Kim 2021
Kim 2021
doi:10.1017/can.2021.3
ARTICLE
Abstract
In the explanations of logical laws and inference rules of the mature version of Begriffsschrift in Grundgesetze, Frege
uses the predicate “… is the True.” Scholars like Greimann maintain that this predicate is a metalinguistic truth-
predicate for Frege. This paper examines an argument for this claim that is based on the “nominal reading” of
Frege’s conception of sentences—the claim that for Frege a sentence “p” is equivalent to a nonsentential phrase like
“the truth-value of the thought that p.” In particular, this paper attempts to establish two points concerning this
argument based on the nominal reading. First, the argument implies a claim about the nature of assertion which
Frege repeatedly denies in his mature works. Secondly, the nominal reading on which the argument depends is
false. A sentence “p” is not equivalent to a nonsentential phrase like “the truth-value of the thought that p” for
Frege. Our discussion will lead to an important lesson about Frege’s conception of sentences and of assertion.
Does Gottlob Frege have a metalinguistic truth-predicate in his logic, Begriffsschrift? Many
commentators say “No”; they claim that Frege’s conception of logic differs from the contemporary
semantic conception of logic that demands a metalinguistic truth-predicate.1 Nonetheless, scholars
like Heck (2012) and Greimann (2008) argue that Frege’s conception of logic substantively depends
on semantics. Some of them such as Greimann (2007, 2008) even contend that we can find a
metalinguistic truth-predicate in Frege’s mature works. Look at, e.g., the following passage of The
Basic Laws of Arithmetic (Frege 1893; hereafter, Grundgesetze):
would be the False only if Γ and Δ were the True while Γ was not the True. This is impossible;
accordingly [Law I]
1
For this point, see, e.g., Burge (1986), Ricketts (1996, 2003), Goldfarb (2001), etc.
2
For the translation of Grundgesetze, I depend on Ebert and Rossberg’s (Frege 2013). For the translation of Frege’s published
or unpublished articles, I depend on Frege 1970, 1979, 1997.
Frege is explaining Law I of Begriffsschrift. Note that Frege’s explanation looks like a metalinguistic
justification of an axiom of a logical system. Also, note that the predicate “… is the True” looks like a
truth-predicate in such a metalinguistic justification. We can find similar passages for other laws
and inference rules of Begriffsschrift, and can also find the same predicate used in those passages.
The claim of scholars like Greimann is that this predicate is a metalinguistic truth-predicate for
Frege.3 I will call this claim “the TP (truth predicate) thesis.”
There is an initial objection to the TP thesis. The predicate “… is the True” is related to Frege’s
unique conception of sentences. For Frege in his mature career, everything is either an object or a
function.4 Now, a function is “unsaturated,” i.e., has empty places for arguments. A function is thus
referred to by an “unsaturated” expression such as “x is prime” or “the value-range of x.” On the
other hand, an object is “saturated,” i.e., has no empty place for arguments. An object is thus referred
to by saturated expression such as “Gottlob Frege” or “the capital of England.” Sentences are
“saturated.” Hence, what they refer to are objects. The reference of a sentence is one of the truth-
values, the True or the False. Therefore, truth-values are objects and sentences are singular
referential terms like proper names (cf. Frege 1891, 1892, 1893, 1906a, 1914).5 This means that
sentences can be put in the position of “x” or “y” in the identity sign “x ¼ y.” For instance,
informally,
can be taken as a sentence that refers to the True, because both the left and the right refer to
the True. Now, the predicate “… is the True” can be regarded as the identity predicate “x is
identical with the True” such that we acquire a sentence that refers to the True by putting a
name of the True in “x.” Given this explanation of “… is the True,” it rather looks as if the
predicate is not a metalinguistic truth-predicate, but just an identity predicate like “x ¼ 2” in
Frege’s formal language.
However, there is an argument that the predicate “… is the True” as such still can, and does,
function as a truth-predicate in the metalinguistic sense. This argument, constructed by Greimann
(2008), is based on a reading of Frege’s conception of sentences, which is shared by commentators
such as Klement (2001), Landini (1996), and Pedriali (2017). This interpretation of Frege’s
conception of sentences argues that for him the sentence “p” is equivalent to a nonsentential phrase
like “the truth-value of the thought that p.” I call this interpretation “the nominal reading (of Frege’s
conception of sentences).” The aim of this paper is to critically examine the argument for the TP
thesis based on the nominal reading.
Joan Weiner (2008) provides an extensive discussion of this argument. However, this
paper’s approach to the argument differs from Weiner’s. Specifically, this paper establishes
two points against the argument. First, the argument implies a claim about assertion which
Frege repeatedly denies in his mature works. Secondly, a sentence “p” is not equivalent to a
nonsentential phrase such as “the truth-value of the thought that p” for Frege. Our discussion
leads to a crucial lesson about how we can understand the act of assertion under Frege’s
unique conception of sentence.
Section 1 introduces the target argument for the TP thesis by following Greimann’s discussion.
Section 2 criticizes the argument. Section 3 draws the lesson about Frege’s conception of assertion
from our discussion of the target argument.
3
Künne (2008) and Taschek (2008) also identify this predicate as a truth-predicate for Frege.
4
Greimman (2007) claims that truth is neither an object nor a function. However, Kim (2019) shows that his claim is
grounded in a mistaken interpretation of Frege’s remarks.
5
The argument that truth-values are objects here follows Frege’s own argument in “Function and Concept” (1891).
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3
Griemann (2008, 410) claims that we can construct a schema for the relevant kind of T-sentences
out of “… is the True”:
Hence, there is no problem with taking “… is the True” as a truth-predicate in the relevant sense. Or
so argues Greimann.
An immediate objection, however, would be that (FSch) uses the operator “the truth-value of.”
Frege never uses such an operator in his explanations of logical laws. It rather seems as if Frege is
using “… is the True” simply as the identity predicate “x = the True,” so to speak, as in
If so, we cannot confirm that Frege is using “… is the True” like a truth-predicate in the relevant
sense (Greimann 2008, 410).
As a response to this objection, Greimann appeals to the nominal reading of Frege’s conception
of sentence (Greimann 2007, 2008; Klement 2001; Landini 1996; Pedriali 2017), according to which
the sense of any sentence “p” is identical with the sense of the phrase “the truth-value of: (the
thought) that p” in Frege. If so, then even sentences such as (S) are in fact instances of (FSch). But
why do we have to accept the nominal reading?6
In Grundgesetze, Frege writes:
are expressions of thoughts, some true, some false. I express it like this: the value of the
function ξ 2 ¼ 4 is the truth-value of the true, or that of the false. It is already clear from this
that I do not want to assert anything yet when I simply write down an equation, but that I
merely designate a truth-value; just as I assert nothing when I simply write down “22 ,” but
merely designate a number. (1893, sec. 2)
What Frege says here is related to the point that a sentence refers to a truth-value. In a sentence, or an
equation in this case, we have a predicate: a word that refers to a concept, i.e., a function whose value is
always a truth-value. For instance, in the above equations, we find the predicate “ξ 2 ¼ 4.” Now, e.g.,
“22 ¼ 4” refers to the value of the concept x2 ¼ 4 saturated with the argument 2. Thus, it refers to the
True. Because the value of a function is an object, truth-values are objects, and so the reference of a
sentence, or an equation, is an object. Now, equations as such express thoughts. In Frege’s Begriffss-
chrift, however, writing an equation down is not asserting that the thought it expresses is true. By
writing it down, we only designate a truth-value. For asserting, a special sign is necessary:
6
I do not dispute Greimann’s claim that (FSch) gives us quasi T-sentences. Further, I do not dispute the claim that Frege
provides a sort of metalinguistic justifications of logical laws. The aim of this paper is to critically examine this particular
argument for those claims, which will be explained in the following.
4 Junyeol Kim
Above it is already stated that within a mere equation no assertion is yet to be found; with
“2 þ 3 = 5”only a truth-value is designated, without its being said which one of the two it
is. Moreover, if I wrote “(2 þ 3 = 5) = (2 = 2)” and presupposed that one knows that 2 = 2 is the
True, even then I would not thereby have asserted that the sum of 2 and 3 is 5; rather I would
only have designated the truth-value of: that “2 þ 3 = 5” refers to the same as “2 = 2.” We are
therefore in need of another special sign in order to be able to assert something as true. To this
end, I let the sign “├” precede the name of the truth-value, in such a way that, e.g., in
(B) “├ 22 = 4”
The assertion sign cannot be used to construct a functional expression; for it does not serve in
conjunction with other signs, to designate an object. “├ 2 þ 3 ¼ 5” does not designate
anything; it asserts something. (1891, 34n)
This raises the question of how (B) can be a name of a truth-value while ├ ξ 2 ¼ 4 is not a concept.
Greimann maintains that Frege distinguishes sentences from (mere) singular terms for truth-
values. Only expressions such as (B) are sentences. Equations such as “22 ¼ 4” are not sentences but
singular terms for truth values. Both sentences and singular terms for truth-values are of course
proper names of truth-values; they “denote (bedeuten)” (2008, 414) truth-values. However, singular
terms for truth-values differ from sentences in that only the former can be used for the speech-act of
reference qua a proper part of the speech act of assertion; only singular terms for truth-values
“designate (bezeichnen)” (2008, 414) in this sense.
Then, the sense of an equation such as “22 ¼ 4,” which would be taken as a sentence, must be that
of an expression that can be used as a part of a sentence like (B) for the sake of the speech-act of
reference qua a proper part of assertion. Indeed, Greimann argues, Frege is paraphrasing the
sentence in the ordinary sense “(2 þ 3 = 5) = (2 = 2)” into the nonsentential phrase: “the truth-value
of: that “2 þ 3 = 5” refers to the same as “2 = 2”’. Greimann insists that, in general, the sense of
a singular truth-value term “p” is identical with that of “the truth-value of: that p.” Therefore, even
“2 þ 2 = 4 is the True” is indeed equivalent to the (quasi) T-sentence “The truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 = 4
is the True.”7 Greimann concludes: “… is the True” is a truth-predicate in the relevant sense.
7
See Greimann (2007, 136). Here, Greimann argues that because the thought of a sentence is a condition when the sentence
refers to the True, “2 þ 3 = 5” indeed has the same sense as “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 3 equals 5.’ He does not repeat the same
argument in his 2008 paper. This argument, however, does not work if our discussion is along the right lines. For the critical
discussion of Greimann (2007), see Kim (2019).
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5
a sentence in the usual sense. So its sense is not a thought. Thoughts differ from senses of nonsentential
singular terms. For an arbitrary thought 〈p〉, it is always identical with 〈〈p〉 is true〉 (Frege 1892, 1897,
1906a, 1914, 1915, etc.). But the same point is not applied to a nonsentential singular term. A case in
point: “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 is 4.” Its sense differs from 〈The truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 is 4 is
true〉.8 If “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 is 4” and “2 þ 2 is 4” have different senses, then one cannot be
the paraphrase of the other.
Of course, as we have seen, Frege takes expressions such as “(2 þ 3 = 5) = (2 = 2)” to be legitimate,
and thus he considers “2 þ 3 = 5” to be a proper name such as “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 3 is 5” in
the syntactical level. One might object that this syntactic assimilation of a sentence to a proper name
strongly suggests that he also semantically assimilates a sentence to a proper name like “the truth-
value of: that … .” However, there is no textual evidence for this claim. Moreover, Frege’s text rather
seems to show that this syntactic assimilation does not lead to the suggested semantic assimilation.
In “On Sense and Reference,” immediately after Frege classifies sentences as proper names (1892,
63), he says that 〈〈2 þ 3 is 5〉 is true〉 is identical with 〈2 þ 3 is 5〉 (64). As we have just said, the sense
of “the truth-value of that 2 þ 3 is 5” is not identical with 〈The truth-value of: that 2 þ 3 is 5 is true〉.
We will come back to this issue at the end of this section.
What is important is that Greimann has a different response to the above objection against the
nominal reading, which does not depend on the controversial claim that Frege’s syntactic assim-
ilation of sentences to proper names implies that he semantically assimilates sentences to the
phrases like “the truth-value of: that p.” According to Greimann, the nominal reading does not
reject that a thought as the sense of a sentence differs from the sense of a singular term like “the
truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 is 4.” When the nominal reading says that “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 is
4” is a paraphrase of “2 þ 2 = 4,” Greimann says, it is arguing that the latter as an expression of
Begriffsschrift is “not to be considered as a sentence but as a complex singular term” (2008, 411). Let
me explain further. According to Greimann, it is not the case that Frege “wants to defend the absurd
view that in natural languages an expression like ‘22 ¼ 4’ is used as a singular [truth-value] term [like
‘the truth-value of: that 22 equals 4’]” (412). In natural language, it certainly expresses 〈22 equals 4〉
and, as such, “can be used to assert something, but not to designate something” (412).9 The point of
Greimann’s defense of the nominal reading is thus that Frege turns what we regard as sentences in
natural languages into singular truth-value terms in Begriffsschrift because he makes a clear
distinction between a mere entertainment of a thought, i.e., what he calls “predication,” and
assertion. With ordinary language sentences like “2 þ 2 is equal to 4,” however, we cannot clearly
mark the distinction. For we can use ordinary language sentences to perform both predication—
entertainment of a thought—and assertion (412). The nominal reading claims that in order to make
the distinction clearly shown, Frege regards “2 þ 2 = 4” qua an expression of his formal language to
mean “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 equals 4,” which alone cannot be used for the act of assertion
because it is not a sentence. A sentence is constructed and assertion is performed only if we write
“├,” a special truth-predicate or truth-operator that can be translated into “… is the True”
(Greimann 2004, 2007), in front of such a term.
Several clarifications are necessary here. First, Greimann claims that while “… is the True” in
“The truth-value of: that grass is green is the True” is a truth-predicate, it does not function as a
truth-predicate when it is “applied to a singular term that does not express a thought, as in ‘5 is the
True’” (2008, 414). This shows that Greimann takes the phrase “the truth-value of: that grass is
8
What only thoughts—but not nonsentential singular terms—have is not assertoric force but positive predication. Positive
predication itself does not amount to assertoric force. Thoughts do not carry assertoric force with themselves, as we will see
below. Frege’s thesis that 〈p〉 is identical with 〈p is true〉 is rather his argument that a thought does not contain assertoric force.
9
Greimann (2008, 412) also claims that Frege’s functional analysis of sentences is only intended to be applied to formal
sentences. But this is not really clear. For instance, when Frege (1906b, 177–78) explains the sentence “2 is prime” in terms of the
saturation of a concept, does he talk about formal languages or natural languages? Or, is he talking about language in general?
Greimann’s claim seems to be question-begging without further discussion.
6 Junyeol Kim
green”—unlike “5”—to express a thought. If he does so, there is a conflict between Greimann’s
terminology and mine. I use “thought” in order to refer to the sense of a sentence like “2 þ 2 equals
4” in English. I also say that a term expresses S just in case a term has S as its sense—following Frege’s
own terminology (1892, 61).10 In my terminology, “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 equals 4” does not
express a thought because it is not a sentence and so its sense is not a thought. Recall that Greimann
accepts that “2 þ 2 is 4” and “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 is 4” have different senses in English and
that only expressions like the former count as sentences in it. Hence, he would accept that only “2 þ
2 is 4” expresses a thought in my sense. Thus, when Greimann says that “the truth-value of: that p”
expresses a thought, he must be using “express a thought” in a different sense. Perhaps, he takes such
a phrase to express a thought in the sense that it includes the name of a thought. What is important
is that while following my terminology, we can still capture Greimann’s point safely as follows:
“2 þ 2 ¼ 4” in Frege’s formal language does not have 〈2 þ 2 is 4〉—the sense of “2 þ 2 is 4” in English
—as its sense. In fact, Greimann’s whole point is that no expression other than the ones prefixed
with “├” can have a thought—the sense of a sentence—as its sense. Given this clarification, keeping
my own terminology in the following discussion with care will not distort Greimann’s reading.
Secondly, one might think that saying that Greimann considers “├” to be a formal counterpart of
“… is the True” is misleading because he says that the horizontal—the short horizontal stroke
attached to the judgment-stroke—is such a formal counterpart (2008, 418). Frege indeed takes the
horizontal to refer to a concept such that it yields the True if the True is given as an argument and
the False otherwise (Frege 1893, sec. 5)—the concept being identical with the True. However, we
need to note that by Greimann’s own light, “— 2 þ 3 ¼ 5,” which is a legitimate expression of
Begriffsschrift, does not correspond to the sentence “2 þ 3 = 5 is the True.” Because it does not have
the judgment-stroke, it can only correspond to “the truth-value of: that 2 þ 3 = 5 is the True.” An
expression that corresponds to the sentence “2 þ 3 = 5 is the True” is made only when we add the
judgment-stroke at the left side of the horizontal. Greimann does not further explain how the
judgment-stroke and the horizontal interact with each other to construct such a sentential
expression. In any event, what is important to our purpose is that the predicate “… is the True”
qua an expression that can produce a sentence of the form “p is the True” only corresponds to “├,”
not the horizontal. That appears to be why Greimann (2008, 418) regards the sign “├” including the
judgment-stroke, but not the horizontal alone, as a truth-operator. In the remainder of this paper,
“… is the True” is a predicate as a part of the sentence of the form “p is the True.” Again, “├” is a formal
counterpart of “… is the True” as such.
Lastly, it is not Greimann’s point that just as Begriffsschrift needs “├” to construct a sentence and
make an assertion, we need “… is the True” in order to do so in natural language. According to
Greimann, for Frege, we perform sentence-construction/assertion in natural language with “the
syntactic mood of assertoric sentences” (2000, 219), not with such a predicate. Therefore, the
functional counterpart of “├” in natural language is the syntactic mood of assertoric sentences in
Greimann’s reading. However, as we have seen, precisely because in natural language we need to
perform sentence-construction/assertion with the syntactic mood of assertoric sentences, natural
language blurs the distinction between assertion and mere predication. For that reason, Greimann
says, Frege makes a clear division between mere predication and assertion by interpreting “├ p” as a
combination of a nonsentential expression such as “the truth-value of: that p”—which does not
express truth—and the truth-predicate “… is the True,” i.e., the judgment-stroke.
To recap the emerging explanation of Begriffsschrift, say—following Greimann—“— 2 þ 2 equals
4E” is an English sentence and “2 þ 2 = 4F” is a corresponding singular term in Begriffsschrift. “2 þ
2 equals 4E” expresses 〈2 þ 2 equals 4〉, and is a sentence in the sense that it can be used to assert, but
not to designate, an object. But “2 þ 2 = 4F” does not express such a thought; it only expresses the sense
of a singular term. Therefore, it is not a sentence in the same sense. We come to have a sentence in this
10
Strictly speaking, a name refers to its reference and expresses its sense (Frege 1892, 61; Frege 1893, sec. 2).
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7
sense only if we put “├” in front of it. Now, “├ 2 þ 2 ¼ 4” does express a thought, namely, 〈The truth-
value of: that 2 þ 2 equals 4 is the True〉. Hence, “├” is a formal version of “… is the True” as a part of a
sentence like “2 þ 3 = 5 is the True” and is the only genuine predicate—which is also a truth-predicate
or -operator—of Begriffsschrift in the sense that only with “├” can we have a sentence.11
One problem with taking “├” to be a truth-predicate is that “├ 2“ can also count as a
Begriffsschriftsatz. Greimann ought to accept that, in such a case, “├” is not a truth-predicate, but
a mere identity predicate. Then, why don’t we say that it is merely such an identity predicate? This
leads to a doubt against his reading of “… is the True” because “2 is the True” seems to be a perfectly
legitimate. But Greimann does not seem to take this issue seriously. He simply admits that, in such a
case, “… is the True” fails to work as a truth-predicate. Greimann’s idea seems to be that as long as
the predicate produces all instances of (FSch), the fact that it can play a different role does not
prevent us from regarding it as a truth-predicate. That idea still seems controversial.12 However, this
is not the major issue I would like to raise here.
According to the suggested interpretation of Begriffsschrift, we do not have a sentence that
expresses a thought without “├” in Begriffsschrift. To put it in a different way, the sense of “├”
contributes to the formation of the thought 〈… is the True〉. At the same time, “├” stands for
assertoric force. Therefore, here, “├” (i) contributes to the formation of a thought and (ii) indicates
assertoric force. In a significant sense, this explanation takes assertoric force to contribute to the
formation of a thought. However, this is what Frege emphatically rejects in many places (e.g., Frege
1892, 1897, 1906a, 1914, 1915). For instance, Frege writes in “On Schoenflies”:
We can of course express a thought, without stating it to be true. The thought is strictly the
same whether we merely express it or whether we also put it forward as true. Thus assertoric
force, which is often connected with the copula or else with the grammatical predicate, does
not belong to the expressions of the thoughts… . (1906b, 177)13
In fact, the main logical defect of natural language concerning assertoric force—and assertion—is
that it leads us to believe that assertoric force comes as a part of thought. In “My Basic Logical
Insights,” Frege writes:
So the word “true” [in the sentences of the form “The thought that p is true”] seems to make
the impossible possible: it allows what corresponds to the assertoric force to assume the form
of a contribution to the thought. (1915, 252)
the word “true” [in “The thought that p is true”] has a sense that contributes nothing to the
sense of the whole sentence in which it occurs as a predicate. (1915, 252)
He is pointing to his claim that “p” and “The thought that p is true” have the same thought. Now,
Frege writes:
Although this attempt miscarries, or rather through the very fact that it miscarries, it indicates
what is characteristic of logic. (1915, 252)
11
Thus, Greimann denies the interpretation that takes the judgment-stroke to be a mere force indicator (2000, 215; 2008,
418). According to him, the judgment-stroke is also a truth-operator for “predicating truth” (2008, 418). Indeed, the early
version of Begriffsschrift (Frege 1879) understands “├” in this way. However, in the version in Grundgesetze, Frege clearly denies
this view because the judgment stroke is not a predicate anymore (the judgment stroke is not identified as a primitive function).
Frege has reasons for this change according to Heck (2012, sec. 2.3).
12
For instance, see Weiner’s 2008 discussion.
13
Also, Frege (1914, 233) says that to assert “we do not need a special predicate.” Greimann’s reading makes “├” a special
predicate for assertion. See section 3 for discussion of this point.
8 Junyeol Kim
We can see what Frege is getting at only if we take into account what he says about judgment and
assertion in the first half of this short manuscript:
Making a judgment (assertion) does not alter the thought that is recognized to be true. When
something is judged (asserted) to be the case, we can always cull out the thought that is
recognized as true; the act of judgment (assertion) forms no part of this… . If I assert “It is true
that sea-water is salt,” then I assert the same thing as if I assert “Sea-water is salt.” This enables
us to recognize that the assertion is not to be found in the word “true’, but in the assertoric
force with which the sentence is asserted. (1915, 25)
The truth-predication that occurs in “The thought that p is true” gives an expression to the nature of
assertion because it does not add anything to the thought of which truth is predicated just as
assertion does not alter the asserted thought.14 The point here is not that the truth-predicate of a
natural language is defective because it fails to make the assertoric force contribute to the formation
of a thought. It is instead that to attempt to make the assertoric force be a part of a thought is
defective because the assertoric force is not a part of a thought. It is hard to believe that Frege would
let his logic commit the mistake he himself points out.
One might object that my argument depends on my terminology of “thought.” Specifically one
might insist that “thought” in the above passages refers to the sense of “the truth-value of: that p.”
However, that is not the case. In the above passages, Frege is analyzing natural language and
diagnosing its problem. As Greimann himself admits, a sentence of natural language has the sense
of a sentence, i.e., a thought in my terminology. Note: the thought that p in the above passages is
identical with the thought that the thought that p is true. As we have already seen, the sense of “the
truth-value of: that p” cannot be said to be identical with 〈the truth-value of: that p is true〉.
Therefore, Frege is talking about a thought in my terminology, i.e., a thought qua the sense of a
natural language sentence. His point in the above passages is that the thought expressed by a
sentence of natural language does not contain assertoric force in itself because assertoric force is not
something expressed by a component of a sentence.
I believe that Greimann is right when he argues that (i) Frege needs a category of “expressions
that are supposed to express a thought without simultaneously asserting its truth” (Greimann 2008,
412) and that (ii) “2 þ 2 = 4F” falls under such a category. The problem is, I believe, that from those
true claims, he proceeds to the conclusion that “2 þ 2 = 4F” must correspond something like “the
truth-value of: that 2 þ 2 is 4” in English.15 It is not clear at all why Frege ought to turn “2 þ 2 = 4F”
into a nonsentential term in order to deprive assertoric force of it. Why can’t he simply regard “2 þ
2 = 4F” as corresponding to “2 þ 2 is 4” in English to which assertoric force is not added, e.g., the
sentence uttered by an actor on a stage (cf. Frege 1892)? Is that because as soon as we form a
sentence and thereby express a thought, we come to make an assertion, i.e., because sentences or
thoughts contain assertoric force in themselves? But, as we have seen, that is just what Frege rejects.
It does not appear that in order to detach assertoric force from “2 þ 2 = 4F” we ought to turn it into a
nonsentential term. All we need to do is to realize that assertoric force is not its semantic
component. If we realize it, then we can take “2 þ 2 = 4F” to be a sentence that expresses 〈2 þ
2 is 4〉 but is not asserted. Assertoric force is added to the thought by “├.”
Indeed, “2 þ 2 = 4F” or what Greimann calls “singular truth-value term” in general is a sentence
that expresses a thought. After introducing eight primitive functions, Frege writes:
14
For Frege, judging or asserting is not adding something to a thought, but taking a step from a thought to its truth-value. See
Frege 1892.
15
Klement (2001), Landini (1996), and Pedriali (2017) make exactly the same move. Thus my criticism here is also applicable
to their versions of the nominal reading.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9
However, not only a reference but also a sense belongs to all names correctly formed from our
signs. Every such name of a truth-value expresses a sense, a thought. For owing to our
stipulations [for those primitive functions], it is determined under which conditions it refers
to the True. The sense of this name, the thought, is: that these conditions are fulfilled. Now,
a [Begriffsschriftsatz] consists of a judgment-stroke with a name, or a Roman marker, of a
truth-value. (1893, sec. 32)
ðBÞ ├ 22 ¼ 4
to be the combination of the judgment-stroke (the vertical stroke) and a name of a truth-value.
Therefore, what Frege calls “name of a truth-value” is not a Begriffsschriftsatz. Rather, something
like the following is an instance of such a truth-value name:
(N) — (—ε)
By the stipulations given for the functions involved in (N), we can specify when it refers to the True.
Frege’s point entails that (N)’s sense is 〈Those conditions are met〉, i.e., 〈The value-range of the
concept referred by the horizontal falls under the concept〉.16 (N) is a typical case of what Greimann
takes as a singular truth-value term: it certainly refers to a truth-value though it is not a
Begriffsschriftsatz. Frege’s remarks are explicit enough to affirm that such a singular truth-value
term “p” in general expresses 〈p〉, not the sense of “the truth-value of: that p.” One might object that
because “p” and “the truth-value of: that p” have the same condition for referring to the True, they
should be taken to be equivalent. However, this objection is refuted by Frege’s remarks here.
Though both “p” and “the truth-value of: that p” refer to the True under exactly the same condition,
only 〈p〉 but not the sense of “the truth-value of: that p” says that the condition is met. Again,
singular truth-value terms express thoughts. A thought is the sense of a sentence. It follows that
Frege takes singular truth-value terms to be sentences. Then a singular truth-value term “p” cannot
be translated into a nonsentential term such as “the truth-value: that p.” The argument for the TP
thesis based on the nominal reading must be rejected because the nominal reading is incorrect.
Above it is already stated that within a mere equation no assertion is yet to be found; with “2 þ
3 = 5” only a truth-value is designated, without its being said which one of the two it is. (Frege
1893, sec. 5; italics mine)
16
The sentence in the latter angled brackets is a natural language analogue of (N).
10 Junyeol Kim
To this end [of asserting] I make use of a vertical stroke at the left end of the horizontal, so that,
e.g., by writing
├2þ3=5
we assert that 2 þ 3 equals 5. Thus here we are not just writing down a truth-value, as in
2 þ 3 ¼ 5,
but also at the same time saying that it is the True (Frege 1891, 34; italics mine).
To assert that 2 þ 3 equals 5 is to identify 2 þ 3 = 5 with the True. We now have a neat explanation of
the point in question. Assertion as such identification is distinguished from designation of a truth-
value. Thus, to write down “├ 2 þ 3 = 5,” i.e., to assert that 2 þ 3 equals 5, is not to designate a truth-
value. Writing down “2 þ 3 = 5” cannot be asserting that 2 þ 3 is 5 because it is not identifying the
Truth with 2 þ 3 = 5.
I believe that it is in Frege’s assimilation of assertion with identification that the standard
interpretation of assertion (judgment) in Frege (Burge 1986; Dummett 1993; Heck and May 2018;
Heck 2012) is grounded. For instance, Heck (2012, sec. 2.3) says that we can understand asserting
that p in Frege as referring the True via 〈p〉 or by the sentence “p.” Note that when we refer to an
object o by the name “N”—as we refer to the True by the sentence “p”—we thereby identify o with
the reference of “N.” We can take Heck to be trying to make sense of Frege’s assimilation of assertion
with identification by way of the notion of the speech-act of referring to an object by a name.
One might object that because an act of identifying an object O1 as O2 is an act of assertively
predicating “x ¼ O2 ” of “O1 ,” “├” is a formal version of “… is the True” as Greimann argues. But
again that cannot be correct. Return to another passage we have seen:
Moreover, if I wrote “(2 þ 3 = 5) = (2 = 2)” and presupposed that one knows that 2 = 2 is the
True, even then I would not thereby have asserted that the sum of 2 and 3 is 5; rather I would
only have designated the truth-value of: that “2 þ 3 = 5” refers to the same as “2 = 2.” (Frege
1891, 34)
What Frege wants to point out is that one cannot “say” that p is the True even by predicating the
identity predicate “x ¼T” of “p“ where “T” is the most obvious name of the True.17 This shows that
to assert that p, i.e., to “say” that p is the True, cannot be done by predicating “… is the True” of “p.”
Thus, “├,” the device for asserting, cannot be such a predicate.
Then how do we have to understand “├”? Recall that the horizontal is a predicate that refers to the
concept being the True. Thus, the horizontal is indeed “… is the True” (as in “p is the True”). Then,
one can argue that the judgment-stroke marks assertoric force attached to this predicate and thus
that by writing down “├ 2 þ 3 = 5” we assert that 2 þ 3 = 5 is the True—identifying 2 þ 3 = 5 with the
True. This reading seems to fit what Frege says in Grundgesetze.
Of the two signs of which “├” is composed, only the judgment-stroke contains assertion
(Frege 1893, sec. 5).
Although this reading is tempting, our discussion in section 2 casts doubt on it. Recall that
Frege repeatedly claims that assertoric force does not belong to any predicate. However, if the
judgment-stroke really marks assertoric force, there is a significant sense in which assertoric
17
It is not clear whether Frege really intends to provide a nonsentential paraphrase of “(2 þ 3 = 5) = (2 = 2).” Weiner’s claim
that such a phrase “may be simply one of many ways of directing his readers to which truth-value a particular truth-value name
names” (2008, 442), seems to be much more convincing. In any event, Greimann’s point is not relevant to understanding this
passage.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11
force belongs to a particular predicate, i.e., the horizontal. That is because the judgment-stroke
must always be attached to the horizontal. “∣ 2 þ 3 ¼ 5” is not even a legitimate expression of
Begriffsschrift although there is a legitimate predicate—the identity sign—and the judgment-
stroke as a marker of assertoric force. We can make an assertion only by “├ 2 þ 3 ¼ 5,” i.e., only
when we attach the judgment-stroke to the horizontal. If the judgment-stroke marks assertoric
force, then the horizontal monopolizes assertoric force in Begriffsschrift and there is a substan-
tive sense in which assertoric force belongs to it. Moreover, Frege maintains that because
assertoric force is not a component of thoughts, “we do not need a special predicate” (1914,
233) in order to assert. However, if the above reading is correct, and so asserting that p is
asserting that p is the True, then we need a special predicate for asserting—the identity predicate
“… is the True” or the horizontal. Thus the above reading of “├” goes against Frege’s repeated
claims about assertion.18
Then, is there an alternative? One alternative is to take “├” to be a pure performative for
performing a nonassertive act of identification. We are not unfamiliar with the nonassertoric
conception of identification. According to Millikan (1998, 2000) or Camp (2002), the act of
identifying is neither an act of predicating an identity predicate nor asserting an identity.
Identification is an activity of its own kind that cannot be explained in terms of predication or
assertion. I believe that Frege is appealing to such a conception of identification when he
elucidates that asserting that p is taking a step from 〈p〉 to its truth-value in “On Sense and
Reference” (Frege 1892).19 To go into the detail of this seminal article goes beyond the scope of
this paper. What is important is that, given all his remarks we have seen, Frege would rather
understand “├” as a performative for such a nonassertoric identification if he indeed takes the act
of asserting that p to be that of identifying the True with p. Now, the remaining question is how we
can understand the compositionality of “├” if it is such a performative. The reading I suggest is to
regard the judgment-stroke as a performative generator that produces a performative for relevant
nonassertive identification when it is combined with an identity predicate. Thus, when the
judgment-stroke is combined with the horizontal, we have a performative for nonassertive
identification of the True. If we understand the compostionality of “├” in this way, Begriffsschrift
does not imply that we do not need the horizontal in order to assert. Of course, we need the
horizontal to acquire the performative. However, that does not imply that we need the horizontal
to assert. What we need for making an assertion is the act marked by “├,” not the components of
the sign. The compositionality of the sign is only for making explicit the nature of the action we
perform. The horizontal marks the point that what we affirm by our action is the identity with the
True, and the judgment-stroke marks the point that what we perform is not assertion of identity.
Also, assertoric force does not belong to the horizontal anymore in this interpretation. For the
judgment-stroke is not a marker of assertoric force. Furthermore, we can say that the act of
assertion is only contained in the judgment-stroke because it is a performative generator while the
horizontal is a mere predicate.
The expressions like “├ ξ 2 ¼ 4” are not functional expressions, because “├” is not a functor at
all. What we have by putting “2” in the position of “ξ” is not a truth-value, but an act of asserting
that 22 equals 4, i.e., “saying” that 22 ¼ 4 is the True. Begriffsschriftsätze are not names of truth-
values. Thus, they do not designate truth-values.20
18
There are other problems with this reading. See Kim (Forthcoming, sec. 2).
19
Kim (2019, sec. 4) points to this interpretation of “On Sense and Reference”; If judging is indeed such a fundamental act of
identifying, we can make better sense of Frege’s claim that “judgment is something peculiar and incomparable” (Frege 1892, 65).
20
Note that, in section 32 of Grundgesetze, Frege does not classify Begriffsschriftsätze as names of truth-values. Also, recall
that Frege says that a Begriffsschriftsatz asserts something. Sentences in the ordinary sense do not assert; we assert with
sentences. Begriffsschriftsätze are not sentences in the ordinary sense. Greimann’s reading, however, compares Begriffsschrift-
sätze to sentences in the ordinary sense. That point is what distinguishes his reading from mine.
12 Junyeol Kim
Junyeol Kim (PhD, University of Connecticut) is a research assistant professor of philosophy at Kookmin University. He also
teaches at Seoul National University and Yonsei University. Kim works on Frege, truth, epistemology, and philosophy of music.
His works have been published in Synthese, Ergo, and Thought, among others.
References
Burge, Tyler. 1986. “Frege on Truth.” In Frege Synthesized, edited by Leila Haaparanta and Jaakko Hintikka, 97–154. Dordrecht,
Nether.: D. Reidel.
Camp, Joseph L. 2002. Confusion: A Study in the Theory of Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Dummett, Michael. 1993. Frege: Philosophy of Language. 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Frege, Gottlob. 1879. Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle a. S.: Louis
Nebert. Translated by Bynum Terrell as Conceptual Notation in Conceptual Notation and Related Articles. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1972.
Frege, Gottlob. 1891. “Funktion und Begriff.” Jena: Hermann Pohle. Translated by Peter Geach as “Function and Concept.” In
Frege 1970, 21–41.
Frege, Gottlob. 1892. “Über sinn und bedeutung.” Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100: 25–50. Translated
by Max Black as “On Sense and Reference.” In Frege 1970, 56–78.
Frege, Gottlob. 1893. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. Jena: Hermann Pohle. Translated by Philip Ebert and Marcus Rossberg as
Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013.
Frege, Gottlob. 1897. “Logik.” Unpublished Manuscript. Translated by Peter Long and Roger White as “Logic.” In Frege 1979, 126–51.
Frege, Gottlob. 1906a. “Einleitung in die Logik.” Unpublished Manuscript. Translated by Peter Long and Roger White as
“Introduction to Logic.” In Frege 1979, 185–96.
Frege, Gottlob. 1906b. Über Schoenflies: Die logischen Paradoxien der Mengenlehre.” Unpublished Manuscript. Translated by
Peter Long and Roger White as “On Schoenflies: Die logischen Paradoxien der Mengenlehre.” In Frege 1979, 176–83.
Frege, Gottlob. 1914. “Logik in der Mathematik.” Unpublished Manuscript. Translated by Peter Long and Roger White as
“Logic in Mathematics.” In Frege 1979, 203–50.
Frege, Gottlob. 1915. “Meine grundlegenden logischen Einsichten.” Unpublished Manuscript. Translated by Peter Long and
Roger White as “My Basic Logical Insights.” In Frege 1979, 251–52.
Frege, Gottlob. 1970. Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege. Edited and translated by Peter Geach and
Max Black. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Frege, Gottlob. 1979. Posthumous Writings. Edited by Hans Hermes, Friedrich Kambartel, and Friedrich Kaulbach. Translated
by Peter Long and Roger White. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Frege, Gottlob. 1997. The Frege Reader. Edited by Michael Beaney. Oxford: Blackwell.
Frege, Gottlob. 2013. Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Edited and translated by Philip Ebert and Marcus Rossberg. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Goldfarb, Warren. 2001. “Frege’s Conception of Logic.” In Future Pasts: The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth-Century
Philosophy, edited by Juliet Floyd and Sanford Shieh, 25–41. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Greimann, Dirk. 2000. “The Judgement-Stroke as a Truth-Operator: A New Interpretation of the Logical Form of Sentences in
Frege’s Scientific Language.” Erkenntnis 52 (2): 213–38.
Greimann, Dirk. 2004. “Frege’s Puzzle about the Cognitive Function of Truth.” Inquiry 47 (5): 425–42.
Greimann, Dirk. 2007. “Did Frege Really Consider Truth as an Object?” Grazer Philosophische Studien 75 (1): 125–48.
Greimann, Dirk. 2008. “Does Frege Use a Truth-Predicate in His Justification of the Laws of Logic? A Comment on Weiner.”
Mind 117 (466): 403–25.
Heck, Richard Kimberly. 2012. Reading Frege’s Grundgesetze. Oxford: Clarendon University Press.
Heck, Richard Kimberly and Robert May. 2018. “Truth in Frege.” In Oxford Handbook of Truth, edited by M. Glanzberg,
193–217. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kim, Junyeol. 2019. “Frege’s Conception of Truth: Two Readings.” Ergo 6 (2): 31–57.
Kim, Junyeol. Forthcoming. “The Horizontal in Frege’s Begriffsschrift.” Synthese.
Klement, Kevin C. 2001. Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference. New York: Routledge.
Künne, Wolfgang. 2008. “Frege on Truths, Truth and the True.” Studia Philosophica Estonica 1 (1): 5–42.
Landini, Gregory. 1996. “Decomposition and Analysis in Frege’s Grundgesetze.” History and Philosophy of Logic 17 (1–2): 121–39.
Millikan, Ruth Garrett. 1998. “A Common Structure for Concepts of Individuals, Stuffs, and Real Kinds: More Mama, More
Milk, and More Mouse.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (1): 55–65.
Millikan, Ruth Garrett. 2000. On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay about Substance Concepts. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13
Pedriali, Walter B. 2017. “The Logical Significance of Assertion: Frege on the Essence of Logic.” Journal for the History of
Analytical Philosophy 5 (8).
Ricketts, Thomas. 1996. “Logic and Truth in Frege.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 70 (supp. vol.): 121–40.
Ricketts, Thomas. 2003. “Quantification, Sentences, and Truth-Values.” Manuscrito 26 (2): 389–424.
Taschek, William. 2008. “Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal: Frege on ‘the Essence of Logic.’” Mind 117 (466): 375–401.
Weiner, Joan. 2008. How Tarskian Is Frege? Mind 117 (466): 427–50.
Cite this article: Kim, J. 2021. Does Frege Have a Metalinguistic Truth-Predicate in Begriffsschrift?. Canadian Journal of
Philosophy: 1–13, doi:10.1017/can.2021.3