher order term of ∆E will lead to much longer collapse time for
some common measurement situations, which contradicts experiments (Gao 2006a, 2006b).
Besides, a similar analysis of the consistency with experiments may also provide a further
32
Note that the common RMS (mean square root) uncertainty also satisfies the swap symmetry. Thus it
still needs to be studied what the exact form of k is.
33
This collapse time formula indicates that there is no wavefunction collapse in continuous time because
tP → 0 leads to τc → ∞. A premise of this conclusion is that the influence of each random stay is proportional
to the duration of stay.
64
4.3. A DISCRETE MODEL OF ENERGY-CONSERVED WAVEFUNCTION
COLLAPSE
support for the energy-conserved collapse model in which the collapse states are energy
eigenstates. First of all, if the collapse states are not energy eigenstates but momentum
eigenstates, then the energy uncertainty will be replaced by momentum uncertainty in the
~EP
collapse time formula Eq. (4.15), namely τc ≈ (∆pc) 2 . As a result, the collapse time will
be too short to be consistent with experiments for some situations. For example, for the
ground state of hydrogen atom the collapse time will be about several days. Note that the
second order or higher order term of ∆p will also lead to much longer collapse time for some
common measurement situations, which contradicts experiments.
Next, if the collapse states are position eigenstates34 , then the collapse time formula
l2 tP
Eq. (4.15) will be replaced by something like τc ≈ (∆x) 2 , where l is certain length scale
relating to the collapsing state. No matter what length scale l is, the collapse time of a
momentum eigenstate will be zero as its position uncertainty is infinite. This means that
the momentum eigenstates of any quantum system will collapse instantaneously to one of
its position eigenstates and thus cannot exist. Moreover, the superposition states with very
small momentum uncertainty will also collapse very quickly even for microscopic particles.
These results are apparently inconsistent with quantum mechanics. Although it may be
possible to adjust the length scale l to make the model consistent with existing experience,
the collapse time formula will be much more complex than that in the above energy-conserved
collapse model. Let’s give a little more detailed analysis here. There are two universal
length scales for a quantum system: its Compton wavelength λc and the Planck length lP .
It is obvious that both of them cannot be directly used as the length scale in the collapse
l2 tP
time formula τc ≈ (∆x) 2 . Then the formula can only be written in a more complex form:
2
λc tP
τc ≈ ( λlPc )α · (∆x)2 . Moreover, experiments such as the SQUID experiments and our everyday
macroscopic experience require α ≈ 8. It seems very difficult to explain this unusually large
exponent in theory. To sum up, the collapse states can hardly be position eigenstates when
considering the consistency with experiments and the simplicity of theory.
Based on the above analysis, the state of the multi-level system at instant t = ntP will
be:
m
X
|ψ(t)i = ci (t)e−iEi t/~ |Ei i, (4.16)
i=1
Besides the linear Schrödinger evolution, the collapse dynamics adds a discrete stochastic
evolution for Pi (t) ≡ |ci (t)|2 :
∆E
Pi (t + tP ) = Pi (t) + [δEs Ei − Pi (t)], (4.17)
EP
where ∆E is the energy uncertainty of the state at instant t defined by Eq. (4.12), Es is a
random variable representing the random stay of the system, and its probability of assuming
Ei at instant t is Pi (t). When Es = Ei , δEs Ei = 1, and when Es 6= Ei , δEs Ei = 0.
This equation of dynamical collapse can be directly extended to the entangled states of
a many-body system. The difference only lies in the definition of the energy uncertainty
∆E. As noted in the last subsection, for a non-interacting or weakly-interacting many-
body system in an entangled state, for which the energy uncertainty of each sub-system can
be properly defined, ∆E is the sum of the absolute energy uncertainty of all sub-systems,
namely
34
In continuous space and time, a position eigenstate has infinite average energy and cannot be physically
real. But in discrete space and time, position eigenstates will be the states whose spatial dimension is about
the Planck length, and they may exist.
65
4.3. A DISCRETE MODEL OF ENERGY-CONSERVED WAVEFUNCTION
COLLAPSE
n m
1XX
∆E = Pi Pj |Eli − Elj |, (4.18)
2
l=1 i,j=1
where n is the total number of the entangled sub-systems, m is the total number of energy
branches in the entangled state, and Eli is the energy of sub-system l in the i -th energy
branch of the state. Correspondingly, the collapse states are the product states of the energy
eigenstates of the Hamiltonian of each sub-system. It should be stressed here that ∆E is
not defined as the uncertainty of the total energy of all sub-systems as in the energy-driven
collapse models (see, e.g. Percival 1995, 1998a; Hughston 1996). For each sub-system has its
own energy uncertainty that drives its collapse, and the total driving “force” for the whole
entangled state should be the sum of the driving “forces” of all sub-systems, at least in
the first order approximation. Although these two kinds of energy uncertainty are equal in
numerical values in some cases (e.g. for a strongly-interacting many-body system), there are
also some cases where they are not equal. For example, for a superposition of degenerate
energy eigenstates of a non-interacting many-body system, which may arise during a common
measurement process, the uncertainty of the total energy of all sub-systems is exactly zero,
but the absolute energy uncertainty of each sub-system and their sum may be not zero. As
a result, the superpositions of degenerate energy eigenstates of a many-particle system may
also collapse. As we will see later, this is an important feature of our model, which can avoid
Pearle’s (2004) serious objections to the energy-driven collapse models.
It can be seen that the equation of dynamical collapse, Eq.(4.17), has an interesting
property, scale invariance. After one discrete instant tP , the probability increase of the
staying branch |Ei i is ∆Pi = ∆E EP (1 − Pi ), and the probability decrease of the neighboring
∆E
branch |Ei+1 i is ∆Pi+1 = EP Pi+1 . Then the probability increase of these two branches is
∆E
∆(Pi + Pi+1 ) = [1 − (Pi + Pi+1 )]. (4.19)
EP
Similarly, the equation ∆P = ∆E EP (1 − P ) holds true for the total probability of arbitrarily
many branches (one of which is the staying branch). This property of scale invariance may
simplify the analysis in many cases. For instance, for a superposition of two wavepackets
with energy difference, ∆E12 , much larger than the energy uncertainty of each wavepacket,
∆E1 = ∆E2 , we can calculate the collapse dynamics in two steps. First, we use Eq.(4.17)
and Eq.(4.13) with |E1 − E2 | = ∆E12 to calculate the time of the superposition collapsing
into one of the two wavepackets35 . Here we need not to consider the almost infinitely many
energy eigenstates constituting each wavepacket and their probability distribution. Next, we
use Eq.(4.17) with ∆E = ∆E1 to calculate the time of the wavepacket collapsing into one
of its energy eigenstates. In general, this collapse process is so slow that its effect can be
ignored.
Lastly, we want to stress another important point. As we have argued before, the dis-
continuity of motion requires that the collapse dynamics must be discrete in nature, and
moreover, the collapse states must be energy eigenstates in order that the collapse dynamics
satisfies the conservation of energy at the ensemble level. As a result, the energy eigenvalues
must be also discrete for any quantum system. This result seems to contradict quantum
mechanics, but when considering that our universe has a finite size (i.e. a finite event hori-
zon), the momentum and energy eigenvalues of any quantum system in the universe may be
35
Note that most collapse states in an ensemble of identical systems keep the shape of the wavepacket
almost precisely.
66
4.4. ON THE CONSISTENCY OF THE MODEL AND EXPERIMENTS
indeed discrete36 . The reason is that all quantum systems in the universe are limited by the
finite horizon, and thus no free quantum systems exist in the strict sense. For example, the
hc
energy of a massless particle (e.g. photon) can only assume discrete values En = n2 4R U
,
hc −33 25
and the minimum energy is E1 = 4RU ≈ 10 eV , where RU ≈ 10 m is the radius of the
horizon of our universe37 . Besides, for a free particle with mass m0 , its energy also assumes
2
discrete values En = n2 32mh R2 . For instance, the minimum energy is E1 ≈ 10−72 eV for free
0 U
electrons, which is much smaller than the minimum energy of photons38 .
It is interesting to see whether this tiny discreteness of energy makes the collapse dy-
namics more abrupt. Suppose the energy uncertainty of a quantum state is ∆E ≈ 1eV , and
its energy ranges between
q the minimum energy E1 and 1eV . Then we can get the maximum
1eV
energy level lmax ≈ 10−33 eV
≈ 1016 . The probability of most energy eigenstates in the
superposition will be about P ≈ 10−16 . During each discrete instant tP , the probability
increase of the staying energy branch is ∆P ≈ ∆E −28 . This indicates that the
EP (1 − P ) ≈ 10
probability change during each random stay is still very tiny. Only when the energy uncer-
tainty is larger than 1023 eV or 10−5 EP , will the probability change during each random stay
be sharp. Therefore, the collapse evolution is still very smooth for the quantum states with
energy uncertainty much smaller than the Planck energy.
67
4.4. ON THE CONSISTENCY OF THE MODEL AND EXPERIMENTS
supercurrents are observed. In the experiment, each circulating current corresponds to the
collective motion of about 109 Cooper pairs, and the energy uncertainty is about 8.6×10−6 eV .
Eq. (4.15) predicts a collapse time of 1023 s, and thus maintenance of coherence is expected
despite the macroscopic structure of the state39 . For more examples see Adler (2002).
68
4.4. ON THE CONSISTENCY OF THE MODEL AND EXPERIMENTS
is wholly absorbed by the electron in the local atom interacting with the photon. This
is clearly indicated by the term δ(Ef − Ei − ~ω) in the transition rate of photoelectric
effect. The state of the ejecting electron is a (spherical) wavepacket moving outward from
the local atom, whose average direction and momentum distribution are determined by the
momentum and polarization of the photon. The small energy uncertainty of the photon will
also be transferred to the ejecting electron41 .
This microscopic effect of ejecting electron is then amplified (e.g. by an avalanche process
of atoms) to form a macroscopic signal such as the shift of the pointer of a measuring device.
During the amplification process, the energy difference is constantly increasing between the
branch in which the photon is absorbed and the branch in which the photon is not absorbed
near each atom interacting with the photon. This large energy difference will soon lead to
the collapse of the whole superposition into one of the local branches, and thus the photon
is only detected locally. Take the single photon detector - avalanche photodiode as a typical
example42 . Its energy consumption is sharply peaked in a very short measuring interval.
One type of avalanche photodiode operates at 105 cps and has a mean power dissipation of
4mW (Gao 2006a). This corresponds to an energy consumption of about 2.5 × 1011 eV per
measuring interval 10−5 s. By using the collapse time formula Eq. (4.15), where the energy
uncertainty is ∆E ≈ 2.5 × 1011 eV , we find the collapse time is τc ≈ 1.25 × 10−10 s. This
collapse time is much smaller than the measuring interval.
One important point needs to be stressed here. Although a measured particle is detected
locally in a detector (e.g. the spatial size of its collapse state is in the order of the size of
an atom), its wave function does not necessarily undergo the position collapse as assumed
by standard quantum mechanics in an ideal position measurement, and especially, energy
can be conserved during the localization process according to our model. The reason can
be summarized as follows. The wave function of the measured particle is usually a spherical
wave (e.g. a spherically symmetric wave function) in three-dimensional space. Its momentum
is along the radial direction, but the local and random measurement result distributes along
the sphere, perpendicular to the radial direction. During the detection, the measured particle
interacts with a single atom of the detector by an ionizing process in each local branch of
the entangled state of the whole system including the particle and the atoms in the detector.
The particle is usually absorbed by the atom or bound in the atom, and its energy is wholly
transferred to the newly-formed atom and the ejecting electrons during the ionizing process
in each branch. Then the amplification process such as an avalanche process of atoms
41
In more general measurement situations, the measured particle (e.g. electron) is not annihilated by the
detector. However, in each local branch of the entangled state of the whole system, the particle also interacts
with a single atom of the detector by an ionizing process, and its total energy is also wholly transferred to
the atom and the ejecting electrons.
42
We take the widely-used Geiger counter as another illustration of the amplification process during mea-
surement. A Geiger counter is an instrument used to detect particles such as α particles, β particles and γ
rays etc. It consists of a glass envelope containing a low-pressure gas (usually a mixture of methane with
argon and neon) and two electrodes, with a cylindrical mesh being the cathode and a fine-wire anode running
through the centre of the tube. A potential difference of about 103 V relative to the tube is maintained between
the electrodes, therefore creating a strong electric field near the wire. The counter works on the mechanism
of gas multiplication. Ionization in the gas is caused by the entry of a particle. The ions are attracted to
their appropriate electrode, and they gain sufficient energy to eject electrons from the gas atoms as they pass
through the gas. This further causes the atoms to ionize. Therefore, electrons are produced continuously by
this process and rapid gas multiplication takes place (especially in the central electrode because of its strong
electric field strength). Its effect is that more than 106 electrons are collected by the central electrode for every
ion produced in the primary absorption process. These “electron avalanches” create electric pulses which then
can be amplified electronically and counted by a meter to calculate the number of initial ionization events.
In this way, a Geiger counter can detect low-energy radiation because even one ionized particle produces a
full pulse on the central wire. It can be estimated that the introduced energy difference during a detection is
∆E ≈ 109 eV , and the corresponding collapse time is τc ≈ 10−5 s according to our collapse model.
69
4.4. ON THE CONSISTENCY OF THE MODEL AND EXPERIMENTS
introduces very large energy difference between the detected branch and the empty branch,
and as a result, the whole superposition will soon collapse into one of its local branches in
a random way according to the energy-conserved collapse model43 . After the collapse, the
state of the measured particle is localized in the spatial region of one atom. Moreover, since
all local branches of the entangled state of the particle and the detector have the same energy
spectrum, the collapse process also conserves energy at the individual level.
70
4.4. ON THE CONSISTENCY OF THE MODEL AND EXPERIMENTS
Let’s see whether the energy-conserved collapse in our model can prevent the above
spreading of the wave packet. Suppose the dust particle is in a superposition of two identical
localized states that are separated by 10−5 cm in space. The particle floats in the air, and
its average velocity is about zero. At standard temperature and pressure, one nitrogen
molecule accretes in the dust particle, which area is 10−10 cm2 , during a time interval of
10−14 s in average (Adler 2002). Since the mass of the dust particle is much larger than the
mass of a nitrogen molecule, the velocity change of the particle is negligible when compared
with the velocity change of the nitrogen molecules during the process of accretion. Then
the kinetic energy difference between an accreted molecule and a freely moving molecule
is about ∆E = 23 kT ≈ 10−2 eV . When one nitrogen molecule accretes in one localized
branch of the dust particle (the molecule is freely moving in the other localized branch), it
will increase the energy uncertainty of the total entangled state by ∆E ≈ 10−2 eV . Then
after a time interval of 10−4 s, the number of accreted nitrogen molecules is about 1010 ,
and the total energy uncertainty is about 108 eV . According to Eq. (4.15) in our collapse
model, the corresponding collapse time is about 10−4 s. Since the two localized states in the
superposition have the same energy spectra, the collapse also conserves energy.
In the energy-conserved collapse model, the collapse states are energy eigenstates, and
in particular, they are nonlocal momentum eigenstates for free quantum systems. Thus it is
indeed counterintuitive that the energy-conserved collapse can make the states of macroscopic
objects local. As shown above, this is due to the constant influences of environmental
particles. When the spreading of the state of a macroscopic object becomes larger, its
interaction with environmental particles will introduce larger energy difference between its
different local branches, and this will then collapse the spreading state again into a more
localized state45 . As a result, the states of macroscopic objects in an environment will
never reach the collapse states, namely momentum eigenstates, though they do continuously
undergo the energy-conserved collapse. To sum up, there are two opposite processes for a
macroscopic object constantly interacting with environmental particles. One is the spreading
process due to the linear Schrödinger evolution, and the other is the localization process due
to the energy-conserved collapse evolution. The interactions with environmental particles not
only make the spreading more rapidly but also make the localization more frequently. In the
end these two processes will reach an approximate equilibrium. The state of a macroscopic
object will be a wave packet narrow in both position and momentum, and this narrow wave
packet will follow approximately Newtonian trajectories (if the external potential is uniform
enough along the width of the packet) by Ehrenfest’s theorem (see Bacciagaluppi 2008 for
an insightful analysis in the context of decoherence)46 . In some sense, the emergence of
the classical world around us is “conspired” by environmental particles according to the
energy-conserved collapse model.
Ultimately, the energy-conserved collapse model should be able to account for our defi-
45
It is interesting to note that the state of a macroscopic object can also be localized by the linear
Schrödinger evolution via interactions with environment, e.g. by absorbing an environmental particle with
certain energy uncertainty. For example, if a macroscopic object absorbs a photon (emitted from an atom)
with momentum uncertainty of ∆p ≈ 10−6 eV /c, the center-of-mass state of the object, even if being a mo-
mentum eigenstate initially, will have the same momentum uncertainty by the linear Schrödinger evolution,
and thus it will become a localized wavepacket with width about 0.1m. Note that there is no vicious circle
here. The energy spreading state of a microscopic particle can be generated by an external potential (e.g.
an electromagnetic potential in general) via the linear Schrödinger evolution, and especially they don’t nec-
essarily depend on the localization of macroscopic objects such as measuring devices. Thus we can use the
existence of these states to explain the localization of macroscopic objects.
46
When assuming the energy uncertainty of an object is in the same order of its thermal energy fluctuation,
we can estimate the rough size of its wavepacket. For instance, for a dust particle of mass m = 10−7 g, its
root mean square energy fluctuation is about 103 eV at room temperature T = 300K (Adler 2002), and thus
the width of its wavepacket is about 10−10 m.
71
4.5. CRITICAL COMMENTS ON OTHER DYNAMICAL COLLAPSE MODELS
~EP 2.8M eV 2
τc ≈ 2
≈( ) ≈ 105 s, (4.22)
(∆E) 0.01M eV
where the Planck energy EP ≈ 1019 GeV . When considering the number of neurons that can
form a definite conscious perception is usually in the order of 107 , the collapse time of the
quantum superposition of two different conscious perceptions will be
2.8M eV 2
τc ≈ ( ) ≈ 10−9 s. (4.23)
100GeV
Since the normal conscious time of a human being is in the order of several hundred mil-
liseconds, the collapse time is much shorter than the normal conscious time. Therefore, our
conscious perceptions are always definite according to the energy-conserved collapse model.
72
4.5. CRITICAL COMMENTS ON OTHER DYNAMICAL COLLAPSE MODELS
gravity-induced collapse conjecture can be traced back to Feynman (1995)49 . In his Lectures
on Gravitation, he considered the philosophical problems in quantizing macroscopic objects
and contemplates on a possible breakdown of quantum theory. He said, “I would like to
suggest that it is possible that quantum mechanics fails at large distances and for large
objects, it is not inconsistent with what we do know. If this failure of quantum mechanics is
connected with gravity, we might speculatively expect this to happen for masses such that
GM 2 /~c = 1, of M near 10−5 grams.”
Penrose (1996) further proposed a concrete gravity-induced collapse argument. The ar-
gument is based on a profound and fundamental conflict between the general covariance
principle of general relativity and the superposition principle of quantum mechanics. The
conflict can be clearly seen by considering the superposition state of a static mass distribu-
tion in two different locations, say position A and position B. On the one hand, according
to quantum mechanics, the valid definition of such a superposition requires the existence of
a definite space-time background, in which position A and position B can be distinguished.
On the other hand, according to general relativity, the space-time geometry, including the
distinguishability of position A and position B, cannot be predetermined, and must be dy-
namically determined by the position superposition state. Since the different position states
in the superposition determine different space-time geometries, the space-time geometry
determined by the whole superposition state is indefinite, and as a result, the superposi-
tion and its evolution cannot be consistently defined. In particular, the definition of the
time-translation operator for the superposed space-time geometries involves an inherent ill-
definedness, and this leads to an essential uncertainty in the energy of the superposed state.
Then by analogy Penrose argued that this superposition, like an unstable particle in usual
quantum mechanics, is also unstable, and it will decay or collapse into one of the two states
in the superposition after a finite lifetime. Furthermore, Penrose suggested that the essential
energy uncertainty in the Newtonian limit is proportional to the gravitational self-energy E∆
of the difference between the two mass distributions, and the collapse time, analogous to the
half-life of an unstable particle, is
T ≈ ~/E∆ (4.24)
This criterion is very close to that put forward by Diósi (1989) earlier, and it is usually called
the Diósi-Penrose criterion. Later, Penrose (1998) further suggested that the collapse states
are the stationary solutions of the Schrödinger-Newton equation.
Let’s now analyze Penrose’s argument. The crux of the matter is whether the conflict
between quantum mechanics and general relativity requires that a quantum superposition of
two space-time geometries must collapse after a finite time. We will argue in the following
that the answer is negative. First of all, although it is widely acknowledged that there exists
a fundamental conflict between the general covariance principle of general relativity and the
superposition principle of quantum mechanics, it is still a controversial issue what the exact
nature of the conflict is and how to solve it. For example, it is possible that the conflict
may be solved by reformulating quantum mechanics in a way that does not rely on a definite
spacetime background (see, e.g. Rovelli 2011).
Next, Penrose’s argument seems too weak to establish a necessary connection between
the conflict and wavefunction collapse. Even though there is an essential uncertainty in the
energy of the superposition of different space-time geometries, this kind of energy uncertainty
is different in nature from the energy uncertainty of unstable particles or unstable states
in usual quantum mechanics (Gao 2010). The former results from the ill-definedness of
49
It is interesting to note that Feynman considered this conjecture even earlier at the 1957 Chapel Hill
conference (see DeWitt and Rickles 2011, ch.22).
73
4.5. CRITICAL COMMENTS ON OTHER DYNAMICAL COLLAPSE MODELS
the time-translation operator for the superposed space-time geometries (though its nature
seems still unclear), while the latter exists in a definite spacetime background, and there is a
well-defined time-translation operator for the unstable states. Moreover, the decay of these
unstable states is a natural result of the linear Schrödinger evolution, and the process is not
random but deterministic. By contrast, the hypothetical spontaneous decay or collapse of
the superposed space-time geometries is nonlinear and random. In addition, the decay of
an unstable state (e.g. excited state of an atom) is actually not spontaneous but caused by
the background field constantly interacting with it. In some extreme situations, the state
may not decay at all when in a very special background field with bandgap (Yablonovitch
1987). In short, there exists no convincing analogy between a superposition of different
space-time geometries and an unstable state in usual quantum mechanics. Accordingly, one
cannot argue for the decay or collapse of the superposition of different space-time geometries
by this analogy. Although an unstable state in quantum mechanics may decay after a
very short time, this does not imply that a superposition of different space-time geometries
should also decay - and, again, sometimes an unstable state does not decay at all under
special circumstances. To sum up, Penrose’s argument by analogy only has a very limited
force, and especially, it is not strong enough to establish a necessary connection between
wavefunction collapse and the conflict between quantum mechanics and general relativity.
Thirdly, it can be further argued that the conflict does not necessarily lead to the wave-
function collapse. The key is to realize that the conflict also needs to be solved before
the wavefunction collapse finishes, and when the conflict has been solved, the wavefunc-
tion collapse will lose its basis relating to the conflict. As argued by Penrose, the quantum
superposition of different space-time geometries and its evolution are both ill-defined due
to the fundamental conflict between the general covariance principle of general relativity
and the superposition principle of quantum mechanics. The ill-definedness seems to require
that the superposition must collapse into one of the definite space-time geometries, which
has no problem of ill-definedness. However, the wavefunction collapse seems too late to
save the superposition from the “suffering” of the ill-definedness during the collapse. In
the final analysis, the conflict or the problem of ill-definedness needs to be solved before
defining a quantum superposition of different space-time geometries and its evolution. In
particular, the possible collapse evolution of the superposition also needs to be consistently
defined, which again indicates that the wavefunction collapse does not solve the problem
of ill-definedness. On the other hand, once the problem of ill-definedness is solved and a
consistent description obtained (however this is still an unsolved issue in quantum gravity),
the wavefunction collapse will completely lose its connection with the problem50 . Therefore,
contrary to Penrose’s expectation, it seems that the conflict between quantum mechanics
and general relativity does not entail the existence of wavefunction collapse.
Even though Penrose’s gravity-induced collapse argument is debatable, the wavefunction
collapse may still exist due to other reasons, and thus Penrose’s concrete suggestions for the
collapse time formula and collapse states also need to be further examined as some aspects
of a phenomenological model. First of all, let’s analyze Penrose’s collapse time formula Eq.
(4.24), according to which the collapse time of a superposition of two mass distributions is
50
Note that if the problem of ill-definedness cannot be solved in principle for the superpositions of very
different space-time geometries, then the wavefunction collapse may be relevant here. Concretely speaking,
if the superpositions of very different space-time geometries cannot be consistently defined in nature, then
it is very likely that these superpositions cannot exist, which means that they must have collapsed into
one of the definite space-time geometries before formed from the superpositions of minutely different space-
time geometries. In this case, the large difference of the space-time geometries in the superposition will
set a upper limit for wavefunction collapse. Though the limit may be loose, it does imply the existence of
wavefunction collapse. However, this possibility might be very small, as it seems that there is always some
kind of approximate sense in which two different spacetimes can be pointwise identified.
74
4.5. CRITICAL COMMENTS ON OTHER DYNAMICAL COLLAPSE MODELS
inversely proportional to the gravitational self-energy of the difference between the two mass
distributions. As we have argued above, the analogy between such a superposition and an
unstable state in quantum mechanics does not exist, and gravity does not necessarily induce
wavefunction collapse either. Thus this collapse time formula, which is based on a similar
application of Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle to unstable states, will lose its original phys-
ical basis. In particular, the appearance of the gravitational self-energy term in the formula
is in want of a reasonable explanation. In fact, it has already been shown that this gravita-
tional self-energy term does not represent the ill-definedness of time-translation operator (or
the fuzziness of the identification between two spacetimes) in the strictly Newtonian regime
(Christian 2001). In this regime, the time-translation operator can be well defined, but
the gravitational self-energy term is not zero. In addition, as Diósi (2007) pointed out, the
microscopic formulation of the collapse time formula is unclear and still has some problems
(e.g. the cut-off difficulty).
Next, let’s examine Penrose’s suggestion for the collapse states. According to Penrose
(1998), the collapse states are the stationary solutions of the Schrödinger-Newton equation,
namely Eq. (2.31). The equation describes the gravitational self-interaction of a single
quantum system, in which the mass density m|ψ(x, t)|2 is the source of the classical gravi-
tational potential. As we have argued in Chapter 2, although a quantum system has mass
density that is measurable by protective measurement, the density is not real but effective,
and it is formed by the ergodic motion of a localized particle with the total mass of the
system. Therefore, there does not exist a gravitational self-interaction of the mass density.
This conclusion can also be reached by another somewhat different argument. Since charge
always accompanies mass for a charged particle such as an electron51 , the existence of the
gravitational self-interaction, though which is too weak to be excluded by present experi-
ments, may further entail the existence of a remarkable electrostatic self-interaction of the
particle52 , which already contradicts experiments. This analysis poses a serious objection to
the Schrödinger-Newton equation and Penrose’s suggestion for the collapse states53 .
Lastly, we briefly discuss another two problems of Penrose’s collapse scheme. The first
one is the origin of the randomness of collapse results. Penrose did not consider this issue
in his collapse scheme. If the collapse is indeed spontaneous as implied by his gravity-
induced collapse argument, then the randomness cannot result from any external influences
such as an external noise field, and it can only come from the studied quantum system
and its wave function. The second problem is energy non-conservation. Although Penrose
did not give a concrete model of wavefunction collapse, his collapse scheme requires the
collapse of superpositions of different positions, while this kind of space collapse inevitably
violates energy conservation54 . Since the gravitational energy of a quantum system is usually
51
However, the concomitance of mass and charge in space for a charged particle does not necessarily
require that they must satisfy the same law of interaction. For example, the fact that electromagnetic fields
are quantized in nature does not necessarily imply that gravitational fields must be also quantized.
52
If there is a gravitational self-interaction but no electrostatic self-interaction for a charged particle, e.g.
an electron, then the charge and mass of an electron will be located in different positions and have different
density distributions in space, though they are described by the same wave function. Concretely speaking, the
mass density of an electron is me |ψ(x, t)|2 as in the Schrödinger-Newton equation, whereas its charge density
is not e|ψ(x, t)|2 but only localized in a single position (which permits no electrostatic self-interaction). This
result seems very unnatural and has no experimental support either.
53
Since the Schrödinger-Newton equation is the non-relativistic realization of the typical model of semi-
classical gravity, in which the source term in the classical Einstein equation is taken as the expectation of
the energy momentum operator in the quantum state (Rosenfeld 1963), our analysis also presents a serious
objection to the approach of semiclassical gravity. Although the existing arguments against the semiclassical
gravity models seem so strong, they are still not conclusive (Carlip 2008; Boughn 2009). This new analysis
of the Schrödinger-Newton equation may shed some new light on the solution of the issue.
54
Diósi (2007) explicitly pointed out that the von-Neumann-Newton equation, which may be regarded as one
realization of Penrose’s collapse scheme, obviously violates conservation of energy. Another way to understand
75
4.5. CRITICAL COMMENTS ON OTHER DYNAMICAL COLLAPSE MODELS
much smaller than the energy of the system, Penrose’s collapse scheme still violates energy
conservation even if the gravitational field is counted. As we have noted earlier, for an isolated
system only the collapse states are energy eigenstates can energy conserve (at the ensemble
level) during the collapse. If the principle of conservation of energy is indeed universal as
widely thought, then the spontaneous collapse models that violate energy conservation will
have been excluded. By contrast, although the interaction-induced collapse models such as
the CSL model also violate energy conservation in their present formulations, there is still
hope that when counting the energy of external noise field the total energy may be conserved
in these models (Pearle 2000; Bassi, Ippoliti and Vacchini 2005). Let’s turn to the CSL model
now.
76
4.5. CRITICAL COMMENTS ON OTHER DYNAMICAL COLLAPSE MODELS
77
4.5. CRITICAL COMMENTS ON OTHER DYNAMICAL COLLAPSE MODELS
lead to the decoherence of the wave function of a quantum system, but it seems that they
have no ability to cause the collapse of the wave function.
Lastly, we will briefly discuss another two problems of the CSL model. The first one
is the well-known problem of energy non-conservation. The collapse in the model narrows
the wave function in position space, thereby producing an increase of energy58 . A possible
solution is that the conservation laws may be satisfied when the contributions of the noise
field w(x, t) to the conserved quantities are taken into account. It has been shown that the
total mean energy can be conserved (Pearle 2004), and the energy increase can also be made
finite when further revising the coupling between the noise field and the studied quantum
system (Bassi, Ippoliti and Vacchini 2005). But a complete solution has not been found yet,
and it is still unknown whether such a solution indeed exists. The second problem is to make
a relativistic quantum field theory which describes collapse (Pearle 2009). Notwithstanding
a good deal of effort, a satisfactory theory has not been obtained at present (see Beding-
ham 2011 for a recent attempt). The main difficulty is that the hypothetical interaction
responsible for collapse will produce too many particles out of the vacuum, amounting to
infinite energy per sec per volume, in the relativistic extension of these interaction-induced
collapse models. Note that the spontaneous collapse models without collapse interaction
(e.g. the energy-conserved collapse model) don’t face this difficulty. We will discuss the
problem of compatibility between wavefunction collapse and the principle of relativity in the
next Chapter.
58
Note that with appropriate choice for the parameters in the CSL model, such a violation of energy
conservation is very tiny and hardly detectable by present day technology.
78
5
We have an apparent incompatibility, at the deepest level, between the two
fundamental pillars of contemporary theory ... It may be that a real synthesis
of quantum and relativity theories requires not just technical developments but
radical conceptual renewal.
— John Bell, 1986
In this chapter, we will briefly analyze random discontinuous motion of particles and its col-
lapse evolution in the relativistic domain1 . It is first shown that the Lorentz transformation
seriously distorts the picture of random discontinuous motion of particles, and the distortion
results from the relativity of simultaneity. We then argue that absolute simultaneity is not
only possible in the relativistic domain, but also necessitated by the existence of random
discontinuous motion of particles and its collapse evolution. This leads to the emergence of
a preferred Lorentz frame when combined with the requirement of the constancy of speed
of light. It is further shown that the collapse dynamics may provide a way to detect the
frame according to the energy-conserved collapse model. If quantum mechanics indeed de-
scribes random discontinuous motion of particles as protective measurement suggests, then
this analysis may be helpful for solving the problem of the incompatibility between quantum
mechanics and special relativity2 .
79
5.1. THE PICTURE OF MOTION DISTORTED BY THE LORENTZ
TRANSFORMATION
different in different inertial frames due to the Lorentz transformation. Let’s give a concrete
analysis.
Suppose a particle is in position x1 at instant t1 and in position x2 at instant t2 in an
inertial frame S. In another inertial frame S 0 with velocity v relative to S, the Lorentz
transformation leads to:
0 t1 − x1 v/c2
t1 = p , (5.1)
1 − v 2 /c2
0 t2 − x2 v/c2
t2 = p , (5.2)
1 − v 2 /c2
0 x1 − vt1
x1 = p , (5.3)
1 − v 2 /c2
0 x2 − vt2
x2 = p . (5.4)
1 − v 2 /c2
Since the jumping process of the particle is nonlocal, the two events (t1 , x1 ) and (t2 , x2 )
may readily satisfy the spacelike separation condition |x2 − x1 | > c|t2 − t1 |. Then we can
0 0
always select a possible velocity v < c that leads to t2 = t1 :
t2 − t1 2
v= c . (5.5)
x2 − x1
0 0
But obviously the two positions of the particle in frame S 0 , namely x1 and x2 , are not equal.
0 0
This means that in frame S 0 the particle will be in two different positions x1 and x2 at the
0
same time at instant t1 . In other words, it seems that there are two identical particles at
0
instant t1 in frame S 0 . Note that the velocity of S 0 relative to S may be much smaller than
the speed of light, and thus the appearance of the two-particle picture is irrelevant to the
high-energy processes described by relativistic quantum field theory, e.g. the creation and
annihilation of particles.
The above result shows that for any pair of events in frame S that satisfies the spacelike
separation condition, there always exists an inertial frame in which the two-particle picture
will appear. Since the jumping process of the particle in frame S is essentially random, it can
be expected that the two-particle picture will appear in the infinitely many inertial frames
with the same probability. Then during an arbitrary finite time interval, in each inertial
frame the measure of the instants at which there are two particles in appearance, which is
equal to the finite time interval divided by the total number of the frames that is infinite,
will be zero. Moreover, there may also exist situations where the particle is at arbitrarily
many positions at the same time at an instant in an inertial frame, though the measure
of these situations is also zero. Certainly, at nearly all instants whose measure is one, the
particle is still in one position at an instant in all inertial frames. Therefore, the many-
particle appearance of the random discontinuous motion of a particle cannot be measured
in principle.
However, for the random discontinuous motion of a particle, in any inertial frame different
from S, the Lorentz transformation will inevitably make the time order of the random stays
of the particle in S reversal and disorder, as the discontinuous motion of the particle is
nonlocal and most neighboring random stays are spacelike separated events. In other words,
the time order is not Lorentz invariant. Moreover, the set of the instants at which the time
order of the random stays of the particle is reversed has finite measure, which may be close
to one. As we will see below, this reversal and disorder of time order will lead to more
distorted pictures for quantum entanglement and wavefunction collapse.
80
5.1. THE PICTURE OF MOTION DISTORTED BY THE LORENTZ
TRANSFORMATION
81
5.1. THE PICTURE OF MOTION DISTORTED BY THE LORENTZ
TRANSFORMATION
correlation between the motion of the two particles in S can only keep half the time, and
the correlation will be reversed for another half of time, during which the two particles
√ will
√
be in state ψu ϕd or ψd ϕu at each instant. For a general entangled state aψu ϕu + bψd ϕd ,
the proportion of correlation-reversed time will be 2ab, and the proportion of correlation-
kept time will be a2 + b2 . Moreover, the instants at which the original correlation is kept
or reversed are discontinuous and random. This means that the synchronicity between the
jumps of the two particles is destroyed too.
To sum up, the above analysis indicates that the instantaneous correlation and syn-
chronicity between the motion of two entangled particles in one inertial frame is destroyed
in other frames due to the Lorentz transformation3 . As we will see below, however, this
distorted picture of quantum entanglement cannot be measured either.
82
5.1. THE PICTURE OF MOTION DISTORTED BY THE LORENTZ
TRANSFORMATION
t − x1 v/c2
t01 = p , (5.10)
1 − v 2 /c2
t − x2 v/c2
t02 = p . (5.11)
1 − v 2 /c2
It can be seen that x1 < x2 leads to t01 > t02 . Then during the period between t01 and t02 ,
the branch √12 ψ20 near position x02 already disappeared, but the branch √12 ψ10 near position
x01 has not changed to ψ10 . This means that at any instant between t01 and t02 , there is only
a non-normalized state √12 ψ10 . According to the picture of random discontinuous motion
of particles, for a particle in the state √12 ψ10 , the probability of the particle being in the
branch ψ10 is 1/2, and the particle is in the branch ψ10 or in the region near x1 only at some
discontinuous and random instants, whose total measure is 1/2. At other instants, whose
measure is also 1/2, the particle does not exist anywhere. In other words, at each instant the
particle either exists in a position near x1 or disappears in the whole space with the same
probability, 1/2. This result indicates that in the inertial frame S 0 , the particle only exists
half the time during the period between t01 and t02 . By contrast, the particle always exists in
certain position in space at any time in the inertial frame S.
Similarly, if the superposition state √12 ψ1 + √12 ψ2 collapses to the branch ψ2 near position
x2 at instant t in frame S, then in frame S 0 , during the period between t01 and t02 , the branch
√1 ψ 0 near position x0 already turns to ψ 0 , while the branch √1 ψ 0 near position x0 has not
2 2 2 2 2 1 1
disappeared and is still there. Therefore, there is only a non-normalized state √12 ψ10 + ψ20
at any instant between t01 and t02 . According to the picture of random discontinuous motion
of particles, this means that during the period between t01 and t02 , there is more than one
particle in S 0 : the first particle is in the branch ψ20 all the time, and the second identical
particle exists half the time in the branch ψ10 (and it exists nowhere in space for another half
of time).
However, although the state of the particle in S 0 is not normalized, the total probability
of detecting the particle in the whole space is still 1, not 1/2 or 3/2, in the frame6 . In
other words, although the collapse process is seriously distorted in S 0 , the distortion cannot
be measured. The reason is that in S 0 the collapse resulting from measurement happens
at different instants in different locations7 , and the superposition of the branches in these
locations and at these instants are always normalized. In the following, we will give a more
detailed explanation.
As noted above, in frame S 0 the collapse first happens at t02 for the branch √12 ψ20 near
position x02 , and then happens at t01 for the branch √1 ψ 0
2 1
near position x01 after a delay. If
we measure the branch √1 ψ 0 , then the resulting collapse will influence the other branch
2 2
|x1 −x2 |v/c2
√ ψ only after a delay of ∆t0 = √
1 0 , while if we measure the branch √12 ψ10 , then the
2 1 1−v 2 /c2
resulting collapse will influence the other branch √12 ψ20 in advance by the same time interval
∆t0 , and the influence is backward in time. Now suppose we make a measurement on the
branch √1 ψ 0 near position x02 and detect the particle there (i.e. the collapse state is ψ20 ).
2 2
during a very short time, which may be much shorter than the time of light propagating between x1 and x2 .
6
This does not contradict the usual Born rule, which only applies to the situations where collapse happens
simultaneously at different locations in space.
7
Concretely speaking, the time order of the collapses happening at different locations in S 0 is connected
with that in S by the Lorentz transformation.
83
5.2. ON THE ABSOLUTENESS OF SIMULTANEITY
Then before the other branch √12 ψ10 disappears, which happens after a delay of ∆t0 , we can
make a second measurement on this branch near position x01 . It seems that the probability
of detecting the particle there is not zero but 1/2, and thus the total probability of finding
the particle in the whole space is larger than one and it is possible that we can detect two
particles. However, this is not the case. Although the second measurement on the branch
√1 ψ 0 near position x0 is made later than the first measurement, it is the second measurement
2 1 1
that collapses the superposition state √1 ψ 0 + √1 ψ 0 to ψ20 near position x02 ; the local branch
2 1 2 2
√1 ψ 0 near position x01 disappears immediately after the measurement, while the influence
2 1
of the resulting collapse on the other branch √12 ψ20 near position x02 is backward in time and
happens before the first measurement on this branch. Therefore, the second measurement
near position x01 must obtain a null result, and why the first measurement detects the particle
near position x02 is because the superposition state already collapses to ψ20 near position x02
before the measurement due to the second measurement.
By a similar analysis, we can also demonstrate that the measurements on an entangled
state of two particles, e.g. ψu ϕu + ψd ϕd , can only obtain correlated results in every inertial
frame. If a measurement on particle 1 obtains the result u or d, indicating the state of the
particle collapses to the state ψu or ψd after the measurement, then a second measurement on
particle 2 can only obtain the result u or d, indicating the state of particle 2 collapses to the
state ϕu or ϕd after the measurement. Accordingly, although the instantaneous correlation
and synchronicity between the motion of two entangled particles is destroyed in all but one
inertial frame, the distorted picture of quantum entanglement cannot be measured.
84
5.2. ON THE ABSOLUTENESS OF SIMULTANEITY
respectively.
If adopting the standard synchrony convention, namely assuming the one-way speed of
light is isotropic and constant in every inertial frame, then k, k 0 = 0 and the Edwards-Winnie
transformation will reduce to the Lorentz transformation, which leads to the relativity of
simultaneity. Alternatively, one can also adopt the nonstandard synchrony convention that
makes simultaneity absolute. In order to do this, one may first synchronize the clocks at
different locations in an arbitrary inertial frame by Einstein’s standard synchrony, that is,
one assumes the one-way speed of light is isotropic in this frame, and then let the clocks in
other frames directly regulated by the clocks in this frame when they coincide in space. The
corresponding spacetime transformation can be derived as follows. Let S be the preferred
Lorentz frame in which the one-way speed of light is isotropic, namely let k = 0. Then we
get
β(k 2 − 1) + k − k 0 = 0. (5.15)
Thus the spacetime transformation that restores absolute simultaneity is:
1
x0 = p · (x − vt), (5.16)
1 − v 2 /c2
t0 = 1 − v 2 /c2 · t.
p
(5.17)
where x, t are the coordinates of the preferred Lorentz frame, x0 , t0 are the coordinates of
another inertial frame, and v is the velocity of this frame relative to the preferred frame.
c2
In this frame, the one-way speed of light along x0 and −x0 direction are cx0 = c−v and
2
c
c−x0 = c+v , respectively.
The above analysis demonstrates the possibility of keeping simultaneity absolute within
the framework of special relativity. One can adopts the standard synchrony that leads to the
relativity of simultaneity, and one can also adopts the nonstandard synchrony that restores
the absoluteness of simultaneity. This is permitted because there is no causal connection
between two spacelike separated events in special relativity. However, if there is a causal
influence connecting two distinct events, then the claim that they are not simultaneous
will have a nonconventional basis (Reichenbach 1958; Grünbaum 1973; Janis 2010). In
particular, if there is an arbitrarily fast causal influence connecting two spacelike separated
events, then these two events will be simultaneous. In the following, we will show that
random discontinuous motion and its collapse evolution just provide a nonconventional basis
for the absoluteness of simultaneity.
Consider a particle being in a superposition of two well separated spatial branches. Ac-
cording to the picture of random discontinuous motion, the particle jumps between these two
85
5.3. COLLAPSE DYNAMICS AND PREFERRED LORENTZ FRAME
branches in a random and discontinuous way. At an instant the particle is in one branch, and
at the next instant it may be in the other spatially-separated branch. The disappearance
of the particle in the first branch can be regarded as one event, and the appearance of the
particle in the second branch can be regarded as another event. Obviously there is an instan-
taneous causal connection between these two spacelike separated events; if the particle did
not disappear in the first branch, it could not appear in the second branch. Therefore, these
two events should be regarded as simultaneous. Note that this conclusion is irrelevant to
whether the two events and their causal connection are observable. Besides, the conclusion
is also irrelevant to the reference frame, which further means that simultaneity is absolute9 .
Let’s further consider the collapse evolution of random discontinuous motion during a
measurement. It can be seen that the measurement on one branch of the superposition has
a causal influence on the other branch (as well as on the measured branch) via the collapse
process, and this nonlocal influence is irrelevant to the distance between the two branches.
Accordingly, the time order of the measurement and the collapse of the superposition hap-
pening in the two separated regions cannot be conventional but must be unique. Since the
collapse time can be arbitrarily short, the measurement and the collapse of the superposition
can be regarded as simultaneous. Moreover, the collapses of the superposition in the two
regions, which are spacelike separated events, are also simultaneous10 . The simultaneity is
irrelevant to the selection of inertial frames, which again means that simultaneity is absolute.
Certainly, the collapse of an individual superposition cannot be measured within the
framework of the existing quantum mechanics. However, on the one hand, the above con-
clusion is irrelevant to whether the collapse events can be measured or not, and on the other
hand, the collapse of an individual superposition may be observable when the quantum dy-
namics is deterministic nonlinear (Gisin 1990), e.g. when the measuring device is replaced
with a conscious observer (Squires 1992; Gao 2004).
86
5.3. COLLAPSE DYNAMICS AND PREFERRED LORENTZ FRAME
~2
τc ≈ , (5.18)
tP (∆E)2
where tP is the Planck time, ∆E is the energy uncertainty of the state. We assume this
collapse time formula is still valid in an inertial frame in the relativistic domain. This
assumption seems reasonable, as the collapse time formula already contains the speed of light
c via the Planck time tp 13 . Since the formula is not relativistically invariant, its relativistically
invariant form must contain a term relating to the velocity of the experimental frame relative
to a preferred Lorentz frame. In other words, there must exist a preferred Lorentz frame
according to the collapse model. We define the preferred Lorentz frame, denoted by S0 ,
as the inertial frame where the above formula is valid. Then in another inertial frame the
collapse time will depend on the velocity of the frame relative to S0 . According to the
Lorentz transformation14 , in an inertial frame S 0 with velocity v relative to the frame S0 we
have:
1
τc0 = p · τc , (5.19)
1 − v 2 /c2
1
t0P = p · tP , (5.20)
1 − v 2 /c2
1 − v/c
∆E 0 ≈ p · ∆E. (5.21)
1 − v 2 /c2
Here we only consider the situation where the particle has very high energy, namely E ≈ pc,
and thus Eq. (5.21) holds. Besides, we assume the Planck time tP is the minimum time in
the preferred Lorentz frame, and in another frame the minimum time (i.e. the duration of a
discrete instant) is connected with the Planck time tP by the time dilation formula required
by special relativity. Then by inputting these equations into Eq. (5.22), we can obtain the
relativistic collapse time formula for an arbitrary experimental frame with velocity v relative
to the frame S0 :
~2
τc ≈ (1 + v/c)−2 . (5.22)
tP (∆E)2
This formula contains a term relating to the velocity of the experimental frame relative to the
preferred Lorentz frame. It can be expected that this velocity-dependent term originates from
12
Although it has been argued that quantum nonlocality and special relativity are incompatible, and a
consistent description of wavefunction collapse demands the existence of a preferred Lorentz frame (see, e.g.
Bell 1986a; Percival 1998b), it is widely thought that the preferred Lorentz frame cannot be measured even
within the framework of dynamical collapse theories.
13
By contrast, the dynamical collapse theories in which the collapse time formula does not contain c are
not directly applicable in the relativistic domain.
14
Here we still use the standard synchrony for the convenience of practical realization.
87
5.3. COLLAPSE DYNAMICS AND PREFERRED LORENTZ FRAME
the relativistic equation of collapse dynamics. Indeed, the equation of collapse dynamics,
whose non-relativistic form is denoted by Eq. (4.17), does contain a velocity term in order
to be relativistic invariant15 :
∆E
Pi (t + tP ) = Pi (t) + f (v) [δEs Ei − Pi (t)]. (5.23)
EP
where f (v) ≈ 1 + v/c when E ≈ pc, and v is the velocity of the experimental frame relative
to the preferred Lorentz frame. From this equation we can also derive the above relativistic
collapse time formula.
Therefore, according to our energy-conserved collapse model, the collapse time of a given
wave function will differ in different inertial frames. For example, when considering the
maximum difference of the revolution speed of the Earth with respect to the Sun is ∆v ≈
60km/s, the maximum difference of the collapse time measured in different times (e.g. spring
and fall respectively) on the Earth will be ∆τc ≈ 4×10−4 τc . As a result, the collapse dynamics
will single out a preferred Lorentz frame in which the collapse time of a given wave function
is longest, and the frame can also be determined by comparing the collapse times of a given
wave function in different frames16 . It may be expected that this preferred Lorentz frame
is the CMB-frame in which the cosmic background radiation is isotropic, and the one-way
speed of light is also isotropic in this frame.
15
This seems to be an inevitable consequence of the requirement of energy conservation for wavefunction
collapse.
16
In general, we can measure the collapse time of a wave function through measuring the change of the
interference between the corresponding collapse branches for an ensemble of identical systems. The main
technical difficulty of realizing such a measurement is to exclude the influence of environmental decoherence
(cf. Marshall et al 2003).
88
Bibliography
[3] Aharonov, Y., Albert, D. Z. and Vaidman, L. (1988). How the result of a measurement
of a component of the spin of a spin-1/2 particle can turn out to be 100. Phys. Rev. Lett.
60, 1351.
[4] Aharonov, Y., Anandan, J. and Vaidman, L. (1993). Meaning of the wave function, Phys.
Rev. A 47, 4616.
[5] Aharonov, Y., Anandan, J. and Vaidman, L. (1996). The meaning of protective measure-
ments, Found. Phys. 26, 117.
[6] Aharonov, Y., Englert, B. G. and Scully M. O. (1999). Protective measurements and
Bohm trajectories, Phys. Lett. A 263, 137.
[7] Aharonov, Y., Erez, N. and Scully M. O. (2004). Time and Ensemble Averages in
Bohmian Mechanics. Physica Scripta 69, 81-83.
[8] Aharonov, Y. and Vaidman, L. (1993). Measurement of the Schrödinger wave of a single
particle, Phys. Lett. A 178, 38.
[9] Aharonov, Y. and Vaidman, L. (1996). About position measurements which do not show
the Bohmian particle position, in J. T. Cushing, A. Fine, and S. Goldstein (eds.), Bohmian
Mechanics and Quantum Theory: An Appraisal, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 141-154.
[10] Albert, D. (1992). Quantum Mechanics and Experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni-
versity Press.
[12] Albert, D. Z. and Loewer, B. (1988). Interpreting the Many Worlds Interpretation,
Synthese, 77, 195-213.
[13] Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., and Zanghi, N. (2008), On the Common Structure
of Bohmian Mechanics and the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber Theory, British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science 59 (3), 353-389.
[14] Anandan, J. (1993). Protective Measurement and Quantum Reality. Found. Phys. Lett.,
6, 503-532.
[16] Bacciagaluppi G. and Valentini, A. (2009). Quantum Theory at the Crossroads: Recon-
sidering the 1927 Solvay Conference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[17] Barrett, J., Leifer, M. and Tumulka, R. (2005). Bells jump process in discrete time.
Europhys. Lett. 72, 685.
89
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[18] Barrett, J. A. (1999). The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
[20] Bassi, A., Ippoliti, E., and Vacchini, B. (2005). On the energy increase in space-collapse
models. J. Phys. A : Math. Gen. 38, 8017.
[21] Bassi, A. (2007). Dynamical reduction models: present status and future developments.
J. Phys.: Conf. Series 67, 012013.
[22] Bedingham, D. J. (2011). Relativistic state reduction dynamics. Found. Phys. 41, 686-
704.
[23] Bell, J. S. (1986a). in The Ghost in the Atom, Davies, P. C. W.and Brown, J. R. eds.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 45-57.
[24] Bell, J. S. (1986b). Beables for quantum field theory. Phys. Rep. 137, 49-54.
[25] Bell, J. S. (1990). Against measurement, in A. I. Miller (eds.), Sixty-Two Years of Uncer-
tainty: Historical Philosophical and Physics Enquiries into the Foundations of Quantum
Mechanics. Berlin: Springer, 17-33.
[26] Belot, G. (2011). Quantum states for primitive ontologists: A case study. http://philsci-
archive.pitt.edu/8468/. Forthcoming in European Journal for Philosophy of Science.
[29] Bohm D. and Hiley, B. J. (1993). The Undivided Universe: An Ontological Interpreta-
tion of Quantum Theory. London: Routledge.
[30] Born, M. (1926). Quantenmechanik der Stoβvorgänge. Z. Phys. 38, 803; English trans-
lation in Ludwig, G., eds., 1968, Wave Mechanics, Oxford: Pergamon Press: 206.
[32] Brown, H. R., Dewdney, C. and Horton, G. (1995). Bohm particles and their detection
in the light of neutron interferometry. Found. Phys. 25, 329.
[33] Carlip, S. (2008). Is quantum gravity necessary? Class. Quant. Grav., 25, 154010-1.
[34] Christian, J. (2001). Why the quantum must yield to gravity. In: Physics Meets Phi-
losophy at the Planck Scale, C. Callender and N. Huggett (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. pp.305.
[35] Czachor, M. (1996). Nonlinear Schrödinger equation and two-level atoms. Phys. Rev. A
53, 1310.
[36] Dass, N. D. H. and Qureshi, T. (1999). Critique of protective measurements. Phys. Rev.
A 59, 2590.
90
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[37] Daumer, M., Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., and Zangh, N. (1997). Naive Realism About
Operators, Erkenntnis 45, 379-397.
[39] DeWitt, B. S. and Graham, N. (eds.) (1973). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quan-
tum Mechanics, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[40] DeWitt, C. and Rickles, D. (eds.) (2011). The Role of Gravitation in Physics: Report
from the 1957 Chapel Hill Conference. Max Planck Research Library for the History and
Development of Knowledge, Volume 5.
[43] Diósi, L. (1989). Models for universal reduction of macroscopic quantum fluctuations.
Phys. Rev. A 40, 1165-1173.
[44] Diósi, L. (2007). Notes on certain Newton gravity mechanisms of wave function locali-
sation and decoherence. J. Phys. A: Math. Gen. 40, 2989-2995.
[47] Duff, M. J., Okun, L. B., and Veneziano, G. (2002). Trialogue on the number of funda-
mental constants. Journal of High Energy Physics, 0203, 23.
[48] Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., and Zanghi, N. (1992). Quantum equilibrium and the origin of
absolute uncertainty. Journal of Statistical Physics 67, 843-907.
[49] Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., and Zanghı̀, N. (1997). Bohmian mechanics and the meaning
of the wave function, in Cohen, R. S., Horne, M., and Stachel, J., eds., Experimental
Metaphysics - Quantum Mechanical Studies for Abner Shimony, Volume One; Boston
Studies in the Philosophy of Science 193, Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
[50] Edwards, W. F. (1963). Special relativity in anisotropic space, Am. J. Phys. 31, 482-489.
[51] Einstein, A. (1905). Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter Körper, Ann. d. Phys. 17, 891-921.
English translations in Stachel, J. (eds.), Einstein’s Miraculous Year, Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1998, pp. 123-160.
[52] Englert, B. G., Scully, M. O., Süssmann, G., Walther, H. (1992). Z. Naturforsch. Sur-
realistic Bohm Trajectories. 47a, 1175.
[53] Everett, H. (1957). ‘Relative state’ formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys.
29, 454-462.
91
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[55] Feynman, R. (2001). The Character of Physical Law (Messenger Lectures, 1964). Cam-
bridge: The MIT Press.
[56] Friedman J. R., Patel, V., Chen, W., Tolpygo, S. K. and Lukens, J. E. (2000). Nature
406, 43.
[57] Frigg, R and Hoefer, C. (2007). Probability in GRW Theory. Studies in the History and
Philosophy of Modern Physics 38, 371-389.
[59] Gao, S. (1999). The interpretation of quantum mechanics (I) and (II). physics/9907001,
physics/9907002.
[60] Gao, S. (2000). Quantum Motion and Superluminal Communication, Beijing: Chinese
Broadcasting and Television Publishing House. (in Chinese)
[61] Gao, S. (2003). Quantum: A Historical and Logical Journey. Beijing: Tsinghua Univer-
sity Press. (in Chinese)
[63] Gao, S. (2005). A conjecture on the origin of dark energy. Chin. Phys. Lett. 22, 783.
[64] Gao, S. (2006a). A model of wavefunction collapse in discrete space-time. Int. J. Theor.
Phys. 45, 1943-1957.
[65] Gao, S. (2006b). Quantum Motion: Unveiling the Mysterious Quantum World. Bury St
Edmunds, Suffolk U.K.: Arima Publishing.
[66] Gao, S. (2008). God Does Play Dice with the Universe. Bury St Edmunds, Suffolk U.K.:
Arima Publishing.
[68] Gao, S. (2011a). The wave function and quantum reality, in Proceedings of the In-
ternational Conference on Advances in Quantum Theory, A. Khrennikov, G. Jaeger, M.
Schlosshauer, G. Weihs (eds), AIP Conference Proceedings 1327, 334-338.
[69] Gao, S. (2011b). Meaning of the wave function, International Journal of Quantum Chem-
istry. 111, 4124-4138.
[70] Gao, S. (2011c). Is gravity an entropic force? Entropy special issue “Black Hole Ther-
modynamics”, Jacob D. Bekenstein (eds), 13, 936-948.
[71] Gao, S. (2011d). Comment on “How to protect the interpretation of the wave function
against protective measurements” by Jos Uffink. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/8942.
[72] Garay, L. J. (1995). Quantum gravity and minimum length. International Journal of
Modern Physics A 10, 145.
[73] Ghirardi, G. C. (1997), Quantum Dynamical Reduction and Reality: Replacing Prob-
ability Densities with Densities in Real Space, Erkenntnis, 45, 349.
92
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[75] Ghirardi, G. C., Grassi, R. and Benatti, F. (1995). Describing the macroscopic world:
Closing the circle within the dynamical reduction program. Found. Phys., 25, 313-328.
[77] Ghirardi, G.C., Rimini, A., and Weber, T. (1986). Unified dynamics for microscopic
and macroscopic systems. Phys. Rev. D 34, 470.
[78] Gisin, N. (1990). Weinberg’s non-linear quantum mechanics and superluminal commu-
nications, Phys. Lett. A 143, 1-2.
[80] Goldstein, S. and Teufel, S. (2001). Quantum spacetime without observers: Ontological
clarity and the conceptual foundations of quantum gravity, in Callender, C. and Huggett,
N., eds., Physics meets Philosophy at the Planck Scale, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
[81] Grabert, H., Hänggi, P. and Talkner, P. (1979). Is quantum mechanics equivalent to a
classical stochastic process? Phys. Rev. A 19, 24402445.
[82] Grünbaum, A. (1973). Philosophical Problems of Space and Time (Boston Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, Volume 12), 2nd enlarged edition, Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel.
[84] Holland, P. (1993). The Quantum Theory of Motion: An Account of the de Broglie-
Bohm Causal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
[85] Holland, P. and Philippidis, C. (2003). Implications of Lorentz covariance for the guid-
ance equation in two-slit quantum interference. Phys. Rev. A 67, 062105.
[87] Hosten, O. and Kwiat, P. G. (2008). Observation of the Spin Hall Effect of Light via
Weak Measurements. Science 319, 787-790.
[88] Hughston, L. P. (1996). Geometry of stochastic state vector reduction. Proc. Roy. Soc.
A 452, 953.
[90] Joos, E. and Zeh, H. D. (1985). The emergence of classical properties through interaction
with the environment. Zeitschrift fr Physik B 59, 223-243.
93
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[91] Kochen, S. and Specker, E. (1967). The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum
Mechanics, J. Math. Mech. 17, 59-87.
[92] Lewis, P. (2004). Life in configuration space, British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science 55, 713-729.
[93] Marshall, W., Simon, C., Penrose, R., and Bouwmeester, D. (2003). Towards quantum
superpositions of a mirror, Phys. Rev. Lett. 91, 130401.
[97] Monton, B. (2006). Quantum mechanics and 3N-dimensional space. Philosophy of Sci-
ence, 73(5), 778-789.
[98] Moore, W. J. (1994). Schrödinger: Life and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
[99] Mott, N. F. (1929). The Wave Mechanics of α-ray Tracks, Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London A 126, 79-84.
[100] Nakamura, K. et al (Particle Data Group) (2010). J. Phys. G: Nucl. Part. Phys. 37,
075021.
[101] Nelson, E. (1966). Derivation of the Schrödinger equation from Newtonian mechanics.
Phys. Rev. 150, 1079-1085.
[103] Okun, L. B. (2009). Energy and Mass in Relativity Theory. New Jersey: World Scien-
tific.
[104] Pearle, P. (1989). Combining stochastic dynamical state-vector reduction with spon-
taneous localization. Phys. Rev. A 39, 2277.
[105] Pearle, P. (1999). Collapse models. In: Petruccione, F. and Breuer, H. P. (eds.), Open
Systems and Measurement in Relativistic Quantum Theory. Springer Verlag, New York.
[106] Pearle, P. (2000). Wavefunction Collapse and Conservation Laws. Found. Phys. 30,
1145-1160.
[107] Pearle, P. (2004). Problems and aspects of energy-driven wavefunction collapse models.
Phys. Rev. A 69, 42106.
[108] Pearle, P. (2007). How stands collapse I. J. Phys. A: Math. Theor., 40, 3189-3204.
[109] Pearle, P. (2009). How stands collapse II. in Myrvold, W. C. and Christian, J. eds.,
Quantum Reality, Relativistic Causality, and Closing the Epistemic Circle: Essays in
Honour of Abner Shimony. The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of
Science, 73(IV), 257-292.
94
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[110] Pearle, P. and Squires, E. (1996). Gravity, energy conservation and parameter values
in collapse models. Found. Phys. 26, 291.
[111] Penrose, R. (1996). On gravitys role in quantum state reduction. Gen. Rel. Grav. 28,
581.
[112] Penrose, R. (1998). Quantum computation, entanglement and state reduction. Phil.
Trans. R. Soc. Lond. A 356, 1927.
[113] Percival, I. C. (1995). Quantum space-time fluctuations and primary state diffusion.
Proc. Roy. Soc. A 451, 503.
[115] Percival, I. C. (1998b). Quantum transfer function, weak nonlocality and relativity,
Phys. Lett. A 244, 495-501.
[116] Reichenbach, H. (1958). The Philosophy of Space and Time, New York: Dover.
[118] Rovelli, C. (2011). “Forget time”: Essay written for the FQXi contest on the Nature
of Time. Found. Phys. 41, 1475-1490.
[120] Salzman, P. J. and Carlip, S. (2006). A possible experimental test of quantized gravity.
arXiv: gr-qc/0606120.
[121] Saunders, S., Barrett, J. A., Kent, A. and Wallace, D. (eds.) (2010) Many Worlds?
Everett, Quantum Theory, and Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[123] Shankar, R. (1994). Principles of Quantum Mechanics, 2nd ed. New York: Plenum.
[124] Sonego, S. and Pin, M. (2005). Deriving relativistic momentum and energy. Eur. J.
Phys. 26, 33-45.
[125] Squires, E. J. (1992). Explicit collapse and superluminal signaling, Phys. Lett. A 163,
356-358.
[126] Suárez, M. (2004). Quantum selections, propensities and the problem of measurement,
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(2), 219-55.
[127] Suárez, M. (2007). Quantum Propensities, Studies in the History and Philosophy of
Modern Physics 38, 418-438.
[128] Tooley, M. (1988). In defence of the existence of states of motion. Philosophical Topics
16, 225-254.
95
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[129] Uffink, J. (1999). How to protect the interpretation of the wave function against pro-
tective measurements. Phys. Rev. A 60, 3474-3481. arXiv: quant-ph/9903007.
[130] Vaidman, L. (2009) Protective measurements, in Greenberger, D., Hentschel, K., and
Weinert, F. (eds.), Compendium of Quantum Physics: Concepts, Experiments, History
and Philosophy. Springer-Verlag, Berlin. pp.505-507.
[131] Valentini, A. (1997). On Galilean and Lorentz invariance in pilot-wave dynamics. Phys.
Lett. A 228, 215-222.
[133] Vink, J. C. (1993). Quantum mechanics in terms of discrete beables. Phys. Rev. A 48,
1808.
[136] Wallstrom, T. (1994). Inequivalence between the Schrdinger equation and the
Madelung hydrodynamic equations. Phys. Rev. A 49, 16131617.
[137] Wheeler, J. A. and W. H. Zurek (eds.) (1983). Quantum Theory and Measurement,
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[138] Winnie, J. (1970). Special relativity without one-way velocity assumptions: I and II,
Philosophy of Science 37, 81-99, 223-238.
96